đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș eric-fleischmann-materialism-and-thick-libertariani⊠captured on 2024-08-18 at 23:56:59. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Materialism and Thick Libertarianism Date: August 2nd, 2022 Source: Retrieved 8/2/22 from https://c4ss.org/content/57122 Authors: Eric Fleischmann Topics: Cooperatives, Karl marx, Anti racism, Materialism, Environmentalism, Historical materialism, Localism Published: 2022-08-02 21:03:30Z
Two years ago, I gave a presentation titled âPrerequisites for Freedom: An Individualist Anarchist Perspectiveâ to a philosophy discussion group, in which I talked about the connection between thick libertarianism and 19th century North American individualist anarchism and how progressive and liberatory values are necessary for genuine and necessarily anti-capitalist individualism. For the uninitiated, the âthicknessâ in thick libertarianism is, according to Nathan Goodman, âany broadening of libertarian concerns beyond overt aggression and state power to concern about what cultural and social conditions are most conducive to liberty.â This broadening takes a number of different forms as outlined extensively by Charles Johnson: for instance, there is âstrategic thickness,â which holds that libertarians need to be concerned about problems like economic inequality because â[e]ven a totally free society in which a small class of tycoons own the overwhelming majority of the wealth, and the vast majority of the population own almost nothing is unlikely to remain free for long;â or there is âthickness from grounds,â which maintains that opposition to ostensibly non-violent hierarchy and domination emerge from the same underlying reasons as the libertarian non-aggression principle does. The cases go on, but in its general usage thick libertarianism is often understood as any libertarianism that sees ideas such as feminism, anti-racism, queer liberation, egalitarianism, and environmentalism as **essential** to any libertarian program internally and therefore desirable for external proliferation in a libertarian society. I have written extensively about thick libertarianism: in my review of Chris Matthew Sciabarraâs **Ayn Rand, Homosexuality, and Human Liberation****,** I claim that â[w]e are all thick libertarians nowâ and that itâs just a difference of whether that thickness is liberatory or reactionary; in my analysis of anarcho-capitalismâs relationship to anarchism, I argue that thickness is one of **the** defining qualities that places stateless left-libertarianism within and anarcho-capitalism outside of the anarchist canon; etc. However, I have yet to explicitly connect my endorsement of thick libertarianism with material analysis (in its dialectical form)âmy favored lens when attempting to make sense of the world. I will therefore take an opportunity to do so with this piece.
A final point I made in the aforementioned philosophy presentation was that such liberatory thickness or, as I put it, ideologico-cultural values extend to the economic realm and entail anti-hierarchy, cooperation, and worker power in the form of cooperatives, an ethico-cultural labor theory of value, â[c]ommunity land trusts, community currencies, open source technology, mutual banks, etc.â There is nothing wrong with this model from a purely individualist anarchist perspective, however I think thatâfrom my personal perspectiveâthis logic is a bit backwards. That is to say: it is actually the economic base that produces ideologico-cultural values and culture in general. This is in accordance with Karl Marxâs and Friedrich Engelsâs model of historical materialism, which Merriam-Webster defines as âthe Marxist theory of history and society that holds that ideas and social institutions develop only as the superstructure of a material economic base.â According to this view, society forms around the means of productionâland, labor, tools, machineryâand the relations of productionâproperty distribution, class divisions, the commodity formâto constitute, as Marx writes in **A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy**, onâthe economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousnessâ and, based on this core analysis, he posits in **The German Ideology** that â[t]he nature of individuals thus depends on the material conditions determining their production.â It is important to note however that the influence is not entirely unidirectional. The Marxist theorist Antonio Gramsci writes of âa necessary reciprocity between structure [aka base] and superstructure, a reciprocity which is nothing other than the real dialectical processâ that must not be ignored when attempting a complete socio-historical analysis. This overall model is often used to organize historical change through various types of societiesâslave, feudal, capitalist, socialist, communistâbut can be used on a smaller scale to demonstrate how to not only achieve immediate thick libertarian ends but also how to generate the desired thick values in general society.
[[e-f-eric-fleischmann-materialism-and-thick-liberta-2.jpg f]]
Letâs take a look at the case of producing values like anti-racism and racial egalitarianism. It must first be admitted that racism is **extremely** complicated, but one way to look at it is as a mechanism of capitalism. This can be seen on a number of levels; racism (particularly anti-Black racism), as explained by Marco La Grotta, has been used to âdivide and rule for capitalist gain.â Historically this can be seen in âthe transatlantic slave trade, which accompanied the birth of both U.S. and British capitalism. In the early days of slavery, a firm distinction hadnât yet been drawn between black slaves and white indentured servants.â So in order to quell the possibility of multi-racial rebellions, âthe U.S. ruling class developed racist theories to âproveâ the inferiority of blacks, doing so to drive a wedge between their subjects, undercut rebellion and to justify their enslavement.â This has continued into the present day through âcodifying [racism] in law, funding racist âscienceâ and broadening its scope . . . [in order for] the capitalists to drive down wages, while creating a seemingly infinite set of divisions in the working class.â Additionally, Robert Knox points out thatâŠ
[c]apitalism, as an expansive system organised around the geographically and geopolitically differentiated exploitation of labour **needs** racism. Capitalist social relations expanded internationally through the racialised dispossession of non-capitalist societies, techniques of racialisation were crucial in imposing labour discipline â up to and including slavery â on the working class, and racialisation (in sometimes subtle forms) remains key in managing and dividing populations in contemporary capitalism, both internationally and domestically.
What these analyses demonstrate is that **one way** to look at racism is as a tool to solidify and expand control by capitalists over labor and the means of production.
An response to this can then be found in the work of Cooperation Jackson, who are attempting to âdevelop a cooperative network based in Jackson, Mississippiâ built upon the âbasic theory of change . . . that organizing and empowering the structurally under and unemployed sectors of the working class, particularly from Black and Latino communities, to build worker organized and owned cooperatives will be a catalyst for the democratization of our economy and society overall.â Such a project addresses the immediate material concerns of anti-racists through community-based businesses, a living wage, non-hierarchical work relationships, etc. but on another level help produce anti-racist **values**. The main thrust of this argument is that if racism thrives in helping capitalism accomplish its imperatives of controlling the working class and expanding extraction/production, then this specific catalyst for racism can be challenged through the creation of economic communitiesâsuch as that promoted by Cooperation Jacksonâseparate from the logic of capitalism; opening up spaces for conversation, accountability, and reparations without the interference of Capital.[1] To somewhat bastardize a quote from La Grottaâs piece, the potential of this project is not âthat racist beliefs die as soon as capitalism disappearsâ or, in this model, is pushed back from autonomous spaces, it is that itâŠ
at last provides the **arena** to stomp out racism; and not only racism, but sexism, homophobia, and so on. Racism has material roots. It must therefore have a material solution.
It should be noted that this cooperative dual power strategy has been called âmarket syndicalismâ by Wesley Morgan and criticized in the same breath for still participating in the logic of capitalism as units of the market economy. But what I think this analysis misunderstands is that present existence and imperatives of âthe marketâ revolve primarily around state-sanctioned/state-enforced monopolies and direct interference by the corporate state. Since this state-capitalist influence over market action is originally rooted in violence and/or threat of violence wielded by the state, strategies that work to dissuade or circumvent said violenceâsuch as radical community self-defense and agorist practicesâcan make it possible to utilize markets autonomously of the present economy.
Another example of the connection between (dialectical) materialism and thick libertarianism is the way in which not only democratizing but also **localizing** the material base of society can help make individuals and communities more environmentally conscious and defensive. Localization, according to the P2P Foundation Wiki, describes the âproduction of goods nearer to end users to reduce environmental and other external costs of globalization.â There is a great deal of work on how this reduction in environmental costs happens, but a central point is usually that certain economic activityâwhether it be industrial agriculture or the extraction and international importation of fossil fuelâcurrently takes place at an unsustainable scale and needs to be radically scaled down (Ă la degrowth). Additionally, Helena Norberg-Hodge argues that localization âalso contributes to resiliency in the face of climate change: diverse localized production systems in an interdependent network, rather than dependence for our basic needs on far-off sources, will better equip communities to withstand the upheavals to come.â Internal to this localization is ideally the proliferation of cooperative enterprises to fill out community economies, which the UN sees as helping to ensure âsustainable consumption and production.â Although the UNâs vision of cooperatives is more globalized than localized, they do give the good examples of the IMAI Farming Cooperative in South Africa: âa womenâs cooperative that has partnered with non-profits and government institutions to turn surplus fresh vegetable produce into pickles. Through this initiative the cooperative increases the incomes of its members by adding value to their products while also reducing food waste.â They also write of the Association of Recycling Collectors and Sorters of La Paz in Bolivia, who âformed a cooperative in 2006 to overcome the waste collection challenges. Their 40 members earn a better income through recycling in total about 194 tonnes of solid waste on a daily basis, including plastic, cardboard, metals, used clothing, glass and occasionally e-waste,â the last of which is sold at an âinformal market.â Even specimens provided by the UN that are linked up with longer supply chains and multiple production or sale locations would seem to be more closely controlled by communities; and while these are only preliminary in terms of the local cooperativization of the means of production it does provide a glimpse of the future as well as a proof of concept.[2]
Once again, these directly address ecological concerns at an immediate level but in doing so can also, as stated above, help produce environmental concern among people. Democratization (through cooperatives) and localization can, for example, follow the logic of Aaron Koekâs call for âdirect confrontation with our current hierarchical conditions . . . [by] seizing the land and resources out of the hands of Capitalists and into our own. Such conditions would mean a direct interaction with individuals and their communities in regards to their immediate biological surroundings, allowing them to make rational decisions based within the knowledge and understanding that comes with localized living.â This new control over property by the masses as opposed to a small group of capitalists leads to âdirect power to affect a meaningful relationship with the biosphereâ and therefore the de-alienation of people from their local environment, allowing people to âprotect the biosphere as an extension of ourselves.â Additionally, environmental conservatives in the UK have latched on to the idea of âoikophilia,â a term originating in the work of Roger Scruton and defined by Sarah Newton as âa family of motives at whose centre is love of oneâs home.â The context of this idea within conservative politics runs the risk of engendering ethnocentrism, xenophobia, nationalism, and other deeply undesirable âvalues,â but I do not believe there is anything inherent in it that would not allow both a love of local multiculturalism and a pursuit of something like cosmopolitan localism (the latter being environmentalist thinker Wolfgang Sachsâs idea of a networked linking of mutually supportive communities across the globe). In a more general sense, oikophilia is used, as it is by Newton, to simply describe an impulse to protect oneâs homeâincluding (and often especially) the environment. The idea is that when one witnesses âdecreases in wildlife or flooding as a result of extreme weatherâ and other consequences of climate change there is a ânatural urge for people to want to work together to protect their environment.â Coupled with the localized ability to actually affect change in their households and communities through such projects as green energy neighborhood planning and local enterprise initiatives, this urge finds a material footing and is therefore able to flourish. I would argue this would be even more the case if the projects extended beyond the status quo economics of UK conservatives and into the localized, democratic market system gestured toward throughout this piece.
The illustrations of how alteration of the material base can cause shifts in cultural values (and in turn reinforce those alterations) go on and onâone might consider looking into the **material** social construction of gender roles (as theorized by Marxist and materialist feminists) or the understanding of queerphobia and cishetetonormativity as being schemes of Capital to enforce both the standardized reproduction of the workforce and the restricted commodification of difference. Although starting a cooperative will not magically make everyone an anti-racist or an environmentalist, as part of a broader movement toward localization of politico-economic power and autonomy from state-capitalism, a mass cooperative movement could begin to make a series of changes in the material base and thereby also the superstructure (particularly cultural values). All left-libertarians already support cooperatives wholeheartedlyâeither as an acceptable or ideal form of market entityâwith much of the call for the labor theory of value, mutual banking, and the common ownership of natural resources centering around allowing for workers to collectively generate and operate enterprises free from capitalist clutches. Additionally, Kevin Carsonâone of the most prominent theorists of left-libertarianismâhas theorized in such pieces as âEconomic Calculation in the Corporate Commonwealthâ and âThe Distorting Effects of Transportation Subsidiesâ that it is through state intervention that economies become artificially large-scale and delocalized, and so it stands to reason that without said state interference, it might be possible to move toward networks of local economies (Ă la the aforementioned cosmopolitan localism). However, it seems deeply important to emphasize how these economic projects can also directly lead to the thick libertarian cultural values that left-libertarians desire, thereby further conceptually fusing thickness and anti-capitalist economics within left-libertarianism.
[1] I am here using the term Capital in the Marxian sense, that is: a social relation based on accumulation through extraction from wage labor via private property.
[2] Obviously all information coming from the UN should be taken skeptically, because itâs coming from⊠well, the UN.