How far should one push the idea that companies have the same rights as

1970-01-01 02:00:00

rlp

Schumpeter

Peculiar people

OVER the past year and a bit the United States Supreme Court has produced two

landmark rulings on the metaphor at the heart of corporate law: the idea that

companies are legal persons. Unfortunately, the rulings point in opposite

directions. In Citizens United (2010) the court ruled that the constitution s

first amendment guarantees companies the same right to free speech as

flesh-and-blood people. This means they have the same right as individuals to

try to influence political campaigns through advertisements. But in a case

involving AT&T the court ruled this month that the company has no right to

personal privacy.

The legal conceit that companies are natural persons is vital to capitalism. It

simplifies litigation greatly: companies can act like individuals when it comes

to owning property or making contracts. Timur Kuran of Duke University argues

that the idea of corporate personhood goes a long way to explaining why the

West pulled ahead of the Muslim world from the 16th century onwards. Muslim

business groups were nothing more than temporary agglomerations which dissolved

when any partner died or withdrew. Legal personhood gave Western firms

longevity.

The concept of companies as people became ever more vital as capitalism

developed. Until the mid-19th century companies (as opposed to partnerships)

were regulated by corporate charters which laid down tight rules about what

they could do. But reformers used the idea that companies, like people, should

be captains of their own souls, to free them from these restrictions. The

result of this liberation was an explosion of energy: Western companies

turbocharged the industrial revolution and laid the foundations for mass

prosperity.

America s legal system has been forced to grapple with the meaning of corporate

personhood more thoroughly than other countries courts have done, because the

constitution is so specific about the rights it bestows on people. And for the

most part the Supreme Court has been generous in extending the rights of

flesh-and-blood people to artificial persons (which include trade unions and

other collectives as well as corporations). In Santa Clara County v Southern

Pacific Railroad in 1886, for example, it ruled that companies enjoy the

protections of the 14th amendment (including due process and equal protection

under the law).

Yet these artificial persons have always provoked worries, too. Aren t they

likely to use their collective muscle to trample over the little people? And

won t they invoke the rights of ordinary people without burdening themselves

with the responsibilities? These worries started in Britain in the age of

chartered corporations. In the 17th century Sir Edward Coke, a jurist,

complained that they cannot commit treason, nor be outlawed, nor

excommunicated, for they have no souls. But the complaints have grown louder

as companies have been freed from their charters and the Supreme Court has

reinforced their rights.

Some critics of corporations have also put the idea of corporate personhood to

their own uses. Joel Bakan, a legal academic, has produced a book and a film

both called The Corporation which argue that, if companies are people, they

are particularly dysfunctional and irresponsible ones. In the film, he even

consults a psychiatrist who argues that companies display all the

characteristics of a psychopath: callous disregard for others feelings,

inability to maintain relationships, a willingness to bend any rule and break

any law if it advances their interests, and an obsession with amassing power

and money.

This is overheated rhetoric, to be sure. But you do not have to be a radical to

worry about the might of organisations that can live for ever and take up

residence in dozens of countries at once. Nor is it unreasonable to wonder why

the idea of corporate personhood should only cut one way: if companies enjoy

the same rights as flesh-and-blood humans then shouldn t they be under the same

obligations? The conservative majority on the Supreme Court is in danger of

digging a trap for itself: strengthening the arguments of people who insist

that companies have a moral duty to pursue social rather than merely business

ends.

Don t take it personally

The court knows it can take the analogy too far. It has ruled against companies

being allowed to take the fifth amendment (against self-incrimination). It has

restricted companies rights to make political contributions: for example, they

cannot give donations directly to individual candidates. In the AT&T decision

John Roberts, the chief justice, devoted a lot of effort to demonstrating that

personal is more than an adjectival offshoot of person : when a company s

boss asks his finance director a personal question he is not likely to be

asking about the company s balance-sheet. Indeed, the term personal is

frequently used to mean the very opposite of corporate . But all this umming

and erring confuses more than it clarifies.

What would help is if the Supreme Court (and indeed corporate law in general)

adopted a clear principle when it comes to the analogy between artificial

persons and real ones: that companies should be treated as people only in so

far as it is expedient. They clearly need to be able to enter into contracts

just like individuals. But they should not be treated as if they experience

such essentially human emotions as embarrassment and a desire for

self-expression. Thus they should not have the same rights to privacy and

political freedom as a citizen, but should have only as much of a right to

confidentiality and political participation as is helpful for the efficient

functioning of business (including letting firms contribute to the public

debate on the regulation of business). Companies or rather their bosses and

owners should welcome such constraints: any further rights would, sooner or

later, be matched by onerous responsibilities.