đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș murray-bookchin-urbanization-without-cities captured on 2024-08-19 at 00:11:08. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Urbanization Without Cities Subtitle: The Rise and Decline of Citizenship Date: 1992 Source: [[https://libcom.org/library/urbanization-without-cities-rise-decline-citizenship][libcom.org]] Notes: This is the 1992 edition published by Black Rose Books Authors: Murray Bookchin Topics: History, Anarchist history, Social ecology, Civilization, Cities, Citizenism, Libertarian municipalism, Urbanization, Black rose books
<em>For **Jane Coleman** and **Dan Chodorkoff**â<br><br>
and in memory of **Zeitel Kaluskaya** (1860â1930),
my grandmother, who raised me
and showed me a world long gone by.</em>
The city at its best is an ecocommunity. To ignore this compelling fact is to ignore the destruction it faces by one of the most
serious phenomena of the modern era, the massive urbanization
that is sweeping it away together with so many natural features of
our planet. Urbanization is not only a social and cultural fact of
historic proportions; it is a tremendous ecological fact as well. At
a time when the overwhelming majority of people in North America and Western Europe regard themselves as city dwellers, we
are obliged, if only for ecological reasons, to explore modern urbanization. We must explore not only its impact on the natural
environment, a subject that has already been discussed in considerable detail by many writers, but, more significantly these days,
the changes urbanization has produced in our sensibility toward
society and toward the natural world. A social ecology of the city
is needed today if ecological thinking is to be relevant to the
modern human condition.
This book attempts to lay the groundwork for such a social
ecology. It tries to develop a concept of the city in those participatory terms that are uniquely characteristic of all âecosystemsâ (or,
as I prefer to call them, ecocommunities). It relates ecologyâs participatory sensibility to the city in all its forms over the course of
history, partly to show that the city was a social ecocommunity at
various times insofar as it fostered diversity, mutualism, and connectedness. In applying a participatory sensibility to the city, I
have been obliged to take the reader on a voyage into the evolution of the city, just as any serious natural ecologist would be
obliged to deal with the biological development of an organism to
better understand its life-cycle. To think about the city as an ecocommunity is to try to understand how it evolved, what forms it
assumed over time, how it functioned as more than a mere market
or center of production, and, in the last analysis, how member
this urban ecocommunity called the city interacted with each
other to produce a form of âsecond natureââa humanly made
ânatureââthat existed in balance with the âfirst natureâ we
usually call the natural environment. Hence the citizens of a city
of no less concern to me than the city itself, for the city at its best
eventually became an ethical union of people, an ethical as
as social ecocommunity, not simply a dense collection of structures
designed for no other purpose than to provide goods and services
for its anonymous residents.
What I wish to do is redeem the city, to visualize it not;
threat to the environment but as a uniquely human, ethical, and
ecological community that often lived in balance with nature and
created institutional forms that sharpened human awareness of
their sense of natural place as well as social place. My repeated
references to the agrarian world could easily be regarded as references to the natural world as well. My emphasis on civic participation can be taken as the social counterpart of biological mutualism
citizenship, as the social counterpart of biotic involvement if
shaping the form of a natural ecocommunity; civic history, as the
social counterpart of natural history. My goal, in effect, has been
to redefine the city and the citizen in the language of social ecol
ogy in the hope that environmentally as well as socially oriented
people today will understand what the city and citizenship *used*
to be in order to better understand what they *should* be in an
ecological society.
The real urban crisis of our time, I shall emphasize, has resulted
not from the emergence of the city as such; rather it results from
the emergence of a relatively new and cancerous phenomenon
that poses a deadly threat to the city and countryside alike: urbanization. The nature of this threatânot merely as geographic sprawl
but a devastating dehumanizing of city life, a destructing of community, and a denaturing of agrarian lifeâis the underlying
theme of this book. I must leave it to the pages which follow for
a more complete description and elucidation of the vast problems
urbanization is creating. My argument runs counter to the conventional wisdom that city and countryside, like society and nature, are necessarily in conflict with each other, a theme that
pervades so much of the writing on urbanity of western society.
Quite to the contrary: however much city life marks a departure
in many social respects from the more natural forms of human
sociation such as tribal and kinship groups, the city has often been
as much a gift to the ecology of a landscape as it has been a harm.
To recover a feeling for the participatory civic institutions that
Once marked city life and citizenship is to recover those ideals of
Civic life and a civic sensibility that could countervail the massive
destruction that urbanization inflicts on city and countryside alike.
This book advances several reflections on how an ecological
politics can be developed. In so doing, it redefines the word politics itself along ecological lines, much as Green groups in North
America and Europe have been doing over the past years. Finally,
this book makes a plea for a confederal and institutional politics,
this is, for enlarging the democratic, grass-roots institutions that
countervail the growing centralization of the nation-state, not the
conventional electoral politics based on single issues and parliamentary tournaments.
Much that motivated my writing of this book stems from my
conviction as a social ecologist and environmental activist that
there is a pressing need to view the cityâmore generally, the
municipality, if we are to include towns as well as metropolitican
areasâas an ecological enterprise, not merely a logistical or structural one. Hence, the largest chapter in this book advances a
programmatic agenda for recovering not only an ecological image
of the city and an active citizenry but a way of looking at politics
that combines the high ideal of a participatory citizenshipâin
short, ecological values based on participation as a mutualistic
phenomena in society as well as in nature.
In any case, the city is here to stay. Indeed, it has been a crucial
part of human history and a factor in the making of the human
mind for some seven thousand years. Can we afford to ignore it?
Must we accept it as it isâas an entity that faces obliteration by
a sprawling urbanization that threatens the countryside as well?
Or can we give the city a new meaning, a new politics, a new sense
of directionâand, also, provide new ideals of citizenship, many of
which were in fact attained in great part during past times? By
ignoring the city and citizenship, we do so at the peril of becoming
isolated from the great mass of humanity which is threatened by
the anonymity and powerless created by urbanization. This is a
issue which all socially and environmentally oriented people must
face and answer in their own way: My goal, here, is to pose the
question of urbanization and citizenship as clearly as I can and
advance some modest solutions based on my own concerns as a
social ecologist
Murray Bookchin
Burlington, Vermont
<br><br>
Director Emeritus,
Institute for Social Ecology,
Marshfield, Vermont
<br><br>
Professor Emeritus,
School of Environmental Studies,
Ramapo College of New Jersey
The city has been a favorite target of hostility from biblical
times onwardâand it is no less so today. Viewed as a festering
source of moral depravity by many people, it has been
variously assailed as an ugly blight on a seemingly pristine
natural landscape, as the sinful embodiment of a human nature
that is aggressive, domineering, or even as âmaleâ in its
ârapeâ of a caring Mother Earth and âherâ gentle aboriginal
folk and animal offspring. I will leave the metaphoric, often
terribly fuzzy ruminations of this genre of anti-city sentiment
aside. A far stronger case can be made for an anti-city sentiment
that regards modern, generally sprawling and formless
urban agglomerations as sources of anomie, fear, self-interest,
and a host of environmental problems. Urbanization, as I call
this ever-encroaching and ever-growing phenomenon that
we so often facilely identify with cities as such, can indeed be
as toxic to the human spirit as it can be to a regionâs natural
integrity.
But what, then, is a city? And are the people trapped in
modern-day urban agglomerations really citizens?
reflective and hopeful way. Far from joining the chorus of
city-denouncers, I wish to explore the enormous value of
citiesâand townsâas remarkable human creations. In
responding to the above questions, I have tried to examine
from a historical viewpoint the origins of cities, their role in
shaping humanity as a highly unique and creative species,
and the promise they offer as arenas for a new political and
social dispensation. I have tried to examine how the city
evolved, what forms it assumed over time, how it functioned
as more than a mere market or center of production, and how
citizens of a city interacted with one another to produce a
form of what the great Roman thinker Cicero called âsecond
natureââthat is, a *humanly* made ânatureââthat existed in
balance with the âfirst natureâ we usually call the natural
environment. Hence the citizens of a city are of no less concern
to me than the city itself, for the city at its best ultimately
became an ethical union of people, a moral as well as a
socioeconomic communityânot simply a dense collection of
structures designed merely to provide goods and services for
its anonymous residents.
What I wish to do is to redeem the city, to explore it hot as
a corrosive phenomenon but as a uniquely human, ethical,
and ecological community whose members often lived in
balance with nature and created institutional forms that
sharpened human self-awareness, fostered rationality, created a
secularized culture, enhanced individuality, and established
institutional forms of freedom. My repeated references to the
agrarian world can easily be regarded as references to the
natural world as well. My emphasis on civic participation can
be taken as the social counterpart of biological mutualism;
citizenship, as the social counterpart of biotic involvement in
shaping the forms of natural ecocommunities; and civic history,
as the social counterpart of natural history. In using the
word *counterpart* here, however, I do not mean that civic
participation, citizenship, and civic history are reducible to
natural mutualism, ecocommunities, and biological
evolution; they differ in far too many ways to be congruent. But
this is a philosophical question I have dealt with in a broad
discussion of first and second nature in my
(Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1990). Suffice it to
say here that my goal in this book has been to redefine the
city and the citizen in the language of social ecology. It is my
hope that thoughtful people today will attempt to understand
what the city and citizenship *used* to be in order to better
understand what they *could* be in a free, rational, and ecological
society.
----
The usual kinds of answers given to the question of what
constitutes a city are often spatial and demographic in character,
viewing the the city as an area occupied by a closely interlocked,
densely populated human community. This definition,
cast in largely quantitative terms, has been advanced for a
long time. In fact, it is the popular criterion for the prestige
enjoyed by some cities over other ones, and of cities generally
over towns and villages. Tradition has it that the larger a city
is, the *better* it is culturally and economically, by comparison
with smaller communities. It is worth noting that years ago,
American census-takers regarded communities of five
thousand people or more as urban and those with smaller
populations as rural. More recent criteria of what constitutes
a city have changed only quantitatively. The word *city*, in fact,
has turned into something of a social euphemism, the
product of a time long past. Today, statisticians and many
urbanologists favor the use of such categories as the Standard
Metropolitan Statistical Area (SMSA)-sprawling, densely
occupied regions that ordinarily embrace milllions of people. In
reality, cities are being supplanted by areas so immense in size
that they are losing their contours, specificity, and uniqueness.
Many urban agglomerations today have larger populations
than many countries had a century ago and are in many
respects hardly different from small nation-states.
My own definition of a *city* cannot be reduced to a single
proposition. Like rationality, science, and technology, which I
regard as defined by their own histories, I view the city as the
cumulative developmentâor dialecticâof certain important social
potentialities and of their phases of development, traditions,
culture, and community features. Least of all do I see
citificationâa processual noun for the city in historyâas a mere
âsystem of space,â to use Henri Lefebvreâs phrase, in which
the geometrical term *space* becomes a quasi-mystical category
for social, economic, and cultural relationships-relation-
ships that I feel should be explored quite directly, without the
convoluted âdecodingâ that enters into the work of certain
postmodernists and neo-Marxists today. Neither from simple
propositional definitions nor from somewhat mystical
postmodernist gymnastics would I have any way of knowing
how cities and their village, temple, and town progenitors
came into being, how they developed, or what they ought to
be if their potentialities were to be fulfilled in a free and
rational society.
Defining the early city, I maintain, begins with the
recognition of the city as a *creative* breach with humanityâs
essentially biological heritage, indeed the âmetamorphosisâ of that
heritage into a new *social* form of evolution. The city was
initially the arena par excellence for the transformation of
human relationships from associations based on biological
facts, such as kinship, to distinctly social facts, such as
residential propinquity; for the emergence of increasingly
secular forms of institutionalization; for often rapidly
innovative cultural relations; and for universalizing economic
activities that had been previously associated with age, gender,
and ethnic divisions. In short, the city was the historic arena
in whichâand as a result of whichâbiological affinities were
transformed into social affinities. It constituted the single
most important factor that changed an ethnic folk into a body
of secular citizens, and a parochial tribe into a universal
become a member of the community without having to satisfy
any requirement of real or mythic blood ties to a common
ancestor. Not only did political relationships replace kinship
relationships; the notion of a shared *humanitas* replaced the
exclusivity of the clan and tribe, whose biosocial claims to be
âthe Peopleâ had often excluded the âoutsiderâ as an
inorganic, exogenous, or even threatening âother.â
Hence the city was historically the arena for the
emergence of such universalistic concepts as âhumanityââand is
potentially the arena for the reemergence of concepts of politi-
cal self-regulation and citizenship, for the elaboration of social
relations, and for the rise of a new civic culture. The steps from
a consanguineous clan, tribe, and village to a *polis*, or political
city; from blood brothers and sisters who were *born* into their
social responsibilities to citizens who in the best of circumstances
could freely decide on their civic responsibilities and determine their own affinities based on reason and secular
interestsâthese steps constitute a meaningful definition of
the city. Cities, to be sure, can rise and fall. They can enjoy
good fortune for a time or, owing to conflicts, totally disappear.
But once the city established firm roots in the history of social
development, it acquired a conceptual reality that still persists,
and it can still undergo many metamorphoses despite the
disappearance or stagnation of individual cities. The city, in effect,
has become a historic traditionâoften a highly moral oneâthat
tends to expand uniquely human traits and notions of
freedom, and an idea of civic commonality that corrodes the
parochial bonds of blood ties, gender distinctions, age status-groups,
and ethnic exclusivity.
We can thus legitimately speak of the history of the city
without focusing on the rise, development, and decline of any
one city in particular. And we can speak of this history as
cumulative. The late medieval city, for example, united civic
and ideological traditions that had originated in Athens,
Jerusalem, and Rome, and that persisted long after those
cities had declined as innovative civic entities. Later, the cities
of the Renaissance, the Baroque era, and the Enlightenment
arose as reworked arenas of ancient and medieval cities,
borrowing from them their architecture, literature, art, religions,
and philosophies, yet transforming them to meet the needs of
a new time.
----
The ways in which actual cities provide US with processual
definitions of the city form much of the content of this book.
Insofar as I am guided by the Greek notion that a city or *polis*
is an *ethical* union of citizens, I am committed to an
overarching vision of what the city *ought* to be, not merely what it *is* at
any given time. The term *ought* is the stuff out of which ethics
is usually madeâwith the difference that in my view the
âoughtâ is not a formal or arbitrary regulative credo but the
product of reasoning, of an unfolding rational process elicited
or derived eductively from the potentialities of humanity to
develop, however falteringly, mature, self-conscious, free,
and ecological communities. I call this integration of the best
in first or âbiologicalâ nature and second or âsocialâ nature an
emergently new âthirdâ or *free* natureâthat is, an ethical,
humanly scaled community that establishes a creative
interaction with its natural environment. From a processual
standpoint, I refuse to bifurcate that continuum we call
âNatureâ into a biological world and a social world that stand in
flat opposition to each other. Both are in a very real sense
realization in those remarkable primates called human beings who,
consciously responding to a sense of obligation to the
ecological integrity of the planet, bring their rational,
communicative, richly social, imaginative, and aesthetic capacities to the
service of the nonhuman world as well as the human.
This ethics of complementarity, as I called it years ago,
would not only be a culminating point of aeons of natural
evolution, once it guided human behavior in the cities of an
ecological society; it would eminently be a culminating point
of reason itselfâa condition in which rational goals could be
established for citizenship not only in new, ecologically
oriented networks of cities but in truly rational beings called
citizens. For citizenship, too, is a processâas the Greeks so
brilliantly sawâa process involving the social and self-formation
of people into active participants in the management of
their communities. As this book stresses, citizens today no
longer even approximate the high and eminently human
standard of citizenship that was established in the Hellenic
worldâa meaning that must be recovered, as well as the personal
and social training, or *paideia*, for producing citizens.
----
To this high civic and ethical calling, so to speak, we are
summoned by reason: to networks of new, humanly scaled cities,
to citizenship, to directly democratic political institutions, and
to a vastly expanded ideal of freedom. The cities I have discussed
in this book approximate the fulfillment of this callingâsome
more than others, a few more highly conscious of
free civic ideals than the restâin civic cultures that held to
such intituitive, often naive notions of citizenship that they
were highly vulnerable to destructive forces; and in thinkers
who projected (often in revolutionary situations,) in thought
what they believed should have been achieved in actuality
but, alas, was not.
When I use the word *networks* in this book, I am alluding
not to ad hoc interactions, tentative agreements, contracts, or
transient associations among cities-although these were
common enough, if usually very short-lived, in the past.
Rather, I am referring to what has long been a theoretical
ideal and at times an impressive municipal reality: namely,
association of cities and towns is part of the development of a
free, ecologically oriented society. Localism, in the narrow
sense of a virtually autarchical locality that aspires to
âself-sufficiencyââin the sense so popular in the ecology movement todayâcould easily produce a parochialism notable for
such evils as racism, cultural insularity, and a stagnant
traditionalism. Conceived localistically, municipalities would
be as regressive as authoritarian nation-states.
Confederalism is explicitly *not* âlocalistâ but is rather
the mutual obligations of confederated municipalities to
systematically adjudicate conflicting claims, coordinate common
efforts, and see to the administration of municipal policies
without infringing on the right of the majority of its
participants. That consensual forms of agreement where possible
would be the most desirable decision-making procedure does
not mean that majority decision-making should not be
adopted if a confederation risks the prospect of being
tyrannized by the few at the expense of the many. Moreover,
confederation, if it is to be successful, must not only function in
accordance with majoritarian forms of decision-making; it
must diminish the authority of confederal councils, the
higher they are, in coordinating the policies formulated at the
basic level of decision-makingâthe citizen assembly of a
municipality.
A clear distinction must be drawn between *administration*
and *policy-making*: the former would fall within the province
of the confederal councils, while the latter would fall within
the province of the municipal assemblies. The traditional
hierarchial pyramid of authority would thus be literally
inverted in confederal municipalism; the âapexâ of all authority
would lie with the municipal assemblies, guided by majority
rule both in the assembly and among the assemblies of a confederal region; the âbaseâ would lie with the broadest confederal councils whose work is simply administrative and adjudicatory, and whose deputies, drawn from smaller confederal bodies, would be easily recallable and subject to
careful popular oversight.
Is this a chimerical scheme? History has shown that the
very contrary is true. Although confederations in the past
often fell apart, each for very specific reasons that would require a full volume to explore, they were often shattered or
confined to limited areas by imperial states and, more recently, the nation-state. Confederations, in fact, have a long and
impressive history. They were the principal political
weapons for resistingâand, for a time, diminishingâstate
power. The struggles of confederated Rhenish cities in the
late Middle Ages against the Holy Roman Empire and of the
confederated Spanish cities against Charles V during the
Reformation era can be cited as partially successful attempts
to abort or restrict imperial and national power. In Spain,
confederal movements had an impact on public life that was
felt well into the 1930s.
In many respects, this contest between confederalism
and the nation-state is reemerging today, although very little
consciousness guides intuitive opponents of the nation-state,
a shortcoming that has more to do with the atrophied consciousness of so-called âLeftâ-wing movements than with
any other single factor. Indeed, if the closing decade of this
century is permitted to pass without the emergence of a
strong, self-conscious, and well-organized movement that is
committed to municipal confederation, radical theory and
practice will deserve the ignominious oblivion into which
Marxist and individualistic âanarchistâ tendencies have been
drifting for some time now. Todayâs dogmatic or subcultural
radical movements may one day be viewed with contempt if
they reject the lastâand in my view their **only**âprospect of
functioning as popular movements, and if they fail to cross
the line from academic or personalistic subcultures into the
public sphere where they could still reach millions of eager
but confused people. Popular albeit inchoate impulses toward
these same ideasâlocal control, confederation, and a new
politicsâmay well be used, in altered form, and manipulated
by reactionary forces in the service of racist, parochial, and ultimately authoritarian ends.
----
the last that can be made in this periodânot only for a new
theoretical framework in which to develop a new politics (in
this termâs Hellenic meaning rather than in the parliamentary
meaning imparted to it by the nation-state). It also advances
an appeal for a self-conscious *practice* in which
confederal municipalists engage in local electoral activity to
alter city and town charters, restructure civic institutions to
provide the public sphere for direct democracy, and bring the
means of production under *citizen* controlânot under the
particu1aristic forms of âworkersâ controlâ that tend to
degenerate into a form of collectivistic capitalism, or under
forms of nationalized production, which enhance the stateâs
authority with greater economic power.
This practice is not a mere âstrategy,â to use the language
of the traditional Leftâindeed, the language of all statist
movements. It is not a âmeansâ to an end, least of all a very
unclear and muddled end. Rather, it is the *unfolding* of an end:
the famous âCommune of communes,â to which socialists
and anarchists alike long aspired, especially after the legendary Paris Commune of 1871, which explicitly used this term.
In this process or dialectic of unfolding, the achievement of a
Commune of communesâor in less colorful terms, a confederation of municipalitiesârequires a completely
uncompromising politics. It rests on the notion of a fundamental
confederated municipalities emerge in flat *opposition* to the
centralized nation-state. Indeed, whatever power confederated municipalities gain can be acquired only at the expense of the
nation-state, and whatever power the
nation-state gains can be acquired only at the expense of
municipal independence.
In the force-field that exists between the two, either the
municipalities and their confederations will increase their
power by diminishing the the power of the ration-state, or
the nation-state will increase its power by diminishing the
authority of the municipalities and their confederations.
Thus, for a municipalist movement to run candidates for
state, provincial, or national office would be an absurd, in
fact, oxymoronic subversion of its very claim to seek a
âgrassrootsâ or âparticipatory democracy,â if only because
a form of representation rather than participation. Even
more significantly, it would ignore the crucial fact that as
they run candidates *for* local offices, confederal municipalists
are also running them *against* state, provincial, and national
offices and institutions. The demand for municipal confederations is simultaneously a demand for opposition to the
nation-state in **all** its forms, and to the illusion that the
control of state, provincial, or national legislative bodies on the
âtopâ is a precondition for the attainment of local power at
the âbottom.â
Not only would campaigns for state, provincial, and
national office relax the tension between the âtop,â which is the
realm of statecraft, and the âbottom,â which is the realm of an
authentic politics; they would diminish the *educational* function of politics at the âbottom,â which alone can become the
realm of a new politics. Far from reaching greater numbers of
people by running candidates for the summits of state power,
such campaigns would confuse the distinction between
politics and statecraft, between the participatory and the representative, between the confederal and the national. Not
only would the tension between these two utterly opposing
spheres of activity be relaxed and its dialectic aborted; and not
only would the truly democratic nature of political education,
which is based on face-to-face discourse between neighbors
and citizens, be replaced by the media; but the very moral and
educational thrust of a libertarian or confederal municipalist
approach would be lost as a heavy mist beclouded the distinction between politics and statecraft. A âCommune of communesâ is not a âRepublic of communesâ or a âCommonwealth of communesâ; indeed, as a confederation of municipalities, it stands uncompromisingly opposed to any specious attempts to reduce a confederation or commune to a
republic or a commonwealth.
Radicals, social-democrats, and liberalsânot to speak of
that hybridized phenomenon known as âthe Greensââhave
never learned how to deal with the problem of state power. If
history from earliest recorded times to the present has
demonstrated anything, it is the implacable fact that state
power is corruptive. None of the most idealistic and principled revolutionary leaders of the past lived comfortably
with the corruptive effects of state power. Either they succumbed to it, or they consciously tried to diffuse it. The retention of state power destroyed the moral integrity not only of
the most radical Puritans of the seventeenth century, who
were eager to gain it, but that of the most dedicated socialists,
communists, and anarchists who actually held it for a time.
The English, French, Russian, and Spanish revolutions provide compelling evidence of the capacity of state power to
corruptâa capacity that can no longer be regarded as a moral
truism but, given its unrelenting nature, must be seen as an
existential fact. To pursue state powerâor to âseizeâ it, to use
the language of traditional radicalismâis to guarantee that it
will persist as a form of elitist manipulation, expand, and be
brutally exercised as an instrument against a popular
democracy.
A libertarian or confederal municipalist politics advances
the best approach against âseizuresâ of state power and its
retention by an elite, by slowly trying to *accrete* power for
municipalitiesâinitially, by acquiring *moral* power for
municipal assemblies, as I have indicated in the closing chapter of this book. Libertarian or confederal municipalism seeks
to expand the democratic institutions that still linger on in
any modern republican system by opening them to the
widest public participation possible at any given time. Hence
the slogan that I have advanced: âDemocratize the Republic!
Radicalize the Democracy!â It is not that state power is to be
âseizedââand then never relinquishedâbut that popular
power is to be expanded until all power belongs to the institutions of a participatory democracy.
From this standpoint, the distinction between politics
and statecraft must be maintained in a clear and uncompromising manner, all the more to assure that no âpragmaticâ exigencies or parliamentaryâ strategiesââeven if they
are used only to propagandize oneâs views or challenge the
âtopâ from the âtopââare invoked for seemingly confederal-municipalist ends. Indeed, the most effective impact of
municipalist propaganda comes precisely from the fact that
it is **municipalist**âthat is to say, that it can be conducted only
by person-to-person contact and its scope hopefully extended by a movement that tries to reach every municipality
in a region or nation. It is this kind of propaganda that makes
for trust, personal interaction, and face-to-face education
and that fosters the development of a face-to-face
democracy. Its authentic starting point is the small study
group, the local lecture hall, the neighborhood press, and
personal discourse-not the electronic media of statecraft
that hypnotized the countercultural âmedia freaksâ of the
1960s.
----
Most of the ideas that appear in this introduction are
elaborated in the body of this book. They are developed
against the larger background of a historic moment in the
evolutionâand I should add, the declineâof city life, namely
the emergence of a major threat to city and countryside alike:
urbanization. The existence of this threatânot merely as
geographic sprawl but as a devastating dehumanization of
city life, a destructuring of community and a denaturing of
agrarian lifeâinforms the views that follow. My argument
runs counter to the conventional wisdom that city and
countryside, like society and nature, are necessarily in conflict
with each other, a theme that pervades so much of the writing
on urbanity in Western society. Quite to the contrary:
whatever may be the ways in which city life marks a departure from the more ânaturalâ forms of human association
such as tribal and kinship groups, the city has been more of a
gift to social life and the ecological landscape than it has been
harmful. To recover a feeling for the participatory civic institutions that once marked city life and citizenship is to
recover those ideals of civic life and civic sensibility that could
countervail the massive destruction that urbanization and
the nation-state inflict on city and countryside alike.
My writing of this book stemmed from my conviction as
a social ecologist and eco-anarchist that there is a pressing
need to view the cityâmore generally, the municipality, if we
are to include towns as wellâas an ecological enterprise, not
merely as a logistical or structural one. The word *ecological*
means a good deal more here than it does in the conventional
environmentalism of the single-issue movements that are
concerned with pollution, the retention of relatively untouched forests, the perpetuation of wildlife, and the like.
Ecology, in my view, is more a societal project than a biological one. It should be conceived in terms that explore how notions of domination and the historical development of
hierarchy have led to the social as well as natural problems
we face today. For a clearer understanding of my ecological
perspectiveâsocial ecologyâthe reader is advised to consult
my many books on the subject, particularly
with what are loosely called âurban problems,â or if you like,
âurban ecology.â Its goal is practical as well as theoretical.
Hence, the largest chapter in the book (âThe New Municipal
Agendaâ) advances a programmatic agenda for recovering
not only an ecological concept of the city and an active
citizenry but the creation of a new politics that combines the
high ideal of a participatory citizenship with a recognition of
what the city or town can be in a rational, free, and ecological
society.
In any case, the city, however much more distorted it
may become in the future, will remain a problem. At its best, it
has been a crucial part of human history and a force in the
making of the human mind for some seven thousand years.
Can we afford to ignore it? Must we accept it as it isâas an
entity that sprawling urbanization threatens to obliterate, as
it threatens to devour the countryside as well? Or can we
give the city a new meaning, a new politics, a new sense of
direction-as well as provide new ideals of citizenship, many
of which were in fact once attained in previous times? We ignore the city and citizenship at the peril of becoming isolated
from the great mass of humanity, which is threatened by the
anonymity and powerlessness created by urbanization. This
is an issue that all socially and enviromentally concerned
people must face. My goal here is to pose the question of the
future of cities and citizenship as clearly as I can and to advance solutions based on the principles of social ecology.
Murray Bookchin
Institute for Social Ecology
Plainfield, Vermont
January, 1992
The title of this chapter has been deliberately worded to create a
paradox in the readerâs mind. How, it may be fair to ask, can, we
speak of urbanization against cities? The two words, âurbanityâ
and âcity,â are usually taken to be synonyms. Indeed, as conventional wisdom would have it, a city is by definition an urban entity,
and an urban entity, in turn, is certainly regarded as a city.
Yet I shall take great pains to show that they are in sharp
contrast to each otherâin fact, that they are bitter antagonists. My
reasons for making such an unorthodox distinction between urbanization and citification are not intended to be semantic word
juggling. The contradiction forms the very rationale for writing
this book. âUrbanization against citiesâ is meant to focus as sharply
as possible on a human and ecological crisis so deep-sfeated we are
hardly aware of its existence, much less its grave impact on social
freedom and personal autonomy. I refer to the historic decline of
the city as an authentic arena of political life (that once lived in
some balance with the natural world) and, perhaps no less significantly, the decline of the very notion of citizenship.
So sweeping a statement obviously requires some clarification
at the outset of our discussion. According to most social theorists,
the traditional âcontradictionâ created by the rise of urbanism has
been the cityâs ages-old âconflictâ with the countryside. History,
we are commonly told, is filled with innumerable examples of the
cityâs efforts to free itself from the trammels of agrarian parochialism. The city, it is emphasized, has always tried to assert its cosmopolitan culture and secular civic institutions over the narrow provincialism and constrictive kinship ties of the rural town and
village. We take it for granted that from ancient to modern times
the city and countryside have been at âwarâ with each other.
Historically, this âwarâ is supposed to be embodied in the conflicting interests between the feudal lord and the urban merchant, the
peasant food-cultivator and town-dwelling craftsperson, the landbased aristocrat and the citified capitalist, the farmer and the industrial worker.
That such conflicts have existed over the course of history and
echo in modern society is true enough. We still retain ingrained
visions of a cleansing and virtuous pastoral life that stands in moral
contrast with the tainted and sinful world of the city. The contrast
has been the subject of Biblical invectives, the theme of some of
our most outstanding novels, and a centerpiece in the writings of
many distinguished sociologists.
Taken as a whole, however, this Manichean drama can be a
gross simplification of reality. It is certainly true that city and
countryside have commonly viewed each other antagonistically in
the past. And there have been long stretches of history when each
tried to assert economic and political dominance over the other.
But there have also been times when they existed in an almost
exquisitely sensitive, creative, and ecological balance with each
other. Some of the most admirable human adventures m culture,
technics, and social freedom have occurred precisely in those periods when a complementary relationship between city and country, indeed between society and nature, successfully replaced the
mutual rivalry for supremacy.
Today, it would seem that the city has finally achieved complete
dominance over the countryside. Indeed, with the extension of
suburbs into nearby open land on an unprecedented scale, the city
seems to be literally engulfing the agrarian and natural worlds,
absorbing adjacent towns and villages into sprawling metropolitan
entitiesâa form of social cannibalism that could easily serve for
our very definition of urbanization. All talk of metropolitan Babylon and Rome to the contrary, we have no comparable parallels
in the past to urbanization on our present-day scale. Worse, the
city seems to be replacing rural culture and all its rich traditional
forms with the mass media and technocratic values we tend to
associate with âcity life.â If all of this is trueâas I frankly believe
it isâI plan to introduce in this book a very discordant qualification. Contrary to most views on the subject, I plan to show that if
we use words such as âcityâ and âcountryâ meaningfully to describe this process of physical, cultural, and ecological urban cannibalism, the image of an all-devouring âcityâ that is engulfing a
supine and helpless âcountryâ is a sheer myth.
The truth is that the city **and** the country are under siege todayâa siege that threatens humanityâs very place in the natural environment. Both are being subverted by urbanization, a process that
threatens to destroy their identities and their vast wealth of tradition and variety. Urbanization is engulfing not only the countryside; it is also engulfing the city. It is devouring not only town and
village life based on the values, culture, and institutions nourished
by agrarian relationships. It is devouring city life based on the
values, culture, and institutions nourished by civic relationships.
City space with its human propinquity, distinctive neighborhoods,
and humanly scaled politicsâlike rural space, with its closeness to
nature, its high sense of mutual aid, and its strong family relationshipsâis being absorbed by urbanization, with its smothering
traits of anonymity, homogenization, and institutional gigantism.
Whether or not the urbanization of both the city and the country
is desirable is an issue that I shall earnestly explore, But I cannot
emphasize too strongly that even if we think in the old terms of
city versus country and the unique political contrasts such a time-honored imagery has nurtured, the conflict between city and
country has largely become obsolete, Urbanization threatens to
replace both contestants in this seemingly historic antagonism. It
threatens to absorb them into a faceless urban world in which the
words âcityâ and âcountryâ will essentially become social, cultural, and political archaisms.
----
Perhaps our greatest difficulty in understanding urbanization and
its grave impact on social and personal life today stems from our
tendency to link it with our very naive idea, of the city. We are
often satisfied to call any urban entity a city if it is demographically congested, structurally sizable, and, most significantly, populated by individuals whose work no longer deals directly with food cultivation. Urbanization, like citification, seems to meet these
criteria so completely that we commonly identify the two, and
distinguish them more as a matter of degree than of kind. Thus,
we tend to regard a sprawling metropolitan area merely as an
oversized city, or it may be an agglomeration of closely packed
âcitiesâ that Americans call âurban beltsâ and the British call
âconurbations.â
Granted that we are finding it increasingly difficult, on careful
reflection, to regard urban belts and conurbations merely as cities.
We uneasily sense that they are something moreâif not something newerâthan what previous generations called cities. What
confuses us about such perplexing issues is that the people who
live in such new urban entities are plainly engaged in city-type
occupations and seem to follow citified lifeways. Increasingly
removed from the natural world, metropolitan dwellers rarely, if
ever, earn their livelihood as farmers, however fashionable urban
and suburban gardening has become in recent years. They are
employed in urban jobs, be they professional, managerial, service-oriented, craft-oriented, or the like. They five highly paced and
culturally urbane lifeways-that lock into mechanically fixed time
slotsânotably, the ânine-to-fiveâ patternârather than follow
agrarian cycles guided by seasonal change and dawn-to-dusk personal rhythms. Urban environments are highly synthetic rather
than natural. Food is normally bought rather than grown. Dwellings tend to be concentrated rather than dispersed. Personal life
is not open to the considerable public scrutiny we find in small
towns or rooted in the strong kinship systems we find in the country. Urban culture is produced, packaged, and marketed as a segment of the city dwellerâs leisure time, not infused into the totality
of daily life and hallowed by tradition as it is in the agrarian world.
That country life is growing more and more like city life and losing
its simplest natural attributes is a point that will become highly
salient for the purposes of our discussion. For the present, what
counts is,that the aforementioned distinction still existsâ in the
image of what we call urbanization (conceived as citification) as
distinguished from ruralization.
Superficial as these continuities and contrasts may be, they
begin to dissolve completely when we start to explore history for
richer, fuller standards of what we mean by the word cities. I use
the plural, cities, advisedly: Despite certain similarities, the differences between cities of the past also have considerable importance. History presents us with a wide range of unique and distinctive citiesâthe earliest in Sumer centering around temples;
later ones, such as Babylon, around palaces; the more dynamic
Greek democracies around civic squares that fostered citizen interaction; medieval and more recent ones, around a variety of
different marketplaces. However diversified cities may have
been in the past, our language gives them considerable prestige.
The term civilization has its origin in *civitas*âa Latin word occasionally used for cityâand denotes the cultural sophistication the
western world has traditionally imparted to some kind of urbanism. Most of our utopian visions, whether heavenly or earthly,
take the form of a pity, a âNew Jerusalemââ to. speak in sacred
terms, or an idealized version of the Hellenic âcity-stateâ to use
Secular language.
----
But here we abruptly encounter the limits of the term urbanization as a synonym for citification. Urbanization does not comfortably fit into an imagery of the city drawn from theocratic, monarchic, democratic, and economic communities peopled by
craftsfolk and small merchants who were engaged in a natural
economy. Our urban belts and conurbations are vast engines for
operating huge corporate enterprises, industrial networks, distribution systems, and administrative mechanisms. Their facilities,
like their towering buildings, stretch almost endlessly over the
landscape until they begin to lack all definition and centrality. It
is difficult to root them in a temple, palace, public square, or the
small, intimate marketplace of craftsfolk and merchants. To say
that they have any specific center that gives them civic identity
is often so ill-fitting as to be absurd, even if one allows for centers
that linger on from past eras when cities were still clearly delineable areas for human association.
What, then, do our premodern cities with their rich diversity of
forms and functions have in common? We arrive at a basic characteristic of city life that is the result not only of human propinquity,
structural size, occupations, and an urbane culture. What major
cities of the past shareâwhatever their differences are largely
moral, often spiritual, attributes with deep roots in a natural environment that sharply distinguish them from the physical attributes we associate with urbanization. Cities of the past from their
very beginnings were ultimately what I would call communities
of the heartââmoral associations that were nourished by a shared
sense of ideological commitment and public concern. Civic ideology and concern centered around a strong belief in the good life
for which the city provided the arena and catalytic agent. The
good life by no means meant the affluent life, the life of personal
pleasures and material security. More often than not, it meant a
life of **goodness**, of virtue and probity. This sense of civic calling
could assume a highly spiritual form such as we find in the Jewsâ
reverence for Jerusalem or a highly ethical form as in the Greeksâ
admiration for Athens. Between these emotive and intellectual
extremes, city dwellers of the past tended to form social compactsâ that were guided not only by material and defensive considerations but by loyalties to their cities that were shaped by
richly textured ideological commitments.
Love of oneâs city, a deep and abiding sense of loyalty to its
welfare, and an attempt to place these sentiments within a rich
moral and ecological context, whether God-given or intellectual,
clearly distinguishes the majority of cities of past eras from those
of present ones. We have virtually no equivalent in the modern
city of the Near Eastern sense of civic spirituality, the Greek feeling of political affiliation, the medieval endearment to communal
fraternity, and the Renaissance love of urban pageantry that infused the otherwise disparate citizenry of the past. Such loyalties,
with their moral underpinnings, may linger on in the residents of
modern cities, but more as a fevered appetite for the material,
cultural, and nervous stimulation of what we today designate as
the good life than as a product of the ethical sturdiness, spiritual
commitment, and sense of civic virtue that marked the citizenry
of earlier eras. It also meant a love of the land, of place and natural
setting that gave rise to a rich ecological sensibility and respect for
the countryside.
To speak truthfully, our present-day relationship to the city
usually takes the form of very pragmatic material requirements.
A modern city, suburb, town, or, for that matter, a village is often
evaluated in terms of the âmunicipal servicesâ it offers to its residents. The traditional religious, cultural, ethical, and ecological
features that once endeared citizens to their city, and its natural
surroundings have dissolved into quantitative, often ethically neutral, criteria. The city is the first fund into which we make a series
of social investments for the express purpose of receiving a number of distinctly material returns. We expect our persons and
property to be protected, our shelters to be safeguarded, our garbage to be removed, our roads to be repaired, our environment
to be physically and socially tidyâwhich is to say, spared from the
invasion of âundesirable elements.â
Doubtless we want our cities to be culturally stimulating,
economically viable, and attractive in reputation. But such attainments are not necessarily a function of the city as such. They often
depend upon the results of personal enterprise, the presence of
individual types who reside in it by virtue of birth or choice. For
a city to claim a famous sonâand, more recently, a famous daughterâdoes not necessarily reflect well upon the cityâs reputation for
producing gifted or renowned people but rather on the individual
gifts of one or more of its residents. It does not provide us with
evidence of the cityâs cultural milieu but of a specific personâs gifts
and biography that often involve a valiant effort to transcend a
communityâs oppressive environment. Such was the case, for example, with James Joyceâs relationship with Dublin, Oscar Wildeâs
relationship with London, or Cezanneâs relationship with Paris.
Hence, urban âcivilizationâ as we know it today is the erratic
byproduct of a particular city, not its main and distinguishing
consequence. Such a âcivilizationâ emerges from the wayward
activities of fairly privatized individuals or corporations rather
than the innate traits of the municipality itself. A civic culture does
not stem from the collective efforts of a unique and cohesive
public, however unusual the city may be in terms of its regional
location and its historic traditions. It stems from the personal activities of certain individuals wKo happen to occupy a residence
within the cityâs confines, staff its shops and offices, work its industries, and, of course, produce its artistic artifacts. Urban âcivilization,â today, is not a characteristic civic phenomenon that
emerges from a distinctive public and body politic; it is simply the
exudate of free enterprise with its patina of âpublic serviceâ and
cultural charity. That mayors, corporate leaders, and philanthropists may vie with each other in celebrating the projects they
initiateâprojects that may range from concert halls and museums
to airports and industrial parksâis simply evidence of the shallowness of what today is called âcivic-mindedness.â Rarely do these
projects, which in any case are seldom free of vulgarity, nourish
the city as a collectivity and arena for public activity. Like iridescent bubbles that rise, glisten, and burst, they form the surface of
the cityâs often stagnant cultural life and social malaise.
In fact, like any marketplace, the modern city is the hectic
center of a largely privatized interaction between anonymous
buyers and sellers who are more involved in exchanging their
wares than in forming socially and ethically meaningful associations. Cities today are typically measured more by their success as
business enterprises than cultural foci. The ability of an urban
entity to âbalance its budget,â to operate âefficiently,â to âmaximizeâ its service with minimal cost, all of these are regarded as the
hallmark of municipal success. Corporate models form the ideal
examples of urban models, and civic leaders take greater pride in
their managerial skills than in their intellectual abilities.
----
This dominant entrepreneurial concept of the city has its precise
counterpart in the dominant contemporary notion of citizenship.
If we tend to view the city as our most immediate social âinvestment,â we expect the city to give us adequate material âreturns.â
We pay our taxes with a distinct expectation of the services they
will buy. The greater the services for the money we pay, the more
profitable it is to reside in a given city. Civic amenities are clearly
measurable in terms of the number of schools, class sizes, parks,
firehouses, transportation facilities, police, crime rates, parking
spacesâindeed, in terms too numerous to inventory. When we
âbuyâ into a residential area, we reconnoiter it primarily for these
material and logistical amenities and secondarily, if at all, for the
cultural stimulation and sense of community it provides.
Not surprisingly, the resident of most cities today tends to develop a very distinctive self-image. It is not the image of a citizenâa historically remarkable term that I have yet to describeâbut
that of a taxpayer. He or she does not have a sense of self appropriate to what we might call a public figure but rather that of a
free-wheeling investor. Doubtless, taxpayers and investors often
form many associations, but they ally with each other to advance
or protect very specific interests. Like all sensible entrepreneurs
who are involved in the business of residing in a city, they want
a favorable return for what they pay, and, as the saying goes, âin
numbers there is strength.â Accordingly, all common adages to
the contrary, they **can** fight City Hallâpresumably, the place
where the corporate board meetsâand, depending as much upon
their wealth as upon their numbers, they may succeed.
But beyorid this economically secure interplay of conflicting
interests and demands, the citizen **qua** taxpayer is not expected
to get deeply involved in municipal affairs. Nor does the contemporary urban environment encourage him or her to do so. A âgood
citizenâ is one who obeys the laws, pays taxes, votes ritualistically
for preselected candidates, and âminds his or her own business.â
This notion of appropriate civic behavior is no t merely a mutually
shared, quietistic vision of modern-day citizenship; it is a political
desideratum that, if violated, exposesâmore active taxpayers to
charges of âmeddlingâ at best and âvigilantismâ at worst. Both
taxpayers and municipal officials prudently acknowledge that the
people of a city should be properly represented by efficient, specialized, and professional surrogates of âthe public.â Day-to-day
power, however, residesâ precisely in the hands of these
managerial surrogates, not in their âconstituenciesâ who increasingly acquire the anonymity andâ facelessness that the word âconstituencyâ denotes. Like the traditional liberal concept that government is best when it governs least, so the contemporary liberal
Concept of citizenship seems to be that a âconstituentâ is best
when he or she acts the least.
----
Such a concept of citizenship is fraught with grave psychological as
well as political consequences. Individuals whose public lives
barely transcend the social level of mere taxpayers tend to form
very passive images of their personalities and of the natural environment around them. An increasingly disempowered citizen
may well become a quietistic and highly retiring self. A major loss
of social power tends to render a person less than human and
thereby yields a loss of individuation itself. Such constituents live
in a painfully contradictory world. On the one hand, society
becomes an intensely problematic presence in their lives. The
social realm is a potential source of war, of economic instability,
of contending factions and ideologies that may reach directly into
the most guarded niches of private life. These problems become
particularly intimate when issues such as abortion, military conscription, sexual freedom, and earning capacity invade the individualâs domestic realm.
On the other hand, while such issues rage around the âconstituent,â he or she is steadily divested of the power to act upon them.
Indeed, the âconstituentâsâ intellectual equipment to form an assured opinion is eroded by an ever-deepening sense of personal
incompetence and public detachment. A preoccupation with
triviaâthe problems of shopping, fashion, personal appearance,
career advancement, and entertainment in a thoroughly boring
milieuâreplaces the more heroic stance of a socially and environmentally involved body politic. We thus encounter a twofold development: a world in which growing social power preempts concerns that were once largely within the purview of the individual
and the community, and the steady erosion of personal power and
the individualâs capacity for action. Within this paralyzing forcefield, the individualâs self-identity begins to suffer a crucial decline.
Self-recognition dissolves steadily into a grim lack of selfhood.
Inaction becomes the only form of action with the result that the
âconstituentâ retreats into an inwardness that lacks the substance
to render one individually functional.
A world in which personality itself resembles the **tabula rasa** of
an aimless society and a meaningless way of personal fife would
seem to raise more universal issues than the fate of the city and
the citizen. But in many respects this universality expresses itself
as a need for a larger perspective toward civic issues. The city is
not only the individualâs first social âinvestmentâ; it is his or her
most intimate social environment. Owing to its vital immediacy,
the city remains (as it has throughout history) the most direct
arena in which the individual can act as a truly social being and
from which he or she can attain the most immediate social solutions to the broader problems that beleaguer the privatized self.
Insofar as the individualâs self-definition as an empowered person
and citizen is even possible today, the civic terrain on all its levels
must be regained by its constituents and reconstituted in new
ways to render people socially operational. Civic reempowerment
of the citizen thus becomes a personal issue as well as a social one.
It Is equivalent to regaining oneâs private selfhood as well as oneâs
public selfhood, oneâs personality as well as oneâs citizenship.
----
To attain such reempowerment and self-reconstitution has its presuppositions. So much of civic participation and civic-mindedness
has been lost in this century, particularly its latter half, that we will
have to probe deeply into the buried history of the city and of
Citizenship for reference points by which to understand where we
Stand in the swirl of urbanization that surrounds us.
We will want to know what the concepts of âcityâ and âcitizenshipâ really meanânot simply as ideal definitions but as fecund
ecological processes that reveal the growth of communities and
the individuals who people themâindeed, that turn them into a
genuine public sphere and a vital body politic. It is painfully characteristic of our present-day myopia that these very words, public
Nphere and body politic, have simply dropped out of our social
vocabulary. When we use them at all, we rarely seem to understand what they mean or at least meant to earlier civilizations in
which we claim to have our civic and social roots. They have been
supplanted by such terms as âelectorateâ and, of course, âtaxpayersâ and âconstituentsââadministrative terms that denature the
concepts of politics and community by definition.
It also behooves us to examine the kind of institutions cities
have created to foster citizenship and public empowerment. A
romarkable number of conflicting institutional issues clustered
around the city as it meandered its way through different historical forms: decentralization versus centralization, direct democracy versus representative republicanism, assemblies of the people versus councils of deputies, recall and rotation of public
officials versus lengthy tenure in office and professional fixidity.
popular management of social affairs versus bureaucratic control
and manipulation. These issues have exploded repeatedly, from
ancient times to the present, into bitter civic conflicts. They persist
in our very midst under the rubric of âreformâ movement to alter
city charters and most recently as neighborhood movements to
establish âgrass-rootsâ democracy.
We will want to know how the high ideals of a free citizenry
with a sense of place in a cherished natural environment were
variously realized and lost, often to be regained for limited periods
of time in the same area or in other parts of the world. We will
have to ask how âcommunal libertyâ (to use Benjamin Barber s
phrase) has fared with the fortunes of the citizenry and how each
interacted with the other, for neither the cityâs forms of freedom
nor the citizen can be isolated from each other without doing
violence to the meaning of both. That urbanization eventually
separated from citification to take on a life of its own and ravage
the city and countryside, ecological as well as agricultural alike
will be an abiding theme in all we shall have to explore. This
separation begins with the massive institutional, technological,
and social changes that eventually dispossessed the citizen of his
or her place in the cityâs decision-making processes. Urbanization,
in effect, both presupposes and later promotes the reduction of the.
citizen to a âtaxpayer,â âconstituent,â or part of an âelectorate.â
We shall see that urbanization yields not only a drastic colonization of the countryside but also of the cityâs and the citizen s very
self-identity. Like the modern market, which has invaded every
sphere of personal life, we shall find that urbanization has swept
before it all the civic as well as agrarian institutions that provided
even a modicum of autonomy to the individual. Born of the city,
urbanization has been its parentâs most effective assailant, not to
speak of the agrarian world that it has almost completely undone.
It will be important to see the extent to which presumably
nonurban institutions, often remotely tribal in origin and rooted
in a more naturalistic society, became integral features of the
democratic city in the form of popular assemblies, neighborhood
councils, and the town meetings so redolent of an active municipalism and citizenship in our own day. Ironically, the same can be
said for feudal, theocratic, and monarchical institutions, with the
castle, temple, and palace as their centers. Indeed, we need go no
further, if we choose, than the American and French revolutions
to find that popular assemblies under different names have been
the principal means by which ordinary people fought out the
issues of justice and freedom with nobles, monarchs, and centralized nation-states. Each opposing camp has fought with the other
for civic and ultimately social sovereignty. The current legalistic
image of the city as a âcreatureâ of the state is not an expression
of contempt. It is an expression of fear, of careful deliberation in
a purposive effort to subdue popular, democracy. That the term
has been codified into laws, even in self-professed âdemocracies,â
expresses a dread of a menacing civic or municipal incubus in
every centralized social system, one that has always threatened to
dismember centralized power as such and restore the control of
society to a public that has been cruelly dispossessed of its very
identity..
History is an all-important vehicle in our enterprise, the counterpart of evolution in an ecological approach. The âpowers-that-beâ live in a compulsive fear of remembrance, a fear of humanityâs
social memory of past institutions, cultures, and the search for
origins. An essential theme of George Orwellâs **1984** is the effort
by a highly totalitarian state to eliminate the sense of contrast
earlier lifeways imposed as a challenge to existing ones. Thinking
itself had to be restructured to exclude this challenge by using
wordsâOrwellâs famous âNewspeakââthat attenuated their previous wealth of meaning and the disquieting alternatives that the
past posed to a fixed, eternalized, and ahistorical ânowâ or commitment to ânowness.â Previously, authority had rested on tradition, often in a highly distorted form; today, it rests oil conditioning, with no regard to a troubling past.
The purpose of Orwellâs âNewspeakâ Was to change thinking by
âthe invention of new words and by stripping such words as remained of unorthodox meanings, and insofar as possible of all
meanings whatever,â Words such, as âfree,â Orwell tells us, still
existed in âNewspeakâ but not âin its old sense ofâpolitically freeâ
or âintellectually free,â since political and intellectual freedom no
longer existed even as concepts and were therefore of necessity
nameless.â{1} One could only use the word âfreeâ in a strictly functional, amoral, and technical sense, such as in the statement âThis
dog is free from liceâ or âThis field is free from weeds.â âNewspeak was designed not to extend but diminish the range of
thoughtâ by a process of abbreviationâby rendering concepts
more functional than moral in nature and by dememorizing
thought (if I may coin a phrase) that was designed to uproot the
mind from a sense of continuity and contrast with a challenging
past.
compromises with an emphasis on ânownessâ and the cybernetic
language of electronic circuitry that is so fashionable today. The
pages that follow are thoroughly infused with history and its moral
meaning, and with language that is rich in secondary meanings.
The reader will find no words like âfeedback,â âinput,â âoutput,â
and âbottom lines,â which are currently used as substitutes for
processual and thought-laden terms such as dialogue, origins,
âexplanations,â âjudgements,â and âconclusions.â I have been at
pains to emphasize my use of history and traditional language for
a very distinct reason. This book deals with cities and citizenshipâtraditionally, the shared fate that confronts âtown and countryâ
in the modern eraâand the impact of urbanization upon personality, freedom, and humanityâs sensitivity to nature. But it is also
a book about morality and ethics. My concern with the way people
communeâthat is, actively associate with each other, not merely
form communitiesâis an ethical concern of the highest priority in
this work. I am concerned with the âsocial compactsâ people form
as ethical beings and the institutions they create to embody their
ethical goals.
To a great extent, this is the Greek, more precisely, the
Athenian, ideal of civicism, citizenship, and politics, an ideal, that
has surfaced repeatedly throughout history. I believe this ideal
forms a crucial challengeâdespite its many limitations for the
modern era. I propose to explore not only the ills of urbanization
insofar as they have subverted town and country (including the
natural environment), alike, but to explore the social and cultural
conditions that gave rise to communities, citizens, and a politics
whose high regard for personal activism has always made community the richest and most fulfilling expression of our humanity.
Conventional accounts of the cityâs origins tend today to be stridently technological: they anchor the emergence of the city in the
discovery of food cultivation, particularly its highly productive
form of animal-powered agriculture. The city, it is assumed, appeared because of the large food surpluses farming folk could
provide with the Neolithic technological innovations that marked
the cultivation of the land. With this new material plentitude at
their disposal, we are told, people began to detach themselves
from agricultural pursuits and develop their skills as potters, weavers, metallurgists, carpenters, jewelers, and masons, not to speak
of administrators, priests, soldiers, and artists. As agrarian villages
increased in size and density, they are said to have reached a
âcritical massââoften of undefinable sizeâthat apparently qualified them to be called âcities.â Generally, we tend to regard the
city itself as a sharp economic breach with the countryside,
marked by a typically urban development of crafts, administration, and, to use a grossly denatured word, âpolitics.â This new,
largely nonagrarian ensemble of activities produced what we like
to call âcivilizationâ: a literate world, culturally âenlightened,â
presumably more rational institutionally and technologically than
the agrarian, society on which, it reliedâin short, what the distinguished Marxian archaeologist, V. Gordon Childe, called the
âurban revolution/â
This conventional image of the cityâs origins projects a highly
modern view, largely ecbnomistic and progressivistic, onto the
past. It assumes that because we are primarily, economic beings
whose civic activities are deeply rboted in industrial, commercial,
and service occupations, our urban âforebearersâ gathered in
towns and cities to follow similar pursuits. They, too, we tend to
believe, conceived of the city as an economic enterprise, massively committed to nonagrarian tasks. We are prepared to concede that in a more âbarbarousâ era early city dwellers were also
preoccupied with their safety or defense from rival cities or pastoral nomads. Hence, they congregated in great numbers behind
defensive palisades and fortified walls. While defensive concerns
might account in part for early urban density, they too were a
function of economic concerns in modern eyes, just as we, today,
assign economic motivations to what we also call defense by
nation-states and imperialistic blocs. Thus we assume that our
urban âforebearersâ were very much like us. They were economic
beings who were busily engaged in the pursuit of their material
interests within the fixed confines of a structural and territorial
entity called the âcity.â
With equal alacrity we assume that just as they shared our
economic lifeways (albeit in a more rudimentary fashion), they
also shared our civic attitudes. Although we are likely to concede
that their sense of communal loyalties was stronger than ours, we
often believe that they judged their cities with a shared viewpoint
like ours. However exotic many of their civic institutions seem in
the light of our own, we tend to believe that their notion of citizenship was essentially as self-serving and self-interested as our own.
They participated in civic affairs to the degree that their material
interests were involved, and essentially their interests were no less
economic than our own. Unwittingly, we subject their civic-mindedness as well as their âcivilization to the very economistic class
analyses we profess to reject in the name of our âhigher idealsâ
and âmorals,â however much these are honored in the breach.
This view is greatly reinforced by the historical literature at our
disposal. Athens, we are reminded, had its *demos*; Home, its **plebs**;
the medieval commune, its *popolo*, just as we have our proletariat
and lower middle classes who live in gnawing envy or hatred of
their aristocratic and bourgeois elites. We are reminded that such
Lorms as âancient,â âmedieval,â and âmodernâ should not impel
118 to greatly distinguish the unalterable content of human nature,
that human beings will seek to satisfy their egoistic impulses despite all their ideological avowals to the contrary. This excursion
Into an unvarying psyche that lies at the core of human behavior
defines the city dwellerâparticularly the citizenâwith the same
modern attributes that define our contemporary metropolitan
dwellers. Hence, we comfortably sit back before the vast tableau
of urban historical development with a sense of self-assurance that
Our contemporary ills are as ancestral and incorrigibly âhumanâ
as our biological attributes and pathologies. They belong to us as
assuredly as the human brain, human fingers, and ingrained
human psychological traits that our species shares with its ancestors and with its heirs.
----
If the city provides any evidence of human association and the immutability of human behavior, a serious account of its rise and
development in no way supports this simplistic and conventional
Imagery. It would be difficult to find one all-embracing reason that
oxplains the emergence of a settled human collectivity such as a
village, much less a population of thousands that we would expect
to find in a city. The earliest cities archaeologists have unearthed
do not seem to have been based on advanced forms of food cultivation, notably animal r powered plow agriculture, a point that Jane
Jacobs has so ably highlighted in her book **The Economy of Cities.**
Although it is doubtful that an âurban revolutionâ gave rise to an
âagricultural revolution,â as Jacobs seems to contend, strong evidence exists that such very early cities as Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk in Anatolia
and Jericho of Biblical fame may have consisted of sizable communities that acquired much, perhaps most, of their food from the
hunting of game and the harvesting of undomesticated plants.
Much plants as were domesticated seem to have been recent
achievements of people who were harvesters of wild wheat varieties rather than experienced food cultivators. Bones of aurochsâthe extinct ancestors of modern cattleâas well as those of wild
deer, boars, asses, geese, and the skeletal remains of such predators as wolves, foxes, and leopards, suggest a âcitified population
of hunters and gatherers whose arts of gardening were of recent
origin. By conventional standards, this economic tableau does not
comfortably explain why a city such as Ăatal, with an estimated
population of at least 6,000 people occupying some 30 acres,
should have been able to flourish on two nearby sites 9,000 years
ago, many millennia before Mesopotamia became the region for
Childeâs celebrated âurban revolution.â
If Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk is to be accorded a major place m the origins o
the city, the reason for its existenceâindeed, for its persistence for
centuriesâseems primarily to have been religious. Although the
city was close to a rich source of obsidian that was almost certain y
bartered for a wide variety of nonindigenous foods it is most
conspicuous for its large number of religious shrines. James Melaart, who has provided us with detailed and richly interpretive
studies of the city, found no less than 40 shrines among the 139
buildings he examined. These shrines were generally larger than
the surrounding houses and decorated with elaborate religious
artwork, paintings on opposing walls that symbolized death in one
case and life in another...
Mellaart found no pottery in Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒkâone of the principal
hallmarks of Neolithic culture that, together with plow agriculture
and domesticated animals, would normally be associated with a
compact city of thousands. The thick walls of Ăatal, its pueblolike
houses, its small plazas, and its ornate artwork so visible to the
public suggest an intensely vivid religious fife that is equally suggestive of an intensely active civic life. Its tool kit and higly
naturalistic artistry suggest an ecologically oriented community of
late Paleolithic hunters and gatherers rather than an early neolithic community of food cultivators. The culture is marked by a
very sophisticated stone and bone technics, by markedly collective dwellings adorned with images of animals and shamanlike
figures amidst paintings of reindeer, leopards, and bow-carrying
hunters. If we are to judge by the considerable amount of comment Ăatal has elicitedâowing partly to Mellaartâs own interpretationsâthe occupants of the city were strikingly matricentric in
their orientation. Women figure highly in the symbolism of the
cityâs cults. The Mother Goddess is the most conspicuous figurine
that we find among the cityâs statuettes, and careful attention
seems to have been given to the internment of women and infants
in joint graves, presumably mothers and their children, a feature
that is absent in male burials. Nor do hierarchy and warfare seem
to be features of the cityâs social life. Judging from the size of
Ăatalâs dwellings and the implements found in burial remains, the
city was fairly egalitarian despite minor differences that are observable. There are no âobvious signs of violence or deliberate
signs of destruction,â Mellaart observes for the original city and its
nearby successor, both of which were simply abandoned for no
apparent reason after centuries of occupancy.{2} Cases of violent
death among the hundreds of skeletons examined on the sites are
notable for their absence.
If the emergence of a city as large as Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk cannot be
explained by a high degree of technical development or by warfare, it is interesting to note that an unknown people, already
familiar with the arts of planting, harvesting, and milling grains,
did not form any kind of permanent settlements on fertile soil as
early as 18,000 years ago, when ice sheets still covered vast portions of the European continent. Evidence of food cultivators has
been found quite recently adjacent to the Nile River at Wadi
Kubbaniya in upper Egypt. They were planting wheat, barley,
lentils, and chickpeas at a time when Magdelenian hunters were
still wandering over the European tundra of Spain and France,
leaving behind their celebrated wall paintings of animals in remote cave sites. The Wadi Kubbaniya people were not Neolithic
farmers, although by every precept of technological or economic
determinism they should have been. Their âdiversified agriculture did not lead directly to the beginnings of village life,â observed Fred Wendrof, Romauld Schild, and Angela E. Chase, who
unearthed the remains of these early food cultivators. âProbably
people continued their wandering ways as hunters and gatherers
for thousands of years more. Farming was just one more resource
in a broad-based way of life. These conclusions raise anew the
question of why civilization emerged.â{3}
In fact, it is fair to say that both the Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk and Wadi
Kubbaniya peoples, who may not have been particularly exceptional, raise the question, Why did âcivilizationâ (more precisely,
the drastic change from hunting and gathering to food cultivation
and civic social relationships) emerge at all? This question seems
shrouded in mystery because the changeover from one cultural
form to another seems to be more drastic than it actually was.
What Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk and the earliest food cultivators tell us is that
the transition from tribe to village and city was not the predictable
result, as archaeological orthodoxy would have it, of technological
change or, as more recent theories would claim, of population
pressure, war, or other drastic environmental pressures that might
have produced hunger on a large scale. In short, the transition
from tribe to city was not the necessary result of economists
relationships that our Euro-American minds foist upon prehistory
and history; nor was the transition, when it occurred, as deliciously
complete and sharply delineated with polarities of a war between town and country as theoretical orthodoxy would have us
believe.
Conversely, hunting and food-gathering peoples, who by all
conventional standards of archaeology seem to have lacked the
âeconomic baseâ for an urban society, actually formed sizable
cities and initially used a technics more akin to late Paleolithic
lifeways than Neolithic. As the anthropologists who studied the
Wadi Kubbaniya sites conclude, âThere does not, in fact, seem to
be any single âcauseâ for the beginnings of agriculture [and we may
reasonably add, the city]. It may well have begun as a natural
interaction between early peoples and the plant species they
came to exploit regularly. It probably happened many times in the
past, whenever Paleolithic peoples made extensive and sustained
use of plant resources. It is important in this instance because the
plants used [by the Wadi Kubbaniya people] were cereals, and
these cereals provided the economic base for the development of
our civilization. The rise of agriculture, however, did not lead
rapidly or inevitably to identifiable social or economic change. It
simply provided another resource in a broadly based hunting,
fishing, and gathering economy.â{4} I find this conclusion, with its
wayward suggestions and its shades of heterodoxy, all the more
tantalizing because its authors do, in fact, use the conceptual
framework and terminology of traditional archaeology with its
recourse to such words as economic base, resource, and exploit.
----
Which is not to say that cities congeal out of mere mist. Clearly a
city requires a tangible food supply, one that is sufficiently plentiful to support such nonagrarian strata as artisans, administrators,
and shamanlike priests to perform their specialties. If the remains
of Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk and the Wadi Kubbaniya cereal farmers suggest
anything, however, it is that early cities formed to meet cultural
rather than strictly economic or defensive needs. The shrines so
evident at Ăatal suggest that the population of the city was committed to the performance of religious rituals, that cultic and
priestly functions do more to explain why this city arose in Anatolia many millennia ago than do economic or military functions.
Paleolithic lifeways; richly elaborated by time and environmental
changes, may have been more tenacious than we have supposed
them to be. They may have been more attractive to tribal peoples,
even many self-anointed âcivilizedâ ones, or, at least, more deeply
rooted in the long evolution of human culture.
If this conclusion is sound, the urban and agricultural ârevolutionsâ so closely associated in the archaeological literature with
the rise of urban culture do not form an elegant fit by modern
standards. The rise of cities may have had more to do with shrines,
cultic practices, and temples rich in naturalistic symbols than with
the âdiscoveryâ of cereal cultivation, plows, and domesticated
animals. Not that the city gave rise to these agrarian basics, as Jane
Jacobs seems to suggest. Apparently, agriculture in a simple form
was known to hunters and food gatherers long before villages
began to dot the landscape that phased from the Paleolithic into
the Neolithic. But the shrine, later enclosed by a temple, may have
been more authentically a harbinger of the city than the plow, and
a quasireligious figure such as the shaman or priest may have been
an earlier civic leader than the politically astute chief. By the same
tokeri, the earliest âcitizenâ may have assumed his or her civic
functions as a member of a congregation rather than, as a âresidentâ of an urban district. The earliest civic center, in effect, may
have been a ceremonial area rather than a marketplace, a center
for the worship of natural deities and forces.
----
If this background accurately portrays the factors that gave rise to
the city and the functions of its residents, it highlights many features of early city life that contradict modern economistic biases
about urbanism, notably contemporary ones that visualize the city
as a business enterprise and its concerns as primarily fiscal or
commercial. Despite the highly sophisticated crafts that appear in
cities as differently situated in time from our own cities as Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk, there is no evidence of the existence of an internal market
within the community itself, and certainly very little beyond local
barter. A considerable amount of trade may have developed between cities or between a city and an essentially tribal community.
But trade inside the city itself was minimal or, at least, marginal.
To summarily repeat Karl Polanyiâs rich probing into what he was
to call âthe anonymity of the economy in early societyâ and his
compelling demolition of the view that the market was necessarily
the decisive element in the founding of the city would exhibit a
lack of appreciation for the thoroughness and elegance of his analysis.{5} Indeed, according to Polanyi, no domestic marketplace appears in early cities until Hellenic times, when the Athenian *agora*
became a modest center for exchanges of goods as well as intense
civic activity. Even so, Aristotle was to regard moneymaking as an
âunnaturalâ urge that required public control and self-restraint.
What early city dwellers actually exchanged with each other were
services. More precisely, men and women cojointly contributed
their share to the common fund of material goods. It was this
shared pool of the means of life that constituted the economic
lifeâ of tribal communities and early cities. People contributed, in
effect, their skills in growing food, in working wool and flax, in
crafting metals and stone, and, by no means of least importance,
their artistic and decorative talents in bejeweling and designing
artifacts for deities, priests, and members of their own community.
âPostulatesâ of âself-sufficiencyâ and the distinction between
ânatural and unnatural tradeâ are not strictly archaic. We find
them most self-consciously and philosophically stated in Greece.
But prior to the full flowering of the Hellenic *polis*, material life
in cities was deeply embedded in the blood ties, religious obligations, mutual loyalties, magical techniques, and the intensely naturalistic sensibilities of the tribal world. Guided more by custom
than rationally vdiced strictures, these form the psychological setting and institutional carryovers for the more rationalistic civilization we later find in the Greek archipelago. This unconscious tribal
and mutualistic substrate of obligation and association was, in fact,
more forceful as a guide for human behavior than its formulation
into a sophisticated civic and political philosophy or social theory.
In the so-called âprimitiveâ or archaic worlds, more than food
entered the âcommon pool,â Possibly, all things short of oneâs
closest possessions, including aspects of oneâs very identity, had a
highly collective aura that destined them to be shared or to be
used communally. Initially, if the city had a pronounced function
at all, it was a religious one. The strong emphasis that many anthropologists now place on political and centralized governmental
forms as institutions for efficiently redistributing produce from
ecologically different areas may be overstated. That great imperial
systems, such as those of the Incas, Aztecs, Babylonians, Egyptians,
Persians, and Chinese, were centers for collecting and redistributing a great variety of goods from highly diverse and distant ecological regions can hardly be faulted as a reality. Indeed, by imperial
times many ancient cities were as conspicuous for their warehouses as they were for their temples and palaces.
But such an emphasis on material function, like the highly deterministic strategies to explain the existence of every community
within our purview, betrays a very modern bias. It reveals a proclivity, almost an unthinking compulsion, to assign a âmaterial
roleâ to every phenomenon, particularly every institution and
form of association, that exists in the past as well as the present.
Worse, it crudely downgrades the richly associative role played by
material things such as gifts, which serve to foster a much deeper
human attribute: the need to be grounded in community, to enjoy
shared sensibilities that are spiritually supportive and without
which authentic individuality is chimerical. Human personality,
which is nurtured by parental care, kinship ties, friendship, and
the assurance or security provided by personal support systems,
becomes a material thingâa manipulatable object among many
other objects and commoditiesâprecisely when its immaterial
support systems are subverted and its traits reified. Quite an opposite case can be made for the belief, so widely promoted by contemporary âcultural materialists,â that chiefdoms, monarchies,
bureaucracies, armies, clerical hierarchies, and the unlimited investment they required were distributive agencies and processes
that served humanityâs âneeds,â mythic or real. It could be more
validly shown that they reflected a mania for domination that
created mythic âneedsâ and systems of control on a scale so harmful to the communities they were pledged to service that they and
their legacy of waste, destruction, and cruelty now threaten the
very : existence of society and its natural fundament, Indeed the
domination of nature was to have its roots in the domination of
human by human such that a credo of domination was to embrace
the planet.
But an important caveat must be voiced here when we speak
of a mania for domination that can so facilely be used to color our
image of the early, essentially temple, cities at the dawn of civic
life. By no means is it clear that the sacerdotal hierarchies that
emerged in these cities from Erech in Mesopotamia to Teobhuacan in Mexico immediately led to a hierarchical restructuring of
the fairly egalitarian tribal or village peoples on whom they dependedâpeoples who built their monuments, often massive in
size; who created their plazas, dwellings, and altars; who filled
their temple storehouses, erected their walls, and shaped the
sculptures that dazzle the modern eye. That such vast efforts with
their enormous mobilizations of labor could have been made for
purposes that seem so âprofitlessâ and âuselessâ by present-day
urban standards without coercion of the most authoritarian kind
seems unthinkable at first glanceâso much, in fact, that all early
temples and mortuaries are normally regarded as the work of
savagely coercive rulers and brutal tyrants.
But if this imagery is certainly true well into history, we have
no reason to believe that it reflects the social relationships that
gave us our earliest cities and their cultic structures at the dawn
of history. I have described elsewhere, in great detail, how an
egalitarian society may have slowly phased into an increasingly
hierarchical one-initially theocratic, ultimately feudal, and
finally monarchical.[1] Here, I would like to emphasize that the
earliest cities were largely ideological creations of highly complex, strongly affiliated, and intensely mutualstic communities of
kin groups, ecological in outlook and essentially egalitarian and
nondomineering in character. We do not know if a sizable city
like Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk, which dates back 9,000 years, or a hugely
monumental city like Teotihuacan, which was slowly erected
around 300 B.c. and ceased to be occupied around 800 A.D.,
were originally constructed by forcibly âmobilizingâ large numbers of âoppressedâ villagers in surrounding communities or, surprising as it may seem, whether they were voluntary enterprises
undertaken by devout âparishionersâ who viewed their civic responsibilities as a sort of âcalling.â We assume that a coercive
strategy was followed by oppressive elites at the inception of city
life because we read our literary accounts of Mesopotamian and
Egyptian forced labor back into city lifeways in a misty preliterate era. It is easy to. overlook the fact that any literary tradition
of urban, life, even the very early Gilgamesh epic that dates back
to the beginnings of Mesopotamian city life, is already evidence
of a technically advanced, often coercive, society. Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk,
Jericho, Erech, Teotihuacan, Monte Alban, and Tikal, to cite cities far-removed from modern urban development in the cultured areas of the Near East and the Americas, are mysteries to
us that we try to dispel with our own motivations and social interests. Yet their archaeological remains are rich with the evidence of ideological aspirations and human relationships that
were fundamentally different from our own secular onesâcultic
and communal sensibilities that viewed âthe cityâ (if such a word
can be used indiscriminately to encompass all sizable human settlements) as a monument to lifeways and sentiments that were
basically different from our own. Possibly, the ordinary people
who reared the monuments in the earliest of these cities were
closer in their outlook to the medieval artisans who often willingly gave of their time and skills to slowly erect over generations the great cathedrals of Europe. In either case, they speak to
a dedication that stands in marked contrast to the mentality of
the engineers and construction crews who are seeding the modern world with high-rise residential and office structures in urban areas of every continent.
[1] See Murray Bookchin: *The Ecology of Freedom* (Palo Alto: Cheshire Books,
1982), pp. 62â88
----
We are confronted, too, with the differences between early and
modern conceptions of âcitizenship.â How did ancestral âcitizensâ of the first cities view themselves? In what sense were they
different from usâor similar to us? By asking these questions, we
encounter a problem that lacks the degree of completeness and
fixity that we find in a physical structure such as the remains of a
temple or palace. Citizenship, as we shall see, is a process, not a
reality that is reducible to a concise, single-line definition. It does
not leap into being from a vacuum, surrounded by streets for
personal display, buildings into which the sovereign individual can
retreat, and dense populations that foster personal intercourse.
Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk, in fact, had no streets at all, to cite an intriguing
feature of the city. A pueblolike city, it had small squares but no
open byways. It lacked the streets that such modernists as Marshall
Berman and Richard Sennett regard as the structural essence of
urbanism, particularly in the form of wide boulevards in which the
monadic ego of our time can display itself in dandylike fashion and
assert its âindividuality.â One moved from one part of Ăatal to
another over rooftops, ascending or descending ladders, entering
into the recesses of dwellings and crossing small squares.
This is a significant personal fact, not merely a structural eccentricity. Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk must have been a highly collective community. It was intensely peopledâmore like a tribe than what we,
today, would call a city. Yet even by modern standards of urbanism such as size and density, it was a town, not a village. From a
historical perspective, given time and place, it was even an immense city if archaeological calculations of its populations are
remotely correct. What does this tableau mean? In what sense
were its men and women âurbanâ? We can surmise that they were
not mere âresidentsâ of the city or the ancestral members of
modern-day âconstituencies.â They were not burdened by the
anonymity and awesome sense of personal isolation that is the
most characteristic trait of the modern urban dweller. In some
sense, they were âprotocitizensâ of a highly articulated and richly
textured community in which a high sense of collectivity, nourished by such organic facts as kinship ties and a sexual division of
labor, was integrated with the civic facts of politically defined
rights and duties. They were communities in transition between
the biological realities of the tribal world, rooted in blood ties,
gender, and age groups, and the political realities of the urban
world, rooted in residential propinquity, vocational mobility, and
legal prerogatives. Early cities probably did not contain citizens in
the sense of self-empowered individuals ethically united by ideals
of civic virtue, rational in their social policies, and completely free
to participate through discourse and practice in the management
of their citiesâin short, those attributes that Greek social thinkers
were to call *phronesis*, the practical reason involved in creating
and managing a community. All the evidence we have of these
protocitizens suggests that their power for social action was
largely controlled by obligations to kin groups and theocrats, their
ideals guided more by faith than reason, their sense of virtue more
pragmatic than ethical, and their social institutions more biologically derivative than cultural in character.
Yet these seemingly uncivic features provided a crucially important matrix for what was to grow into the highly sophisticated
classical notion of the âcitizen.â If social empowerment seemed to
derive more from such group attributes as the family or the clan
than from personal attributes, the individual living in these cities
enjoyed a real sense of power as such, not a body of conferred
rights that were more formal and juridical than substantive. Tribal
societies are known that exhibit a high degree of respect for individual uniqueness and free will, however much custom and public
opinion seem to place limits on personal behavior. One cannot
simultaneously deny the existence of primitive individuality while
acknowledging the existence of a fairly spontaneous ego and considerable self-assertion among, say, certain hunting and gathering
communities such as the pygmies of the Ituri Forest who include
outrageously boastful men and extremely shrewd women. By
their marked presence, such personal traits as boastfulness and
shrewdness, indeed humor, gaeity, and reflectiveness, frankly contradict the conventional image of preliterate peoples as divested
of ego and personality, the modern claim to individuality. The
contemporary neurotic notion of personality may not have been
as common among so-called primitives as it is today in the metropolitan areas of Europe and America, although by no means is it
absent. But individuality certainly exists among remaining preliterate communities, albeit in a different form and faced by more
overt constraints than our own, notably where the rules of the
game are fairly explicit and mutualistic in contrast to our modern,
highly engineered society, which bombastically celebrates its formal âfreedomsâ and tries to ignore its lack of social concern.
----
Surprisingly, citizenship and the political forms that foster it would
be difficult to explain without looking precisely at those primal
organic institutionsâparticularly clanlike relationships, popular
assemblies or the various councils that spin off from them, and the
egalitarian outlook, in sum, the tribalismâthat the city, in the
conventional wisdom of the recent past, was supposedly designed
to overcome. Rousseau was to pithily observe that âhouses make
a town but citizens make a city.â{6} Yet he would have been no less
surprised than all the major social theorists of his day to learn that
the most important attributes, of citizenship derive more directly
from the tribal world than the village world, from rude shelters
rather than houses. Houses may make towns, even huge urban
belts that subvert the conditions for an active, participatory body
politic, but simple huts and tentsâthe âprimitiveâ dwellings of
hunting, gathering, and pastoral peoples^âprovided the homes for
institutions and social types that often embodied the civic ideals
we associate with citizenship.
Notions of human scaleâof communities that are modest in size
and comprehensible politically and logistically to their residents
are distinctly tribalistic in character and origin. They are formed
from the idiom of a civic mentality that is rooted in familial loyalties andâextended kinship relationships. Not surprisingly, many
early cities, insofar as they leave any written account that is open
to us, are. âfoundedâ entities. Their âancestryâ originates in a
shared deity or a delineative progenitor with some kind of personal embodiment. The Sons of Aeneas, the Trojan hero who
âfoundedâ Rome in the cityâs urban mythology, are no different
in principle than the Children of Israel and the Biblical Jacob who
was the patriarchal ancestor of the Hebrew tribes. The word âcitizen,â in fact, appears sporadically, or late in the history of cities.
Quite commonly, the âcitizensâ of a community denoted themselves as âbrothers,â a term in widespread use throughout the
Middle Ages and early Renaissance. Men and women in the towns
and cities of the past visualized their relationships in terms of
familial connections. As âstrangersâ began to form the majority of
urban dwellers in late classical and medieval cities, this familial
imagery with its emphasis on smallness of scale, accessibility of
person, and close-knit support systems of the kind we associate
With âhumanly scaledâ communities became the outlook and prerogative of urban elites, notably the municipal aristocrats and!
nobles who staked out a real or legendary claim to the cityâs âfounder.â Ultimately, the newer, dwellers of the city, too, formed their
own âbrotherhoodsâ in which ties, rights, arid duties were solemnized by blood oaths and kinshiplike rituals. In time, the word
âbrotherâ became an ecumenical form of civic address and affiliation, spanning class ties and interests.
The civic institutions that we most commonly associate with a
âparticipatory democracyâ often reach back in almost unbroken
continuity to tribal assembles. It is fairly certain that face-to-face
assemblies of the people in ancient cities were often the keystone
of the civic institutional arch and extensions of tribal assemblages
with their remote origins in primitive egalitarian relationships. So,
100, the notions of consensus where it existed, prolonged discourse
with its goal of arriving at a commonality of views, and a sense of
agreement were pronounced features of such a radical political
(lomocracy. By contrast, councils, the representative organs of
assemblies, patently originate in the smaller assemblies of elders,
chiefs, and warriors. As contractions of the popular assemblyâthe
âvoice of the peopleâ as distinguished from the people themselvesâthey are ubiquitous features of a tribalistic view of the reduced
assembly projected into republican concepts of self-governance.
----
Yet here, too, I must add a caveat that initially seems to break the
continuity of the development from tribe to city. The city may
continue the traditions of the tribe institutionally into a rich skein
of participatory, indeed ecological relationships, but it also constitutes its antithesis biologically. The city is the perpetuator of the
kin group insofar as the latter is a parochial expression of blood ties
I hut exclude the strangerâthe outsiderâwho cannot claim a common ancestry with the brothers and sisters. Tribalism is equatable
with familial exclusivity, not only familial solidarity. The distinction between exclusivity and solidarity is crucial here. Whether
He live or real, tribalism has its universal solvent in blood, the
medium that accords equality or *isonomia* (to use the Hellenic
term) to its members. Theoretically, one does not join a tribe; one
is born into it or, at most, adopted by it because of the services it
requires. Adoption involves elaborate rituals that transform the
outsider into an insiderâan âinorganicâ being, to use Marxâs formulation, into an âorganicâ part of the community.
The city breaks this biological spell, with its ecological aura,
however fictive it may be in reality. It exorcises the blood oath
from the family with its parochial myths and its chauvinistic exclusivity, while retaining or reworking its concept of socialization.
Paternity is given a high place in the civic firmament of values, but
the fathers are slowly divested of their absolute powers over the
sonsâsons who are needed by the city to perform administrative
and military services. The stranger is denied formal legal status in
the cityâs system of governance but is admitted into the magic
circle of civic protection and solicitude, especially if bearing skills,
wealth, and material resources.
But the ecological aura remains as legend by hypostasizing the
cityâs founders, the ethnic continuity of its citizens, the status of
its rulers, although reality enhances the hidden powers of the
newer residents who can claim no tie to the civic progenitors.
Hence, the city creates a special kind of social space. A projection
of familial and tribal forms, the city subverts the authentic substance of the parochialism that flavors kinship ties with a mysterious inwardness and rescues tribal institutions as ecumenical forms
of civic administration. The Greek democrat, Kleisthenes, is almost a symbol of these shrewed maneuvers, maneuvers by no
means unique to the Athenian *polis*. To break the hold of family
ties that obstructed the power of civic institutions, the citizenry
was organized into territorial âwards,â but each âwardâ was felicitously called a âtribe.â The municipal space of Athens, in effect,
was expanded to create a largely civic citizenry, unencumbered
by the mindless tribal obligations and blood oaths that impeded
the rights of the stranger but in a form that wore the symbols and
enjoyed the prestige of tribal tradition. Indeed, one of the great
tasks of ecological thinking will be to develop an ecological civicism that restores the organic bonds of community without reverting to the archaic blood-tie at one extreme or the totalitarian âfolk
philosophyâ of fascism at the other.
Politics has acquired a fairly odious reputation among the great
majority of people today. The word seems to denote techniques
for the unsavory end of exercising power over human beings. We
âplay politicsâ not only on an international national, and local
scale; we do so in domestic relations, in schools and places of
learning, in ordinary jobs or extraordinary careers. Politics, in
effect, is seen to have invaded the most private recesses of our
lives. At worst, it is viewed as oppressive, manipulative, cunningly
seductive, and basically degrading. Few words more readily evoke
a contemptuous sneer than the term âpolitician.â Conceived instrumentally as a means to control people, politics is regarded as
inherently corruptive of both its user, the politician, and the public on whom it is used. The ideal of a political life earns few acolytes
among people with any degree of moral probity. Traditional conservatives and anarchists alike identify it with the state and preach
a message of the attenuation or outright abolition of âpolitical
power.â Liberals and socialists rarely celebrate politics as a
desideratum, but they wed it so closely to the stateâa necessity
in modern liberal and socialist theoryâthat its practice is seen as
unavoidable in a highly imperfect world.
Modern social ideologies tend to blend politics with the state
almost unthinkinglyâand often throw society into the brew for
good measure. The confusion on this score is massive. Just as there
are many people who, by virtue of the all-pervasive role the state
plays in their private lives, draw no distinction between âgovernmentâ and âsociety,â so an incalculable number are incapable of
distinguishing between the state and âpolitics. These attitudes
and they are often, little moreâare justified today by ordinary
experience, as we shall see. That the social, political, and âstatifiedâ are not synonymous, indeed, that they are broadly demarcatable arenas with histories and identities of their own, is so far
removed from the publicâs mind that to distinguish them seems
paradoxical.[2] The equatability of political with state activities is
taken as a given. The penetration of the two, normally conceived
as one common phenomenon, into private affairs still encounters
considerable resistance, although in the form of a psychological
tension that finds expression in existential resistance such as petty
violations of the law rather than ideological clarity.
[2] How paradoxical can be judged by the fact that âstatifiedâ is a word I have had
to create for my own needs to denote the extent of the stateâs penetration into
social and political life. It does not exist in the English language. This term, which
I used extensively in my *Post-Scarcity Anarchism*, produced numerous tiffs with
a dedicated editor and repeated misprints with a knowledgeable printer.
In recent years, however, serious attempts have been made to
probe the distinction between âsocietyâ and politics, which has
traditional roots in theoretical distinctions between, society and
the state. The anarchists have been saying for years what everyone
either knows or feels: the state is not the same kind of phenomenon as the family, workplace, fraternal and sororal groups, religious congregations, unions and professional societies, in short, the
âprivateâ world that individuals create or inherit to meet their
personal and spiritual needs. This personal world can be designated as âsocial,â however much âgovernmentâ penetrates, regulates, or, in totalitarian states, absorbs its forms. It is a world that
has deep roots in what Marx and later Hannah Arendt were to
designate as the ârealm of necessity,â a world where the individual satisfies the conditions for his or her personal survival. Here,
biology provides the soil for a system of self-maintenance such that
people have a culturally conditioned but systematic way of reproducing their kind, feeding and clothing themselves, satisfying
their needs for shelter and the support systems for resisting an
inclement, presumably âcruel, mute, and blind natural world.â
----
To have sharpened the distinction between the social and the state
is one of the major contributions of traditional anarchist theory.
That there could be a political arena independent of the state and
the social, however, was to elude most radical social thinkers, even
so intense a political âthinker as Marx who allowed for âdemocraticâ states that could âevolveâ toward socialism and âBonapartistâ states that stood above and balanced off conflicting class interests. The reformist wing of Marxian socialism was by no means
alone when it envisioned a pliable state that could be used for
socialist interests. Its own âfounding fathersâ:â were no less riddled
with uncertainties about the nature of the state than the reformists
are today.
The emergence of the political realm as unique has a complex
background in the history of ideas,. Politics as a phenomenon distinguishable from the state and from social life initially appears in
the extant writings of Aristotle, perhaps the most Hellenic of the
Greek social theorists and philosophers. With Aristotle we are still
dealing in terms of human association on the level of the city, or
to be more precise, the *polis*, which is commonly mistranslated as
the âcity-state!â. [3]
[3] Quite often, in fact, the word *polis*, for which there is no comparable term in
English, is translated as *state*.
By the middle of the fifth century B.C., when the Athenian
democracy was approaching its high point of development, the
concept of a stateâof a professionalized bureaucratic apparatus
for social controlâwas notable for its absence; Attic Greek
contains no word for state. The term is Latin in origin, and its
etymological roots are highly ambiguous. It more properly
denotes a personâs condition in lifeâhis or her status or way
of life and âstandingââthan a commonwealth or a state in the
modern sense of the term. Not until the early sixteenth century,
when we witness the rise of authentic nation-states and highly
centralized monarchies, does the word come to mean a professional civil authority with the power to govern a âbody politic.â
There is a very real sense in which the evolution of the word
broadly reflects the evolution of the state itself. Not that state
powers were rarities in the ancient and medieval worlds. Eric
Vogelinâs âcosmologicalâ empiresâMesopotamian, Egyptian,
Persianâand the more âecumenicalâ Roman empire were certainly states in the sense that they controlled vast resources, dominated millions of people, and were structured along highly professional, rationalized, and bureaucratic lines. State institutions
emerged very early in human history, although in varying degrees
of development and stability, often in âbits and pieces,â as it were,
with highly tribalistic features. The Pharaonic state in the Nile
valley already reached back thousands of years, perhaps beyond
the unification of northern and southern Egypt, long before the
Roman empire had begun its long decline.
Athens had a âstateâ in a very limited and piecemeal sense.
Despite its governmental system for dealing with a sizable slave
population, the âstateâ as we know it in modern times could
hardly be said to exist among the Greeks, unless we are so reductionist as to view any system of authority and rule as statist. Such
a view would grossly simplify the actual conditions under which
humanity lived in the âcivilized world.[4] Until recent times, professional systems of governance and violence coexisted with richly
articulated community forms at the base of societyâcity neighborhoods in the worldâs few large urban areas, self-contained
towns and villages, a network of extended kinship ties, a great
variety of vocational, mutual-aid, and fraternal groupsâwhich
were largely beyond the reach of centralized state authorities. In
fact, these distinctly social formations were necessary to the maintenance of the state. They were sources of its revenues, its military
personnel, and, in many cases, the source of many labor services
for a great variety of public and religious tasks.
[4] I use the word âcivilizedâ throughout this book to mean literally the world of
the *civitas* or city in the broad Latin sense this term was used, not in any culturally
pejorative sense. Readers of my book, *The Ecology of Freedom*, will know that the
word denotes no monumental advance in the human condition over so-called
âprimitiveâ societiesâapart from certain technical and scientific amenities that
may have lightened humanityâs material burdens.
The Athenian democracy, if anything, was the opposite of a
professionalized system of governance organized strictly for social
control. If we choose to translate the word for the Athenian *polis*
as âstate,â which is done with appalling promiscuity, we would
have to assume that the notion of a state is consistent with a body
politic of some forty thousand male citizens, admittedly an elite
when placed against a still larger population of adult males possibly three times that number who were slaves and disenfranchised
resident aliens. Yet the citizens of Athens could hardly be called
a âclassâ in any meaningful sense of the term. Indeed, within this
body politic, we encounter economic distinctions that run the
entire gamut of material resources from the wealthy to the impoverished.
We would also have to assume that the notion of a state is
consistent with a consciously amateur system of governance,
based on almost weekly popular assemblies, a judicial system
structured around huge juries that represent the assemblies on an
attenuated scale, the selection and rotation of civic officials by
sortition, that is, the use of the lot, and the absence of any political
professionalism or bureaucratism, including military forces that
are authentic militias of armed citizens rather than professional
soldiers.
----
These few remarks do not do full justice to the Athenian system of
democracy, notably its high level of consciousness, civicism, commitment, and esthetics. They must suffice for the present to understand how politics was created on the rare occasions when it appeared in history with a reasonable degree of authenticity, and
how it was conceived by its most renowed theorist, Aristotle. It is
to Aristotle that we must turn for the earliest known distinctions
between the social and political realms, the household and the
public arena. The state was not alien to Aristotle; it existed as
monarchy and tyranny, as everyone could see among the states
that surrounded the Athens of Periclesâs day. And they were as
easily confused with the *polis* by Aristotle and his students, just as
we, today, confuse *politikos*, the administration of the *polis*âs
affairs, with the state. What was central to Aristotleâs thought,
however, was the *polis*, not that ambiguous phenomenon, the
state. What is central to modern thought, by contrast, is the state
not politics or, strictly speaking, the affairs of administering an
entity that could pass for a *polis*. Hence, although politics and the
state intermesh in both cases, they do so in very different ways and
from remarkably different perspectives.
This distinction should not be reduced to a simple difference of
vantage points toward a shared phenomenon. Aristotle and the
modern social theorists are, in fact, looking at two very dissimilar
worlds. The difference becomes very evident in Book Seven of
Aristotleâs Politics where the proper size of the âidealâ *polis* is
discussed. Both Aristotle and most modern social theorists would
agree that a community that is very small risks the possibility, if
it relies primarily on its own resources, of inadequately furnishing
its inhabitants with the means of existence, much less providing
for the âgood life,â however one chooses to interpret this highly
problematical phrase. Almost presciently, Aristotle derides, the
view that a communityâs greatness is to be judged by its demographic and territorial size. Important as numbers and resources
may be, a *polis* with too large a population and area cannot have
a âgood legal government.... Law [*nomos*] is a form of order, and
good law must necessarily mean good order; but an excessively
large number cannot participate in order: to give it order would
surely be a task for divine power, which holds the universe together. Hence the *polis* also must necessarily be the most beautiful with whose magnitude it combines the above-mentioned limiting principle; for certainly beauty is usually found in number and
magnitude, but there is a due magnitude for a *polis* as there is for
all thingsâanimals, plants, tools,â otherwise it will lose âits true
natureââ as well as workability. Summing up this remarkable body
of notions, Aristotle concludes âthat the best limiting principle for
a *polis* is the largest expansion of the population with a view to
self-sufficiency that can be taken in at one view.â{7}
Probably no modern social theorist would reason out this case
for âbeautyâ *qua* âmagnitudeâ and âlimitâ *qua* âtrue natureâ as
the essence of a community. The ease for human scale has been
argued by heterodox urbanologists on logistical, democratic, and
esthetic grounds; but rarely, if ever, has it been argued on ethical, indeed metaphysical, grounds. A community âthat can be
taken in at one viewââthat is, decentralized, comprehensible,
and attractiveâwhich Aristotle and his modern counterparts regard as a desideratum, is rooted in many, similar but also many
different premises. Aristotle speaks to us from an age that found
In magnitude and harmony the essence and, in the âtrue natureâ
of a human community, the limit to a *polis*. An ethical pragmatism pervades Aristotleâs remarks that qualitatively differs from
the instrumental pragmatism of the modern urbanologist, however much the two share a common practical view of human consociation.
Politics, in turn, is also inseparable in Aristotleâs mind from its
ethical context. Men are âanimals,â a fact that greets us early on
In the *Politics*, but they are animals of a very special kind. It is
manâs destiny or *telos*, if he is to fulfill his âtrue nature,â to live in
the *polis*. A *polis*, however, is more than a community or *koinonia*.
It is a *koinonia* that has reached the ideal form of a shared commonality of purpose among men whose self-realization is the âgood life.â
The âgood life,â in turn, includes a degree of material self-sufficiency that goes beyond mere survival. But it does not consist
in on appetite for goods, with all its attendant excesses, that clouds
manâs ethical and intellectual clarity. Man transcends his animality
insofar as he has reason and speech, or *logos*, which combines both
lit tributes in the ability to symbolize verbally and generalize logically. But these abilities do not guarantee that man has reached or
oven approximates the fulfillment of his potentialities. Institutions
must exist that constitute the means for achieving human self-fulfillment; a body of ethics must exist that gives the required
Institutions substance as well as form; a wealth of social activities
must be cultivated in the civic center or *agora* of the *polis*, the
gymnasium, and in the theater as well as the popular assembly and
courts to nourish, interactions and discourse; a mode of character
development and education, both of which are combined in the
(Ireek word *paideia*, must be at work to enrich the interactions
among men and thereby foster the growth of ethical and intellectual insight.
Underlying these various âmeansâ is Aristotleâs emphasis on
human solidarity or *philia*, which includes friendship (the common English translation for the Greek term) but which is a word
more far-reaching in its connotation of civic commonality. The
Intimacies of friendship may be reserved for a limited few, but
which is to say that he is destined not only to live in a community
but also to communize. In criticizing Lylcophron the Sophist, who
contends that the *polis* is a âmere allianceâ among men to prevent
them from inflicting harm on each other (Hobbesâs later view of
the âsocial contractâ) and promote the exchange of goods to satisfy
their individual needs, Aristotle argues that the *polis* is an end in
itself, the realization of manâs need for consociation apart from its
material benefits. âIf men formed the community and came together for the sake of wealth,â he declared, âtheir share in the
that the argument of the champions of oligarchy would appear to
be valid... ; but if on the other hand the *polis* was formed not
for the sake of fife only but rather for the good life... and if its
object is not military alliance for defence against injury by anybody, [and] it does not exist for the sake of trade and of business
relations,â the *polis* would be more than a community and its
citizens would âtake civic virtue and vice into their purview.â
Indeed, lacking a concern for âcivic virtue and vice,â men would
form communities no different from those of animals or slaves,
who are simply concerned with survival. Communities united by
mere economic and military alliancesâand, here, Aristotle has the
Etruscans and Carthaginians in mindâwould be no different from
the associations other people establish who, for all âagreements
about imports and covenants [to abstain] from dishonesty and
treaties... for mutual defence,â have no âofficials in commonâ and
take no âconcern as to the moral character of the other.â{8}
By contrast, the household is the sphere of mere survival, the
place to which our *zoon politiken* repairs to satisfy his biological
need for food, clothing, shelterâin sum, the ârealm of necessityâ
to cite Marxâs commonly used phrase. It is the domain of the manâs
wife, children, kin, and slaves where an apolitical âkingshipâ (patriarchy) prevails. Here, the manâs relationship between his own
person and the members of his domestic group is determined not
by *logos* but by need, and the social tie is strictly one of ârulerâ
and âruled.â âThe family,â we are bluntly told by Aristotle, âis the
association established by nature for the supply of menâs everyday
wants...â{9}
But men aspire for more and accordingly group their families
together to form villages. To the extent that villages are transformed by manâs potential for the good life into ethical and cultural communities, the *polis* begins to appear. The family still exists
to satisfy manâs animal wants. Hence the two worlds of the social
and political emerge, the latter from the former. Aristotleâs approach to the rise of the *polis* is emphatically developmental and,
in this way, resembles Platoâs account of the rise of the âideal
whole from the growth of a social and biological part, a realm of
the latent and the possible. Family and village do not disappear in
Aristotleâs treatment of the subject, but they are encompassed by
the fuller and more complete domain of the *polis*.
[5] Literally, *politea*. The word *republic*âthe Latin for *res publica*, literally *public things*âhas no meaning or analogue in Greek, and, in this writerâs view, no
place in the title of Platoâs famous dialogue.
The distinction between the social and political in Aristotleâs
thinking is strikingly processual: the difference is explained by the
growth and development of the social into the political, not by
their polarization and mere succession. The state has not yet
emerged in a form that gives it a uniqueness apart from the other
two domains. âBuieâ properly belongs to the family. Where it does
appear in the *koinonia*, it is simply a brute extension of the patriarchal family to the civic world (*monarchia*) or it takes the form
of a despotism ruled by a tyrant (*tyrannos*). And Aristotle views
monarchies and tyrannies as warped or unfinished forms of civic
administration that are unbecoming to a *polis*, although rule by
a monarch with its traditional constraints on the ruler is to be
preferred to rule by a tyrant, which is the arbitrary supremacy of
one man.
Nor does he prefer the rule of the few over the manyâan
aristocracy at best and an oligarchy at worst. By the same token,
democracy that Aristotle understands to be the rule of the many
over the fewâspecifically, a condition where the âpoorâ rule over
the âwealthyââis by no means desirable, although he does not
seem to find it as abhorrent as arbitrary one-man rule.
The best-ordered *polis* is structured around a system of governance where the most ethically and materially meritorious stratum
of the population manages the *polis*âs affairs in the interests of all.
This âpolityâ or âmeritocracy,â as it has been called, is an ethical
union that simultaneously yields the âgood lifeâ in a moral and
material sense. Politics consists of the practical reason (*phronesis*)
and action (*praxis*) that enters into such a felicitous *koinonia*.
----
Athenian politics was nothing if it was not vital, indeed voluble, and
popular in every sense of the term. Within a span of some three
centuries, the Athenian people and their renegade aristocratic
surrogates such as Solon, Kleisthenes, and Perikles were to dismember the traditional feudal system of Homeric times, wage a
steady war against privilege within the citizen body, and turn the
popular assembly from a lifeless, rarely convened mass meeting
into a vital on-going forum for making major decisions, thereby
opening public life to every Athenian adult male. Power ceased to
be the prerogative of a small, well-born stratum of the population.
It became a citizen activity. Athensâs historic calendar is marked
by seething upsurges of the people, startling fluctuations between
aristocratic rule, tyranny, limited popular government, until, by
the latter half of the fifth century B.C., Athenian political life stabilized around a face-to-face democracy of the most radical kind. We
may assume that similar developments occurred: in many Hellenic
In any case, in recorded history we have no structure comparable to the Athenian democracy. Popular assemblies such as the
New England town meeting and the Parisian revolutionary sections of 1793â94 were to appear elsewhere over time. The Swiss
Confederation is one of the few among many aborted or incomplete examples where popular control formed the underpinnings
of an on-going political system. Athens, however, is unique historically in that the *polis* fostered a degree of citizen participation not
only in the decision-making activities of the assembly but in the
everyday politics of the *agora* that impelled its admirers over the
ages to regard it with uncritical adulation as evidence of a âpureâ
democracyâand its opponents as evidence of a horrendous
âmobocracy.â
If politics is taken to be a form of popular activity in administering public life that, strictly speaking, is neither a, state, conceived
as a highly professionalized system of governance, nor a âsociety,â
conceived as forms of personal association for promoting survival
and well-being, the Atheniansâ could be said to have literally
created politics. It was a parochial politics by modern âglobalâ
definitions of the term: civic rather than regional in,scale, limited
to a minority of the population, Hellenic in its purview of the
âcivilizedâ world, contemptuous of slaves, women, the âbarbariansâ beyond the confines of the Greek *ethnos*, and resident aliens
who performed much of skilled work and engaged in most of its
trading activities.
Qualitatively, however, Athens made up in depth what it lost
In scope. It may well be, as the Jewish Zealots were to believe, that
a special insight of a spiritual or moral nature is the privilege not
Of great empires but of small communities on the margins of the
great classical ecumenes. Both peoples, the Hellenes and the Israelites, provide visible evidence of the truth that may be hidden
In this seemingly self-serving conviction. Yet a âcreationâ had
Certainly emerged that opened a new dispensation in human
affairs. A new realm of life had appeared, the political realm,
winch was to acquire many different meanings but whose origins
in classical Greece still keep faith with the pristine values and
practices that impart meaning to those ill-used words, the âpublic
sphere.â
The Roman Republic, which looms high in its impact on the
Euro-American political tradition, stands in marked, contrast to
the Athenian notion of a public sphere., Polybius, the Greek
chronicler of Romeâs rise to world hegemony, offers us the classical
theory of republican, government, a theory that was to deeply
affect the thinking of American and French constitutionalists in
the eighteenth century.
According to Polybius, the virtues of monarchy were embodied
III the consuls, the two chief magistrates of the Republic. The
Sonate provided the Republic with the advantages of aristocracy,
with its gradations in descending order of consular, praetorian,
aedilitian, tribunitial, and quaestorial ranks. The image of the
Roman Senate freely debating public issues is essentially a myth:
no senator could voice his views on an issue unless the presiding
consul solicited his opinion, and these requests were directed in
a strict hierarchical sequence that often left little time for oratory
by the bodyâs lower orders. Finally, democracy was represented
by several assemblies of the people. These assemblies (some four
have been identified) reflected, in their variety and ascendancy,
the fortunes of the plebeians and other lowly orders in their conflicts with the ruling patriciate. Whatever their origins, Roman
popular assemblies elected all the magistrates of Rome, some of
whom, such as the tribunes and praetors, had enormous control
over other branches of the government during their heyday.
Assemblies could be used by ambitious politicians to bypass the
Senate and enact laws that the ruling oligarchies opposed. Hence,
two political strategies existed during the more fervent periods of
the republican era: an oligarchical one and a popular one. The
of republican times. A complex mix of weighted voting groups
sorted out according to military status and, later, according to
classes based on property and age, the assembly was highly structured along hierarchical lines. It elected Romeâs consuls, praetors,
and censorsâeach successively forming the most important or
prestigious magistrates of the republic. The elective functions of
the *comitia centuriata* were to be slowly supplanted by the Roman
tribal assembly, the *comitia tributa*, largely based on territorial
divisions in which 35 tribes were classified into 31 rural tribes and
4 urban ones. Coexisting with both of these ranked assemblies, the
<em>plebs</em> had their own exclusive *concilium plebis* from which all
patricians were excluded. The *concilium* chose its own tribunes
and aediles, the latter constituting officials who administered public works and police and took charge of the grain supply and games
that gave the city such ill-famed distinction.
We owe the word âplebisciteâ (*plebiscitia*) to the right of the
plebeian tribunes to submit laws for the approval of the *concilium*.
Either the *Campus Martius* along the westward bend of the Tiber
or the Forum constituted the principal meeting places for these
assemblies, and discussion, if it occurred at all, was minimal. Laws,
edicts, declarations of war were presented to the people by officials such as consuls, praetors, and tribunes; elections and confirmations were voted upon methodically. We cannot say with certainty that Roman popular assemblies were simply mute. Before
the assemblies divided into their specific units, the highly structured *comitia* was preceded by a loosely organized *contio* where
discussion may have been possible. âThe *contio* may be a survival
of an early form of assembly,â opined the late Lilly Ross Taylor,
âlike that of the Homeric warriors or the Spartans of later times,
in which men expressed their opinion by shouting.â{10} If so, the
highly talkative Athenian assembly. Indeed, Greek observers of
Roman procedures found the difference between the *contio* and
âGreek writers on Roman institutions have difficulty with the
word *contio*.â{11} Polybius and Dio Cassius were to call the assemblies by one word, *demos*, or, simply, the people. Appian, an Alexandrian Greek, and Plutarch, who was born in Boeotia, seem to
have been removed sufficiently from the traditional *polis* to designate the Roman assembly form as an *ekklesia*, the Greek word for
the popular assembly that, as Ross emphasizes, âcombined speaking and voting.â{12} If the *contio* was anything like the Homeric and
Spartan assemblies, it did more listening than speaking, voicing its
approval by acclamation and shouts rather than by oratory.
Polybiusâs association of the Roman assemblies with democracy
Is specious. The republic had no democratic component in the
Hellenic sense of the term, and speech, while relatively free, was
more an affair of delivering elitist rhetoric to manipulable audiences in the Forum than the verbal interchange of political equals.
A face-to-face relationship, between active citizens for the purpose
of arriving at a consensus is alien to republican systems of government. A democracy is participatory; a republic, representative.
The first involves the exercise of power directly by the people; the
Second, its delegation to selected surrogates, who then *reconstitute* the political realm that initially existed at the base of the
at its summit. Republics are beyond the immediate reach of popular control; democracies are not even confronted by the issue of the displacement of power.
Rousseau, with barely concealed irony for the French *philosophes* who were so endeared to English constitutionalism, was to
draw these distinctions sharply. âSovereignty, for the same reason
as it makes it inalienable, cannot be represented. It lies essentially
in the general will, and will does not admit of representation: it is
either the same, or other; there is no intermediate possibility. The
deputies of the people, therefore, are not and cannot be its representatives: they are merely its stewards, and can carry through no
definitive acts. Every law the people has not ratified in person is
null and voidâis, in fact, not a law. The people of England regards
itself as free: but it is grossly mistaken: it is free only during the
election of members of parliament. As soon as they are elected,
slavery overtakes it, and it is nothing.â{13}
The Roman cult of *libertas* is structured around personal freedom/not political. An individual can exercise a wide range of
choices in vocations, responsibilities, and the satisfaction of tastes.
Roman license during the Empire, with its almost psychotic appetite for âextremes, merely expanded this cult into a way of life.
Credo was warped into extravagant practice with the result that
the state soon found it ceased to enjoy the support of its citizenry.
Its citizens fled from military service, public obligations, tax levies,
and the most minimal communal responsibilities. Accordingly,
every aspect of government had to be professionalized, Under the
Empire, Romeâs troops were mercenaries, increasingly of alien
birth and culture; its bureaucracy became an elaborate apparatus,
staffed by numerous ex-slaves who had acquired the skills for political affairs that their former masters lost and that Roman citizens generally neglected.
This extraordinary erosion of personal competence blemishes
every aspect of the imperial era. But even the republic prepared
the way for Romeâs decline, In the political sphere, Roman *libertas*
never became freedom, the Greek vision of *eleutheria* based on
equality. One searches Latin for a term other than *libertas* or
collective and weighted units of the *comitia* and councilium. The
search is a vain one. The Roman concept of political life is corporatist, even statist, to the core, and there is no reciprocal interaction between the personal and the political.
To find an individual who has room for a political fife, we turn
to the Roman noble or well-born for examples. Here, political life
is obligatoryâindeed, apart from war, the authentic calling of an
aristocrat. Hence it is to be conceived as a profession and suffers
from the very professionalization of politics that Greek democrats
tried so assiduously to avoid. Young men of patrician lineage were
trained from birth in diction and rhetoric, physical fitness and
military skills, amiability and the. arts of influence. Overly mannered and self-conscious, they were taught to gain favor with the
powerful and befriend the potentially influential. By degrees, they
were initiated into legal skills and affairs together with martial arts
and the> postures of command. Polybius advises us that ten years
of military service are necessary before a man can aspire to a
political careerâa prerequisite that was mercifully abbreviated in
the later years of the Republic. One then went into the service of
a provincial governor and moved onward, at home, to a minor
magistrate or a military tribune.
To become a praetor was the ânext obligatory office,â as Taylor
puts it, followed by the consulship, if at all possible. Between
times, one held important offices in the provinces where the opportunities for enrichment and plunder were immense. These
broad outlines of the noblemanâs training and career could be
painted with details that more appropriately describe politicking,
rather than politics. The right friends, devoted clients, and suitable personal connections were critically important in achieving public office and political renown.
Even more significant than the Roman cult of *libertas* was the
Roman cult of *amicitia*, the Latin word for âfriendship.â Career
success depended not only upon lineage and wealth but also on
the elaborate system of friends and shared obligations a rising
patrician developed. I use the word âsystemâ advisedly to single
out the complex machinery of personal ties and interactions on
which the whole structure of rule was based. Roman âpoliticsâ
must be seen as a network of clients and associates rather than
dubs and parties. The fierce differences between factions in the
Republic, that finally brought it to ruin were more personal in
nature than political. Ciceroâs allusions to the *partes* of the *populores* and the *optimates* (the âpartiesâ of the âpeopleâ and âaristocrats,â to use these terms in a modern sense) are evidence of
differences in methods of manipulation rather than programs.
None of the nobles, with the exception of the brothers Gracchi,
over tried to really shift political power from the patrician elite to
the populace. Indeed, Roman politicians were rarely burdened by
Nontimentality for the oppressed or the plight of the commoners.
To use the people for personal ends and career ambitions, however, was a widespread technique, not only during republican
times but also during the imperial era. Nor were the Roman people the worse For the use of such demagogic tactics. Nobles gave
immense quantities of their wealth to gain popular support against
their rivals. A steady flow of emoluments, gifts, festivals, and
games came to be expected by the Roman people as a characteristic feature of politics. Roman client and gift politics, in turn, accelerated the degradation of the citizenry, fostering an appetite
for sensationalism and brutality that emerged in marked contrast
with its traditional republican spirit and virtues. âPublic thingsâ or
âthingâ to be sold, bought, and pilfered. In this respect, the Empire changed very little in Roman âpolitics.â It merely made the
process of demoralization, vulgarization, and pilfering more systematic and orderly.
Early Rome did not produce a breed of kindly menânor, for
that matter, did Athens and other Greek *poleis*, Kindness and
sentimentality are not classical traits. Obligation and duty are the
preferred personal attributes of the ancient world. But these attributes did create an ideal of a highly committed, morally certain,
and fiercely independent yeomanry. The landholdings of these
yeomen provided the material competence for a solid independence of mind and a sense of community rootedness. Behind the
more distinguished names of early republican Rome, such as Cincinnatus, who left his farmstead for vigorous public service, were
the stern traditions of family cults, civic deities, and an unblemished ancestryâa lineage to be cherished because it exhibited
soldierly simplicity and agrarian virtues. *Dignatas* and *honorare*
were to be prized over wealth, social status, and public esteem,
although invariably such rewards came with family probity.
These stern and dutiful farmers were to fill the legions commanded by Scipio in the brutal wars with Carthage. They were the
fodder of costly, long-term, and debilitating conflicts that brought
ruin to their farms and the destruction of their social moorings.
Thereafter, an unyielding patriciate, too urbane to value the innocent simplicity of its own rural ancestors, effaced what the Punic
Wars had largely undoneâthe ideals of republican virtue and the
agrarian material conditions in which this sense of virtue and duty
was rooted. Cincinnatus belonged to a social world rather than a
political one. Governance in his day was seen as a domestic responsibility in which a public servant tended to the needs of the people
more as a father than an administrator. Such men became short-lived *dictatori* without ever establishing dictatorships; they
promptly went back to their farms after answering the call to
public service. They did not thirst for power, much less professionalize it.
But Rome could not strike the balance between aristocratic
values and public rights achieved by Athens. More precisely,
Rome failed to turn the governance of the *civitas* into a genuinely
political community. Men like Cincinnatus were to lose not only
the landholdings that gave them independence of mind and spirit;
they were to lose the social base for public commitment without
developing a politics that could control and contain the new civic
dispensation that was forming around them. Like Athens, Rome
was to growâand, like Athens, it was to be brought into a broad
regional theater of power relationships and responsibilities. But
where Athens drastically reworked its yeoman society into a vital
public realm that fostered active citizenship among all its social
elements, Rome permitted its yeomanry to dissolve into rootless
constituencies and its public fife to languish. A republic rather
than a democracy came into existence with a degree of administrative ingenuity unprecedented in the history of jurisprudence,
efficiency, and military prowess. But for this achievement it paid
a penalty that ultimately spelled its death. The late Roman Republic was not a world that could nourish a Cincinnatus or even a
Marcus Portius Cato, whose writings are filled with denunciations
of Romeâs moral debasement, lasciviousness, and extravagance.
Politics was claimed almost exclusively by the patriciate and jealously guarded from any serious invasion by the people. In this
sonse, republican Rome was true to itself: like all elitist regimes,
it would have been exceptional if it failed to turn from an increasingly oligarchical republic into a completely despotic empire.
----
Athens and Rome ultimately became legendary models for two types
of âpopularâ government: a democracy and a republic. And later
social theorists and political practitioners who had lost any monarchic proclivities were to clearly favor a republican system of governance over a democratic one.
But democratic notions of a body politic did not disappear.
They were to surface from the depths of a popular âundergroundâ
of deviant Christian sects throughout âthe Middle Ages, such as the
Brethren of the Free Spirit, Anabaptist movements, and blatantly
anarchic conventicles during the Reformation Era. Like Athens,
they were not without their flaws: elites are to be found within
elites, saints within larger communities of believers, and the like.
Nevertheless, village democracies kept alive strong traditions of
popular assemblies that may have been inherited from distant
Neolithic and similar institutionsâand that also emerged in many
medieval towns. The notion of the âpeopleâ or *demos* did not
disappear. The ideals of âpopular ruleâ were to linger on from
classical antiquity well into modern times.
More commonly, however, republican theories of governance
were hybridized with democratic notions, and they were to produce rising demands of self-governance with institutions that were
redolent of democratic Athens. Machiavelliâs **Prince** and **Discourses** glitter with a fascinating mixture of republican and democratic ideas, largely translated into the virtues of his beloved
Roman Republic, His aversion for the idle nobility is pronounced.
Politics, in Machiavelliâs eyes, is not the fare for the slothful, ignorant, and crested boors who are the fatuous heirs of titles and
aristocratic pedigrees. It is a highly skilled craft that must be exercised as gently by the prince in his relationship with the people
as it must be exercised ruthlessly by him in his relationship with
his rivals. Machiavelliâs demand for a total commitment by his
chosen sovereign to politics reflects the emergence of a new kind
of man, the Renaissance prince: secular, keenly intelligent, skillful,
and cunning. He is a man of reason rather than faith, of judgement
rather than belief, and self-reliance rather than dependency, A
new political dispensation is in the air, a modern one, that draws
its precedents from the senatorial party of the early Roman Republic rather than the sacerdotal party of the medieval church.
Machiavelliâs references are to Scipio, not to Augustine; to Livy,
not Aquinas.
But within this republican idea of a meritocracy, Machiavelli
advances for sixteenth-century Italian concepts that could be
found in Perikles and the Athenian commitment to amateurism.
Comparable only to his, hatred of the nobility is his hatred of
mercenaries who were plaguing and plundering Italy in his dayâprofessional soldiers. The most commanding need of a well-ordered state, he tells us, is a citizen-army. Mercenaries are as
unreliable as they are unscrupulous. They are born plunderers
who have no allegiances other than those that money can buy.
âMercenary captains are either very capable men or not,â he
declares; âif they are, you cannot rely on them, for they will always
aspire to their own greatness, either by oppressing you, their master, or by oppressing others against your intentions; but if the
captain is not an able man, he will generally ruin you. And if it is
replied to this, that whoever has armed forces will do the same,
whether these are mercenaries or not, I would reply that as armies
are to be used either by a prince or by a republic, the prince must
go in person to take the position of captain, and the republic must
send its own citizens. If the man sent turns out to be incompetent,
it must change him; and if capable, keep him by law from going
beyond the proper limits. And it is seen by experience that only
princes and armed republics make very great progress, whereas
mercenary forces do nothing but harm, and also an armed republic submits less easily to the rule of one of its citizens than a republic armed by foreign forces.â{14}
Machiavelliâs argument clearly tips toward a republic and an
armed citizenry rather than a prince and a professional army.
Clearly, if princely government was central to his concerns, the
princeâs competence would normally be beyond any legal assessment. There would be nothing that could prevent him from
âgoing beyond the proper limits,â indeed, to tolerate any limits at
all. Nor could Machiavelli, whose mind was steeped in the Greek
and Roman classics, have been unmindful that the Athenian military forces, in contrast to the Roman imperial ones, were structured around clearly accountable captains who were strictly regulated by law, indeed by the *ekklesia* or popular citizen-assembly.
Amateurism takes high priority over professionalism and political
Institutions, visibly peopled by a free, and an armed, citizenry,
over a state power with its mercenary bureaucrats and soldiers.
Machiavelli undoubtedly had his eyes sharply focused on Italy and
the cause of national independence, but his feet were firmly
planted in his beloved Florence and the cause of freedom. The sap
flowed, as it were, from the roots upwardâfrom city to nationâwith the result that a republican, even princely, state was nourished by and mixed with civic democratic notions.
----
Ideologically, the hybridization of two very distinct and potentially
conflicting classical ideas of public governance arises from a serious confusion over what we mean by politics and statecraft.
The rise of the nation-state from the sixteenth century onward
greatly altered the entire framework of political discourse. The
basic unit of public governance was the city, not larger entities
such as the province, nation, or empire. A citizenâs allegiances to
gover nin g institutions could be comfortably enumerated as a very
distinct hierarchy of loyalties. He was first and foremost a townsman. The town was the authentic and most meaningful locus of his
personal and public life. Only secondarily did he identify himself
with a province or a region. The idea of ânationalityâ was at best
vague, that is when it existed at all. Romans in the most far-flung
reaches of the empire consistently visualized themselves as citizens of the imperial city. Among the Greeks, civic loyalty was
virtually all-consuming: Athenians, for example, sharply and disdainfully distinguished themselves from Spartans or Corinthians,
a sentiment that was freely reciprocated by all citizens of other
who were to pave the way for Christianity insisted well into
Roman times that civic loyalty defiled the novel notion that all
men were brothers. But the Stoic notion and its very novelty has
the ring of an ideological protest against the more popular view
that citizenship implies a primary loyalty to oneâs town, not to a
vagary called âhumanity.â
The rise of the nation-state altered this hierarchy of loyaltiesâand, with this change, the way in which politics was conceived.
Not that ancient and medieval civic parochialism was an unblemished desideratum. Parochialism had a very harmful, often dehumanizing, effect on urban life generally. The tendency to set one
city against another fostered local chauvinism with such pathologies as ethnic antagonisms, wars, and cultural introversion. In a
world where the city produced a deep sense of ethnic and cultural
identity that compares with the modern worldâs most strident
forms of nationalism, the conquest of one city by another often
terminated in the sheer annihilation of a people as a distinct community. Romeâs total destruction of Carthage in the last of the
Punic wars was not merely the dismantling of a major ancient city;
it was the enslavement and total effacement of a peopleâof their
identity, culture, traditions, uniqueness, indeed their very claim to
exist. Jericho, Troy, and Jerusalem were to suffer similar fates, to
cite only the most well-known examples of what urban destruction
often meant in the early and classical worldsâan act of devastation comparable only to genocide in the modern world.
With the rise of nationalism and the nation-state, the state
began to assume ideological preeminence over the city, and even
radical social thinkers began to formulate their political ideologies
in broad territorial or national terms. Puritan revolutionaries
thought of their ârightsâ not as citizens of London, which formed
the real center of parliamentary unrest against the court, but as
âEnglishmen.â Puritan theory, based on a doctrine of natural
rights, formulated these ârightsâ not in the characteristically civic
forms of popular assemblies and politics based on personal intimacy; a nation, âEngland,â was conceived as the legendary victim
of invading âbarbarousâ Normans who had crossed the channel
from France some five hundred years earlier and imposed a royal
tyranny on a representative system of Saxon self-governance. The
Combatants in the revolution expressed their loyalties in terms of
their adherence to âparliamentâ or the âcourt.â Larger-than-life
Institutions, far beyond the reach of the ordinary citizen, began to
Supplant the civic institutions within which some kind of face-to-face democracy was feasible. Republicanism, in effect, was a radical ideology of nations rather than cities and statecraft became the
âpoliticsâ of highly centralistic state structures.
It is hard to overstate the amount of intellectual mischief the
extension of the word politics, basically rooted in the civic life of
the *polis*, produced when it was permitted to encompass statecraft. Classical politics always implied the existence of a body
politicâin its own way, a kind of ecological community in the
social sense even in Rome, when the words **<em>populus** Romanus</em>
came to mean little more than an aristocratic oligarchy. The classical notion of a body politic was not a euphemism for an âelectorateâ or a âconstituency,â as it is today; it was a real, physical, and
clearly observable entity. It could be seen daily in public squares
where heated discussions over political issues intermingled with
the chitchat of personal and business problems; it assembled with
almost weekly regularity on a hillside of Athens, the Pnyx, where
meetings of the *ekklesia* were convened, or it gathered in open
spaces of the Roman Forum where the **comitia tributa** often held
its sessions. It could be heard quite audibly, whether by acclamation in Sparta, arguments in Athens, or even in the most despotic
of Romeâs imperial periods when the hoots and shouts of commoners at the Coliseum reminded the emperors that they were not
beyond the reach of public criticism. In more militant times, this
body politic rioted in Romeâs St. Peterâs Square during the Middle
Ages and stormed into Florentine churches to hear the sermons
of Savonarola during the Renaissance. In short, the body politic
existed in the literal sense that it was a tangible, protoplasmic
entity that expressed its concerns in the eye-to-eye contact of
personal confrontation and fervent discourse.
This eye-to-eye contact of active citizens was an organic politics
in its most meaningful, protoplasmic, and self-fulfilling sense. Political assemblies were not mere audiences on which public officials practiced their arts of statecraft; they were legislative communities united by a reasonable commonality of shared, public
interests and ethical precepts. That political life had worked its
way out of social life to acquire a distinct identity of its own and
presupposed social forms as its underpinnings is evident enough
from any account of the *polis* or its near-equivalent in the medieval city-state or âcommune.â But even so conservative a thinker
as Aristotle never confused a family or a workshop with the *agora*,
where public affairs were normally discussed, and the *ekklesia*.
Where the body politic physically assembled to make public decisions. Hence, the Greek *polis* was never a state in any modern
sense of the term with professional surrogates for an assembled
body politic, nor was it a social entity such as a âfamilyâ that united
the people into an authentic kin group. Aristotleâs notion of *philia*
or solidarity as a crucial precondition for a political life expressed
the unique identity politics possessed as a form of governance, one
That transcended mere kinship obligations. If kinsmen were obligated to each other by virtue of blood ties and tribal custom,
citizens were obligated to each other by virtue of civic ties and
ethical precepts.
If politics can be said to have emerged from society in the strict
sense that I use the latter word to denote familial, vocational, and
sociable relationships, so statecraft can be said to have emerged
from politics conceived as the activities of a directly involved body
politic. Aristocracies, monarchies, and republics ultimately dissolve the body politic as a participatory entity, an essentially ecological phenomenou into an amorphous mass of privatized âsocialâ beings we so aptly call an electorate or a constituency. The
âdeputies of the peopleâ replace the people, to use Rousseauâs
pithy formulation, and bureaucratic institutions replace popular
assemblies. The identity of politics as a unique phenomenon to be
distinguished from other, presumably âsocialâ activities, is not a
concept that was confined to classical thinkers such as Aristotle. It
is a recurring and often perplexing problem that appears in the
writings of Rousseau, in constitutional documents of the past that
distinguish between âactiveâ (propertied) citizens and âpassiveâ
(propertyless) citizens, and today, most strikingly, in the writings
of a highly gifted political philosopher, Hannah Arendt.
What is so curious about this literature and its attempt to single
Out politics as a clearly identifiable area of public activity is the
extent to which it is burdened by the institutional weight of the
nation-state. Arendtâs distinction between a âpolitical realmâ and
one that is âsocialâ allows for very little difference between political activity and statecraft. The state has so thoroughly merged
with the politicalâinstitutionally and functionallyâthat the two
almost seem identical. What is remarkable is that modern social
theory does not find this congruence of very different arenas of
public governance problematical. Clear as the old Aristotelian
distinction between the social and political may be, the equally
crucial distinction between the political and the statist tends to be
lost in the modern literature on politics. Political activity and
statecraft have become so thoroughly intermixed in theory and
lâOality that the present-day usage of the word âpoliticsâ is taken
to be the âartâ of the politician, who, for all practical purposes,
replaces the body politic. That the state historically depoliticized
tills body politic and essentially disbanded it institutionally seems
like a meaningless ideological curiosity in a world where political
activityâ takes the form of an on-going battle of political gladiators
in a strangely muted, almost empty arena.
Perhaps the main reason why the confusion between politics
and statecraft persists so strongly today is that we have lost sight
of the historic source and principal arena of any authentic politicsâthe city. We not only confuse urbanization with citification, but
we have literally dropped the city out of the history of ideasâboth
in terms of the way it explains the present human condition and
the systems of public governance it creates. Not that we lack any
valuable histories of the city or attempts to evaluate it sociologically. But our urban literature generally neglects the relationship
between the city and the remarkable phenomenon of citizenship
it produces. Urban historians tend to fixate on largely narrative
accounts of the cityâs development from village to megalopolisâaccounts that are riddled by nostalgia for the past or a brute acceptance of existing urban conditions and the future they portend.
The notion that the city is the source of immensely provocative
political, ethical, and economic theoriesâindeed, that its institutions and structures embody themâis generally alien to the modern social theorist.
An ethical interpretation of historical urban standards must
highlight one central issue: the need to recover civic forms and
values that foster an active citizenry. This amounts to saying that
we must recover politics againânot only the social forms of personal intercourse that underpin every kind of human activity. The
city, conceived as a new kind of ethical union, a humanly scaled
form of personal empowerment, a participatory, even ecological
system of decision making, and a distinctive source of civic cultureâthis civic notion of community must be brought back again into
the history of human ideas and practical wisdom. It must be critically reexamined as a realm of thought and activity that gives riseâas it did in various periods of historyâto political consociation,
a politics that places family, work, friendship, art, and values
within the larger context of a rounded civic world. Politics, in
effect, must be recreated again if we are to reclaim any degree of
personal and collective sovereignty over our destiny. The nuclear
unit of this politics is not the impersonal bureaucrat, the professional politician, the party functionary, or even the urban resident
in all the splendor of his or her civic anonymity. It is the citizenâa term that embodies the classical ideals of *philia*, autonomy,
rationality, and, above all, civic commitment, The elusive citizen
who surfaced historically in the assemblies of Greece, in the communes of medieval Europe, in the town meetings of New England,
and in the revolutionary sections of Paris must be brought to the
foreground of political theory. For without his or her presence and
without a clear understanding of his or her genesis, development,
and potentialities, any discussion of the city is likely to become
anemically institutional and formal. A city would almost certainly
become a shapeless blob, a mere chaos of structures, streets, and
squares if it lacked the institutions and forms appropriate to the
development of an active citizenry. But without the citizens to
occupy these institutions and fill these forms, we may create an
endless variety of civic entitiesâbut like the great urban belts that
threaten to devour them, they would be completely socially lifeless and ecologically denatured.
If the city makes it possible for us to single out politics as a unique
sphere of self-governance that is neither social nor statist, the
citizen as the viable substance of this unique sphere makes it
possibleâto undo the confusion that blends these very distinct
spheres into a collage of overlapping terms and blurred meanings,
For it is in the citizenâin his or her activity as a self-governing
beingâthat! the political sphere becomes a living reality with the
flesh and blood of a palpable body politic.
The Greeks may have been the first people to give us a clear
image of the citizen in any politically intelligible sense of the term.
Tribal peoples form social groupsâfamilies, clans, personal and
community alliances, sororal and fraternal clubs, vocational and
totemic societies, and the like; They may assemble regularly to
examine and decide communal affairsâcertainly a nascent form
of politicsâbut the issues that confront them rarely deal with ways
and means of governing themselves. Custom plays a paramount
role in establishing their norms for community management; discourse, beyond, direct argumentation, occupies a place secondary
to the enormous authority of precedence and long-established
administrative procedures. Nor is this approach to be disdained as
trivial or âprimitive/â Group safety and stability require that the
community preserve the old, well-tested ways of life, of expeditiously applying and modifying time-honored and secure structures of group management. The kin relationship forms the social
tissue of this governing body, whether the blood tie be real or
fictitious. Religious belief, too, may play a very important role, as
Fustel de Coulanges has argued.
But politics as a creative and rational arena of discourse with its
vastly innovative possibilities for shaping and bonding widely disparate individuals is only latent in tribal assemblies. It still has a
domestic character with powerful familial biases that exclude the
stranger. Tribal assemblies of preliterate peoples invoke the past
political assemblies of free citizens create a future. The former
tends to be highly conservative; the latter, highly innovative. If
the two were juxtaposed with each other, we would be obliged to
contrast custom to reason, precedent to a sense of futurity, kinship ties to civic ties, mythopoeia to ethics. In waxing enthusiastically over the popular assemblies that existed very early in
Mesopotamian cities, Henri Frankfort declared that the assembly
form âis a man-made institution overriding the natural and primordial division of society into families and clans. It asserts that
habitat, not kinship, determines oneâs affinities. The city, moreover, does not recognize outside authority. It may be subjected by
a neighbour or a ruler, but its loyalty cannot be won by force, for
its sovereignty rests with the assembly of its citizens.â{15}
Which is not to say that these contrasts are so absolute that they
polarize the tribal assembly against its civic counterpart. Athenian
citizenship, based on a civic myth that all citizens shared a common ancestry, became highly parochial by Periklesâs time. For a
well-established resident alien or *metoikos* (metics) to become a
citizen of the *polis* was virtually impossible. Doubtless, Athenians
knew that Solon, a century earlier, offered the lure of Athenian
citizenship to all skilled craftsmen who were willing to migrate
from various parts of the Mediterranean to Athens. And Kleisthenes, a generation removed from Perikles, permitted many
metics to become citizens in his day. Athenian citizenship, conceived as a form of status based on blood ties, was a shaky affair
at best. But under Perikles, the body politic behaved like an oversized medieval guild. For patently self-serving reasons, it simply
closed its doors to outsiders who might stake a reasonable claim to
the privileges afforded by the corporate community. In principle,
the impediments Athenians raised to citizenship in the middle of
the fifth century B.C. were not different from those that modern
nation states place in the way of immigrants and alien residents.
The Greek citizen ideal, however, differed very profoundly
from the modern. It was not simply some specious myth of shared
heredity that united citizens of the *polis* with each other but a
profoundly cultural conception of personal developmentâthe
Greek notion of *paideia*. *Paideia* is normally translated into English as education, a term that is notable for its sparseness and
limitations. To the Greeks, particularly the Athenians, the word
meant considerably more. The education of a young man involved
a deeply formative and life-long process whose end result made
him an asset to the *polis*, to his friends and family, and induced
him to five up to the communityâs highest ethical ideals. The
German word, *bildung*, with its combined meanings of character
development, growth, enculturation, and an well-rounded education in knowledge and skills, more appropriately denotes what the
Greeks meant by *paideia* than any word we have in English. It
expresses a creative integration of the individual into his environment, a balance that demands a critical mind with a wide-ranging
sense of duty. The Greek word, *areté*, which in Homeric times
denoted the warrior attributes of prowess and valor, was extended
by the classical era to mean goodness, virtue, and excellence in all
aspects of life. *Paideia* and *aretĂ©* are indissolubly linkedânot as
means and ends but as a unified process of civic- and self-development. Excellence in public life was as crucial to an Athenianâs
character development as excellence in his personal life. The *polis*
was not only a treasured end in itself; it was the âschoolâ in which
the citizenâs highest virtues were formed and found expression.
Politics, in turn, was not only concerned with administering the
affairs of the *polis* but also with educating the citizen as a public
boing who developed the competence to act in the public interest.
training. It rooted civic commitment in independence of mind,
The modern notion of âpoliticsâ as a form of managerial âefficiencyâ or of education as the mere acquisition of knowledge and
skills would have seemed pitiful to an Athenian citizen of classical
times. Athenians assembled as an *ekklesia* not only to formulate
policies and make judgments; they came together to mutually
educate each other in the ability to act justly and expand their
civic ideals of right and wrong. The âpolitical process,â to use a
modern cliche, was not strictly institutional and administrative; it
was intensely processual in the sense that politics was an inexhaustible, everyday âcurriculumâ for intellectual, ethical, and personal, growthâ*paideia* that fostered thjs ability of citizens to creatively participate in public affairs, to bring their best abilities to the
service of the *polis* and its needs, to intelligently manage their
private affairs in Accordance with the highest ethical standards of
the community.
This âcallingâ to civic and personal excellence was more than
a family responsibilityâor an institutionalized form of personal
training. By classical times, Athenians who could afford them had
tutors aplentyârhetoricians to teach them the arts of persuasion;
philosophers and logicians to instruct them in wisdom and consistency of thought; elders to provide them with the inherited lore of
their families, civic traditions, and models of behavior; gymnasia
in which to train and control their bodies or learn martial arts;
courts to shape their faculties for judgment; and, in time, the
and debate. But every *polis*, be it a garrison-state such as Sparta
or a democracy such as Athens, provided a variety of public spaces
in which citizens could gather on more intimate terms, often daily,
to discuss public and practical affairs. Perhaps the most important
of these spaces, the *agora*, which M. I. Finley calls the âtown
square,â was an informal meeting ground in the people could be
assembled when needed.{16} By Periklesâ time, the Athenians were
to shift the formal assembly of the peopleâthe *ekklesia*âto a
hillside (the Pnyx), but, as Finley notes, the *agora* originally meant
a âgathering place,â long before it was invaded by shops, stalls,
and temples.
The *agora* provided the indispensible physical space for turnÂŹing citizens hip from a periodic institutional ritual into a living,
everyday practice. Home was the place in which one ate, slept,
and tended to the details of private life. But the Greeks generally
held this private world in small esteem. Life was authentically
lived in the open public space of the *agora*, where the citizens
discussed business affairs, gossiped, met friendsânew and oldâoccasionally philosophized, and almost certainly engaged in vigorous political discussion. Perikles could be waylaid there by badgering critics as surely as Sokrates could be drawn into lengthy discussions by the intellectually earnest young nobles of the *polis*.
Jugglers, acrobats, poets, and play-actors mixed with tradesmen,
yeomen, philosophers, and public officials, a crowd spiced by
strangely costumed visiting foreigners who gawked at the looming
acropolis above and the superbly adorned public buildings nearby.
During inclement weather, this colorful and eminently vocal
crowd could take refuge in the colonnaded arcades or **stoa** that
lined part of the twenty-six-acre square. There, they encountered
artisans working at their trade and merchants who displayed their
wares, often women who sold much of the farm produce that fed
the community. In its emphasis on-direct, almost protoplasmic
contact, full participatory involvement and its delight in variety
and diversity, there is a sense in which the *agora* formed the space
for a genuine ecological community within the *polis* itself. Thus
politics, which found its most ordered and institutionalized expression in the *ekklesia*, originated in the daily ferment of ordinary life
In the *agora*. Its informal genesis reveals the organic way in which
Important policies slowly developed into popular ideas before
they were formulated as verdicts and laws in the courts and official
assemblages of the *polis*. The democratic institutions of Athens,
for all the ritualistic panoply that surrounded them, were merely
the structural forms in which everyday debate and gossip were
hardened into the legislated expression of an easy-going, unstructured, and popular politicsâone that was embodied by an earnest,
Spontaneous, and an extraordinarily active citizenry. The âtyranny of structurelessnessâ that so many contemporary liberals and
socialists fling so reprovingly at their libertarian critics as an âultrademocraticâ vice would have been incomprehensible to the
Athenian citizen. The teeming âanarchyâ of the *agora* was, in fact,
an indispensible and fecund grounding for âlibertarianâ structures
(to use Jaegerâs term) that, given time and neglect, would have
Otherwise turned into oligarchic institutions with a democratic
veneer.
Citizenship, in effect, involved an on-going process of educational, ethical, and political gestation for which such words as
âconstituentâ and âvoterâ are modern parodies of a politics that
was more existential than formal. This gestative process occurred
in the *agora* days before it found expression in the *ekklesia*. It is
a cliche to say that Americans are a âpractical people,â Italians an
âemotional people,â Germans a âmethodical people.â In any case,
there can be no doubt that the Athenians were a âpolitical peopleâ
and citizenship was their destiny, not merely the avocation it has
become in the modern world. Behind their ideal of citizenship,
nonperishable as long as there is a meaningful literature on democracy, is the way that citizenship was formed. It was a citizenship formed by the moral fortitude of a mountain peopleâin Athensâs case, tempered by the wide cultural contacts afforded by a
major seaportâand a delicate balancing of social conflicts that
pitted opposing classes against each other without obliterating the
virtues each possessed in its own right. Greece was to inherit not
only the aristocratic epics of Homer and their high standard of
courage but the mundane litanies of Hesiod with their workaday
sense of practicality. Her long journey from a tribal to a political
world, from a society of peasants to one of citizens, is a fascinating
narrative in its own right. But it is also an exemplary biography of
the citizen as such, at least insofar as this remarkable individual
was to approximate an ideal that Athens more closely attained
than any community that followed herâand one that the modern
world may well lose at the peril of its freedom.
----
The first phase of this journey into a political world begins with the
way the Athenians managed to shed the narrow features of the
kinship bond based on blood ties, religion, and familial loyalties,
while simultaneously developing an almost ecological **sensibility**
based on a Active kinship, territorial commonality, rationality, and
a healthy secular humanism.
Greek society was not immune to a general historical trend that
raised humanity out of a dismal archaic era, one which reworked
an egalitarian tribal world into a hierarchical feudal one. By Homeric times, commanding patriarchal clans had already imposed
their will on loosely structured and highly vulnerable peasant
communities. Ironically, the very tribal features of kin and blood
that once had produced egalitarian norms of mutual aid and material reciprocity were used to achieve their very opposite: a hierarchical system of rule focused on domination and acquisition. This
new reordering of traditional clans or phratries from tribal into
aristocratic families fostered exclusivity and privilege rather than
sharing and communal responsibility. The âbribe-devouring
judgesâ whom Hesiod, the Boeotian peasant, had denounced in
the eighth century B.c. had become land-devouring nobles by the
seventh. Gross inequalities in the ownership of land that mark the
Greek world in that period of transition seem like forerunners of
the Roman agrarian crisis that followed the Punic Wars. That
Greece, especially Athens, did not become a mere historical preface to Rome, indeed that the *polis* developed a political life so
markedly different from any republican system of governance,
can be explained only in terms of a remarkable constellation of
factors from which the modern world can learn much.
What aristocratic Greece and democratic Greece were to share
as a common legacy is a vigorous ideal of independenceâan ideal
oven stronger than its widely touted ideal of justice. To the Greek
mind, clientage in any form verged on slavery, indeed a denial of
the individualâs humanness and personality. This notion, which
many Greek scholars were to regard as an aristocratic disdain for
Work as such, actually expressed a concern for the citizenâs capacity to form independent judgements insulated from external or
personal interests. âTo build oneâs own house, oneâs own ship, or
to spin and weave the material which is used to clothe the members of oneâs own household is in no way shameful,â observes
Claude Mosse in her insightful study on work in the ancient world.
âBut to work for another man, in return for a wage of any kind,
is degrading. It is this which distinguishes the ancient mentality
from a modern which would have no hesitation in placing the
independent artisan above the wage-earner. But, for the ancients,
there is really no difference between the artisan who sells his own
products and the workman who hires out his services. Both work
to satisfy the needs of others, not their own. They depend on
Others for their livelihood. For that reason they are no longer free.
This perhaps above all is what distinguishes the artisan from the
poasant. The peasant is so much closer to the ideal of self-sufficiency (*autarkeia*) which was the essential basis for manâs freedom
in the ancient world. Needless to say,fin the classical age, in both
Greece and Rome, this ideal of self-sufficiency had long since given
way to a system of organized trade. However, the archaic mentality endured, and this explains not only the scorn felt for the artisan,
labouring in his smithy, or beneath the scorching sun on building
sites, but also the scarcely veiled disdain felt for merchants or for
rich entrepreneurs who live off the labor of their slaves.â{17}
As befitted free men, farmers enjoyed the economic independence and material security that were needed to form decisions
untainted by self or class interests. In fact many Greeks would
have seen even wealthy tradesmen as clients of their buyers and
highly skilled craftsmen, artists, and poets as dependents of a fickle
market for their products. To be free in Athens meant very little
if oneâs basic needs were not satisfied within a mutualistic group
of self-sufficient producers. The word *autarkeia*, strictly translated, has the double meaning of the rarely used definition of
âselfirule,â as weil as. the. more familiar notion of âself-sufficiency.â
In its latter meaning, *autarkeia* has long been replaced by *autonomos*, literally the conditipn of living by oneâs own laws. This
concept of independence is more juridical than political. The English translation of these words, notably the use of âautarchyâ to
mean economic self-sufficiency and autonomy to denote personal freedom or self-government, creates a disjunction between
the material and political that would have been alien to the Greek
ideal of independence. We would be hard put to understand Artistotieâs belief that all tradesmen, artisans, merchants, and servants
should be denied the franchise if we failed to recognize that it is
not simply labor and trade he despised but, more importantly,
material clientage in any form that could affect the citizen s independence of judgement. Independence without the substance of
material self-sufficiency and personal autonomy would have been
formal at best and hollow at worst to the Greek mind. No client,
however well-off, could render a judgement or reason freely without deferring to exogenous authorities and interests on whom his welfare depended.
It is worth noting that these Hellenic precepts have entered
into modern ecological thinking with little knowledge of their
remote origins and political orientation. But such a demanding
notion of independence could not have emerged solely from ideological considerations. Here, the mountainous terrain of the Greek
archipelago comes verymuch to our aid. âNature gave to Greece,
as to her neighbors, the tendency to equality together with abundant opportunities for the growth of public opinion, and then
intensified these forces by strictly limiting the areas in which they
could operate,â observes Alfred Zimmern. âEach little plain, rigidly sealed within its mountain-barriers and with its population
concentrated upon its small portion of good soil, seems formed to
be a complete world of its own. Make your way up the pasture-land, over the pass and down on to the fields and orchards on the
other side, and you will find new traditions and customs, new laws
and new gods, and most probably a new dialect.... The Greeks
were not painfully taught to value local independence. They grew
up unable to conceive of any other state of government. It was a
legacy slowly deposited through the long period of isolation which
intervened between the first settlement of the Hellenic invaders
and their emergence centuries later as a civilized race. They
never themselves realized, even their greatest writers did not
realize, how unique and remarkable their political institutions
were.â{18}
Colorful and truthful as these lines may be, Zimmern understates the extent to which Greek thinkers were conscious of their
heritage and political uniqueness. Indeed, as we shall see, it was
the extraordinary acuity of this consciousness that imbued Athens
with a high sense of mission and clear sense of direction. No political sphere was more carefully, thoughtfully, and artistically
crafted than the Athenian. Equality or *isonomia* followed from an
even more basic; influence than Greeceâs mountainous terrain exercised on its pocket-sized communities of free villagers. To five
in such isolation and forced independence required that every
family and family-sized community had to fend for itself. The
Greek farmer had to be a well-rounded man in a more tangible
sense than we use this cliche today. He was obliged to know how
to fight for his land,as well as cultivate it, build his shelters as well
as repair them, methodically tend to his wounds as well as cunningly avoid needless conflicts, plan his long-range needs as well
as satisfy his immediate ones, function as a caring father, loyal
spouse, dutiful son, supportive brother, a wary buyer of things that
his co mm unity could not produceâin short, he needed to combine a working knowledge of all the techniques needed for his
survival with soldiering and âpoliticking.â Together with his
spouse, who presided over all the domestic affairs of the family, the
Greek farmer gained in practical competence and personal fortitude what isolation denied him in acculturation. In the Latin sense
of competereâto be fit, proper, or qualifiedâhe had no equal in
the ancient world. Hence, he could be âunequalledâ by self-anointed superiors who tried to subordinate him and assert their
authority over his destiny. A magnificent amateur, he embodied
the nascent citizenship in which all his peers acknowledged the
need for a self-possessed individual who could be entrusted as
much with the affairs of his community as with the satisfaction of
his private needs.
The flow of ideas from the independence of a mountain-dwelling villager to the egalitarianism of a *polis*-dwelling citizen must
be seen as an unbroken continuum. The Greek language itself is
magnificently processual and organic. A crucially important word
such as *arche*, from which an entire political vocabulary has been
constructed, denotes the originating principle as well as the ordering principle of any *kosmos*, the Greek word for âorderâ in the
broadest sense of the term. To think of an âorderâ without deriving it from its origin and, hence, the latent possibilities that it could
fulfill is linguistically built into the Greek mindâand also provides
us with an important clue to the languageâs ethical thrust. Origin,
history, f ulfillm ent, and possibilityâall form a unified whole in
Greek, so that whether we choose to speak of the universe,
humankind, the *polis*, or the citizen, these concepts, charged with
ethical meaning, denote the unity of civic, natural, and social life
or what we call âconnectednessâ today. Accordingly, autarchies or
self-sufficient communities lead us organicallyâdeductively, if
you willâto independence, competence, and *isonomia*. The
Greek *polis* has its *arche* in this germinal phasing of a highly
competent farmer who, by an immanent process of sociopolitical
development, found his fulfillment as a highly competent citizen.
The old Greek aristocracy was no mere anachronism in this
process. The Athenian democracy did not shed it; rather, it tried,
with qualified success, to absorb it. Its epic culture, gospel of valor,
high sense of *philia*, and code of honor, marked by a disdain for
material thin gs, were incorporated into the puritanical virtues of
the democracy, which abjured luxury, ornateness of dress, culinary delights, and self-indulgence. The democratic hero was not
only valorous but sternly self-willed and emotionally controlled.
Warrior manliness did not die; it was reworked into civic loyalty,
personal dignity, and a high regard for virtuous behavior. The
comradeship of the military camp became the *isonomia* of the
competent equals. Hence, all could participate in the governance
of the *polis* on the same footing, a practice which, as we shall see,
was translated into the widespread use of sortition and attempts
to arrive at decisions by consensus as well as by voting.
It is worth emphasizing that nearly all the men who turned
Athens from an aristocratic oligarchy into a democratic polity
were of noble lineage, Solon, Kleisthenes, and Perikles, to cite the
most well-known figures in forming the democracy, were members of the most elite clans, the *genos*, of Attica, the territorial
domain of Athens. In contrast to their Roman counterparts, however, they did not become the leaders of an unruly *partes populares*, nor did they try to rise in an oppressive hierarchy by throwing away their fortunes in gifts to a debased urban mob. They were
commonly men of exceptional distinction who could be as heroically selfless in political causes as their ancestors were heroically
valorous in military ones. As Werner Jaeger was to point out,
Athens did not destroy its aristocracy but rather tried to turn its
entire citizen body into one.
----
This pithy formulation has several levels of meaning. Politically, it
sums up the slow but sweeping way in which Atticaâs âbribe-devouringâ nobles were shorn of their power. By the seventh
century B.C., Athens and its environs were on the brink of revolution. Plutarch tells us that the âcommon people were weighed
down with debts they owed to a few rich men. They either cultivated their lands for them and paid them a sixth of the produce
and were hence called *Hectemorioi* and *Thetes*, or else they
pledged their own persons to raise money and could be seized by
their creditors, some of them being enslaved at home, and others
being sold to foreigners abroad. Many parents were even forced
to sell their own children (for there was no law to prevent this) or
to go into exile because of the harshness of their creditors. However, the majority, which included the men of most spirit, began
to make common cause together and encourage one another not
to resign themselves to these injustices, but to choose a man they
co,uld trust to lead them. Having done this, they proposed to set
all enslaved debtors free, redistribute the land and make a complete reform of the constitution.â{19}
At this point, Athens might have easily gone the way of Rome.
Five centuries later; the Gracchi brothers, who faced a nearly
identical crisis between bitterly polarized classes of landless peasants and bloated patricians, raised such sweeping demands for
political change and agrarian reform that they opened irreparable
wounds in the Roman body politic. It remains to the credit of the
Athenians that the crisis was handled very gingerly. The moderation that Hellenic society turned into a deeply personal as well as
civic ethos was to find its embodiment in Solon, a noble of considerable prestige who had earned the respect of the Athenians as a
whole. No one could have contained the crisis that faced his people with greater prudence.
Elected archon of the *polis*âits chief magistrateâand invested
with sweeping powers to resolve the, conflict, Solon followed the
middle course that eluded the Gracchi and the more sincere populates in the closing years of the Republic. For the poorest of the
pressing economic burden by cancelling all outstanding debts and
making debt slavery illegal. To strengthen their political status, he
revived and expanded the functions of the *ekklesia*, which had
virtually ceased to exist since tribal days. The assembly was authorized not only to enact the communityâs laws and elect its magistrates; it convened as a court of justice to deal with all cases other
than homicide, a crucial advance in empowering the *demos*, The
upper crust of the nobilityâthe *Eupatridai*âwere obliged to relinquish their hereditary claim to, furnish Athens with its archons,
a powerful, annually elected magistracy whose number Solon increased to nine. The office, to be sure, could only be filled by
landowners, but the door to executive power, which later generations were to open, was now unlocked for the *demos*.
Solon never pretended that he desired the political and economic supremacy of *demos*, nor did he try to divest the nobility
of power. As his verses indicated, he shrewdly steered a middle
course through a crisis that would have exploded in social chaos
had any of the contending orders gained absolute supremacy over
the others:
To the mass of people I gave the power they needed,
Neither degrading them, nor giving them too much rein;
For those who already possessed great power and wealth
I saw to it that their interests were not harmed.
I stood guard with a broad shield before both parties
And prevented either from triumphing unjustly.{20}
The land magnates were not deprived of their holdings, nor
were the *Hectemorioi* permitted to reclaim the sixth of their produce that was taken by their landlords. Usury still plagued the
Attic peasantry, although the lender and borrower were more
evenly squared off by the controls that the *ekklesia* exercised over
legal disputes. Solon also created a Council of Four Hundredâthe
famous Athenian *boule*âto which only propertied men could be
elected annually. However, the *boule* served to check not only the
popular *ekklesia* by rigorously determining its agenda and supervising its deliberations; it also checked the behavior of the aristocratic Council of the Areopagus (formerly the powerful Council of
the Eupatridai), whose functions over the years were to, become
more ceremonial than political. A number of reforms, unique for
their time, were made to expand individual rights and alter popular etiquette. An heiress, burdened by an impotent husband, was
free to marry his next of kin, and relatively poor women were
spared the need to collect dowries. Individuals could will their
property as they âchose, not according to familial dictatesâa law
that struck an important blow at the collective solidity of the
aristocratic *genos* and its concentration of sizable wealth. A number of lesser laws restricted displays of excessive luxury and riches.
But perhaps the most strikingly Hellenic law imputed to Solon was
one that disenfranchised any citizen who, to use Plutarchâs words,
âin the event of revolution, does not take one side or the other.â
It was Solonâs intention, Plutarch emphasized, not to reward citizens who seek the safety of neutrality, apathy, or indifference at
the expense of the public interest. Athenians were expected to be
politically involved, irrespective of the causes to which they adhered, or else they were not worthy of citizenship. It was an
affront to the Hellenic concept of citizenship for a man to prudently and selfishly âsit back in safety waiting to see which side
would win.â
Characteristically, Solon refused to linger on as a tyrant by no
means a pejorative term or a despised status in those days despite pleas that he become one, and went into voluntary exile for
ten years. His work did not resolve all the political and economic
problems that brought him to the archonship, nor did it prevent
a tyrant from ultimately replacing him. But it provided Athens
with the opportunity to absorb his reforms and the time needed
for its citizenry to mature politicallyâto use and accustom itself
to the *ekklesia*, to learn the arts of compromise, and to develop a
political etiquette that fostered a sense of civic commonality
rather than social conflict. The rather mild tyranny of Peisistratus
and his son Hippias, which followed Solon s departure, greatly
reduced the power of the Attic nobility and initiated the economic
and political changes that were to lead to the democracy. Recalcitrant nobles were forced into exile and their estates divided
among the poor. The needy were given livestock and seed, exports
were promoted, and a vigorous foreign policy opened new markets to Athenian commerce. Peisistratus, despite the personal control he exercised over Atticaâs affairs and his blatant nepotism,
adhered to the Solonic constitution so meticulously that even
Solon was induced to support him after his return to Athens. The
political level of the Athenian citizen was raised enormously by
the tyranny, and the commonersâfarmers, shepherds, artisans,
and merchantsâbenefited so considerably from the archonships
of Peisistratus and Hippias that the tyranny became self-vitiating.
Three generations had passed since Solon had been given the
archonship, and Athens was now ready for a democracy. In terms
of the mere flow of events, the efforts to initiate authentic popular
rule seemed to come almost as a reaction to attempts by the
aristocracy to restore their old clannish oligarchy, and many of the
democracyâs features must be seen as institutionalized efforts to
prevent the emergence of entrenched power by elites of any kind.
But the Athenian people, too, seem to have become more certain
of themselves and their capacity to govern their own affairs. The
aristocracy, in turn, appears to have suffered a genuine lack of
nerve. After a feeble attempt to eliminate the reforms of Solon
and the Peisistradae, the nobles broke ranks. One of their own
kind, Kleisthenes, the head of the aristocratic Alcmaenodae, became archon in 506 B.C., and the democraticization of Athens was
launched in earnest.
Kleisthenes struck decisively at the societal basis of aristocratic
powerâthe traditional kinship network that gave the Attic nobility its very sense of identity. The ancient Greek phratries and clans
were simply divested of any political power and gradually declined in importance for want of any significant functions. The old
Ionian system of four ancestral tribes was converted into ten
Strictly territorial âtribesâ based exclusively on residence. The
villages and towns of Attica, in turn, became outlying sections of
Athens and were designated as â*demes*â instead of *genoi*. Politics
now became inseparable from territorialism: the *demes*, with their
own popular assemblies, were grouped together in varying numbers into thirds or *trittyes*, and three *trittyes*, in turn, constituted
a tribe, hence Attica was composed of thirty *trittyes*. Ten of the
thirty *demoi* were composed of residents in or around Athens;
another ten, from the maritime districts; and the remainder from
the interior.
Kleisthenes shrewdly placed one urban trittys in each of the ten
tribes, so that the Attic agrarians from whom the nobles garnered
whatever popular support they had were politically buffered by
City citizensâthe men who were to form the backbone of the
democracy. This switch in the governance system of the *polis* was
Strategic: it fostered the power of a citizenry that was distinctly
urbane, cosmopolitan, and forward looking, vitiating the strongly
hierarchical structure of a once-entrenched, highly parochial, feudal class system. At the same time, tradition was kept alive by
using the language of the tribal world (even the word *gene* had a
special clannish origin), retaining a number of local religious associations, chieftainlike figures such as **demarchs** (the demeâs version of the Athenian archons), and by making membership in a
dome hereditary even though a citizen might choose to reside at
some later time in another part of Attica. Kleisthenes, in effect,
ârevolutionizedâ Athenian political life in the literal sense of the
term: he replaced a once-egalitarian tribal system that had been
perverted into a harsh feudal hierarchy by a tribalistic structure
that actually restored the old freedoms of the people on an entirely new political and societal level. Athens had revolved in a
full circleâmore precisely, a spiralâto the **isonomia** of its tribal
past, but without the innocence that made the early Greeks vulnerable to hierarchy and domination.
The *boule* was increased from a council of four hundred to five
hundred and restructured so that fifty men from each of the ten
tribes rotated every tenth of the year as an administrative âexecutive committeeâ between sessions of the *ekklesia*. Each tribe selected its fifty *bouleutes* by lot, a practice that became so widespread that even archons were so chosen from members of the *boule*, as were members of Athenian juries (*dikastoi*) and lesser
functionaries. Apart from the *polis*âs magistrates, no property qualifications debarred Athenian citizens from participating in the
governance system, and under Perikles the last restrictions that
lingered on from Kleisthenesâs reforms disappeared completely.
In time, members of the *boule*, the *ekklesia*, and the *heliaea* or
courts were compensated for participating in these institutions,
generally on a *per diem* basis and in the case of the *boule*, annually. No public office could be held for more than a year, and with
certain exceptions (jurymen and generals) none could be held
more than twice in a lifetime.
This extraordinary opening of public life to the Athenian citizenry was completed during the sixty years that saw Kleisthenes
assume the archonship in: 492 B.C. and the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War in 431. An analytic account of the democracy, its
possibilities and its limitations, properly belongs to the discussion
of civic freedom that follows in the next chapter. For the present,
what counts is the way the democracy formed the citizenry and,
in turn, was formed by it. Democratic leaders such as Kleisthenes
and Perikles did not foist a remarkably open system of participatory governance on a passive people; the institutional structure
and the body politic interacted closely with each other against a
haunting background of quasitribal social forms and relationships.
This is politics at its bestâin a lived sense, not a formal one. The
Athenian notion of *areté*, the daily practice of *paideia*, and the
institutional structure of the *polis* were synthesized into an ideal
of citizenship that the individual tried to realize as a form of
self-expression, not an obligatory burden of self-denial. Citizenship became an ethos, a creative art, indeed, a civic cult rather
than a demanding body of duties and a palliative body of rights.
At his best, the Athenian citizen tried not only to participate as
fully as possible in a far-reaching network of institutions that elicited his presence as an active being; the democracy turned his
participation into a drama that found visible and emotional expression in rituals, games, artwork, a civic religionâin short, a
collective sense of feeling and solidarity that underpinned a collective sense of responsibility and. duty. This drama extended beyond
life itself. The Athenian citizen had little hope of any certain
immortality other than the memory he left behind in the *polis*.
Afterlife became a form of political life and eternahty existed only
insofar as noble political actions were memorable enough to become part of the *polis*âs history and destiny.
----
The *polis* shrewdly availed itself of aristocratic attributes to bring
the individual Athenian into the full light of citizenship, with its
high standards of civic responsibility. We have seen how the *agora*
prepared the way for the *ekklesia*. By the same token, the gymnasium, presided over by a **paidotribes,** extended the all-consuming
fascination of the Greeks for athletics into martial arts, thereby
preparing the young for military training. Troubling as this may
be in modern eyes, war was a fact of life in antiquity. Apart from
certain cults and religions, pacifism found no following among the
ancients. One either fought unquestioningly for oneâs city or faced
clientage and slavery in the event of defeat. The citizen-soldier
was much more than: a pillar of Athenian military strategy. He was
a guardian not only of the *polis* but also of the democracy, as we
shall see later, just as the citizen-farmer became the embodiment
of its ideal of *autarkeia*.
But the *polis*, particularly the democracy, gave the familyâs
aristocratic attributes a uniquely public character. And it is in this
non-elitist sense that the democracy elevated its citizens into an
âaristocracyâânot only as a result of the participatory nature of
Its courts, assemblies, and councils, but also the familial mood of
essentially religious character, rituals and festivals became a form
of politics. The *ekklesia* opened with prayers, and its agenda was
composed of sacred as well as secular topics. Problems of constructing temples or planning festivals occupied the assembly as
earnestly as matters such as ostracism or the ratification of treaties.
In famous funeral oration, which so vividly captures the spirit of
the democracy, Perikles cites among its attributes âthe contests
and sacrifices throughout the year, which provide us with more
relaxation from work than exists in any other city.â{21} Websterâs
observation that the Athenians tended to turn their holy days into
holidays suffers from a certain degree of misunderstanding.{22}
Athenian life struck a remarkable balance between religiosity and
secularity: the camaraderie of participating in a spectacle or sharing fully in the excitement of the games imparted a quasireligious
sense of communion to civic life. This sense of communion more
accurately conveys the intense meaning of *koinonia* than do such
commonplace words as âcommunity.â At the risk of repitition, we
could say that such shared experiences unravel the Athenian notion of âcommunityâ as an on-going activity of communizing, not
simply an institutionalized form of participation. Like the *agora*,
the âcontests and gamesâ of Athens often created a shared sense
of preternatural civic enchantment.
The democrats knew this very well and these âcontests and
gamesâ occurred with considerable frequency. To discuss them in
detail would require a volume in itself. Let it suffice to say that
every year, many days were devoted to the Lesser Mysteries in
February and the Greater Mysteries in September, rituals that
centered around Persephoneâs descent into Hades and Demeterâs
mourning, the mythical explanation for the occurrence of winter
and its lean months. Every July, Athenians participated in the
Lesser Panathenaia, which culminated quadrennially in the
Greater Panathenaia, an extraordinary parade of Athenians and
Athenian life in full array, if we are to judge from the bas relief
that girdles the Parthenon. Almost every month, Athenians witnessed or participated in a variety of rituals, contests (athletic,
musical, poetic, and choral), or celebrations to honor deities, historic events, great personages, victors in Panhellenic festivals such
as the Olympics or the fallen of past and recent battles. Religion
and civic loyalty blended the great variety of personal and social
interests within the body politic into an underlying commonality
of outlook that, if it did not remove serious conflicts, rarely
reached such desperate levels that they could efface the democracy from within. Ultimately, it was to be Macedonian rule that
brought the democracy to its definitive end, not the Athenians.
For all its shortcomings, the democracy in various forms persisted
through nearly two of the most stormy centuries of the ancient
world and, at its height, exhibited a degree of cultural and intellectual creativity that has no peer in western history.
Perhaps the most important of the Athenian festivals was a
comparatively new one: the City Dionysia. Even more than the
Greater Panathenaia, when all of Athens went on display with a
large tapestry (the *pelops*) that depicted the triumph of Olympian
âreasonâ over the chthonic rule of âforce,â the City Dionysia was
strongly democratic in its focus. It was then, for three out of a span
of six days that overlapped March and April, that Athenians could
witness the great dramatic tragedies that gave the democracy its
ideological meaning. By the thousands, Athenians flocked to the
Theater of Dionysos on the southeast slope of the Acropolis to see
the plays of Aeskylos, Sophokles, Euripides, and others who literally created serious drama in western culture. Under the clear
skies of a high Mediterranean spring, they watched with absorption the Aeskylean drama of their own *polis* and its human antecedents unfold with a majesty that may have verged on reverenceâcertainly a thrilling sense of exaltation that compels a modern
historian of the democracy, W. G. Forrest, to cite Aeskylos âas the
greatest of the three Athenian tragedians,â and for many, including myself, the greatest of the worldâs dramatists.{23} Aeskylosâs
trilogy, the *Oresteia*, advanced a powerful validation of the democracy that, in its emotional and declaratory power, may even
exceed the funeral oration of Periklesâa trilogy that was constantly replayed and kept winning prizes at the City Dionysos long after the authorâs death.
Its story has been told and interpreted repeatedly, and to explore it at length would be a tiresome redundancy. Let it suffice
to say that the murder of Agamemnon, the returning chief of the
besiegers of Troy, by his wife, Klytemnestra, followed by her own
death at the hands of her vengeful son, Orestes, opens the whole
drama of Athensâs transformation from a quasitribal society,
rooted in kinship rules, custom, and chthonic deities, into a political communityâa *polis*âbased on residence, reason, and the anthropomorphic Olympians. It is Athene who, in a challenging
statement against the Erinyes (the three female guardians of âmatriarchalâ blood ties and tribal retribution for the murder of oneâs kin), solemnly declares:
It is my task to render final judgement here.
This is a ballot for Orestes I shall cast.
There is no mother anywhere who gave me birth,
and, but for marriage, I am always for the male
with all my heart, and strongly on my fatherâs side.
So; in a case where the wife has killed her husband, lord of the
house, her death shall not mean most to me. And if the other votes
are even, then Orestes wins.{24}
After being pursued by the Erinyes for committing a blood
crime more damning than a marital oneâand particularly against
his mother from whom early tribal descent may have been tracedâOrestes is absolved and the Erinyes reconciled by acquiring a
civic status as Eumenides, the kindly ones who look after the
well-being of the Athenian *polis*.
The trilogy has many levels of meaning, probably all of which
had a gripping effect on the audience that knew Aeskylos personally or, in later years, by reputation. The *Eumenides*, the last
drama of the trilogy, celebrates the victory of civic law and rationality over tribal custom and unthinking mimesis. Athene, born of
Zeusâs head, embodies *logos* and justice. In a strongly patriarchal
society that saw male rationality as the sole bulwark to dark chaos
and an uncertain, untamed world, it was not difficult to identify
âfickleâ woman with nature and the *polis* as the sole realm of
freedom and law. Orestesâ trial, which marks the culmination of
the trilogy, is presented as a new dispensation in the affairs of men.
The Erinyes unrelentingly pursue any homicidal perpetrator of
the blood tie. All that counts with them is the act of murder of
oneâs kin, not the circumstances or motive that produced it. To the
Athenians, this behavior was evidence of unreasoning tribalism, of
an irrationality that precluded any civic union based on discourse,
logic, and orderly compromise. Recourse to trial rather than ordeal, to the weighing of circumstantial evidence, motive, and logical judgement rather than mere action and contests of fortitude, marked the first step toward a political *koinonia*âthe city as a *polis*.
To the Athenian audience, which believed Athens was the first
city to establish a system of laws, the trial of Orestes was a founding
act. Athensâs decision to try homicide by a judicial process literally
created the *polis* as an ethical union based on justice. âIf it please
you, men of Attica,â intoned Athene, the patroness of the *polis*,
âhear my decree now, on this first case of bloodletting I have
judged. For Aegeusâ population, this forevermore shall be the
ground [the Hill of Ares] where justices deliberate-No anarchy,
no rule of a single master.... I establish this tribunal. It shall be
untouched by moneymaking, grave but quick to wrath, watchful
to protect those who sleep, a sentry on the land.â{25} Henceforth,
justice, not tradition; reason, not custom; fact, not ordeal; motive,
not myth are to guide the men of Attica, for without this new
dispensation, the *polis* has no ethical meaning, nor does the democracy have an ethical rationale.
It is easy to see in Aeskylos not only the clearest voice of the
Athenians, who apparently revered Aeskylos, the *Oresteia* unfolds
the emergence of justice from a hazy âdarkâ world of tribal antiquity and its fortunes in the arbitrary domain of warriors, nobles,
and the *genoi*, into the clear light of the *polis* and its orderly
citizenry. The identification of the audience with the drama must
have been intensely personal; it was the authentic protagonist of
the play. Of Aeskylosâs remaining dramas, **Prometheus Bound** arrests us to this very day with its message of heroic defiance against
unfeeling authority and its expansive belief in humanityâs sense of
promise, indeed its capacity to advance toward an ever-wider
horizen of intellect and wisdom.
It would be easy enough to end our discussion of the Athenian
drama with Aeskylos, but Sophokles beckons us with other facets
of meaning that must have deeply affected the Athenian spirit. His
<em>Antigone</em> raises the ambiguities of justice in the form of conflicting
Individuals, indeed personalities. Antigone herself becomes the
ombodiment of tribal kinship rules in her frenzied zeal to bury the
body of her brother, Polyneikes, whom Kreon, the King of Thebes,
wishes to leave to vultures and dogs as an example for future
rebels. Kreon thus appears as the embodiment of secular authority, the civil counterpart to Antigone. The drama emerges as a
fugue, in which deeply emotive ethical themes are played against
each other and intermesh. If Aeskylosâs characters tend to appear
as forces rather than individuals, despite Klytemnestraâs awesome
personality and Atheneâs majesty, Antigone wins us as a persecuted heroine who seeks the burial of her brother s body and
Kreon as the willful embodiment of civil rule, prior even to the
rise of the *polis*. For we are still in the time of the royal *oikos* or
household. In writing the drama, Sophokles may have tried to
show that after the decline of this prepolitical world of blood clans
and regal palaces the Athenian citizen no longer had to confront
the pangs of tragedy in Hegelâs sense of the termâa drama in
which both sides are right. The *polis* spares us the need to pit
divine law in the form of tribal commandment against human law
in the form of civil retribution for rebellion. We can read our
romantic sympathies for Antigone into the drama, but a Greek
audience might have viewed her differently. It would have been
obliged to place Kreonâs civil obligation on a par with Antigone s
tribal obligation, and its sympathies would have been allotted
according to political as well as personal sensibilities. Relief
emerges from the sense of delivery that a concealed theme in the
drama affords: the free air of the *polis* in which the citizen can
breathe without the presence of such exotic conflicts.
Such is also the case in one of Sophoklesâs most celebratedâand
possibly one of his most misunderstoodâplays, **Oedipus the King**
and **Oedipus at Colonus**. Here man, potentially the citizen, rises
to a clear and level gaze at his fate and his ability to learn from
suffering. If there is anything that impresses us about the play, it
is the fact that Oedipus emerges with greater nobility toward the
end of his life, all his misfortunes notwithstanding, than in its
portentous beginnings. No broken King Lear confronts us but
rather a hero whose passion for truth ultimately transcends the
disastrous impact of patricide and incest. The cathartic core of the
drama is unmistakable: it is the nobility of the individual, purged
of archaic curses and trammels, of manâs high promise and destiny
to achieve insight and wisdom when he acquires the status of a
free citizen.
Yet, the Greek ideal of the citizen, in contrast to ours, is not
monadic. However individuated the Greek drama became with
Sophokles and even more decidedly so with Euripides, the
Athenian citizen would have mocked the entrenched bourgeois
myth that the free man is an atomized buyer and seller whose
choices are constrained by his own psychological and physical
infirmities. He would have seen beyond the arrogance of this
self-deception into the pathos of the bourgeois citizenâs clientage
to the powerful, his aimless pursuit of wealth, his reduction of life
to the acquisition of thingsâin short, a **moira** or destiny governed
more by **ananke** or necessity than by the understanding that even
such a nascent personality as Oedipus brings to his own insight
into reality. Such a despised bourgeois being, he would have concluded, is no less archaic than the Erinyes, who must be freed from
their primality as mere forces and reconstructed by reason and
justice into the âkindly ones.â Only then, in synchronicity and
ethical union with the *polis*, is citizenship more than a formality
and its practice more than a ritual.
By the same token, the Athenian citizen was not a corporate
being in our usual meaning of the term. Most present-day discussions of the Athenianâs lack of individuality and the *polis*âs tendency to subserve his personality to an overbearing collectivity are
weighed down by Eurocentrically neurotic images of the individual as such. The modern identification of individuality with egotism and personality with neurosis has been overindulged under
the rubric of âmodernityâ with an arrogance that bears comparison only with the conceited claims of psychoanalysis and psychohistory to explain the human drama in all its aspects. That human
beings can be individuated in different waysâsome as highly social and political beings, others as private and self-indulgent beings, still others as combinations and permutations of bothâis as
alien to the imperialistic claims of âmodernityâ as it is to the
admirers of *gemeinschaft*, the stagnant folk community based on
kinship and organismic relationships. To the Hellenic citizen of a
seemed as prehuman as the folk community seemed prepolitical.
Individuality meant citizenship. And, ideally, citizenship meant
the personal wholeness that came from deep roots in tradition, a
complexity of social bonds, richly articulated civic relationships,
shared festivals, *philia*, freedom from clientage and freedom for
collective self-determination through institutions that fostered the
full participation and everyday practice of a creative body politic.
To he such a citizen, one had to live in a *polis*âa city that possessed an *agora*, a space to convene general assemblies of the
people, a theater to dramatize the reality and ideology of freedom,
and the ceremonial squares, avenues, and temples that gave it
reverential meaning. To remove any of these elements that made
up this whole was to instantly destroy it. Without every one of
them, cultivated on a daily basis by the *paideia* of citizenship and
guided by an unerring concept of *areté*, the Athenian ideal of
citizenship fell apart and its institutions became hollow forms.
But such notions, valuable as they may be, lack a processual
content that sees this whole from the standpoint of an ever-fuller
development. We can see this by looking closely at the quixotic
nature of the Greek dramatic tragedy itselfâthe staged experience of the *polis* and citizen. For it was through the tragedy that
the Athenian underwent self-examination, much as though he
could withdraw from his own skin and observe himself thoughtfully for what he really was. It is notable that all the tragedies we
have at our disposal are made up of mythic and epic material. As
civic experiences, they seem to function dissonantly with stuff that
is drawn from a prepolitical world, from eras that precede the
heroines are Bronze Age characters who still live under the commandments of a tribal or warrior society, by canons of right and
wrong that are archaic at best and chthonic at worst. In the transformations that the dramas recount from one world to another, we
rarely seem to rise from new foundations embedded in still older
ones to the edifice that the audience knew at handâthe *polis* of
the, fifth century B.C. and its democracy.
Yet the antiquity of the characters, material, and themes with
which all the great tragedians seem to have worked is belied by
a startling sense of innovation, by tensions from which new ideals,
institutions, and credos are born. The, *Oresteia* seems to not only
justify radically new communal dispensations, indeed most of
which already existed when the trilogy was presented; its radicalism consists in the fact that Atheneâs decrees are fraught with the
promise of change, with motives that are likely to yield ever-wider
ethical and political horizons. One senses that a community
guided by justice has just begun to emerge, that the civic ideal of
freedom is still nascent, that citizenship and the *polis* are still
experiencing birth pangs and their future still lies before them.
Few Athenians, I suspect, could have left such dramas without
feeling an intense sense of futurity and a serene commitment to
growth. **Prometheus Bound** is even more challenging in its thirst
for heroic innovation and its passion for a fuller arid richer experiential life, as are the Oedipus dramas for truth at all costs.
Hence, seemingly conservative material is played, replayed,
and ultimately transmuted into searingly progressive hopes and
possibilities. When we bear witness to these dramas by viewing
them in all their starkness as idealized âarchetypesâ of an immutable human nature, we do violence to the tensions they probably
produced in the Athenian audiences of their day. These plays
were no mere spectacles or cathartic outlets for pent-up civic
anxieties. Quite to the contrary: they were sources of motivation
and tension, designed to move their audiences forward to noble
deeds and great enterprises, to contrast past with present so that
meaning, continuity, and tendency could be imparted to the future. They voiced a hope in the human spirit that belies the conventional interpretation of the Athenian drama as fatalistic in its
view of life and resigned in its image of destiny. Indeed, it is with
Euripides, that most âmodern,â ârealistic,â and âindividualisticâ
of the Greek tragedians, that hopelessness, alienation, and the
insufferable burden of circumstances seem to devour the characters of the drama and exhaust the hopes of the audience. Here, the
drama with its promise of futurity and hope.
The *polis* was no less a theater for the practice of virtue than
the orchestra at the foot of the Acropolis was a home for the
performance of the plays it watched. And the citizen was no less
an actor in a great civic drama than the men who performed for
him with masks in the City Dionysos. In both cases, the plot we
call the history of Athens incorporated the layered traditions that
formed its cultural biography and ideology. So central was the
citizen to this plot with his âfreedom forâ as well as his âfreedom
from,â that the histories of the time, when they refer to Attica,
speak more commonly of âthe Atheniansâ than they do of âAthens.â Unerringly, they reveal that Athens was no mere collection
of structures, no simple geographic locale, that any aggregate of
people could occupy without the *polis* losing its authenticity. Admittedly, the city outlived the *polis*, and the democracy in a formal sense outlived the citizens. Democratic institutions persisted
in a truncated form long after Athens s final defeat by the
Macedonians at Krannon in 322 B.C. No city was a *polis*, in Aristotleâs view, unless it had an *agora*; but, needless, to say, no *agora*
could have produced a democracy unless it had the kind of citizen
the historians of that day called âthe Athenians.â
----
There is a myth that the classical Athenian *polis* was the spontaneous product of custom and tradition. Hence, its integrity rested
largely on hidden presuppositions of which it was largely unconscious, indeed, to which it was sublimely oblivious. This notion of
an unreflective Athenian morality, imputed to Hegel and held by
many romantics in the last century, is belied by almost everything
we know about the democracy. The Aeskylean tragedies and Periklesâs funeral oration, to cite two highly important and widely
separated examples, completely refute the image of the democracy as a phenomenon based on mere habit and convention. One
must totally ignore Kleisthenesâs reforms and the subtle melding
of religious tradition with clearly formulated political goals not to
recognize that the democracy was a consciously crafted structure,
the product of purposeful, insightful, and thoughtful efforts to
achieve clearly perceived goalsâand, let me add, guided by a
philosophy and practice of its own. The introduction of the lot, the
rotation and limitation of tenure in public office, the development
of the assembly and the *boule*âall reveal a degree of intentionality and clarity of purpose that has few equals in any later constitutional developments. That Sokrates was executed for questioning
this order on charges that were archaic even by conservative
standards of fifth-century Athens has more to do with the politics
of the trial, particularly Sokratesâ arrogance and his desire for
martyrdom, than the challenge his philosophy posed to the *polis*âs
âethical order.â No political community was more aware of its
uniqueness and wondrous of its achievement than the Athenian
democracy. And no one was more consciously committed to this
humanly wrought body of institutions than the Athenian citizen.
By contrast, later ideals of citizenship, even insofar as they were
modeled on the Athenian, seem more unfinished and immature
than the originalâhence, the very considerable discussion I have
given to the Athenian citizen and his context. As we shall see
shortly, there were impressive attempts to create patterns of civic
freedom that approximated the democratic *polis* in medieval city-states and in the American and French revolutions. These attempts were usually intuitive. The Americans who attended town
meetings in New England after 1760 and the French **sans-culottes**
who filled the radical sections of Paris in 1793â94 were hardly
aware of the political drama that unfolded in Athens some two
millennia earlier, although their more knowledgeable spokesmen
fingered Plutarch throughout their lives and occasionally adopted
heroic names during fervent moments of the two revolutions.
What was lacking in their attempts to achieve a living approximation of civic democracy was not merely ideology. Greece, commonly Athens (although Spartaâs garrison-state was a close runner-up for some utopian writers and for Rousseau), was held up as a
fascinating experiment in popular self-governance and, as usual,
compromised with the republican ideals generated by the emerging nation-state,
For this reason, the Athenian ideal of citizenship, like its parallel creation, politics, demands careful exploration today even
more than at any time in the past. If moderns find democratic
politics and citizenship a desideratum, they will never achieve
them without a supreme act of consciousness. They must not only
want it but know it. Athenian civic goals, for all their shortcomings
(notably Athensâs treatment of women, alien residents, and its
widespread use of slave labor), must be rooted in an everyday
notion of what we mean by politics. Is it statecraft? Or does it
center around social entities such as cooperative, vocational societies or tribes in the countercultural sense of this much-abused term? Or some broad concept of grass-roots organization that
passes under words such as âlocalism,â âdecentralism,â and âbioregionalismâ? Is it an educational activityâa civic *paideia*âthat
fosters the citizenâs empowerment, both spiritually as well as institutionally? Or is it primarily a form of âmanagementâ whose goal
is administrative efficiency and fiscal shrewdness?
No modern body of ideas, to my knowledge, has wrestled with
the answers to these questions adequately enough to draw clear
distinctions among the social, the political, and the statist so that
a meaningful outlook can be formulatedâone that will seek the
delicate balance of ingredients (traditional, familial, ethical, and
institutional) and the *paideia* that articulates an authentically
democratic politics with a concept of citizenship that gives this
outlook reality. Nor do we have a clear idea of the extent to which
the city, properly conceived as a humanly scaled ethical community, differs from urbanization and the inhuman scale produced by
the nation-state. We rarely understandâhow integrally an ethical
politics is wedded to a comprehensible civic scale, to the city itself,
conceived as a thoroughly manageable and participatory union of
citizens, richly articulated by tradition and by social, cultural, and
political forms. We live so contemporaneously within the given
state of affairs, the overbearing ânowâ that eternalizes the status
quo, that no society is more prey to the workings of mindless forces
than bur own. Bereft of a serious regard for history, indeed for the
experiences of our own century, we find ourselves in the airless
vacuum of an immutable âpresent/ a time warp that precludes
any sense of futurity and ability to reason innovatively.
Accordingly, where thinking of a crude kind does exist, lines of
thought fecklessly crisscross each other like the scrawlings of an
infant that can barely grasp a pencil. Oligarchies are accepted as
democracies; virtual monarchies as republics; state institutions as
social forms; social forms as political ones. One, can hardly speak,
here, of a kind of shallow eclecticism that afflicts every age; rather
one encounters a potpourri of unfinished notions, barely worthy
of being called âideas,â that are mingled together in the viscera
rather than the head. To think out ideas to their logical conclusion,
to be consistent and complete in thought, is viewed as a form of
intellectual aggression that stimulates reticence or withdrawal
rather than dialogue or response. The modern âegoâ is now so
fragile that the mere presence of passion, particularly in the form
of argumentation, is a stimulus to flight or, worse, cause for a
yielding quietism. The emphasis that the Athenians placed on
speaking, which was identified with democracy, spells out the
extent to which a qualitative breach separates our pitiful image of
public activity from the classical one of two millennia ago.
What should be stressed, for the present, is that the Athenian
ideal of citizenship did not die in the formal sense, even after
Macedonia had eviscerated the democracy. The *ekklesia* and
Mediterranean-wide belief in Athensâs uniqueness, all the more to
cloak a growing despotism that finally caused the last institutional
vestiges of the democracy to wither completely. And here lies a
lesson that later institutionally oriented democrats were to learn
at great cost. An *agora* does not in itself produce a *polis*, nor does
an *ekklesia* in itself produce citizens. All of them must exist, to be
sure, if a democracy is to be established; but they remain mere
formalities if they fail to interact in the proper way to form a
unified whole. It was this largely formal sense of democracy and
citizenship that served, in part at least, to abort the only attempt
to rescue the Roman republic in the guise of the Athenian *polis*.
It would be difficult to tell from Plutarchâs biographies of Tiberius
and Gaius Gracchus that the brothers were no mere agrarian
reformers; indeed that their laws to supplant the Senateâs powers
by the authority of the *comitia tributa* came as close to a fundamental political revolution as Rome ever experienced. The brothers, in M. I. Rostovtzeffâs view, were clearly out to âset up at Rome
a democracy of the Greek type,â a âdream or farce,â as he calls
It, that was designed âto transfer from the Senate to the popular
assembly the decision of all important business, or, in other words,
to set up at Rome a democracy after the Athenian model.â{27} Nor
Was this goal entirely impractical, at least institutionally. âTo secure this point no special law was required: according to the constitution all important business was, in theory, settled by the popular assembly; the innovation was this, that business which by
custom had hitherto been decided by the Senate was now laid by
[Gaius] Gracchus, as tribune, before the popular assembly, for
their consideration and decision.â{28}
The effort ultimately foundered not for want of institutional mechanisms but for lack of a genuine citizenry. Despite
Rostovtzeffâs aristocratic biases, he is on solid ground when he
emphasizes that âto allow land even to every member of the
proletariat could never bring back a time when the state rested
NOCurely upon a strong peasant population.â{29} The culture that
produced men such as Cincinnatus or the elder Cato was waning
and had to be recovered or a new one developed in its place if
mere institutional changes were to be viable and lasting. The
Gracchi would have had to deal with still another change that
would ultimately undermine the entire republican edifice. Rome
was no longer a city in any Hellenic sense of the term. It was the
center of an emerging empire, an *urbs*, to use the conventional
Latin word for âcity,â that had ceased to be a *civitas*, the word
Romans commonly used to denote a âunion of citizens.â The terminological distinction is apt: the Roman *urbs* was growing uncontrollably by the second century B.C., at the expense of the Roman
scope, especially after the spoils of the Punic Wars began to fill its
coffers. Conceivably, the yeoman-citizens who founded the republic could have turned it into a democracy. But once they âcame
down from the Seven Hillsâ on which Rome was founded, they
became âsmall,â to use Heineâs words. The âidea of Romeâ as a
spiritual heritage diminished in direct proportion to the growth of
the city. âThe greater Rome grew,â Heine wrote, âthe more this
idea dilated; the individual lost himself in it: the great men who
remain eminent are borne up by this idea, and it makes the littleness of the little men even more pronounced.â{30}
The decline of the ancient world did not efface the ideals that
Athens and Rome inspired. Later eras were to blur them so that
we now speak of two kinds of âdemocracy,â âdirectâ and ârepresentative,â as though they derive from a common heritage. During inspired moments, medieval and modern cities were to fluctuate between the two and, at times, come closer to a Hellenic
democracy and citizenry than the Gracchi could have achieved in
Rome. What these cities achieved in fact, however, they rarely
achieved in ideology; hence their patterns of civic freedom were
basically intuitive creations. They did not last long. But in an era
of chilling discontinuities, when our knowledge of western culture
is in grave peril of disappearing, we can no more ignore the legacy
of their example than we can ignore the sprawling urbanization
that threatens our civic identity and political freedom.
Although the city was the cultural center of the ancient world, its
material base was extremely fragile. Hence the remarkable rise
and fall of cities throughout antiquity. City life depended to a
remarkable degree on the viability and the economy of agrarian
communities and labor so that cities appear more as islands in a
vast rural ocean than self-sustaining economic entities. Indeed,
prudent estimates of the number of rural workers needed to sustain a single city dweller have been placed at a ratio of ten to one.
Hence any serious agricultural catastrophe like a drought, floods,
or pest infestation, not to speak of wars that devastated agriculture, could lead to the breakdown, indeed the complete disappearance, of a major city as so many civic ruins from antiquity
attest to this very day.
The fragile dependence of the city on the countrysideâs economy placed a high.premium on the stability of urban institutions.
The Hellenic emphasis on the *polis* as a realm of reason that had
to vigilantly guard itself against a surrounding world of chaotic
uncertainty and mindless barbarismâa sensibility so important to
understanding its attitude toward women, slaves, and aliensâis
not without its roots in the compelling realities of ancient urban
life. A nature tamed by man, specifically by well-established and
reliable farmers, forms the matrix of Hellenic philosophy and the
great cultural monuments of the Athenian *polis*. Civic democracy
was largely an agrarian democracy, and its ideal of the farmer-citizen, however dubious it became in the later history of the *polis*,
was the product of a very viable agrarian heritage. Rome, too,
developed these ideals and did ndt require Greek culture to produce them.
Correspondingly, the ancient city was not only a center for
country life whose standards were formed by farmers, later by
nobles and âcountry gentlemen,â but it was âseafaringâ in a very
loose sense of the term. Owing to the insecurity that the city felt
as an âatoll... on an ocean of rural primitivism,â it direly needed
access to the sea to cope with any dislocations between town and
country. The all-important factor that could correct any imbalances caused by drought, flood, plague, arid other such disasters
was imports or, put more bluntly, the tribute that a city-state could
exact from a league of captive âalliesâ or the victims of outright
conquest. The Delian League,i which Athens established to assert
its supremacy over the eastern Mediterranean, quickly turned
into a relatively modest looting enterprise to feed and provide the
âgood fifeâ for its citizens. The Roman Empire is a lasting historical example of parasitism run riot to the point of moral, cultural, and societal suicide.
Hence, ancient cities were located within a hundred miles or
so of the Mediterranean Sea or close to navigable rivers that led
to major bodies-of water. Ancient Lugdunum (modern Lyons)
provides us, with an example of a city that Rome founded in 43
B.C., deeply inland in Gaul, that was. felicitously located at the
confluence of the Rhone and Saone rivers. Beyond the coasts and
rivers, cities dwindled to towns and, not much farther, to villages
and hamlets that then phased into a little known wilderness where
military forts kept a guarded eye on restless barbarian tribes. Ancient cities were never autonomous urban centers. Fragile in the
extreme, they depended upon local agricultural communities for
the most important essentials of fife, a very simple technology, and
a considerable amount of human muscle power to work it, If they
expanded beyond the capacity of their agricultural base, they
direly needed tribute from other city-states to sustain themselves
unless they enjoyed natural blessings such as the Nile, whose annual overflow in September provided Egypt with endless quantities of fertile soil from the highlands of Ethiopia.
Modern urban dwellers tend to feel uneasy about so tentative
and qualified an image of the city., We like to think of cities as
âeternalâ and urban cultural fife as free of rural social influences.
We are willing to grant that cities do change with architectural
innovations, technology, and societal advances but that basically
they are immune to the ravages of time and the vicissitudes of
history. The tombs of buried cities in Anatolia, Mesopotamia,
North Africa, and the ruins of Central America and Mexico are
grim reminders that cities can die forever without successors to
overlay them, indeed that historically they have been terribly
Vulnerable to social and ecological changes. Nor do we like to
think that, cities have any significant roots in agrarian societies,
Indeed that they did not always âdominateâ the countryside in the
(ill-encompassing sense that they do today. The enormous power
modern cities exercise over rural fifeânot only economically and
technologically but culturallyâseems to be a historic destiny in
Our eyes that is structured into citification or âcivilizationâ from
its very origins, a *telos* that predestines urban fife to achieve lasting supremacy over all other fife ways. The great urban belts that
sprawl across the land, ugly as they may be, appear to us as the
culmination, perhaps the fulfillment, of a drama in which early
temple cities or Greek *poleis* were merely archetypal characters
ill a larger and more sweeping civic story that reaches its climax
In what we call âmodernityâ and all its citified amenities. That
contemporary urbanization does not represent the culmination or
fulfillment of citification, that the history of the city cannot be
properly understood with the hindsight and Eurocentricity of a
New Yorker, Parisian, Berliner, or Londoner reveals a modern
conceit that under critical examination tells us how skewed and
misleading are popular ideas of how cities actually developed and
the special identities they acquired.
This conceit, to be sure, is not entirely modern. Ancient empires such as the Babylonian and Persian built cities to last and
earnestly believed in their immortality. The Greek image of the
fame that would survive his own mortality. The words âeternal
Romeâ are proverbial. Even before the rise of Christianity, they
entered deeply into the consciousness of the cityâs citizens. As it
turned out, the closing years of the empire, a span of two centuries
before it finally fell apart, were riddled by deep civic pessimism.
The Romans of that time were filled with a fatalistic despair about
the future of their city and eventually transferred their allegiance
from the âeternal cityâ to the âCity of God.â
What distinguished their civic optimism from our civic arrogance, however, is our preening belief in the autonomy of the city,
our conviction that city life and its traditions have always enjoyed
a supremacy over rural lifeways and cultures, indeed that the
former stands in innovative and exciting contrast to the latter.
This conceit is very different from the ancient commitment to the
city and has its origins in the highly introverted civic development
of Europe during the late Middle Ages. Judging from the comedies
of antiquity, Greeks and Romans had their âcountry bumpkinsâ
who were the naive foils for âcity slickers. But the ancients never
doubted that these âbumpkinsâ were their âcountry cousinsâ in a
very real cultural and material sense. The ancestral farm, if an
urban citizen owned one, or the family village where the bones of
his ancestors lay, was a place to which he repaired from the demands and stresses of city living. It was there that he found his
ârootsâ and from there that he carried his household deities into
the very confines of the city. It was from the country, too, that he
acquired his bread, cheese, figs, and precious olives so characteristic of Mediterranean fare, for no doubt existed in his mind that,
all its cultural amenities aside, the city was materially dependent
upon the immediate countryside and the farmers who trundled its
produce into his squares.
His political fife, such as it was after the decline of the *polis*, had
a distinct rural imprint: it centered around assemblies even in
Rome and other cities outside Latium, on such councils of âeldersâ
as the Senate, and, in republican times, on a citizen-militia, all of
which were institutions formed by early village and town democracies. It is in this sense, by no means a strictly exploitative one,
that we can agree with Chester G. Starrâs observation that nearly
all ancient cities âcontrolled a wide expanse of countryside, which
extended in more recently urbanized areas as far as fifty miles or
more from the city walls; they thus resembled an American or
English county more than our purely urban units of government.
Commerce and industry might have some significance within this
complex but did not need to do so, for its unity rested primarily
on administrative, agricultural, and psychological bonds.â{31} A
brisk walk of an hour or so could bring a Roman within clear sight
of farmland and within two or three additional hours to villages
that seemed largely untouched by urban culture.
That the ancient city also carried enormous political weight in
Mediterranean life and was a source of considerable ferment, indeed, potentially, of serious rebellions against its imperial sovereigns, is a fact that never left the minds of the Roman emperors.
Not that the peasantry was totally passive and free of strong resentmentsânot only toward the imperial city but also its own
urban centers. Atticaâs âparty of the Plain,â as historians call it,
enviously regarded the Athenian town-dweller as a parasite and
periodically aligned itself against him, hence Kleisthenesâ shrewd
admixture of urban with rural *trittyes* to neutralize these conflicts.
In Roman times a rural police was created by the city, particularly
In the Near East, to maintain âorderâ among the agricultural poor.
But the emperors kept an especially tight rein on the cities
under their control, for it was here that internecine conflicts
against urban oligarchies and civic chauvinism could reach acute
proportions. âThe ancient city was an institution which swallowed
up much of its citizensâ hearts,â Starr tells us, and Roman emperors âwere undoubtedly right in feeling that the Roman world
could not endure outright war among its constituent units but the
necessary alternative was deplorable: the race for titles was miserable stuff to fire civic loyalty and to promote urban thinking.â{32}
Ultimately, through imperial paternalism, legal constraints, and
the use of oligarchies to control or deflect the anger of lower
orders in their own cities, âthe vigor of local politics waned; the
cities were not granted, as a substitute, a really significant, inspiriting influence on the imperial government. In all this the Empire
was wiping out not merely freedom of thought in the political
Sphere but the very possibility of serious political action for the
bulk of its subjects. So it was destroying a very important focus for
the forces which had led to the expansion and remarkable vitality
of Mediterranean civilization up to this point. The upper classes
and the Caesars both delivered devastating blows at the sense of
local attachment, the solidarity of the city, from which the thinkers of the past had drawn their strength.â Whatever Roman civilization seemed to produce in the way of order and uniformity of
laws, it more than destroyed in the way of creativity and political
commitment. By the latter part of the fifth century A.D., the Mediterranean basin had ceased to be either orderly or innovative. In
balance, the cost of imperial and bureaucratic control from above
with its loss of local control and participation outweighed, by far,
the dubious benefits it professed to confer and the entire basin
suffered a collapse that was to haunt civilization throughout future
centuries.[6]
[6] For a more detailed discussion of the decline of Rome and the problems the
empire created, the reader should read my book, *The Limits of the City* (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1973, pp. 32â35).
----
By contrast to the Mediterranean basin, Europe through the Middle Ages and well into modern times followed a very different
development. Although European patterns of civic freedom
never equalled the institutional and political creativity of the
the Greek cities, and it is from this world that modern images of
urban supremacy really derive. From the thirteenth century onward, particularly in Italy and the lowlands of modern Belgium
and Holland, city-states began to emerge that were structured
around uniquely urban tasksâartisan oriented, financial, commercial, and industrialâthat slowly loosened urban fife from its traditional agrarian matrix and provided the town with an authentic
civic fife and momentum of its own.
Which is not to say that medieval towns and cities ceased to be
dependent upon their rural environs for food and raw materials.
But as time passed, in different parts of western Europe, it was to
be the city that gradually remade the countryside in its own image
and entangled the landed nobility in its own economic and political concerns. And ultimately it was to be the city that imposed its
technics, economic relationships, culture, and values on agrarian
communities.
Traditional agrarian attitudes did not place a high premium on
artisans, merchants, and financiers; these were not orders that
were respected in ancient society. A Greek or Roman âbourgeoisâ
who made a profitable income from trade and workshops tried to
accumulate enough wealth in order to retire on landed property
of his own and five in rural gentility with the airs of a noble.
Capital migrated from town to country, not the reverse. The
medieval world radically altered this movement. For the first time
on a large scale, urban entrepreneurs began, to view their vocations as honorable and invest their earnings from generation to generation in their own enterprises.
As family fortunes increased, they remained in the city and
were not invested into estates. Quite to the contrary, it was the
Italian and Flemish noble who often moved to town and began to
enchance his own fortunes by involving himself in industry, trade,
and foreign promise. The âmerchant princeâ of the Middle Ages
was not simply a euphemism for men of ignoble lineages who
managed to, acquire âprincelyâ fortunes from trade. The words
often included noblemen of highly prestigious families who regarded the city as a center of a very lucrative commerce and began to participate in it with the avidity of the most pedestrian
burgher.
How this reversal of traditional trends occurred can only be
noted summarily here, The breakup of the top-heavy, highly parasitic, and costly Roman Empire led to a general retreat of the Latin
cities and their European affines in Iberia, Gaul, and Britain to
their authentic ecological *chora*: the land base that could properly
support a modest urban population. As sources of tribute began to
break away from the empire and its provinces were assailed by
repeated invasions of semitribal German, Slav, and Magyar peoples, the fragile ancient city dwindled to little more than a village
scale, at least in western Europe where urban fife had a, very
limited land base and abutted the vast forest that still covered
most of the continent. Romeâs population alone declined from its
highpoint of a million to less than 50,000 in the âDark Agesâ that
followed and never fully recovered demographically through the
medieval period, despite its enormous importance as the center of
western Christianity. Already, as early as the third century, the
European provinces such as Iberia, Gaul, and Britain began to
detach themselves from the empire in everything but name and
move toward a localist economy that produced only for their own
particular needs. As John Mundy and Peter Reisenberg point out,
the foundations for a decentralized medieval society were not
created by German invaders, the âbarbarians at the gatesâ who
sounded the death knell of a terminally ill empire; they were
established by Rome itself when the late Caesars, faced with a
completely unwieldly imperial structure, set each order in Roman
society adrift with the necessary âduties, privileges and special
jurisdictions [it needed] to implement its work.â Each group, in
effect, was obliged to make âits own lawâ in order to survive.
âMoreover, the old classical conception of liberty was replaced by
something less grand but more socially exact. Gildsmen, or **collegiati,** were privileged, for example, even to the equestrian
grade. But privilege depended upon obligatory service. This perception of an inmixture of liberty and servitude pervaded late
Roman and much of medieval social thought.â{33}
The veering of the former Roman provinces toward a highly
localist society, one in which each component was internally held
together by an elaborate hierarchy of clearly defined rights and
duties, laid the foundations for European feudalism. Autarchy,
now based on hierarchy, surfaced with a vengeance in the form
of minutely segmented and self-sufficient communities, all supported by agriculture and a rude form of manorial artisanship.
Cities that were once the islands in a rural world largely disappeared while the rural society seemed to solidify into minute congeries of simple manors, each surrounded by small dependent
villages. The serfs who peopled these villages were not attached
permanently to the land. Both manor and village, in turn, seemed
to be haunted by the nearby debris of ruined cities, some partly
occupied, which were testimony to an exotic world clouded by
legends of past greatness and the misty traditions of imperial
power. Within this setting, we do not have to go too far to understand the origins of the Arthurian legends of Britain and the dreams of grandeur that clustered around the name of Charlemagne.
These ruins came to fife very slowly, often as the building
materials of churches, modest villas, and town halls. The medieval
towns and the few cities that we find in the eleventh century after
the great tides of âbarbarianâ invaders and the fractured empires
of Charlemagne receded into history were very unusual
phenomena. Although they were never independent materially,
there is a very real sense in which they were to become quite
autonomous economically, to an extent, in fact, that was quite rare
in the ancient city. To begin with, they were not simply religious
or administrative centers as were so many of their classical predecessors, although such centers were fairly common in medieval
Europe. What is significant about them is that they were largely
structured around the tasks that most markedly distinguish the
city from the agrarian village: crafts, trade, a nascent form of
mechanized industry, and a cultureâmoral, artistic, architectural,
and even religiousâthat is peculiar to such a citified constellation
of activities. No longer was nonagricultural work demeaning, nor
for that matter was work generally, as ultimately became the case
during the imperial period of Rome and the old Mediterranean
slavocracy. Quite to the contrary, nonagricultural work was to be
celebrated over all other forms as authentic evidence of âcivilization,â so that, etymologically speaking, the word now came into its
own. The artisan and tradesman, normally metics whom the ancient city dweller viewed with condescension as the urban counterparts of the rural âprimitivesâ (the view that the imperial age
created toward its once idealized yeomanry), now found themselves the center of a new concept of urbanity, indeed, the cityâs
most prized and productive member. Trade itself, which aristocrats at all times slyly exploited to their own advantage, was
openly acknowledged as an honorable enterprise, and wealthy
merchants began to give lavishly of their fortunes to adorn this
new civic temple to their interests. However much the Church
viewed profit making as intrinsically evil, it soon learned to accommodate itself to this new civic reality despite its pious denunciations of gain from the pulpit.
This new kind of city appeared not only because of the extraordinary energy Europe brought to a world drained by imperial
tribute; it also emerged because of the inherent weakness that
marked a highly decentralized and parochial system of agriculture. Whatever may be the image Roman nobles developed of
their servile farming orders, the aristocrats of the ancient world
still prized their status and traditions as landed gentry. To own a
large estate, worked by gangs of slaves and tenants, was as much
a calling as it was a lucrative enterprise. The nobles, moreover,
had used the Empire to wrest all political power from the artisan
and merchant orders, and thus gave their imprimature to the
ancient city: its odium of parasitism, display, indolence, luxury,
and class arrogance. The cities they now controlled became monuments to their power as lords of a basically agrarian economy and
culture. Under the Caesars, this economy and culture did not
disappear; quite to the contrary, it was greatly strengthened by a
huge bureaucracy and enriched by an immense flow of tribute.
The ancient city never transcended these economic and cultural
limits. The *polis*, to be sure, gave it a creativity that made civic
life seem like a work of art. Rome, particularly under the Empire,
gave it a highly elaborate state apparatus that made it a self-destructive engine for exploiting Mediterranean society.
The medieval city was more fortunate and found itself surprisingly free of these limits. Agrarian society in the Middle Ages was
much too fragmented to establish lasting obstacles to urban development:, and its culture was much too introverted to challenge the
new âcivilizationâ nurtured by the towns. The famous medieval
maxim, âUrban air makes for freedom/â could be, said to include
freedom of thought and an openness to innovation as well as personal and political liberty. Like a calculating observer who can
patiently stand by while his opponents exhaust themselves in mutual combat, the medieval towns played for time and waited for
the temporal lords to drain their strength in the ceaseless rivalries
that marked the era. When the local nobles were weak enough or
drained of their wealth, the cities stepped in to assert their own
autonomy, either by buying their freedom or by force of arms, and
ultimately were to assert their supremacy over the countryside.
This drama, to be sure, did not unfold with the elegant consistency we often expect from a good story. Many cities and towns
failed to gain their freedom for generations, despite bitter struggles with their territorial lords. And when they did so, their liberties were often fragile and highly vulnerable to internal as well as
external challenges. In retrospect, however, we can see a fairly
distinct pattern of civic freedom emerge, not only from territorial
lords but also structurally, within the medieval *civitas* itself. The
Italian city-states, in particular, provide the **dramatis personae**
and almost exemplary âplot linesâ for an overall story of European
civic development. Not that other citiesâFlemish, German,
French, and Swissâare not good examples in their own right, or,
in some cases, more lasting patterns of civic freedom. But what
Lauro Martines calls the âpower and, imaginationâ of the Italian
city-states is so vibrant, so artistically creative and institutionally
stimulating, that one senses a degree of organicity and roundedness rarely matched for that period by other European regions.{34}
And if we rise above the national chauvinism that afflicted medievalists of the recent past, it would be hard to disagree with Mundy
that the âdistinction between the northern European and Italian
townâ drawn by Belgiumâs great historian, Henri Pirenne, a distinction that so greatly biased a whole generation of medieval
scholars toward the northern city-states, âseems to have no basis
in fact, at least through the ages of urban renewal up to the twelfth
century,â a time when urban freedom reached its peak internally.{35}
We also know that the movement for civic freedom really
began in Italy and only later did it move up to Flanders, northern
France, and southern, Germany. Thereafter it became a contagion
in the cities of western and central Europe. To discuss so mixed
and uneven a development in civic freedomâ we would be obliged
to leap almost dervishly from one region to another to uncover the
underlying sequence of events that makes medieval urban development reasonably intelligible. If most of this account focuses on
the Italian experience, it is because the peninsulaâs city-states encapsulate in a clearly definable area the basic cycle that marked
the rise and decline of civic democracy in Europe as a whole.
Indeed, it was in Italy that the city-state of the High Middle Ages
was to come into its own, and it is from the rich accounts of that
civic worldâits extraordinary art and architecture, its changing
political relationships, and its cycle of birth, maturation, and decayâthat the European municipality was to play out its most authentic internal development and lead, almost unerringly, to the urban
drama that is unfolding before our eyes today.
----
The origins of these city-states need not concern us. After at least
a millennium of urban development, from the legendary founding
of Rome in 753 B.C. to the last of the emperors in 476 A.D., probably no area in ancient Europe was more citified than Italy and few
municipalities exhibited more staying power than those that the
German invaders engulfed as they rolled over the peninsula. Thus,
Italian cities never really disappeared. However much they declined demographically, they recovered fairly early and by the
tenth century began to grow with exceptional verve and energy.
Nor need we trouble ourselves too much about the factors that
led to this recovery. So far as the northern Mediterranean was
concerned, the Saracen floodtide that swept over the basin began
to recede by the eleventh century: even Sicily was reclaimed for
Christianity by 1091, after two centuries of Muslim occupation. By
this time, a lively trade existed between Italian and Arab merchants until the Mediterranean between the twelfth and fourteenth centuries was largely controlled by the Italian city-states
lake from 1150 to 1350. These city-states were soon the major
entrepot agents that brought Christian and Muslim into commercial contact with each other, and the economic foundations for a
flourishing municipal fife were securely established.
The locale of the Italian city-state, or **communa** to use its medieval Latin name, covered most of the northern and central areas of
the peninsula and embraced the great Renaissance cities of Florence, Venice, Verona, Pisa, Sienna, and Cremona, to cite only a
few, and those great political nodal points of Italyâs history, Milan,
Genoa, and Bologna. It is not the Renaissance that will concern us
here, except insofar as the Dominican Fra Savonarola represented
a popular reaction to the aristocratic and simoniacal world that
fostered it, and it is not the **communa** as a âcity republic,â words
so easily interchangeable with âcity-stateâ that will be our main
focus of interest. What is insufficiently known about the Italian
commune is the extent to which it became a stage for a working
democracy and its actors a new expression for an active citizenry.
Dazzling as its cultural treasures and adventurous as its stories
may be, we must put aside the pure glamour of the commune and
examine those brief periods when it seemed more like a *polis* than
a republic.
Democracy clearly emerged in the early Italian cities, not only
representative forms of governance and oligarchies of various
kinds, only to submerge and then reappear again for a short time
in richly articulated forms. Its principal institution took the.form
of a popular assembly and we hear of it almost from the inception
of the commune itself. The Italian commune, it should be clear,
was not simply a community or even a town in the customary civic
sense of the term, although it was this as well. It was above all an
association of burghers who were solemnly united by an oath or
we might simply designate as a town into a vibrant fraternity.
Although motivated by shared practical concerns, the burghers
who took this oath were presumably foreswearing their personal
self-interest on behalf of a common one, a conscious act of mutual
fealty not to a local noble, cleric, military chieftain, or distant
monarch. Despite its strongly religious terms, it was an act of
citizenship, unique in an age of religious congregations, that
pledged members of the commune to respect each othersâ civic
rights and extend them untampered to newcomers and future
generations.
The *conjuratio*, in fact, did considerably more: it committed the
citizens of the commune to orderly and broadly consensual ways
of governing themselves with a decent respect for individual liberty and a pledge to their mutual defense. The stormy conflicts
between the monarchs of the Holy Roman Empire and their Italian vassals, and more disruptively between local bishops, nobles,
and military captains over landed domains and control over the
cities, were resolved by a delineable and, at times, a logical course
of urban development to which the *conjuratio* forms a point of
ethical entry. Once the cities replaced arbitrary rule with some
kind of elective rule, coordinates emerged for gauging its political
evolution. Men then swore to aid and defend each other, to pledge
their prestige and bring their personal jurisdictions to the service
of a shared community, and to respectfully invest the chosen
heads of this civic association with executive and judicial powers.
A consulate, composed of all the consuls in formal assembly, constituted the highest executive and judicial magistracy of this remarkable association. We know that its members were chosen at
a general assembly of the commune itself, a popular assembly that
âwas quite likely convened with some regularity, and in times of
trouble even more often,â Lauro Martines tells us. âHere the
views of leading men were heard and important decisions taken,
usually by acclamation.â We know, too, that this general assembly
of âall the members of the communeâ was the âoldest communal
institutionâ of these Italian cities, and further, that the, consuls
usually âsounded out the general assemblyâ before they made any
major decisions about such issues as war and peace, taxes, and
laws.{36} What is so vexing is that we know so little about this revival
of a highly democratic, face-to-face form of political control and
of the citizens who created it. Whether age endowed it with the
legitimacy of an unbroken tradition back to ancient times, we do
not knowâonly that it was the oldest of the communeâs structures.
This much is clear: whatever authority the assembly enjoyed prior
to the consulateâthat is, if it existed at all before the *conjuratio*âis clouded by the furious infighting between clerics, nobles,
opportunists of all kinds who managed to grasp and lose control
of the cities for nearly two centuries before these civic entities
freed themselves of arbitrary rule and disruptive rivalries.
Considering the volatility of the Italian city-states, the assembly
soon lost ground to the consulate and the consuls, who began to
elect their own successors. The Italian city was never to be restrained by such Hellenic mores as ânothing in excessâ or the
Pythagorean ideal of **harmonia**. One could almost say that seldom
did anything but excess and explosive political theatrics, mark
these fervent and creative urban entities. In any case, civic leadership fell into the hands of large, wealthy families who were to
establish the parameters of civic âpolitics for centuries to come,
even after they were temporarily removed from power or replaced by newcomers from within or outside the city. The assembly, in turn, never totally disappeared. It lingered on in a highly
atrophied form and haunted the oligarchs and despots who
usurped its powers. We know that in Bergamo, for example, as
elsewhere, outgoing consuls were obliged to hold elections for
new ones in popular assemblies, although the nomination of candidates was the privilege of only a few. Such practices persisted well
into the twelfth century when cities such as Genoa and Pistoia
tried to eliminate prearranged nominations of consuls between
electors that favored one of the parties at the expense of another.
In time, this early popular democracy gave way to republican
forms of governance, and the powers of the city were invested in
a large legislature dominated by influential urban families. In
some places, the assembly continued on as a vestige to be manipulated by oligarchs. Elsewhere, it was replaced by âassembliesâ that
were simply republican legislatures. âEmulating all princely
courts and the general assemblies in Italian towns, some of these
[representative] assemblies hoped to meet four times a year,â
observes John H. Mundy. âThis was impracticable for general
assemblies, but smaller select councils often did meet three or four
times yearly....â{37} Although Mundy is referring here specifically
to England, the drift from popular assemblies to oligarchical councils was as true of Italy as it was for Europe generally. The âconciliarism,â as this parliamentary trend was called, essentially replaced civic democracies, such as they were, with authentic city
republics, and the great towns of Italy looked more, institutionally
speaking, like preimperial Rome than classical Athens.
We must not suppose, however, that Italy became a centralized
State at this time, even on a municipal base. Whether as a democracy or a republic, the Italian city rested to an astonishing extent
on little neighborhood âcommunesâ that existed within the larger
urban commune. We have no parallel for this development in
ancient Athens or Rome. Irrespective of the kind of consulate it
had, the cityâs neighborhoods acquired an autonomy of their own
that is truly spectacular by any standards of civic governance.
Fortified towers rose everywhereâin Milan, Florence, Pisa,
Verona, Pavia, Parma, and the likeâheld by noble families in
the commune as a whole. Oaths were sworn everywhere in the
tradition of the *conjuratio* but so localist in their commitments
that we can only describe a commune as a loose confederation of
neighborhood communes, indeed, a confederation of neighborhoods within the commune. âWhen a union of this sort brought
peace to a neighborhood,â observes Martines, âthat part of the city
became nearly impregnable, because the linking of towers and the
easy blocking of the narrow streets made for an effective domination of the adjoining area.â{38}
Let there be no mistake about the fact that these *consortia*
were anything but neighborhood democracies. The towers were
built by leading wealthy families who were much too powerful in
Home respects, and much too weak in others, to seize complete
control of the commune. They were highly localist oligarchies that
kept Italian cities in continual turmoil until they were supplanted
by despotic **signori**, family dynasties ruled by one man who replaced a multitude of oligarchies, often to be unseated again and
his sons restored in reckless shifts of aristocratic and military
power. Italian civic history is not notable for any even or linear
development from democracy through republican systems to oligarchy, monarchy, and despotism. All five of these institutional
forms bubbled up in an unpredictable assortment of patterns,
predominantly as one at certain times or in combination with each
other on many other occasions. Ultimately, the Renaissance cities
settled down as oligarchies and princely courts where an electrifying but aristocratic humanism gave us the priceless artistic treasures of that era.
But the *consortia* created âbadâ and lasting habits that fostered
a highly democratic atmosphere at the base of city fife. It produced neighborhood loyalty and citizen empowerment with a
vengeance. âPropertied urban inhabitants were attached tenaciously not merely to a city but to a street, a parish, an ambienceâto a radius of perhaps 150 meters,â declares Martines. âAnd
though a citizen might frequent an estate in the country, he lived
in the city and there, if fortunate, he died. More likely than not,
he married someone from that vicinage, and all his main blood
ties, as well as his closest friendships, were there. The character of
the neighborhood could be so distinctive, couldâ leave so deep an
imprint on its inhabitants, as to make for different linguistic expressions and even for different intonations or accents. Dante detected neighborhood differences in speech at Bologna.â[7]{39}
[7] This is a feature that existed even in New York during the 1930s, which I
distinctly recall as a young man. This great city, at one time an agglomeration of
a thousand ethnically unique neighborhoods, seemed to have been stopped in
time, for a generation or two, and created much the same degree of neighborhood
loyalties and distinctive accents. I have encountered such differences in New
Orleans today, although they are rapidly disappearing. The emergence of civic
variety, loyalty, and cultural diversity even in modern American cities is an important theme to which we shall return later in this book, and the consequences of
its loss will be fully explored as a consequence of contemporary urbanization.
These loyalties gave the commune a political vitality it never
fully lost until recent times. Conciliar governance did not abolish
major democratic features of the city such as the selection of
consuls by sortition at Lucca, for example, where the neighborhoods or **contrada** convened in their own assemblies and âlots
were drawn,â notes Daniel Waley, whereupon âeach of the 550
men who drew slips inscribed **elector consiliari** then had the duty
of naming one man from his own **contrada** as a councillor.â{40}
When the **podesta** system of government or **podesteria** was established in Italian communes that vested all executive power in a
single man, he too was often chosen this way. In Vicenza during
the mid-thirteenth century, twenty city electors âwere chosen by
lot, and of these twelve were eliminated by voting; the eight
remaining electors then proposed three names, from which the
final choice was made by a further vote of the council.â{41} The
councils, in turn, often required a quorum of two-thirds to arrive
at a decision, and in some cities councillors were fined for failing
to attend. Nor is it unusual to learn that a majority of two-thirds
was needed to make major decisions, at which time even larger
quorums and majorities as high as 10/11 or 16/17 were requiredâproportions that could almost be regarded as consensual.
The **podesteria**, for all its majesty and seeming absolutism, was
by no means the authoritarian ogre it initially appears to be. A
<em>podesta</em> was not selected from any members of the community.
He had to be an outsider who could distance himself from the
internecine familial and factional conflicts that often brought the
city to the brink of chaos, hence too the elaborate electoral system
that was meant to buffer the influence of particularly powerful
groups. Nor could he come from a neighboring commune, which
obviously was privy to the cityâs infighting. He was selected for his
impartiality, for his legal training, and ordinarily held his office for
no more than a year, often as little as six months. The consulate,
like the assembly, did not disappear; indeed, in Treviso as late as
1283, general assemblies of virtually all resident citizens who enjoyed rights to public office were convened to deal with emergencies, even if only to bestow almost despotic powers of control on
a military captain.
A detailed account of the **podesteria**, **signori**, the later courts of
the Sforza and Medici, and the republican oligarchies that overturned these various forms of one-man control, would require a
volume in itself. Here we must focus on the conflict between the
âPeopleâ and the ânobility,â the *popolo* and *nobilta* as they were
called respectively. Equivalently, we could have called the âpeopleâ the âfoot soldiersâ or **pedites** and the ânobilityâ the âknightsâ
or **milites**, the military characterizations so redolent of the rise of
Greeceâs **hoplites** and the supremacy they achieved over the aristocratic cavalry. The parallel, limited as it may be, is quite instructive. What the Italian citizens of the twelfth and early thirteenth
centuries called the *popolo* was in no sense the urban poor, the
inchoate stratum of journeymen, relatively unskilled craftsmen
who verged on being proletarians, laborers, servants, itinerant
tradesmen, runaway serfs, and that vast **déclassé** of beggars and
thieves who plagued the medieval cities almost from their inception. Many of these elements could be expected to follow any
standard that filled their empty pockets. In a feudal world where
a feeling of social place was crucial to oneâs sense of self-regard,
they were outside the pale of the communeâs life and its broader
political concerns.
^yhat the commune meant by the *popolo* were men with a
certain amount of material substance, such as master craftsmen,
professionals, notaries, well-off tradesmen, even financiers and an
emerging commercial bourgeoisie that owned sizable fortunes
from foreign trade. Although there was a close interlinking of the
draw precise class lines in the conflicts that brought the two into
opposition with each other, many of the *popolo* wereâ virtually
excluded from the cityâs political life and were treated like resident aliens, the **metics** of ancient Athens. They paid its taxes,
served in its militia, and were subject to all its laws without any
right to hold public office or enter into its civic councils. In cities
of 40,000 or more, active citizenship was restricted by property
qualifications, social status, and length of residence to a thousand
or less. Although the Milanese *popolo* provided the city with the
greatest part of its revenues, for example, they held only one-fifth
of the consulateâs offices. Later, on the intervention of the Holy
Roman Emperor, Otto IV, they were given half of the conciliar
seats. This reform and others like it were enough to whet appetites
without providing enough sustenance to keep them satisfied. In
the first half of the thirteenth century, the *popolo* began to take
over the reins of power in one commune after anotherâBologna
by 1231, Pistoiain 1237, Florence in 1250âand to acquire a growing voice in the governance of Piacenza, Lodi, Bergamo, Siena,
Parma, and Qenoa. âThe *popolo*âs breakthrough into politics was
the result of revolutionary organization,â declares Martines with
a decisiveness that is not easy to encounter among many historians
of the era.{42} In a very real sense, perhaps more sweeping than we
realize, he is correct.
In retrospect, what makes the *popolo*âs ways of organizing so
revolutionary was its highly localist and organic fashion of acting
politically, a form of organizing that is utterly antithetical to modern concepts of party politics. The *popolo* had turned themselves
into a neighborhood movement, not unlike the **contrada** in structure and the **consorterie** in their âconfederal way of interlinking
with each other. The noble families of two centuries earlier had
taught its more servile orders well in the arts of political organization and power, The tradition of organizing a movement on a
block-to-block, square-to-square basis had not died out in Italian
cities after the *podestarie* subdued the interfamilial squabbles
within the nobility. It was still very much alive, and the *popolo*
used it well. However varied the specific structures this organization produced, certain forms clearly emerged from this neighborhood base.
The rise of vocational gilds provided one very important pattern for linking men of the same occupation from different neighborhoods into a common organization. Gilds were established not
only for merchants, physicians, apothecaries, jurists, and notaries,
but also for smiths, cloth finishers, butchers, bakers, furriers, tanners, leather makers and the like, generally reflecting the *popolo*âs
social composition as a whole. These vocational groups, composed
almost exclusively of well-to-do tradesmen and master craftsmen
in their fields, were the earliest popular organizations of which we
have any record, and they tried not only to control the operations
of their crafts and its produce but also constituted themselves into
armed societies with the very distinct goal of controlling the commune. Before long, open clashes exploded between the *popolo*
and the *nobilta* at Brescia in 1192, Piacenza in 1198, Milan in
1201, and in year-by-year sequence, Cremona, Assisi, Lucca, and
onward to Pistoia in 1234.
Neighborhoods were now convulsed by strife between poorly
trained and the more highly skilled fighters of the noble **consorterie**, Rarely had the armed citizen moved so much to the forefront
of civic political life. By now, armed popular societies based on
neighborhood ties began to supplant the gilds in order to deal with
the endemic warfare that erupted in the cityâs streets. These societies were better trained than the vocational organizations. More
closely cemented by their ties as neighbors, they had a better
knowledge of the quarters in which they functioned and they
could muster their forces more rapidly and on shorter notice as
emergencies arose. If Bologna can be taken as an example of the
enhanced ways of dealing with the *nobilta*, it demonstrated the
need for the armed neighborhood societies to extend beyond the
gild framework into a more cohesive, area-oriented, well-synchronized, and highly cooperative form of military organization. By
the middle of the twelfth century, the city could boast of twentyfour armed neighborhood companies in comparison to Florenceâs
twenty and still smaller numbers elsewhere. Moreover, the Bolognese societies were consolidated across adjacent urban parishes
into what looked very much like a citywide militia. The *popolo*, to
be sure, had not created the idea of a neighborhood militia out of
thin air; such companies of men living in the same parts of the city
had been the backbone of the communal military system for years.
What the *popolo* did, however, was to change the militiaâs function from a mere civic guard, designed exclusively to defend the
commune from external enemies, into a politically insurrectionary
force designed to change the communeâs internal structure and
power relationships.
Florenceâs armed societies can be taken as a general example
of the structure that the *popolo* established in the popular communes of Italy after their victory over the *nobilta*, The twenty
neighborhood companies it had created earlier now became the
communeâs exclusive fighting force, absorbing the remains of the
old one where it could. In districts where the *popolo* was weak,
a larger number of militia units were assigned to guard its interests. The rest were equally distributed throughout the city. Each
company adopted its own banner and insigniaâa âdragon, a whip,
a serpent, a bull, a bounding horse, a Hon,â even a ladder, âwere
emblazoned on individual shields and helmets,â Martines notes.
âRigorous requirements required guildsmen to keep their arms
near at hand, above all in troubled times. The call to arms for the
twenty companies was the ringing of a special bell, posted near the
main public square. A standard-bearer, flanked by four lieutenants, was in command of each company. These men were elected
by a council of twenty-four members of the company and served
one year. The Captain of the People was the commander of the
twenty companies. Being an outsider, he was expected to stand
above the temptations of local partisanship. His oath of office
obliged him to call the companies to action whenever there was
a threat to the *popolo*.... The *popolo* had no trouble finding only
the most committed and reliable men for its armed companies.
The success of this was seen in moments of crisis, when the ardor
of the companies won many victories for the *popolo*,â a fact that
was not lost on Machiavelli some two centuries later when he
voiced his compelling argument for a citizen-militia as opposed to
the use of mercenaries in *The Prince*.{43}
Once it came to power, the *popolo* did not completely eliminate
the podestal constitution. A large Council of the People was formed
to counterbalance the power of the old communal legislature and a
powerful council of âeldersâ functioned as the communeâs executive. The Captain of the People was elevated to a status that, for all
practical purposes, matched that of the **podesta**, and he was fully
regaled with a court system that paralleled that of the podestal one.
The *popolo*, in effect, had structured a dual power into the older
constitution, matching the communal council with a popular one,
the **podesta** with the militia chieftain, and courts of both men as
counterweights to each other. Overarching this entire structure
was the popular militia itself, which could easily intervene in the
If this was a democracy, it was one of merchants, notaries,
professionals, and master craftsmen, not of journeymen, weavers, dyers, and laborers who formed the only âproletariatâ the
thirteenth-century world knew. By the same token, however, it
was not a democracy of blooded idlers and aristocratic bullies.
The popular democracy was composed of men who worked with
their hands at crafts or devoted long hours of the day to the
chores of administration, business, and legal affairs. Whether
they were wealthy entrepreneurs or men of modest means, they
saw themselves as self-made individuals, not the heirs of family
wealth and unearned status; they believed; with good reason,
that, they lived highly productive, sober,âand socially useful lives
and were far more capable than the nobles of bearing serious
responsibilities on, their shoulders. They were no oneâs clients
and no oneâs masters, except where they trained their own
successors in the skills of their crafts. Although the new manufacturers who operated with hired labor could hardly make this last
claim for themselves, they were far from constituting a majority
of the typical ltalian *popolo*. Italy in the thirteenth century was
not an industrial society with modern capitalists and workers. It
was a largely artisan and highly paternalistic world, and the men
who fathered its workshops as well as its families were not, disposed to grant the least modicum of: power to anyone who was a
subordinate. These men knew only too well that, without them,
the commune would quickly atrophy and disappear, but without
the nobles and, to a considerable extent, their own subordinates,
it could survive and ultimately flourish.
For limits of space, it is impossible to explore the vast cultural
impact the popular commune had on its age, be it the painting of
Giotto, the sensual realism of Boccaccio, the shift of literature from
Latin to the vernacular, the laicization. of education, the huge
increase in popular literacy, or a political tradition that trounced
any attempt at institutionalized despotism. For all his aristocratic
inclinations, Dante was a *popolani*, no less than the chronicler
Giovanni Villani whose history of Florence is one of the best to be
written of his era. The popular commune created new men who
breathed a fresher urban air than any of their medieval contemporaries: one relatively free of superstition, turgid scholasticism, and
social status; Above all, it produced a new kind of citizen who, with
his Weapons by his side and craft tools in his hands, felt boldly
empowered arid politically confident. Alert to any threat to his
liberties; he was prepared to fight for his rights with the same
energy with which he fashioned his produce. This alertness extended beyond a defensive stance against an aggressive nobility
into a mili tant interest in public affairs and a readiness to occupy
public responsibility. Not since Hellenic times did men of relatively modest means feel so close an identification between their
own interests and those of the city in which they lived. Deeply
individuated, indeed animated by a vivacious love of public debate and political discussion, such as Italians are to this very day,
this new citizen seemed all the more motivated to shape his cityâs
destiny as well as his own. The ancient *civitas* as an association of
active citizens had been reborn, and its spirit was to live in its
citizen body long after its institutions were to atrophy and pass
into history.
That the popular commune did not last as long as the Athenian
problems could not be resolved by replacing a small oligarchy
with a bigger one. The popular commune, was not a âlevelerâ of
social orders and economic classes. Quite to the contrary, it gave
a new impetus to trade, the accumulation of wealth, and increasing economic and political differentiation, setting the *popolo grosso* or âfat peopleâ against the *popolo magro* or âthin people.â
In time, the commune developed a siege mentality, fearful of the
gathering their forces outside them. To live with oneâs weapons by
oneâs side with an ear open to the requests of a buyer and another
to the peals of an alarm bell is not conducive to trade and is
exhausting to the spirit of a nascent bourgeois. After a few generationsâand the time span varied from city to cityâsignorial rule
began to overtake republican virtue. The process was as insidious
then as it is today: popular assemblies began to vote increased
emergency powers to their **podesta** and captain; the same men
were repeatedly confirmed in executive office, and their tenure
was extended from one year to five, from five to ten, and ultimately to lifetime office. Soon the leaderâs son supplanted his father after death and dynasties began to turn elective offices into
mere charades. However much they lingered on ceremoniously in
form, the republics began to die in fact, and the Italian cities,
unevenly and with trepidation, entered the age of the **signori**.
That the republican era never ceased to haunt the Italian mind is
attested to by sporadic attempts to revive it. The most notable, to
be sure, were Cola di Rienziâs assumption of power as the tribune
of a new Roman republic in the mid-fourteenth century and Fra
Savonarolaâs theocratic republic in Florence toward the end of the
fifteenth. Rienzi, however, had his eyes focused more on a unified
Italy than an emancipated Rome, a project that was woefully advanced for its time, and Savonarola turned Florence into a hysterical battleground for an apocalyptic battle between Christ and
Satan. If Rienzi was too early for the fourteenth century,
Savonarola was too late for the fifteenth. Both men challenged
entrenched attitudes that stood as insuperable obstacles to their
projects: Rienzi, a predominantly feudal sensibility; Savonarola, a
vivacious Renaissance sensibility that increasingly made his monkish mentality an anachronism. And both men went down in tragic
defeat: Rienzi as a hero of Italian nationalism, Savonarola as a
fanatic of Italian medievalism.
----
There can be no doubt that all of Europe watched the career of the
Italian city-state with keen interest and borrowed heavily from its
pioneering civicism. If Europe had any capital during the High
Middle Ages, it was papal Rome, also an Italian city-state. Pilgrims
and invaders, kings and beggars, knights and merchant-adventurers, all crisscrossed the peninsula for reasons of their own, and
Italian merchants were to be seen everywhere: at fairs in France,
city gates in Germany, on Londonâs docks, and in Flemish city
squares. Hence, if civic freedom needed a stimulus it could not
generate on its own, the Italian city-state was a ubiquitous presence that could provide one. In any case, and in almost every way,
the cities of western Europe went through all the phases that the
Italian cities had pioneered and added certain adornments of their
own.
Generally, European towns north of the Alps lagged behind the
Italians by a half-century or so, and at some point in time they
branched off from this shared development into institutional stagnation. Various kinds of republican structures can be found at one
time or another in almost every town of Europe, often preceded
by consulates and followed by oligarchies with a wide variety of
names. Elective systems of governance, which Roman traditions
inspired in Italy, were reinforced north of the Alps by German
tribal traditions. Not until well into the High Middle Ages did
hereditary kingships come into fashion; until then, monarchs were
elected to the throne and by no means did they occupy it with
complete regal confidence. Moreover, they were surrounded by
councils that spawned the parliamentary structures of later times,
essentially oligarchic in character but in some measure reflective
of the aristocratic, clerical, and commoner estates that made up
the sovereignâs realm. As in Italy, the word âpeopleâ was defined
in a highly restricted manner. âNote that there is a difference
between the people (**populus**) and **plebs** which is the same as that
between an animal and a man or between a genus and a species,â
declared a thirteenth-century canonist in the Aristotelian language of the day. âFor nobles and non-nobles collected together
constitute the **populus**, The **plebs** is where there are no senators
or men of consular dignity.â{44} The inferences we can draw from
these remarks are that the âpeopleâ include everyone of all orders
and degree; the **plebs** consist of that segment of the âpeopleâ who
are not equipped to govern. The governing councils of European
towns generally reflected this distinction: an urban patriciate
monopolized most of the civic offices. Rich merchants took over
Bruges in the mid-thirteenth century; Rouen in the late twelfth;
Freiburg, which established a lifetime consulate, in 1218; and
many large cities of Germany such as Cologne. The conciliar system and the early assemblies were reworked into oligarchies.
Needless to say, there were also exceptions. At Nimes, the constitution provided for the election of five consuls from the âwhole
people of the city or its larger part,â typically indirectly, such as
existed in the Italian city-states. Arles locked its carefully controlled general assemblies into an oligarchy by placing virtually all changes of law and imposition of taxes in the hands of its consuls
and their council.
âDemocratizationâ of the European cities occurred slowly and
generally followed on the heels of the popular communes in Italy,
often in exacting detail. Basel established a captain of the people
in 1280; Freiburg turned its oligarchy into an annually elected
board of twenty-four consuls following a âpopularâ revolt very
similar to Bolognaâs; Liege created what can best be called a gild-type city republic, headed by sixty governors of its craft gilds and
two burgomasters. The city went even further than most when,
from 1313 onward, it made the issuance of new laws contingent
upon the approval of a popular assembly composed of all the cityâs
citizens, irrespective of their status. Even broader extensions of
civic liberties were to mark the stormy popular movement of
Flanders when civic government was shaped by the despised
weavers and fullers of cloth-manufacturing towns such as Ghent
and Ypres where the âfatâ and âthinâ people were to clash in
brutal conflicts. This chronic struggle is too complex to narrate
here; it involved not only battles between well-to-do oligarchies
and virtual proletarians who manufactured wool products as mere
hired help but also the intervention of the Count of Flanders, Guy
de Dampierre, and the French monarch, Philip the Fair. Patriotism intermingled with class conflicts to a point where democratic
demands were repeatedly diluted by the hatred of the Flemish
people toward France. As a result, lowly artisans and their lordly
masters fought side-by-side when they were not fighting face-to-face. Ultimately, the âthinâ people, organized into âlesser gildsâ
triumphed over their patriciates, and established a civic structure
that gave adequate representation to the weavers, fullers, and
gildsmen of âlow degreeâ in a tripartate magistracy that excluded
all or most of the patricians.
What the European communes could not resist was the steady
rise of the nation-state, indeed one that the rich merchants favored to restrain their unruly local barons who interfered with the
free movement of trade and their unruly laboring classes who
posed a continual threat to civic oligarchies. Perhaps the earliest
harbinger of this new drift toward territorial centralism occurred
when the Flemish communes, led by Philip van Artavelde, the son
of the great champion of Flemish liberty, Jacques van Artavelde,
were thoroughly routed by Count Louis in the Battle of Roosebeeke in 1382. âHenceforth, Flanders was to give up the dream
of government by a league of independent towns and submit to
the ever more and more centralized rule of powerful territorial
lords, whose model was naturally the aggressive monarchy of
France,â concludes Ephraim Emerton in his wistful account of this
tragic history. âAt the death of Count Louis in 1383 the county
passed by inheritance to his son-in-law, Philip the Bold of Burgundy, the first in the fine of princes through whom the Low
Countries were drawn into the politics of France, the Empire, and
Spain. The cities, still great and powerful, enjoying very wide
privileges, were to be only incidents in the larger relations of the
country.â{45}
----
Emertonâs closing remarks on the struggle of Flemish towns for
civic freedom and autonomy might well seem like a touching
epitaph for the commune as the nation-state began to emerge. Not
only did it survive as little more than a haunting dream in Flanders, but also in Italy, where the triumph of the **signori** by the
fifteenth century was virtually completed. Savonarolaâs brief restoration of a Florentine republic in the closing years of that century reads more like a parody of the cityâs glorious republican: past
than an authentic revival. It would seem that Daniel Waleyâs verdict on the nature of Italian civic republicanism could be applied
to European communes as a whole. âThe existence of republican
forms of government in the Italian city-states was intensely precarious,â Waley writes in an assessment that can only be regarded
as an understatement. âThese institutions were so constantly
under pressure or even in full crisis that there is little reason to be
puzzled at their failure to survive in most of the cities.â{46} Internal
factionalism, which often reached insurrectionary proportions,
âsuffices on its own to explain why, in most cities, the regime of
a single individual was able to secure acceptance before the end
of the fourteenth century. Clearly the occasional survival of
republicanism as an exception needs more explaining than do the
triumphs of the **signori**. Republicanism in decline is seen as a
puzzling historical problem only if the republic is regarded as the
body politic in health, the âtyrannyâ (**signoria**) as a pathological
form.â{47}
Perhaps, as Waley seems to suggest, we should reverse the
judgement modern liberal historians have of what constitutes the
health arid pathology of a body politic. But it is fair to ask, as I have
throughout this book, whether any kind of politics, much less one
that can be âembodiedâ in an active citizenry, is possible under
a tyranny or, for that matter, a ârepresentative democracyâ (republic). Waley seems to surrender the need for an ethical judgement of the commune, of the *conjuratio*âs radical implications and
its sense of promise, if he asks us to surrender to the âfactsâ of the
historical record rather than cherish the possibilities civic freedom
holds for a humanity that has yet to fulfill its unfinished potentialities for a rational way of life. We can never let this commitment
to an ethical judgement give way to the evidence of a grossly
irrational reality merely because the record of the human enterprise speaks faultingly against it. Truth rarely lies in the center of
experienced facts. If it did so, we would still believe the earth is
flat and justice is merely the authority of the strong. These are the
irrefragable facts as they are experienced in everyday life. Historians, in turn, would merely be turgid chroniclers of anecdotes,
storytellers of things past whose accounts can never be free of
their own hidden biases and proclivities. Until very recent times,
philosophy for more than two millennia has warned us that âbrute
factsâ do not really exist and are never free of interpretation, even
as we deny humanity any sense of possibility, the hope of going
beyond the âfactsâ and achieving its most worthy ideals. âBrute
factsâ will become real only when we become brutish and deal
with the existing reality on its own terms, no different in principle
from the adaptive ways we impute to other living beings.
Actually, the history of civic freedom does not end with the
fourteenth century or the rise of the nation-state. The ideal of
popular assemblies as a form of self-governance, and the city as the
nuclear arena for politics and an active citizenry, seems to have
enjoyed a remarkable degree of persistence, especially if we bear
in mind that there were so many factorsâstatist, economic, logistical, and demographicâto work against. That it exists even today
in the form of the New England town meeting, however vestigial
it appears by comparison with its past, is testimony to the need
people have felt in fairly politicized regions to retain forms of
face-to-face decision making and direct democracy. In fact, the
town meeting is much too close to our discussion of the cityâs
future to be examined in any detail here. It may be regarded as
a legacy, but it is still a living legacy that should not be consigned
to the past. Suffice it to say, for the present, that from 1760 to the
closing years of the American Revolution, it spread out of New
England and reached as far south as Charleston. During this period, it fueled the revolution as surely as the more well-known
Committees of Correspondence and such popular societies as the
Sons of Liberty. Considerable effort was needed to eliminate the
town-meeting form in many communities of the new United
States and to nibble away at its powers in New England itself. We
shall see that as recently as the 1960s, Vermont townships and
their popular meetings essentially controlled the state government because the House of Representatives was elected by towns, not along geographic and demographic lines.
Nor can we deal with the challenging problems raised by the
Swiss Confederation, a piece of contemporary history that seems
to have been shunted away from âmainstreamâ accounts of civic
freedom. To assign a few paragraphs to a living illustration of
confederalism, participatory democracy, and active citizenship,
despite the philistine smugness of Swiss life and the conservatism
of Swiss politics, would be doing violence to the extraordinary
example of freedom that is also with us. It will require a section
of a later chapter on civic confederal forms to even remotely
approximate the insights Benjamin Barber brings to this issue in
his discussion of direct democracy in the Swiss cantons. What
Barber asks us to recognize is that democratic forms in themselves, however radical they may seem to be, âare inherently
neither conservative nor progressive; they can be employed to
bring about rapid and even radical change under conditions of
consensus and unity of governing and people. They can obstruct
reform and paralyze effective government altogether where the
people are no longer one with their governors or synonymous with
their government.... Democracy in Switzerland appears reactionary because the conditions that justify it have eroded; democracy in the villages of GraubĂŒnden is failing because the village
communities are themselves moribund. Neither the institutions
themselves nor a putative peasant mentality is to blame.â{48} Democracy, in sum, has its own prerequisites, and it will be no small
part of the coming chapters to examine them in the light of modern societal problemsâAmerican, European, GraubĂŒnden, no less
than those that exist for a New England town-meeting democracy.
The most dazzling, almost meteoric example of civic liberty and
direct democracy in modern times is the rise and brief ascendancy
of the sectional assemblies in the Great French Revolution, a
movement that addresses the typical question of whether or not
a face-to-face democracy is possible in a large city, indeed by the
standards of two centuries ago a world city. It should be kept in
mind that eighteenth-century Paris, where the sectional assemblies flourished, was the capital of continental Europeâs most absolute monarchies, a city that, more so than any other aside from
London, seemed to have been a creature of the nation-state.
Under the Bourbons, Paris had very little self-government of its
own. Ruled more or less directly by the monarchy, it groaned
under the imposition of an inept regal administration and a corrupt nobility that reduced its lower orders to sheer destitution. Yet
within a span of only four years, Paris acquired not only complete
control over its own civic afFairs but created a system of control
that was built around face-to-face neighborhood assemblies, coordinated by a commune that, at its revolutionary highpoint, called
for the complete restructuring of France into a confederation of
free communes. This demand was to survive for nearly a century
after the revolution, when it became the insurrectionary program
of the more famous Paris Commune of 1791.
Ironically, the sectional assemblies have their origin in the sixty
district assemblies Louis XVI convened in Paris to elect the cityâs
middle-class deputies to the Estates General. These assemblies
were directed to select the 147 electors who, in turn, were to
choose Parisâs twenty deputies to the Third Estate. The French
Revolution, although spurred into action by the power plays between the Third Estate and the monarchy, really began from
below and, most typically, as a result of Parisian militancy. Despite
the highly discriminatory franchise that the Xing imposed on his
own capitalânearly a quarter of the cityâs population was disenfranchised in contrast to a sixth in the rest of Franceâthe district
assemblies were highly spirited and acted in flat defiance of the
throne. They rejected the presiding officers with whom they were
saddled by the municipality and chose presiding officers of their
own; the 147 electors to whom they were entitled were unabashedly raised to four hundred; and what is perhaps most damning, they refused to go home as the monarchy directed them to do.
They defiantly established themselves as permanent fixtures of
Parisâs municipal government. The four hundred electors, in turn,
began to meet almost daily at the museum and shortly afterward
at the Town Hall, where they simply edged out the royal appointees to the municipal government. The electors, in effect, became
a provisional Paris, âCommuneââ until an authentic Commune was
constitutionally elected. By September 1790, the Paris Commune
numbered three hundred and coexisted uneasily with the sixty
district assemblies from which it drew its representatives.
The tension between the Commune and its district assemblies
and within the assemblies themselves mounted as the revolutionary fever of theâ city rose. The distinction between propertied
âactive citizensâ who had franchise rights and propertyless âpassiveâ ones who were expected tp be little more than political
bystanders ultimately made any exclusion of the disenfranchised
people, the *sans culottes*, increasingly awkward. By this time, the
âdistrictsâ had been renamed âsectionsâ and their number reduced from sixty to forty-eight by the National Assembly in order
to diminish their power. Despite such attempts to suppress the
âdistrictsâ and later the âsectionsâ as deliberative bodies, the assemblies largely ignored the National Assemblyâs decrees. In May
1790, the Assembly tried to limit the concerns of the sectional
assemblies to purely municipal issues, a ploy typipal to this day of
conservative elements in New England town meetings, but the
restriction ultimately proved to be ineffectual. With the outbreak
of war, the revolution moved markedly leftward. In July 1792, the
Theatre-Français sectipn decreed the elimination of all distinctions between âactiveâ anil âpassiveâ citizens, a decree that was
quickly adopted by all the forty-eight sections of Paris. The sectional assemblies were now thrown open to all the underprivileged orders of Paris: the laboring classes, relatively unskilled
artisans, carpenters, construction workers, nascent proletarians of
the textile and luxury goods workshops, and the like. A year later,
on Dantonâs request, the newly elected revolutionary Convention
that replaced the National Assembly dbcreed that poor citizens
could receive a stipend of forty sous for, attending sectional assemblies, which were reduced to two a week, presumably so that the
attempt by the liberal Girondins to close all sectional assemblies
by nine in the evening so that working *sans culottes* would be
unable to attend the assemblies after they returned home contributed greatly to the popular insurrection that removed them
from the Convention and brought the Jacobins to power.
Although the details of how these local assemblies functioned
leaves much to be desired, partly because the minutes of the
sections were lost in the flames of the Paris Commune of 1871,
partly, too, because their history has yet to be written by historians
sympathetic to their decentralistic outlook, we know enough to
describe them in broad terms. Sectional assemblies met at least
twice weekly in the summer and autumn of 1793, the high tide of
the **sans culotte** movement and often went into âpermanent sessionâ during hectic periods of the revolution. Attendance fluctuated widely from a hundred or less when the agenda was routine
to overflowing halls (usually in state-commandeered churches and
chapels) when serious issues confronted the revolutionary people.
Structurally, each section had a president with a committee to
assist him, a recording secretary, tellers for counting votes, and
ushers to maintain order. Although it is not very clear how fixed
these positions were, the Presidentâs committee was renewed
monthly by an assembly vote, and very few presidents seem to
have held office for more than a year. Each section, it must be
stressed, made its own rules and probably varied in form and the
frequency of its meetings.
A multitude of revolutionary commissars and committees surfaced from these assemblies and dealt with a large number of
important economic, political, and military problems. We have
only to enumerate the names of the sectional committees to gain
some idea of the functions this neighborhood democracy undertook. Aside from its *assemblee generale* of the local citizen body,
each sectionâs âmost important function, that of police, was entrusted to a **commissaire de police**, aided by sixteen **commissaires de section**. To meet the needs of local administration the sections
formed almost as many committees as a modern American town
or city. There were **comites civile** and **comites revolutionaires**
(Vigilance Committees); there were **comites de bienfaisance** (Relief Committees), *comites militaires*, *comites dâagriculture*, and
had its own revolutionary court system and justices of the peace
as well as special committees to organize work for the unemployed (*ateliers de charite*), or tenth-day festivities (*fetes decadaires*), or open-air suppers for the poor (*banquets populaires*).[8]
[8] France, it is worth noting, had extended its newly adopted decadenal metric
system from weights, measures, lengths, and areas directly into the calendar with
the result that a week was measured in ten days. This did not displease the French
bourgeoisie, which was only too glad to have a longer work week than existed
under the older religious calendar.
The forty-eight sectional assemblies, in turn, were coordinated
by the Paris Commune to which each section elected three deputies at an *assemblee primaire*. Also at this special assembly, usually
quite heavily attended, the sections elected the *Bureau* of the
Commune: the cityâs mayor, its *procureur*, and his two deputies,
who essentially constituted a communal executive committee to
which sixteen *administrateurs* were chosen from the Communeâs
normal complement of 144 sectional representatives. To buffer
this rather manipulative executive from popular pressure, an additional thirty-two members were added to the *Bureau* to form a
<em>Corps Municipal.</em> When this majestic group of forty-eight sectional notables convened with the remaining ninety-two deputies
that formed the Commune, it bore the solemn title of the *Conseil General de la Commune* or, as it came to be known in the historical literature, the Communeâs General Council.
The more radical sections of Paris were not unmindful that
these concentric rings of authority surrounding the communeâs
Bureau were meant to camouflage an inner circle of executives
who were as disquieted by the irascibility of the sections as the
Convention was of the Commune, a body that it really saw as a
dangerous challenge to the nation-state. Although the Commune
eventually became more radical under sectional pressure as time
went by, the sections were always more radical than the Commune and began to act very much on their own. When necessary,
as was frequently the case, **sans culotte** sections did not hesitate
to bypass the Commune completely and form their own interlocking committees and networks. Delegations from one section often
visited the assemblies of another, where they were usually greeted
with fervent embraces, hortatory speeches of welcome, and characteristic âkisses of fraternity,â which often culminated with banquets topped by endless toasts to liberty and the brotherhood of
man. As F. Furet *et al*. tell us: âFrom the angle of political solidarity, the participants in activities of the sections saw themselves as
forming a whole, a âfamilyâ of âbrothers and friends,â where the use
of the familiar form *tu* broke down all the barriers of social and
cultural origin. Outside the section this fraternal solidarity was
further expressed by âfraternization,â a sort of pact for mutual aid
between the popular sections to resist the pressure of the aristocrats and the moderates, and then to eliminate them from the
committees which they controlled. Thus on May 14, 1793, the
Social Contract section, under the direction of its president, went
in a body to the Lombard section to chase out the âaristocracy.â In
this way the sections were regenerated in the bourgeois quarters
dominated by the moderates before the fall of the Girondins, and
by the ânew moderatesâ after the month of September 1793.â{49}
It is difficult to fully convey the enormous powers the sections
accrued by 1793 before they were subverted by the Convention.
The titles of their various *comites* and *commissions* do notâ tell us
how intensely active the sections had become in the administration of their neighborhoods and finally in running the entire city
of Paris. They were sources of information on local counterrevolutionaries and grain speculators, both of whom existed by the nestful in the city. They became the dispensers of a rough-and-ready
popular justice, the guardians of the âmaximumâ that regulated
the price of staples, the dispensers of food for the poor and sustenance for the widowed and orphaned, the caretakers of refugees
from the provinces and the homeless who all but lived on the
streets. They were the authentic organizers of the great *journées*,
the insurrectionary âdaysâ that pushed the revolution in an increasingly egalitarian direction much to the dismay of the Jacobins, whom they mistakenly worshipped with almost unthinking
reverence before they were betrayed by the Robespierres, Dantons, and Saint-Justs. They forged the âholy pikeâ that armed the
revolutionary populace and made it possible for it to intervene
directly in the Conventionâs proceedings and alter the course of
its decrees and laws. Going even further, the sections began to
intervene significantly in the economy of the city. Their *comites dâagriculture* scoured the countryside to feed the city, their committees to establish *ateliers de charite* freely appropriated workshops abandoned by wealthy emigres and used them to provide
jobs for the unemployed who made uniforms, weapons, and gunpowder fpr the embattled revolutionary armies at the front. Not
unlike the Athenian festivals of an earlier age that did so much to
cement the *polis* together, the sections not only called periodic
fetes decadaires and neighborhood *banquets populaires* but
helped to stage the fervent citywide celebrations that occurred
throughout the revolution, fostering a sense of civic fraternity that
Paris was to rarely see again after 1793, when the âyear of the *sans culottes*â passed into history. And it was these *canaille*, or ârabbleâ as they were also called, who were to be pushed from tho
stage of history and shot down by the thousands in the reaction
that followed the tenth of Thermidor (July 28,1794), when Robespierre and his followers were guillotined.
Finally, âFrom the principle of popular sovereignty,â observe
Furet and his colleagues, âthe *sans culottes* went as far as the
notion of direct government. With the same verve which made
them rise against the Girondins, in the summer of 1793 certain
sections demanded to keep their own civil records, to levy their
own taxes, and to render justice without appeal. No limitations
should be imposed upon the assembly of citizens, which decided
everything. A decision by the Convention (September 9, 1793)
having limited section meetings to two days a week, the **sans culottes** got around the decree by holding a daily meeting of the
âSociety of the section.â This assembly claimed to supervise the
civil servants and magistrates, who in their eyes were merely their
subordinates. Members of the *comites civiles*, revolutionary commissions, police commissioners, or commissioners for supplies
were subjected to constant surveillance by the sections, at least as
long as the latter maintained their independence from the revolutionary government. Censure, âpurifyingâ votes, and revocability
of elected persons were the principal means by which this popular
sovereignty was exercised, according to the Rousseauean principle of a sovereign and indivisible popular opinion.â{50}
The well-to-do classes of France had everything to fear from
these sectional assemblies and a radical Commune of Paris. Although it was highly unlikely that the largely bourgeois districts
of 1789 ever envisioned a France governed by a completely popular direct democracy, the rise and growing influence of the sectional assemblies clearly evoked images of a confederal France
structured around sections similar to the Parisian in all the cities
and towns of the countryâa nationwide commune of communes.
The extent to which this vision of an entire European country
began to take hold of the popular imagination as early as November, 1792, is suggested by a statement that the **Section de la Cité**
circulated for the approval of other sectional assemblies. âThe
citizens of Paris declare ... that they recognize no sovereignty
except a majority of the communes of the republic ..the statement provocatively declares, âthat they only recognize deputies
In the Convention as composers of a draft constitution and provisional administration of the republic.â By the spring of 1793, such
views ceased to be isolated. On April 29 of the following year, the
the concentric groups within that body, took practical steps toward implementing the idea of a federation of communes by establishing a corresponding committee to communicate with the
44,000 municipalities of France. In a printed circular to the
municipalities, the committeeâs secretary boldly declared: âThat
is the only kind of federalism the people of Paris want.... All the
communes in France should be sisters.â{51}
For all his biases and preconceptions, Daniel Guerin is on solid
ground when he resolutely concludes, âThe bourgeois philosophers who had pronounced direct democracy unworkable in large
countries [no less Rousseau than other social theorists of his day],
on the grounds that it would be materially impossible to bring all
the citizens together in one meeting, were thus proved wrong.
The Commune had spontaneously discovered a new form of representation more direct and more flexible than the parliamentary
system and which while not perfect, for all forms of representation
have their faults, reduced the disadvantages to a minimum.â Indeed, it is doubtful if the Commune and the sectional assemblies
could be regarded as a system of ârepresentation.â The *sans culottes* had gone much further than any assembly form of which we
know in establishing a direct democracy, this in the very heart of
a nation-state that the Jacobins had centralized to a degree that
would have been the envy of Franceâs most absolutist monarchs.
It remains one of historyâs great ironies that the city, which reworked stagnant archaic systems of corporate life based on status
and kinship into the innovative, free realm of politics and citizenship, was to produce the very factors that led to its own undoing.
European cities, I have pointed out, were different from their
ancient counterparts because of their inherent autonomy as civic
entities. The increasing separation of the medieval town from the
cityâs traditional agrarian matrix produced not only a new kind of
city with an identity of its own; it also produced a new type of
economy, culture, and political structure that profoundly altered
the countryside and slowly remade it into the cityâs image. Today,
we have no difficulty in recognizing this profound changeâthe
âurbanizationâ of the landâas a logical step in a mythic ascent of
societal life from what Marx lamely called ârural idiocyâ to what
we like to call âcivilization.â Modern agribusiness is the patent
âconquestâ of agriculture by industry, a city-born enterprise and
technics; so, too, is mass culture, which has urbanized as well as
homogenized agrarian lifeways. What we do not fully sense is the
extent to which early city dwellers would have regarded such a
sweeping urbanization of the countryside as peculiar, nor could
they have anticipated the extent to which it would have undermined civic life and citizenship. We have simply lost contact with
the problem of urbanization as antithetical to citificationâand to
the extent that we are oblivious to the very existence of the issue
itself, we have become its mute and unknowing victims.
How, then, did this remarkable change from civic autonomy to
civic supremacy come about? And in what sense, institutionally
and economically, did it begin to challenge the city s integrity,
ultimately to raise the very real problem of its subversion as a
realm of genuine politics and meaningful citizenship? Gur answers to these questions, so crucial to an understanding of modern
urbanization arid the threat it poses to the city, oblige us to examine the new kind of economy and values that became preponderant in the communes of the late Middle Ages and the role they
played in replacing civic life with the nation-state or, more precisely, politics with statecraft.
We must first look at the new economic relationships that began
to link European cities and regions togetherâand I say âfirstâ not
because they are the sole, the âdefinitive,â cause that produced
this new economic and political dispensation. Whether the European continent ânecessarilyâ would have been changed from a
loose association of towns, cities, baronies, duchies, and the allpresiding, if ineffectual, Holy Roman Empire into a clearly articulated group of nation-states is a problem in divination, not in
social analysis. How Europe could have developedâwhether toward confederal communities or toward highly centralized nation-statesâis an open question. One can single out many reasonable alternatives European towns and cities might have followed
that were, no less possible than the one that became prevalent in
fairly recent times. No single course of development was âinevitableâ or âpredeterminedâ by the economic, social, and political
forces at work. Indeed, that Italy did not become a nation-state
until the nineteenth century must remain an utter mystery if a
constellation of cultural, social, and political factors, particularly
the role of its cities, is not invoked against strictly economic explanations. Seemingly, no area of Europe was more âmodern,â âcapitalistic,â or entangled in a market economy some 500 years ago
than the Italian peninsula, and yet Italy was to lag behind western
Europeâs trend toward nation-state building for centuries. Nor can
we understand why it was only in England that a market economy
virtually absorbed all other economic forms of life such that the
British Isles became the âmodelâ for a capitalistic society in the
nineteenth century while Spain, which entered so early on in the
development of nation-states, lagged behind Europe as a whole
and remained a predominantly agrarian society until well into the
1930s.
This much is clear: from the thirteenth or fourteenth centuries
onward, Europeâand, most notably, Italyâwas the scene for an
entirely new economic and social dispensation. The Italian city-states began to break with-traditional economic relationships that
had been ingrained in ancient and early medieval civic life ways.
From Italian ports and inland commercial citiesâand in northern
Europe from Flemish industrial centersâforeign trade began to
bring a growing number of parochial communes into a new kind
of commercial network, one that resembled what we would now
regard as capitalistic. Trade, accumulation, and the reinvestment
of profits into expanding and competitive business enterprises
now became ends in themselves, not simply means to achieve
personal wealth, land holdings, and aristocratic status. Not that
this development was totally universal, as we shall see very
shortly. But it occurred on a sufficiently wide scale to make it
unique and to subvert the traditional agrarian lifeways that
marked European society, merchant as well as noble, in past historical eras.
Yet new as this development was, I do not wish to overstate it.
Our own society, a society that celebrates the ascendancy of âfree
tradeâ and a competitive capitalist economy, is ideologically imperialistic: it tends to cast the past too much in its own image. All
the roads of European history do not lead to the triumph of the
twentieth-century market economy. The fact is that feudal values,
rooted in an elaborate system of rank and a strong orientation
toward the ownership of land, were no less a part of received
wisdom of the new, rising urban âbourgeoisieâ than of the old
agrarian nobility. Trade did not alter this received wisdom of
feudal society for centuries to come. Indeed, like the merchants
of antiquity, whose goal consisted of amassing enough wealth from
the âsordidâ operations of commerce in order to retire to a
manorial life in the countryside, many Italian and Flemish merchants had very similar ambitions. Prestige gained by titles
through intermarriage and by the ownership of landed property
was still a desideratum among these early âbourgeoisââand such
goals were to remain widespread in Europe well into the eighteenth century. On this score, the merchants of antiquity and their
descendants in the Middle Ages were very much alike in outlook,
particularly the most wealthy ones. In their psychology and sense
of cultural self-definition, the city rich were similar to all the upper
rural strata of the time. And we shall also see that these ambitions
and this mentality exercised less of a hold among the more middling sort of city dwellers, such as artisans, ordinary merchants,
and aspiring members of the plebeian orders. Differences in attitudes and wealth were to profoundly divide the medieval towns
and cities internally, greatly complicating their relationships with the emerging monarchies.
For the present, it is important to emphasize that the wealthy
merchants of the late Middle Ages differed from their ancient
counterparts in the **way** in which they were committed to commercial operations. Although their outlook closely resembled a
feudal one, their practice was very akin to a modern one. The
tension between the old and new, between precept and practice,
introduced ways of functioning that deeply altered European life.
Ancient trade, generally speaking, was surprisingly simple in comparison to later medieval business transactions despite its Mediterranean-wide scope. Ordinarily it was local and more like barter
than modern forms of exchange; the ancient economy was not as
highly monetized as it is today. Money was conspicuous more by
its absence than by its presence, and the extent to which ancient
trade was a regulated affair would have chilled modern acolytes
of **laissez-faire** doctrines.
Like the cities, which were usually religious and administrative
centers, often as parasitic in their need for tribute from the surrounding countryside as in the exactations they placed on distant
subject peoples, Mediterranean commerce found itself physically
and culturally hemmed in by a distinctly agrarian world and a
largely subsistence economy. Beyond the ancient cities that clustered along the shores of the Mediterranean or were planted
strategically at intersections of inland waterways, the early trader
faced a semifeudal world of crude manors and impoverished peasant villages, a world that dissolved into a forested, semitribal communal world. Both of these worlds, the manorial and the tribal, in
antiquity constituted a very precarious, indeed hazardous, terrain
for the merchant, for his caravans on the land and his ships in
remote waterways.
The ancient merchant responded to these barriers accordingly.
Trade was distinguished by its highly personalized and somewhat
tentative character. The merchant and his sea captain or caravan
leader were united by a specific enterprise rather than a highly
organized business, although there were always many notable exceptions to this rule. Ships often went to sea and caravans with
pack animals went inland to make a âkillingâ just as a wayfaring
stock-market speculator today seeks his âlucky break.â In this
sense, merchants were literally âmerchant-adventurers,â and
their âcompaniesâ had quasimilitary characteristics. They commonly went abroad as armed expeditions. Loans were often no less
personal than the expeditionary techniques that brought a fleet of
ships or a caravan of pack animals together. Although credit was
fairly well developed by Roman times when the empire was already quite secure, in foreign trade to fairly remote parts, at least,
credit was often seen more as a gamble than a safe investment.
Such profits were high, and went into hoards or were invested in
land rather than the expansion of on-going businesses. I speak here
of foreign trade, not local trade; of the ancient worldâs âmerchant-adventurers,â not its home-based business enterprises, artisans,
and commercial farmers.
----
What the Italian merchants introduced in the Middle Ages was as
close to a ârevolutionâ as anything that goes by that name. A broad
network of business houses, credit institutions, trading depots,
warehouses, and affiliates began to interlink Italian city-states with
numerous medieval European towns, and the movement of goods
was gradually secured by treaties, tribute, and hired mercenaries
from the predations of robber barons and bandits. The Venetian
navy virtually swept the cityâs Mediterranean trade routes of pirates, attaining a sea supremacy that rivalled the naval power of
the more formidable empires around the basin. Business became
systematic, safe, a predictable enterprise. Money was invested not
only in the expansion and acquisition of landed property; it was
also invested in larger commercial operations whose profits not
only attracted ordinary people but also the local, nobility. The lure
of this fairly safe source of wealth, still disdained culturally but
crassly attractive to an increasingly practical and secularized
world, was enormous. It opened new doors everywhere in late
medieval society. Indeed, the social mobility of the fourteenth and
fifteenth centuries sharply contrasts with the social stagnation of
the classical world. Well-to-do commoners were closely interlinked with nobles by marriage as well as by trade. Aristocrats
offered titles and pedigree in exchange for the wealth and material security offered by merchants. Alliances were forged not only
with families of the same social order but between families of
different social orders. This melding of âclasses,â largely feudal
and âbourgeois,â has only recently received the attention it deserves and was to have a profound effect on the so-called âbourgeois revolutionsâ that marked the eighteenth century.
Finally, where elite orders were not interlinked by marriage,
merchants and even professionals acquired aristocratic status by
buying it outright, especially from the fifteenth century onward.
A considerable portion of the revenue acquired by the French
Bourbon kings, for example, came from the sale of titles, a sale that
united the higher orders of society by a shared sense of titular
nobilityâeven as it divided them by a sense of shared disdain
between the purchased ânobility of the robe" and the hereditary
ânobility of the sword.â In time, alliances and differences were to
become as tentative and precarious as distinctions formed by
wealth, when the rich of one day could easily suffer the pangs of
penury after the misfortunes of another day.
What did last and expand, however, were the trade networks
established between communities, particularly the larger towns of
medieval Europe. But the enormous growth, continuity, and increased stability of this foreign tradeâthe nearest thing to a capitalistic enterprise the continent developedâshould not cause us
to overlook the rich elaboration of the local market that occurred
within the medieval communes and their immediate environs.
The decline of the Roman Empire and the eclipse of the administrative cities that held it together brought the European continent
face-to-face with itself and threw it back on its own mainsprings.
No longer could the continent be sustainedâand civilized, much
less managed and exploited, by the Mediterranean basin with its
rich granaries and sources of tribbte. Beyond the highly cultivated
Roman-controlled territories of Europe lay great forests and bogs,
a huge continent within the continent itself that was fairly pristine
and open to new forms of social development. Communes began
to appear in this virginal terrain that were now structured not only
around religious and governmental institutions but, significantly,
around the markets qf craftsmen and artisans. These artisan towns,
to be sure, were crude and unpolished; they were more villagelike
than urban. The work and the markets that emerged from this
highly decentralized, localistic society were still mainly organized
around religious and feudal values. Often collecting around
churches and cathedralsâindeed, commonly under the sovereignty of a bishopâthey nevertheless became productive towns
with small markets arid family-operated workshops, living off the
agricultural produce in their environs and providing rural folk
with the more skillfully crafted commodities they could not make
in the countryside.
Here we encounter something remarkably new: communes
marked by a rich social fife, and with it a popular politics rooted
in gilds, systems of mutual aid, a civic riiilitia, and a strong sense
of community loyalty. The gild, the most important institutional
center of a new kind of artisan society, should not be confused with
the ancient collegia that it resembled structurally or with such
strictly economic associations as modern trade unions, which it
seems to resemble functionally. The Roman Empire exhibited a
very low tolerance for nonstatist bodies that could challenge the
authority of the monarchy and its bureaucracy. Hence ancient
collegial associations of craftspeople were rarely permitted to extend their activities beyond those of burial societies and festive
fraternities. They were allowed to have no economically regulative or protective functions. Essentially, they were cultural and
quasireligious institutions. Modern labor unions, in turn, are primarily economic organizations andâ assume few cultural, much less religious; undertakings.
The medieval gild, by contrast, assumed the responsibilities of
the ancient collegium, the modern labor union, and a great deal
more. Possibly religious in origin, it became highly secular in many
of its activities, fostering material as well as moral commitments.
It was a sworn, covenanted brotherhood that punished its members for lowering the quality of goods or seeking higher than
prescribed prices. It regulated personal, moral, and religious behavior as well as the output of goods. Not only did it care for
widows and orphans, the ill and infirm of its own members, but it
gave alms to the poor, performed charitable works of all kinds,
celebrated feast days, punished its members for usury, blasphemy,
gambling, and other presumably âimmoralâ infractions of good
behavior.
What made medieval gilds particularly significant in ways that
mark a sharp departure from towns of the past is that they attained
a degree of legislative and governing authority that made them
the principal municipal institution of many communes. However
parochial they seem to us today, European towns by the thousands
achieved a degree of autonomy that few municipal entities had
acquired in times past or were to acquire later. This autonomy was
pieced together corporately from a localized world of small artisans, craftsmen, and merchantsâa feudal world, in fact, not a
capitalistic one, however much it was centered around the marketplaceâbefore European communes were to be networked together by foreign trade. The communeâs growth and elaboration
took place organically, not artificially, within a highly decentralized agrarian society. In contrast to the Roman-controlled town,
the European town was a unique phenomenon insofar as local
autonomy became the rule rather than the exception. Control
from below thrived at the expense of an institutionally weak feudal society that was beleaguered by overlapping and conflicting
jurisdictions between landed nobles, urban bishoprics, papal legates, and insecure monarchs. The unending series of conflicts
that these jurisdictions generated was exacerbated by an undeveloped system of communications and by a crude armamentorium, one that made civic militias a powerful military force in
social life.
Foreign tradeâmore precisely the capitalistic carrying trade
that emanated from the Italian city-states and the Flemish communesâdefinitely worked against this communal autonomy as
surely as it played a role in interlocking Europeâs towns and cities.
And in so doing, it posed a historic problem: would the commercial
network created by intercity trade yield the formation of nation-states, centralized by monarchical and later republican systems of
power, or would it give rise to confederal institutions, united in a
shared continental system based on local community control?
That the nation-state was to gain ascendancy over confederal systems of self-governance does not mean that its victory was predetermined by Europeâs historyânor does it mean that its victory
cannot be undone. How that nation-stateâs ascendancy was
achieved is a story worth telling because it also brings to fight an
achievement that was often very tenuous, owing to the resistance
of the towns to centralism, a struggle that has not been definitively
foreclosed by urban issues that are emerging today.
For the present, we shall confine our account of the nation-state
to the way it was achieved, with the clear reservation that other
alternatives continually existed, indeed dramatic alternatives that
we will explore later. Initially, the intercity carrying trade that
began to unite Europe economically from the twelfth century
onward not only tore into a complex web of mutual personal and
communal dependencies in which trade as well as behavior was
carefully regulated; it also became the infrastructure for a new
body of societal institutionsâinitially regional rather than local,
later overwhelmingly nationalâthat cut across the grain of a time-hallowed and intensely communal and decentralized mode of social fife. It eventually introduced nationalism, a distinctly European phenomenon that was to spread beyond the continent itself
and acquire global dimensions.
The ancients, like the early Europeans, had very little experience with the notion of nationhood. Largely tribalistic or locafistic
in outlook, they tended to look inward toward their traditional
fifeways, to elaborate them rather than innovate new institutions
and values. Even the Greeks and Romans, who were comparatively âforward lookingâ in their attitudes, were heavily guided by
tradition. Cultural as well as economic âlimits to growthâ were
deeply molecular: people owed their strongest allegiances to their
kin group; next, to their community or perhaps region; rarely to
a ânation.â The idea of a ânationâ was alien to the ancient mind,
a tribalistic form of mind that opposed the locality to the ecumene.
Although pan-Hellenism was very much in the air among the
Greek *polei* shortly before Alexander brought the western world
and the Near Eastern together institutionally, it quickly drifted
into a cosmopolitan Hellenistic ecumene that adopted Greek for
its *lingua franca* and Greek culture for its spiritual adornment.
Hence a Greek ânationâ never developed among the Greek *polei*.
Israel seems to have acquired a strong sense of nationhood after
the Maccabean Revolt, but it was smothered by foreign invaders.
Religion ultimately placed a stronger claim on the Jews than a
sense of territorial nationhood, hence a budding form of nationalism was soon supplanted by a powerful belief in a spiritual community whose strength still defies the economistic explanations advanced by crude variants of Marxâs âhistorical materialism.â The
great empires of the ancient world were nOt ânationsâ in any sense
of the term. Indeed, it is difficult to associate them with the modern, class-based nation-state. In the Near East, these empires assumed a highly patronymic form: a âproperty,â as it were, of a
deified, patriarchal monarch for whom the vast lands under his
control were regarded as part of his *oikos* or household. Lands
annexed to the monarchâs original inheritance became the tributaries of a centralized household rather than the territory of an
institutionalized body politic. The Roman Empire, particularly in
its imperial rather than republican form, inherited this Near Eastern tradition-bound state form, however much it was secularized
and regulated by laws. Indeed it should be kept in mind always
that the Roman state was managed primarily by patricians, a
group of âfathers,â by definition, rather than by citizens. The
emperors, in turn, were the âfathersâ of their people, not simply their sovereigns,
European nations, by contrast, were pieced together by sterner
stuff. However muph monarchical nation building, so redolent of
ancient statecraft, went hand in hand with the marketâs expansion,
the infrastructure created by commerce laid a stronger foundation for nationalism than anything we encounter in the ancient
i world. This new, continentwide commercial nexus, formed out of
the interlinking of towns, produced material dependencies for
goods that cut across the moral relationships fostered by traditional society. Even before the monarchs of Spain, France, and
England asserted their authority over their respective nations,
they shrewdly exploited the divided loyalties and value systems
created by a growing commercial dependence on far-flung markets on the one hand and a powerful psychological dependence
produced by a richly elaborated localist community on the other.
Between the material wealth offered by the former and the
spiritual security offered by the latter, many towns were to divide
internally as sharply as they divided against the countryside.
Hence the European commune was pulled in two opposing directions: between the desirability of the nation-state and an ideal of
communal confederation. France ;was to provide an existential
example of the first, the Swiss Confederation, in its early days, of
the second.
Such alternatives did not really exist in the ancient world apart
from Greece. The administrative cities of antiquity easily dissolved in the West into virtual villages with the decline of the
empire, villages that formed the real community base of that society. Indeed, once sources, of tribute disappeared, the resources for
maintaining the Roman imperial state disappeared as well and the
West devolved into decentralized feudal society. Europe fell back
on its own resources and its own authentic forms of social and
economic organization.
The long history of Europeâs medieval development, a development that brings us to the opening of the modern era, totally
changed the setting for urban evolution. European-wide trade,
centered entirely around a new kind of self-sustaining municipality, opened sharply contrasting opportunities for development.
The wealthy elites of the towns were riddled by the divided loyalties and interests to which I have already alluded. Among the rich
merchants and their noble urban allies, a growing trend surfaced
for unfettered trade, free of gild, restrictions and traditional moral
constraints. On the other hand, the great majority of artisans,
journeymen, small retailers, and professionals were to demand the
perpetuation of traditional controls, their time-honored source of
security and stability. What complicates this fairly conventional
account of the âclass struggleâ within the medieval city is the very
disconcerting fact that the medieval patricians and plebeians
often united as readily as they fought with each other, notably
against assaults from outside the city itself. Although by no means
consistently, both âclassesâ commonly joined together to support
their municipal privileges against landed nobles and, more strikingly, even against monarchs who were bent on achieving a highly
centralized state. While the ordinary plebeian strata tended to be
more consistent in their commitment to their civic rights, the
more conflicted patrician stratumâfeudal in outlook but decidedly bourgeois in its commercial practicesâoscillated in its loyalties between the more popular elements in the city and the elite
elements, noble and kingly, to which it felt a groveling loyalty that
marks all parvenu elements in society. As we shall see, such alliances within the commune tended to be tentative and inconclusive, at times giving rise to serious urban revolts against the newly
emerging absolute monarchs, at other times dividing the towns so
seriously that they easily fell prey to monarchs who were to fashion the modern nation-state.
The reader who looks for an elegant and compact development
toward a modern urban society will not find one here. Between
the fourteenth and sixteenth centuries, when nation-states began
to form, the continentâs towns and cities found themselves deeply
entangled in a skein of shifting alliances and conflicts. Modern
notions of âfree trade,â largely confined to merchants engaged in
the carrying trade of the Mediterranean basin and the continent,
were nevertheless permeated by feudal values rooted in land ownership and status to an extent that would have seemed curious to
the modern mind. âCapital,â in effect, was at war with itself and
had very little identity of its own. Newly emerging capitalists of
the high and late Middle Ages were often pulled in sublimely
contrary directions by a fading past and a barely emerging future.
For their part, the plebeian elements of the towns were deeply
committed to their ancient traditions, that is, to the corporative
values of the medieval world. No affinity to âfree tradeâ or notions
of unregulated business practices were to be found among these
less privileged groups. Despite their quasifeudal notions, however,
they resolutely opposed territorial lords who sought to challenge
the liberties of their towns, ironically in contrast to the wealthy
merchant strata in their own communities who feared both camps
in this conflict and variously allied themselves with one against the
other. Finally, the newly emerging princes and monarchs who
were to eventually piece together the nations of Europe were
themselves deeply divided by this skein of tentative alliances and
conflicts. They were more than willing to use the European communes against nobles who challenged monarchical authority. But
they were equally willing to subdue the communes when they
raised the cry for their ancient municipal liberties and autonomy.
It is within this highly unstable yet very traditional worldâunprecedented in the ancient Mediterraneanâthat a new form of
societal organization was to permeate very old ones: a centralized
state apparatus structured around a distinct national entity. The
ancient world had seen the centralized state in all its grandeur and
power. And it had even seen in a bare, rudimentary form the
outlines of the nation. But never before had the twoâstate and
nationâbeen cojoined to produce a form of statism based on nationalism with its far-reaching sequelae for the modern world and
the emergence of a highly corrosive global market economy.
----
Within this rich, highly variegated, and fluid period of history, when
societal development could have followed very different directions from the one toward which it moved, we must reexamine the
conventional wisdom about the rise of the modern state and the
formation of the nation.
That the state preceded the nation historically hardly requires
emphasis here. The previous pages of this work have operated
with this fact throughout. The professional institutionalization of
power and the monopolization of violence by distinct administrative, judicial, military, and police agencies occurred fairly early in
history. The state, so conceived, emerges as a highly compact
entity whose persistence from ancient times to the present seems
almost unchanged functionally, however much it has varied in
form.
But so functionally similar an institution, seen only in terms of
its âclass characterâ and its coercive role, can be very tricky when
it is treated without respect for the many nuances of its development. Among many social theorists, this simplistic notion of the
state has given rise to images of various state forms as mere epiphenomenal expressions of a basic, deceptively unchanged structureâindeed, to use Marxian language, as the mere âsuperstructureâ of an unaltered âbase,â hence an institution that scarcely
deserves searching analysis. In modern politics, this simplistic approach produced considerable mischief. The careless use of words
similar to âfascist,â applied to established republican states as well
as totalitarian ones, can generate very slovenly and crude political
attitudes. States have been called fascist or, for that matter, democratic that are very far from being either one or the other; and
their opponents have often disregarded hard-won civil liberties
that deserve the most; earnest support by any ideological standards
or values.
What is no less disturbing, there has been a gross disregard of
democratic rights generally among self-styled âprogressivesâ
whose concerns for material justice have supplanted their concerns for social justice. The primacy given to economics, an emphasis uniquely characteristic of a market-economy mentalityâand most evident, ironically, in socialist and syndicalist ideologiesâhas led to a troubling disregard for libertarian political institutions whose preservation and expansion is of immeasurable importance to the development of a new, municipally oriented politics.
These institutions have often been contemptuously dismissed as
âbourgeoisâ by many socialists and anarchists alike, although we
shall have occasion to see that the âbourgeoisieâ was never libertarian in outlook and rarely republican in its commitment to state
institutions. Even liberal and conservative ideologies have used
such words as âfreedomâ so ecumenically that both the content
and form of the term have been absorbed into a meaningless
âblack holeâ of sociological rhetoric.
The interchangeable use of the words âstateâ and ânation,â in
turn, has been even more troubling. Trite avowals of âmy country
right or wrong!â imply no commitment to a republican state, even
when the cry is justified by a countryâs seemingly democratic or
libertarian institutions. Patriotism today is nationalism, not democratism, although during the French revolution the two words
could have easily passed as synonyms. âLove of countryâ may
characterize the sentiments of a fascist, socialist, liberal, or conservative, and this love does not in itself commit any one of them
to a particular state form, much less to a free community. Hence
the development of the state and the emergence of the nation are
not matters of academic interest. Their history is deeply entangled
with the prevalent societal values of our time and profoundly
affects our visions of societyâs future, especially in a discussion of
the municipality.
A close study of the state shows that there are and have been
varying *degrees* of statehood, not simply the emergence of a
finished phenomenon called â*the* state.â Indeed, the universal use
of such words as âstateâ can impede a clear understanding of the ;
extent to which âthe stateâ exists at various levels of societal developmentânot only historically, but also today in modern society.
Conceived in a processual way with due regard to the degrees of
statism that have existed historically and functionally, I should
emphasize very decidedly that âthe stateâ can be less pronounced
as a constellation of institutions at the municipal level, more pronounced at the provincial or regional leyel, and most pronounced
at the national level. These are not trifling distinctions. We cannot
ignore them without grossly simplifying politics. Differences in
degrees of statification can have major practical consequences for
politically concerned individuals and communities.
History, moreover, provides us with compelling evidence of
germinal states, quasistates, partially formed, often very unstable
states, and finally fully formed and all-embracing states. The
Athenian *polis* and even the Roman Republic were not fully
formed statesâthis in contrast, for example, to the fairly well-formed Roman imperial state and even more fully formed Egyptian state of Ptolemaic times. When applied to classical Athens, the
use of the word **âstateâ** has a very limited meaning, despite the
presence of slavery. Even in the modern nation-states we know
best, municipalities are often less âstatifiedâ than nations, with the
exception, to be sure, of the patently totalitarian states that have
emerged in our own time. In practical terms, a modern municipal
politics can be very different from a national parliamentary âpolitics,â as we shall see in the closing chapter of this book, and localist
politics can rest on ideological traditions and premises very different from those we associate with the formation of the nation-state.
The fact is that we have been much too concerned with the
origins of the state, conceived primarily as an instrument of class
domination, to give due recognition to the history of the state: its
evolution, its various unfinished forms, its varying kinds of structure, and its capacity to penetrate the social and political life of the community as well as the nation.
Living, as we do in âfoundedâ republican states of one kind or
anotherâstates that are clothed in a panoply of âdeclarations,â
âconstitutions,â âcharters,â and even highly personified âfathersâ
and âfoundersââour images of âthe stateâ tend to acquire a highly
contractual, legalistic, and contrived form. âThe state,â with its
clearly dated documents, seems more like a social contract than
a historically conditioned phenomenon. Behind the âcontractualâ
state lies an anthropology and history that, carefully considered,
desanctifies its rationalistic claims to authority and its mandate as
the source of an orderly society. The state, in fact, had to fight its
way into existence against claims that were no less rationalistic and
morally valid than those that it advanced on behalf of its own
legitimation. It had to emerge organically, that is to say, within the
framework of social relationships and, later, political norms that
were by no means consistent with and were, at times, highly
antithetical to the formation of a state apparatus. Hence, it is fair
to say that just as the constituted or constitutional state preceded
the formation of the nation, so an organic state, uncertain of its
pedigree and of dubious legitimacy, preceded the establishment
of a constituted or âconstitutionalâ state. The organic origins of the
state, in turn, bring into question the extent to which the state can
be validated wholesale on strictly rationalistic terms and, above
all, its capacity to absorb the very aspects of social and community
life in which it was gestated. To demystify the authority of the
state as a rationalistic contrivance is to take the first step toward
recovering the Hellenic notion of politics as a public activity, the
domain of authentic citizenshipânot as statecraft, the domain of
the professional legislatures, military, and bureaucrats.
Contrary to rationalistic and contractual images of the state,
state institutions emerged slowly, uncertainly, and precariously
out of a social milieu that was distinctly nonstatist in character. In
fact, the social and organic sources of the state had to be meticulously reworked before they could give rise to state institutions.
The ancient temple corporation, actually a religious legitimation
of tribal collectivity and public control of land, seems to have been
the most likely source of the Near Eastern state. This was a time
when priests commonly became kings or, at least, when the kingship often took on a priestly character. In either case, the temple
and palace monumentalized as well as deified the tribal community.
Despite the increasing secularization of the state, notably m
Greece and Borne, the state never completely lost its religious
trappings and its function as the custodian of the collectivistic
community. This attribute, whether as an ensemble of feudal nobles or a monarchy and ultimately as an absolutist empire, remained with it well into recent times. The traditional âhead of
state,â be he a lord or king, always remained the âfather of his
people,â whether by divine right or as a divinity in his own right.
Hence, prior to the rise of republican systems of governance, the
state always appeared not as a constituted phenomenon but as a
reworking of a very traditional, organic, patriarchal, indeed tribalistic body of relationships in which power was not simply conferred by the community as in the case of elected kingships but
inherited along lineage and blood lines in a manner redolent of the
ancient tribalist blood tie. The present always entailed a reworking of the past, a transmutation rather than a dissolution of traditional forms to meet new needs and imperatives.
It is notable that the rise of the centralized nation-state in
Europe also followed this archaic and highly organic process of
transmutation of old into new. Indeed, until âThe Age of the
Democratic Revolutions,â to use the title of R. R. Palmerâs distinguished book, it was not through the constitution of new states but
the recovery of ancient rights that king and community were
thrown into civil war with each other, a conflict that often took the
shape of monarchy against municipality.{52} Neither one party nor
the other sought to innovate new forms of governance but rather
to restore old ones from the past. Characteristically, the earliest
form of the European nation-state appears not as the emergence
of a national economy, significant as this development proved to
be, but as the increasing sovereignty of the kingly household itselfâthe monarchical *oikos*âand the image of the ânationâ as a kingly patrimony.
The evolution of the kingly household into an authentic state is
strikingly revealed by the evolution of the English monarchy. The
reputation of England as a uniquely centralized state from the
days of the Norman Conquest in 1066 tends to be overstated.
Admittedly, William the Conquerer took firm possession of Anglo-Saxon England shortly after the defeat of Harold in the Battle of
Hastings, but the area under Norman control was relatively small,
almost provincial in size. Wales and Ireland had yet to be conquered and Scotland to be absorbed. Williamâs absolutism was not
only restricted territorially; it was short-lived historically. The English stateâand certainly its highly fragmented sense of nationhoodâis notable not for its continuity but its discontinuity. Growing baronial strength clearly began to abridge monarchical rule in
little more than a century after the conquest: the Magna Carta, to
which John unwillingly set his seal at Runnymede in June 1215 is
testimony not to the rise of English democracy, all legends about
the charterâs intent aside, but to the power that the English barons
acquired at the expense of the monarchy. Although Johnâs father,
Henry II, had left his sons a state buttressed by a system of royal
law remarkable for its timeâextending the âKingâs peaceâ to
include civil and criminal cases, a rationalized system of trials,
punishments, and juries, and a professional royal judiciary to translate this system into practiceâmany of these jurisdictions were to
be reclaimed by the barons. Nominally centralized, England remained remarkably decentralized under the weaker monarchs
who filled the long span between Henry II and Henry VII, a period
of some three centuries. A centralized infrastructure had emerged
from the conquest, but history had yet to flesh it out with effective
royal institutions.
What makes the English state interesting is the challenge it
raises to simplistic theories of state formation and rule. I refer to
its organic roots and its evolution out of household offices. The
English state was born not out of an administrative body of autonomous departments but rather it was formed out of the personal
responsibilities of the kingâs servantsâhis immediate household
coterieâoften in opposition to the doubtful loyalties of the kingâs
own feudal barons. Perhaps the foremost of these royal servants
was the kingâs personal secretary, his chancellor, who carried the
royal seal and coordinated the emerging departments that comprised the administrative portion of the royal court. In time, the
chancellor became the pole around which an increasing number
of clerks, experts, and specialists in various governmental areas,
and overseers of what was to become a fairly complex executive
authority collected to form the all-important English chancery.
Almost every aspect of monarchical rule fell within its purview,
principally the kingâs exchequer who saw to the collection of taxes
and Henry IIâs professional judiciary.
In fact, the English state was formed largely from the kingâs
bedroom, dining table, men-in-waiting, and household clergy, not
from constituted principles of government that spoke in the interests of a specific âruling class.â Class theories of the âorigins of the
stateâ to the contrary notwithstanding, the English state of the
Middle Ages began as the elaboration of a patrimony rather than
the institutionalization of one âclassâsâ authority over that of another. The English barons, who were to view the formation of this
state with suspicion and later with overt hostility, found it difficult
to claim it as their own. A continual tension; existedâoccasionally
expressing itself in a violent formâbetween the baronial infrastructure of English medieval society and the monarchy, which
formed the originating impulse of an authentic, fairly complete
state, In its patrimonial form, the English state is no exception to
the âorigins of the stateâ generally; this mode of state formation
is very similar to the way in which the âbarbarianâ chiefdoms of,
an earlier tribal society gradually extended their power from networks furnished by their personal retainers and clans. The journey
from âvaletâ to âprime minister,â amusing as the juxtaposition
may seem, is closer to the truth of state formation than the more
âsociologicalâ idea that the state emerged as an agency of class
interestâwhatever it was to become later in history.
I have dwelt in some detail bn the origins of the English stateâin time to be regarded as the prototype of the nation-state *par*
continuity with the ancient past. The organic growth of the English monarchy parallels to a remarkable degree the rise of *oikos*
forms of statehood. Historically, these forms go back to early
Egypt, Persia, Babylonia, and even Rome before the empire became heavily bureaucratized.
Why did the English state become such a useful framework for
the modern nation and for modern capitalism? An answer to this
question lies precisely in the limits as well as the rationalistic and
centralistic forms it assumed, both territorially and institutionally.
Despite its exhausting adventures in France, the English state by
Tudor times remained focused more fixedly on its own island
territories than did its archaic antecedents. And institutionally, it
never achieved a degree of absolutenessâor at least was never
permitted to do soâsuch that it devoured its own bourgeois
âgolden goose.â It permitted a flexibility of market development
that was rarely to be seen in the past, not only in the medieval
world. Thus, while the absolute monarchs of England (principally
Henry II and the Tudors) managed to hold a nation together, at
least in the Anglo-Saxon core areas of the island, eventually integrating the Scots as well as the Welsh within a national framework,
it provided ample space for its middle-class âcommonsâ to flourish,
prosper, and, in time, resist the exactations and arbitary demands
Charles I imposed upon them. Throughout much of its history,
England was burdened less by a bureaucracy than her rivals in
western Europe. While the monarchy retained a well-knit bureaucratic structure, particularly in the administration of royal law and
the collection of taxes, England was largely managed by its local
squirearchy, a highly personalized system of management guided
by the rationalized standards introduced by Henry II and the
Tudor monarchs. The English Revolution of Cromwellâs time
finalized this delicate balance between the king and his âcommonsâ in a way that imparted a fictive quality to the English state
as an ideal âbourgeoisâ political system. Indeed, it was Englandâs
âconstitutional monarchyâ that was to have an almost hypnotic
attraction for the progressive intelligentsia of the French and German enlightenments.
Ironically, it was France rather than England that was to create
the kind of all-pervasive bureaucratic nation-state that characterizes present-day bourgeois state forms. Given the waywardness of
history that defies attempts by historians to systematize the development of events in the name of historical materialism and
other âscientificâ explanations of the nation-state s emergence,
Franceâs preeminence as the prototypic nation-state is explained
not by her âadvancedâ development as a âbourgeoisâ society but
rather by the lateness of that development, indeed by delays that
were to significantly initiate that development in the midnineteenth century, well after it occurred in England. To be sure,
French absolutism did not emerge in a sudden burst of centralization but quite to the contrary. Louis IX (âSaint Louisâ), more than
a century after Henry II of England, still issued his decrees with
a terminology that is redolent of the early Frankish system of
collective rule in which the Germanic kings were considered
merely first among equals. The expression âWe and our barons
recurs in Louisâs pronouncements, a phrase that in no way suggests a commanding authority over the feudal community. But
even more so than England, France began to enter into a phase
of state evolution that was to induce many historians to regard
French absolutism as the predecessor of all Europeâan overstatement, to be sure, but a sufficiently suggestive one to impart to the
French Revolution, which overthrew it, a particularly incendiary
challenge to absolutism as such.
By the end of the twelfth century, France had already begun
to catch up with England by creating **les officiers du roi** (officials
of the king) who shared power with the French barons in the
traditional royal council. By degrees, the French began to outpace
their English rivals. Functionaries, emerging from the royal
household, acquired expanding administrative roles so that the
kingly servants were soon to be royal bureaucrats rather than
household administrators. In contrast to the English monarchy,
the French carried this development much further: it encompassed time-honored
<em>local</em> as well as royal jurisdictions. Already a
huge hierarchy of petty officials had arisen, such that by the end
of the thirteenth century, Philippe le Bel was obliged to place the
host of **lieutenants, sergents,** and **hedeaux** who afHicted the
French people on local and provincial levels under the scrutiny of
<em>controlleurs,</em> a royal strategy that may have enhanced rather than
diminished the bureaucratization of the nation. Royal **commis·**
<em>saires</em> were to become permanent regional officials by the midsixteenth
century and a far-reaching network of **intendants,** supervised
by **surintendants,**
acquired the odious status of a financial
bureaucracy that particularly aroused popular hatred.
In time, the immense French bureaucracy of the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries, in theory answerable only to the monarchy, acquired a lifeâindeed an outlookâof its own. The emergence of a bureaucratic sensibility, permeating all levels of French
society, can hardly be emphasized too strongly. A new, almost
ubiquitous ânobility of the robe,â ennobled more as functionaries
of the monarchy than by virtue of birth, began to overshadow the
hereditary ânobility of the sword.â In contrast to so much of feudal
Europe, the sons of the French middle classes began to regard the
royal bureaucracy rather than the clerical hierarchy as the avenue
toward upward mobility and power, a shift in perspective that
linked the French âbourgeoisie,â whatever that word meant some
two centuries ago, to the monarchy more tightly than historians
of âclass conflict would have us believe. The French Revolution,
conceived as the âclassic bourgeois revolutionâ of emerging capitalism, was to test this âclass analysisâ in the fiery crucible of
insurrection, with more dismal results than later, nineteenth-century historians suspected.
Herderâs conclusion to the contrary notwithstanding, France
was by no means the âprecursor of all Europe.â It is beguiling to
think that an even more centralized and bureaucratized ânation-stateâ was established in Sicily in the early thirteenth century,
when Norman conquerors dispossessed the Arab rulers of their
control over the island and established what many historians have
variously called the âearliest modern stateâ and âabsolute monarchyâ in Europeâs history. Emperor Frederick II did, in fact, create
an âomnipotent royal powerâ that led to the, âcomplete destruction of the feudal stateâ to use Jacob Burckhardtâs words, a state
marked by a completely centralized legal system, a professional
army (which the French monarchy introduced very early in its
evolution), and an all-encompassing bureaucracy of professionally
trained officials, all indubitable traits of Norman Sicily.
But these are traits of a kind that in no way made Sicily a
âmodern state,â much less a ânation-state.â{53} Such state forms, in
fact, were to appear very early in human history. The Ptolemaic
state that followed Alexanderâs conquest of Egypt in ancient times
did not differ in fundamentals from the structure that Frederick
imposedâon Sicily some fifteen centuries later. Characteristically,
both Alexanderâs general, Ptolemy, and the Norman monarch,
Frederick, wedded the economy of the Nile and of the island to
the state itself. In both cases, key commercial operations, particularly the grain trade, became state monopolies and economic activity was. bound to statecraft. The Norman state in Sicily was an
âOriental despotism,â to use the language of nineteenth- and early
twentieth-century historiography, not a âmodern state,â much
less a ânation-state.â Administered t>y conquerors and their
bureaucracies with highly regulated economies, the Norman state
was no more âmodernâ than the Inca state in Peru or the Egyptian
state in North Africa.
We are faced with the paradox that one of the earliest approximations to a centralized ânation-stateâ emerged in Spain, even
before the Tudors in England and the Bourbons in France fully
consolidated their rule. Yet Spanish absolutism and nationalism
did not promote the development of a âbourgeoisieâ or a âbourgeois societyââdevelopments that have been associated with the
emergence of the nation-state. In fact, Charles V and his successors were to virtually devour a flourishing Spanish burgher stratum, milking it of its wealth, preempting its power, and essentially
subverting town life in the Iberian peninsula. At the beginning of
the sixteenth century, a swath of almost meaningless royal parasitism and domestic extortion cut across Spanish history, eventually
undermining a flourishing city network that enjoyed extraordfi
nary wealth and autonomy. The extortions initiated by the Spanish
state led, as we shall see shortly, to one of the greatest urban
uprisings in western history, an uprising that decided the future
of the new nation that had emerged from the Christian reconquest of the Iberian peninsula after centuries of Moorish rule. City
life and commerce were to stagnate or decline for reasons that had
much more to do with absolutism and its efforts to forge Spain into
a nation-state than did the decentralization that marked the ensuing history of the country.
What is most intriguing is that neither absolutism nor the rise
of a nation-state provides us with an adequate explanation for the
rise of a ânational economyâ as Hannah Arendt suggests. Although
Spain was to remain a largely agrarian society up to the 1930s,
indeed a very traditional one, its Hapsburg kings were no less
âenlightenedâ than the Bourbon kings of France and, with the
exception of the two Henrys and Elizabeth, the Tudor and Stuart
kings of England. Nevertheless, Spain moved into a period of
economic decline that still weighs on her shoulders today while
England became the âfactory of the worldâ and France its cultural
âperfumery.â Although European nation-states from the sixteenth
century onward created the arena for a national economy, they
did not necessarily create the forces that shaped it. Absolutism,
which, sculpted a sense of nationhood out of feudal parochialism,
played a very crucial role: it not only supplanted localism with,
nationalism; it also stifled a highly decentralistic, localistic, and
spontaneous society, marked by a rich diversity of cultural, economic, and communal attributes, replacing it with increasingly
homogenized lifeways, bureaucratized institutions, and centralized state forms. In some cases, this absolutist alternative favored
the later expansion of a market economy; in others, it led to state
parasitism and outright regression. In all cases, however, it turned
localist politics into nationalist statecraft, divesting citizenship of
its classical attributes and turning vital, empowered, and strongly
etched men and women into passive, disempowered, and obedient âsubjects.â
This shift from a living people to deadened subjects did not
occur without furious resistance. A belief in autonomy, regional
and local identity, and citizen empowerment ran very high between the late Middle Ages and fairly recent times. The battle to
retain these distinctly political qualities and rights was to be
fought not in national political parties or by professional statesmen; rather, it was conducted on the level of village, town, neighborhood, and city life, where the ideals of confederation were to
be opposed to demands for a nation-state and the values of decentralization were to be opposed to those of centralization. What lay
in the balance was not only the future of the town and countryside
but the development of political institutions as opposed to state
institutionsâand an active citizenry as opposed to a passive âconstituency.â
----
It has become somewhat conventional in urban historiography to
treat âcity-statesâ as though their relationships with each other
were normally marked by endless petty squabbles and their relationship to absolutism by an almost unqualified degree of support.
âCity-states,â we are commonly told, were almost innately quarrelsome, hence the wars that were endemic on the municipal level
of politics. Ultimately, so the argument goes, they were to show a
unique commonality of interests in the support they gave to the
emerging absolute monarchies and nation-states of the late Middle
Ages. Like the monarchy, they opposed feudal lords who placed
imposts on their commercial transactions and blocked the development of their markets with a self-enclosed manorial economy.
The partial truth this conventional view conveys is outweighed
by the serious error it contains. It expresses a characteristically
liberal and Marxist prejudice that prevailed a century ago against
all decentralized societies, a prejudice that was to be placed in tho
ideological service of European nationalism and its gospel of the
centralized state. Only today do we seem willing to recognize how
reactionary and false was this imagery of ever-embattled, quarrelsome, and promonarchical cities, whose economic power was presumably placed with few if any qualms in the service of absolutism.
There is more than enough historical evidence to show that
cities were as disposed to form,leagues and confederacies with
each other as they were to fight with each other. Many of these
leagues and confederacies, in fact, were not only networks of mutual aid; they were vigorously directed against absolutism and its
threat to communal liberties. Finally, territorial lords were often
quick to abandon their traditional feudal or manorial forms of
rights and duties, to participate as vigorously in commerce as the
most avaricious merchants. Indeed, English capitalism cut its first
teeth in the countryside where many squires and nobles turned
agricultural and common lands into sheep runs to meet Flemish
demands for woolâperhaps the earliest example of agribusiness in
modern times.
Confederacies or leagues of cities go back as far as Greek times
when *poleis* entered into various associations with each other for
mutual protection, shared religious beliefs, economic interests,
even for quasitribal honorific reasons. At least fifteen of these
confederacies of one kind or another, known more generally as
marked by fascinating examples of cooperation. These confederacies can often be traced back to tribal groups that were established
as early as the Bronze Age. Tribalism never completely disappeared as a framework for the later confederations, Thus the famous Delian League that Athens developed was initially Ionian,
composed of *poleis* that generally claimed a shared ethnic ancestry. By the same token, the Peloponnesian League that opposed
it was largely Dorian, and the Achaean League claimed a shared
ancestry with the archipelagoâs early Mycenean settlers although
âAchaeaâ itself was really composed of a mixed population of
Dorians and their precursors, the simpler Arcadians.
A troubling feature of many confederations is that one *polis*
tended to become the pole around which its confederates clustered, whether by inclination, necessity, or coercion. The Delian
League formed by Athens eventually became so overarchingly
Athenian in character that historians were to call its later phase an
âAthenian empire,â This is an overstatement. That Athens battened itself on the revenues it extracted as âprotection moneyâ
from the league and used coercion when persuasion failed to hold
its confederates in line is doubtless true; but there is an inescapable irony in the fact that it foisted its own democratic institutions
on *poleis* with limited freedoms of their own, whether they
wanted a democracy or not. The internal politics of the leagueâs
members stands in very sharp contrast to the despotic institutions
we encounter in virtually all ancient empires. In fact the original
confederal council of the league, formed early in the fifth century
to check Persiaâs advances into Greece, was distinguished by its
high sense of fraternity. All members of the council had an equal
vote, and its treasury was kept in the Temple of Apollo on the
politically neutral island of Delos. Only later, when the Persian
threat ended, did Athens assert complete sovereignty over the
league, preventing Naxos and Thasos from seceding and bringing
the leagueâs treasury to the Athenian acropolis.
We also know of confederacies, however, where *poleis* were
permitted to function very much on their own. Pellene, for example, showed considerable independence in the Achaean Confederacy; conversely, Thebes was held in check by *poleis* that made
up the Boeotian Confederacy, particularly after it was reformed
toward the end of the fourth century B.C. The use of the word
<em>sympoliteia</em> to designate many confederacies, particularly those
that extended byeond traditional tribal areas, is significant. Taken
literally, the word describes a union of *poleis*, presumably of equal
status, in contrast to a *patria* or âfatherlandâ with its connotations
of a capital city, or an *ethnos*, with its real or fictive tribal bonds
based on blood ties. At the molecular level of the **sympoliteia**âs
life, the human bond is based on citizenship, on the *polites*, not
on some form of juridical national identity at one extreme or
kinship ties at the other. Citizenship, in effect, is not dissolved into
an impersonal national affiliation or a presumably biological or
tribal one. And, in fact, many *polites* or citizens of a confederacy
enjoyed rights in other confederal *poleis* that they normally denied to resident aliens. They could buy land, enjoy the full protection of a confederated *polis*âs laws, and, in some cases perhaps,
participate in its *ekklesia*, although normally their political rights
were linked to the institutions of their own cities. In short, the
confederacies of ancient Greece were to enlarge the whole concept of citizenship, well beyond the parochial framework of early
How were the confederacies structured? Our knowledge of
them is very limited and any extended discussion of their known
institutions is precluded by lack of space as well as facts. But
certain general outlines can be noted. Normally, a Greek *polis*
consisted of magistrates, a board of generals, a council or *boule*,
and a citizensâ assembly. This form of âgovernmentâ existed in
many Greek *poleis* from the fifth to the third century, when it was
finally swept away by the Romans.
This is not an overstatement. The fact is that Greek *poleis* had
very little experience with ârepresentativeâ forms of governance;
indeed it was very hard for the Greeks to think in terms of ârepresentationâ generally. They could understand the rise of an oligarchy, which they often identified with a tyranny or repressive control of some kind, and a democracy, which, in its Perikleaii form,
seemed radical or âexcessiveâ to its opponents. And republican-type structures did surface among them from, time to time. But
these republics rarely produced stable institutional forms. Human
scaleâa distinctly municipal scaleâcontinued to be the only congenial and comprehensible level of institutional form that seemed
to satisfy Hellenic lifeways and modes of thinking. Any form larger
than the *polis* or confederacies of *poleis* cut across the grain of the
Gfeek mind and Greek social theory. The rise of the Macedonian
empire, regaled with all the trappings of royalty, generally horrified the Greeks, and the Roman empire seems more to have
fascinated them, as Polybiusâs writings indicate, than attracted
them until the very memory of political democracy had faded
away, In any case, even when a republican regime did emerge
among the Greeks, notably with the ascendancy of Rome, it was
often called a **demokratia** and there was a tendency to trace its
pedigree back to the *polis* of classical times. The Macedonian and
Roman empires, in effect, constituted an annoying challenge to
the Greek image of political consociation: its ethical as distinguished from administrative ways of visualizing or defining politics: its high regard for some degree of citizen participation in
formulating policy or executing it. Just as a Roman in imperial
times might look back nostalgically to the republica, so Greeks
under foreign rule looked back endearingly to the *demokratia* and
often used the word when it no longer applied to their institutions.
Not surprisingly, the *boule* and *ekklesia* the council and the
citizensâ assemblyâwere to appear in many Greek confederations, not only within Greek *poleis* themselves. There is evidence
that an *ekklesia* formulated policies for the Thessalian Confederacy in the closing decades of the fifth century B.C., possibly as an
aristocratic body. But in time cities began to encroach upon the
power of the territorial nobles. Apparently, a democratic faction,
strongly influenced by the Athenians, successfully extended popular rule within the Thessalian cities and the confederacy itself,
after which the confederacy eventually became more centralized
and exclusive. The Boeotian Confederacy was, as J. A. O. Larsen
puts it, âa land of **hoplites**â because the area itself favored small-scale farming.{54} But it is surprising to find that the Confederacy
more closely approximates a republican state than any we encounter so early in Greek history. This may have been the result more
of Spartan influence than the internal development of the Thessalian *poleis*, an influence that did not go unchallenged by a pro-Athenian faction in the cities that made up the confederacy. Unfortunately, the details of its development are closed to us by the lack of adequate historical data.
The Phocian Confederacy alternated between an oligarchy
and a democracy: a strong executive made up of generals had to
answer to a popular assembly that enjoyed the power to depose
its military leaders. The Locrian Confederacy seems to have had
a citizensâ assembly; indeed, from the scant evidence we have,
democracy found a comfortable home here, often together with
shared citizenship that made it possible for citizens of one *polis*
to acquire property and to intermarry with citizens of another
Greeks generally singled them are out for their fairly humane
and decent treatment of foreigners. The Aetolian Confederacy
appears to have had an *ekklesia* in which all citizens not only
had the right to vote but followed the Athenian fashion of voting
as individuals, not as citizens of their own *poleis*. This extraordinary degree of political individuation within a confederacyâa
rarity even in decentralistic and confederal social theoriesâshould not go unnoticed. What the Athenians did within Athens
and its environs, the Locrians did within a confederation of separate cities. Meetings of their confederal assembly were held
twice a yearâonce in the spring when the military campaigning
season began and again in autumn when it came to an end. We
shall have occasion to emphasize that democracy cannot be
disassociated historically from military associations when they involve the mobilization of citizens for warfare, changes in arms
and military technique, or simply a high valuation that is placed
on the image of the armed citizen.
The Achaean Confederacy, perhaps the best known of all Greek
confederacies, became so democratic that it was in advance of
Athens in some respects. Finally, in 417 B.C., Sparta was obliged
to step in to impose oligarchic rule. This intervention stirred up
a medley of reactions in which a pro-Athenian faction restored
democracy that led to further Spartan intervention. Nevertheless,
there seems to have been a persistent *ekklesia* on a local level that
certainly was in existence in Hellenistic times, the era following
Alexanderâs conquests in the Near East and North Africa. Unfortunately, we know far too little about other Greek confederacies to
provide even capsule descriptions about their structure and development.
What does it mean in very concrete terms to say that a Greek
confederacy had a citizensâ assembly? It is tempting to think that
in comparatively large confederal areas, such an assembly is simply a euphemism for a representative system of government, not
a direct, face-to-face body of citizens. Actually, this is far from true.
Judging from the Achaean Confederacy, citizens from various
would mean a journey over wide distances, hence assembly meetings would tend to attract only the well-to-do who had the means
and leisure to attend them. But much the same could be said of
the Athenian *ekklesia*. Attika was more than the environs of Athens, and for communities in the more distant parts of Athenian
territory a journey to the city would have been a fairly difficult
one. Like Athens, however, the poorer elements in the host city
or ââcapitalâ of a Greek confederacy often outnumbered the well-to-do who could afford to make the journey and may have, provided it with a popular, indeed radical, ambience.
Whatever may have been the possibilities and limits of ancient
cities, municipal democracy withered and finally died under
Roman rule. The Roman Empire, a purely parasitic phenomenon,
was extremely wary of municipal autonomy. It provided cities
with only enough freedom to police themselves and extract tribute from subject populations. In the centuries following Periklean
democracy, city life as a political reality began to decline and, after
the second century of the contemporary era, shrivelled disastrously, at least in Europe and the northern rim of the Mediterranean basin. Nor was urban life to revive in this area until the
eleventh century. But with this revival came the emergence of
new confederacies, an extremely important aspect of European
history whose story has been badly neglected. Peter Kropotkinâs
work on the city confederacies and leagues of Europe, limited as
it may be, may be cited as a truly pioneering effort.{55} The period
of the French Revolution and the nineteenth century were to
.witness a depressing shift in perspective from historical studies of
localism and urban confederalism to the nation-state, a shift that
reflects a distinctly centralistic bias in radical as Well as liberal
historiography. The lacuna that exists in this field is by no means
the result of oversight: it originates from a distinct political proclivity in Marxian historiography and liberal social theory to emphasize the role of the nation-state in fashioning the modern era,
an emphasis for which we have paid dearly in evaluating the
alternatives that face this era today with its increasing bureaucratization and centralization of social life.
Despite its brevity and incompleteness, Kropotkinâs work still
provides us with a robust framework for recovering some sense of
the vitality this municipal world offered as an alternative to the
nation-state. âAlready in the years 1130â1150 powerful leagues
came into existence,â Kropotkin tells us, âand a few years later,
when [Emperor] Frederick Barbarossa [of the Holy Roman Empire] invaded Italy and, supported by the nobles and some retardory cities, marched against Milan, popular enthusiasm was
roused in many towns by popular preachers. Crema, Piacenza,
Brescia, Tortona, etc., went to the rescue; the banners of the guilds
of Verona, Padua, Vicenza, and Trevisa floated side by side in the
citiesâ camp against the banners of the Emperor and the nobles.â{56}
The following year saw the emergence of the first of the Lombard Leagues (1167), which numbered, sixteen cities at its height,
followed by a second in 1198 and finally a third (1226) that collectively included nearly all the major cities of northern Italy. Not
only was Milan a member of all three leagues but also Bologna,
Verona, Brescia, Ferrara, Faenza, Vercelli, and Alessandria. Even
Venice, proud and independent, joined the first of the leagues. A
league of Tuscan cities was formed shortly after Henry Viâs death
in 1195, and still another two centuries later, guided largely by
Rome during the papacyâs quarrels with the empire. The number
of leagues that formed in Italy during this time are too numerous
to examine here. Some clustered around powerful cities such as
Florence, Venice, Milan, and the papal seat in Rome, surfacing in
the Romagna and in Umbria as well as in northern Italy. With the
passing of time, these leagues either fell apart into rival cities or
formed genuine city-statesâin fact, small republics or duchies,
depending upon the internal political structure of cities that led
them. By the thirteenth century, this structure was usually oligarchical: the *popolo*, had given way to **signori**, and Italy was to
become a battleground for majorâ European powers that tried to
dip into the still very considerable wealth of the peninsula. Although eminent urban historians such as Lewis Mumford are
highly disdainful of this development, particularly the continual
discord between the cities that are believed ultimately to have fed
the parcelization of the area, Kropotkin is careful to note that it
was precisely âwhen separate cities became little States [that] wars
broke out between them,â generally as, a âstruggle for supremacy
or colonies.â{57} Whether Italyâs parcelization is quite the overall
âevilâ that characterizes most historical accounts of the Italian
city-states or a desideratum that delayed the emergence of an
overly centralized nation-state has yet to be assessed.
The creation of city confederacies in central Europe followed
a development that is very similar to what we encounter in Italy,
but they were-also marked by characteristics that make them
highly distinctive. That Italy led Europe in urban development is
not surprising: the peninsula had been dotted by cities for centuries when much of the continent north of the Alps was still covered by forest. The German-speaking cities, however, were
unique. Although they were to follow their Italian counterparts in
time, they differed from them in social texture. They were
burgher cities with sturdy domestic markets based on the ordinary
staples of life to an extent we do not quite find in Italy (apart from
Florence) or encounter in France. Cities involved in the Mediterranean trade made their fortunes largely from luxury goods such
as silk, spices, gems, well-wrought armor, gold and silver ornaments, and the like, mainly transported from the Near East, North
Africa, and Asia. By contrast, Germanâcities tended to deal in the
making and sale of coarser cloths, tools, simple armor, food staples,
and raw materials. These commodities gave rise to a stay-at-home
artisan and merchant order that underpinned very stolid communities with a deep sense of rootedness and a strong appetite for
security. Accordingly, a localist civicism and proclivity for autonomy persisted after the Italians had become relatively jaded in
their municipal loyalties and yielded to despotic regimes. The
German word **Gemeinde** has a special meaning in civic history for
which other languages have poor equivalents. It denotes an organic community, a community that has a sense of identity and
personality, indeed one in which city hierarchies are notable for
the contribution they make to the collective good at each level
rather than the oppression they inflict on subordinates.
Genoa and Venice acquired their wealth mainly from exotic
goods and a Mediterranean-wide trade. Hamburg acquired its
wealth from brewing and Liibeck from herring and the furs of east
European forests. Merchant and artisan, trader and primary producer developed a symbiotic relationship that was relatively rare
in the Latin cities of the south. The city confederacies projected
their burgher traits onto their confederacies: cities and towns
came together not only to protect their autonomy and liberties;
they also joined to promote trade and share in a common prosperity, not simply as rivals whom circumstances forced into collusion
with each other. The persistent conflict that marked so many
Italian cities, especially when they developed into city-states that
placed lesser communities under their control, was more subdued
north of the Alps. Although bitter internal wars unravel this picture in the Flemish cities, where a nascent âproletariatâ stood at
loggerheads with a nascent âcapitalist classâ in the wool-processing industry of the time (a problem, I may add, that afflicted
Florence no less than Bruges), the gild structures of central and
northern Europe were more entrenched than elsewhere. They
helped to create and empower a stratum of middling people,
mainly artisans and small merchants, who enjoyed relatively comfortable lives and had a stabilizing effect on the community, cushioning the conflicts that were spawned by great disparities of
wealth.
Thus, one has the sense that German cities formed more stable
confederacies than did other urban entities in Europe. Indeed the
Swiss Confederation, perhaps the most enduring and libertarian to
emerge in Europe, rested heavily on the formation of the **Graubunden** or âGray League,â the canton that was to be dubbed *die kleine Schweiz* or âlittle Switzerland,â partly because of its prototypic character as the home of Swiss democracy, partly too because of
its ethnic diversity although its population is mainly German-speaking. Here, the Swiss recourse to referenda is reputed to have
been born and âNowhere through the whole range of history,â
declared F. B. Baker exultantly, nearly a century ago, âis it possible
to find a country where the democratic principle was more
thoroughly applied ... or where the good and bad results of that
principle have been more thoroughly demonstrated.â{58}
Mumfordâs churlish statements about the municipal confederacies of central Europe to the contrary notwithstanding, what the
cities of Germanic Europe lacked in durability, they tended to
make up in recuperability.{59} Some four centuries of German history are marked by a large number of municipal confederations
that continually bubbled up to the surface of political life. The
Hanseatic League, perhaps the most durable of the lot, existed
from 1241, when Liibeck and Hamburg signed a treaty of mutual
protection, to 1669, when its last diet was convened. Officially, the
league was never terminated and cities such as Hamburg and
Bremen are still designated as âHanseatic cities.â Largely based
on the Baltic trade, the league at its height embraced between 60
and 80 cities (I have taken the most conservative figures at my
disposal), including the wool-processing center of Bruges in Flanders. Nearly all the major Baltic ports belonged to this confederacy
at one time or another, and its ships ranged widely from Novogorod in the east to London in the west and along the Atlantic coastline.
Still earlier, major confederacies appeared in parts of central
Germany,; principally the short-lived First Rhenish League in
1226, followed by the Second in 1254, which lasted until 1258.
Some eighty cities, virtually all the leading Rhineland communities, belonged to the league until its members drifted away after
supporting contending claimants to the throne of the Holy Roman
Empire. Intermixed with the politics of the empire and endemically at war with nobles who preyed on their trade, their history
weaves a story of enormous complexity and challenges. By 1384,
a Swabian League had been formed that brought German cities
to unprecedented influence. League members even advanced
proposals to join the Swiss Confederation. Had the Swiss been
responsive to these overtures, European history might have taken
a very different turn than it did, possibly replacing nationalism
with confederalism. But the union was not to be, and the cities,
ever mindful of their autonomy and liberties, failed to prevail over
the empire and the princes. Later leagues were to appear
throughout Europe, even in England and, very significantly, in
Spain. If we bear in mind the large number of municipal confederacies! that existed in Europe during the eleventh century and in
the centuries that followed it, the certainty so prevalent in present-day historiography tliat the nation-state constitutes a âlogicalâ
development of Europe out of feudalism can only be regarded as
a bias, indeed a misuse of hindsight that verges on a mystical form
of historical predetermination.
Again, how, may we ask, were the Italian and northern European municipal confederacies structured? None of them created
the popular intercity assemblies we encounter among the Greeks,
Although citizen assemblies emerged within the cities, they did
not appear between the cities. In Italy, the ad hoc nature of the
confederacies did not create any serious problem of entrenched
representatives who could defy the will of their constituencies: the
confederacies were notable for their impermanence. They were
little more than defensive alliances and disappeared as soon as
they were not needed. The First Lombard League created a parliament of its own, but as Daniel Waley tells us, it simply assigned to its members areas of military responsibility and settled
the price contributions of each to field armies (*tallia milium*) and
garrisons.â This âparliamentâ never became a supracommunal
authority.â Rather it functioned more like a temporary general
staff. âTo the communes,â Waley adds, âthis *societas* or League
was, like the Empire, an institution to be judged by its utility
rather than by any theoretical implications: only an immediate
imperialist threat could keep it in being.â{60} To the extent that we
can speak of âcapitalismâ at this time, the highly aggressive entrepreneurial spirit of the Italian municipalities, fed by the enormous
wealth of the Mediterranean-wide trade, fostered a degree of rivalry that inhibited cooperation between the cities and imparted
a highly imperialistic spirit to the largest among them.
This was not entirely the case north of the Alps. German city
confederations, for example, provide us with more enduring
efforts to institutionalize intercommunal cooperation, efforts that
reflect the prudent and deeply rooted burgher spirit of the communities that composed them as distinguished from the more
reckless and venturesome features of the Italian merchants. The
Second Rhenish League, shrewdly playing off the different candidates for the imperial throne, demanded and received formal
recognition from William of Orange as a confederationâa *civitates conjuratae*âand avowed in its declaration that its citizens
âhave mutually bound [themselves] by oath to observe a general
peace from St. Margaretâs Day (July 12, 1254).â This declaration
was to go well beyond peacekeeping. Each member of the : league
agreed to send four representatives to a city assembly or *StĂ€dtetag*âone at Worms for the upper Rhine, the other at Mainz for the
lowerâto remove excessive river tolls, provide for the common
defense, add or expel new members, and foster the commerce and
welfare of each of the leagueâs members to the benefit of all civic
orders, including Jews and clergy, not only ordinary citizens. A
board of arbitration was established to settle quarrels between
confederate cities. Finally, an assembly meeting of the municipalitiesâ representatives was held on a quarterly basis, not on the usual annual one we encounter elsewhere.
The Swabian League followed almost naturally out of its Rhenish predecessor and functioned as a countervailing force to the
empire and the territorial lords. Its very formation without imperial sanction was an act of defiance against the efforts of Emperor
Charles IV to assert centralized control over the German cities,
hence its articles of agreement have a markedly defensive tone.
But it functioned very much like the Rhenish League. By the
1380s, the confederacy forced the princes into temporary submission and, in combination with the League of the Rhine, which it
structurally resembled, formed one of Europeâs greatest urban
confederacies.
The emergence of the celebrated Swiss Confederation or
âSwitzering anarchistsâ as Cromwellâs supporters were to call it
centuries later, must be seen as an extension of the Rhenish and
Swabian leagues, not an anomaly that stands at odds with the
supposedly parochial traits imputed to European cities and their
leagues. Switzerland was formed out of a milieu and modelled
after examples that existed in central Europe as a whole.[9] The
Swiss confederation, far from being an almost lonely âexceptionâ
to the confederal trends that existed in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, was actually a product of them. That the creation
of nation-states was to be so greatly delayed in Germany and Italy
is due in great measure to the obstacles that the cities, their
confederacies, and later the powerful impact of their traditions of
autonomy and freedom exercised on political life as a whole. It was
not localist âpettinessâ and âparochialismâ that kept central and
southern Europe from achieving nationhood until well into the
nineteenth century. Rather, the âdelayâ was in great measure the
product of a strong tradition of municipal autonomy and a dramatic history of resistance to centralization, however perverted
this history became in later times. The Hanseatic Leagueâs Diet,
the *StĂ€dtetag* of the Rhenish League, and autonomous confederalâ
bodies elsewhere in Europe haunt the history of the continent like
the unexorcised spirit of a more active public life and a vital civic
politics. That the nation-state eventually did unite the laggard
principalities of Germany, Italy, and, as we shall see, Spain into
centralized states was not quite the happy dispensation it seemed
to be at the turn of the present century, when nationhood was
regarded as evidence of âmodernityâ and âprogress.â Viewed
with hindsight, the images of Mussolini, Hitler, and Franco rise up
to remind us that the ideological celebration of the nation-state,
which marked social theory during the Victorian era, was grossly
misplaced. We of a later generation have good reason to lament
the loss of the confederal alternative that appeared at an earlier
epoch in Europe, one that might have averted the terrifying turn
ânational unityâ took between 1914 and 1945.
[9] Hence my strong objections to the way European, particularly German, city
confederacies are treated in the mainstream historical literature of the time, particularly by Toynbee and Mumford. In this respect, Kropotkinâs writings are still
exceptional for their sympathy, although they are not given sufficient attention in
his work.
Confederalism was not merely an intuitive civic reaction to the
feudal parochialism that marked so much of the medieval world
at the time. There were theoretical not only practical considerations that were to surface almost simultaneously in two charismatic figures of western Europe. Heraldic rebels such as Cola di
Rienzi in Rome and Etienne Marcel in Paris, contemporaries during the mid-fourteenth century, were to formulate the numerous
moves toward confederal unity in very dramatic form. Rienziâs
efforts to restore a new Roman republic evoke images of the Gracchi and their efforts to restore Romeâs traditional republican virtues. His attacks on the venal nobility of papal Rome and his efforts
to create a citizensâ militia were apparently part of a larger effort
to unite Italy into civic leagues under Romeâs suzereinty. Present-day historians tend to depict Rienzi as a forerunner of Italian
nationalism when they are not occupied with defaming him as a
âdemagogueâ with strictly self-serving intentions. The greater
likelihood is that he was a strident leader of Italian confederalism.
As a self-styled âTribune of the People,â a title redolent of the
Gracchi rather than a Cincinnatus, Rienziâs âparliamentâ was to
be made up of delegates from Italian cities, not peninsular âprovincesâ that had yet to come into being. This effort was to be
aborted when the papacy and nobility allied with each other,
ultimately leading to his murder in 1354.
Etienne Marcel emerges from this stormy era in a far more
favorable light. A âprovost of the merchantsâ and economically
well-to-do in his own right, Marcel was clearly a popular leader of
the âThird Estateâ in Paris whose efforts to enlarge the powers of
the **Estates Generale** at the expense of the monarchy and nobility
and make royal taxes more equitable developed into a wider challenge to absolutism and aristocratic power. Marcelâs own goals, in
fact, were probably more âbourgeois,â possibly even more ârepublican,â than his own order would have been prepared to accept. Like Rienzi, he was to enjoy immense support until a royalist
faction within the middle class itself assassinated him in 1358. The
tendency of nineteenth- and twentieth-century historians to read
a ânation-stateâ mentality into men who lived in an era guided
largely by feudal or confederal visions of political life is misleading.
Underlying this bias is the: myth that Europeâs âbourgeoisieâ was
initially republican and basically nationalist in its convictions.
Rierizi and Marcel rose to prominence because they spoke for
artisans and the urban poor as well as merchant and professional
strata, many of whom sided with the nobility against the ordinary
people of Europeâs cities. Perez Zagorin seems to be much closer
to the truth when be observes, âGrievances born of unfavorable
<em>conjoncture</em> and wretched conditions underlay the popular upsurge, whereas Marcel himself was a revolutionary reformer who
wanted to build an alliance of towns, strengthen the Estates General, and fasten political limitations on the monarchy. His movement also established some slight ties with the Jacquerie, the big
peasant revolt that had broken out at the same time in the Ile-de-France and surrounding region.â{61} This judgement speaks to a
confederal outlook, one that was more in tune with the period
than a ânationalistâ vision of a centralized France.
Zagorinâs reference to the Jacquerie reminds us that the period
faced a series of major peasant tumultsânot only in France but
throughout western Europe. The English Peasant Rebellion of
1381, which followed the French *Jacquerie* by less than three
decades, formed a high point in the restive village upsurges that
finally led to the brief seizure of London by a peasant army. John
Ball, an itinerant priest whoâ was to color the rebellion with powerful declamations against social and economic inequality, gave the
rising a larger-than-life image. Actually, the peasantry tended to
rise in the aftermath of wartime ravages of the countryside or
unpredictably in isolated pockets against feudal exactations, royal
taxes, excessive âtithes,â upper-class highhandedness. To detail
these uprisings would be impossible. Occasionally, they managed
to cojoin with urban unrest into full-scale rebellions and to pose
serious challenges to provincial and central authorities. Whether
this connection was well-establishedâas was the case in the
Hussite Wars of Bohemia during the fifteenth centuryâor assumed an emphemeral character, agrarian unrest became endemic throughout the centuries that followed and persists to this
day in the Third World.
Ordinarily, peasant revolts were short-lived and fragmented.
The climax of these uprisings in western Europe was to emerge
from the Lutheran Reformation of the 1520s, when the cities and
countryside of Germany were thrown into years of persistent unrest. Between 1524 and 1526, German peasants rose on a mass
scale; sweeping over large areas of the western and southern parts
of the country and entering into historical annals as the famous
âPeasantsâ War.â Presumably, this was regarded as a ârevolutionâ
by chroniclers, who were eager to distinguish it from the many
ârebellionsâ that exploded sporadically in the countryside from
medieval times to the Enlightenment. The medley of ideologies,
sentiments, and interests that are imputed to the German peasant
uprising has endeared it to Marxists, liberals, romantics, theologians, and nationalists alike. It has been variouslyâ seen as a precursor of modern communistic movements, a striking example bf
class war, an effort at moral regeneration, even as a forerunner of
the German nation-state or a force that shapedâ its development.
Most of these appraisals do not give sufficient emphasis to the
deep-seated communitarian impulses that moved the peasants to
action: their attempts to preserve the rural **Gemeinde** from fern
dal, commercial, and clerical encroachment. If there is any unifying drama to the upheaval, it is the peasantryâs effort to preserve
its organic communal ties, its traditional village universe that encompassed time-honored values, institutions, and lifeways as well
as landholdings that were challenged by princely and baronial
encroachments. It is this universe, so much of a piece with the
civic values of traditional society as such, that makes the Peasantsâ
War of 1524â26 so fascinating to theorists and historians of municipal development.
The fortunes of this conflict, with all their varied interpretations,
have been explored extensively enough to require no detailed
treatment here. Thomas Munzerâs legendary âcommunistâ tenets
of the time probably articulated the peasantryâs commitment to its
traditional networks of mutual aid, its timeless visions of a âgolden
ageâ based on equality, its precarious reality of collective management of land and goods that marked the **Gemeinde**âall village-based traditions rather than âanticipationsâ of socialist and communist theories that appropriately stem from a sophisticated
industrial society rather than an old agrarian one. To the romantics
who found in the peasantry the embodiment of a German *ethnos*,
the conflict offers no inspiring myths of a united people motivated
by a sense of blood and soil. The Peasantsâ War was as fragmented as
the society from which it stemmed. Only once do we hear of a really
earnest effort to bring what were separate uprisings into a unified
struggle. A âpeasant parliamentâ was convened at Memmingen to
form a âChristian Union of the Peasantsâ and coordinate the peasant armies of Upper Swabia. The union brought together the three
completely replicated the administration of the peasant village.
The village form, in effect, was projected onto the shared command
structure of the mili tary forces, mirroring the traditional society
that it was meant to preserve.
The Memmingen âparliamentâ also formulated and adopted
the famous âTwelve Articlesâ of the peasant revolt, a program
worded in terms of scriptural authority. The articles âhumblyâ
petition the secular authorities for the right of the villages to
choose and depose their own pastors, to fix their own âtithesâ
according to the needs of the pastor and the poor of the community, to abolish serfdom, diminish corvee labor, reduce feudal dues
and rents, and, finally, to restore all enclosed common land to the
village and end further enclosures definitively. Allowing for many
local variations, the Memmingen Articles became the basic program of the rebellious German peasantry and was soon the most
widely circulated document of the war. Given its tone of humility,
recourse to scriptural legitimacy, and humane demands, it completely expressed the spirit and values of the **Gemeinde**, It was the
voice of a traditional village world by which the municipal life of
the era was nourished and from which it drew its vitality. Herein
lies the real continuity of the articles with German civic life: its
strong solidarity as an ethical covenant.
The German princes were to unite and crush the Peasantsâ War
in a terrible bloodbath. Although city support of the peasants was
very widespread, it was often qualified and prone toward compromise. The Twelve Articles resonated with the urban poor and
lower classes, and its moral tone and appeals to scripture won it
considerable clerical support. The almost evangelical nature of the
uprising gave it the qualities of a crusade for human rights and
decency, traits that were not lost on many of the educated strata
of the cities. Despite its radical rhetoric, Frederick Engelsâs appraisal of the Peasantsâ War is pervaded by all the prejudices of the
last century. The warâs âchief result,â we are told, was the
âstrengthening of German decentralization which, in turn, was
the âcause of [the warâs] failure.â{62} One is disposed to ask if victory
by the peasants would have yielded a âcentralizationâ of Germany
that would have overcome the fragmentation created by the German princes. Accordingly, the Peasantsâ War was either a ârevolution,â as Engels claimed, or a crude anachronism as he should have
claimed by his own standards of âhistorical materialism,â in which
case it belonged not to the truly ârevolutionary traditionâ of Germany but to a âreactionaryâ one. His appraisal becomes all the
more entangled when he rejects confederacy as a valid solution to
Germanyâs problems, a solution that the peasants intuitively seem
to have desired. This problem is not an academic one. It raises the
crucial question of whether or not seemingly âundevelopedâ peoples today are to achieve what we so flippantly call âmodernizationââby confederalism or nationalism, decentralism or centralism, libertarian institutions or authoritarian ones. We have not
removed these questions from the future of our civilization nor
can they be concealed from purview by the veil of history. If
anything, hindsight has made them as searing today as they were
in earlier times, when the terrifying future that now looms before
us was very far removed from the eyes of men and women in the
sixteenth century.
This much must be emphasized: the attempts to create a nation-state in western Europe four centuries ago did not occur
without considerable resistance from the free cities of the era,
rebellious villages, and aroused artisans, not only recalcitrant nobles. The sixteenth century, which was decisive in the rise of
European absolutism and ultimately nationalism, bears witness to
a veritable deluge of village, provincial, and urban uprisings. Even
England was not spared from dramatic agrarian unrest: Kettâs
Rebellion of 1549, while more of a mass protest against land enclosures than a revolutionary challenge to royal authority, required
the use of thousands of troops before it could be subdued. In
France, the rebellion was followed by the rising of the *Croquants*
between 1592 and 1595, a struggle more redolent of German
demands for village autonomy than the English one. Such revolts,
generally localized and easily subdued, were to become endemic
as France passed deeper into absolutism and ultimately revolution. Indeed, it was not until the Napoleonic Era that they came
to a definitive end, and a once rebellious peasantry was turned into
a conservative pillar of the Bonapartist monarchy.
None of these rebellions produced confederations or developed
into serious challenges to the emerging nation-states of the West.
The civic roots of the English Revolution have rarely been appraised from a municipal viewpoint, although the revolution that
began in England in the 1640s was to find a remarkably democratic fulfillment in the townships of New England. (This is a
development we must reserve for a later and fuller discussion.)
The Great French Revolution, in turn, was to evoke the ideal of
communal confederation without giving it permanent reality. Indeed, the Jacobin âdictatorship,â if such it can be called, was to
turn France into one of the most centralized nation-states in
Europe. But the ideal did not die. Later, it acquired a brief and
glowing moment of reality in the subsequent Paris Commune of
1871, a commune or âcity councilâ that called upon all the cities
of France to joinâit in a huge civic confederationâonly to be
crushed in bloody fighting with troops of the Third Republic after
some two months of existence. With magnificant stubbornness,
the Paris Commune of the nineteenth century had tried to bring
to life what its predecessor of the eighteenth century had entertained in its conflict with the Jacobin-controlled Convention during the last years of the Great Revolution.
Ironically, the most serious threat to absolutism and the nationstate by a confederation of municipalities was to emerge during
the sixteenth century in a country where absolutism seemed virtually triumphant: Spain under the rule of Europeâs sternest and
politically least yielding monarch, Charles V. The period directly
preceding the final subjugation of the Moors in 1492 was marked
by a remarkable burgeoning of city life and the consolidation of
Spanish absolutism under the Catholic monarchs, Ferdinand and Isabella. Spainâs prosperity and its movement toward a nation-state seem like an almost textbook example of collaboration between a monarchy and an urban âbourgeoisie.â That monarchy
and city could have eventually entered into conflict with each
other would have seemed inconceivable at the time if it did not
actually happen. Isabella, following an active policy of fostering
city life and playing urban strata against landed magnates, promoted internal commerce, scrupulously respected municipal
rights, and worked closely with the Spanish *Cortes*, the countryâs
âparliament.â This policy was intended to develop institutions and
forces countervailing the rapacious Spanish territorial lords. The
gilds, long the objects of royal hostility, were permitted to extend
their ordinances and confirmed in their Tights to control production operations. The ââcrusadeâ against the Moors was shrewdly
used to increase popular enthusiasm for the monarchy, indeed to
give it a centrality in Spanish life and religion that, it had never
enjoyed. The image of a morally regenerated Christian Spain
evoked hopes of a stable, unified, and powerful nation whose restive nobility and centrifugal regionalism had to be brought under rigorous control.
This image was translated into a certain measure of fact, especially in Castile, the Spanish heartland. Castile formed the bulwark of the newly emerging nation, the source of its prevailing
dialect, its manners, and the âprototypicâ Spanish character,
which held such linguistically, ethnically, and culturally disparate
âSpainsâ as the Basques, Catalans, and largely Moorish Andalusians together. Here, tod, the monarchy in later years was to
choose its future capital, Madrid, and turn the city into the administrative center of the country as a whole. This state machinery
was one of the most sophisticated in Europe. At the same time, the
Catholic kings began to shore up their relationship with the cities,
deflecting urban hostility from the monarchy to the nobility and
drawing upon urban wealth to consolidate royal rule, Ferdinand
and Isabella enlarged their bureaucratic control over the independent cities of the province. The *corregidores* or town officials of the
crown were given extended powers to bring the urban noble clans
under control and protect the cities from landed magnates who
exploited them.. Municipal land that the magnates had illegally
seized were restored in some measure; tax farmers, whose actions
verged on outright plunder, were replaced by the *encabezamiento* system in which the main tax, the *alcabala*, was
collected by local officials; the Royal Council was staffed by university trained lawyers, the *letrados*, and a supervisory hierarchy of
officials to oversee the burgeoning bureaucracy from secretaries to
A centralized and professional judiciary, together with various
councils of brotherhoods, the Inquisition, and the *Cortes* itself
balanced out a bureaucracy and provided for close royal supervision of nearly all aspects of Spanish life.
This machinery, partly traditional and partly new, was destined
to have a very limited life span. Although the French monarchy
was to install a similar one that lasted for some two centuries, the
Spanish state machinery began to weaken appreciably even during the reign of the Catholic monarchs. The final struggle against
the Moors essentially brought the conflict between the monarchy
and nobility to an end. Despite her fears of the landed magnates,
Isabella was obliged to use them militarily to complete the reconquest, and the magnates claimed their full rewards for supporting
the state. Increasingly, the lost municipal lands were recovered by
the aristocracy, their taxing powers were increased, their abilities
to sidestep disagreeable court decisions were enhanced, and their
financial control of the monarchy increased immensely. When in
1519 Charles V became king of Spain as Carlos I and entered his
claim to the throne of the Holy Roman Empire, the monarchy was
largely under aristocratic control. Born and raised in Flanders,
Charles quickly earned the mistrust of his Spanish subjects as a
foreigner whose principal concerns were his own imperial ambitions and who lived mainly abroad to advance them. Virtually all
strata of Castilian society viewed the newly installed king as a man
who regarded Spain as a resource for his squabbles abroad, freely
bilking the country of its wealth.
To exacerbate matters still further, the central administrative
apparatus was all but taken over by a coterie of Flemish advisors
that was notable for its insensitivity to Spanish traditions and interests. Inept and clumsy, Charlesâs Flemish surrogates turned the
monarchy into a parasitic entity in which the aristocracy was the
main beneficiary of the new dispensation. Increasing taxes, a grave
decline in the honesty and effectiveness of the *corregidores*, a
breakdown in the road system that led to higher, often unbearable
financial levies on impoverished village and town populations, a
failure by inept or corrupt supervisory officials to discharge their
responsibilities in controlling the bureaucracy and aristocracy, a
decline in the integrity of the court system, a military system that
quartered ill-paid and unruly troops with an increasingly impoverished populationâall, well underway before Charles became king,
were exacerbated by alien rulers, a suspect monarch, the declining prestige of the royal power, and the growing encroachments of a self-serving aristocracy.
On May 30,1520, a crowd of woolworkers seized a hated member of Segoviaâs *Cortes* delegation and hanged him, leading to a
revolt in the city that forced all its royal officials to take to their
heels. This seemingly local act of crowd violence was to unleash
one of historyâs most extraordinary municipal ârevolutions,â as
many historians call it, the rising of the ***Comuneros*** (literally translated as Communards). Although this *comunidad* or community
revolt was fairly short-lived, it is outstanding for its institutional
creativity. The action of the woolworkers in Segovia pales before
the more serious rebellion that developed when Toledoâs city
council, challenging an unfavorable change in royal tax policy,
wrote to all the cities represented in the *Cortes* and defiantly
called upon them to establish a common front against the royal
government. What may have appeared like one of many urban tax
revolts that marked the whole period soon turned into a full-scale
revolution. Within months, city after city in Castile began to collect and impound all taxes collected for the monarchy. Civic militias were organized, and far-reaching changes were introduced
to democratize and enhance the autonomy of municipal governments. On Toledoâs suggestion, a national junta was established
with delegates from all the *Cortes* cities. The **Comuneros**, in effect,
had established a parallel or âdualâ power in opposition to the
prevailing royal administration.
Early reactions to this development ranged from the enthusiastic to the tolerant. Even the landed magnates, ever mindful of an
opportunity to gain from any diminution of the central government, placed a tactful distance between themselves and the monarchy. By mustering an impressive army of citizens with an infrastructure and added detachments of professional soldiers, the
threatened to replace the entire royal state with a municipal
confederation. The **Comuneros** had created their own military
system, an administrative apparatus that reached deeply into most
of Castileâs social order, tax resources, and a tremendous reservoir
of popular goodwill, cutting across seemingly insurmountable
âclassâ barriers (including clerical ones) that seemed irresistible in
the early months of the **junta**âs existence.
What brought this movement to an end in April 1521 when its
last major field detachments were defeated, near the village of
Villalar? Toledo, it should noted, held out against royalist forces
until February 1522, and other cities tried to resist after the battle
of Villalar. Perhaps the most strategic military fact was the swing
of the nobility from a generally neutral position over to the monarchy. No less important was the support that the royalists slowly
acquired from the city elitesâthe knights or *Caballeros* who lived
in urban areas, well-to-do merchants, the higher clergy, and generally more prosperous strata, who were alienated by the radicalization and democratization of civic life. The **Comuneros**, like their
heirs centuries later in Paris, were stridently urban in outlook and
retained a basic hostility to the peasantry (who actually were their
natural allies) as a class controlled by the nobles. Finally, the
<em>Comuneros</em> could not extend their movement beyond the center
of Spain. Viewed as Castilians by the other âSpainsâ that surrounded them, the movement was seen as the work of a privileged
population that had revolted against its even more privileged
overlords. The Catalans, Basques, and Andalusians, to cite the
most well-known regions hostile to Castilian hegemony, could not
be brought to identify with a Castilian cause, however much the
<em>Comuneros</em> solicited their support
It is easy in view of these reasons to see the revolt of the
<em>Comunidades</em> as a strictly âclassâ movement, to speak of it variously as âatavisticâ because it posed a mere municipal challenge
to a seemingly âprogressiveâ nation-state or to regard it as a conflict of interests between vague, indefinable class strata: nobles, a
âbourgeoisie,â a ânascent proletariat,â and the like. The term
ânascentâ is what makes such a âclass analysisâ questionable. Of
all the clearly definable âclassesâ that were to play a major role in
later Spanish historyâapart from Spainâs enduring peasantry-only the landed magnates survived the era as a cohesiye stratum
and were to carry on intact until recent times. The others are
more properly âordersâ in their indefinability, that is, in their
paucity of economic roots, their wavering stability as social groups,
and the murkiness of their concerns. What we have here is a
typical, quasifeudal âThird Estate,â ranging from well-to-do, even
wealthy, strata to an amorphous mass of artisans, merchants, âintellectualsâ of various sorts, clerks, and clerics, to which we may
add a considerable number of servants, laborers, and beggars. This
âThird Estateâ was united by its urbanity, literally by a shared
culture as town dwellers. Despite the many material differences
that were to separate them, either they were citizens Of a particular city or they aspired to be. Their ideological unity came from
the primary loyalty that the city claimed and from the political
arena it created. It was the city, not their âclass,â that evoked in
them a real feeling of place, a meaningful commitment of service,
and a clear sense of self-definition. This collective loyalty to a
dwellers during that era, is difficult to convey today when nationalism has invaded all public sentiments of local loyalty. In the sixteenth century it was intense enough to impart an alien, almost
exogenous, quality to the central power and to focus oneâs devotion on the village, town, or city in which one lived rather than the still-emerging nation-state.
Nowadays, we would be inclined to believe that such varied
economic groups would be in chronic conflict with each other, a
conclusion that seems to be supported by the internal conflicts
that engulfed many cities of Europe, particularly the Flemish and
Italian ones. Actually, this is a very one-sided picture of urban fife
in the past. It is easy for historians to forget how readily disparate
strata in a city united against invaders or other city rivals, despite
their divergent economic interests. In fact, it would be hard to
understand why the **Comuneros** could unite in the first place,
given the disparities in wealth and social position that existed in
their cities, and why a strong sense of unity existed to the very last,
even after urban elites began to fall away from their movement.
Their royalist opponents did not win all the well-to-do strata of the
Castilian cities; in fact, there was resistance to the very end, especially in Toledo, which held out against royalist opponents for
nearly a year after the battle of Villalar. What the royalists succeeded in achieving was enough of a division between these strata
to tip the balance in their favor and bring the greater military
prowess of the aristocracy into an advantageous position over relatively inexperienced civic militias.
What the **Comuneros** really achieved has yet to be fully grasped
by some of its historians. The movement opened civic life on a
scale that had rarely been seen in Europe since Hellenic times. It
expanded the very meaning of the word âpolitics,â not only at a
confederal, city, or town level but at a neighborhood or parish
level. *Comunero* demands were strikingly radical even for our
day: a *Cortes*, composed of city delegations, which would greatly
limit royal authority, and a municipal democracy whose extent
varied from one city to another. In a group of articles formulated
in Valladolid, the **Comuneros** demanded that delegates for the
Cortes be chosen with the consent of parish assemblies instead of
city councils, the practice followed by the monarchy. These delegates in turn were to be guided by the mandate of their electors
and were to acquire the right to consult with their cities if their
instructions did not adequately cover the problems that surfaced
at the Cortes, a right that the monarchy had consistently denied
city delegates to the parliamentary body. Had these demands
been realized, Spain would have seen the emergence of a broadly
based local democracy, one deeply rooted in city neighborhoods
as well as municipalities. Such a democracy, in fact, went far beyond radical conceptions of political representation. They were an
open invitation to revitalize the entire public sphere, opening it
to all strata of the population and advanced urban concepts of
citizenship that were all-inclusive and completely grass-roots in
character. In cities such as Toledo and Valladolid, this neighborhood democracy was not merely a demand; it became a working
reality, one that was rarely to be achieved again until the rise of
the Parisian sectional movement in the Great French Revolution.
Many *Comunero* demands constituted a sixteenth-century âBill
of Rights.â The *Cortes* was to meet regularly and all the grievances
of the **Comunidades** were to be addressed before it could terminate its proceedings. The **Comuneros**, of course, called for the
protection of property from legal confiscation except in cases of
treason; freedom from harsh punishment in criminal cases; limits
on the quartering of visiting royalty; prohibition of the sale of
public offices; reforms of judicial and appeals procedures; and the
complete âCastilianizationâ of the court, which Charles had filled
with aliens who knew very little about Spanish problems. The
demands contained a strong, basically egalitarian appeal for choosing officials according to their personal merit, professional qualifications, and moral probity rather than for their status and social
background.
Charlesâs victory over the **Comuneros** signalled the triumph in
Spain of statecraft over politics, of the nation-state over confederalism. It was a victory that was attained primarily by the force of
arms, not by a hidden logic of history. The struggle of the **Comunidades** with the monarchyâit was never a struggle against monarchism as such although it came very close at times to a challenge
of monarchical rule in its sixteenth-century formâhad been
preceded by similar conflicts between city leagues or confederacies almost everywhere on the European continent. It was to be
followed by greater or lesser struggles of a similar nature after
nation-states had been well-established. If Spain, one of Europeâs
strongest absolute monarchies in the sixteenth century, is singled
out for study, the *Comunero* movement did not establish a tradition that an âascendingâ bourgeoisie could claim for itself. Quite
to the contrary: the **Comuneros** found a later, albeit highly
modified, expression in Pi y Margallâs Federalist movement of the
late nineteenth century, which distinctly resisted state centralization, and finally in the largest anarchist movement in Europe.
Charles V did nothing to foster a capitalist society. Indeed,
absolutism became a lethal cancer in a once prosperous country
that was devitalized by massive state expenditures for imperial
adventures abroad. The *Comunero* movement, by contrast, tried
to rein this monarchy and ultimately drastically diminish its power.
Its failure was followed over a period of time by an incredible
decline of Spanish economic and urban life. Cities sank into lethargy, agriculture stagnated under the rule and mismanagement of
the magnates, roads were permitted to decay, and the wealth of the
country was vastly diminished. On the other hand, the Industrial
Revolution in Europe, which presumably dates the ascendancy of
urban capitalism over traditional society, did not foster a city development in Spain that was wholesome or vital. It did not revive
community life; rather, it replaced what remained of community
with urbanization, anomie, and, under Francisco Franco, with a
ferociously terrorist regime that has variously been called ânationalistâ by its admirers and âfascistâ by its opponents. Whether or not
the two terms actually reveal the convergence of a development
that was to yield centralized authority in its most brutal forms is a
problem that we have yet to resolve in our own time.
That there is a logic in certain historical premises, one that
unf olds more as a tendency than a necessity, is certainly not arguable: nationalism does foster totalitarianism, and the centralized
state tends to develop into an all-embracing state. But it is certainly difficult to argue, that a suprahuman phenomenon called
âhistoryâ exists and predetermines a societyâs development. The
<em>Comuneros</em> had opened a pathway to a cooperative, unified Spain
that could have yielded a very different dispensation from that
which came with a centralized nation-state. So, too, had earlier
city confederacies, whose achievements meet with so much disdain. Politics had to be structured around a community of one kind
or another, whether as a **polis, Gemeinde, burg, commune,** or city.
Lacking the flesh and blood of politically involved people and
comprehensible self-governing institutions, the human phenomenon we call âsocietyâ tends to disintegrate at its base, even as it seems to consolidate at its apex.
Centralization becomes most acute when deterioration occurs
at the base of society. Divested of its culture as a political realm,
society becomes an ensemble of bureaucratic agencies that bind
monadic individuals and family units into a strictly administrative
structure or a form of âpossessive,â more properly acquisitive,
individualism that leads to privitization of the self and its disintigration into mere egoism. The city, in turn, is no longer united by
any sort of ethical bond. It becomes a marketplace, a destructured
and formless economic unit, a realm in which the Hobbesian war
of âall against allâ becomes a virtual reality, ironically designated
as a âreturn to nature.â
Such a condition and the mentality it produces constitute a
dissolution of nature and societyâs evolutionary thrust toward diversity, complexity, and community, a problem that appropriately
belongs to the newly developing field and philosophy of social
ecology rather than urban sociology. It is a social problem because
we are talking about one of the most elemental forms of human
consociationâthe cityâwhere people advance beyond the kinship bond to share, create, and develop the means of life, culturally as well as economically, as human beings. Here, **humanitas** as
distinguished from the âfolkâ comes into its own. And it is an
ecological problem in the sense that diversity, variety, and participation constitute not only the basis for the stability of human
consociation but also for the creativity that is imparted to us by
diversity, indeed, ultimately, the freedom that alternative forms
of development allow for the evolution of new, richer, and well-rounded social forms.
Urbanization, which I see as the dissolution of the cityâs wealth
of variety and as a force that makes for municipal homogeneity
and formlessness, is a threat to the stability, fecundity, and freedom that the city added to the social landscape. A critical analysis
of how urbanization emerged, its genesis partly in the nation-state,
partly in industrialism, and generally with the onset of capitalistic
forms of production and distributionâall examined from the
viewpoint of social ecologyâis a problem of crucial importance for
our time, indeed one that will help us define the future of the city,
politics, and, above all, citizenship.
From the sixteenth century onward, Europe was the stage for a
drama unique in history: the development of nation-states and
national cultures in which populations tended to identify with
what we, today, accept as a commonplaceâa sense of personal
nationality. Even the notion of citizenship, long-rooted in loyalty
to a city and the public body that occupied it, began to shift toward
a large territorial entity, the ânation,â and to its âcapitalâ city.
Politics, too, began to acquire a new definition. It increasingly
denoted the professionalization of power with roots in the state
and its institutions.
We would be gravely mistaken to assume that these changes
and redefinitions occurred within the span of a few centuries or
that they have been completed even in our own time. The development toward nationalism was slow, uneven, and very mixed.
Nor is it secure in its major European centers. There is a strong
human proclivity, reaching back to the socialization process itself
and familial care, that identifies âhomelandâ with home rather
than nationalist abstractions, hence even the most consolidated
nation-states are more divided internally than nationalist myths
would have us believe. For example, the intense domestic conflicts
that beleaguer the United Statesânotably between ethnic groups,
regions, and even localities, not to speak of economic classes and
interestsâare testimony to the hold of specific cultural and territorial identities among populations, even those that belong to
highly nationalistic âsuperpowers.â These divisions are more
strongly evident in modern Russia.
Nationalism exercises its strongest power over the popular
imagination in oppositional ways when a nation is in some sense
under attack. As an internally cohesive fdrce, it has always been
fragile. The success of National Socialism in âunifyingâ the German people has deeper roots in German history than in a sense of
national allegiance, a history that is notable for the tragic decline
of German social life after the Reformation and the need for compensatory mechanisms to counteract the slump that marked that
bloody and ennervating period.
But how did these nation-states come into existence? What role
did European cities play in forming them? And what began to
happen to citiesâand with them, politics and citizenshipâwhen
the nation-state asserted its sovereignty over public fife?
We have seen that nationalism existed only in an incipient form
in the ancient world where, with few exceptions, people psychologically and culturally identified themselves with their villages,
towns, cities, and immediate territorial area. Classical antiquity
was mainly an era of empire building, not of nation building, and
ancient imperialism took a very special form. It was patrimonial,
not strictly political; its center was the royal household, not a
capital in any nationalist sense. If âall roads lead to Rome,â it is not
because Rome; was, a city that commanded a high degree of national loyalty butârather because it was the hub of ancient power
and order. Its centrality was derived from its administrative significance, not, as is the case with Jerusalem, its symbolic significance. Indeed, insofar as Rome was symbolic of anything, it was
seen as a symbol of oppression. Crucifixion, a mode of punishment
normally reserved for rebels and intransigent slaves, imparted to
the cross a symbolic meaning not unlike that which was attached
to the Nazi swastika during the World War II. The adoption of this
symbol by the Church instead of the fish, which early Christians
used as an expression of plentitude and conversion, reflected the
accommodation of the heavenly city to the worldly cityâRomeâand of a rebellious creed to the institutions it originally opposed.
Rome, once the whore of the world; to the early Christians became the holy city of the papacy and acquired a spiritual status in
the very act of seducing its most intransigent rebels, a lesson in
statecraft that far too many rebels have failed to learn.
Medieval Europe did, not have nations at all. Loyalties were
mainly localist in character, notably to oneâs, village, parish, town,
city, barons, and rather tenuously to oneâs monarch. Strong kings
such as Henry II of England and Philip Augustus of France had an
unusual amount of power for their times and, by their innovations
as well as their actions, exercised a great deal of authority over
their barons and clerics. More often than not, however, tlieir heirs
were weaklings and royal authority was easily subverted by feudal
lords until another strong monarch surfaced and managed to centralize power for a brief period of time. Personal authority and the
forcefulness of a monarchâs character created the illusion of a
nation-state, but it was still along patrimonial lines. The association
of the monarch with the ânation,â such as it was, was so close that
ânationalismâ in the Middle Ages rarely survived the person of the
king. The wide swings in royal authority that we encounter in
European feudalism stem from the tenuous basis of centralized
authority as such in the ancient arid medieval worlds. Centralized
power was limited by the hard facts of a primitive communications system and a largely Neolithic technology. Armies and officials could move no faster than horses; roads were very poor, often
almost trackless; and weaponry had barely emerged from the
Bronze Age. The simple fact that obedience depended heavily
upon personal ties and a reasonable modicum of fear of a resolute
king resulted in a loosely hanging political system based on individualâ commitments and the use of brutal punitive measures. The
times were cruel rather than barbarous because of the nature of
statecraft in a world where authority was extremely fragile and
punishment took a very harsh form in order to sustain monarchical
and baronial power.
The one institution that commanded widespread allegiance beyond that which any monarch could hope to achieve was the
Roman Church and the papacy. Shaped over centuries into a vast
hierarchical bureaucracy, the Catholic Church eventually became
the most unifying and certainly the most centralized apparatus in
western Europe. It could reach into villages with an effectiveness
that was the envy of any royal authority, and its command of
resources had no precedent on the continent. I refer not only to
its enormous wealth and landholdings but also to its spiritual
powerâultimately the power of excommunication and interdiction that brought even emperors such as Frederick Barbarossa to their knees.
Yet here one encounters a paradox to which J. R. Strayer gives
deserved emphasis.{63} The papacy as early as the eleventh century,
during the time of Gregory VII, was an empire unto itself. More
important than its centralized institutional structure is the compelling fact that it was an elaborate state: a vast apparatus not only
with its black-robed bureaucracy but a system of law and a juridical machinery adequate enough to make its legal sovereignty
effective. The emergence of ecclesiastical law served to open a
crucial area for the development of secular law. In the great division of power that Gregory VII created between church and state,
the latter essentially disentangled itself from the former. Secular
law, rarely free in the past of ecclesiastical influence and priestly
functionaries, could now come completely into its own. In the
very act of charting and firming up its own authority, the Church
created an ever-growing space for the expansion of the state and
for a largely nonreligious form of statecraft that no longer required supernatural sanction and legitimation. However much
monarchs were to claim divine right to support their authority,
their rights were divine, not their originsâorigins that even the
Roman Caesars claimed. Hence, like all rights, they could be challenged even on religious grounds by the church, the barons, and
later by the people. Rights are always subject to rational evaluation and legitimate defiance, a problem that monarchs such as
Charles I of England and Louis XVI of France were to face before
accusing regicides. That the Church, too, by claiming a legal domain of its own, was to pay a heavy penalty by being removed later
on from every sphere other than its spiritual authority is a part of
history that adds a dimension of irony and paradox to all assertions
of powerâthe paradoxical reality of historyâs own dialectical process.
The great division between state and church, monarch and
pope, secular and divine can be taken as a symbolic expression for
the many divisions that riddled medieval society and made the
nation-state possible. Had medieval society been entirely unitary,
it might very well have been blanketed by large, suffocating, patrimonial empires that would have drained its resources and diverted it into a relatively stagnant dead end. Ironically, it was the
fragmentation of the European world that made its unification
into several nation-states possible. In contrast to empires, nations
are relatively self-contained; their existence, at least between the
sixteenth and eighteenth centuries, was possible only because empire building by one state was blocked by the power of another.
Nation building, in effect, occurred not only because monarchs
accumulated sufficient power to establish a central authority in
parts of western Europe but also because their ability to extend
that power beyond a region was arrested by countervailing powers external to them. Charles Vâs efforts to create an empire in the
sixteenth century failed because other states acquired enough
power to successfully resist him and his son, Philip II. The successful revolt of the Netherlands and the defeat of the Spanish Armada
by England ended any serious attempt to create an empire within
Europe up to our own time, despite the Napoleonic wars and
Germanyâs expansion from 1940 to 1945. Nation-states and nationalism have vitiated all efforts to create empires on the continent,
at least by direct means. Russian expansion toward the west, seemingly vigorous after 1945, has visibly begun to ebb. American
power in Europe, although rarely exercised in a direct manner,
stands at odds with its strongly republican institutions.
This external system of âchecks and balancesâ that medieval
Europe produced on a continental level has its parallel in an internal system of âchecks and balancesâ that existed on a domestic
level. The intercity trade that provided economic underpinnings
to the formation of nation-states repeatedly came up against
strong localist barriersâartisan gilds, relatively self-sufficient village economies, popular hostility to trade that formed the legacy
of medieval Christianity, and a very strong individual desire, particularly among craftsmen and free peasants, to live directly by
their own skills and on their own property with minimal commercial intercourseâa state of mind we would call âself-sufficiency,â
today, which has its roots in the Greek concept of *autarkeia*. Nor
can we ignore the immense hold of the **Gemeinde**, the local community, on. the minds of people during that period, a sense of
communal loyalty that was reinforced not only by cultural bonds
but by a tradition of communal land ownership and mutual aid.
The considerable attention that recent economic historians
have given to the role of foreign trade in producing a capitalistic
society and the nation-state is somewhat ingenuous. That the earliest forms of capitalism in the ancient as well as medieval worlds
were commercial and that port and riverine cities often enriched
themselves enormously, promoting a domestic market for goods
acquired abroad, does not remove the need for a balanced perspective toward the reach this economy had into the depths of
emerging European, nations. Owing to the poor condition of the
roads that existed in Europe, the cost of commodities brought
from abroad rose enormously as they moved inland. A cartload of
hay priced at 600 denari during Diocletianâs time increased by 20
denari every mile so that the cost of transporting it as little as 30
miles rendered its sale in a nearby market prohibitive. Unless a
good network of waterways existed, foreign trade had a limited
economic impact on the interior of a region. Generally, the commodities that passed from port and riverine cities to inland towns
were luxury items or direly needed goods in limited supply.
Spices, expensive cloths, skillfully crafted artifacts and weapons,
and exotic foods from abroad were the usual fare that were carried
from port cities into the interior of Europe. Within the heartland
of the newly emerging nations, trade was often local rather than
national. Intercity trade brought towns and villages together but
in regional networks and local, markets, not in national ones.
This âparochialism,â to use a term that is distinctly pejorative
today, gave inland towns a certain degree of economic strength:
their relative self-sufficiency and ingrown cultures provided them
with the material and spiritual fortitude to resist the overbearing
effects of the nation-state, particularly during the âAge of Absolutism,â when strong monarchs came to the foreground of European
political life. Decentralism remained a major obstacleâand, for
generations, an abiding civic impulseâin counteracting the extension of royal power. Hence, emerging European nation-states
were often checked internally as well as externally from successfully engaging in empire building. European empire building
found an outlet not in the âoldâ continent but abroad, in so-called
ânewâ continents such as the Americas, where indigenous peoples,
living in tribal communities were easily quelled by recently discovered firearms, and, in no small part, by dazzling European
trinkets. Needless to emphasize, European epidemics, too, played
a major role in depleting aboriginal populations and demoralizing
them..
The rise of European nation-states, so unique when compared
with the imperial systems of antiquity and the fragmented social
structures of feudalism, can thus be explained by a special conjunction of forces. A few are simply negative: the internal resistance
within emerging nations to centralism that made a highly organized patrimonial state difficult to achieve and the balance between new states that confined them to a ânationalâ scale. Other,
factors, more positive in nature, consist of the fairly organic links
established between municipalities primarily by local and regional
trade and secondarily by the exceptionally rich rewards that port
cities acquired from foreign commerce. The royal power that built
the nation-state, virtually brick by brick as it were, used the internal intercity networks as political routes for extending its bureaucracies into the depths of the country just as the Church, centuries
earlier, sent its missionaries and holy orders into the forests and
farmlands of barbarian Europe along trails and footpaths.
Despite the enormous wealth monarchs gained from the taxes
these commercial networks provided, nation building was still
primarily a political phenomenon. Economic explanations to the
contrary notwithstanding, the absolute monarchs of the sixteenth
century who dominated the emerging era of European nationalism drained the economy as much as they fostered its development; The removal of feudal tolls on roads and riverways, the
domestic tranquility provided by the âKingâs peace,â the creation
of a national currency and presumably a reliable monetary system
were vitiated by the enormity of royal taxes, the ongoing wars
between nation-states that placed Europe in a chronic state of
siege, and the monetary instability produced by royal loans and
defaults.
----
The role cities played in this development was very mixed; indeed, to understand it, we must know what kind of city we are
talking about and what phase of nation building we are examining.
Generally, the smaller, artisan-oriented towns tended to oppose
the nation-state and often gained support for their opposition from
the relatively free peasantry in their environs. Indeed, it could be
said in a very broad way that where artisans were the majority of
a free town, they elected for municipal freedom and were more
predisposed to forming town confederations than larger, commercially oriented cities. Their high sense of independence and their
striking defiance of authority was not to end with their opposition
to royal rule; whether as master craftsmen or as skilled workers,
they shared an intuitive inclination toward a vague kind of republicanism, often even democracy, that clashed with the politically
more conservative merchant, banking, and professional strata in
their own communities and in strongly commercial cities.
The radical role played by skilled artisans in precapitalist society and in periods of transition to the nation-state and capitalism
is only recently gaining the attention it deserves. This is not to say
that this on-going stratum that was not to disappear as a major
social force even after the Industrial Revolution, which virtually
destroyed it, shared a completely unified outlook. Between a master craftsman who enjoyed the privileges conferred by gild membership and a skilled worker who was barred from the status of a
master by increasing gild exclusivity, a serious gap developed that
could rend communities in violent struggles. We have seen evidence of such struggles in Flanders and Italy, where skilled as well
as unskilled workers were proletarianized and reduced to exploited wage earners. But elsewhere in Europe, the traditional
bridges between master craftsmen and skilled workers served
effectively to close the gap that had been created by status differences; indeed, in many places gild doors remained fairly open well into the Middle Ages.
What is so noticeable about this town stratum, taken as a whole,
is the fairly high educational level it attained. Artisans were often
well-read, surprisingly well-informed, and intellectually innovative. Craftsmanship sharpened not only oneâs dexterity and esthetic sense; it sharpened oneâs mind as well. The radical heretical
movements within medieval Christianity consisted of large numbers of well-read artisans, not simply âmillenarianâ peasants, as
Marxist historians such as Eric Hobsbawn would have us believe.{64}
The Brethren of the Free Spirit and many revolutionary gnostic
sects that challenged the churchâs hierarchical system were filled
with artisans. Town revolts against ruling bishops, barons, and
commercially minded patricians were initiated by well-informed,
even well-read, artisans who could argue holy writ with disquieting acuteness. They often provided the ideological coherence for
these uprisings that historians often impute to professional strata,
not only mass support. This tradition did not die out with the
Middle Ages. It continued for centuries, through the Reformation,
which was by no means only a peasant war, through the era of the
democratic revolutions, and into the Industrial Revolution, indeed
for several generations afterward.
Skilled workers, particularly craftsmen, are remarkably self-contained individualsâthe urban counterpart of the yeoman
farmer who formed the basis for the democratic revolutionary era.
Skill and a minimal competence, whether in the form of a personally owned shop or land holding, confers a sense of independence
and self-esteem upon a person. It is out of these traits that the
classicalâand, to some extent, the modernâideal of citizenship
was fashioned. The lack of a respected skill and the absence of
material independence makes for mobility in the pejorative sense
of the term, notably, a wayward, fickle, and free-floating mob that
is easily manipulated, no less by patrician demagogues than by
dispossessed ones. Rebellion that lacks men and women with the
moral substance produced by a sense of material independence
and self-esteemâor, at least, a sense of hope that these attributes
can be acquired by concerted actionâtends to degenerate as easily into nihilistic counterrevolution as it does into constructive
revolutionary behavior. The gap that emerged between the
skilled *popolo* of Italian cities during the High Middle Ages and
the more or less lumpenized proletariat was to last for centuries
and disappear only when craftsmanship was dissolved by the factory system.
European absolutism repeatedly came up against this human
element in its endeavor to place its territorial realm under royal
authority. That many artisans were in the service of the royal court
as producers of luxury items does not tarnish the character of those
who lived outside the orbit of absolutism and opposed it. These
outsiders, in fact, were the great majority in Europe and generally
serviced local and regional markets. By contrast, the bankers,
professionals, and merchants whose incomes were derived from
loans to the upper classes, bureaucratic positions, and international tradeâthej âbig bourgeoisie,â as it wereâwere generally
royalist and more irresolute than the artisans in their localist loyalties. Absolutism provided them not only with domestic security
and a huge source of revenues; banker and merchant followed in
the wake of royal armies, garnering the spoils acquired by conquest, the need for arms, and the opening of new markets. Where
these strata were deeply entrenched in a municipal establishment,
they tended to resist but rarely rebel against royal authority. Here
they might act as an inertial force against nation building but
seldom as a major obstacle. Hence they formed opportunistic alliances with rebellious artisans that, they readily betrayed when
things threatened to get out of hand and demands for civic autonomy threw municipalities into violent and serious opposition with the centralized state.
The âbourgeoisieâ that is said to have given support to absolutism against the feudal lords consisted mainly of bankers and merchants and later, to some extent, of the new industrial bourgeoisie,
Indeed, this âbourgeoisieâ was strikingly conservative; it consistently supported some kind of royal power, whether absolutist in
the sixteenth century or constitutional in the eighteenth. Republicanism and democratism (a very revolutionary concept until well
into the nineteenth century) found its most steadfast recruits in
artisans and, less reliably, the âmobilityâ people or rootless, statusless, and homeless âmob,â whom even the English Levellers
viewed warily because of their dependence on the largesse of the
possessing classes.
Our picture is further complicated by the aspirations of the
territorial lords, who openly rose in rebellion time and again
against the monarchyâand, of course, by the peasantry that never
lived on comfortable terms with the royal power, the manorial
estates, or the towns. The story of the conflict between the monarchy and nobility, a struggle that reached its violent zenith in the
Fronde, which literally chased the young Louis XIV out of Paris,
is the stuff out of which the conventional history of European
absolutism is written. It does not require emphasis here. The peasant wars in England in the late fourteenth century and in Germany in the early sixteenth were really climactic events in a
chronic conflict that went bn for centuries from the High Middle
Ages to our own time. John Ball and Thomas Miinzer were the
ancestors of a host of later agrarian leaders such as Emilian Pugachev in Russia and Emiliano Zapata in Mexico. All of them shared
the central goal of preserving the village community, its insular
lifeways, its networks of mutual aid, its common lands and communitarian economy.
Nation building during the era of absolutism was unique precisely because it occurred withinâand by the tensions it produced
and fosteredâa highly diversified and creative social arena for
political development. The ancient world had been dominated by
massive, generally immobile empires that suffocated social development with their parasitism and massive bureaucratic structures.
Medieval Europe was an embryonic worldârich in promise, to be
sure, but largely unformed, lacking in cohesion, indeed more particularistic than decentralistic. Absolutism and the early era of
nation building stood somewhere in between. As Perez Zagorin
tells us: âIn spite of the expansion of absolutism and its critical
collisions with rebellious subjects, royal government never became uniform or monolithic, even in the kingdoms where it suffered least limitation. Confusions of jurisdictions and rivalries and
conflicts among governmental institutions abounded under its
rule. Its actual power was more like an intricate mosaic of particular prerogatives, rights, and powers than a homogeneous, all-inclusive authority. The attributes of sovereignty that were ascribed to absolute kings by royalist lawyers and political philosophers, such
as the French thinker Jean Bodin, were more often than not
greater in theory than the powers these same kings could dispose
of in practice. The monarchies of our early modern states continued to be in many regards conservative and traditionalistic, as
befitting regimes ruling hierarchic societies and of centuries-long
growth from ancient origins. Absolutist kings did not quarrel with
social privilege, of which their own position was the supreme
manifestation. They quarreled only with the privileges that resisted their authorities or claimed immunity from their government [which, one is obliged to add, seems to mean that they
opposed all social privilege but their own]. In building their more
centralized states, they did not sweep the stage clean with a new
broom and many older and outmoded political forms and institutions survived the reign of absolutism, like scenery left standing while a new play was performed.â{65}
What Zagorin seems to reproach the absolutist monarchies for
-namely their failure to âsweep the stage clean with a new
broomâ and achieve a more homogenized, efficient, and smoothly
working social orderâis what gave the era its incredibly
mism and creativity. It was precisely the rich social features of the
sixteenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth centunes-the extraordinary diversity of social life and its forms, the creative tension from
whffih so much mobility in status, cultural, and intellectual fervor
emergedâthat makes the era so fascinating and provocative. The
absolute monarchies, caught in a complex web of ancient priveleges and rights, thus became the reluctant conservators and the gnawing subversives of an accumulated wealth of old customs
autonomous jurisdictions, traditional liberties, and hierarchical
claims to authority.
Within this immense warehouse of historical rights and duties,
communities and individuals, institutions and interests could
move with remarkable freedom and function with exciting fecundity often invoking past precedent to defend recent innovation
in an old guise and play history against present to create amew
future Marx was to reprove the French revolutionaries of 1848 for
dressing their rhetoric, claims, and ideals in the slogans of the
French revolutionaries of 1789â94, who in turn borrowed the
language and postures of the Roman Republic to legitimate then
own ideals. Yet it was precisely this rich sense of historicity and
variety of forms, manners, and ideas-whose power and insightfulness
we will explore in the closing chapter of this book-that gave
such fecundity to both French revolutions and opened such
sense of promise in Europe two centuries ago. What an individual
âthinks of himselfâânot simply the hidden economic laws or
some unknown âspiritâ that ostensibly guides historyâhas a
very profound effect on how he or she acts as a social being
deeply influences the course of social development, Marx to the
contrary notwithstanding. The richly variegated images that people had of their own time, their rights, and themselves profoundly
taped much of the history of that time. Diversity made fo
greater choice and a more fertile social landscape, however often
precedent was invoked and reshaped to serve new ends. The
tensions created by the alternate developmental pathways that
emerged before communities, orders, classes, and, yes, individuals
fostered a highly creative practice in the achievement of their
ends.
Nor is it true, as Marx tells us, that âNo social order ever
perishes before all the productive forces for which there is room
in it have developed.â{66} I leave aside the fact that this dictum begs
the very question it poses: we presuppose that the limits of a social
order are defined by their âproductive forces,â notably technology and the various ways of organizing labor, indeed that they
constitute the essence of a âsocial order.â Actually, we have no
way of knowing how far the âproductive forcesâ could have developed in precapitalist society, nor do there seem to be any limits
to the development of âproductive forcesâ today, which means, by
inference, that a market society will be with us forever.
But what is most disquieting about Marxâs vision of social
change is the extent to which it denies the power of speculative
thought to envision a new society long before an old one becomes
intolerable or is bereft of any room for development. Artisans and
peasants in the era of nation building had many sound ideas about
the kind of society they wished to create. It is a mechanistic arrogance of the most extreme kind to predetermine how far communities can goâwhether forward, backward, or both, m their
vision of the good society and the elements that compose itâand
literally dictate the material or productive limits of their vision, its
âpreconditions,â its possibilities, and its place in a theory of history
structured around various âstagesâ and presuppositions.
We may say, returning to Zagorinâs description of absolutism,
that it was not in spite of a monarchâs âbrutal collision with rebellious spiritsâ but because of this collision that the nation builders
of Bodinâs time failed to âsweep the stage clean with a new
broom...â English, French, and Spanish monarchs, like their
ancient counterparts who built huge empires, wanted very much
to achieve âhomogeneous and all-inclusive authority. They did
not require the existence of local hierarchies to justify the development of a national hierarchy, nor did they need the challenges
created by local privileges to justify their own claims to national
privilege. To the extent that they tolerated local hierarchies and
privileged strata, it was because they did not have the resources
and the economic supports to replace them. Jean Bodinâs justification for the all-inclusive authority of every national government
over the rights claimed by lesser, more local jurisdictions is evidence of a prevailing vision among the monarchies of his day that
clashed with the reality of their situation and profoundly unsettled
the real world. What European monarchs did âthinkâ of themselvesânamely, all-powerful rulers of highly centralized stateâsâdeeply affected the development of European history. Their centralists proclivities clearly influenced the thinking of men like
Robespierre, Franceâs centralizer par excellence, who also struggled to overthrow royalism as such, using Rousseau-like principles
of a democracy that âforcesâ men to be free. Herein lies one of the
great ironies of the modern era: leaders of the popular opposition
to absolutism were to function in many ways like the monarchs
they professed to oppose and, ultimately, they were to turn against
the very popular movements that brought them to power.
It was the artisans and peasantsâof the autonomous towns
whose walls centralistic royalists such as Cardinal Richelieu were
to demolish, not only self-governing and parochial feudal lords
who were to rise in rebellions against the monarchies of Europe.
I have already examined the resistance and alternative offered by
the **Comuneros** and the German peasants as examples, together
with others who typified the most important efforts to arrest centralism and statist forms of nation building. The seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries, no less than the sixteenth, exploded in numerous albeit more localized conflicts of the kind that produced
so much civil turmoil in the sixteenth. To catalogue these smaller
but highly numerous revolts, particularly those that occurred in
France, would be tedious. Their overall pattern, however, is described by Zagorin very ably:
In every case, some new exorbitancy of royal finance, a tax on
taverns, for instance, or the abolition of as exemption from certain
imposts, sparked the outbreak. Then the residential quarters of the
poor erupted, mobs of three, five, and even ten thousand took to the
streets, and the pursuit of the *gabeleurs* [tax collectors] became the
order of the day. Riot and excitation, violence coupled with aspects
of a popular festival and its drunken indulgence, dominated these
outbreaks, as the lower orders dropped their workaday routine for
the collective action that demonstrated their anger and made them
feel their strength. The militant base was always the urban **plebs**:
not made up entirely, perhaps, of what the president of the parlement of Bordeaux called âthe lowest part of the people,â but com
sisting of artisans, journeymen, day laborers, small shopkeepers, and
sometimes womenfolk, too, who participated with their men! At,
Bordeaux a boatman and a tavernkeeper, at Agen a master glover,
a pack-saddle maker, and again a tavernkeeper, at Perigeau a physician, stood out as leaders and hafanguers of the crowd. Peasants
swarmed in from the outskirts to unite briefly with the revolt, as
happened in Bordeaux, At Agen, six thousand peasants who tried to
enter were kept out by the bourgeois militia and burned the property of *gabeleurs* in the vicinity.{67}
A more detailed account would include attacks upon the town
hall, the release of jailed prisoners, the killing of tax collectors and
finance officials, even of wealthy individuals who were suspected
of being in collusion with the state. Without the leadership provided by artisans, small proprietors, occasionally professionals, and
even members of the lesser nobility, it is unlikely that these uprisings would have gone very far. Apparently their extent depended
upon âthe passivity, neutral or ambiguous behavior, and even
partial support [of] the notables and well-to-do. The bourgeois
militia of Bordeaux showed little will to act.. At Perigeux the
bourgeois guard was similarly slack. Only at Agen, where the
violence was particularly intense and accompanied by a definite
social antagonism, did elites and authorities take concerted steps
against the outbreak.â
The limits of these insurrections, rural as well as urban, should
be noted. Again, Zagorin comes to our aid:
Taken as a whole, French urban rebellions were devoid of programs
or ideas. In the same way as the concurrent agrarian revolts, they
seemed to reflect a stasis in French society despite its exceptional
amount of violence and insubordination, an inability by insurgent-forces to transcend the existing state of things with any informing
vision of an alternative. Although again and again the centralist
offensive led to resistance, the latter failed to give rise to demands
for political changes.... Urban rebellion was essentially a defensive
response by the whole community. To the plebeian populace, the
punishment of *gabeleurs* was a deserved act of communal justice.
If such people took the largest, most active part in these insurrections, that was because they were the most sensible of fiscal oppression. But elites usually shared responsibility in some measure. Their âown opposition to exactions helped to legitimize resistance, and
they encouraged revolt, whether by actual instigation, covert approval and sympathy, or inaction, when disorder broke out.... But
they were helpless to hold back the advance of absolutism and its
centralizing grip because they had no political reforms to propose
and conceived of no new institutional limits on the power of the
royal state. {68}
Actually, Zagorinâs account of the way these chronic town insurrections unfoldedâultimately leading to the French Revolution itself a century or so laterâfails to explore certain important
details that help us understand the extent to which the uprisings
actually did âhold the advance of absolutism and its centralizing
gripâ under control. The French monarchs such as Louis XIII and
Louis XIV were strong kings who were guided by even stronger
advisors such as the cardinals Richilieu and Mazarin, respectively.
They created the strongest armies and created the most far-reaching bureaucracies in western Europe in their day. They were
ruthless centralizers and patently hostile to their own nobility,
often encouraging trade and playing the âbourgeoisâ classes
against the noble classes who were as protective of their particularistic privileges as they were of their economic. Western Europe in
the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries was a status-oriented
world. It was made up more of âordersââstatus groups who enriched themselves, developed extravagant patterns of conspicuous consumption, and spoke in a mannered language according to
an elaborate body of etiquetteârather than of classes who simply
and unadornedly pursued their material interests. Power and social recognition were no less important than wealth; in fact they
were major sources of material wealth. Personal enrichment, in
turn, was often pursued precisely to gain more power and greater
social recognition. Consumption in all its dazzling forms thus assumed greater significance than production, even for the bourgeoisie, which tried to elbow its way into the social hierarchies of
the era. Mary Beardâs account of the merchantâs values in the
Roman world holds as well in the era of absolutism as it does in the
era of empire, a thousand years earlier. The trader, she observes,
âhad drained the wealth of the West for âbones and stonesâ [gems
and ornaments] from the East and thereby brought on currency
troubles for which there was apparently no remedy.... Because
he had yielded much to the landed gentlemanâs ideal, he tended
to draw fortunes away from the business to the land, taking wealth
out of circulation and energy out of business enterprise. His children, growing up in the country, were often lost to business entirely.â{69}
In western Europe, especially in âclassicalâ Franceâthe country that so many radical and liberal thinkers were to regard as the
model for âpureâ feudalism and the âbourgeois-democraticâ revolutionâthis process of moving from the status of trader to that of
nobleman was especially marked and adds considerable ambiguity
to what we mean by the word âbourgeois.â Many âbourgeoisâ and
noble interests coalesced. Both orders generally had a greater fear
of the âmobâ than of each otherâand, in moments of crisis, of the
monarchy. The two orders were united by bonds of marriage, land
ownership, cultural tastes, values, andâ a desire for status and the
power, political as well as economic, that it conferred.
The âbourgeois militiaâ of Bordeaux, Perigeaux, and Agen
probably included many aspiring master craftsmen, merchants,
and a good sprinkling of âindustrialistsâ who were eager to acquire
noble statusâeven if only ânobles of the robeâ (nobles who had
noble status conferred upon them for service to the state or, quite
crassly, for money) rather than ânobles of the swordâ (hereditary
nobility). They were more like medieval burghers, than capitalists
in the present-day sense of the term. Indeed capitalism, conceived
not simply as an economic system structured around commercial
transactions or trade but, in its truly modern sense, as an accumulative system (what Marx called âexpanding reproductionâ)
in which industrial expansion became an end in itself, was a feeble
thing in western Europe in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, more characteristically Dutch than either English or French.
Hence, it would be of value to discriminate between the words
âbourgeoisieâ and âcapitalistsâ rather than turn them into synonyms.
By the same token, the âlowest part of the people,â whom the
president of the Bordeaux Parlement designated as the principal
activists in the urban rebellions of the 1630s, were not simply
laborers, vagabonds, and beggars. In a status-oriented society, they
could also be said to include master craftsmen, artisans, shopkeepers, and small-property owners. The fact that tavernkeepers, master glovers, pack-saddle makers, and. even a physician âstood out
as leaders and haranguers of the crowd,â to use Zagorinâs words,
tells us something about the âcrowdâ they led and harangued.
That nobles, too, occasionally became such âleadersâ tells us something about the transclass nature of such uprisings and the extent
to which nearly all sectors of society could be united against the
centralization of power by the monarchy. Most of the people
hated men like Richelieu, Mazarin, and members of the kingâs
administrative bureaucracy, despiteâtheir ritualistic expressions of
affection for the king. Such cries as âLong live the king without the
status as a caring father, could earn popular loyalty only if he was
shorn; of the all-important fiscal means for maintaining his commanding position in the countryâa position that amounted to
very little without the money for provisioning his army, paying his
bureaucrats, and carrying on domestic wars against recalcitrant
towns and nobles.
Which raises Zagorinâsâ question of how much of a program
French insurrectionaries actually needed if French society was
indeed in a âstasis.â Zagorinâs use of the word *stasis* stands at odds
with, his notion that the insurrectionaries were âhelpless to hold
back the advance of absolutism and its centralizing grip.â The
âstasisâ of the time consisted precisely of a lasting balance of forces
between the central power and the regions, localities, orders, and
classes of the time, not an ever-encroaching central power. Richilieu and Mazarin, working ruthlessly on behalf of their monarchs, tried to forge a completely centralized nation-state around
the king and his bureaucracy. It is myth, in my view, to believe
that any but the most naive of the absolutist Frerich kings trusted
their nobles, although one French monarch, Louis XVI, tried to
enlist his nobles in 1788 against an ever-demanding âThird Estate.â They betrayed him without scruples and, in the most self-seeking manner, brought about his downfall as well as their own.
Thus Richelieu and Mazarin did not succeed, in fact. They carried centralization far in France, but not so far that it could prevent the French Revolution, which tried in its early phases to
reverse the power of the king and the aristocrats alike, initially
driving toward a relatively decentralized, indeed minimal, state.
If centralism is to be identified with the interests of the newly
emerging capitalist economy insofar as the âbourgeoisieâ seeks a
politically unified country, the French Revolution was categorically not a âbourgeois revolution.â Nor did the French âbourgeoisieâ want a âdemocracyâ or even, necessarily, a republic. Indeed,
it tried to model France on Englandâs constitutional monarchy.
The supreme irony of the French Revolution is that a movement
designed to curb privilege, hierarchy, and, above all, centralized
power was twisted by liberal intellectuals, âforward-lookingâ lawyers, and marginal strata into the most centralized state in Europe
in order to defeat its counterrevolutionary enemies. In some respects, the Jacobin Republic that followed the collapse of these
hopes for a constitutional monarchy and a fairly decentralized
political structure was marbled by feudal concepts of government,
notably, the famous âmaximumâ that limited the rise of placed
prices and wages, state intervention in many parts of the economy
and society, and a moral posture that espoused ârepublican virtueâ as a political calling. The Jacobin Republic, in effect, was a
wartime state that Napoleon was to make fairly permanent. This
quixotic turn of events etched itself, deeply into French national
fife for nearly two centuries, and centralism became a focal issue
around which popular movements were to rebel throughout the
nineteenth century. The climax of this popular movement was
reached in May 1871 when the Commune of Paris tried to establish a confederal republic based on a commune of communes, a
struggle that ended in a bloody massacre and the ebbing of decentralistic notions of socialism in France itself.
----
Robespierre and napoleon, more than Richilieu and Mazarin, were
the true forgers of the nation-state in France, and it was they who
provided the real âclassicalâ example of centralized national authority in Europe.
What role did the towns and cities play in abetting this development from the sixteenth century onward? Towns and cities responded, as we have seen, in very mixed ways to the emergence
of a centralized authority that tried to absorb them. Some resisted
that authority with very little internal division or difference of
opinion. Others, particularly where the âbourgeoisieâ and elite
orders prevailed, favored a well-coordinated society in which
trade could prosper. They thereby abetted the work of Richelieu,
Mazarin, and Napoleon, both the original article and his nephew,
Louis Bonaparte, in the 1850s and 1860s. But there is a sense in
which all the towns of Europe unwittingly abetted the formation
of nation-states, even as they opposed it for social, political, and
cultural reasons. They did this by creating the arteries and veins,
as it were, for national consolidation: the elaborate, indeed historically unprecedented, road systems and nodal market towns that
fostered the monetization, commercialization, and industrialization of nationsâand with these possibilities, the effective centralization of the state along national lines.
I wish to advance the view that this was one of the most important achievements of Europe during the Middle Ages and well
into recent times. So much emphasis has been placed by historians
on Europeâs development of a market economy, its relative freedom of trade, and its openness to industrial innovationâfeatures
that are certainly uniquely Europeanâthat we fail to recognize
how little they would have been able to affect the continentâs
development without a network of roads, canals, and rivers to
make such an economy possible. Apart from the trade that created
market townsâtowns where all goods were systematically exchangedâlong-distance commerce was an elitist affair and served
the well-to-do, not society at large. Local trade was necessarily
very local because of the insular nature of most European communities. So, too, was political power. Rivers, canals, and maritime
transportation served to link a fair percentage of Europeâs towns
and villages together, but by no means the majority. A European
âhinterlandâ existed almost everywhere on the continent, such
that towns and villages were almost entirely self-sufficient in the
staples of everyday life and culture remained highly insular. These
âhinterlandsâ were largely beyond the reach of the nation-state
and surprisingly impenetrable to commerce, monetization, and
the âbourgeoisâ incubus that was to claim Europe for itself during
the nineteenth century.
We can begin to sense the importance of road systems in economic development and political control today (perhaps even
more than during any other part of our century) because of the
effectiveness of guerrilla warfare in the Third World. The very
lack of âdevelopmentâ and the poor road systems that exist in
Central America, mountainous portions of Asia, and the rain forests in southeast Asia have brought even nation-states aided by
âsuperpowersâ to their knees. All the âcolonizersâ of the past
recognized the need for effective road systems. The Romans were
able to hold their empire together precisely because it was networked by a highly elaborate system of roads that penetrated into
the Iberian peninsula, Gaul, and portions of Britain and Germany
as well as the hinterlands of the Mediterranean basin. Even quasi-tribal societies such as the Inca of Peru developed âempiresâ because roadsâactually well-maintained pathways and footbridgesâmade central coordination possible. It matters little whether
elaborate road networks emerged because âeconomic forcesâ
created a need for them or because they made the emergence of
such âeconomic forcesâ as a market economy possible. The two,
in fact, may have interacted reciprocally with each other: road
building stimulating commerce and commerce stimulating road
building.
Judging from Romeâs network, however, good roads in themselves did not necessarily foster a high volume of commerce, although they were indispensable for commercial advances. This
great network of antiquity was not constructed primarily to transport merchandise. It was created mainly to move troops and imperial administrators to various parts of the empire. Even the transport of goods to supply the legionnaires was a secondary factor in
road design and its routes. As R. S. Lopez tells us in his absorbing
discussion of land transport, Roman troops were encouraged to
live âas far as possible on the food produced in their immediate
vicinity and the administrative centres were almost all situated
either on the sea or on internal navigable waterways.â{70} This orientation is very âun-Europeanâ: it reflects the astonishing extent
to which a world oriented toward agrarian values dominated its
merchants and morally denigrated their sources of income. Essentially, it was the âmerchant, glutted, or rather contented with his
profit, [who] retires from the port to become a landed proprietor,â
Cicero tells us, â... [who] seems to me worthy of full praise,â not
the âsmall-scaleâ trader, much less, artisan, âwho should be of
little account.â{71}
Accordingly, Roman roads wore built almost defensively along
mountain crests, very much like fortresses, rather than through
populous valleys. Their seemingly indestructible large blocks of
stone gave them a rigidity that increased their vulnerability to
climatic changes, opening large surface cracks that, as Lopez tells
us, âneeded gangs of slaves, or continuous work by those obliged
to furnish road-services to the state, and even so they were unsuitable for heavy or broad vehicles.â{72} The Roman road system, indeed ancient road networks generally, were not designed to expand local commerce beyond its regional confines or open trade
routes to a continental exchange of ordinary staples. Long-distance trade of luxury goods and delicacies transported by sea or
along rivers was favored over a mosaic of local and regional commercial transactions that brought ordinary goods and money into remote areas of the continent.[10]
[10] Which is not to say that grain, that all-important import of the Greek cities and
Rome, was not a major staple in the Mediterranean basin and along European
water routes. But the inland transportation of grain by carts was quite secondary
to luxury objects once we look beyond a regional economy in Europe.
By contrast, Europe placed a high premium on the local artisan
and merchant. At a time when so much emphasis is placed on the
role of long-distance commerce in forming capitalism and the
modern age, it is important to recognize how local producers and
local markets slowly reworked the interior of the European continent, preparing it for a monetized economy and providing the
goods and markets for creating a market society. This slow but
historic change in the economic culture of Europeâa slow but
decisive change in attitudes toward trade, production for sale, and
the use of moneyâwas the work in large part of small towns, not
only busy, glamorous ports.
Little by little a new network of roads was put into effective operation, different totally in structure and methods from the ancient one
and used by quite different types of transport and haulage. The
changes in transport which accompanied the commercial revolution and the outburst of economic activity in this period can themselves be described as a slow revolution, If we consider them more
closely, we find that they reveal the changed political and social face
of Europe. For in medieval Europe there was no large and powerful
state like the Roman Empire. Slavery disappeared and in many
regions, of which Italy was the first, serfdom was abolished. Finally,
the dignity of the, merchant and of trade won recognition, though
with many reservations. Hence private initiative or local associations largely took the place of coercive government action. The
routing of roads reflected the needs of commerce rather than the
convenience of soldiers and civil servants. Maximum use was made
of animal labour in transport, while human labour was safer as
possible, economized.
Lopez goes on to say that road construction âinitiative came from
autonomouslocal bodies or independent private companies. Plurality of roads, which is always possible when the dogma of the
straight line is abandoned, enabled a great number of minor centres to be included in the network.â
To say, Ferdinand Braudel reminds us, that âNapoleon moved
no faster than Julius Caesarâ misses a number of very important
points. Even if this statement were true, Napoleon had a greater
variety of transportation choices than Caesar and climatic factors
limited his strategic decisions far less than those of his Roman
counterpart; so, too, for the European tradesman by comparison
with the Roman. Even if we examine the regional network of
roads created by this gradual transportation revolution, new possibilities and a sharper division of labor between the artisan and
food cultivatorâwith its concomitant elaboration of skills, local
inter action, use of money, and growing wantsâall constituted the
indispensable spadework for creating a sophisticated market economy.
What is important is that it was the proliferation of craftspeople,
of new wares and technics, of more craft organizations or gilds,
and the intensive as well as extensive development of market
interactionsâgenerally intimate, humanly scaled, and ethicalâthat is most characteristic of the market economy that emerged
in Europe. Let me emphasize that this rich patchwork of commercial relationships enhanced human interaction, unlike the capitalistic type of market economy that was to replace it centuries later.
Even as it slowly advanced over the European continent, trade on
a small, local scale between closely associated communities and
individuals fostered cooperation rather than competition. It
tended to deepen and extend local ties rather than sever them. It
was more participatory than adversarial, more moral than predatory, and politically it provided the individual producer with a
stronger material base for the exercise of citizenship.[11] Finally, it
tended to dissolve barriers between local communities and adjacent regions, opening the doors to new ideas, cultures, values, and
the interchange of skills and technics. In time, the towns themselves acquired greater political and economic weight in the struggle to form nation-states. It may have entangled them in the crises
of nation building, but it also turned them into centers of revolutionary social transformation, an advance signalled by the
Comunero movement in Spain and the sectional movement in
France.
[11] I find it fascinating that so many radicals, socialists and anarchists alike, almost
intuitively rally to the support of small-scale farmers against agribusiness and small
family enterprises against giant supermarkets, this despite their hostility to private
property of any kind. Americans seem to suspect that domestic forms of society,
however propertied, are a desideratum in themselves and foster individuality in
a mass society. This Jeffersonian legacy acts as one of the most important inertial
elements against the full colonization of society by corporations and big business,
even though its historical context in the making of the free city and free citizen
has not been fully understood; so, too, for our appreciation of craftsmanship.
These markets and towns were not capitalistic. Marx has appropriately designated their economy as âsimple commodity productionâ in which profit making and the plowing of surplus earnings
back into capital expansion are largely nonexistent. Taken in this
pure form, his account of their âmode of productionâ is more of
a Weberian âideal typeâ than an actual reality. Capitalism almost
certainly did exist in European towns, even predominantly in
some artisan ones, and even dominated many European cities,
particularly port and riverine cities. But Europe also developed
for centuries by elaborating its artisan-oriented towns rather than
by significantly transforming them. Viewed as a whole, the continent from the fourteenth century onward until well into the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries seemed to have a mixed
economy, which was neither predominantly feudal, capitalist, nor
structured entirely around simple commodity production. Rather,
it contained and combined elements of all three forms. That one
of these elements seemed to be of greater significance than another in some communities and areas does not alter the mixed
nature of economic life as a whole. Contrary to the widely held
belief that a capitalistic economy emerged within the âwombâ of
feudalism and asserted itself as a âdominantâ form with the attempt to build nation-states in the sixteenth century, it seems
more accurate in my view to say that capitalism coexisted with
feudal and simple commodity relationships. This long era, perhaps
spanning more than five centuries, simply cannot be treated as
âtransitionalâ without reading back the present into the past and
teleologically structuring European history around an Aristotelian
âfinal causeâ called âcapitalism.â
At various times and in various places, this mixed economy
assumed a very balanced formâin some respects more stable in
terms of everyday life than our own war-ridden century. Marxist
and liberal historians have been vexed to give this long era a name
that accords with the dogmatic âstagesâ theories of history that
abound in Marx and Engelsâs writings. Its existence seems to be an
affront to the neat categories that even radical historians impose
on the rich flux of social development. Conclusions that it was
either âfeudalâ or âcapitalist,â or what able writers like Paul
Sweezy designate as âprecapitalist commodity productionâ (a designation that tells us we know more about what it was not than
what it really proved to be), often stand in flat contradiction to the
data at our disposal.{73}
A more open-minded reading of the data and the empirical
evidence at our disposal on the eraâone that extended well beyond the sixteenth-century period of nation buildingâwill show,
I submit, that western Europe existed within a force field in which
feudal traditions interacted with simple commodity and capitalist
forms of societal organization. Nor were feudalism, capitalism, and
simple commodity production socially rigid economic systems.
They were evolving cultures, differing in values, sensibilities, ways
of experiencing the world and organizing it artistically and intellectually, not simply âmodes of production,â to use Marxâs terminology again. They constituted unique social ecologies, as it were,
that were patterned in highly diverse ways throughout the continent. They also changed with the passage of time in varying degrees and with varying accent or emphasis on their components,
often as a result of their interaction with each other.
Space does not allow me to make a closer examination of thisâ
seemingly âtransitional era,â which in actuality forms a yery definable and long era of European history. That it fits none of the
dogmatic interpretations advanced by many moderni historians
who have an ideological ax to grind says more about academic
trends in contemporary historiography than the richly varied texture of European life over the past thousand years: The âstasisâ to
which Zagorin alludes in his account of the stateâs development
seems also to have occurred in town development during the
fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, possibly even later in many
parts of Europe. Although greatly increased in number, European
towns seem to have entered into a demographic slack period
where urban populations ceased to grow and in some cases diminished. Trade, too, appears to have declined and the development
of new towns generally came to an end.
A number of historians have called this period the âcrisis of
feudalism,â a terminology that may very well express a typically
modern identification of âprogressâ with expansion. This bias
tends to overlook qualitative growth and cultural elaboration for
quantitative growth and cultural change. Apparently, âprogressâ
is to be defined primarily as material growth, the increasing âdomination of nature.â Cultural stability and the elaboration of cultural traits, by contrast, is often conceived as evidence of stagnation,â even of âcrisisâ and social regression. The received wisdom
of historians to the contrary, is it not possible that Europe had
paused during these centuries and begun to live with minimal
changes in the âforce fieldâ of the era, perhaps even reaching a
fairly stable balance between the three components of the mixed
economy that began to develop centuries earlier? That violence,
was endemic at that time, as it generally was before and afterward,
does not alter the stability of everyday life, especially in the small
towns that contained the majority of Europeâs urban population.
This much is reasonably clear: by the seventeenth century, western Europe and its towns seem to haye reached a historic crossroads. The continentâs further âdevelopment,â a term that by no
means denotes âprogressâ in any qualitative sense, was to depend
less on the growth of a centralized state and on the expansion of
commerce than on technologyâon the development of machines
and transportation techniques that were to rework all the traditional ties that had produced such an ecologically extraordinary
cultural, political, civic, and economic diversity of social and urban
forms.[12]
[12] Put bluntly: there was no âtransitionâ from feudalism to capitalism in the simple sense presented by most Marxist and liberal historians and theorists. Nor is
it true to say that capitalism developed âwithin the wombâ of feudalism and then
âemergedâ as a dominant social order through a series of âbourgeois-democratic
revolutionsâ whose âparadigmâ is the French Revolution of 1789â94 (in the view
of some historians, the span of the revolution is expanded to included the Napoleonic era, notably up to 1814!). The remarkably mixed, diversified, and complex
society that is often presented to us as a âtransitional periodâ was, in fact, an era
in its own right that social ecology can describe and interpret more insightfully
than economistic interpretations. We shall see that the view of this remarkable era
as merely âtransitionalâleads to a host of errors, particularly its depiction of the
revolutionary era and its democratic aspirations as âbourgeois,â an imagery that
makes capitalism a system more committed to freedom, or even ordinary civil
liberties, than it was historically.
----
The market society we call âcapitalismââa society that tends to
reduce all, citizens to mere buyers and sellers and debases all the
ecologically varied social relationships produced by history to the
exchange of objects called âcommoditiesââdid not âevolveâ out
of a feudal era. It literally exploded into being in Europe, particularly England, during the eighteenth and especially nineteenth
centuries, although it existed in the ancient world, the Middle
Ages, and with, growing significance in the mixed economy of the
West from the fourteenth century up to the seventeenth. It is still
spreading around the worldâintensively in, its traditional Euro-American center and extensively in the non-European world; Its
forms have varied from the largely mercantile (its earliest kind)
through the industrial (its more recent eighteenth- and nineteenth-century forms) to the statist, corporate, and multinational
forms of our own time. It has slowly penetrated from its special
spheres, such as market arenas of exchange and the production of
commodities in cottages and later in factories, into domestic life
itself, such as the family and neighborhood. This is a fairly recent
âadvanceâ that can be dated most strikingly from the midpoint of
the twentieth century. Its invasion of the neighborhood, indeed of
villages and small towns into the recesses of the domestic or familial relationships, has subverted the social bond itself and threatens
to totally undermine any sense of community and ecological balance and diversity in social life.
Moreover, the newly gained dominance of the capitalistic market relationship over all other forms of production and consociation is a major source of what I have denoted as âurbanizationââthe explosion of the city itself into vast urban agglomerations that
threaten the very integrity of city life and citizenship. What makes
the market society we call âcapitalismâ unique, even by contrast
to its early mercantile form, is that it is an ever-expansive, accumulative, and, in this respect, a cancerous economic system
whose âlaw of lifeâ is to âgrow or die.â Capitalism in its characteristically modern and âdominantâ form threatens not only to undermine every ânatural economyâ (to use Marxâs own terms), be
it small-scale agriculture, artisanship, simple exchange relationships, and the like; it threatens to undermine every dimension of
âorganic society,â be it the kinship tie, communitarian forms of
association, systems of self-governance, and localist allegiancesâthe sense of home and place. Owing to its metastatic invasion of
every aspect of life by means of monetization and what Immanuel
Wallerstein calls âcommodification,â it threatens the integrity of
the natural worldâsoil, flora, fauna, and the complex ecocommunities that have made present-day life forms and relationships
possible by turning everything ânaturalâ into an inorganic, essentially synthetic form.{74} Soil is being turned into sand, variegated
landscapes into level and simplified ones, complex relationships
into more primal forms such that the evolutionary clock is being
turned back to a biotically earlier time when life was less varied
in form and its range more limited in scope.
The effect of capitalism on the city has been nothing less than
catastrophic. The commonly used term âurban cancerâ can be
taken literally to designate the extent to which the traditional *urbs*
of the ancient world have been dissolved into a primal, ever-spreading, and destructive form that threatens to devour city and
countryside alike. Growth in the special form that singles out
modern capitalism from all earlier forms of economic fife, including earlier forms of capitalism itself, has affected what we still
persist in calling the âcityâ by leading to the expansion of pavements, streets, houses, and industrial, commercial, and retail structures over the entire landscape just as a cancer spreads over the
body and invades its deepest recesses.
Cities, in turn, have begun to lose their form as distinctive
cultural and physical entities, as humanly scaled and manageable
political entities. Their functions have changed from ethical
arenas with a uniquely humane, civilized form of consociation,
free of all blood ties and family loyalties, into immense, overbearing, and anonymous marketplaces. They are becoming centers
primarily of mass production and mass consumption, including
culture as well as physically tangible objects. Indeed, culture has
become objectified into commodities as have human relationships,
which are increasingly being simplified and mediated by objects.
The simplification of social life and the biosphere by a growth-oriented economy in which production and consumption become
ends in themselves is yielding the simplification of the human
psyche itself. The strong sense of individuation that marked the
people of the mixed society preceding capitalism is giving way to
a receptive consumer and taxpayer, a passive observer of fife
rather than an active participant in it, lacking in economic roots
that support self-assertiveness and community roots that foster
participation in social life. Citizenship itself, conceived as a function of character formation, and politics, as part of *paideia* or the
education of a social being, tend to wane into personal indifference to social problems. The decline of the citizen, more properly
his or her dissolution into a being lost in a mass societyâthe
human counterpart of the mass-produced objectâis furthered by
a burgeoning of structural gigantism that replaces human scale
and by a growing bureaucracy that replaces all the organic sinews
that held precapitalist society together. The counselor is the humanistic counterpart of the indifferent bureaucrat and the counseling chamber is the structural counterpart of the governmental
office.
Let it be said that this debasement of the ecological complexity
of the city, of its politics, citizens, even of the individuals who
people its streets and structures, is of very recent origin. It did not
really begin in a manorial society, with its barons and serfs, food
cultivators and artisans, and all the âordersâ we denote as feudal.
Nor did it follow from those grossly misnamed revolutions, the
âbourgeois-democraticâ ones of England, America, and France,
that ostensibly catapulted capital into political control of a society
it presumably âcontrolledâ economically during earlier generations. Rather, this development began to appear with technical
innovations that made possible both the mass manufacture of
cheap commodities and, that is crucially important, their increasingly rapid transportation into the, deepest recesses of western
Europe, inexpensive and highly competitive with the products of
local artisans who serviced their localities for centuries. It need
hardly be emphasized that this development depended enormously for its success on the opening of colonial markets abroad:
the Americas, Africa, and particularly Asia, the area where the
English crown found its richest jewel, notably India.
It was the extraordinary combination of technical advances
\yith the existence of a highly variegated society, relatively free of
the cultural constraints to trade that prevailed in antiquity, that
gave economic ascendancy to the capitalistic component of the
mixed economy over all its other components. Neither wealth
from the Americans nor the large monetary resources accumulated by port cities from long-distance trade fully explains
the rise of,industrial capitalismâa form of capitalism that more
than any other penetrated into the very inner life of Europe.[13] Had
the wealth acquired from the âNew Worldâ been a decisive factor
in creating industrial capitalism, Spain rather than England should
have become its center, for it was Spanish cqnquistadores who
initially plundered the Aztec and Inca empires and brought their
precious metals to Europe. The very wealth these âempiresâ provided for the ascendant nation-state in Spain served to weaken
town life in the Iberian peninsula and provide the means for
absolute monarchs to embark on an archaic program of continental empire building that eventually ruined Spanish cities and the countryside alike.
[13] This I believe probably accounts for Karl Marxâs strongly productivist bias in
economic theory over the more consumptionist biases of contemporary economists. Marx, I believe, was quite correct when he pointed out that under capitalism,
at least, it was production that created demand, not demand that created production, although there is an obvious interplay between the two at a surface level of
economic life. Where he was most lacking was in his failure to recognize the
cultural constraints that limited production and profoundly influenced the vulner·
ability of a society to technological innovation. In this respect, ancient society was
always a mystery to him, and its development was often explained in surprisingly
conventional ways.
Nor did long-distance trade provide the most important sources
for capitalizing industrial development. Rather it fostered consumption more than production, the dissolute lifeway that makes
for a diet of luxuries instead of the parsimonious habits that steer
investment into new means of production. Indeed, too much state
centralization and too much commerce, despite the wealth they
initially generated, ultimately led to excessive expenditures for
territorial expansion and high living by elite groups in all the
orders of a courtly society. That nation-building, increased ceritralization, or, more properly, national consolidation prepared the
way for industrial capitalism by opening more âhinterlandsâ to
trade is patently clear. So, too, did increases in the population of
dispossessed, propertyless hands, whether as a result of land enclosures or normal demographic growth, hands that were available
for a factory system that had yet to appear on the economic horizon. Europe, in effect, was more open than any part of the world
to the expansion of its Capitalistâcomponent along industrial lines.
This was especially true of England, a country in which a remarkable balance had emerged between a particularly bourgeois-minded aristocracy and monarchy on the one hand and a very
open economy on the other, peopled by a tight-fisted, god-fearing
Puritan yeomanry and structured around towns with decaying
gild systems and cottagers in the countryside who were already
engaged in a domestic form of textile mass production. Whether
the new industrial capitalists who were destined to totally reshape
the country emerged from the merchants involved in the sale of
raw wool to cottage weavers and its sale in the towns, or whether
it came from well-to-do artisans, yeomen, artistocrats who used
sheep to create a new form of pastoral agribusiness, or merchants
who were inclined to siphon their wealth into productionâpossibly even all of them combined at one time or anotherâneed not
concern us here. What pushed the capitalist component of this
mixed economy into a nation that could regard itself as the âworkshop of the worldâ in the, nineteenth century was a series of inventions that made the factory system and the distribution of its wares possible.
Nor need we be concerned with whether the needs of a ârising
bourgeoisieâ produced the Industrial Revolution or the Industrial
Revolution gave rise to the âbourgeoisie,â which in any case was
always a presence in all the major cities of Europe. Factories, in
fact, had begun to appear in eighteenth- and even seventeenth-century England long before an industrial technology had
emerged. Wherever the âbourgeoisieâ entered into the productive sphere rather than the commercial, it tried to bring labor
together and rationalize output even with tools, hence a strictly
technological interpretation of the *rise* of industrial capitalism
would be greatly misleading. My concern here is how industrial
capitalism managed to gain ascendancy over *other* forms of production, including commercial capitalism, and alter *all* social relationships that encountered its power. Waterwheels had preceded
the steam engine as a prime mover, and worksheds organized
around simple tools had preceded mechanized factories. But without the inventions that introduced the Industrial Revolution in the
late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, it is doubtful that
industrial capitalism could have impacted so powerfully on
Europe and ultimately on the entire world.
England, perhaps more so than other countries in the western
European orbit, seems to have been an ideal terrain for technological innovation. Its society was highly mobile socially and extremely fluid territorially. The few remaining feudal inhibitions to
change of its various elites, aristocratic as well as commercial, had
already been shattered by the civil war of the Cromwell period,
a conflict that brought armed Puritans to power and added a
strongly plebeian character to the countryâs system of government. Even the English aristocracy had been readied for a gainful
capitalistic economy by the wealth it acquired from the sale of
wool. We shall have occasion to note that landed squires and industrial capitalists were not without serious differences over the distribution of manpower in the countryâs economy, nor did the rural
patronal system disappear completely. But it can be said that
England, more than any other European country at the time, had
begun to acclimate itself to industrialization owing to the relative
weakness of absolutism, which might have drained the nationâs
wealth to fulfill imperial ambitions and the growth of a money-minded yeomanry and a highly avaricious merchant class.
One must consult Max Weberâs *The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism* to understand how much gain became a
quasireligious âcallingâ among Englandâs merchants and its well-to-do yeomanry and artisans; how much they were readied psychologically for the plundering of their own communities and
country. The Spanish *conquistadores* had ruthlessly sacked the
Indian âempiresâ of the Aztecs and Inca in order to enrich themselves, not to âsaveâ their âsouls.â They were maniacally involved
in acts of destruction that often verged on self-destruction with
only indirect effects upon the texture of Spanish society. The English Puritans, by contrast, dourly plundered their own country in
a systematic and lasting manner to accumulate capital. Their behavior seemed to be guided by a moral imperative that made
greed an end in itself, an imperative that was to transform the
lifeways of the precapitalist society from which they had derived.
Long after Puritanism had passed away as a movement, English
society had become secularized. The joyless spirit that the Puritans brought to England then lived on, largely bereft of the few
moral constraints that religion generally imposed on the acquisitive spirit engendered by the Reformation.
Within a span of some two generations, England was transformed on a scale unprecedented in the history of western
Europe. Frederick Engelsâs *The Condition of the Working-Class in England*, a period piece based on personal observations in
1844, could justly call the changes introduced by the new industrial inventionsâprincipally in textiles, metallurgy, and transportationâa historic change of unpredented proportions. The rapidity of the transformation is what makes these changes so startling
in a domain of human endeavorâtechnologyâwhich had developed over centuries at a slow, piecemeal pace. The social and
cultural ramifications of this technological revolution were nothing less than monumental. âSixty, eighty years ago, England was
a country like every other,â Engels tells us, âwith small towns, few
and simple industries, and a thin but *proportionately* large agricultural population. Today {1844} it is a country like *no* other, with
a capital of two and a half million inhabitants; with vast manufacturing cities; with an industry that supplies the world, and produces almost everything by means of the most complex machinery; with an industrious, intelligent, dense population, of which
two thirds are employed in trade and commerce, and composed
of classes wholly different, forming, in fact, with other customs and
other needs, a different nation from the England of those days.â{75}
Engelsâs words are meant as much to praise the ârevolutionaryâ
work of the English industrial capitalist as they are intended to
startle the German readers, who first encountered his book. The
Enlightenmentâs uncritical commitment to technical progress
completely infects the authorâs generalizations, however much he
is bitterly critical of, the misery inflicted by,industrial capitalism on
the new proletariat. Accordingly, we learn that the preexisting
cottage weavers, who were to be devastated economically and
culturally by the new textile machines invented around the middle
of the eighteenth century, âvegetated throughout a passably comfortable existence, leading a righteous arid peaceful life in all piety
and probity; and their material position was far better than that of
their successors. They did not have to overwork; they did no more
than they chose to do, and yet earned what they needed: They had
leizure for healthful work in garden or field, work which, in itself,
was recreation for them, and they could take part besides in the
recreations and games of their neighbours, and all gamesâbowling, cricket, football, etc., contributed to their physical health and
vigour. They were, for the most part, strong, well-built people, in
whose physique little or no difference than that,of their peasant
neighbours was discernable. Their children grew up in the fresh
country air, and, if they could help their parents at work, it was only
occasionally; while of eight or twelve hours work for them [introduced, later, by the factory system] there was no question.â{76}
The mixed messages in this passage reflect the characteristic
tension created among the âprogressivesâ of the era between the,
claims of an abstract sense of âhistoryâ and an existential sense of
humanity that was to rend apart major socialists such as Engels
and ultimately, owing to his commitment to industrial progress
as a âpreconditionâ for a free society, justify the most horrible
barbarities of a Stalin as the âmodernizerâ of Russia, The unquestioning humilityâ of the English cottage weavers and yeomen,
âtheir silent vegetation ... which, cosily romantic as it was, was
nevertheless not worthy of human beings,â to use Engelsâ pejorative remarks, is doubtful on its own terms, particularly from the
standpoint of our own time when the ebullient concept of â progressâ that prevailed over the past two centuries is so much in
doubt.[14]{77} But placed in a broader historical context, it is hard to
square this denigration of the cottage weavers and lesser yeomanry with their vigorous role in the English Civil War of the
1640s and their resistance to the introduction of machineryâindeed, the role they played in theâ Chartist movement, the most
radical cause, culturally as well as economically, that England has
seen since the Puritan revolution.
[14] That Engelsâs commitment to a harsh concept of technological progress, indeed, the whole Marxist theory of âhistorical materialism,â was meant to slap not
only the face of philosophical idealism but also of the high spirit of European
romanticism is an issue that has yet to be fully explored. Gray became a favorite
color of Marxian socialism as part of its deliberate endeavor to disenchant the world and relegate the past, with all its humane as well as barbarous traditions, to a
historical âjunk heap.â Eventually socialism, like Puritanism, was to be deprived
of all its ethical content and turned into a doctrine very much like the egoistic
political economy of the industrial bourgeoisie itself.
The explosive nature of the Industrial Revolution and the emergence of industrial capitalism can best be understood by rioting
the limited time span in which the new technology surfaced and
swept over Englandâa period so brief that it is almost difficult to
call it an âera,â as so many historians do. James Wattâs steam
engine, which freed the factory system from its reliance on waterpower, was invented by 1769; James Hargreavesâ spinning jenny,
which enormously increased the output of yarn, by 1764; Richard
Arkwrightâs throstle, a sophistication of the spinning machine calculated for the use of a mechanical prime mover, by 1767; Samuel
Cromptonâs mule, by 1785, followed around the same time by
Arkwrightâs carding machine and preparatory frames; finally, Edmund Cartwrightâs workable power loom by 1785. All of these
inventions totally revolutionized the production of textiles as it
had been pursued for thousands of years and catapulted English
cottons, woolens, linens, even lace and silken goods (as a result of
another group of machines invented in the first decade of the
nineteenth century) into a largely agrarian domestic and world
market. The opening of extensive coalfields and iron mines, owing
in large part to the use of coke, and the staggering enlargement
of smelting furnaces on a scale fifty times bigger than earlier, more
customary sizes paved the way for transportation changes that
were to open the most remote areas of the country to industrialization and âcommodification.â
The men who invented the textile machines and prime movers
that powered them were plebeians and, by no means accidentally
within the context of modern English history, included a sprinkling of very pious individuals, even clergymen. Watt was an instrument maker; Hargreaves, an engineer; Arkwright, a barber;
and relegate the past, with all its humane as well as barbarous traditions, to a
historical âjunk heap.â Eventually socialism, like Puritanism, was to be deprived
of all its ethical content and turned into a doctrine very much like the egoistic
political economy of the industrial bourgeoisie itself.
Crompton, an ordinary textile worker; and Cartwright, a minister,
who went on to work with Robert Fulton in the development of
the steamship. English society had opened itself, more than most
European societies, to advancement by individuals in the âlower
classes/â Moreover, many of the inventors whose work introduced
the Industrial Age were to become major capitalists in their right.
Only a few exhibited the breadth of spirit that characterized Robert Owen, a textile manufacturer who demonstrated at New Lanark that relatively humane conditions for workers did not conflict
with the acquisition of high profits and later placed his life and his
fortune in the service of the rising labor movement.
The transportation revolution that paralleled the Industrial
Revolution is of monumental proportions in the development of
modern capitalism itself, a revolution that a century and a half
later was to turn into a âcommunications revolutionâ whose
effects have yet to be fully grasped. During the first forty years of
the nineteenth century, Scotland, much of which had been an
untamed âhinterlandâ only two generations earlier, was interlaced by nearly a thousand miles of good roads and an even larger
number of bridges. This was largely âthe work of private enterprise,â Engels tells us, âthe State having done very little in this
direction.â{78} Indeed by 1844 England, apart from Scotland, had
well over two thousand miles of canals, substantially in excess of
its navigable river mileage. Finally, the early railroad fines that
finked Manchester to Liverpool, were rapidly extended across the
entire industrial midlands, sweeping in Lancester, Sheffield,
Leeds, Newcastle, and, of course, London further to the south.
English industrial and commercial towns, too, exploded in sifee
and population. Within the first thirty or forty years of the nineteenth century, Birmingham increased its inhabitants from 73,000
to 200,000; Sheffield from 46,000 to 110,000; Halifax from 63,000
to 110,000; Leeds from 53,000 to 123,000. Such astonishing rates
of growth among comparatively small communities in so short a
time had never been seen before in European history. The congestion and diseases they produced have been fully chronicled in the
novels as well as the histories of the period. For the first time, apart
from a few cosmopolitan centers in antiquity and perhaps some
Flemish and Italian towns in medieval times, we begin to see the
authentic devouring of cities, not only the countryside, by urbanization. Birmingham, Sheffield, Halifax, and Leeds, among many
others in England, were beginning to lose their identity as cities
in any classical meaning of the term. Their factories, sprawling out
into the countryside, were phasing into urban agglomerations,
sweeping in villages and small towns that had existed with relatively little change for centuries. William Wyldeâs panoramic
painting of Manchester in 1851 reveals a forest of smokestacks and
a dense collection of squalid dwellings, a new, formless, and repellent urban world that industrial capital began to introduce into the
worldâfirst in England, then in France, Belgium, Germany, and,
of course, across the Atlantic where the grimmest images of Pittsburgh as a steel-making center seem interchangeable with
Wyldeâs picture of Manchester as a textile center generations earlier.
Yet, what is very important about this period of rampant industrialization is the fact that the more commercial and administrative cities of England and even the industrial towns that blighted
the islandâs landscape were to develop a communal character of
their own. Growing industry, commerce, and âcommodificationâ
did not seep completely into the neighborhood fife of the new
cities, nor did it totally destroy the conditions for the regeneration
of domestic fife. The buffeting that towns and cities of the nineteenth century took from industrialization, however disastrous its
initial effects on traditional fife ways, did not destroy the inherently villagelike subcultures of workers and middle-class people
who were only a generation or two removed from a more rural
culture. Like the ethnic groups that entered the New World
through New York City throughout much of the nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries, displacement was followed by resettlement and recommunafization, even in the most desperately poor
slums of the overpopulated cities of Europe and America. The pub
in the industrial cities of England, the cafe in France, and the beer
hall in Germany, no less than the various community centers
around which the ethnic ghettos formed in New York and other
American cities, provided foci for a distinctly working-class culture, largely artisan in its outlook, class-oriented in its politics, and knitted together by mutual self-help groups.
This recolonization of community life was greatly abetted by
the organized labor movement in all its different forms. Socialist
clubs, trade-union centers, local cooperatives, mutual-aid societies, and educational groups created a public space that included
classes in reading, writing, literature, and history. The socialist
clubs and union centers provided libraries, periodicals, lectures,
and discussion groups to âelevateâ worker consciousness as well as
mobilize them for political and economic ends. Picnics, athletic
activities, outdoor forays into the countryside served to add a very
intimate dimension to purely educational projects. The *casas del pueblo* established by Spanish socialists and the *centros obreros*
established by the Spanish anarchists, which existed up to the late
1930s, are reminders of the vigorous development of community
life even in the most depressed areas of Europeâindeed, of an
âundergroundâ culture that always paralleled the received culture of the elite orders and classes.
There was always a plebeian cultural domain at the base of
society, even in the most dismal and squalid parts of ancient,
medieval, or modern cities, that was beyond the reach of the
conventional culture and the state apparatus. No economy or state
had the technical means, until very recently, to freely infiltrate
this domain and dissolve it for a lasting period of time. Left to
itself, the âundergroundâ world of the oppressed remained a
breeding ground for rebels and conspirators against the prevailing
authority. No less urban in character than agrarian, it also remained a school for a grass-roots politics that, by definition, involved groups of ordinary people, even in sizable communities, in
a plebeian political sphere and often brought them into outright
rebellion. This âundergroundâ school created new political forms
and new citizens to deal with changing social conditions. Even
after the great boulevards of Baron Haussmanri ripped into the
plebeian *quartiers* of Paris, opening the city to artillery fire and
cavalry charges against barricades, the sizable neighborhood
pockets left behind retained an imperturbable rebellious vitality
that finally culminated in the Paris Commune. Few of Europeâs
major cities were spared crowd actions and uprisings in the nineteenth century, indeed well into the first half of the twentieth. As
industrial capitalism spread out from England into western
Europe and America, the initial destabilization it produced as a
result of urbanization and mechanization was followed by a regeneration of popular culture along new patterns that also included
the integration of old ones. Just as the French village was reproduced as *quartiers* in French cities and the Spanish *pueblo* as
and âLittle Irelandsâ were reproduced in altered form but with
much Of their cultural flavor, personal intimacies, and traditional
values in world cities such as New York. Even the industrial cities
replicated on a local basis the specific cultural origins of their
variegated populations and regions.
The elaboration of the Industrial Revolution into a textile economy in England, a luxury goods economy in France, an electrochemical economy in Germany (itself a second industrial revolution in the last half of the nineteenth century), and an automotive
economy in America did not eliminate this âundergroundâ communal world. Which is not to say that any of the countries cited
above did not also, expand economically and technologically into
the key industries that distinguished each from the other. But the
textile manufacturing that catapulted England into the world
market and even helped to make it; the fashioning of luxury goods
that gaye France, especially Paris, its distinction as the artistic
center of the world; and the mass production of electrochemical
commodities and automobiles by Germany and the United States,
respectively, which finally began to transform the world into its
present formâall seemed to carry over into the popular culture
and give it specific national features. We find a fixidity in England
along industrial lines that appears in its conventional and underground cultures as well: a strong systemâof orders, open enough
to add titles to the names of its gifted plebeians but consciously
hierarchical in its cultural and social structure with a tendency to.
retain social status and elaborate it along stable lines. The intellectuality of France, expressed by its esthetic emphasis in industrial
production, carried over into the popular culture as a discursive
politics that nourished an ideologically innovative working class,
largely ar tisanal in its outlook but with all the intellectuality of that
stratum. Germany, which seems to have straddled the hierarchical
culture of England and the intellectual culture of France, gave rise
to a philosophically inclined popular Culture that took pride in its
academic spokesmen as surely as English workers were endeared
to noblemen who often spoke on their behalf. The pragmatism
and dynamism of American culture, with its strong republican
values, carried into the popular culture as various images of the
âAmerican Dream,â partly utopian, partly materialistic, in which
the automobile symbolized enhanced sexuality together with freedom of movement, both socially upward and territorially outward.
This symbolism was to shape American architecture and city planning by producing the first skyscrapers and the most sprawling,
homogeneous âcitiesâ of the twentieth century, even if one includes London.
Yet every class culture was always a community culture, indeed
a civic cultureâa fact that finks the period of the Industrial Revolution and its urban forms with precapitalist cultures of the past.
This continuity has been largely overlooked by contemporary socialists and sociologists. While the factory and mill formed the first
fine of the class struggle in the last century, a struggle that in no
way should be confused with the class war that is supposed to yield
working-class insurrections, its fines of supply reached back into
the neighborhood and towns where workers lived and often mingled with middle-class people, farmers, and intellectuals. Wage
earners had human faces, not merely mystified proletarian
faces, and functioned no less as human beings than class beings.
Accordingly, they were fathers and mothers, brothers and sisters,
sons and daughters, citizens and neighbors, not only âfactory
hands.â Their concerns included issues such as war and peace,
environmental dislocation, educational opportunities, the beauty
of their surroundings as well as its ugliness, and in times of international conflict, a heavy dose of jingoism and nationalismâindeed
a vast host of problems and concerns that were broadly human,
not only class-oriented and rooted in wages and working conditions.
This communal dimension of the industrial era is of tremendous
importance in understanding how class conflicts often spilled over
beyond economic issues into broadly social, even utopian, concerns. Indeed as long as the market did not dissolve the communal
dimension of industrialism, there was a richly fecund, highly
diversified, cooperative, and innovative domain of social and political fife to which the proletariat could retreat after working hours,
a domain that retained a vital continuity with precapitalist fife-ways and values. This partly municipal, partly domestic domain
formed a strong countervailing force to the impact of an industrial
economy and the nation-state. Here, workers mingled with a great
variety of individuals, particularly artisans, intellectuals, and farmers who brought their produce into the towns. In a purely human
fashion that revealed all the facets of their personalities, they
developed a sense of shared, active citizenship. This communal or
municipal citizenship kept political fife alive even in highly centralized and bureaucratized nation-states. It would be difficult to
understand not only the radical uprisings of the nineteenth century but also the twentiethâparticularly the series of urban and
agrarian uprisings that culminated in the Spanish Civil Warâwithout keeping this communal dimension of the âclass struggleâ
clearly in mind. Every class movement from the late eighteenth
to the early twentieth centuries was also a civic movement, a
product of neighborhood, town, and village consociation, not only
the factory, farm, and office. It was not until a technology developed that could make deep, perhaps decisive, inroads into this
âundergroundâ municipal domain that politics and citizenship
were faced with the total âcommodificationâ of society, the supremacy of statecraft, and the subversion of the cityâs ecological
diversity and creativity.
----
The older generation of our time is still too close to the present and
the younger too far from the past to realize the extent to which
communal, precapitalist cultural traditions permeated the first
half of the twentieth century. Nor do we fully realize how rapidly
these traditions are being simplified and the extent to which they
are disappearing in the second half of the century, largely as a
result of sweeping technological and cultural developments that
occurred during the Second World War and its aftermath. Science
systematically applied to technics has only recently revealed the
deepest secrets of matter and fife with nucleonics and bioengineering. We are just making contact with the possibilities opened
by cybernetics, space travel, and communications systems for public surveillance, not to speak of mass âmind bendingâ with techniques that will make conventional advertising methods seem
childish and means of detection that will make fingerprints seem
primitive.
The psychological implications of these chilling advances are as
significant as their cultural and institutional ones. The military
armamentorium they have produced is as disempowering to the
individual as it is frightening to the public. The result is that the
ego itself tends to become passive, disembodied, and introverted
in the face of a technological and bureaucratic gigantism unprecedented, indeed unimaginable, in earlier human history. Public
life, already buffeted by techniques for engineering public consent, tends to dissolve into private life, a form of mere survivalism
that can easily take highly sinister forms. Citizenship, in turn,
tends to retreat into an increasingly trivialized egoism in which
banal conversation and venal pursuits replace searching discourse
and rebellious demands. Even more than ordinary individuals, the
people of mind and art who formed for ages the troubled conscience of past societies and were deeply engaged in public life as
the principal catalysts for achieving the good societyâin short,
those socially involved thinkers whom the Russians of the last
century called the *intelligentsia*âretreat into the confines of the
academy and are transformed into mere intellectuals. Research
tends to replace creative speculation; libraries tend to replace the
cafes that nourished a Diderot; classrooms replace the squares that
brought a Desmoulins to the surface of public life; the academic
conference and its journals replace the clubs and presses that
provided the public forum for a Thomas Paine.
Industrial capitalism in the nineteenth century treated a market economy in which production and exchange still formed a
layer;of social life, not a substitute for society. The âcash nexusâ
that Marx and Engels regarded as the core of the new economy
in *The Communist Manifesto*âculturally as well as commerciallyâwas evidence more of their foresight than a description of the f
actual conditions of their times. Important barriers stood between
the penetration of the âcash nexusâ created by the factory and by
commerce into the community and domestic life, where the oppressed in all their different forms and even the agrarian squirearchy seethed with hatred of the new economy. The Speenhamland Law, which English country squires passed in the 1790s to
provide the material means for keeping the rural population out
of the emerging factory system, reveals the stronghold precapitalist patronal traditions had on a society in the very midst of the Industrial Revolution.
What is Unique about the post-World War II era, now unfolding
four decades after tbe warâs end, is that the market *economy* to
which industrial capitalism gave a firm and dominant productive
base is turning into a *market society*. The âcash nexusâ has become
an all-embracing commodity nexus in which consumption, not
only production, has become an end in itself. Objects now mediate
nearly all the social relationships that once had a living and creative flesh-and-blood character. Popular culture, which meant the
disdained culture produced from below by the people, has now
become âpop culture,â the synthetic âcultureâ generated from
above by the mass manufacture of books, sounds, pictures, movies,
radio shows, and, above all, television âgoodiesââfrom news to
situation comedies, soap operas, and even serialized novels that
transfix millions of viewers to their âtubes.â Human relationships
are increasingly defined in terms of material things and expressed
in a commercial vernacularâbe it marriage as an âinvestment,â
child rearing as a âjob,â life as a âbalance sheet,â ideals as things
one âbuys,â and community as a âbusiness.â The notion that towns
and cities should be âmanagedâ by âentrepreneursâ as though the
civic bond has no dimensions to it other than its âefficiencyâ in
coordinating âservicesâ and its capacity for generating ârevenuesâ permeates the language not only of bankers, merchants,
politicians, and retailers but even liberal andâmost tellinglyâsocialist public officials. Social life, so conceived and lived in the
form of marriage, child rearing, education, friendship, conviviality, entertainment, culture, and values, reveals a degree of commodity penetration and commercialism unprecedented even in
the halcyon days of âfree tradeâ and capitalist production.
Which is not to say that the period following the Second World
War did not have its preludes in the pre-war era. Technologically,
the radio and particularly the cinema had a strong grip on popular
culture throughout the twenties and thirties. The automobile and
the vast economy created were already part of American life well
before the outbreak of the war. Mercifully, the Great Depression
of the 1930s froze this development for a decade, and the war
aborted it for an added five years while the world reverted to the
barbarism of organized slaughter and urban demolition. The assembly line was a portent of what was soon to come as was the
increasing wedding of science to technology, which the war put
on a thoroughly systematic basis.
But there was much that these pre-war preludes to the post-war
era left untouched. The Depression had given a bad name to
capitalism and placed its legitimacy in grave doubt. This loss of
faith stimulated a sweeping drift toward cultural and social movements that challenged the systemâs integrity and claims to meet
human needs. Agrarian life still had a strong base in American and
French society, even as depression foreclosures reduced its economic significance. As late as 1929, twenty-five percent of the
employed labor force in the United States owned or worked labor-intensive farms that had changed very little from the last century.
Approximately three-fourths of American agricultural produce
was sold at home. Although tractors were beginning to appear in
growing numbers, horses were still in wide use and kerosene was
still a major fuel for illuminating farm homes. Culturally, agrarian
values were very much alive in America. They were embodied in
the high proportion of immigrants from the villages of eastern
Europe, Italy, and Ireland, and in the yeoman farmers who were
being scattered throughout the continent by the dust storms that
swept over middle America.
The Depression, in fact, witnessed a remarkable regeneration
of precapitalist agrarian values. The end of the First World War
had seen a cultural mystification of urbanism and substantial migrations of young people from rural areas to cities. Songs such as
âHow Can You Keep Them Down on the Farm After Theyâve
Seen âPar-ee!â â typified a glorification of urban lifestyles in the
1920s. The rural âhick,â once conceived as the source of Americaâs
sturdy republican values and the âpioneerâ of continental settlement, had become a caricature in the cartoons, literature, and
cinema of the twenties, a âcountry-cousinâ bumpkin who would
do well to conceal his identity in the âbig city.â This remarkable
change in the historical imagery of Americans reflected the ascendancy of the industrial city and the modern age over the small town and the Jeffersonian ageâin short, the cosmopolitan capitalistic era over the parochial precapitalist era.
The Depression decade reversed this imagery dramatically. For
millions of unemployed or economically uncertain Americans,
capitalism was patently not a working system. For all the hoopla
about the decline of socialism as a movement from its high point
in the period immediately preceding the First World War, it is
worth recalling that Norman Thomas, the presumed heir of Eugene V. Debs, received 900,000 votes in 1932 as the Socialist
Partyâs presidential candidate, a figure that comes very close to
Debsâs highest vote some fifteen years earlier. The Depression
reversed the migration from farm to city, at least until the dust
storms of later years drove many farmers to other parts of the
country. Rural culture also began to thrive in the mass media of
the decade, particularly as an evocation of community values,
mutual aid, and compassion for less fortunate people. The extraordinary degree of social vitality that marked the 1930s stands in
marked contrast to the socially devitalizing selfishness of the
1920s, which celebrated Calvin Coolidgeâs maxim: âAmericaâs
business is businessââand, one might reasonably add, let morality
go to the devil. Social justice, not personal venality, rings through
the thirties as the motif of the radical left and radical right. Indeed,
for much of the political spectrum, the business ethic was relegated to damnation together with the values of the twenties,
which to many Americans had brought on the crises of the thirties.
Characteristically, the cinematic foppery of the twenties and
early thirties began to give way to movies that focused on such
themes as poverty, unionism, justice, and the pristine values of
agrarian lifeways. Even where capitalists are shown in a benign
light, such as in *The Devil and Miss Jones*, businessmen were seen
as converts to the new humanitarianism and the high sense of
public responsibility that marked the decade. Others, like
precapitalist rural values and vilified the rich, hypostasizing the
face-to-face simplicity and high moral sense of the small town. The
rural community was set ethically against the spiritual poverty and
cynicism of the city. A cultural populism swept over America after
1935 that has no parallel with any time before the 1890s, one that
gave to community, public service, political idealism, and social
justice a premium that makes the decade unique in twentieth-century American history.
To a leftist of the 1930s, it seemed that industrial capitalism had
reached its economic, social, and cultural limits; that from an ascending society, it had begun to descend historically, just as feudalism did centuries earlier. The Depression held on doggedly up
to the Second World War; indeed, in the judgement of some
economists, the closing years of the thirties appeared to be drifting
into a new economic crisis comparable to or worse than the one
that had darkened the decadeâs opening years. Technological advance, saddled by the inertial weight of an increasingly monopolistic economy, seemed to have come to a virtual end. The monographs of the Temporary National Economic Committee of the
late thirties, established to assess the growth and effects of business
concentration in the United States, were filled with citations of
technological stagnation, indeed the suppression of technical innovations that made for higher productivity and lower prices.
That these innovations, seen as a source of economic instability
and oligarchic control, had been generally arrested wasâ cited by
the literature of the time as evidence of a âdeclineâ of capitalism
itself and as proof of the Marxian thesis that âbourgeois social
relationsâ stood in a âhistorical contradictionâ to the âmode of
production.â Capitalism, it was argued by liberals and leftists alike,
was incapable of furthering the âproductive forcesâ of society and could no longer play a âhistorically progressiveâ role.
Yet there were also harbingers of significant tendencies counteractive to the radical analyses that marked the decade. Rural
electrification was to basically alter the traditional agrarian life-ways that the Depression decade celebrated. It brought the radio
into the home and exposed a socially pristine population to the
mass media. The spate of public works that marked the Roosevelt
era opened roads into the remaining hinterlands of the continent
and the automobile culture improved existing roads for engine-powered vehicles. The great federal highway system of a later
generation was to give, the *coup de grĂące* to regional isolation and
network the entire country with a remarkable road system that all
but obliterated centuries-old cultural variations and customs. Distance and time were being overcome by the internal combustion
engine, whether by rail, road, or air.
Finally, the need for state intervention into a failing âfree enterpriseâ economy vastly strengthened the nation-state and enlarged its bureaucratic apparatus. Rural life, however much it was
celebrated culturally, was being locked into urban life and the city
increasingly placed in a position subordinate to the nation-state.
Business, too, was becoming concentrated and centralized. By
1929, nearly half of American industrial wealth was controlled by
200 large corporations and by 1932, despite the ravages of the
Depressionâor perhaps because of themâ600 corporations controlled nearly two-thirds of the countryâs industrial economy.
Politically and economically, power was to concentrate and centralize into fewer hands, linked together by an endless number of
bureaus, bureaucrats, and shared interests that were to prepare
the way for the âtechnobureaucraticâ nation-state so characteristic of our own time.
The Second World War, while holding the values of die thirties
somewhat in place during the first half of the forties, foisted another Industrial Revolution on western society whose scope, as we
are now beginning to see, rivals the shift of humanity from a
hunting-gathering society to an agricultural one. By 1946, the
technical basis had been created for a world that men and women
of the thirties could never have anticipated. Electronics, nuclear
power, giant strides in biochemical research, and the sophistication of rocket propulsion, not to speak of less visible but monumental advances in physics, chemistry, and biology that were tb yield
revolutionary applications of scientific knowledge to industry,
were to totally change the economic landscape. Political change
for âtotal warâ had already given rise in Europe to a new phenomenon in the westâthe totalitarian stateâbeside which royal absolutism seems in retrospect like a feeble thing. The population
dislocations created by military mobilization as well as war refugees, followed by the expansion of migration of industry to the
western United States, and the pouring of billions into European
reconstruction, vastly transformed the urban landscape. Los Angeles, a âsmallâ city in the thirties by present-day standards, became the âparadigmâ for unlimited, unplanned, and sprawling
urbanization with its individual anomie, and a predatory form of
capitalistic enterprise that overshadowed the âRoaring Twenties,â
with its naive imagery of personal greed and vice. The fifties
introduced a more anonymous and faceless phenomenon: corporate greed and commercialized vice, the marketing of managerialism and suburban self-indulgence (material as well as sexual) as a
new way of life and a new set of values.
Cities were to lose not only their territorial form; they were to
to lose their cultural integrity and uniqueness.
managerial bureaucratism, despite the movieâs tribute to suburban family fife. Social justice, idealism, and agrarian values of
community gave way to privatization, self-indulgence, and suburban cookouts. The desiderata of a corporate age, its synthetic and
highly personalized culture, was a sanitized and socially vacuous
world, held together not by the âundergroundâ culture of past
centuries but by an âabove-groundâ culture engineered by government and corporations. A mass society, notable for its de-spiritualized and amoral version of âpossessive individualismâ had
emerged from the debris of the thirties, a mass society structured
around television networks, counseling offices, bureaucratic agencies, and, above all, commodities. The market society had begun
to come into its own, destructuring the city, the domestic world,
the psyche, and ultimately the natural world. âMan,â brought into
collision with âmanâ in a highly competitive world mediated by
commodities, was finally brought into collision with nature on a
scale unprecedented in history.
Urbanization may be taken as the symbol and the reality of this
historic ecological disarray of the modern landscapeâindeed this
reversal of the evolutionary clockâfrom organic to synthetic
human and biotic relationships. Nor can this disarray be sorted out
and pieced together on the summits of social fife. Historically, the
power of preindustrial fifeways to survive and preserve a moral
sense of social fife depended on the existence of an âundergroundâ
culture in towns, neighborhoods, and citiesâeven during the stormiest periods of nation-building, industrialization, and âcommodificationââto countervail the power of the market and the
official culture. They depended, in effect, upon the power of a
popular culture to resist the elite culture and, in no small part, on
the inability of the elite culture to successfully penetrate the popular one. The crisis of our time as expressed in the decline of political fife and citizenship, of community and individuality in the
classical sense of these concepts, stems from the invasion and
colonization of cultureâs subterranean domain by a highly metastatic capitalistic technics and its commodities. Objectified and
fragmented, the social bond itself faces dissolution. What we call
the âgrassrootsâ of society is turning into straw, and its soilâthe
locality or municipalityâis turning into sand. Whatever evidence
of âfertilityâ and âfifeâ these roots exhibit seems to be the result
of toxic chemicalsâmass media, bureaucratic sinews, and
managerial controlsâthe nation-state and corporations seem to be
pouring into its bedrock, just as agribusiness generates âfoodâ out
of the chemically saturated sponge we call âsoilâ today.
Redemption must come from below, from the municipal level
where the âundergroundâ culture of past times flourished, not
from an âaboveâ that constitutes the very source of the problems
we face. The âlong march through the institutions,â which sixties
radicals such as Rudi Dutschke advocated in Germany and Herbert Marcuse evoked in America more than a decade ago, has
demonstrated that it is the institutions that ultimately absorb modern rebels, not the rebels who capture the institutions.
Urbanization, insofar as it still permits the city to retain any
identity, alters not only its form but its function as a civilizing
arena for humanity. The âstrangerâ who could once find a home
in the city and a role in its political fife as a citizen atavistically
reverts to his or her status as an alien. Ghettoization moves hand
in hand with urban sprawl, the dissolution of the self hand in hand
with the cityâs dissolution. Bureaucracy fills the vacuum created by
the absence of an active community fife, notably the police officer
who is the last custodian of order in disintegrating neighborhoods
and the social worker who is the last custodian of order in domestic
life. Critically viewed, the social ecology of urbanization is theâ
compelling story of the destructuring of all social life from home
to community, the erosion of heterogeneity, interaction, and civic
creativity. The return of the stranger expresses the change from
the âlonely crowd,â explored by David Reisman three decades ago
in his book of same nameâindeed, to, the fearful crowd of today,
a crowd in which everyone moves guardedly through the modern
city with a sense of subdued dread toward surrounding people and
unfamiliar neighborhoods. As urbanization spreads, so too does
the state machinery needed to administer it. Whatever its form,
the nation : state increasingly approximates a totalitarian state and
the privatized individual, riddled by egoism and fear, increasingly
becomes more like one commodity among many rather than a
consumer. Ultimately, society threatens to become as inorganic as
an ecosystem that has been divested of its flora and fauna. When
totalitarianism eventually does emerge, it is likely that the coherent self, so direly needed to resist it, will have undergone such erosion that it may well lack the psychological resources to recognize the danger, much less oppose it.
From the moment nomadic hunter-gatherers began to settle down
into stable villages, they introduced radically new changes that go
beyond the turnâfrom food gathering to food cultivation. Where
villages became towns, human beings began to âdetribalizeâ
themselves, and create those civic institutions we associate with
âcivilization/â The blood tie, the male-female divisions in functions, and status groups based on age formed the sinews of tribalism and were slowly absorbed into an entirely new social dispensation: the city. Cities were to be structured primarily around
residence, a vocational division of labor, and a variety of âordersâ
and classes, some of which were united by economic interests but
others by power and prestige. The biological facts of blood, sex,
and age, in effect, began to slowly phase into the social facts of
propinquity, Vocation, wealth, and privilege.
Out of this sweeping historical transformation, new ways of
ordering life began to emerge. The biological realm of life, seemingly ânaturalâ in its origins, became what we normally regard as
the social: the realm in which people formed to meet their material needs, to reproduce as well as produce, to ârelateâ with each
other as individuals and family groups, to fraternize in a variety
of personal associations and degrees of intimacy. The town and
city, even the village, provided a political realm of life, human-made in origins, in which individuals related to each other as
citizens in order to manage their communities and cope with its
âcivicâ affairs. Until comparatively recent times, to be sure, âbiologicalâ and political realms overlapped significantly so that political elites such as aristocracies legitimated their authority over
towns and cities by the highly tribalistic claims of ancestry and
genealogy. Until the Emperor Caracalla made all free men in the
Roman Empire citizens of the state, citizenship was largely regarded as an ancestral privilege. The rights it conferred to citizens
in the management of the community were marked by various
degrees of ethnic exclusivity.
But the city, initially the Hellenic *polis*, created a new social
dispensation: minimally, a territorial space in which the âstrangerâ or âalienâ could reside with a reasonable degree of protectionâlater even a measure of participationâthat few tribal communities allowed to outsiders, however hospitably they were treated.
Two new civilizatory categoriesâpolitics and citizenshipâbegan
to absorb the largely biosocial forms that held early familial and
tribal lifeways together.
The professionalization of power and violence that we associate
with the state came much later. Indeed, in its national form it is
a fairly recent phenomenon. State and the practice of statecraft
has no authentic basis in community lifeâby which I mean that,
until recently, the acquisition of power by professionals encountered the greatest difficulty in legitimating itself. Tribal institutions can be easily understood because human beings are, after all,
natural organisms. They must feed themselves, acquire their
means of subsistence, reproduce, live in safety, and, given their
evolution as primates, engage in some kind of communal intercourse. In contradistinction to other animals, however, they organize these activities into institutions and make them operationally
systematicâhopefully rational, predictable, and ideologically legitimate. Animals, including the genetically programmed âsocial
insects,â do not have institutions, however habituated and predictable their behavior may be; in short, they do not have consciously
formed ways of ordering their communities that are continually
subject to historical change.
It is important to distinguish the social in humanity from the
political and, still further, the political from the statist. We have
created a terrible muddle by confusing the three and thereby
legitimating one by mingling it with the other. This confusion has
serious consequences for the present and future. We have lost our
sense of what it means to be political by assigning political functions and prerogatives to âpoliticians,â actually to a select, often
elite, group of people who practice a form of institutional manipulation called statecraft. Inasmuch as many politicians are viewed
with a certain measure of contempt, we have degraded the concept of politicsâonce a participatory dimension of societal life and
the activity of an entire communityâby confusing it with statecraft, a distinctly power-oriented form of activity. Accordingly, we
have lost our sense of what it means to be a citizen, a status we
increasingly accept as mere âconstituentsâ or, worse, voters and
taxpayers who are the passive recipients of the goods and services
provided to us by an all-powerful state and our âelectedâ representatives.
Ideologically, we tend to justify this historical degradation of
our status as political beings by invoking the ânationâ as the basic
and most elemental unit of social life, an entity that is itself of very
recent origin. That nations are made up of cities, towns, and villages on which our well-being, culture, and security ultimately
depend has begun to elude us and slip from our consciousness. It
remains a lasting contribution of Jane Jacobs to have demonstrated
in a very compelling way that our economic well-being depends
on cities, not on nation-states; indeed that while nations may be
âpolitical and military entities it doesnât necessarily follow from
this that they are also the basic, salient entities of economic life or
that they are particularly useful for probing the mysteries of economic structure, the reasons for rise and decline of wealth.... We
canât avoid seeing, too, that among all the various types of economies, cities are unique in their abilities to shape and reshape the
economies of other settlements, including those far removed from
them geographically.â{79} We may leave aside Jacobsâs conventional
use of such words as politics, her imagery of the economy as a
strictly market, indeed, a capitalistic economy, and her strongly
economistic interpretation of cities primarily as centers of production and exchange. Her argument invites a debate about the
superfluity of the state that has been too long neglected, and her
examples can only be ignored for the most dubious ideological
reasons.
A close reading of history has demonstrated that the stateâand,
in our own time, the nation-stateâis not only the repository of
agents and institutions that have made a mockery of politics; it
shows, in fact,â that these state agents and institutions have degraded the individual as a public being, as a citizen who plays a
â participatory role in the operations of his or her community. In
this respect, the nation-state has impeded the development of
much that is uniquely human in human beings^ disempowering
the individual and rendering him or her a warped and self-degraded being. â
It is equally demonstrable that the stateâand, again, the nation-stateâparasitizes the community, denuding it of its resources
and its potential for development. It does this partly by draining
the community of its material and spiritual resources; partly, too,
by steadily divesting it of the power, indeed of its legitimate right,
to shape its own destiny. Despite recent rhetoric to the contrary,
nothing has seemed more challenging to the state than demands
for local self-management and civic liberty. Decentralization, a
term that is often abused these days for the most cynical ends of
statecraft, is not merely rich in geographic, territorial, and political values; it is eminently a spiritual and cultural value that links
the reempowerment of the community with the reempowerment
of the individual.
Municipal freedom, in short, is the basis for political freedom
and political freedom is the basis for individual freedomâa recovery of a new participatory politics structured around free, self-empowered, and active citizens. For centuries, the city was the
public sphere for politics and citizenship, and in many areas the
principal source of resistance to the encroachment of the nation-state. In its acts of defiance it often delayed the development of
the nation-state and created remarkable forms of association to
counteract the stateâs encroachment upon municipal freedom and
individual liberties.
----
The case for the nation-state today is almost entirely logistical and
administrative. Social life, we are normally told, is too âcomplexâ
to allow for municipal autonomy and participatory citizenship.
This argument does not stand up very well against historical and
contemporary evidence. Fascinating examples can be found of
economic and political coordination within and between communities that render statecraft and the nation-state utterly superfluous.
Aside from Hellenic, Italian, medieval German, and Castilian
endeavors, one of the most lasting are the Swiss communes whose
practice of using local resources without turning them into private
property was to be an object of fascination for generations to
visitors in the mountain areas of central Europe. These communes
and the confederations they formed for their common welfare, and
safety seem to have absorbed almost tribalistic forms of intimacy
into their practices, even attitudes that Viewed sharing according
to need rather than work into their ways of dealing with material
goods. According to some accounts, the word âland,â which was
often open to use by all who needed it, included streams, clay pits,
quarries, or, in H. Mooseburgerâs words, âthe entire region with
every and all its products and fruits.â{80} Let me emphasize that this
was a municipal form of âownershipâ about which we shall have
more to say later, riot the nationalized forms advocated by Marxian socialists, the âeconomic democracyâ advanced by many liberals, or systems of âworkersâ controlâ demanded by orthodox
anarchistsâall of which, I may add, involve some degree of state
involvement or a particularistic and potentially competitive body
of interests within the community, however collectively âownedâ
or, democratically âmanagedâ an enterprise may be.
The Gray Leagues (**Graubunden**), the source of the Swiss referendum and the town meetings of its 222 communes, have to be singled out as the most libertarian of all. Until Napoleon forced it
into the Swiss Confederation, the *Freistaat der Drei Bunde* (literally, the Free State of the Three Leagues) arid specifically the
Graubund itself, the league that give its name to the confederation of the three leagues that composed it, was to exist for nearly
three centuries (1524â1800) and place its distinctly decentralistic
imprint on Switzerland as a whole. This Free State âwas not
merely democratic,â observes Benjamin Barber in his superb account of the league and its standards of community freedom. The
fact is that âit was democratic in a particular way not easily accounted for by the conceptual perspective of Anglo-American
thought... **Graubunden**âs experience with democracy has been
inseparable from its experience with community, and as a model
of integral community, no region of Switzerland can equal
itâ{81}
Barberâs conclusions cannot be emphasized too strongly. What
they concretely indicate is that the ultimate source of sovereignty
reposed in the communeâthe village, town, and cityâwhose assent or opposition to a course of action was achieved by referendum. The confederal system that united the communes had the
right to deal with foreign affairs, and little more. Beyond this
sphere, confederal bodies were concerned mainly with preventing their component leagues from making foreign alliances on
their own than with any formulation of foreign policy. Issues such
as war and peace were decided directly by the communes themselves. âThe only instrument of the central government was a
three-man commission (*Haupter*) made up of the heads of each of
the leagues that, with the assistance of an elective assembly (*Beytag*), prepared the referendum and executed the will of the communes,â Barber tells us. âIn the new structure power was an
inverse function of level of organization. The central âfederalâ
government had almost none, the regional communes had a great
deal.â{82} Whatever its capacity to deal with the problems that confronted the Free State, the people were provided âwith several
centuries of real thoughtful independence and a measure of autonomous self-government rare in Germanic Europe.â
The challenges faced by the Free State and its component
leagues over these centuries require a lengthy study of the kind
provided by Barber. The problem of dealing with foreign intervention; the incorporation of sizable towns and the expansion of
older ones into cities; the disparities in status, wealth, and power
that developed, not to speak of local parochialism at one extreme
and cosmopolitian âmodernityâ at the other, were never fully
resolved. But they were held in remarkable balance for most of
the Free Stateâs history. Even after Napoleon had reduced the
Free State to a canton in the more centralized Swiss Confederation, Barber notes that the peasant still turned the harshness of his
sparse land âinto a discipline of individuality, a teacher of autonomy. He held the intuitive conviction that his rural mountain life,
his uncomplicated involvement in a pastoral economy that left
him considerable leisure time, was inextricably bound up with his
independence and his freedom.â{83}
By no means should this strong sense of individuality be mistaken for the âindividualismâ associated with traditional ânatural
lawâ ideologues and the modern-day proprietary emphasis on
egoism. The hardships inflicted on Alpine dwellers, locked in a
glacial land of heavy snowfalls, avalanches, and floods, placed a
high premium on âcollective labor and common decision making.
... Thus as the hardness of life molded a manâs sense of autonomy,
it also compelled him to cooperation and collective action.â As
Herman Weilenmann has put it, to the villagers of the **Graubunden** freedom involved ânot individual emancipation from his obligations to the whole, but the right to bind himself by his own
choice.â{84} Neither the individual nor the collective, in effect,
claimed sovereignty over each other but rather they formed a
complementary relationship that supported each other.
These are abiding notions that are difficult for modern Euro-Americans to accept nowadays. Yet they are deeply rooted in the
American tradition itself. I refer more to the New England town
meeting tradition from which so many of the authentic libertarian
aspects of the âAmerican Dreamâ derive rather than the âcowboyâ tradition that presumably âtamed the Westâ and threatens
to reduce it to a battleground of sheer avarice. We are only now
becoming aware of the localist and communitarian motives that
drove Puritan settlers to New England. Religious persecution by
Charles I was only one of several reasons that the lives of the
Puritans were intolerable under the Stuart kings. âIf Charles I is
remembered at all today, it is as an ineffectual monarch who lost
his head on the chopping block,â observes T. H. Breen, whose
work on Puritan institutions is perhaps one of the best that has
been published in recent years. âDuring the first years of his reign,
however, he brought considerable energy to his position. He instituted or tried to institute far-reaching changes in civil, ecclesiastical, and military affairs. These unprecedented, often arbitrary
policies disrupted the fabric of local society, and they were a major
preoccupation of the men and women who moved to Massachusetts Bay. One cannot fully understand the institutional decisions
that the colonists made in America unless one realizes how gravely
Stuart centralization threatened established patterns of daily life
in Englandâs local communities.â{85}
The men and women who formed the New England townships
of the seventeenth century sought not only to restore Christianity
to its âpure,â ecclesiastically untainted, biblical forms; they also
sought to restore society itself to its pristine, egalitarian, and devoutly communitarian patterns, presumably paralleling the ethical and social covenants that appear in âActsâ and the quasitribal
democracy of the Hebrew Bedouins and their compacts. A shared
assumption seemed to exist that the English town corresponded
to the Hebrew tribal community and that its restoration was a
necessary move toward social as well as religious purification.
Every community was conceived as an ethical compact, not simply a form of association for personal and collective survivalâa
notion decidedly antithetical to the Hobbesian and Lockean principles that enter into liberal conceptions of republicanism as we
know them today. Men and women, in the Puritan world view,
formed communities to achieve a âgood societyâ in the moral, not
merely the material, sense of the term: a society marked by virtue
as defined in Christian precept. Individual and community, in this
sense, were no less inseparable among the early colonists of New
England than they were among the villagers of the Swiss *Graubund*.
The stormy declamations of angry prophets such as Amos,
whom Ernst Bloch has so aptly called a âbarn burner,â sear the
Puritan soul, and explain the institutional development of Puritan
communities. It was Charles I and his âill-advised attempt to increase his authority by attacking local English institutionsâ who
appears as the Moloch in this drama, and the Puritan divines as the
prophets who denounced royal encroachments on the âliberties of
Englishmen,â to use the language of the day. Despite the diversity
of their origins, ranging from âpopulous commercial centers such
as London and Norwichâ to âisolated rural communities ... most
had been affected in some personal way by the kingâs aggressive
efforts to extend his civil and ecclesiastical authority ... The
experience of having to resist Stuart centralization, a resistance
that pitted small congregations against meddling bishops, incorporated boroughs and guilds against grasping courtiers, local train-bands against demanding deputy lieutenants, and almost everyone in the realm against the collectors of unconstitutional revenues, shaped the New Englandersâ ideas about civil, ecclesiastical,
and military polity. The settlers departed from England determined to maintain their local attachments against outside interference, and to a large extent the Congregational churches and self-contained towns of Massachusetts Bay stood as visible evidence of
the foundersâ decision to preserve in America what had been
threatened in the mother country.â{86}
In view of the grim reputation the Puritan towns acquired as
dour âtheocraciesâ and parochial, self-righteous, dogmatic nests of
intolerance, we must provide, with more nuance, a picture of their
variety, roundedness, and militancyânot simply as they existed at
any given moment in time but as they evolved, eventually to
become centers of social rebellion, civic autonomy, and collective
liberty. Nor can we ignore the strong-minded yeomanry they produced, the high sense of individuality and citizenship they nourished. We must bear in mind that these personal and social traits
persisted in New England for some three centuriesânot as mere
historical ephemera that pass like wispy clouds across the social
horizon but as an established democratic legacy. No less ingrained
in the mythology of the American tradition than the reality of
business and its virtues, this legacy has always acted as a force
countervailing the egoistic sensibility fostered by reactionary nationalists and liberal centralists in other parts of America.
Let us quickly rid ourselves of the idea that this Yankee yeomanry was âtight-fisted,â âcommercially oriented,â âgrasping,â
and emotionally guarded. This imagery mistakes Boston, a commercially oriented and acquisitive port, for New England as a
whole. The port cities, in fact, often stood at odds with the many
small townships that were networked into the interior of the New
England colonies and states. These colonies and their interiors
were unique insofar as they were municipal entities, vital towns,
in contrast to other regions of America, which were generally
marked by dispersed settlements and farmsteads. Two facts
emerge that deserve emphasis. Firstly, Boston and other port cities in New England were no different in their outlook and interests
than Baltimore or Charleston, hence they were fairly atypical of
the Yankee spirit of the region. Indeed, they were no different as
commercial ports than port cities elsewhere in the world. Secondly, the fact that small towns could be planted so firmly, indeed, doggedly in New Englandâs thin, rocky, glaciated soil was an
act of ethical defiance, for the region is a poor agricultural area
that offers no congenial home for flourishing communities.
The towns and townships that emerged on the rocky soils of
Massachusetts, Connecticut, Rhode Island, and particularly New
Hampshire, Maine, and Vermont were a challenging moral statement of firm intentions to live in a very definite way, a structural
expression of what constitutes a virtuous life, not merely a bountiful one. Whereas Boston eventually visualized itself as the âNew
Worldâsâ counterpart of London, many New England townships
saw themselves as biblical communities, united by Old Testament
convenants that hypostasized simple living, a high regard for essentials over frivolities, fairness and mutuality in relationships,
egalitarianism in status, self-sufficiency in the development of
needs and their satisfaction, and more elaboration of communitarian values than fetishization of change. In short, they were
committed to a moral economy and society, not to lifeways premised on the market and gain.
We must look at these lifeways closely if we are to understand
the political institutions and economic relationships that expressed them and were designed to reinforce them. However
much these moral lifeways variedâowing, in part, to their ties
with the commercially oriented port citiesâthey were remarkably self-sufficient. I speak, here, of a world in which the yeomanry
comprised 70 percent of the agrarian population. Crops were cultivated mainly for survival rather than trade. As one yeoman
wrote in the 1770s, a farm gave âme and my whole family a good
living on the produce of it. Nothing to wear, eat or drink was
purchased, as my farm provided all.â{87} That surplus crops were
used to purchase manufactured goods such as iron, nails, glass,
weapons, gunpowder, and medicine does not alter the marginality
of commerce for most townships. Land utilization reflected the
domestic nature of the economy. It was very sparsely used despite
the large amount that was available for cultivation. Although yeomen often had fifty or more acres of land, generally only a fifth to
a tenth was actually put to pasture and food cultivation, and usually only for the family and its livestock. Women were engaged in
caring for the home, child rearing, making homespun clothing,
and other family and farm chores; men, in the also arduous tasks
of farming, woodcutting, and construction. Diversified crop cultivation is evidence of efforts to meet domestic more than market needs.
If anything, this yeomanry seems to have viewed commerce
disdainfully, indeed as parasitic and demeaning to a productive
and spiritually oriented way of life. In the words of the Bostonian,
George Richards Minot, writing in the 1780s, yeoman-landed
property âhad always been held in higher esteem and more valuable nature than any personal estate.â Indeed, its âpossession ... seems to be of greater gratification to the pride and independence of men.â{88} This image of agriculture, divested of acquisitive
and commercial ends, provided the New England farmer with a
sense of personal and ethical autonomy that made him eschew the
word âfarmerâ or âpeasantâ for âyeomanâ or âhusbandman,â an
example of the way in which men think of themselves that was to
profoundly alter their behavior and the course of history.
Yet as David P. Szatmary points out, âa feeling of independence
did not necessarily lead to individualism. Although priding themselves on their autonomy, yeomen lived in a community-oriented
culture. To ease their backbreaking work during planting and
harvesting, they asked family and friends for help. The independent status of yeomen, then, resulted neither from self-s uffi ciency
nor a basically competitive system but led, rather, to cooperative,
community-oriented interchanges.â{89} More concretely, this communal orientation brought women directly into food cultivation
and enhanced their social status, all talk of Puritan âpatriarchyâ to
the contrary notwithstanding. The enormous respectâand troubled concernâthat made dissenters such as Anne Hutchinson the
center of religious and political controversy in the early years of
the colony attest to the forwardness of women in this society and
their enormous strength of character.
Barter and the sharing of resources reinforced neighborliness
and fostered a warmly hospitable openness to people, even to
newcomers, as the Marquis de Chastellex was to observe in his
tour of New England during the early 1780s. The all-encompassing egalitarianism that pervaded this yeoman world included even
agricultural laborers, a mere ten percent of the rural workforce,
who usually owned some land in their own right or were given
land in reward for their services. New England did not really have
a rural proletariat Indeed, disparities in wealth were too insignificant to give rise to a stable class society.
Out of this world emerged the town meeting, a direct democracy in which local and, in times of social unrest, broadly political
issues were fervently debated and resolved. Here, in contrast to
Swiss democracy, attempts to trace the New England town meeting back to Germanic tribal traditions may well be examples of
historical overkill. The immediate source of the town meeting lies
very much at hand. Puritans were mainly Congregationalists, a
form of Protestantism that denies by definition the need for any
ecclesiastical hierarchy or centralizing body. In this utterly anarchic conception of Christianity, all powers of religious interpretation belong to the local congregation, which is mystically united
to others of the same kind by the presence of Christ, a spiritual
metaphor rather than an institution. This radically decentralistic
interpretation of the community as an autonomous congregation
can easily extend outward into the civil, world in the form of an
equally autonomous political body, the town meeting. The periodic meeting of the entire male population of a community in
order to govern its own affairs is a logical outcome of Puritan
religious belief and forms of organization. Property and income
restrictions on the right to participate in town meetings were not
taken too seriously. Disparities in land ownership and the payment of taxes could have excluded only a small number of residents in most New England towns. In the more rural areas, these
restrictions counted for virtually nothing. By the 1760s, when
colonial unrest was to lead to outright revolution^ town meetings
were so notoriously open that even newly arrived or transient
residents could participate ih them. Historians who tend to tie
property qualifications to New Englandâs franchise system have
proven themselves to be sticklers for regulations that went unenforced two centuries ago or were essentially nonexistent.
The reaction to Charles Iâs attempts to place localities under
centralized control and weaken local militias heightened the sensitivity of the New England towns to their autonomy and right to
bear arms. It is contemporary libel regarding the role of an armed
people to invoke the insecurities of the American frontier as an
excuse to ban arms ih the more âstableâ and, presumably, more
âsecureâ society of our own day. By the late eighteenth century,
the New England states were largely free of Indian attacks. The
prevalent notion of a covenanted township and a covenanted militia had very little to do with personal safety. The yeomen of New
England were not so much in fear of Indian forays against their
persons as they were concerned with statist forays, against their
liberties. In one of the most radical state constitutions to be
adopted during the American Revolution, Vermont yeomen,
gathering at Windsor in July 1777, not only abolished slavery and
property qualifications for the franchise, they also avowed that âas
standing armies, in the time of peace, are dangerous to liberty,
they ought not to be kept up.â Accordingly, âthe people have a
right to bear arms for a defense of themselves and the State,â a
right that explicitly goes far, beyond the reticent wording of âthe
Second Amendment to the United States Constitution. These, sentiments reflected the yeomanryâs state of mind two-hundred years
ago. They had nothing to do with the Westâs âgun slingingâ and
its bullying machismo. Rather they expressed the sound conviction that the state cannot be trusted to claim a monopoly of violence over its citizenry and the full custody of public freedom.
Democracy, if it was to mean anything, presupposed the active
involvement of the citizen in developing a participatory politics,
public security, and the direct face-to-face resolution of community problems. Hacking the means and instruments, particularly
the weapons, to enforce its decisions, such a citizenry in the eyes
of the yeomanry would be reduced to a mere instrument of the
state, whose legitimacy in their eyes was extremely dubious.
The township formed the living repository of institutions such
as the town meeting and the militia. âWhen the eighteenth-century Yankee reflected on government,â observes Robert A. Gross,
âhe thought first of his town. Through town meetings, he elected
his officials, voted his taxes, and provided for the well-ordering of
community affairs. The main business of the town concerned roads
and bridges, schools, and the poorâthe staples of local government even today. But the colonial New England town claimed
authority over anything that happened within its borders. It hired
a minister to preach in the town-built meetinghouse and compelled attendance at his sermons. It controlled public uses of private property, from the location of slaughterhouses and tanneries
to the quality of bread sold at market. And it gave equal care to
the moral conduct of its inhabitants ... No issue was in theory
exempt from a townâs action, even if in practice the provincial
government occasionally intervened in local disputes and told the
inhabitants how to run their lives.â{90}
Not surprisingly, the town meeting in even more secular form
swept out of New England during the Revolution and was to
extend as far south as Charleston. With the end of the Revolution
itself, municipal âcounterrevolutionsâ (to use the language of the
historians) essentially pushed it back to the region of its origin and
replaced municipal assemblies with mayors and aldermanic councils. New England and a number of towns bordering the region
tenaciously, even defiantly, held on to their democratic municipal
institutions, at least in the smaller towns and villages.
The âFounding Fathersâ who fashioned the national constitution of 1788 created a fairly centralized republic, but they were
also obliged to tolerate a basically confederal, face-to-face municipal democracy within their instrument of government and a fairly
radical âBill of Rightsâ that had been foisted upon them by a
restless yeomanry. The United States Constitution, in effect, expresses a precarious compromise between demands for a municipal democracy and a centralized nation-state. Running at cross
purposes throughout the document and the quasilegal âDeclaration of Independenceâ are agrarian, precapitalist commitments to
freedom, a participatory politics, and an involved citizenry on the
one hand, and a distinctly capitalistic imagery of acquisitive individualism favored by the rising commercial elements in the port
cities and inland market towns of the new nation.
----
Having examined the yeoman world of New England in the eighteenth century, our account would be incomplete if we failed to
look at the urban commercial world that coexisted with it. It was
in this world that the seeds of urbanization were already planted.
Port cities and inland market towns of New England âlived in a
largely commercial culture,â notes Szatmary, âThe market-oriented way of life included the drive toward acquisition and accumulation and emphasized the individual over the community.
Merchants, shopkeepers, professionals, commercial farmers,
urban artisans, sailors, and fishermen formed the most important
economic groups in this society. New England merchants, residing
in large port towns such as Boston, Newport, and Providence,
dominated and represented the most successful sector in the commercial culture. Handling and transporting farm goods, manufactured commodities, and, at times, human cargoes, they primarily
sought personal wealth. Such middlemen, although they worked
at as lower pace than modern industrialists, had the accumulation
of money as their primary goal.â{91}
Commerce and acquisitiveness, as I have emphasized, are not
new to the precapitalist world. What makes the merchant stratum
unique in the modern social landscape is that it funneled its earnings into its various enterprises and sought unceasingly to expand
themâpartly as a response to the intense competition that existed
in new markets, partly in an effort to gain control of home markets. This difference between an acquisitive and expanding market economy on the one hand and precapitalist markets that were
not nearly as accumulative on the other is important. The yeomanry outside the cities bartered produce to meet its basic survival needs. The merchants within the city exchanged goods to
expand and absorb rivals. The simple commodity markets of the
village, even of many medieval communes, encountered cultural
constraints to growth that placed socially accepted moral limits on
the acquisition of wealth. Gilds and public opinion enforced these
limits hand-in-hand with religious precepts. Acquisition seemed
demonic rather than elevating. Hence trade could be held in
check and a mixed economy developed that maintained its integrity against the corrosive, homogenizing effects of an uncontrolled market economy.
By contrast, the rising capitalists of the eighteenth century in
their port and inland commercial towns removed virtually all of
these moral, public, and religious constraints to acquisition and
expansion. Even land, once the refuge of the ancient capitalists
from a life devoted to commerce, became a mere commodity so
that its acquisition in the eighteenth century, particularly in the
âNew World,â conferred no special status on the new merchant
stratum.âThe Ohio Land Company, a speculative enterprise
formed in the late 1780s by New England and New York merchants, did not intend to cultivate any of the vast territories it
acquired on the western frontier. Its goal was âto profit from their
purchases through quick sales to incoming settlers.â{92} As one Boston lawyer put it in 1785: âMoney is the only object attended to,
and the only acquisition that commands respect.â{93}
This monetary and speculative mentality, while not unprecedented historically, is unique when it acquires such complete centrality! What is significant here is that moneymaking became an
ethic such that prestige, personal integrity, indeed social status
depend upon the acquisition of capital, not upon the ownership of
land and the acquisition of titles. By the eighteenth century, the
new republican ethos of the cities was altered such that it placed
a high premium on the accumulation of money and the means for
making money, not on social position and. high living. The aristocratic values that had permeated merchant strata from time immemorial were replaced by acquisitive values, egoism, and a brutalizing appetite for profit. In such a highly acquisitive and
competitive economy, the virtues of community were subordinated to the value-of personal gain and capital expansion.
From an ethical association for mutual support community was
turned into an entrepreneurial nexus for competition and manipulation. This sweeping inversion of the very meaning of consociation and friendship has no precedent in human history. Whatever
else the seafaring warriors of the Bronze Age did during their acts
of brigandage or the merchants of the classical and feudal eras did
in their forays abroad, their own communities were seen as refuges from their predations, and they made lavish contributions to
civic beautification! The new merchant and particularly the industrialist who followed, began to view his own community as an
object of predation and often plundered it ruthlessly. This behavior, graduated to the level of the âbusiness ethic,â began to supplant the religious precepts and cultural values that had been
passed on from time immemorial, even to earlier merchants and
entrepreneurs. Herein lay its enormous power: the ability to replace one set of ethical ideals with another, in short, to make gain
itself a value that could be used to countervail and ultimately
overcome all traditional constraints to asociality and predation.
Enveloping this distinctly antisocial form of individualism was a
new ideological support system: laws that gave an almost religious
sanction to contracts irrespective of their content and clerics who
legitimated gain as a heavenly calling. The courtierlike profligacy
and extravagance of French merchants and, the passion for titlesâ
that existed among English merchants, were dissolved by American merchants into an ethos of prudence, simple living, and the
embellishment of gain with the myth of ârepublican virtue.â
Let it be noted that this ethos did not roll over the new American republic like a moral tidal wave. Most of the country still adhered to yeoman values, albeit in a less communitarian form
than we still find among rural New England Yankees, Southern
plantation owners still held to aristocratic values that placed a
higher premium on consumption than acquisition. To spend oneâs
substance in a grand fashion was the sign of a gentleman, in contrast to the craven acquisitiveness of the New England merchant.
On the frontier, material self-sufficiency and personal autonomy
were still ends in themselves, and the acquisition of wealth that
sent so many adventurers to the West in pursuit of gold originated
more in visions of luxurious living than capital expansion. It was
not until the Reconstruction Era following the Civil War that
American capitalism, seen as a system of growth for its own sake,
began to hypostasize all of these acquisitive values and steadily
destructure earlier institutional, ethical, and personal ideals.
Urbanization became the physical expression of this destructuring process, the way in which it assumed visibility. I speak here of
the industrial, commercial, and residential sprawl that we call
urban belts. Already early in the twentieth century cities such as
New York, Chicago, Boston, Philadelphia, and, in Europe, London, Manchester, Berlin, even Paris began to absorb adjacent
towns and cancerously afflict the landscape with overbuilt, densely
populated, and overextended structures. The new electric trolley
systems that networked communities within regions supplemented the railroads that networked regions into nation-states.
Vast areas of the western world, once relatively impenetrable to
the deadening effects of capitalistic forms of urbanism, were ruthlessly opened to exploitation and homogenization. By the 1920s,
the automobile became the vehicle of choice for expanding suburban development and for subverting the remaining distinctions
between town and country that were so vital for maintaining the
identity of both. The famous âantagonism between town and
country,â so celebrated by historians as a driving force in social
development, had produced much of the political and cultural
variety we associate with the mixed economy preceding modern
capitalism and energized the movements that gave us modern
concepts of democracy. The tension between rural and urban
society and the diversity it created as people moved between both
worlds accounts in very great part for the fecundity of social life
in the past. The 1930s, perhaps mercifully, arrested urban homogenization and reinforced agrarian values that had nourished the
democratic images of the yeomanry and artisans. Placed in the
urban context of the decade, this remarkable marriage of countryside and town had produced a vitally creative hybridization of
outlooks from which the Depression years gained so rich a sense
of humanism and social commitment.
The end of the Second World Warânotwithstanding the 1960s
decadeârevived the trends initiated by the twentieth century.
The acquisitive individualism that existed on a pocket-size scale in
American society during the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries ballooned out over the entire country. Today it constitutes
a social malignancy, more properly a cancer *of* society that threatens to destructure and undermine not only the social bond but the
natural world. Its primary effect is simplification, the unraveling
of all social ties into the loose threads of the marketplace with its
anonymous buyers and sellers, its objectification of all values, its
monetization of idealsâand its unrelenting âgrowth,â which takes
the demonic form of turning everything organic into the inorganic, ossifying community and individual alike. That it may yield
a society divested of all cultural variety, a human psyche divested
of all uniqueness, and a natural world divested of all diversity is the
hidden intuition of our times for which nuclear immolation and
the wasteland it may yield is as much a metaphor for our times as
it is a potential reality. Politics and citizenship are not only the
victims of this corrosive process. It may well be that they are also
the antidote for itâprovided, to be sure, that we can reconstruct
them in ways that are redolent of their classical meaning and
enlarged by what we can learn from the modern world.
----
Any agenda that tries to restore and amplify the classical meaning
of politics and citizenship must clearly indicate what they are not
because of the confusion that surrounds the two words.
Politics is not statecraft, which, alas, is what we ordinarily mean
when we speak of âpoliticsâ today. And citizens are not âconstituentsâ or âvoters.â Statecraft consists of operations that engage the
state: the exercise of its monopoly of violence, its control of the
entire regulative apparatus of society in the form of legal and
ordinance-making bodies, its governance of society by means of
professional legislators, armies, police forces, bureaucracies, and
the ancillary professionals who service its operations such as lawyers, educators, technicians, and the like. Statecraft takes on a
political patina when so-called âpoliticalâ parties attempt, in various power plays, to occupy the offices that make state policy and
execute it. This kind of âpoliticsâ has an almost tedious typicality.
A political âpartyâ is normally a highly structured hierarchy,
fleshed out by a membership that functions in a top-down manner.
It is a miniature state, and in some countries, notably modern
Russia, actually constitutes the state itself.
The Soviet example of the state *qua* party is simply the logical
extension of the party into the state if only because every party has
its roots in the state, not in the citizenry. The conventional party
is hitched to the state like a garment on a clothing hook. However
varied the garment and its design may be, it is not part of the body
politic; it merely clothes it. There is nothing authentically political
about this phenomenon: it is meant precisely to contain the body
politic, to control it and to manipulate it, not to express its willâor even permit it to develop a will. In no sense is a conventional
âpoliticalâ party derivative of the body politic or constituted by it.
Leaving metaphors aside, âpoliticalâ parties are replications of the
state when they are out of power and often synonomous with the
state when they are in power. They are formed to mobilize, to
command, to acquire power, and to rule. Thus they are as inorganic as the state itselfâan excrescence of society that has no real
roots in it, no responsiveness to it beyond the needs of faction,
power, and mobilization.
Politics, by contrast, is an organic phenomenon. It is organic in
the very real sense that it is the activity of a public bodyâa community, if you willâjust as a plant is rooted in and nourished by
soil. Politics, conceived as an activity, involves rational discourse,
public empowerment, the exercise of practical reason, and its
realization in a shared, indeed participatory, activity. It is the
sphere of societal life beyond the family and the personal needs
of the individual that still retains the intimacy, involvement, and
sense of responsibility that is enjoyed in private arenas of life.
Groups may form to advance specific political views and programs, but these views and programs are no better than their
capacity to answer to the needs of an active public body. A clear
failing of many âpoliticalâ parties is the fact that their programs
or âideologiesâ are imposed on the public by individuals or their
acolytes whose relationship to the community is tenuous and
largely conceptual: One thinks here of the insights of a Karl Marx
whose ideas were developed within the confines of the British
Museum and then foisted on the world with a scriptural authority
that still generates an endless stream of academic dissertations
even though they exercise virtually no influence in public life.
By contrast, political movements, in the authentic sense of the
word, emerge out of the body politic itself, and their programs are
formulated not only by theorists, invaluable as they may be, but
in great part by the public itself, which plays a participatory role
in their elucidation and dissemination. The populist movements
that swept out of agrarian America and Tsarist Russia or the anarchosyndicalist and peasant movements of Spain and Mexicoâall,
despite their ideological patina, emerged from the populace and
articulated their deepest social and political aspirations. They developed into political cultures that solidified completely into the body politic.
Social theorists seem to lack a sufficient awareness of the publicâs power to create its own political institutions and forms of
organization. Twentieth-century popular uprisings such as the
Russian, German, Spanish, and, most recently, the Hungarian
revolutions witnessed the widespread self-organization of the people into councils (some that were networked into regional and
national congresses), popular assemblies in a wide variety of areas,
and autonomous municipalitiesâoften without party leadership.
The notion, so common across the political spectrum, that a party
structured along conventional hierarchical lines and guided by a
commanding leadership is indispensable to political change is, in
fact, thoroughly belied by experience.
Robert Michels, despite his jaundiced view of the âcompetenceâ of the âmassesâ in *Political Parties* and his proclivity for
charismatic leaders, provides a compelling argument for the inertial effect of conventional political parties in periods of rapid social
change. They tend to take over institutions that the people create
rather than innovate them, indeed, ultimately reworking them
along statist lines.
The Bolshevik Revolution of 1917â21 is a textbook example of
the appropriation of a popular movement by a highly centralized
party. The revolution ended, in the evisceration of an elaborate
grass-roots council system (the Soviets) by a state-oriented party
and the complete divestiture of all power that the populace had
so painstakingly acquired. A new state apparatus was largely embodied in the Bolshevik party. By the 1920s in Russia, statecraft
had completely replaced politics, and constituentsâmore properly, subjectsâhad replaced citizens. The Russian Bolsheviks had
introduced a new wrinkle in the concept of a constituent, Deprived even of the status of âvotersâ and any representation in the
state, the Russian people were turned by Bolshevism into a
âmass.â Bolshevism, in effect, established a pattern for âmass mobilizationâ that was to be emulated and used with socially disastrous effects by National Socialism in Germany.
The recovery and development of politics must, I submit, take
its point of departure from the citizen andâhis or her immediate
environment beyond the familial and private arenas of life. There
can be no politics without community. And by community! mean
a municipal association of people reinforced by its own economic
power, its own institutionalization of the grass roots, and the confederal support of nearby communities organized into a territorial
network on a local and regional scale. Parties that do not intertwine with these grass-roots forms of popular organization are not
political in the classical sense of the term. In fact, they are bureaucratic and antithetical to the development of a participatory politics and participating citizens. The authentic unit of political life,
in effect, is the municipality, whether as a whole, if it is humanly
scaled, or as its various subdivisions, notably the neighborhood.
Nor can politics be structured around the delegation of power.
The words ârepresentative democracy,â taken literally, are a contradiction in terms. Democracy, conceived as the ârule by the
peopleâ is totally inconsistent with the more republican vision of
ârule by representativesâ of the people. It is historical cliche to
emphasize that the authors of the United States Constitution,
which replaced the Articles of Confederation in the 1780s, meant
that they and their social strata were the âPeopleâ in the opening
sentence of the document. The Constitution did not create a democracy along Hellenic lines; it created a republic along Roman
lines. And like the Roman Republic it unavoidably and reluctantly
incorporated inherited democratic institutions such as popular
assemblies, which the brothers Gracchi tried to radically expandâan endeavor that ended in tragic failure.
All statist objections aside, the problem of restoring municipal
assemblies seems formidable if it is cast in strictly structural and
administrative forms. New York City has no way of âassemblingâ
if it tries to emulate Athens with its comparatively small citizen
body. New York City, in fact, is no longer a city in the classical
sense of the term and hardly rates as a municipality even by
nineteenth-century standards of urbanism. The âcityâ is a sprawling urban belt that sucks up millions of people daily from communities at a substantial distance from its commercial center. But
New York City is made up of neighborhoodsâthat is to say, largely
organic communities that have a certain measure of identity,
whether they are defined by a shared cultural heritage, economic
interests, a commonality of social views, or even an esthetic tradition such as in Greenwich Village. However much its administration as a logistical, sanitary, and commercial artifact requires a
high degree of coordination by experts and their aides, it is quite
open to political decentralization. Popular, even block, assemblies
can be formed irrespective of the size of a city, provided its organic cultural components can be identified and their uniqueness
fostered. Discussions about the âoptimalâ size of such components, while interesting to statistically minded sociologists, are politically irrelevant.
Assemblies can be formed from populations that may consist of
anywhere from a typical residential block to a dozen or more.
They can be coordinated by strictly mandated delegates who are
rotatable, recallable, and, above all, rigorously instructed in written form to support or oppose any issue that appears on the agenda
of local confederal councils composed of delegates from several
neighborhood assemblies. There is no mystery involved in this
form of organization. The historical evidence of their efficacy and
their continual reappearance in times of rapid social change is
considerable and persuasive. The Parisian sections of 1793, despite the size of Paris (between 700,000 and a million) and the
logistical difficulties of the era (a time when nothing moved faster
than a horse) functioned with a great deal of success on their own,
coordinated by sectional delegates in the Paris Commune. They
are notable not only for their effectiveness in dealing with political
issues based on a face-to-face democratic structure; they also
played a major role in provisioning the city, in preventing the
hoarding of food, and in suppressing speculation, supervising the
maximum for fixed prices, and many other complex administrative tasks. No city, in fact, is so large that it cannot be networked
by popular assemblies for political purposes. The real difficulty is
largely administrative: how to provide for the material amenities
of city life, support their immense logistical and traffic burdens, or
maintain a sanitary environment.
This issue is often obscured by a serious confusion between the
formulation of policy and its administration. For a community to
decide in a participatory manner what course of action it should
take in dealing with a problem does not oblige all its citizens to
execute that policyâunless, to be sure, there are obvious forms of
behavior that involve everyone in the community. The decision to
build a road, for example, does not mean that everyone must know
how to design and construct one. That is a job for engineers, who
can offer alternative designsâa very important political function
of experts, to be sure, but one that the people in assembly can be
free to decide. But to design and construct a road is a strictly
administrative responsibility. To debate and decide the need for
a road, including the choice of its site and the suitability of its
design, is a political process. If the distinction between policy
making and administration is kept clearly in mind, the role of
popular assemblies and the people who administer their decisions
easily unscrambles logistical problems from political ones, both of
which are normally entangled with each other in discussions on
decentralistic politics based on municipalities and assemblies. Superficially, the assembly system is a âreferendumâ form of politics:
it is based on a âsocial contractâ to share decision making with the
population at large and abide by the rule of the majority in dealing
with problems that confront a municipality, a regional confederation of municipalities, or, for that matter, a national entity.
Why, then, is there reason to emphasize the assembly form as
crucial to self-governance? Is it not enough to use the referendum,
as the Swiss profess to do today, and resolve the problem of democratic procedure in a simple and seemingly uncomplicated way?
A number of vital issues, involving the nature of citizenship and
the recovery of an enhanced classical vision of politics, must be
considered in answering these questions. The autonomous individual *qua* âvoterâ who forms the social unit of the referendum
process in liberal theory is a fictionâwhether in seemingly democratic notions at one extreme or a totalitarian politics of mass
mobilization at the other. The individual, left to his or her own
destiny in the name of autonomy and independence, becomes a
seemingly asocial being whose very freedom is denuded of vital
traits that provide the necessary flesh and blood for genuine individuality. Indeed, âindividuality is impaired when each man
decides to shift for himself,â observes Max Horkheimer in a pithy
critique of personalistic atomism. â... as the ordinary man withdraws, from participation in political affairs, society tends to revert
to the law of the jungle, which crushes all vestiges of individuality.
The absolutely isolated individual has always been an illusion. The
most esteemed personal qualities, such as independence, will to
freedom, sympathy, and the sense of justice, are social as well as
individual virtues. The fully developed individual is the consummation of a fully developed society. The emancipation of the individual is not an emancipation from society, but the deliverance of
society from atomization, an atomization that may reach its peak
in periods of collectivization and mass culture.â{94}
One can take these observation still further. The dependent
individual violates the justifiably high premium we place on autonomy, will, control of oneâs destiny, and untrammeled assertion
of ideas. In liberal society, this has led to a mythic âindividualismâ
that in popular parlance is presumably âruggedââthat is to say,
totally âindependentâ and âself-seeking.â âRugged individualismâ is as little a desideratum as dependence, which we normally
associate with an inadequate formation of selfhood. The real anthropology of our species involves the prolonged dependence of
the infant and young on elders, a socialization process that, until
recent times, ultimately led to a deep sense of interdependence
in adulthood, riot a brash sense of âindependence.â The notion of
âindependence,â which is often confused with independentthinking and autonomy of behavior, has been so marbled by pure bourgeois egoism that we tend to forget that our freedom as individuals
depends heavily on community support systems arid solidarity. It
is not by childishly subordinating ourselves to the community on
the one hand or by detaching ourselves from it on the other that
we become authentically human. What distinguishes us as social
beings, hopefully with rational institutions, from solitary beings,
presumably with minimal or no institutions, are our capacities for
solidarity with each other, for mutually enhancing our self-developnient and creativity and attaining freedom within a socially creative and institutionally rich collectivity.
âCitizenshipâ apart from community is as debasing to our political selfhood as âcitizenshipâ within a totalitarian community. In
both cases, We, are thrust back to the state of dependency that
characterizes our infancy and renders us dangerously vulnerable
to manipulation, whether by powerful personalities in private fife
or the state and corporations in public life. In neither case do we
attain individuality or community. Both, in fact, are dissolved by
removing the communal ground on which authentic individuality
depends. Rather, it is interdependence within an institutionally
rich and rounded community that fleshes out the individual with
the rationality, solidarity, sense of justice, and, ultimately, the reality of freedom that makes for a creative arid caring citizen.
Paradoxical as it may seem; the authentic elements of a rational
and free society are communal ones, not individual bnes. Conceived in more institutional terms, the municipality is the basis for
a free society, the irreducible ground for individuality as well as
society. The significance, of theâmunicipality is all the greater because it constitutes the discursive arena in which people can intellectually and emotionally confront each other, indeed, experience
each other through dialogue, body language, personal intimacy,
and face-to-face modes of expression in the course of making collective decisions. I speak, here, of the all-important process of
communizing, of the on-going intercourse of many levels of fife,
that makes for solidarity, not only the âneighborliness,â so indispensable for truly organic interpersonal relationships. The referendum, conducted in the privacy of oneâs voting booth or, as some âThird Waveâ enthusiasts would have it, in the electronic isolation
of oneâs home privatizes democracy and thereby subverts it. Voting, like registering oneâs âpreferencesâ for soap and detergents
in opinion polls, is the total quantification of citizenship, politics,
individuality, and the very formation of ideas as a mutually informative process. The mere vote reflects a preformulated âpercentageâ of our perceptions and values, not their full expression.
It is the technical debasing of views into mere preferences, of
ideals into mere taste, of overall comprehension into quantification such that human aspirations and beliefs can be reduced to numerical digits.
Finally, the âautonomous individual,â lacking any community
context, support systems, and organic intercourse, is disengaged
from the character-building processâthe *paideia*âthat the Athenians assigned to politics as one of its most important educational
functions. True citizenship and politics entail the on-going formation of personality, education, a growing sense of public responsibility and commitment that render communing and an active
body politic meaningful, indeed that give it existential substance.
It is not in the privacy of the school, any more than in the privacy
of the voting booth, that these vital personal and political attributes are formed. They require the existence of a public presence,
embodied by vocal and thinking individuals, a responsive and
discursive public sphere, to achieve reality. âPatriotism,â as the
origin of the word indicates, is the nation-stateâs conception of the
citizen as a child, the obedient creature of the nation conceived
as a *paterfamilias* or stern father, who orchestrates belief and
commands devotion. To the extent that we are the âsonsâ and
âdaughtersâ of a âfatherland,â we place ourselves in a mindless,
indeed infantile, relationship to the state.
Loyalty, by contrast, implies a sense of commitment to a human
community that is guided by knowledge, training, experience, and
a sense of caringâin short, by a political education created in the
course of political participation, not by institutional obedience.
The Greek term, *philia*, ordinarily translated as âfriendship,â but
which I prefer to call âsolidarity,â is the ultimate result of the
educational and self-formative process that *paideia* was meant to
achieve. In the absence of a humanly scaled, comprehensible, and
institutionally accessible municipality, this all-important function
of politics and its embodiment in citizenship is simply impossible
to achieve. Indeed, it ceases to even enter into contemporary
notions of âpoliticsâ and âcitizenship.â Accordingly, we begin to
gauge âpolitical involvementâ by the âpercentageâ of âvotersâ
who âparticipateâ in the âpolitical processââa degradation of
words that totally denatures their authentic meaning and eviscerates their ethical content. If the class-oriented politics in the past
was ultimately a civic politics, individual politics today is ultimately a municipal politics. In both cases, I use the term âpoliticsâ
to denote not only the direct self-management of the *polis* or
community by its citizens but the educational process of forging
a self that is capable of the self-management of the municipality.
----
There are many questions that arise when one tries to develop a
new municipal agenda today, and many possibilities, I may add,
that open the way to a new, richly imaginative politics as well as
a traditional conception of citizenship as participatory, educative,
and community oriented.
In an era of growing power in nation-states and corporations,
when administration, property ownership, production, bureaucracies, and the flow of capital as well as power are notoriously centralized, how can we invoke a localist, municipally oriented society without seeming to be starry-eyed visionaries? Is this
municipalist, decentralist, and participatory vision of self-governance and selfhood utterly incompatible with the overwhelming
trend toward public massification? Does the notion of clearly
definable, humanly scaled communities not seem to be redolent
of atavistic, backward-looking parochial ideas of a premodern
world, indeed of the âfolk communityâ (*Volksgemeinschaft*) advocated by German Nazism? Do its advocates, specifically this
writer, wish to undo the technological gains achieved by the several industrial revolutions that followed the first one, two centuries ago? Can a âmodern societyâ be governed any longer by local
groups in an era when centralized power is presumably âhere to
stayâ?
To these largely theoretical questions, I can add a host of very
practical ones. How will politically localized citizensâ assemblies
be coordinated to deal with the practical questions of such simple
facts as rail transportation, road maintenance, the supply of resources and foodstuffs, from distant or select regions? How can we
readapt an economy based on the business ethic (including its
plebeian counterpart, the âwork ethicâ) to one that is guided by
an ethics of self-fulfillment and self-realization in productive activity? How can we change present-day instruments of government
such as national constitutions and city charters to reflect a system
of self-governance based on municipal autonomy? How can we
restructure a profit-oriented market economy, reinforced by a
centralists technology, into a humanly oriented moral economy,
reinforced by an alternative decentralis,tic technology? Finally,
how can all of these visions be brought into accord with an ecological society that seeks a harmonious, indeed participatory, relationship with the natural world, free of social hierarchy,â class and gender domination, and cultural homogeneity?
This work, let me emphasize, is not a handbook for social
recipes that meet the taste of every palate. To make it soâand
more than enough books exist that profess to do so is to subvert
the very meaning of the libertarian municipal project it seeks to
advance. In the last analysis, these pages are an effort to apply the
principles of social ecology to ah interpretation of the present and
to a past that really is always with us, informed by a deep concern
for the contours of a liberatory and ecological future society. To
provide a detailed institutional and economic map of what such a
future society should or âmustâ look like is to use a seemingly
ecological interpretation of the future against one of the most
fundamental precepts of social ecology: unity in diversity. The
ecological belief that every human community, indeed every individualânot to speak of every natural ecocommunity is deliciously unique permeates this book from its opening lines to those
that close it. Detailed recipes that profess to resolve every problem that every decentralized human community will faceâand
should creatively face, given its uniqueness and specificityâis to
cut across the grain of all the ecological ideas that give coherence
to this book. It is to assume precisely what social ecology emphatically denies: namely, that all our social problems are so universal,
indeed so âglobalâ (to use the pop vernacular of environmentalism
today), that we have no need to âact locally.â Localism, taken
seriously, implies a sensitivity to speciality, particularity, and the
uniqueness of place, indeed a sense of place or *topos* that involves
deep respect (indeed âloyalty,â if I may use a term that I would
like to offset against âpatriotismâ) to the areas in which we live and
that are given to us in great part by the natural world itself.
Once this is emphasized, there are still broad answers that can
be advanced to the questions I have raised, particularly to those
that have a highly polemical character. In trying to answer these
questions, I presuppose a thorough understanding of the essential
principles raised in this book: not only is politics to be sharply
distinguished from statecraft, but policy making is to be distinguished from administration; not only is ârugged individualismâ to
beâ distinguished from authentic individuality, but the notion of
the isolated individual is to be distinguished from the rounded
individual who is rooted in a rounded community; not only is
independence to be distinguished from dependence, but authentic independence is indistinguishable from interdependence.
These caveats cannot be restated often enough. The notion that
decentralized communities are premodern, indeed antimodern,
âatavismsâ reflects an almost willful failure to recognize that an
organic community is not necessarily an âOrganismâ in which the
individual parts are subordinated to the collective whole. That
such highly bourgeois prejudices should be echoed by socialists
and liberals alike reflects a very clouded view of individualism that
confuses individuality with egoism. Our market society, riddled by
its preoccupation with objects called âcommoditiesâ and its gross
monetization of all aspects of life, has never produced authentic
individuality, unless one chooses to mistake buccaneering industrial and commercial predators for authentic personalities. While
any attempt to fashion an ecological society out of free, autonomous, and organic communitiesâorganic no less in their respect
for land, flora, and fauna than in their attempts to foster human
solidarity and social support systemsâalways risks the possibility
of becoming a âfolk communityâ in the parochial, even fascistic,
sense of the term, they also open the possibility of producing a
highly fecund terrain for promoting the development of deeply
individuated and richly creative personalities. Ironically, Nazism,
for all its bombast about the desirability of a German *Volksgemeinschaft*, opportunistically surrendered the utopian content of this
popular yearning for a sense of place and community to a leadership principleâ that totally subordinated localism to centralism,
community to nationalism, technical conservatism to industrial
innovation, particularly in the design of weapons and methods of
political surveillance. The academic frippery that clothes the hard
realities of Nazism with myths that it patently discarded is almost
textbook evidence of the yawning separation of campus scholasticism from the real world beyond its confines.
There is nothing that is either âbackward lookingâ or âforward
lookingâ about humanityâs effort to find community together with
individuality. The impulse to achieve these complementary aimsâespecially in times like our own, when both of them are faced
with sweeping disintegrationâis an abiding human goal that has
been expressed as much in religion as in secular radicalism, in
utopian experiments as in city neighborhoods, in self-enclosed
ethnic groups as in expansive cosmopolitan cities. Nothing but a
feeling for truth and its custody by the human mind has ever kept
any notion of community and individuality from tipping over into
spiteful parochialism at one extreme or fragmented atomism at
the other.
The result is that consciousnessânot pat formulasâultimately
determine whether humanity will achieve a rich sense of collectivity without sacrificing a rich sense of individuality. A creative
politics without a creative citizenry is as unattainable as a creative
citizenry without a creative politics. The guarded mind, whether
we call it âclass consciousnessâ or âsocial consciousness,â is the sole
guarantor of a social and personal life that will be guided by the
thin line of truth. The tendency of radicals and liberals who emphasize abstractions such as âclassâ and âsocialâ over the more
existential need for consciousness is the true âbetrayal of the intellectualsâ that was mourned in earlier times. Any expectation that
a formula, even a salad of democratic institutions, will in itself
rescue us from any impulses that yield totalitarianism, whether in
its âfuturisticâ or atavistic forms, is sheer myth. The guarded
mind, informed by knowledge and a humane sense of solidarity,
is all that we possess as a fortress against authoritarian âreversionâ
at one extreme and authoritarian âprogressâ at the other. Indeed
the âdark pastâ has become the counterpart of the âdark futureâ
in an age that seeks form rather than content to guide us through
its modern dilemmas and panaceas.
Paradoxical as it seems and dialectically irascible as it may be,
the conflictâmore precisely, the tensionâthat exists between a
localistic vision and a nationalistic reality is the most important
basis for a new politics that we can redeem from the present crisis
for which âurbanizationâ is a metaphor. The growing power and
centralization of the state and its corporate underpinnings are not
necessarily the harbingers of victory over the municipality. It may
well be that they are the harbingers of a deepening social crisis
that may give new vitality to municipal politics and alter the very
shape of politics itself. One does not have to be a visionary (apparently, a pejorative term, these days) to see that every human
impulse is now being affronted by the disempowerment of ordinary people in everyday life. Locked increasingly into an inward
world in which society and collectivity are excluded, transclass
desires seem to be slowly welling up in countless individuals who
are seeking the open air of a meaningful public life, not to speak
of a more creative personal one. Like the tensions that gathered
together in western society during the four centuries directly
preceding the emergence of industrial capitalism, we are witnessing a new period of transition with deep-seated tensions that are emerging in our own era.
Localism, in fact, has never been so much in the air as it is todayâall the more because centralism and corporatism have never
seemed more overwhelming than they are today. The state and
the corporations have âghettoizedâ the western world, particularly North America, to such a suffocating extent that public sentiment threatens to overflow the barriers they have created and
perhaps in time to burst them. Demands for local control and
attempts to redefine democracy along ever-expansive lines are
yielding a multitude of interest groups and citizen-initiative committees. Demands for local control and redefinitions of democracy
that are normally preceded by such adjectives as âgrass-rootsâ are
yielding a multitude of various local associations, âalliances,â and
block committees that stress local control as well as economic
justice. âSocialistâ mayors have been elected in several American
communities for the first time since the 1930s. The town meeting,
initially a New England institution, is becoming a byword in regions of the United States that have no shared tradition with the,
American Northeast. Community and action groups have invaded
local politics, a terrain that was once the exclusive preserve of
political parties, on a scale that has significantly altered the entire
landscape of municipal policy making.
That these grass-roots organizations are often ephemeral or
co-optable does not alter the fact that the underlying ferment at
the base of American society is vitalized precisely by the fact that
the centralized state has made the most elementary hmnan demands for self-expression and self-empowerment highly problematical, a fact that may well change the entire texture of American politics. The tension between vision and reality is no less a
creative force than it was in times past, particularly in periods of
social and economic transition.
Put bluntly, a latent âdual powerâ seems to be emerging today
in which, the local base of society is beginning to challenge the
authority of its seemingly invulnerable state and corporate apex.
It. is precisely the inaccessibility of this apex to grass-roots influence that threatens to disintegrate the very architecture of power
as such. The fact that public control over public fife has never
seemed more visionary is precisely what makes the demands for
such control particularly compelling, just as intractable resistance
by power tends to foster opposition rather than mute it. Almost
intuitively, people seem to be molding their own institutions for
expression in the public realm with an obstinacy that may well
render localist politics an irrepressible force. The very ephemeral
nature of many such grass-roots institutions and organizations is
evidence less of failure than of persistence. I am no longer talking
of the explosive episodes that marked theâ uprisings of the 1960s,
such as those in black ghettos or antiwar street actions. Grass-roots
politics, specifically popular municipal politics, is becoming an
integral part of American politics as a whole, one that has yet to
find a coherent voice and sense of direction. But the fact is that
it is here to stay and has worked its way, however confusedly, into
the real world of the political landscape.
In trying to formulate a municipal agenda for our time, the real
question is how will this often formless political energy be institutionalized? What structures will it create that will turn it into a
powerful force to countervail the growing power of the state and
a centralized corporate economy? What kind of political culture
can it create that will play a transformative role in an era of urban
and governmental gigantism? And what kind of political economy
can it fashion that will avoid the pitfalls of a property-oriented
market economy on the one hand and a totalitarian nationalized
economy on the other?
I do not profess to have answers to these questions that applyâ
to all municipalitiesânor, giyen their variety, would it be anything but presumptuous to provide them. But certain basic coordinates can be formulated that are integrally wedded to any conception of municipal freedom, certainly of a kind that is meant to recover a participatory idea of politics and a classical idea of citizenship.
The most important of these coordinates is theârevival of the
scaled communities or neighborhood assemblies in large, even
metropolitan urban entities. Such assemblies are not merely a
historical legacy that belong to the archaeology of urbanism. A
large portion of this book would be completely meaningless if the
reader failed to see that in nearly all periods of social upheaval
people have turned to assembly forms as a way of entering the
doors of history and taking control of their destiny, If these assemblies seem remote, even archaic, when we stray back to ancient
Mesopotamia and classical Greece, they become very close to our
fives when we see them in revolutionary America and France, and
even seem to make direct contact with us when we find them in
the Paris Commune of 1871 and the post-World War II era. Apparently, we have something at work here that has a more abiding
reality than the distant âage of cities,â which has since been supplanted by the âage of nation-states.â They seem to be speaking
to something in the human spirit that demands systems of governance based on face-to-face! decision making, a personafistic as
well as a participatory politics. It is as though the need for community and communing were not simply a social desideratum but an ethical one that emanates from the human spirit itself.
The second of these major coordinates is the need fpr the assemblies to âspeakâ to each other, literally, to confederate. Leagues of
towns and cities, as I have argued earlier, have always surfaced,
however, temporarily, as centripetal forms of municipal association. Calls for the creation of nationlike entities structured around
confederations of municipalities go back to Greek times and range
over history up to the Paris Commune, indeed into very recent
times when the centralized nation-state threatens to become an
overbearing force in local affairs. The concept of confederation is
as old as the fact of municipal life itself. Initially more defensive
than creative in character, it has provided us with extraordinary,
indeed inspiring, examples of freedom within localities and in the
relationships between localities. Even as a word, âconfederationâ
implies a commitment to liberatory ways of associating that ânationalism,â with its jingoistic and totalitarian nuances has rarely
possessed. It is notable that the first American constitution was
deliberately called âthe Articles of Confederation,â which, for all
its limitations, was cynically and secretively replaced by a so-called
âfederalâ Constitution, one that Hamilton and his supporters
foisted on the American people as the next best alternative to a
constitutional monarchy.
The third of the major coordinates for guiding us toward a
municipal democracy is the need to create politics as a school for
genuine citizenship. Ultimately, there is no civic âcurriculum,â as
it were, that can be a substitute for a living and creative political
realm. But what we must clearly do in an era of commodification,
rivalry, anomie, and egoism is formulate and consciously inculcate
the values of humanism, cooperation, community, and public service in the everyday practice of civic fife, not only in our schools,
religious institutions, and local societies. Grass-roots citizenship
must go hand in hand with grass-roots politics. The Athenian *polis*,
for all its many shortcomings, offers us remarkable examples of
how its high sense of citizenship was reinforced not only by systematic education, but by the development of an etiquette of civic
behavior and an artistic culture that adorned its ideals of civic
service with the realities of civic practice. Deference to opponents
in debates, the use of language to achieve consensus, on-going
public discussion in the *agora* in which even the most prominent
of the *polis*âs figures were expected to debate public issues with
the least known, the use of wealth not only to meet personal needs
but to adorn the *polis* itself (thus placing a high premium on the
disaccumulation rather than the accumulation of wealth), a multitude of public festivals, dramas, and satires largely centered on
civic affairs and the need to foster civic solidarityâall of these and
many other aspects of Athensâs political culture created the civic
loyalty and responsibility that made for actively involved citizens
with a deep sense of civic mission.
The development of citizenship, in effect, must become an art,
not merely an educationâand creative art in the esthetic sense
that appeals to the deeply human desire for self-expression in a
meaningful spiritual community. It must be a personal art in
which every citizen is fully aware of the fact that his or her community entrusts its destiny to his or her moral probity, loyalty, and
rationality. The very essence of state power and statecraft today
is that the âcitizenâ is an incompetent being, indeed infantile and
normally untrustworthy, while the state is a disciplinary institution, not an avenue of self-expression. Even liberal theory, not to
speak of Christian theology, justifies the existence of the state as
a whip to keep its ânaturallyâ irascible subjects in hand and correct their inherent âincompetenceâ by entrusting public affairs to
professional politicians and bureaucratic institutions. For citizens
to directly intervene in public affairs beyond obediently voting
annually for preselected candidates and paying their taxes with a
reasonable modicum of honesty has been regarded as a safety
valve for public dissatisfaction at best and âanarchyâ at worst.
The municipalist conception of citizenship assumes precisely
the opposite. Every citizen is regarded as competent to participate directly in the âaffairs of state,â indeed what is more important, encouraged to do so. Every means is provided, whether esthetic or institutional, to foster participation in full and see it as an
educative and ethical process that turns the citizenâs latent competence into an actual reality. Social and political fife are consciously orchestrated to foster a profound sensitivity, indeed a real
sense of caring for the adjudication of differences without denying
the need for vigorous dispute when it is needed. Public service is
seen as a uniquely human attribute, not a âgiftâ that a citizen
confers on the community or an onerous task that he or she must
fulfill. Cooperation and civic responsibility are seen as expressions
of care, concern, and sociability, not as ordinances that the citizen
is expected to honor in the breach and evade where he can do so.
Put bluntly and clearly, the municipality is seen as a theater in
which life in its most meaningful public form is the plot, a political
drama whose grandeur imparts nobility and grandeur to the citizenry that forms the cast. By contrast, our modern cities have
become in large part agglomerations of bedroom apartments in
which men and women spiritually wither away and their personalities are trivialized by the petty concerns of entertainment, consumption, and small talk.
The last and perhaps the most intractable of our coordinates is
economic. Today, economic issues tend to center around âwho
owns what,â âwho owns more than whom,â and, above all, how
disparities in wealth are to be reconciled with a sense of civic
commonality. Nearly all municipalities have been fragmented by
differences in economic status, pitting poor, middle, and wealthy
classes against each other often to the ruin of municipal freedom
itself as the bloody history of Italyâs medieval and Renaissance
cities so clearly demonstrates.
These problems have not disappeared in recent times. Indeed
in many cases they are as severe as they have ever been. But what
is unique about our own timeâa fact so little understood by many
liberals and radicals in North America and Europeâis that entirely new *transclass* issues have begun to emerge that concern
environment, growth, transportation, cultural degradation, and
the quality of urban life generallyâissues that have been produced by urbanization, not by citification. Cutting across conflicting class interests are such transclass issues as the massive dangers of thermonuclear war, growing state authoritarianism, and, ultimately, global ecological breakdown. To an extent unparalleled in
American history, an enormous variety of citizensâ groups have
brought people of all class backgrounds into common projects
around problems, often very local in character, that concern the
destiny and welfare of their community as a whole.
Issues such as the siting of nuclear reactors or nuclear waste
dumps, the dangers of acid rain, and the presence of toxic dumps,
to cite only a few of the many problems that beleaguer innumerable American municipalities, have united an astdnishing variety of
people into movements with shared concerns that render a ritualistic âclass analysisâ of their motives utterly irrelevant. No less
remarkable in crossing traditional class, ethnic, and economic barriers is the emergence of feminism, a movement that sees the
gender oppression that afflicts wealthy women, no less than poor,
a matter of dignity and self-respect. Carried still further, the absorption of small communities by larger ones, of cities by urban
belts, and urban belts by âstandard metropolitan statistical areasâ
has given rise to militant demands for communal integrity and
self-government, an issue that surmounts strictly class and economic interests. The literature on the emergence of these trans-class movements, once so secondaryâ to internecine struggles
within the cities of earlier times, is so immense that to merely list
the sources would require a sizable volume.
I have given this brief overview of an emerging general social
interest over old particularistic interests to demonstrate that a
new politics is already coming into beingâindeed one that is not
only restructuring the political landscape on a municipal level but
the economic landscape as well. The old debates between âprivate
propertyâ and ânationalized property,â between âindividual ownershipâ and âpublic ownership,â are becoming threadbare. Not
that these different kinds of ownership and the forms of exploitation they imply have disappeared; rather, they are being increase
ingly overshadowed by new realities and concerns. âPrivate property?ââ in the traditional sense of the term, with its case for
perpetuating the citizen as an economically self-sufficient and
politically self-empowered individual, is fading away. It is disappearing not because âcreeping socialismâ is devouring the âfree
entrepreneurâ but because âcreeping corporatismâ is devouring
everyoneâironically, in the name of âfree enterprise,â The economy of North America, like that of Europe and even Third World
countries, is becoming either âcorporatizedâ or ânationalizedââor to use the one term that embraces both, âbureaucratized.â The
Greek ideal of the politically sovereign citizen who can make a
rational judgment in public affairs because he is free from material
need or clientage has been reduced to a mockery. The oligarchic
character of economic life, whether in the âwestern blocâ of the
âeastern,â threatens democracy such as it isânot only on a national level but also on a municipal level, where it still preserves
a certain degree of intimacy and leeway.
We come here to a breakthrough approach to a municipalist
economics that innovatively dissolves the mystical aura surrounding corporatized property and nationalized property, indeed
workplace elitism and âworkplace democracy.â I refer to the
municipalization of property, not its corporatization or its nationalization. As for the workplace, I refer to more than âeconomic
democracyâ or âeconomic collectivization.â Rather, I refer to the
substitution of public democracy for both of these traditional images of productive management and operations. Significantly, âeconomic democracyâ in the workplace is no longer incompatible
with corporatized or nationalized economy. Quite to the contrary:
the effective use of âworkersâ participationâ in production, even
the outright handing over of industrial operations to the workers
who perform them, has become another form of time-studied,
assembly-line rationalization, the systematic exploitation of labor
by bringing labor itself into complicity with its own exploitation.
Many workers, in fact, would like to get away from their factories and find more creative types of work, not simply âparticipateâ
in their own misery. What âeconomic democracyâ meant in its
profoundest sense was free, âdemocraticâ access to the means of
life, the guarantee of freedom from material want, not simply the
involvement of workers with onerous productive activities that
we would do better to turn over to machines. It is a blatant bourgeois trick, in which many radicals unknowingly participate, that
âeconomic democracyâ has been reinterpreted to mean âemployee ownershipâ or that âworkplace democracyâ has come to
mean workersâ âparticipationâ in industrial management rather
than freedom from the tyranny of the factory, rationalized labor,
and âplanned production.â
A municipal politics, based on libertarian principles, scores a
significant advance over all of these conceptions by calling for the
municipalization of the economyâand its management by the
community as part of a politics of self-management. Syndicalist
demands for the âcollectivizationâ of industry and âworkersâ controlâ of individual industrial units are based on contractual relationships between all âcollectivizedâ enterprises, thereby reprivatizing the economy and opening it to traditional forms of private
propertyâwhether collectively owned or not, while libertarian
municipalism politicizes the economy and dissolves it into the
civic domain. Neither factory nor land becomes a separate or
potentially competitive unit within a seemingly communal collective. Nor do workers, farmers, technicians, engineers, professionals, and the like perpetuate their vocational identities as separate
interests that exist apart from the citizen body in face-to-face
assemblies. âPropertyâ is integrated into the municipality as a
material constituent of its free institutional framework, indeed as
part of a larger whole that is controlled by the citizen body in
assembly as citizensânot as âworkers,â âfarmers,â âprofessionals,â or any other vocationally oriented special-interest groups.
What is equally important, the famous âcontradictionâ or âantagonismâ between town and country, so crucial in social theory
and history, is transcended by the âtownship,â the traditional New
England jurisdiction, in which an urban entity is the nucleus of its
agricultural and village environsânot a domineering urban entity
that stands opposed to them. A township, in effect, is a small region
within still larger ones, such as the county and the bioregion.
So conceived, the municipalization of the economy should be
distinguished not only from âcorporatizationâ but also from seemingly more âradicalâ demands such as ânationalizationâ and âcollectivization.â Nationalization of the economy invariably has led
to bureaucratic and top-down economic control; collectivization,
in turn, could easily lead to the emergence of a privatized economy in a collectivized form with the perpetuation of class or caste
identities. By contrast, municipalization brings the economy as a
whole into the orbit of the public sphere, where economic policy
can be formulated by the *entire* communityânotably its citizens
in face-to-face relationships working to achieve a general interest
that surmounts separate, vocationally defined specific interests.
The economy ceases to be merely an economy in the strict sense
of the term, composed of capitalistic, âworker-controlledâ enterprises. It becomes a truly political economy (to use a very traditional terminology in a very untraditional sense): the economy of
the *polis* or the municipality. The municipality, more precisely,
the citizen body in face-to-face assembly, absorbs the economy
into its public business, divesting it of a separate identity that can
become privatized into a self-serving enterprise.
What can prevent the municipality, now reinforced by its own
economic apparatus, from becoming a parochial city-state of the
kind that appeared in the late Middle Ages? Once again I would
like to Emphasize that anyone who is looking for guaranteed solutions to the problems raised here will not find them in the form
of blissfully insulated institutions that take on a life of their own
apart from the role of consciousness and ethics in human affairs.
But if we are looking for countertendencies rather than âguarantees,â there is an answer that can be given. The most important
single factor that gave rise to the late medieval city-state was its
stratification from withinânot only as a result of differences in
wealth, but also in status positions, partly originating in family
origins, partly, too, in vocational differences. Indeed, to the extent
that the city lost its sense of collective unity arid divided its affairs
into private and public business, public life itself became segmented into the âblue nailsâ or plebeians who. dyed cloth in cities
such as Florerice and theâ more arrogant strata of artisans who
produced quality goods. Wealth, too, factored heavily in a privatized economy where material differences could expand and foster a variety of hierarchical differences.
The municipalization of the economy not only absorbs the vocational differences that could militate, against a publically controlled economy; it also absorbs the material means of life into
â communal forms of distribution. âFrom each according to his ability and to each according to his needsâ is now institutionalized as
part of the public sphere. This traditional maxim, which is meant to assure that people will have, access to the means of life irrespective of the work they are capable of performing, ceases to be
merely a precarious credo: it becomes a practice, a way of functioning politicallyâone that is structurally built into the community as a way of existing as a political entity.
Happily, no community can hope to achieve economic autarchy, nor should it try to do so unless it wishes to become self-enclosed and parochial. Interdependence between communities
is no less important than interdependence between individuals.
Divested of the cultural crossfertilization that is often a product of
economic intercourse, the municipality tends to shrink into itself
and disappear into its own civic privatism, Shared needs and resources imply the existence of sharing and, with sharing, communication, rejuvenation by new ideas, a wider social horizon that
yields a wider sensibility to new experiences. The recent emphasis
in environmental theory on âself-sufficiency,â if it does not mean
a greater degree of prudence in dealing with material resources,
is regressive. Localism should never be interpreted to mean parochialism nor should decentralism ever be interpreted to mean that
smallness is a virtue in itself. Small is not necessarily âbeautiful.â
The concept of human scale, by far the more preferable expression for a truly ecological community, is built around the ability of
people to completely grasp their political environment, not to
parochially bury themselves in it to the exclusion of cultural stimuli from outside their communityâs boundaries.
, Given these coordinates, it is possible to envision anew political
culture with a new revival of citizenship, popular civic institutions, a new kind of economy, and a countervailing dual power,
confederally networked, that could arrest and hopefully reverse
the growing centralization of the state and corporate enterprises.
Moreover, it is also possible to envision an eminently practical
point of departure for going beyond the town and city as we have
known them up to now and developing future forms of habitation
as genuine ecocommunitiesâhuman ecocommuniti.es, in this
case, that seek to achieve a new harmonization between people
and between humanity and the natural world. I have emphasized
the word âpracticalâ because it is now clear that any attempt to
tailor a human community to a natural âecosystemâ in which it is
located cuts completely against the grain of centralized power, be
it state or corporate. Centralized power invariably reproduces
itself in centralized forms at all levels of social, political, arid economic life. It is not only âbigâ; it thinks big. Indeed, this way of
being and thinking is a condition for its survival, not only its growth.
Not surprisingly, the ecotechnologies that came very much into
vogue during the 1970s, such as solar, wind, and methane power,
later to be explored and toyed with by the national governments
of the world, literally collapsed under their own weight. Governments almost invariably designed them with technical gigantism
in mind. One thinks here of the huge tidal dams that were constructed in France, the plans for immense solar installations that
were designed in American universities, the oversized windmills
that were reared by federal agencies, some of which were almost
calculated to fail and few of which could have significantly affected
local life. Organic agriculture, while given a ritualistic nod of approval and a modicum of funding by state agencies, was virtually
elbowed out by the more earnest attention that was given to
conventional agribusiness and industrial techniques for cultivating food.
Ecotechnologies of this kind have been earnestly used almost
entirely by individuals and local communities. To the extent that
solar and wind power are used today, it is mainly because ecologically concerned citizens and their neighbors have introduced
them as part of their home dwellings, not because their use has
been taken very seriously as part of a national agenda. To induce
the nation-state and corporations to think about energy, designers
are obliged to speak about the feasibility of nuclear power plants,
immense, ecologically destructive hydroelectric dams, and large
fossil fuel installations. The ideological terrain of the nation-state
is primarily continental, not local, just as the ideological terrain of
the medical profession is primarily disease, not health. The very
notion of sensitively tailoring technology to fit the natural ecocommunity in which people five is possible to a serious extent only
within a locally oriented political community where the uniqueness of the natural environment can be fully experienced in all its intimacy.
Moreover, it is the only level in which natural cycles can be
respectfully lived outânot as the mere rhetoric of âenvironmentallyâ-oriented politicians but as the everyday experience of
householders who are able to return domestic wastes to their
organic gardens and recycle the American consumersâ kitchen-middens of discardable trash for more rational ends. Nation-states
are instruments for the domination of other nation-states and for
the domination of the natural world. If we are to remove this
fixation on domination that first appeared with the emergence of
hierarchy, particularly with the domination of women by men, we
are in dire need of local communities, technologies, and a political
culture that will bring people into a face-to-face relationship with
their natural habitat and the communities around them. In such
communities, technology will then hopefully cease to be a force
for âdominating natureâ as the received wisdom of our era would
have it. Indeed, like the political culture that is meant to bring
citizens into a participatory relationship with each other, we can
expect that such ecologically oriented municipalities will see
themselves as integral parts of the natural world and technology
as a way of fostering natural fecundity rather than exploiting or
vitiating it.
We five today in a world that casts relationships oppositionally,
not integratively. Mind is set against body, thought against materiality, individual against community, urban belts against towns,
towns against countryâand humanity as a whole against a natural
world that is seen as âstingy,â âcruel,â and âintractable,â a world
that has to be conquered by science and technology before society
can hope to be free. Nation-states and corporate enterprises invoke large-scale technology presumably to achieve this very end.
They not only presuppose the basic divisions that have separated
humanity from nature but exacerbate them as justification for the
rationalization and exploitation of human labor. Urbanization is
the physical expression of this divisive reality at one of its most
fundamental levels: the place where people live, produce goods,
and consume them, indeed the most immediate arena in which
they enter into contact with each other apart from their places of
work. Urbanization not only removes these relationships and activities from the individualâs control; it undermines, simplifies, and
literally fossilizes them such that people and their habitats become
entirely inorganic, indeed synthetic objects that can be easily
manipulated and ultimately divested of all their living attributes.
To restructure our institutions into richly articulated forms, to
reorganize our relationships into creative forms of human solidarity, to reempower our communities and cities so that they can
effectively counteract state and corporate powerâindeed replace
the nation-state with politically confederated and economically
vital municipalitiesâand to create a new, nonhierarchical and
participatory relationship between humanity and nature by means
of a sensibility and technics that fosters a participatory form of
complementarity rather than atomistic antagonismsâall, taken
together as one coherent ensemble, constitute not only a desideratum of major proportions but anew ethical calling. The incarnation
of this human project is the immediate, indeed unmediated, community that enters so profoundly into the fashioning of our humanity. This is the community in which we genuinely encounter each
other, the public world that is only a bare step above our private
world, in short, our towns, neighborhoods, and municipalities. How
we begin the great project of refashioning this, public world and
articulating it institutionally, economically, eonfederally, and technically will determine whether we exist as public beings, interactively as discursive and rational human beings, or whether we
disappear in the huge maw of modern-day urbanization.
----
It is always temptingâand perhaps eminently humanâto break
away from abstractions about municipalism arid personalize them
in the hard realities of oneâs own experiences. I have hesitated to
fix my general coriclusions in speculative details. Utopias have a
bad way of becoming fixed blueprintsâafter which they degenerate into inflexible dogmas. But perhaps it would not be amiss if I
take the liberty of fleshing out some of my speculations with my
lived experience, notably in the urban area with which I am most
fa mil iar at the present timeâBurlington, Vermontâand in the
âbioregionâ I know best, the excitingly libertarian state of Vermont. Reduced to basics, it is in these two areas that my speculations may take on some concrete meaning that has relevance to
problems that face many urban dwellers today.
Vermont, the fourteenth state to enter the original union of
thirteen American colonies,âwas a free republic between 1777 and
1791, and it still retains many of the libertarian traditions, of that
revolutionary era. This historical legacy may make it somewhat
exceptional, but it does not make the area any less real. That
Vermont exists is a fact that is existentially more real than many
myths that have moved human beings over the ages to greater acts
of nobility than reality itself. One thinks, here, of the Judeo-Christian tradition that kept the Jews intact for two thousand years of
incredible persecution and also sent other millionsâtheir Christian brethrenâinto bloody spiritual conflicts over the same span
of time. This is true, too, for Moslems and men and women of other
faiths. Here, I Would like to, repeat the caveat that what humans
think of themselves, however fancifully, often determines their
behavior more decisively than their âobjectiveâ material interestsâmany social thinkers, including Marx, to the contrary notwithstanding.
So it is with Vermont, or, for that matter, America and the rest
of the world. If history would have it otherwise and people acted
immediately, even ultimately, according to their âobjectiveâ or
material interests, this world would long have been the best of all
possible worldsâor maybe the worst, depending very much on
what one regards as objective. Iriany case, Vermont thinks of itself
as what America âused to beâ rather than what it is today and
often acts upon this self-conception as though it were true. Generally, this means that the state is remarkably unencumbered by the
extravagant amount of statecraft that afflicts so many other American states. It has a citizensâ legislature in which no elected official
apart from the executive branch (the governor, a modest bureaucracy, the police, and judiciary) receives a livable, full-time salary
for public service and must answer for his or her public service
every two years in contrast to the four-year terms that prevail in
most of the United States. The accessibility of nearly all public
officials, including the stateâs governor, to the public has few
equals in most Euro-American republics; face-to-face discussion,
inquiries, and debates turn politics into a very intimate affair;
Vermonters would not have it otherwise. They take for granted a
wide array of political rights that would be regarded as deferential
privileges in almost any sizable political jurisdiction.
Vermont is also town-meeting countryâindeed vigorous town-meeting country notwithstanding the ritualistic articles that appear annually in *The New York Times* and *Wall Street Journal*
that lament the decline of these remarkable democratic institutions. Having attended many town meetings over the past fifteen
years, I can personally attest to their vitality. In fact, I have seen
a remarkable resurgence of town meetirig democracy in Vermont,
partly because the citizenry has begun to treasure the power this
institution accords them in a period of growing centralism elsewhere; partly, too, because town meetings have intervened into
international affairs such as the nuclear-breeze issue and have
given these Yankee Americans an enhanced sense of âgrass-rootsâ
control over seemingly historic public affairs. This control, to be
sure, is strictly moral; it does not carry the ponderous weight of
law. But it isâ characteristically American that a republican national
constitution, permeated by a countervailing revolutionary democratic tradition, has given rise to a state of mind that imparts a
higher authority to a grass-roots moral movement than a legislative mandate. In this case, American politics can be credited with
being more vulnerable to moral movements than its critics fully
realize, Vermontâs town meetings, like those of its New England
neighbors, are often more effective nationally than they truly realize, precisely because they are hallowed by moral traditions that
give America its national identity. It is the enormous weight of
their moral voice, their invocation of an ethically charged past that
ha un ts the present with its ambience of virtue and freedom, that
gives them enormous potential power for social change.
This past affects the so-called âcitiesâ of Vermont, not only its
small towns and villages. Despite the fact that Vermontâs few
sizable townsâparticularly Burlington, its largest, with a population of 37,000âare structured around a mayoralty system with a
typical board of aldermen, election day is still called âtown-meeting day.â The possibility of restructuring Burlingtonâs âbig cityâ
apparatus around town meetings, each located in one of the cityâs
six wards, has been in the air for more than a decade. Personally,
this writer raised such a proposal fifteen years ago, and it began
to surface in the cityâs political discourse in 1981, when a conference of Burlingtonâs neighborhood organizations passed a very
strong âresolve,â taking up my proposal and voting it through
almost unanimously. Thereafter, in September 1982, Burlingtonâs
Board of Aldermen accepted a more attenuated structure of
âNeighborhood Planning Assembliesâ (NPAs) to implement citizen participation in the allocation of federal community-development block grants. NPAs were thereupon established in each of
the wards and proceeded to formulate constitutions for periodic
meetings, coordinating committees, and the like. They were open
to all registered voters of a given ward, although their agendas
were often presented by agencies in the mayorâs office.
By adding the word âplanningâ to the words âneighborhood
assembly,â the cityâs mayoral administration (which is headed by
a fairly authoritarian âsocialistâ mayor for whom leadership often
is equatable with a high degree of âpaternalismâ) limits the assembliesâ power to a largely consultative role. At this writing, the
situation is very much in flux: the NPAs are occasionally âassembledâ by agencies in the mayorâs office to rubber stamp or give
legitimation to the mayorâs pet schemes. In still other cases, they
do exhibit a certain amount of initiative. Generally, the life of the
assemblies has been muted by the centralistic or paternalistic behavior of this highly self-centered âsocialistâ mayor who is committed, together with his âclass enemy,â the business community,
to economic growth, expansionist âplanningâ notions, and a presumably âradicalâ version of Reaganesque âsupply-sideâ economics in which the âpoor, the elderly, and the working peopleâ (to
use City Hallâs most favored nouns) are supposed to indirectly
benefit from the construction of hotels, condominiums, boutiques,
department stores, and the like. That this kind of âgrowthâ has
significantly changed Burlington physically and produced major
economic differences between its poorer neighborhoods and more
well-to-do ones is an experience that is not unique to the otherwise
easy-going communities of northern New England.
What can be done in a city like thisâand, for that matter, in a
state like Vermont?
Minimally, Burlington could benefit enormously from a municipalist political movement whose candidates are ultimately mandated and recallable by citizensâ assemblies. I refer not to the
NPAs, which are actually gerrymandered ward organizations, but
to assemblies that are rooted in authentic neighborhoods where
the citizenry shares common economic, cultural, and political interests. Such neighborhoods exist in Burlington, as they do in
many cities and towns of America. But they have been shrewdly
amalgamated with other neighborhoods, often very different in
character, to produce a melange of conflicting interests that favor
oligarchic control of municipal politics.
These mandated and recallable delegatesâin no way to be
confused with ârepresentativesâ who are free to make policy decisionsâcould initially form a âboard of aldermenâ or, if you like, a
council of assembly delegates to parallel the official aldermanic
board itself. The council, while legally powerless in its initial
phases, could exercise a very effective moral influence on the
official Board of Aldermen until it acquires increasing legal power
of its own. It could track the agenda and business of the official
board in every detail, expand it at will, or challenge such legislative measures that it finds unsuitable in the public interest. By the
same token, it could run its own regular aldermanic candidates
who, hopefully, would be expected to act as a voice for the parallel
council within the city administration. All actions of the council,
in turn, would have to be confirmed or could be altered by the
assemblies so that each delegate would merely be the repository
of his or her assemblyâs views on specific issues.
Optimally, it would be the goal of the Council of Assembly
Delegates to replace the Board of Aldermen and institute genuine
town-meeting democracy in Burlington. There is no reason why,
from a strictly administrative viewpoint, such a change would
affect in any way the normal operations of the city. The only
objection to this system of self-governance I have encountered is
that it is âtoo democratic,â not that it is âdisruptive.â Such objections generally imply that the citizenry of the city is âincompetentâ to deal with public matters, an objection that could obviously be raised against town-meeting governance itself if its
centuries of success were not compelling testimony to the contrary.
What I have described for Burlington could exist for Vermont
as a whole. Actually, until the late 1960s, state government in
Vermont was largely run by the municipalities. The stateâs House
of Representatives was chosen by townships, riot by electoral districts based on population numbers. Accordingly, large Vermont,
towns had two representatives for example, and small communities had one. Towns thus directly controlled the House, not anonymous voters who were demographic ally agglomerated together
with no political roots in a civic collectivity. Admittedly, a system
so constricted to one or two representatives from a city or township favored a minority of voters, generally rural at the expense
of urban populations, but politics was conducted in a more organic
fashion than it is today. Town-meeting discussions favored a decent measure of public consensus and widespread public participation in a richer political process than mere âvoting.â Voters
were not mere spectators in a legislative duel conducted in the
state capital; they came fairly close to being direct participants in
it, placing their representatives under regular public review at
town meetings or in the daily life of their communities. A 1966
U.S. Supreme Gourt decision, the famous âone vote for one voterâ
decision, swept this structure away as an âundemocraticâ archaism. However faulty the original systemâfaults that could have
easily been corrected by increasing the representation of larger
communities, not by eliminating this kind of representation completelyâVermonters were not reduced to a mere electorate or its
politically concerned people turned into mere constituqnts..
Federal law preempts state lawâin Vermont, of course, no less
than other American states, although the Vermont Senate, from
its inceptioii early in the nineteenth century, has always been
elected from couritywide voting,districts. Hence, there is a sense
in which both systems, the strictly electoral one as well as the
municipal one, coexisted throughout most of the stateâs history
and, balanced each other out. Short of changing the federal Constitution itsfelf, there is no way in which this balance can be restored
or made more equitable. Nor would it be desirable for any legislative body to structure itself around a system that provides one vote
in the House for a, sparsely populated township and the same for
another that is densely populated. But there is no reason why a
third house in addition to the Senate and House of Representatives cannot be established on a statewide basis, a Council of Assembly Delegates, from all the townships and cities of Vermont,
which would function as a *moral* monitor of the official state legislature. This âparallelâ ethical system of governance, legitiinated
by the will of the people in yermontâs municipalities and corresponding to the âsecond chamberâ in Burlingtonâs civic government, could âenactâ its own âlawsâ and ordinances^ carefully
scrutinizirig, criticizing, and correcting legislation that is under
consideration in the Senate and House. It could function as the
popular voice of the citizenry articulated into communities rather
than anonymous voters. No less than in Burlington, the delegates
of such a statewide council could be mandated and recallable by
the communities from which they are chosen, and their choice
would be more reflective of populatiori differences than the House
that existed before the 1966 Supreme Court decision.
I would like to advance a more general argument: firstly, that
the emergence of paralegal and morally powerful assemblies of
delegates from the, townships and cities of Vermont as well as
within the stateâs cities could begin to create a radically new political climate, activating Vermontâs citizens and profoundly influencing the very nature of legislation and ways of legislating in
the state. With a visibly grass-roots and institutionalized assembly
of municipal delegates tracking a less representative state legislature, Vermontâs politics could probably change in a very crucial
way. Governance by legislative command, with its panoply of
penalties and coercion, would begin to yield to governance by
moral suasion, with its evocation of public responsibility and individual probity. Statecraft, which has always been premised on the
publicâs incompetence to govern itself and its ultimate recourse to
violence, would increasingly give way to politics with its classical
vision of community life as an ethical compact. This conceptual
framework, which sees human consociation as a distinctly human,
and humane, attribute of individual socializationâso markedly in
contrast to the egoistic and interest-oriented, indeed disciplinary
image of the contemporary public sphereâwould mark a highly
significant turn in the way we conceive the management of society
and the participation of its citizenry in the political process. A dual
structure of municipal government, paralleling the stateâs conventional legal structure, could open a creative institutional restructuring of the body politicâone that would not only countervail the
centralizing and destructuring process of urbanization and growing state power but introduce a new principle of politics based on
morality as well as cooperation and personal responsibility.
Secondly, I would like to point out that the leap from local to
statewide forms of municipal control, even in so small a state as
Vermont, may well open an institutional gap between town and
state that could create a problematic area for a hybridized form
of statecraft, neither political nor statistâone that would vitiate
the entire project of a moral politics. What is worth recognizing
is that the county system in Vermont provides a remarkable arena
not only for closing this structural gap but also for enhancing this
new kind of politics. Vermontâs seventeen counties, patched together by their quiltwork of numerous townships, provide an almost ideal jurisdictional unit for municipal confederations, each of which could be united by its own County Confederation of
Municipalities and organized in all essentials like the councils of
assembly delegates within the cities and the Council of Assembly
Delegates for the entire state. These countywide confederations
would have the extremely important function of pooling the resources of Vermontâs townships and cities to maintain roads,
schools, public lands, and provide many other vital services that
have been preempted by the conventional state government and
legitimate its increasingly centralized powers. The countywide
confederations would thus not only enhance the moral authority
of Vermontâs municipal assemblies and form a connecting link
between the townships and their statewide council; they would
become the all-important material repository for reclaiming the
financial control exercised by the legislature and executive branch
over vital services such as road maintenance, services that cannot
be dealt with alone by smaller communities in the state.
The municipalization of Vermontâs economy would have to
occur in piecemeal steps, I suspect, and on many different levels,
indeed in such a way as not to infringe on the proprietary rights
of small retail outlets, service establishments, artisan shops, small
farms, local manufacturing enterprises, and the like. Rather, this
process might **begin as a transitional measure** with the reclamation of public lands by the municipalities, indeed where funds
exist with the purchase of sizable enterprises, particularly those
that are failing financially and could be managed more efficiently
by their workers than by profit-oriented entrepreneurs. The use
of land trusts as a means not only for providing good public housing but promoting small-scale, often artisanal production would
occupy a high place on the agenda of a municipalityâs economic
program. Cooperatives, farms, and small retail outlets would be
fostered with municipal funds and placed under growing public
controlâa policy that might very well command greater consumer loyalty than we would expect to find toward failing corporate enterprises.
Viewed in a still broader perspective, it is crucially important
that a municipal movement foster a new psychological ambienceâa sense of civic loyalty and responsibility that would make each
citizen feel committed to the success of a moral economy. Even
more than the well-known âunderground economyâ that has
revived barter and mutual aid in the exchange of goods and services, the municipalityâs citizens would have to feel that they have
a personal stake in the communityâs welfare. This is a function of
citizen empowerment, not of political rhetoric. A citizenâs stake in
a moral economy has to be real and visible in the sense that the
municipalityâs economy has to be public business in a highly expressive and democratic formâthe subject of vigorous discussion
in neighborhood assemblies and town meetings, the object of voluntary services, stemming from a highly personalized knowledge
of how the economy is functioning as well as how it can he enhanced by greater citizen participation.
A moral economy is either a moral enterprise that is guided by
a genuine spiritual desire to create one, even at the expense of
strictly economic considerations, or it will degenerate into another
profit-oriented and exploitative, use of resources. Citizens who are
not prepared to pay higher prices to support such an economy and
volunteer their own efforts on its behalf are not likely to be prepared for self-governance in. any form. Hence the need for a new
municipal politics to become an intensely educational and participatory experience at every level of civic life. The appalling
failure of so many âprogressiveâ movements in the towns and
cities of America to recognize the need for civic *paideia* in the
classical meaning of the term accounts for the repeated compromises that have made the heroic periods of their administrations
so listless and routine after a few years in office. Doubtless, a full
armamentorium of economic, fiscal, and administrative devices
can be psed to make a municipalist politics workable; for example,
Proudhonâs vision of a âPeopleâs Bankâ that will collect funds from
the populace at large to finance municipal projects; the direct sale
of locally grown food from farmer to consumer that will provide
special price advantages for both; more barter, comprehensive
mutual aid networks, and the use of public land to foster domestic
gardeningâthese are only some of the many possible projects that
could give tangibility to a moral economy. The fostering of civic
voluntarism, such as unpaid public efforts to construct community
centers, parks, squares, and other structures that would provide
citizens with places for public discussion and personal intercourse,
and efforts to collect funds (a sort of voluntary taxation, if you like)
to beautify and improve the communityâall can be viewed as
moral challenges to the citizenryâs civic probity and its commitment to assume responsibility for its own community. But none of
these efforts or projects are likely to succeed if a new politics is not
educational, indeed if it is not a new form of civic enlightenment
that challenges the citizenry to take control of its own community.
It may well be that this *civicisme*, as the French called it two
centuries ago, can no longer flourish in an urbanized world that
has been so extensively commodified and permeated by a market
economy. But it may well be that precisely because of the deep
frustration this urbanized and commodified world has produced,
the will to create a new politics, citizenship, ecologically viable
habitat, and municipal economy lies directly below the surface of
conventional behavior as we know it today, waiting to break
through if creative and imaginative alternatives are developed.
Much of this book consists primarily of accounts drawn mainly
from the past that demonstrate how the hidden aspirations of
ordinary people welled up and exploded into powerful localist
movements that profoundly redefined politics and citizenship in
ways that emphasized the authority of the community over the
state and self-empowerment over statecraft. There is no reason to
believe that the most human of impulses, the need for consociation and community support, can be irretrievably cast into a limbo
from which there is no redemption. Indeed, once released, this
impulse often tends to surge forward beyond all the prescribed
boundaries we normally impose upon it. If state power begets
state power, so too does self-governance beget self-governance. It
has seldom failed that whatever power people gain from the state,
the state, in turn, loses institutionally as well as legitimately. A
historic verdict that will finally place the state over the municipality has yet to be rendered conclusively. The greater danger we,
face is that even those localists most committed in theory may
have lost the existential commitment to turn their visions into
practice. Sweeping as urbanization may be today, it has still not
swept the ideal of the free, confederally organized municipality
from the agenda of historyâand as long as it exists there, it is
something devoutly worth fighting for.
----
Never has it been so necessary to place every innovative practice in
the light of a visionary ethical ideal. Ironically, this is the great
edge that reaction has over progress: its shrewd emphasis on ethics
and matters of spirit in an increasingly meaningless as well as
materialistic world. It has been noted With irony that Nazism
achieved much of its success among the German people a half
century ago not because of any economic panaceas it offered in
opposition to its competitors from the center and left but because
of its mythic ideal of nationhood, community, and social regeneration. In more recent times, reactionary movements in America
have won millions to their cause on such moral grounds as the
integrity of the family, religious dogma, the renewal of patriotism,
and the right to lifeâa message, I may add, that has been construed not only as a need for antiabortion legislation but as a hypostasization of the sacredness of the individual, born as well as
unborn.
Characteristically, liberal and radical causes are still mired in
economistic and productivistic panaceas. Their moral message,
once a heightened plea for social justice, has given way increasingly to strictly material demands. Far more than the right, which
avows egoism even as it emphasizes community virtues, the political middle ground and the left avow a solid bourgeois gospel of
bread on the table and money in the bank. The spiritual emptiness
that a market society produces in such large numbers of Americans has largely ceased to be a problem of the very people who
profess to oppose that society, a failure in ethical vision that has
left them isolated and puzzled.
The word âmoralâ must be repeatedânot as rhetoric to match
the claims of reaction but as the felt spiritual underpinnings of a
new social vision. It must be repeated not as part of a patronizing
sermon but as a living practice that people incorporate into their
personal lives and their communities. The vacuity and triviality of
life today must be filled precisely by those visionary ideals that
sustain the human side of life as well as its material side, or else
the coordinates by which the future should be guided will totally
disappear in that commodity oriented world we call the âmarketplace of ideas.â The more serious indecency of this âmarketplaceâ
is that these ideals will be turned into objectsâmere commoditiesâthat will lack even the value of things we need to sustain us.
They will become the mere ornaments needed to garnish an inherently antihuman and antiecological society that threatens to
undermine moral integrity as such and the simple social amenities
that foster human intercourse.
A municipal agenda to countervail urbanization and all that it
signifies is not a mere program, such as we expect from rival
parties and electoral coalitions. Programs, whether âgreenâ or
âred,â radical or liberal, are shopping fists of demands, precisely
suited for that âmarketplace of ideasâ we have misnamed âpolitics.â They are ideological agents for effacing crucial differences in
outlook. The need for thinking out ideas and giving them coherence, which alone imparts meaning to an agenda for a new municipal politics, is lost and in that loss is replaced by the chaos of
ideological confusion. A cranky pluralism replaces a stern appreciation of focused thinking; a confused eclecticism replaces the need
for wholeness, clarity, and consistency. The ecology movement
and movements for a new politics have been plagued by this
indigestible fare for decades, a problem that has grown even
worse due to the cultural illiteracy that plagues American society.
Any attempt to countervail urbanization and replace it with a
new politics and authentic citizenship must not only be a movement for ethical renewal, clearly focused in its analysis and goals;
it must also be a movement that has a sense of âhome,â as it were,
as well as a sense of mission. Most movements that derive from the
liberal center or the left are notable for their lack of any roots in
traditions that are dear to Americans or articulate the best in their
history. Given the emphasis of these movements on centralism,
planning, coordination, and mass mobilization, they stand inherently at odds with a creative American legacy that formulated its
ideals of freedom around decentrafism, popular initiative, confederation, and individualismâideals that admittedly can be degraded by manipulative reactionaries for authoritarian ends but
can also be enlarged and given a more responsive, humanistic
meaning for more emancipatory goals. That decentrafism can
mean local parochialism, even racism; confederation, a denial of
any rational coordination of resources and services; and individualism, a psychology of rampant egotismâall are simply the most
negative way of viewing a constellation of notions whose logic can
yield genuine freedom. That these very ideals of freedom guided
the radical movements of heretical Christianity centuries ago,
nourished the English, American, and French revolutions in a
more recent time, inspired the Communards of 1871, and surfaced again in Spain during the 1930s as well as among various
citizensâ and civic movements during the past two generations
should be enough to give the most sectarian radicals pause before
denouncing them. It remains to the great credit of early populism,
not only in America but in Russia and Spain, embellished by their
own anarchistic traditions, to have extracted the diamond of radicalism from the rubbish heap of reaction. A new politics and sense
of citizenship in America still awaits a movement that can occupy
itself with the difficult process of separating the jewel from its
matrix and making it glitter as it once did.
It will not do to live on a diet of hating America because of its
adventures abroad or its mistreatment of ethnic minorities at
home any more than it will due to immunize the country from
criticism by dressing it in a flag and perverting its revolutionary
origins in a struggle for freedom. Indeed, it would be a far more
worthy and historically sound enterprise to disengage the democratic traditions and institutions of the country such as its town
meetings and its Bill of Rights from a very mistaken notion that
they are, entangled with the âbourgeoisie,â whatever this word
means these days. The words âbourgeois democracyâ turn history
into a canard: the real bourgeoise of the past never favored democracy in any form. A more searching account of the great democratic revolutions of two centuries ago reveals that they were
committed primarily to a constitutional monarchy and only resigned themselves to an oligarchic form of republicanism whose
model was senatorial Rome. It was the people, often of varied class
origins, who foisted the liberties we enjoy today on the possessing
classes, classes that consistently tried to pervert them and are still
in the business of perverting them. Tragically; reaction has been
permitted to appropriate the âAmerican Dreamâ and give it a
chauvinistic meaning while liberals arid radicals have mocked it,
degrading it in their own way for ends that are often no less
authoritarian than those of their opponents.
Yet this âAmerican Dreamâ has many faces, and it still remains
to be seen whether its most liberatory, visionary, and utopian
aspects will find expression in the credo of a new politics. One face
of the dream was born in yeoman New Erigland, where community acquired ascendancy over privatism; individuality over egotism; decentralism over the concentration of power; direct democracy over republicanism. Another face was born in the cowboy
west, where the privatism of the ruggedly individualistic âlone
riderâ was hypostasized over the âfence-rearingâ farmer and his
family; where egoism was enclosed by the perimeter of the lonely
campfire; where to be armed was a token not of the free citizen
but the marauding gun slinger; and where social chaos prevailed
over democracy and republicanism,alike. Still another face of the
âAmerican Dreamâ was added by the late-coming immigrant for
whorri American cities were not only refuges from European oppression but, as the maxim has it, where âthe streets were paved
with gold.â This face featured no particular virtues beyond personal security from arbitrary rule and material well-being. History
has scrambled these faces together so that they now appear a blur,
not a unified tradition in which one face stands at odds with the
others.
A municipal agenda that does not piece together the emancipatory features of the âAmerican Dreamâ such that this agenda can
speak in a clear and unqualified voice to the American people will
not be worth the paper on which it is written. Americans, no less
than Europeans, must recover, a whole that has been served up to
them in fragments: their history as a story of human freedom, not
merely as the history of the freedom of property, trade, and the
unbridled egoism of greed. For decades, social innovators have
talked to the American people in German (Marx), Russian (Lenin),
Chinese (Mao), Vietnamese (Ho Chi Minh), indeed in virtually
every language but Englishâwhich is to say, in the language of
traditions and âismsâ that are largely incomprehensible to Americans. An ethical and visionary case can now be made, perhaps
more than at any time before, that community, individuality, decentralism, and direct democracy are ideologically more âhomelikeâ than ârugged individualism,â egoism, gun slinging, and
chaos. Arriericans have welcomed this yeoman American message
eagerlyâas the cynical right and one of the countryâs oldest presidents have clearly demonstratedâonly to see it betrayed into a
cowboy parody. They no longer believe that their âstreets are
paved with gold,â if only because the immigrant generation that
accepted this myth has already passed into history. The political
landscape is open again for the revival of a dream that emphasizes
community, decentralism, individuality, and direct democracy.
The yearning to render it applicable to a modern America is intense, if only it can be properly articulated and earnestly advanced. It will be an unpardonable failure in political creativity if
a movement that professes to speak for a new politics does not try
to occupy that landscape but rather, in a self-indulgent âhate
Americaâ mood, debarks to a âThird Worldâ ideological ghetto
abroad with shrieks about the ââmad dogs of imperialism,â snarling
perpetually at its most natural allies at homeâthe ordinary citizen
desiccated by his or her own spiritual poverty.
Nor can a new politics ignore the most essential attribute of that
dream: its molecular nature and its gradual development from
neighborhood and town to county and region. Dreams are more
than party platforms, which are normally violated or ignored.
Attempts to reconstruct an authentic politicsânot another ensemble of statecraft techniquesâinvolve a remaking of the body
politic itself: politics conceived as the recovery of citizenship and
civic education. This kind of politics has an almost cellular form of
growth, a process that involves organic proliferation and differentiation such as that of a child in a womb. To âengineerâ a politics
into existence the way one puts together an automobile engine
with its engine block, gaskets, cylinders, spark plugs, and the like
is to desecrate the meaning of the word âpolitics,â itself, not to
speak of the disdain it exhibits for the human freight that this
engine is meant to bring to polling booths and the âcitizenryâ or
âvotersâ it is meant to mobilize. Until the social innovators of our
day discard the notion that the âpolitical processâ is a matter of
mobilization rather than education, of charismatic leaders rather
than participatory citizens, of âbread-on-the-tableâ panaceas
rather than visionary ideals charged with ethical meaning, their
politics, far from being ânew,â will be the old authoritarian statecraft garnished with mere rhetoric.
A new political agenda is necessarily a municipal agendaâor it
is neither an agenda for remaking society nor politics in any meaningful sense of the term. The living cell which forms the basic unit
of political life is the municipality from which everything else
must emerge: confederation, interdependence, citizenship, and
freedom. There is no way to piece together any politicsâold or
newâunless we begin with its most elementary forms: the villages, towns, neighborhoods, and cities in which people live on the
most immediate level of political interdependence, the only level
that is the next step beyond private life. It is on this level that they
can begin to gain a familiarity with the political process, a process
that involves a good deal more than âvotingâ and âinformationââa term that has become the modern substitute for wisdom. It is
on this level that they can go beyond the privateness and parochialism of family lifeâa life that is celebrated for its inwardness and
seclusionâand improvise those public institutions that make for
participation and consociation. In short, it is from the municipality
that people can reconstitute themselves from isolated monads into
a creative body politic and create an existentially vital, indeed
protoplasmic, civic life that has institutional form as well as civic
content: the block committees, assemblies, neighborhood organizations, cooperatives, citizensâ action groups, and public arena for
discourse that go beyond such episodic acts as demonstrations and
retain a lived as well as organized continuity. To ignore this irreducible civic unit of political life is to play chess without a chessboard,
for it is here that the coordinates exist for playing the game in its
most direct, basic, and intimate sense.
I have tried in this book to formulate a body of ideas that have
meaning for the political restructing of our times, not another
handbook that offers recipes for how to make a ârevolutionâ in
oneâs backyard or front lawn. I have tried to suggest a political
philosophy that lends itself to modification, extension, and a decent regard for the great variety of needs that distinguish one
community from another, not a blueprint that dogmatizes and
rigidifies the idea of freedom into an inflexible credo. But I do not
seek to rarify this political philosophy of civicism into a mere
intellectual duel with abstract philosophies that stand in opposition to it. This book has been thoroughly informed by historyânot
because I seek lived âprecedentsâ for truths that deserve to rest
on their own intrinsic worth rather than âexpediencyâ or, to use
what has become a synonym for that term, âefficiency.â Political
life is not legitimated by how well it âworks.â If it were, totalitarianism could be more successfully legitimated because it is generally more âefficientâ than democracy, just as business techniques
are more âeffectiveâ than that âwastefulâ process involved inâ debates and free forms of decision making. Doubtless, âtime is
money,â but freedom is a way of life that even money cannot buyâor certainly should not.
My recourse to history and to speculations about my own community, Burlington, and its Vermont setting is primarily an endeavor to show that living human beings, not their science-fiction
replicas, actually engaged in and continue to involve themselves
in a political process that may initially seem visionary when it is
presented abstractly. I have tried to show that our contemporary
market society; only three or four decades old at best, and our
two-centuries-old market economy were preceded by a far more
mixed society and economy, possibly four centuries old, that
phased out of a rigidly structured feudalworld, later to phase into
a chaotically destructured capitalist world. What men and women
have done in the past and, in some degree, continue to do today
can certainly be recovered again. These people were no less real
than weâall rhetoric about the fixidity of human nature to the
contrary notwithstanding; If they went from a highly structured
world through a centuries-long âtransitionâ formed around a
highly mixed, almost ecological economy and society, to a very
recent destructured market society, who is to say which of the
three is merely âtransitional,â âclimatic,ââ or constitutes evidence
of a steady ascent in history? It may well be that our present-day
market society is evidence of social regression, not of social progress; indeed that the insane proliferation of commodity relationships that embodies all human ties in mere objects constitutes a
cancer of social life as such, not, as Marx would have it, a âpreconditionâ for a free society in an idealized, Eurocentric image of social progress.
This book has also been informed by another belief: power that
is not retained by the people is power that is given over to the
state. Conversely, whatever power the people gain is power that
must be taken away from the state. There can be no institutional
vacuum where power exists: it is either invested in the people or
it is invested in the state. Where the two âshareâ power, this
condition is only temporary and extremely precarious. Sooner of
later, the control of society arid its destiny will either shift toward
the people and their communities at its base or the professional
practitioners of statecraft at its summit. Only if the whole pyramidal structure is dismembered and turned from a vertical hierarchy
into a horizontal ecocommunityâmodelled more on what ecologists diagram as a âfood webâ than a âfood pyramidâ (with humans invariably at its apex)âwill the issue of power and domination as
such disappear and be completely replaced by participation and
the principle of complementarity.
Power, however, must be conceived as real, indeed solid and
tangible, not only as spiritual and psychological. To ignore the fact
that power is a muscular fact of life is to drift from the visionary
into the ethereal and mislead the public as to its crucial significance in affecting societyâs destiny. What this means is that if
power is to be regained by the people from the state, the management of society must be deprofessionalized as much as possible.
That is to say, it must be simplified and rendered transparent,
indeed, clear, accessible, and manageable such that most of its
affairs can be run by ordinary citizens. This notion, with its emphasis on amateurism as distinguished frorn professionalism, is not
new. It formed the basis of Athenian democratic practice for generations. Indeed, it was so ably practiced that sortition rather than
election formed the basis of the *polis*âs democracy. It was to resurface again repeatedly, for example, in the very simple constitution
written by Vermontâs yeomanry two centuries ago, a constitution
that is still notable for the brevity of its articles and the minimal
amount of statute law that clothes it.
Power is also a solid and tangible fact to be reckonedâwith
militarily, notably in the ubiquitous truth that the power of the
state or the people eventually reposes in force. Whether or not the
state has power depends upon whether or not the state exercises
a monopoly of violence. By the same token, whether or not the
people have power depends upon whether or not it is armed and
creates its own grass-roots militia, not only to guard itself from
criminals or invaders but also from the ever-encroaching power of
the state itself. Here, too, the Athenian and Vermont yeomen
knew only too well that a professiorial military was a threat to
liberty and the state was a vehicle for disarming the people.
A true civicism that tries to create an authentic politics, an
empowered citizenry, and a municipalized economy would be a
vulnerable project indeed if it failed to replace the police, the
professional army, even that pseridomilitia, the National Guard,
with an authentic militia, a civic guard, composed of rotating
patrols for police purposes and well-trained citizen military contingents for dealing with external dangers to freedom. Greek democracy would never have survived the repeated assaults of the
Greek aristocracy without its militia of citizen **hoplites**, those foot
soldiers who could answer the call to arms with their own weapons
and elected commanders. The tragic history of the stateâs ascendancy over autonomous municipalities, even the history of the rise
of oligarchy within free cities of the past, is the story of armed
professionals who commandeered power from unarmed peoples
or disarmed them presumably (as so many liberals would have it
today) from the âhazardsâ of domestic and neighborhood âshootouts.â Typically, this is the cowboy or âgunslingersâ image of the
âAmerican Dream,â often cynically imposed on its more traditional yeoman face.
----
Beyond the immediate agenda i have presented thus far lies another
one: a political world in which the state as such will finally be
replaced by a confederal network of municipal assemblies; the
corporate economy reduced to a truly political economy in which
municipalities, interacting with each other economically as well as
politically, will resolve their material problems as citizen bodies in
open assemblies, not simply as professionals, farmers, and blue- or
white-collar workers. Not only will they then transform themselves from occupational beings into public beings, but they will
create a world in which all weapons can indeed be beaten into
plowshares and ultimately a human ecocommunity that will be
exquisitely tailored psychologically and spiritually as well as technologically, archictecturally, and structurally to the natural eco-communities that compose our planet.
I would hope that such an agenda would offer an image of a
nonhierarchical as well as a classless community in which differentiation, natural as well as social, is respected without that divisive
sense of âothernessâ that has produced such disastrous effectsâon
our relationship with our own kind and the life forms that share
the planet with us.
This second agenda for a more distant future embodies the
âultimateâ vision I have elaborated in greater detail in my previous writings. Its achievement can no longer be seen as a sudden
ârevolutionâ that within a brief span of time will replace the
present society with a radically new one. Actually, such revolutions never really happened in history as the litany of their failures
so dramatically reveals. Even the French Revolution, which radicals have seized upon as a âparadigmâ of sudden social change,
was generations in preparation and did not come to its end until
a century later, when the last of the *sans culottes* were virtually
exterminated on the barricades of the Paris Commune.
Nor can there be any myth today that barricades are more than
symbols and a civic guard is little more than a first step toward
disarming the state, a feeble step at that, albeit a crucial assertion
of where the âmonopoly of violenceâ should really reposeâif violence can be mitigated in a world that is overstocked with nuclear
bombs. What links my minimal agenda to my ultimate one is a
process, an admittedly long development in which the existing
institutions and traditions of freedom are slowly enlarged and
expanded. âRevolutionâ originally meant the restoration of.traditional rights in the context of a changed world, a legitimation of
emancipation by the power and dignity of tradition. For the present, we must try to democratize the republic, a call that often is
simply defensive and consists of preserving and expanding freedoms we have earned centuries ago together with the institutions
that give them reality. For the future it means that we must
radicalize our democracy, imparting a utopian and creative content to the democratic institutions we have rescued. Admittedly,
at that point we will have moved from a countervailing position
that tries to play our democratic institutions against the state into
an aggressive attempt to replace the state with municipally based
confederal structures. It is to be devoutly hoped that by that time,
the state power itself will have been hollowed out institutionally
by local or civic structures, indeed that its very legitimacy, not to
speak of its authority as a coercive force, will simply lead to its
collapse in any period of confrontation. If the great revolutions of
the past can be used to provide us with examples of how so major
a shift is possible, it would be well to remember that seemingly
all-powerful monarchies that the republics replaced two centuries
ago were so denuded of power that they crumbled rather than
âfellâ much as a mummified corpse turns to dust after it has been
suddenly exposed to air.
Another ultimate vision also faces us: one in which urbanization
will so completely devour the city and the countryside that the
word âcommunityâ will become an archaism; a market society
filtering into the most private recesses of our lives as individuals
and effacing all sense of personality, much less individuality; a
state that will not only render politics and citizenship a mockery
of these words but a maw that will absorb the very notion of
freedom itself.
This âvision,â if such it can be called, is still sufficiently removed
from our most immediate experience so that its realization can be
arrested by those countervailing forcesâthat dual powerâI have
outlined in the previous pages. Given the persistent destructuring
of the natural world as well as the social, more than human freedom and autonomy are in the balance. The proliferation of nuclear
reactors, like that of nuclear weapons, is a reminder that we are
reaching a point of almost cosmic finality in our affairs on this
planet; that the recovery of an authentic politics and citizenship
is not only a precondition for a free society. It is also a precondition
for our survival as a species. Hanging over us is the shadow of a
completely destructured and simplified natural world as well as a
completely destructured and simplified urban worldâa natural
world so ossified and divested of its variety that we, like all other
complex life forms, will be unable to exist as viable beings.
{1} George Orwell: 1984 (New York: Signet; 1950), p. 156.
{2} James Melaart: Ăatal HĂŒyĂŒk (London: Thames and Hudson; 1967),
pg. 58.
{3} Fred Wendorf, Romuald Schied, and Angela E. Close: âAn Ancient
Harvest on the Nile,â Science 82, November, 1982, pg. 68.
{4} Ibid., p. 73.
{5} Karl Polanyi: Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economics: Essays of
Karl Polanyi, George Dalton, ed. (Boston: Beacon Press; 1968), p. 81.
{6} Jean-Jacques Rousseau: The Social Contract (New York: Everyman
Edition; 1950), p. 15.
{7} Aristotle: Politics (London: Loeb Classical Library; 1932), 1326a30-
40. Translation modified by author.
{8} Ibid., 1280a-1280b.
{9} Aristotle, op. cit., 1252a3. Translation modified by author.
{10} Lilly Ross Taylor: Roman Voting Assemblies (Ann Arbor: University
of Michigan Press; 1966), p. 2.
{11} Ibid., p. 3.
{12} Ibid., p. 3
{13} Jean-Jacques Rousseau, op. cit., p. 94.
{14} Niccolo Machiavelli: The Prince (New York: The Modern Library
Editions; 1940), pp. 45â46.
{15} Henri Frankfort: The Birth of Civilization in the Near East (New
York: Doubleday & Co.; 1956), p. 77.
{16} M.I. Finley: Democracy-Ancient and Modern (New Brunswick,
N.J.: Rutgers University Press; 1973), p. 22.
{17} Claude Mosse: The Ancient World at Work (New York: W.W. Norton
& Co.; 1969), pp. 27â28.
{18} Alfred Zimmern: The Greek Commonwealth (New York: The Modern Library Editions; n.d.), p. 59.
{19} Plutarch: âSolonâ in The Rise and Fall of Athens (Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books, Ltd.; 1960), p. 54.
{20} Ibid., p. 62.
{21} Quoted in Thucydides: The Peloponnesian War (New York: Modern
Library Editions; 1944), pp. 121â22.
{22} T.B.L. Webster: Life in Classical Athens (London: B.T. Batsford,
Ltd.; 1969), p. 87.
{23} W.G. Forrest: The Emergence of Greek Democracy (New York:
McGraw-Hill Book Co.; 1966), p. 214.
{24} Aeschylus: *Oresteia* (Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1953),
735â40.
{25} Ibid., 681â706
{26} W.G. Forrest, op. cit., p. 204; George Thomson: Aeschylus and Athens (New York: Grosset & Dunlop; 1968).
{27} M. Rostovtzeff: Rome (London: Oxford Univerity Press; 1960), p. 104.
{28} Ibid., p. 100.
{29} Ibid., p. 104.
{30} Heinrich Heine: Reisebilder, quoted by Ian Scott-Kilvert in Makers
of Rome: Nine Lives by Plutarch (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books,
Ltd., 1965), p. 12.
{31} Chester Starr: Civilization and the Caesars (New York: W.W. Norton
& Co.; 1965), p. 90.
{32} Ibid., p. 105.
{33} John H. Mundy and Peter Riesenberg: The Medieval Town (New
York: Van Nostrand Reinhold Co.; 1958), p. 18.
{34} Lauro Martines: Power and Imagination (New York: Vintage Books;
1980).
{35} John H. Mundy in âIntroductionâ to Henri Pirenne: Early Democ-
racy in the Low Countries (New York: W. W. Norton & Co.; 1963),
p. xxii fn.
{36} Lauro Martines, op. cit., p. 27.
{37} John H. Mundy: Europe in the High Middle Ages (London: Longman
Group Ltd.; 1973), p. 409.
{38} Lauro Martines, op. cit., p. 35â36.
{39} Ibid., p. 37.
{40} Daniel Waley: The Italian City Republics (New York: McGraw-Hill
Book Co.; 1969), p. 63.
{41} Ibid., p. 63.
{42} Lauro Martines, op. cit., p. 49.
{43} Ibid., p. 52.
{44} Quoted in John H. Mundy: Europe in the High Middle Ages. op. cit.,
p. 408.
{45} Ephraim Emerton: The Beginnings of Modern Europe (New York:
Ginn and Co.; 1917), p. 207.
{46} Daniel Waley, op. cit., p. 221.
{47} Ibid.
{48} Benjamin Barber: The Death of Communal Liberty (Princeton:
Princeton University Press; 1974), p. 263.
{49} F. Furet, C. Mazauric, and L. Bergeron: âThe Sans-Culottes and the
French Revolutionâ in New Perspectives on the French Revolution,
Jeffry Kaplow, ed. (New York: John Wiley & Sons; 1965), p. 235.
{50} Ibid., pp. 234â35.
{51} Cited in Daniel Guerin: Class Struggles in the French Revolution
(London: Pluto Press; 1977), pp. 32â33.
{52} R.R. Palmer: The Age of Democratic Revolutions (Princeton: Prince-
ton University Press; 1959).
{53} Jacob Burckhardt: The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy (New
York: Phaidon Publishers; 1950), p. 2.
{54} J.A.O. Larsen: Greek Federal States (London: Oxford University
Press; 1967), p. 27.
{55} Peter Kropotkin: Mutual Aid (Montreal: Black Rose Books; n.d.).
{56} Ibid., pp. 204â5
{57} Ibid., p. 205
{58} F. Grenfell Baker, The Model Republic (New York, 1892) p. 308.
Quoted in Benjamin Barber, op. cit., pp. 14â15.
{59} Lewis Mumford: The City in History (New York: Harcourt Brace and
World; 1961), pp. 339â40.
{60} Daniel Waley, op. cit., p. 126.
{61} Perez Zagorin: Rebels and Rulers. 1500â1600, Vol. I (New York:
Cambridge University Press; 1982), p. 232.
{62} Fredrich Engels: The Peasant War in Germany (New York: International Publishers; 1926), p. 150.
{63} Cf.Joseph R. Strayer: On the Medieval Origins of the Modern State
(Princeton: Princeton University Press; 1970).
{64} Cf. Eric Hobsbawn: Primitive Rebels (Manchester: Manchester University Press; 1959).
{65} Perez Zagorin, op. cit., p. 93.
{66} Karl Marx: âPrefaceâ to A Contribution to the Critique of Political
Economy Selected Works, (Moscow: Progress Publishers; 1969), Vol.
I, p. 504.
{67} Perez Zagorin, op. cit., p. 243.
{68} Ibid., p. 244.
{69} Mary Beard: A History of Business, Vol. I (Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press; 1938), p. 50.
{70} R.S. Lopez: âThe Evolution of Land Transport in the Middle Ages,â
Past and Present, April, 1956, p. 17.
{71} Ibid., p. 18
{72} Ibid., p. 17.
{73} Cf. Paul Sweezy: âA Critiqueâ and âA Rejoinderâ in The Transition
From Feudalism to Capitalism, Rodney Hilton, ed. (London: New
Left Books; 1976), pp. 33â56, 102â8.
{74} Cf. Immanuel Wallerstein: Historical Capitalism (London: Verso
Editions; 1983).
{75} Fredrich Engels: The Condition of the Working Class in England in
1844 in Marx-Engels Collected Works, Vol. 4 (New York: International Publishers; 1975), p. 320.
{76} Ibid., p. 308.
{77} Ibid., p. 398.
{78} Ibid., p. 319.
{79} Jane Jacobs: Cities and the Wealth of Nations (New York: Random
House; 1984), pp. 31, 32.
{80} H. Mooseburger: Die Bundnerische Allemande (1891), p. 5. Quoted
in Benjamin Barber, op. cit., p. 112.
{81} Benjamin Barber, ibid., p. 15.
{82} Ibid., p. 49.
{83} Ibid., p. 100.
{84} Herman Weilenman: Pax Helvetica: Oder Die Demokratie der
Kleinen Gruppen, (Zurich, 1951). Quoted in Benjamin Barber, ibid.,
p. 101.
{85} T.H. Breen: Puritans and Adventurers (New York: Oxford University
Press; 1980), p. 3.
{86} Ibid., pp. 4â5.
{87} Massachusetts Centinal, June 24, 1786. Quoted in David P. Szat·
mary: Shaysâ Rebellion (Amherst: University of Massachusetts; 1980),
p.l.
{88} George Richard Minot, quoted in Jackson Turner Main: Political
Parties Before the Constitution (New York: Norton; 1974), p. 96 fn.
{89} David P. Szatmary, op. cit., p. 6â7.
{90} Robert A. Gross: The Minutemen and Their World (New York: Hill
and Wang; 1976), pp. 10â11.
{91} David P. Szatmary, op. cit., pp. 10â11.
{92} Ibid., p. 11.
{93} James Warren, letter to John Adams, January 28, 1785, in Warren-Adams Letters, Vol. II (Boston: Massachusetts Historical Society;
1925), p. 249. Quoted in David Szatmary, ibid., p. 11.
{94} Max Horkheimer: The Eclipse of Reason (New York: Oxford University Press; 1947), p. 135.