đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș uri-gordon-leviathan-s-body captured on 2024-08-19 at 00:20:27. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Leviathanâs Body Subtitle: Recovering Fredy Perlmanâs anarchist social theory Date: 2023 Source: Forthcoming in *Anarchist Studies* (2023) Authors: Uri Gordon Published: 2023-06-14 04:31:00Z
Fredy Perlmanâs anarchist maximalism had a formative influence on the
movementâs post-1960s revival, quite apart from his later and
better-known critiques of domestication. Perlmanâs longneglected books,
pamphlets and parodies from 1968â1972 show him championing an
antivanguardist ethos of direct action and practical de-alienation,
while working towards an original and distinctly anarchist social theory
of domination. This article traces the influences of Isaak Rubin, C.
Wright Mills, and possibly Henri Lefebvre and Peter Kropotkin, on
Perlmanâs thought. Perlmanâs originality was to generalise a heterodox
Marxian critique of social reproduction, including but exceeding
productive relations. Thus, he explicitly sets the state in analytical
parity with capital, theorising authority as a fetish distinct from
exchange value. Implicitly, he points to other containers for alienated
powers, including the family, religion and scholarship. Perlmanâs
account of self- and community powers remains incomplete, however,
eliding constitutive violence and inviting engagement with current
intersectional approaches.
<play>
Keywords: Perlman, Fredy (1934â1985); alienation; New Left; power; the
state
</play>
Some Anarchists differ from Marxists only in being less informed. They
would supplant the state with a network of computer centers, factories
and mines coordinated âby the workers themselvesâ or by an Anarchist
union. They would not call this arrangement a State. The name-change
would exorcize the beast.
(Perlman 1983:5)
The scholarly neglect of Fredy Perlman contrasts sharply with his
posthumous legacy. Alongside Noam Chomsky and Murray Bookchin, Perlman
was easily the most influential American anarchist writer of his
generation, a âprophetâ whose âpenetrating vision cuts across and
reveals the essential orderliness and limitedness of his [former two]
peersâ conceptions of anarchyâ (Moore 1995:363). Perlman produced four
book-length political works, over twenty articles and pamphlets, two
novels, two plays, and (with his Detroit co-operative *Black & Red*) the
first English translations of key texts including *The Society of the
Spectacle* (Debord 1970), *History of the Makhnovist Movement* (Arshinov
1974) and **The Wandering of Humanity **(Camatte 1975). His richly
illustrated, selfprinted works were also a landmark in DIY visual
culture, infusing underground aesthetics with its now-familiar mix of
Dada, Surrealism and Situationism.
Nevertheless, outside the direct action movement Perlman remains
virtually unknown. His work is the focus of a single academic study to
date: Mark Hubaâs (2005) courageous PhD on spiritual politics in
<em>Against His-story, Against Leviathan! </em>(*AHAL*) (Perlman 1983).
While this mythopoeic opus occasionally resurfaces in discussions of
anarcho-primitivism and technological overreach (el-Ojeili and Taylor
2020, Dunlap and Jakobsen 2020), Perlmanâs abundant earlier work has
received no sustained treatment. Lorraine Perlmanâs biography (1989),
two graphic retrospectives (Blauvelt 2016, Aubert 2019), and several
brief tributes and reviews exhaust the available literature (Poynton
2018, Tucker 2017, Artnoose 2014, Lee 2010, Cohen 2009, Black 2004,
Watson 1997, Cafard 1996, Moore 1995).
The neglect is doubly puzzling in view of the last two decadesâ upswell
of interest in all aspects of anarchism, radical aesthetics and the New
Left. Even the recent semi-centennial of the French May 1968 uprising,
of which Perlman co-wrote the first extended critique (Gregoire and
Perlman 1969), did not occasion a revival of interest. To be sure,
Perlmanâs iconoclastic, genrebending oeuvre is easier to approach
experientially than analytically. Imaginative prose, blistering parody,
and textual collage came to outweigh intellectual commentary in his
work, as âFredy went from brilliant theoretician to singer, from
political activist to intuitive rebel ⊠approaching those now forgotten
archaic rhythms which beat deeply in us allâ (Watson 1997:246). Perhaps
the very richness and variety of Perlmanâs expression has stood in the
way of critical appraisal, with no help from his own scorn towards
academia. Whatever the reason, engagement with his rich output remains
as rewarding as it is scarce.
This article focuses on Fredy Perlmanâs middle-period work (1968â1972),
amid the political and intellectual debris of the sixties miscarried
revolutions. Over a decade before his ideas were reshaped by rising
concerns with genocide, femicide and ecocide, and by his encounter with
the indigenous past of the Great Lakes, Perlman was already grappling
with the obstinate reassertion of domination and representation through
cycles of social upheaval, and with their durability in everyday life.
In the process, he began to work towards an original and distinctly
anarchist theory of domination as a totality, which could account for
diverse human powersâ alienation into the hierarchical institutions they
reproduce, and by the same token make the case for direct action and
immediacy in transformative struggle. Recovered from their diverse
stylings, and from under the shadow of his later work, Perlmanâs essays
in social theory can richly inform current anarchist discussions of
power and liberation.
Perlmanâs starting point, which informs his entire body of work, is a
critique of alienation as practice. Initially drawn from Marx via Isaak
Illich Rubin, and later influenced by the Situationists and possibly
Lefebvre, the key to this critique is the concept of fetishism, which
stands for the inverted domination of social forms of alienated power
over the individuals who reproduce them. Influenced by his activist
experiences and by the anarchist histories he read and translated, and
taking further selective cues from C. Wright Mills and possibly from
Kropotkin, Perlmanâs breakthrough is to generalise this account of
fetishism to include but exceed productive relations. Thus, he
explicitly sets the state in analytical parity with capital, theorising
authority as a fetish distinct from exchange value. Implicitly, he
points to various other containers for alienated human powers, including
the family, religion and scholarship. In further identifying direct
action with the reclamation of alienated powers, Perlman adds
sociological coherence to the anarchist case against representation and
for collective autonomy in social struggles.
Perlmanâs work in the period studied here displays a mix of
post-scarcity expectations and critiques of modernity, alongside
sustained textual and graphic references to ancient and mythical themes.
I must leave it to others to trace these themes to his 1980s critiques
of domestication, patriarchy and progress. This is not to discount
anarcho-primitivist political expression (el-Ojeili and Taylor 2020),
let alone anarchist engagements with early humanity (Wengrow and Graeber
2015, Scott 2017) and critiques of technology (Firth and Robinson 2020).
However, my central argument here is that Perlmanâs earlier and more
lasting contribution to the anarchist revival of the last decades is to
be found in his *maximalism* â Mooreâs term for an anarchist critique
encompassing not only state and capital but the âtotality of power
relations and the ensemble of control structuresâ (Moore 1998:9),
coupled with anarchist practices âcommitted to direct actionâ and
experimental alternatives (13). Despite and because of its centrality to
the anarchist tradition, it was this maximalism which Perlman
championed, not only against New Left vanguardists but also those
anarchists focused on membership and propaganda rather than affinity and
action. Perlman refused to call himself an anarchist, or any other -ist
except âcellistâ (Perlman 1989:96). However, as we shall see, he often
uses the terms âanarchyâ and âanarchistsâ with ironic approval, as
something feared by state officials and leftist organisers alike, and
increasingly deploys an anarchist rather than Marxian political
vocabulary. Inasmuch as maximalism has come to (re)define both anarchist
practice and readings of the anarchist tradition, it is in large part
thanks to Perlman and his followers.
Following a biographical sketch, sections 2â3 below trace the
development of Perlmanâs ideas, with special attention to
<em>Worker-Student Action Committees </em>(*WSAC*) and the <em>Manual
for Revolutionary Leaders. </em>Section 4 concludes the interpretative
commentary, then moves to a substantive critique. This problematises
Perlmanâs elision of violence in his account of self- and community
powers, opening the way for engagement with current intersectional
theories. In conclusion, avenues are suggested for further research on
Perlmanâs rich but neglected work.
</quote>
Born in Brno, Czechoslovakia, Perlman and his family fled the Nazi
invasion to Cochabamba, Bolivia and later settled in Kentucky. From 1959
to 1963 he studied at Columbia University and lived in Manhattan with
his partner, Lorraine, becoming the printer for the Living Theatre and
writing the anti-imperialist play *Plunder*. The couple then moved to
Yugoslavia, where Perlman completed his doctorate on rural development
policy at the University of Belgrade. Between 1966â 69 Perlman taught at
Western Michigan University in Kalamazoo, where the first *Black & Red*
pamphlets were published. In May 1968, after teaching a two-week course
on economic theory in Turin, he boarded the last train to Paris before
the railway lines were closed, and was immediately engrossed in the
heady scenes of the French uprising.** **Perlman soon afterward
broke with academia and the couple settled in Detroit. They became part
of a co-operative press that printed most of Perlmanâs works and
translations under the imprint **Black and Red. **Perlmanâs
articles in the Detroit paper **Fifth Estate **marked his turn
towards ecofeminism and primitivism (Perlman 1979, 1982,
1984), capstoned by <em>Against His-story! Against Leviathan (AHAL)
</em>and the unfinished novel <em>The Strait. </em>Perlman had lifelong
health problems, and died following his second heart surgery in 1985
(Perlman 1989).
Perlmanâs accidental role at the epicentre of the Paris uprising was
crucial to his political and intellectual development. In Paris, Perlman
âtook part in a loosely-organized group of intellectuals, students and
young workers who held discussions at the Sorbonne universityâs Censier
classroom complex and who also tried to communicate their aspirations to
auto workers who lived and worked in the Paris suburbsâ (Perlman
1989:47). These Student-Worker Action Committees produced several
leaflets, one of them calling for âworker-student unity in the struggle
âto destroy this police system which oppresses all of usââ; another
promoted uncompromising internationalism and solidarity with foreign
workers (Gregoire and Perlman 1969:14; cf. Gordon 2011). During this
time he âlearned about ideas and histories which influenced him in the
decade which followed: the texts of the Situationist International,
anarchism and the Spanish Revolution, the council communistsâ (Perlman
1989:48). Inspired by the spectacle of the black and red flags flying
side by side over the Sorbonne and the Bourse, he would later make
anarchist, left-communist and Situationist texts.
Perlmanâs reports from Paris, written as the events took place, became
the first part of *Worker-Student Action Committees*. The further
critical discussion was completed in Kalamazoo with Roger Gregoire
visiting from Paris. The book is illustrated with many cartoons and
graphics from the uprising. The authors located the exemplary nature of
Censier occupation in its practical break with the social division of
labour: it replaced the universityâs institutional norms with a
selfmanaged structure of working groups and a general assembly; it
transformed the building from an authoritative institutional enclosure
for specialised knowledge into a site for self-directed creation,
reflection and action; and it practically abolished the distinction
between âworkerâ and âstudentâ as personifications of social roles.
Through this conscious âprocess of political dis-alienationâ (Gregoire
and Perlman 1969:43), the participants for the first time realised their
social power in practice.
In contrast, as the Communist Party-controlled unions rapidly move to
control the strikes,
the occupied factories are not transformed into places for expression
and learning; general assemblies are not formed; workers do not become
conscious of their collective power, and they do not appropriate
societyâs productive forces. The appropriation of social power by the
working population would have meant the transformation of the entire
society into a place for collective expression, a place for active,
conscious, de-alienated creation. Such anarchy is averted. (67)
The book contains twelve further positive-ironic uses of âanarchyâ and
âanarchistsâ. The thrust of the critique, however, points to the Censier
occupiers themselves (including the authors), who failed to carry over
their practical and cognitive break with alienation to actions outside
the occupied space: âWhen the people who organized their activities
inside an occupied university went to âthe workers,â either on the
barricades, or in the factories, and when they said to âthe workersâ:
âYOU should take over YOUR factories,â they showed a complete lack of
awareness about what they were already doing in the ex-universitiesâ
(71, orig. caps.).
In addressing the workers as a specialised sector of society, the
occupiers reverted to accepting the dominant social division of labour.
Instead of taking direct action on their own behalf, the occupiers chose
to defer to the initiative of the factory workers: âOne of the favorite
arguments of âanarchistsâ and âlibertariansâ at Censier was: âThe
workers must make their own decisions; we cannot substitute ourselves
for themâ. This is a blind application of an anti-bureaucratic tactic to
a situation where this tactic had no application at allâ (89).
Since no assemblies were organised in the factories, such deference
merely abandoned the field to the Communist unions, rather than
autonomously confronting them. Perlman imagines a genuine revolutionary
escalation, with thousands invading multiple factories and declaring
them social property â not âon behalfâ of âthe workersâ but as an act of
collective power that transcends alienated social categories. Such an
opportunity may have existed early on, but was lost as soon as the
Action Committees defined their role in terms of outreach. Subsequent
conflicts over institutionalisation, the antics of self-appointed
leaders, and the final police clampdown were merely a drawn-out
epilogue.
To contextualise this critique, we should turn back to trace Perlmanâs
intellectual formation.
Here, the catalyst is easily identified as Isaak Illich Rubinâs
<em>Essays on Marxâs Theory of Value. </em>
Perlman co-translated this book in 1967 (via Serb-Croat) with his former
Belgrade supervisor MiloĆĄ SamardĆșija, adding an original preface (Rubin
1973; cf. Perlman 1970)**. **From 1926 until his arrest in 1931,
Rubin had been a Research Associate at the Marx-Engels Institute in
Moscow . Forced to implicate the Instituteâs director, David Ryazanov,
in an alleged Menshevik conspiracy, Rubinâs actual transgression was
ideological (Boldyrev and Kragh 2015). Rubinâs value-form approach to
capital centred on the reification of abstract labour, and regarded
commodity fetishism as the cornerstone of Marxâs political economy. This
not only ran contrary to Stalinist economism, but was also dangerously
applicable to âa state bureaucracy that purchases alienated labor and
accumulates Capital in the name of Marxâ (Perlman 1969a:17). Perlman
bookended his preface with strident critiques of American college
economics, where âintellectual legislationâ excludes political economy
and renders Marx illegible (Perlman in Rubin 1973:x). His exposition
centres on Rubinâs argument that Marx doses not discard the concept of
alienation found in his early work. Instead, Marxâs critique of
political economy contains its further development as the theory of
commodity fetishism. Rubin does not mention Marxâs *Economic and
Philosophical Manuscripts*, which were published in Russian by Ryazanov
in 1927 but misidentified as âPreparatory Work for *The Holy Family*â
(Musto 2015:234). Perlman fills an important gap in Rubinâs argument by
quoting extensively from the *Manuscripts*. He argues that while there
is âno doubt that in 1844, Marx spoke of a human society and a human
essence which could be rehabilitated, returned, or restored ... an
unalienated, ideal, unhistorical manâ, after his break with Proudhon in
1859 âthe conflict reappears on a new plane ... [not] between ideal and
reality, but as a conflict between productive forces and social
relations which are both parts of realityâ (1973:xxi).
Perlmanâs accessible presentation of value-form theory, <em>The
Reproduction of Daily Life </em>(Perlman 1969a)**, **was widely
read by New Left students (Cohen 2006:3ff.)**. **Its central
argument is that âthe deliberate alienation of living activity, which is
perceived as necessary for survival by the members of capitalist
society, itself reproduces the capitalist form within which alienation
is necessary for survivalâ (Perlman 1969a:14). Perlman indicates his
diachronic view at the very opening, using tribal and slave societies as
first examples to illustrate how humansâ daily activities âreproduce the
inhabitants, the social relations and the ideas of the society ... the
Under capitalism, daily activity reproduces wage labour and capital, and
people âreproduce the personifications of the dominant forms of activity
under capitalism; they reproduce the wage-laborer and the capitalistâ
(7). Perlman borrows the term *personification* from Rubinâs
interpretation of Marxâs passing comment in *Capital* v.3 (1966:866)
that the capitalist and the landlord âpersonifyâ capital and land. This,
according to Rubin, points to the inverted domination of fetishes over
the persons whose social relations they mediate, with the result that
â<em>particular individuals are subsumed under the dominant type of
production relations </em>... In this way, the apparent contraction
between the âreification of peopleâ and the âpersonification of thingsâ
is resolved in the dialectical, uninterrupted process of reproductionâ
(Rubin 1973:23â25, emph. in orig** **). On this reading, alienation
is âneither a feeling nor an ideaâ (Perlman 1969a:5); âMen[1]do
in fact relate to each other through things; the fetish is in fact the
occasion for which they act collectively, and through which they
reproduce their activityâ. (8â9) To borrow terms from Norman Geras
(1971), Perlmanâs account is clearly one of fetishism as real domination
rather than as mystification and false consciousness â a âconstitutive
account of fetishism in which human social relations constitute external
and alien entities that dominate societyâ (OâKane 2013:22).
The pamphletâs title echoes Henri** **Lefebvreâs <em>Critique de la
vie quotidienne </em>(Lefebvre 2014). According to Lorraine Perlman
(personal communication, 2.6.20), âThe book is not in our library and I
donât remember Fredy reading it. But he certainly knew about it and the
title of
âReproductionâ acknowledges the linkâ. Whether Perlman read Lefebvre or
only Rubin and the Situationists, the similarities are instructive.
Lefebvre starts from practical activity and the âforms of appearanceâ it
assumes under specific historical conditions. He thus views fetishism
neither as a property of the fetishised object nor as an individualâs
epistemological error; instead it is a social category, both abstract
and concrete, which in the process of social reproduction âtends to
function as an objectivity independent of men [*sic*] ... both a mode of
existence of the social reality, an actual mode of consciousness and
human life, and an appearance or illusion of human activityâ (Lefebvre
2009a:80â1). Therefore, a break with alienated social reproduction
implies not merely a cognitive break, but the deliberate practice of
different social relations. This was the basis for Lefebvreâs explicitly
pro-anarchist support for **autogestion **(self-organisation),
which along with its inherent anti-statism âtends to restore primacy to
use value. It âisâ the use value of human beings in their practical
relationsâ, valorising them âagainst the world of the commodityâ and
pointing to a radical contestation of both capital and the state
(Lefebvre 2009b:148).
Returning to the Action Committees, we can now see how Perlman
concretely applies this approach to assess them in terms of their
(limited) practical break with alienation. In doing so, he is
effectively using value-form theory to formulate the hallmark anarchist
principle of unity between means and ends. While such unity can equally
be framed in terms of virtuous practice (Franks 2020) or path dependency
(Gordon 2018), Perlman ties it to a specific explanatory account of
social reproduction. On this view, de-alienation is at the same time the
overall aim of social transformation *and* the essential quality of
practices in its furtherance. While based on a heterodox reading of
Marx, and notwithstanding Perlmanâs criticism of the âanarchistsâ and
âlibetariansâ at the occupied Censier, his argument promotes the same
ethos of direct action which anarchists associate with terms like
prefigurative politics or concrete utopia.
Importantly, we also begin to see Perlman generalising fetishism beyond
value-form categories. Early on in *WSAC*, he explicitly distinguishes
between four forms of alienation and the divisions they sustain (39â40,
my paraphrased summary):
1. Alienation of political power by all members of society, and its
2. Sale of productive labour by producers and its purchase by
3. Alienation of reflective activity to a specialised corps of
4. Alienation of creative activity to âartistsâ (creators and
The account does nothing to assign analytical primacy to component (2),
and thereby points away from the orthodox Marxist privileging of
production and proletarian agency. It could be said that, for Perlman,
since de-alienated practice cannot be grounded in the fetishised social
categories which it no longer reproduces, during revolutionary
transformation both ex-students and ex-workers are equally members of a
class in self-abolition (cf. Proletarios Revolucionarios 2020).
Direct action was also central to the first <em>Black & Red
</em>pamphlets, published by the Perlmans in
Kalamazoo. Issue 2, a critical report from the 1968 Democratic National
Convention in Chicago (Perlman 1968a), commends the Yippiesâ occupation
of a public park: by âorganizing their own activities without orders or
permission, without compromise or negotiationâ, they âacted outâ their
freedom in reclaiming public space and thereby âceased to recognize the
legitimacy of the stateâ â drawing out its violence. In contrast, the
failures of student organising are lampooned in Issue 4, <em>We Called a
Strike and No One Came </em>(Perlman 1968b). At the printing press,
Perlman began to discover many new graphic possibilities, and his work
would now rapidly move away from conventional textual formats. *Strike*
is a case in point: a 46-page A5 collage-comic, with speech bubbles
coming from the mouths of figures in renaissance paintings, grotesque
sculptures, and white men in suits.
This âAllegorical Epic with Footnotesâ (1) is loosely inspired by
the latest round in a cosmic struggle between Satan and God. Satanâs
avatars discover that God means to re-establish his slipping power by
abandoning Christianity and appropriating Satanâs gift of Reason; he
will âherd men into rationally organized institutions where each does
the work established by Authorityâ (5). Failing that, he will bring
about Doomsday. God, portrayed as Clark Kent and Superman, then
introduces his own essence as âthe social relation of Authority and
Submission ... any relation between Rulers and Ruledâ (10). He promises
to disrupt the plans of Satanâs followers, who âon the verge of absolute
negation, of freedom ... will only use this freedom to enslave
themselves anewâ (12). As it transpires, the new SDS chapter draws a
circus of hippies, liberals and Leninists. They call a strike but
dismiss the avatarsâ proposals for concrete actions in preparation, and
on Doomsday end up marching through the administration building yelling
âStrike! Strike!â. God concludes:
Even thine own avatarsâŠcould barely pass from the word to the deed. And
as for the rest ... I have âtil now kept from them the knowledge of
their power ⊠Yet am I not satisfied. For well do I know that My Time
draws to a close. Well do I know that the elimination of scarcity
foreshadows the elimination of Authority. Well do I know that I cannot
long continue to keep man ignorant. (45)
This sense of technological optimism sits alongside the comicâs
immersive mythological framing, predating *AHAL* by 15 years. *Strike*!
is much more playful, but also significant in terms of Perlmanâs
political language and affinities. He uses comical archaisms (God to
Satan: âThou grooveth, but thou diggeth me notâ) but also the archaism
of capitalising nouns to highlight key concepts such as Authority,
Submission, Reason, Bureaucracy, Power, Scarcity, Fear, Law and
Order â all associated with the anarchist lexicon. Also striking is
Godâs grotesque restatement of the Ten Commandments under four headings:
Religion (unquestioning acceptance, normalised hypocrisy, no depiction
of a sense of community); The State (ageism, killing of âenemiesâ);
Private Property (sexual privation, minority ownership, dominant regimes
of truth); and The Family (women as property; slavish deprivation). The
Sabbath is omitted and the tenth commandment is split in two. Like the
keywords he capitalises, and like the example from *WSAC*, these four
institutional headings are plainly divorced from Marxâs analytical
prioritisation of productive relations, which even *heterodoxoi* like
Rubin and Lefebvre preserve.
Instead, we find Perlman increasingly aligning himself with anarchist
accounts of class and domination â specifically those âoligarchical<em>â
</em>accounts (my term) whereby several groups concentrate different
forms of power through distinctive, if related, institutional
structures, none of which enjoys analytical primacy over the rest. Thus
Malatesta argues that, in addition to the owning class, the history of
conquest and exploitation has also given rise to âa special class
(government)â, which legalises and protects property but also âuses the
powers at its disposal to create privileges for itself and to subject,
if it can, the owning class itself as wellâ; and âanother privileged
class (the clergy)â which âas well as serving the interest of the owning
class, serves its own; (1899/2014:280). Consider also Kropotkinâs
account of the State as âThe power which was created for the purpose of
welding together the interests of the landlord, the judge, the warrior,
and the priestâ (Kropotkin 1903:ch.10) â qualitatively distinct
concentrations of power which preceded capitalism. The
Perlmansâ library contains a read but unmarked copy of the 1969 Freedom
Press edition of Kropotkinâs selected works. According to Lorraine
(pers.comm. 26.09.20), âwe may have bought it when we were in London
that year ... So I guess my answer would be: âItâs likely he read itâ.
Even if he didnât the parallels are relevantâ.
Perlmanâs interest in non-Marxist theories of class and domination is
further evident in his last scholarly work, a critique of his former
teacher C. Wright Mills titled <em>The Incoherence of the Intellectual
</em>(1969). Early on, Perlman praises the young Mills for attempting to
grasp domination at its root: âMills did not read [Franz] Neumannâs
dissection of the Nazi Behemoth as a description of a distant enemy:
âThe analysis of Behemoth casts light upon capitalism in democracies ...
he
[Neumann] locates the enemy with a 500 watt glare. And Nazi is only one
of his names ...
Behemoth is everywhere unitedâ. (Perlman 1969b quoting Mills
1942:177).[2]
However, Perlman argued, throughout his ensuing career âMills the
independent revolutionary continues to coexist with Mills the academic
cynicâ. Thus, âWeberian leaders and the leaderless Wobblies occupied
separate compartments in Millsâ mind ... [and] never directly confronted
each otherâ (1969a:np). Alongside his astute critiques of post-war
American society, argues Perlman, Mills continued to publish works in
positivist sociology which muddle the analysis of these same issues â
betraying Millsâs limited understanding of alienation as disaffection,
rather than as the daily activities through which people in fact
âalienate their power to shape their environmentâ (1969a:n.p.).
In** Incoherence** we find Perlman engaging with the non-Marxist
political sociologies of
Millsâs two contradictory masters, Max Weber and Thorsten Veblen.
Perlman finds Mills âreverent, âobjective,â and uncriticalâ towards
Weberâs scientism and his appeal to charismatic leadership. Again,
Perlman argues, Mills fails to identify alienation as the link between
âMarxâs emphasis upon the wage worker as being âseparatedâ from the
means of productionâ and Weberâs view that the âmodern soldier is
equally âseparatedâ from the means of violence; the scientist from the
means of enquiry, and the civil servant from the means of
administrationâ (Mills 2009:88). Yet if alienation is properly accounted
for, this Weberian insight reveals its value. Perlman may well have
quoted Millsâs further statement that Weberâs thereby ârounds outâ
Marxâs analysis with a âpolitical and military materialismâ, and that
therefore âmilitary and religious, political and juridical institutional
systemsâ should be analysed on par with âthe economic orderâ (85) â thus
dislodging productive relations from their analytical primacy in Marx.
In contrast to Weber, Perlman held Thorsten Veblen in high esteem
(Perlman 1989:43). Mills (1962:35) had called Veblen âthe best social
scientist America has produced, who probably ... was at heart an
anarchist and syndicalistâ, and grouped him with the Wobblies. However,
writes Perlman, in **The Power Elite **Mills âcompletely
obfuscatesâ Veblenâs ethics, and excludes the possibility of
transformative social change:
According to [Millsâs] files elites make history, and consequently Mills
addresses himself to the people characterized by Veblen as âthe noble
and the priestly classes, together with much of their retinue,â the
âintellectuals, artists, ministers, scholars, and
scientistsâ**...**fragmentary men whose social positions rest on
their service to power (1969a:n.p.)
This is again to highlight Perlmanâs interest in non-Marxist sociologies
of class â in this case, Veblenâs institutional account which is not
ultimately indexed to productive relations. These elements would come
closest to a synthesis in the final work considered here, the <em>Manual
for </em>
Published under the pseudonym Michael Velli, the <em>Manual
</em>ostensibly advocates the âmodern model of revolutionâ, namely
ârevolutionary organizational ideology, leadership and the struggle for
State powerâ (Perlman 1972, 11). It is the Perlmansâ most richly
illustrated work. The menacing cover features a Balinese fanged dancer
and Gothic fonts, anticipating his use of Blakeâs devouring monster on
the cover of *AHAL*. The first chapter (âGeneration of Revolutionariesâ)
features nine full-page surrealist collages, in which tanks ride the
tiers of Breugelâs *Tower of Babel,* a motley religious procession
traverses a wall of televisions, and Matisseâs *Dance* revolves amid
fiery riots at the Capitol. In the second chapter (âRise to
Leadershipâ), the historiated initial of each of the 62 paragraphs
portrays a âGreat Leaderâ, running backwards from the likes of Castro,
Dmitrov and
Lenin to Robespierre, Henry VIII, Ceasar, and finally Sargon of Akkad (a
key character in *AHAL)*. Images of machinery, restaurant food,
wasteland and mass murder illustrate the third chapter
(âSeizure of State Powerâ).
No less striking is the *Manual*âs** **use of textual collage.
While the first, theoretical chapter is wholly original, the
programmatic second chapter is a prank of egregious plagiarism,
sequencing hundreds of unattributed quotations from contemporary
articles in *New Left Notes*, *National Guardian, The Movement*,<em> Red
Papers </em>and similar outlets**. **Threaded through these are
quotes from three other sources: Marx and Engelsâs <em>The German
Ideology, </em>Michelsâs** The Iron Law of Oligarchy, **and
Hitlerâs *Mein Kampf*. In the scenarios narrated in chapter 3, Lenin and
Mao often speak from the mouths of party officials and lackeys. Only in
the second edition was a list of references added, explaining that Velli
had âre-constituted the project which unifies these widely dispersed
statementsâ and âplaced them into the single Thought of which each of
these ideas is a mere fragmentâ (263).
Crucially, a third thread in the text â also italicised in the second
edition â consists of key sentences from the first chapter that reappear
in the next two. Prefixed to blocs of authoritarian quotations, they
recast the latter as a twisted appreciation of the first chapterâs
original analysis. Hence, I would like to argue that Velliâs âmodern
modelâ âis not merely a parodic mirror of authoritarian trends in the
New Left, but the grotesque inversion of Perlmanâs genuine social
analysis; Velli cynically instrumentalises an accurate understanding of
fetishised power to develop his totalitarian programme. Chapter 1âs
consistency with Perlmanâs evolving ideas, and the powerful case it
would otherwise make for anarchist strategies of de-alienation, make
this reading compelling. Beneath the irony, we find Perlman advancing a
strikingly original critique of authority and the state.
In fact, the *Manual* moves to account for capital and alienated labour
only after an account of the state, âby far the most importantâ among
âthe personifications, embodiments, representatives of societyâs
estranged powersâ: âThe State is the personification of the power of
community, the estranged power of individuals to decide collectively the
methods, means and purpose of their social activity. It is the specific
office of the State to use all available means to ensure that the power
of community remains estrangedâ (17).
Unlike productive power, whose alienated form of appearance is
commodities or money, social or community power is alienated into
offices bearing socially legitimated authority. Perlman construes
authority as a separate, first-order category of fetish, invested with
normative rather than exchange value:
By accepting the legitimacy of an office to wield a specific social
power, individuals abdicate their own power over that part of social
life ... the office to which the power is abdicated becomes an
âauthorityâ which has the ârightâ to wield that power; an individual who
does not abdicate the power becomes a âcriminalâ who has no ârightâ to
wield it; all others are obedient, âgood,â and âlaw-abiding citizensâ to
the extent that they exert no power over that part of social activity.
(18)
Perlman goes no further to work out the substance of social- or
community power absent authority, an issue I take up below. For the
moment, I would like to argue that in placing an account of community
power, authority-fetishism and the state prior to his account of
productive power, commodity-fetishism and capital, Perlman clearly aims
to set them in analytical parity. Further evidence is provided by dyadic
statements about humans âabdicating their power of community to the
State and their productive power to Capitalâ(19); âwielding the
estranged human powers represented by money and wielded by officesâ(29);
and living in a society where âestranged power of community â the State,
government â is experienced as the only real community. Estranged
productive power â Capital, money â is experienced as the only real
productive agentâ (29).
This points away from any view of the state as auxiliary to productive
relations, whatever relative autonomy it may possess. Instead, the state
is a first-order domain of alienated power, an institutional container
that cannot be reduced to its role in enforcing owner-worker relations.
Moreover, while Perlman continues to use the term âpersonificationâ to
denote the subsumption of individuals by dominant social forms, he
explicitly dissociates the fetish of authority from the
Marxian material base:
complete types, perfect embodiments of the ruling behavior, can be found
in activities which are physically separated from societyâs productive
forces, which are geographically quarantined: the activities of artists,
independent âprofessionalsâ, full-time political organizers, and
particularly the activities of members of the political and educational
hierarchies (25).
Perlman goes further to argue that the state, as a domain for estranged
power, is not only older than capital but also poised to succeed it in
dominance over production. This portrays capitalism as a âbrief
digression from the normal histories of civilizationsâ (35). As evinced
by the examples of colonialism, Meiji Japan, the USSR, and post-colonial
socialist states, it âbecomes possible to institute the central
relations of Capital accumulation directly by means of State power,
without recapitulating the historical development of capitalismâ (42).
In the West, the âseizure and consolidation of the estranged power of
community, the State, has become the form of development of productive
forces in conditions where earlier forms of Capital accumulation ceased
to perform their historical taskâ (43).
For the sake of stability and order, the development of productive
forces must be controlled, obstructed, reversed. The cornucopia of
technological progress ceases to give rise to hopes and increasingly
spreads vague fears. Behind the productive forces slouches a rough
beast, its hour come round at last, ready to loose mere anarchy upon the
world. (36)
Hence, the role of the vanguard is not to promote a transition to
communism, but to *interrupt* it â instating a totalitarian state which
then takes over the production process itself, along with all aspects of
life. The anarchist reading of the vanguard party as a totalitarian
state-in-waiting is thereby cynically embraced in Chapter 2, describing
how the organisation and its leader should appropriate the militantsâ
estranged self-powers.
The problem, however, is that workers in advanced capitalist countries
are the ones least inclined to follow party militants. In their daily
contact with the means of production, modern workers âare expected to be
simultaneously automatic and imaginative, simultaneously obedient and
creativeâ(240). This drives their anarchic ferment, manifest in
âabsenteeism, sabotage, wildcat strikes, occupations of productive
plants, and even attempts to dismantle the entire social order...a
growing resistance to State power...refusal to alienate productive
activity...rejection of specializationâ (239; cf. Zerzan 1988). Thus,
Chapter 3 narrates the misadventures of party organisers who offer their
leadership to insurgent workers and communities who are already
reclaiming their self-powers, passages acclaimed as âcomic skits in the
finest tradition of Sid Caesarism and Groucho Marxismâ (Black 2004).
Hence Velliâs brazen strartegy: when â<em>a revolutionary upsurge
</em>takes place the revolutionary leaders <em>must take power at once â
otherwise a wave of real anarchy may become stronger than we areâ
</em>(137, italics quoting Lenin 1917:234).
Twisting Perlmanâs analysis, Velli writes that state power should be
seized:
when people are on the verge of independence, when they reach the
frontier ... and temporarily recoil. It is the moment when all the
official authorities have been *sprung into the air*, but when societyâs
individuals have not yet actively appropriated the powers they had
vested in the deposed authoritiesâ (184; italics quoting Marx and Engels
1848).
So far, we have seen how Perlmanâs encounter with anarchism not only
informed his antiauthoritarian politics, but also enriched his social
theory. In between the lines of his parodic critiques of vanguardist
politics, Perlman was developing an account of domination as a totality,
casting fetishism as a general dynamic with explanatory force towards
several domains of estranged powers: notably the state and capital but
also, implicitly, the family and religious and intellectual
institutions. Exceeding Marxian materialism, Perlman suggests a
differentiated account of** power** as the basis for social
critique â reflecting not only his critical debt to Veblen and Mills,
but also his growing engagement with anarchism, whose ideological core
concepts he increasingly employs (cf. Franks, Jun & Williams, 2018). At
stake here is Perlmanâs generalisation of Marxâs key insight on
alienation as practice, with labour no longer the explanatory
cornerstone but only a special case of *power*, whose diverse forms are
alienated through interlinking regimes of domination and the
institutions that reproduce them.
Perlman would never offer a more systematic account of his political
sociology, and the conceptual apparatus of power, alienation and
personification echoes but faintly in his later work. Indeed, as Huba
(2005) convincingly argues, the spiritual politics of **AHAL **is
framed by a quasiManichean dualism. While the initial description of
Leviathan makes plain its reliance on human operators, it is also
portrayed as a terrifying alien power, unstoppable in its race towards
planetary conquest and extinction. For all its force, this
one-directional, overpowering account â chiefly indebted to Jacques
Camatteâs concept of the âflight of Capitalâ (cf. El-Ojeili 2014) â
moves away from Perlmanâs earlier approach to fetishistic reproduction
and its potential dissolution in practice. As a result, the question of
social transformation is re-posited across the impassable strait between
humanityâs Edenic origins and the wasteland of civilisation. Perlman
ends up identifying revolutionary rupture with ecstatic rapture, an
escape from domestication into wildness.
Black (2004) thus finds in the *Manual* ânot much anticipation of the
critique of civilizationâ in **AHAL **and *The Strait*. This is
certainly the case regarding technological progress. Echoing Godâs
concerns in *Strike*, Velli warns that independent workers who âsow the
seeds of anarchyâ would âspread with the continuing development of the
productive forcesâ (1974:249â250). Yet already in the *Manual* this
post-scarcity teleology is set up to be interrupted by the authoritarian
vanguard, allowing the state to resurge in its archaic form. Indeed, the
and in particular his focus on the stateâs ancient and inherent tendency
to colonise and territorialise â another possible debt to Kropotkinâs
writings on the Russian Empire and early-modern state formation in
Europe (cf. Kinna 2016: ch.4; Ince 2012). I would also suggest that the
abundance of ancient and mythical themes in the *Manual* are Perlmanâs
indication of the diachronic generality of his social critique, valid
across time just as it is valid synchronically across the totality of
institutional concentrations of alienated human powers. Finally, the
central theme of capitulation to estranged powers returns to drive the
narrative of *AHAL*, where a succession of anarchic rebellions are
upstaged by *coups* *dâetat*, while indigenous peoples take up the logic
of domination even as they resist invasion.
In general, there is more continuity than disjuncture between Perlmanâs
earlier and later work than some of his primitivist followers might
suggest. By the same token, however, his influence on contemporary
anarchism should by no means be limited to primitivist currents. While
his later writings were part of the Detroit paper *Fifth Estate*âs turn
towards a critique of the megamachine (Millett 2018; cf. Watson 1981),
Perlmanâs earlier works and translations had far broader impact. The
maximalist critique of domination across regimes and institutions, and
the coupling of revolutionary politics with a commitment to collective
and individual dis-alienation, successfully reflected the intersecting
grassroots mobilisations of the 80s and 90s, and became the discursive
boundary between anarchism and the Marxist and liberal left. By the time
the alter-global movement was in full swing, âpost-leftâ anarchists had
also turned this critique on anarchist platformism, syndicalism and
social ecology (Black 1998, Moore 2016, Jarach 1999, Landstreicher
2002), raising tensions that endure to this day. Therefore, although
critiques of domestication do remain central to eco-anarchism and total
liberation agendas, these build on Perlmanâs earlier and more basic
articulation of anarchist maximalism as such, which is at the core of
the recent decadesâ anarchist revival.
So much for a contextual interpretation of Perlmanâs work. In the rest
of this section, I would like to shift to a more analytical approach,
and problematise Perlmanâs model of power and how it ends up eliding
constitutive violence. Returning to the dual model in the *Manual*, we
find two distinctive forms of power (productive and community) with two
distinctive fetishised forms (commodities and offices), representing two
distinctive values (exchange and legitimation) and thus part of two
analytically distinctive domains (capital and state). In both cases, it
is daily practical activity (work and obedience) which reproduces these
powersâ estrangement, abdication or alienation. One problem with this
account is its incompleteness. While neatly constructing the above
parallel, it remains silent on which (other) powers are alienated in the
reproduction of the family and religious/intellectual institutions â
both of which seem to require equal consideration on Perlmanâs view.
hence, it offers no grounds for a first-order analysis of either
patriarchy or ideological production.
More significantly, however, there is a basic conceptual problem in
Perlmanâs account. While productive power is alienated through the
labour process, what he says is alienated into the state is community
power, âthe power of individuals to decide collectively the methods,
means and purpose of their social activityâ (1972: 17). However, in
Perlmanâs terminology, productive power is a <em>self-power
</em>which<em> </em>the individual continues to wield in practice, even
if it is alienated as wage labour, corvée or slavery. In contrast,
community power is (trivially) wielded by a group, and completely ceases
to be exercised once replaced with obedience. Perlman is not very
precise here â Velli says state power should be seized âduring the brief
moment after the population has expropriated the ruling classesâ but
before it âgains confidence in its own self-powersâ (184)â the term
self-powers now applied collectively, becoming indistinct from community
power. Yet the discrepancy goes deeper. Consider that, absent
alienation, the âmethods, means and purposeâ of social activity
determined through community power would also cover how *productive*
power is organised and allocated. Hence, community power is abdicated
just as much in the case of wage labour as it is in the case of
legitimated obedience.
At issue is Perlmanâs substitution of a second-order, coordinative and
collective form of power for what should be another first-order,
constitutive self-power corresponding to the state. This raises the
question: which âspecific social powerâ (18), other than productive
power, does the state contain in its alienated form? Otherwise we are
left without a first-order form of power which could be regulated
through community power, but which today is alienated specifically as
state authority, on par with productive powerâs alienation as
commodities and money. Velliâs argument that the state is poised to take
over from capital in administering production seems almost designed to
make this problem go away. Compelling as it may have been with the
Soviet Union still in existence, this argument only weakens the modelâs
definition.
The answer â which should have perhaps been obvious to Perlman â is that
authority specifically masks not the capacity to organise life (which
commodities do as well), but the capacity to kill and injure. While
State power is always entangled with the productive process, its
distinct content lies not in its coordinative functions but in the
violent force that underwrites its commands. Perlman, who is keen to
emphasise daily reproduction, ends up side-lining violence from its
constitutive role:
Although many of the commands of a personification are enforced by
violent means, the granting of legitimacy is not the result of coercion.
If the power of a personification rested on violence alone, the
personification would not need to be legitimate to realize its commandsâŠ
Violence accompanies the power wielded by a personification, but does
not make the personification legitimate. (18)
Indeed, violence does not produce legitimation. But it also does more
than to âaccompanyâ it â violence is the institutionalised physical
force that underwrites obedience, and which emerges in the face of
resistance to coercive threats â as the Yippies had exposed. However, by
working backwards from powersâ fetishised forms, Perlman effectively
confuses empirical frequency with analytical order. While legitimation
is the most common source of obedience, it is not its ultimate
guarantee.
This is not just an anarchist and a Weberian insight; even Engels (in a
moment of candour) defines the State as âthe institution of a public
force which is no longer immediately identical with the peopleâs own
organization of themselves as an armed power ⊠Officials now present
themselves as organs of society standing above society ⊠representatives
of a power which estranges them from societyâ (1972; pp. 229â230).
Within the synthesis Perlman seems to be reaching for, the dyad of
productive and community power makes much less sense than one of
productive and destructive (or violent) power, regulated either through
community power or their respective processes of alienation. Both
represent âan individualâs self-powersâ (31), regardless of whether the
individual wields them within the context of a self-directed community
or as part of their function in an alienated process. To the
productive-violent dyad we can now add a second, regulative dimension,
ranging from full community power to full capture by fetishised social
forms.
While this analytical correction may strengthen the conceptual coherence
of Perlmanâs
account, the dyadic structure itself is clearly limited: both in scope,
failing to account for gender, religion etc.; and in over-definition,
its neatness obscuring the entanglements between the powers and
institutions it describes. Nevertheless, the discussion above already
demonstrates the possibility of treating Perlmanâs ideological
expression as substantive groundwork for a distinctly anarchist
political sociology. Directly promoting anti-representational practice,
his approach provides anarchists with the rudiments of their own
consistent lens through which to analyse institutional concentrations of
power, and the regimes of domination that intersect through them. It
thus does the double work of explaining the dynamics of power and
providing the rationale for a politics of direct action. Crucially,
Perlman does not assign analytical primacy to any of these institutions
and regimes, thereby inviting synthesis with newer theories of
intersectional, reproductive and state power (Pritchard 2021, Angulo
2019, Laursen 2021) as well as decolonial and total liberation agendas
(Black Seed 2021; Nocella et al. 2015). Whether such a synthesis can
truly inform social struggles remains an open question.
Fredy Perlmanâs work remains richly available for study. Long due
recognition as a nova in the anarchist cynosure is long overdue, this
article has only skimmed the surface of his voluminous and varied
output. At this time, Lorraine Perlman is preparing the second,
unfinished volume of **The Strait **for publication. A great deal
remains to be written about Perlmanâs literary treatment of
revolutionary politics and loyalties in *Letters of Insurgents*; about
his subsequent engagements with ecofeminist and decolonial critiques;
about his conflicted relationship with his Jewish heritage and the
Holocaust; and about his rapidly shifting visual language. Perlmanâs
archives, to which I have not had access, may provide new insights into
all of these.
Perlmanâs creative talents were so diverse, and his expressive fount so
individual, that he found no reason to specialise. One after another he
would master a scholarly discipline or a genre of expression and move on
to something else. Had he lived longer he may have found his way back to
a more systematic account of his social theory, but given his personal
and intellectual transformation this is doubtful.
The hopeful euphoria Fredy felt in 1968 dissipated during ensuing
decades, and his eager wish to participate in a collective effort to
abolish repressive social institutions went unrealized. His search for
an appropriate agency for social change was also unsuccessful. He
nevertheless remained committed to these goals both in his personal life
and in intellectual projects. He examined, with sympathy and attention,
attempts of a variety of resisters; and used his impulses for
craftsmanship to produce attractive publications hoping, through them,
to communicate with... (in [**Letters of Insurgents **character]
Sophiaâs words) âhis likesâ. (Perlman 1989:139)
Today, Perlmanâs earlier work communicates his sustained concern with
our daily reproduction of complex regimes of domination, but also his
continued faith in the power of mass uprisings to open the way for
community and mutual aid. Both are crucial themes, which should remain
in our focus as the planetary collapse continues to unfold. Late as we
may be to avoid the biospheric implications of climate change, ecosystem
loss and toxic contamination, we can still fight to face these
implications within free human societies, based on equality and
solidarity.
<biblio>
Angulo, Silvia. <em>The Feminist Third Wave: Social Reproduction,
Feminism as Class Struggle, and </em>
Angeles, 2019.
Artnoose. 2014. Love & Letters of Insurgents. *Fifth* *Estate* 392
Arshinov, Peter. 1974/1923. *History of the Makhnovist Movement*.<em>
</em>Detroit: Black & Red
Aubert, Danielle. 2019. *The Detroit Printing Co-op*. Los Angeles:
Inventory Press
Black, Bob. 1998. **Anarchy After Leftism **(San Francisco: CAL
Press)
Black, Bob. 2004. We Have Met the Enemy and They are Us. *Social
Anarchism* 36
Black Seed. 2021. **Not on Any Map. **Berkeley: Black Seed
Blauvelt, Andrew. 2016. All Printing Is Political. *The Gradient*, Dec.6
Boldyrev, Ivan and Martin Kragh. 2015. Isaak Rubin: Historian of
Economic Thought during the
Stalinization of Social Sciences in Soviet Russia. <em>Journal of the
History of Economic </em>
Cafard, Max. 1996. The Dragons of Brno. **Fifth Estate **347
Camatte, Jacques. 1976. *The Wandering of Humanity*. Detroit: Black &
Red
Cohen, Mitchell. 2009. *Out In Front of a Dozen Dead Oceans*. Brooklyn:
Red Balloon
Dauvé, Gilles (Jean Barrot) and François Martin. 1974. <em>Eclipse and
Re-emergence of the </em>
Debord, Guy. 1970. **Society of the Spectacle. **Detroit: Black &
Red el-Ojeili, Chamsy. 2014. âCommunism⊠is the affirmation of a new
communityâ: Notes on
Jacques Camatte. *Capital & Class* 38.2:345â364 el-Ojeili, Chamsy and
Dylan Taylor. 2020. âThe Future in the Pastâ: Anarchoprimitivism and the
Critique of Civilization Today. *Rethinking Marxism* 32.2:168â186
Firth, Rhiannon and Andrew Robinson. 2020. Robotopias: mapping utopian
perspectives on new industrial technology. *International Journal of
Sociology and Social Policy* 41:3/4:298â314
Franks, Benjamin. 2020. *Anarchisms, Postanarchisms and Ethics*. Rowman
& Littlefield.
Franks, Benjamin, Nathan Jun and Leonard Williams, eds. 2018.
Geras, Norman. 1971. Essence and appearance: aspects of fetishism in
Marxâs Capital. **New Left **
Gordon, Daniel. 2011. Reaching Out to Immigrants in May 68: Specific or
Universal Appeals? In
Anna-Louise Milne &
James S. Williams. Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 93â108
Gordon, Uri. 2018. Prefigurative Politics Between Ethical Practice and
Absent Promise. **Political **
Gregoire, Roger and Fredy Perlman. 1969. <em>Worker-Student Action
Committee</em>s. Detroit: Black &
Red.
Huba, Mark. 2015. <em>The Other Shore: On Politics and âSpiritâ in Fredy
Perlmanâs </em>Against Hisstory, Against Leviathan**.** PhD, Monash
University.
Ince, Anthony. 2012. In the Shell of the Old: Anarchist geographies of
territorialisation. *Antipode*
44.5:1645â1666.
Jarach, Lawrence. 1999. Anarchists, Donât let the Left(overs) Ruin your
Appetite. **Anarchy AJoDA **48
Kinna, Ruth. 2016. *Kropotkin: Reviewing the Classical Anarchist
Tradition*. Edinburgh University
Press.
Kropotkin, Peter (1903/1969) *Modern Science and Anarchism*. In
<em>Selected Works. </em>London:
Freedom Press
Landstreicher, Wolfi. 2002. From Politics to Life: Ridding Anarchy of
the Leftist Millstone,
<em>Anarchy AJoDA </em>54
Laursen, Eric. 2021. The Operating System: An Anarchist Theory of the
Modern State. Oakland:
AK Press
Lee, Unruh. 2010. Reading âLetters of Insurgentsâ 34 Years After its
Publication. **Fifth Estate **383 Lefebvre, Henri. 2014 (1947,
1962, 1981). *Critique of Everyday Life*. London: Verso.
Lefebvre, Henri. 2009a (1940). *Dialectical Materialism*. Minneapolis:
University of Minessota
Press.
Lefebvre, Henri. 2009b (1966). Theoretical Problems of *Autogestion*. In
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp.138â152.
Lenin, Vladimir. 1917. Letter to the Central Committee. In *Collected*
Progress Publishers
Malatesta, Errico. 1899/2014. An Anarchist Programme. In *The Method of
Freedom*, ed. Davide
Turcato. Oakland: AK Press.
Marx, Karl. 1966. *Capital* vol.3. Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Mills, C. Wright. 1942. Locating the Enemy: The Nazi Behemoth Dissected
(Review of Franz Neumann, *Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of
National Socialism*). In *Power, Politics and People,* pp. 170â178.
Mills, C. Wright. 1946/2009. *From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology.*
London: Routledge
Millett, Steve. 2004. Technology is Capital: *Fifth Estate*âs critique
of the Megamachine. In
Jonathan Purkis and James Bowen, eds., <em>Changing Anarchism.
</em>Manchester University
Press, pp.73â98
Moore, John. 1995/2016. Prophets of the New World: Noam Chomsky, Murray
Bookchin, &
Fredy Perlman. In** Anarchist Speculations**. Berkeley: Ardent
Press. pp.343â366
Moore, John. 1998/2016. Maximalist Anarchism/ Anarchist Maximalism. In
Musto, Marcello. 2015. The âYoung Marxâ Myth in Interpretations of the
Economic-Philosophic
Manuscripts of 1844. *Critique* 43.2:233â260
Nocella, Anthony, Richard White and Erika Cudworth, eds. 2015.
<em>Anarchism and Animal </em>
Jefferson, NC:
McFarland
P. R. 2020. The self-abolition of the proletariat as the end of the
capitalist world. Quito: Proletarios
Revolucionarios
Perlman, Fredy and Lorraine Perlman. 1968a. *Black & Red* 2: *Chicago,
1968*
Perlman, Fredy and Lorraine Perlman. 1968b. *Black & Red* 4: <em>We
Called a Strike and No One </em>
Perlman, Fredy. 1969a. **The Reproduction of Daily Life. **Detroit:
Black & Red
âââ. 1969b. <em>The Incoherence of the Intellectual: C. Wright Millsâ
Struggle to Unite Knowledge and </em>
âââ. 1970. Essay on Commodity Fetishism. *Telos* 6:244â273
âââ and Lorraine Perlman (as M. Velli). 1972/1974. <em>Manual for
Revolutionary Leaders. </em>Detriot:
Black & Red
Perlman, Fredy. 1976.** Letters of Insurgents.** Detroit:<em>
</em>Black & Red
âââ. 1979. Progress and Nuclear Power. **Fifth Estate **14.2
âââ. 1982. Anti-Semitism and the Beirut Pogrom. *Fifth Estate* 17.3
âââ. 1983. *Against His-story, Against Leviathan!* Detroit: Black & Red
âââ. 1984. The Continuing Appeal of Nationalism. <em>Fifth Estate
</em>19.4
âââ. 1988.** The Strait.** Detroit:** **Black & Red
Perlman, Lorraine. 1989. *Having Little, Being Much: A Chronicle of
Fredy Perlmanâs Fifty Years*.
Detroit:** **Black & Red
Poynton, Darren. 2018. Introduction to <em>The Machine and its
Discontents: A Fredy Perlman </em>
Pritchard, Gareth. 2021. Modelling Power in Anarchist Perspective.
Proletarios Revolucionarios. 2020. The self-abolition of the proletariat
as the end of the capitalist world. Quito: P. R.
Rubin, Issak Illich. 1971. *Essays on Marxâs Theory of Value*, trans.
MiloĆĄ SamardĆŸija and Fredy
Perlman. Detroit: Black & Red
Scott, James. 2017. **Against the Grain**. Yale University Press
Tucker, Kevin. 2017. Introduction to Fredy Perlman, *Anything Can
Happen*. Salem, MO: Black and Green
Watson, David. Against the Megamachine. *Fifth* *Estate* 306, July, 1981
âââââ. 1997. Homage to Fredy Perlman. In *Against the Megamachine*.
Brooklyn: Autonomedia
Wengrow, David and David Graeber. 2015. Farewell to the âchildhood of
manâ: Ritual, seasonality, and the origins of inequality. *Journal of
the Royal Anthropological Institute* 21.3:597â619.
Zerzan, John. 1974/1999. Organized Labor versus âThe Revolt Against
Workâ. In **Elements of **
</biblio>
[1] This is the last time I could find Perlman using âmanâ and âmenâ
[2] This compellingly suggests Neumannâs title, and not only