This is the html version of the file http://www.phil-inst.hu/mobil/2005/
Nyiri.pdf.
Google automatically generates html versions of documents as we crawl the web.
Page 1
Krist f Ny ri
Collective Thinking
With the rise of ubiquitous networked communication due to the internet and its
enhancement by mobile access anytime, anywhere, our capacities for effective
problem-
solving both on the practical and the more abstract levels have vastly
increased. Two
domains where one would expect such increases to be particularly noticeable are
dem-
ocratic politics on the one hand, and scientific and technological creativity
on the other.
The advancement of e-democracy and m-democracy was amply demonstrated by a
number of talks given at the Budapest mobile communications conferences of May
2002, April 2003, and June 2004 just think of the papers by D nyi
1
, Paragas
2
, Kim
3
,
and Lai
4
and the momentous changes occurring in research and development with the
rise of the new communication patterns have been lucidly analyzed by Laki and
Pall at
the 2002 conference. Recall, also, the scientific feat the world witnessed in
2003: the
identification of, and the production of a test for, the SARS virus within a
matter of
weeks, an achievement unimaginable without ubiquitous networked communication.
It appears that a new kind of collective thinking has emerged, robust and
tangi-
ble. The gains we are enjoying are obvious; but might we not suffer losses as
well? Ac-
cording to an influential line of argument that also surfaced at the 2004
Budapest mobile
communications conference, continuous connectedness, and thereby the lack of
extend-
ed periods of mental solitude, inevitably leads to superficiality in thinking.
James Katz
alluded to the concern that due to "mobile-communication activities in
classrooms"
problems may be emerging such as "damage to attention spans" and to
"critical-thinking
skills", as well as the loss of "ability to concentrate, to plan, and to work
with complex
ideas"
5
. Raimondo Strassoldo employed less uncertain terms. As he put it: "There is a
time for speaking and communicating; but there should also be a time for
thinking, for
meditation, for contemplation, for concentration, for reflection, for
introspection, for in-
ternal talk within oneself and, perhaps, with the inhabitants of the self."
Strassoldo ob-
serves that with the spread of the mobile phone people "only seem to be able to
exist as
1
Endre D nyi Mikl s S k sd, "M-Politics in the Making: SMS and E-mail in the
2002 Hungarian Elec-
tion Campaign", in Krist f Ny ri (ed.), Mobile Communication: Essays on
Cognition and Community, Vi-
enna: Passagen Verlag, 2003, pp. 211 232; Endre D nyi, "WLC 2 UROP /
Interconnected Public Spheres
in the Age of Mobile Communication" in Krist f Ny ri (ed.), A Sense of Place:
The Global and the Local
in Mobile Communication, Vienna: Passagen Verlag, 2005, pp. 129 137.
2
Fernando Paragas, "Dramatextism: Mobile Telephony and People Power in the
Philippines", in Krist f
Ny ri (ed.), Mobile Democracy: Essays on Society, Self and Politics, Vienna:
Passagen Verlag, 2003, pp.
259 283.
3
Shin Dong Kim, "The Shaping of New Politics in the Era of Mobile and Cyber
Communication: The
Internet, Mobile Phone and Political Participation in Korea", in Krist f Ny ri
(ed.), Mobile Democracy,
pp. 317 325.
4
On-Kwok Lai, "Mobile Communicating for (E-)Democracy beyond Sovereign
Territorial Boundaries:
Transnational Advocacies versus E-Government Initiatives in Comparative
Perspectives", in Krist f Ny ri
(ed.), Mobile Democracy, pp. 327 337; Shizuka Abe On-Kwok Lai, "Mobile
Communicative Actions
in (Anti-)Globalization Processes: Social Agencies and the State in an
Information Society", in Krist f
Ny ri (ed.), A Sense of Place, pp. 93 103.
5
James E. Katz, "Mobile Phones in Educational Settings", in Krist f Ny ri (ed.),
A Sense of Place, p. 316.
Here Katz is referring to Marilyn Gilroy's paper Invasion of the Classroom
Cell Phones , Education Di-
gest, vol. 69, no. 6 (2004), pp. 56 61.
Page 2
2
nodes and terminals of communication networks". As he sees it, the young are
ever less
capable of becoming "autonomous, self-directed individuals", and he recalls
David
Riesman "denounc[ing] more than half a century ago the trend toward
other-directed-
ness".
6
Strassoldo's reference to Riesman is not entirely apt. The latter did in fact
make
the connection, in his 1950 book The Lonely Crowd, between the printed book and
inner-directedness;
7
however, Riesman's notion of other-directedness is thoroughly
bound up with the experience of centralized mass media. Networked communication
of
course provides one with very different experiences. Do we have reason to
believe that
the network individual's cognitive achievements
8
are in any way inferior to that of the
inner-directed one? It was in the wake of Strassoldo's talk
9
that I decided, during the
planning stages of the present conference, to dedicate my paper to the topic of
collective
thinking.
10
Solitude
Will the incessantly communicating individual, then, produce but superficial
thoughts; is solitude a necessary precondition of depth? Note that the term
"solitude" has
no meaning unless set against the background of a given communicational
technology.
The solitude of one bewitched by a book is different from the solitude of
sulking Achil-
les and the solitude of the lonely texter. For members of nonliterate cultures
solitude is
an enforced condition, bound up with exceptional events such as rites of
passage, or oc-
curring as a result of unusual, indeed catastrophic, events. Similarly with
silence. Refer-
ring to a nonliterate Eskimo tribe in the 1950s, psychiatrist J. C. Carothers
found it sig-
nificant that people there "talked a great deal", obeying the "rule of Eskimo
life ... that a
6
Raimondo Strassoldo, "The Meaning of Localism in a Global World", in Krist f Ny
ri (ed.), A Sense of
Place, p. 56.
7
The Lonely Crowd: A Study of the Changing American Character, by David Riesman
in collaboration
with Reuel Denney and Nathan Glazer, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, see
esp. pp. 89 97. A
singularly perceptive analysis of this book as seen from the perspective of the
orality/literacy contrast is
provided by J. C. Carothers in his paper "Culture, Psychiatry, and the Written
Word", Psychiatry: Journal
for the Study of Interpersonal Processes 22 (1959), 307 320.
8
I have begun using the term "network individual", for designating what I think
is a new type of personal-
ity, in the early stages of the project COMMUNICATIONS IN THE 21ST CENTURY (cf.
century.phil-inst.hu/2Summ.htm, see also my preface to the volume Krist f Ny ri
(ed.), Mobile Democra-
cy, p. 16).
9
And as a consequence of the recognition that the phenomenon Strassoldo refers
to the tendency for
young people to be in continuous mobile contact has clearly become a very
real one. A dramatic narra-
tive is Lin Prřitz's paper "Intimacy Fiction: Intimate Discourses in Mobile
Telephone Communication
amongst Norwegian Youth", in Krist f Ny ri (ed.), A Sense of Place, pp. 191
200. My favourite sentence
in Prřitz's paper is the one where she says of the teenage couple she deals
with: "they send persistent text
messages to each other from the very moment they wake up until they go to sleep
interrupted only, so to
speak, by the text message break that occurs when they are physically together"
(ibid., p. 198).
10
I became further motivated by an article in the December 13, 2004, issue of The
Christian Science
Monitor, quoting Naomi Baron, Professor of Linguistics at American University,
author of Alphabet to
Email: How Written English Evolved and Where It s Heading, London: Routledge,
2000. "If you talk to
students you often find they have trouble being alone", Baron said. "Some argue
that cellphones make it
possible to have larger social safety net and that contact is good. I argue
that part of what makes a human
being is the ability to be alone with no one to help [think] through a number
of difficult circumstances ...
to figure out who [we] are, where [we] want to go, who [we] want to be." I side
with those who believe
that what constitutes a human being is the ability to communicate with other
human beings.
Page 3
3
man must not keep any thought to himself for if he does so he will go mad".
11
Prelit-
erate, Homeric Greek had no words to represent solitary, inner, mental events;
thinking
was a dialogue, thinking to oneself a dialogue between parts of one's body.
There was
no vocabulary to express abstract cognitive states or processes.
12
That vocabulary was
gradually built up by Western philosophy, beginning with Plato, and reaching a
point of
culmination and a new beginning with Descartes. Ernest Gellner's book Language
and
Solitude
13
sketches a variety of perspectives from which to understand Cartesian-type
loneliness; in the present talk, I will concentrate on one such perspective,
namely that of
silent reading.
Deep Thoughts
The term "superficiality" is merely a metaphor, complementing the already du-
bious metaphor of "depth", the latter suggested by the metaphor of "immersion"
engen-
dered by the experience of silent reading. As demonstrated in the 1920s in the
pioneer-
ing work of the Hungarian scholar J zsef Balogh, silent reading was almost
unknown in
ancient Greece and Rome, and all through the Middle Ages;
14
the written text, devoid of
intervals and punctuation, had to be read out loud in order to be understood.
Under such
conditions, written-down thoughts, as contrasted with spoken-out-loud ones, do
not ex-
ude the suggestion of depth. Neither in Plato's Academy, nor in Aristotle's
school would
"depth" have been a word of praise. Plato extolled "clearness and perfection
and serious-
ness", "communicated orally for the sake of instruction and graven in the soul,
which is
the true way of writing"
15
even if, of course, he himself committed his philosophy to
writing, while mimicking, in his dialogues, the style of spoken exchange. As to
Aristot-
le, it is here essential to register the simple truth which centuries of
specialist scholar-
ship, for obvious psychological and sociological reasons, have refused to
accept, namely
that the Corpus Aristotelicum was not the work of a single individual, but of
generations
of teachers and students of the Peripatetic School. The Corpus is the written
documenta-
tion of oral discussions stretching over many decades. As Grayeff puts it in
his work Ar-
istotle and His School: "as regards both their meaning and their structure,
[these writ-
ings] become intelligible only when it is realized that they are part of a[n
imaginary] di-
alogue carried on between the lecturer and rival philosophers".
16
What the Aristotelian
school valued was not depth, but articulateness, and dexterity in open
argumentation.
The printed page is easily scanned; with the spread of Gutenberg's invention,
in
the course of two or three centuries, silent reading becomes the rule. Words on
the print-
ed page appear clearly and distinctly, creating an illusion of autonomous ideas
clear and
distinct in the reader/thinker's mind. The prophet of this illusion was
Descartes. The sto-
11
Carothers, op. cit., p. 314. The reference is actually a quote from Katharine
Scherman's Spring on an
Arctic Island, Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1956.
12
For references, see my paper "Thinking with a Word Processor", in R. Casati
(ed.), Philosophy and the
Cognitive Sciences, Vienna: H lder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1994, pp. 63 74. A digital
version of the paper is
available at http://www.phil-inst.hu/nyiri/KRB93_TLK.htm.
13
Ernest Gellner, Language and Solitude: Wittgenstein, Malinowski and the
Habsburg Dilemma, Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
14
Cf. Josef Balogh, "'Voces Paginarum': Beitr ge zur Geschichte des lauten Lesens
und Schreibens", Phi-
lologus 82 (1926), pp. 84 109, 202 40. See also Paul Saenger, "Silent Reading:
Its Impact on Late Medi-
eval Script and Society", Viator 13 (1982), pp. 367 414.
15
Phaedrus 278a, Jowett transl.
16
See esp. Felix Grayeff, Aristotle and His School, London: Duckworth, 1974
Page 4
4
ry of his withdrawal into seclusion during the winter of 1619 1620 is
well-known, and
the philosophical results of his solitary meditations were of course pathetic.
The formula
"Cogito, ergo sum" might have convinced some generations of thinkers labouring
under
unnatural conditions of communication similar to those affecting Descartes; but
it would
definitely meet with incomprehension on the part of today's texters, becoming
unsure of
themselves the moment the stream of incoming messages is at a low ebb.
Similarly in-
comprehensible to habitual senders and receivers of e-mails, to regular mobile
phone
users, or indeed to ardent employers of texting/chatting abbreviations, would
be John
Locke's thesis that the words of language are actually "marks for the ideas
within [one's]
own mind"
17
a thesis directly leading to the position according to which, as Wittgen-
stein put it, "[t]he individual words of language refer to what can only be
known
to the person speaking", namely to "immediate private" mental contents, with
the im-
plication that "another person cannot understand the language".
18
Wittgenstein believed
himself to have shown that a private language is impossible; but what he
actually did
show, I think, is that such a language is impossible under the conditions of an
oral cul-
ture.
19
In the culture of the printed book one can indeed become enmeshed in one's ver-
bal abstractions, ending up with unfathomable ideas: deep thoughts, if you
like. By the
late 18th century there arose a feeling that depth is ineffable. As the
Romantic poet
Friedrich Schiller wrote: "Spricht die Seele so spricht ach! schon die Seele
nicht mehr."
Visible Thoughts
Now it is essential to note that while writing in its fully developed form,
i.e. the
printed text, fosters a seeming clarity, and actual obscurity, of thinking
turned inward,
from the very beginning it also gives rise to an enhanced coherence of thinking
conduct-
ed externally, publicly. As the Hungarian historian Istv n Hajnal wrote in the
early
1930s, referring to the beginnings of alphabetic literacy in Greece: "Writing
vividly ac-
companies the human being's outer and inner life, objectifying it and thus
rendering it
capable of being observed. It links together the past and the present in the
life of both
the individual and the community, it encourages rational thinking, and enables
the build-
ing of complicated mental edifices."
20
As, not independently of Hajnal's work, Walter J.
Ong underlines in his Orality and Literacy, writing of course is, in a sense,
alienating.
However, as he puts it: "Alienation from a natural milieu can be good for us
and is in
many ways essential for full human life. To live and to understand fully, we
need not
only proximity but also distance."
21
Seen from the perspective opened up by Hajnal it is
not difficult to understand why people often prefer to write SMS messages
instead of
17
John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Book 3, chapter 1, sect.
2.
18
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1953, Part I, 243.
19
See my paper "Writing and the Private Language Argument", in J. C. Ny ri,
Tradition and Individual-
ity: Essays, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992. My point of departure in that paper is
Bronislaw Malinowski's es-
say in the Ogden and Richards volume The Meaning of Meaning (1923). Language in
a preliterate culture,
Malinowski emphasized, is never "a mere mirror of reflected thought"; in
writing however "language be-
comes a condensed piece of reflection", the reader "reasons, reflects,
remembers, imagines". Such reflec-
tion is, as Malinowski sees the matter, a philosophically dangerous enterprise,
leading to a "misuse of
words", and thereby to a misleading picture of human communication and
cognition.
20
Istv n Hajnal, " r sbelis g, intellektu lis r teg s eur pai fejlőd s"
["Literacy, Intellectual Stratum, and
European Development"], 1933, repr. in Hajnal Istv n, Technika, művelőd s:
Tanulm nyok ["Technolo-
gy, Education: Essays], Budapest: Hist ria, 1993, p. 43.
21
Walter J. Ong, Orality and Literacy: The Technologizing of the Word, London:
Methuen, 1982, p. 82.
Page 5
5
calling; or why, as for instance Abigail Sellen and Richard Harper have
discovered,
22
surrounding the computer display with an array of printouts is indispensable if
office
workers want to understand longer texts and compose decent documents. On a less
pe-
destrian level, Hajnal is a precursor of Merlin Donald's external memory
theory, accord-
ing to which the "three broadly different modes of visual symbolic invention"
making
up the last evolutionary transition in the development of humankind, namely the
"picto-
rial, ideographic, and phonological", signalled the beginnings of "a new
cognitive struc-
ture", leading, also, towards forms of "analytic thought", i.e. "formal
arguments, system-
atic taxonomies, induction, deduction".
23
And Donald's external memory theory is then
taken over by Andy Clark, a fact perhaps less than sufficiently acknowledged by
the lat-
ter, in the form of the "extended mind" theory, a theory that plays a major
role at the
present conference: Andrew Brook, John Preston, and Zsuzsanna Kondor all deal
with
it.
24
In the first chapter of McLuhan's Understanding Media there is a passage that
ends with an intriguing, seldom-quoted sentence. "The content of writing", the
passage
runs, "is speech, just as the written word is the content of print, and print
is the content
of the telegraph. If it is asked, 'What is the content of speech?', it is
necessary to say, "It
is an actual process of thought, which is in itself nonverbal.' "
25
Donald's external mem-
ory theory does allow for thought to be nonverbal, in that it underlines the
primary role
of the pictorial in the sequence of visual symbolic inventions. Thoughts are
made visible
not just by writing, but also by images. However, as alphabetical literacy
became in-
creasingly dominant, with written texts widely copied while the technology of
duplicat-
ing pictures was severely lagging behind, visible thinking became, for many
centuries,
merely thinking in words.
26
This situation has changed, at first gradually, with the in-
vention of the printed image and later with the rise of photography, and then
dramatical-
ly with the emergence of computer graphics. Computer graphics are at their best
when
turned into animations. Animations, however, cannot be conveyed via hardcopy;
you
need to watch a screen, and, ultimately, you also need to be online. We are
back at the
recognition that serious thinking, today, is inevitably thinking in the medium
of ubiq-
uitous networked communication.
The Collective Mind
In my paper "Thinking with a Word Processor", given at the 1993 Wittgenstein
Symposium in Kirchberg am Wechsel, I concluded by saying: "When we think with a
word processor it is a synchronous intellectual exchange with fellow thinkers
all over
22
Abigail J. Sellen Richard H. R. Harper, The Myth of the Paperless Office,
Cambridge, MA: The MIT
Press, 2002.
23
Merlin Donald, Origins of the Modern Mind: Three Stages in the Evolution of
Culture and Cognition,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991, pp. 278, 284, 273.
24
Clark's new study, with direct bearing on the issue of mobile phones, the book
Natural-Born Cyborgs:
Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2003, con-
tains two references to Donald the index lists him as Merlin, D. neither of
which does any justice to
the very close parallels between the external memory / extended mind theories.
25
Marshall McLuhan, Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1964,
p. 8.
26
I have dwelled at some length on this theme in my papers "The Picture Theory of
Reason", in Berit
Brogaard and Barry Smith (eds.), Rationality and Irrationality, Wien: bv-hpt,
2001, pp. 242 266, and
"Pictorial Meaning and Mobile Communication", in Krist f Ny ri (ed)., Mobile
Communication, pp. 157
184; see also my essay "Images of Home", in Krist f Ny ri (ed.), A Sense of
Place, pp. 375 381.
Page 6
6
the world we are, ultimately, engaged in. So what are we thinking with when we
think
with a word processor? The word 'with' here does in the last analysis point
not to in-
strumental application but to human companionship."
27
This paper was basically a
continuation of what one could call Wittgenstein's theory of the extended mind,
put for-
ward, for example, in one of the opening remarks of the Blue Book: "We may say
that
thinking is essentially the activity of operating with signs. This activity is
performed by
the hand, when we think by writing; by the mouth and the larynx, when we think
by
speaking If we talk about the locality where thinking takes place we have a
right to
say that this locality is the paper on which we write or the mouth which
speaks."
28
Wittgenstein's theory of the extended mind essentially involves the position
that
the agent of thinking encompasses not just devices external to the individual
brain, but
also the community of thinkers playing the same language-game. As he puts it in
a well-
known passage of the Philosophical Investigations: "If language is to be a
means of
communication there must be agreement not only in definitions but also (queer
as this
may sound) in judgments. This seems to abolish logic, but does not do so.
human be-
ings agree in the language they use. That is not agreement in opinions but in
forms of
life."
29
It is interesting to note that Heidegger, along with Wittgenstein the other
great
twentieth-century philosopher of post-literacy, had quite similar views, even
if express-
ed in a rather different terminology. "We do not merely speak the language", he
wrote,
"we speak by way of it. ... We hear language speaking. ... language speaks."
30
("Wir
sprechen nicht nur die Sprache, wir sprechen aus ihr. ... Wir h ren das
Sprechen der
Sprache. ... die Sprache spricht.") Both for Wittgenstein and Heidegger,
speaking, and
thus thinking, is first, foremost, and to the end, a collective achievement.
The primary
agent of thinking is the community of speakers; the rules of traditional logic
are a
makeshift substitute in the mind of the solitary thinker for the absent voices
of inter-
locutors. In the age of post-literacy linear logic is, once more, supplanted by
the logic of
conversation. As McLuhan's theory of the extended mind foresaw: "In the
electric age
our central nervous system is technologically extended to involve us in the
whole of
mankind the creative process of knowing will be collectively extended to the
whole of human society".
31
But let me note, in closing, that the working of the collective mind does not
al-
ways rely on networking. It was a fundamental insight of the economist and
philosopher
Friedrich August von Hayek that not only is social knowledge, under modern
condi-
tions, fragmented in the sense that "each member of society can have only a
small frac-
tion of the knowledge possessed by all, and ... each is therefore ignorant of
most of the
facts on which the working of society rests", but also that this knowledge must
remain
"widely dispersed among individuals", since it is tacit, practical, local, not
of the kind
that can be transferred, ordered, united. How can we benefit, Hayek asks, from
"knowl-
edge ... we do not possess"?
32
Hayek's question is echoed by James Surowiecki in his
27
J. C. Ny ri, "Thinking with a Word Processor", cf. note 12 above.
28
Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958.
pp. 6 f.
29
Philosophical Investigations, 241 f.
30
Martin Heidegger, "The Way to Language" (1959), in Heidegger, On the Way to
Language, New York:
Harper & Row, 1971, p. 124.
31
Understanding Media, pp. 3 f.
32
F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty, vol. 1: Rules and Order, London:
Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1973, pp. 13 15.
Page 7
7
recent The Wisdom of Crowds,
33
a stimulating albeit inconclusive book; but then Hayek
himself, at the end of the day, was unable to outline a conclusive answer.
Hayek empha-
sized the role the market plays in co-ordinating local segments of knowledge;
he did
not, however, build upon the fact that the marketed goods themselves bring
together,
embody, and carry such knowledge. Our tools and devices are materialized
results and
vehicles of, as well as ever new inputs to, collective thinking. And here,
finally, the mo-
bile phone re-enters not as a means of communication, but as the supreme
instance of
an instrument incorporating the expertise of a vast number of specialists,
enabling the
individual to enjoy the fruits of that enhanced scientific and technological
creativity to
which I was referring when I embarked on this talk.
33
James Surowiecki, The Wisdom of Crowds: Why the Many Are Smarter than the Few
and How Col-
lective Wisdom Shapes Business, Economies, Societies, and Nations, New York:
Random House, 2004.