💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › document › laure-akai-individualism-vs-individualism captured on 2024-08-18 at 20:16:22. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

⬅️ Previous capture (2023-03-20)

🚧 View Differences

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Individualism vs. Individualism
Date: 1992
Source: http://flag.blackened.net/liberty/indvsind.txt
Notes: Written for the magazine “Osvobohkdyeneyi Leechonostee” (“The Liberation of the Individual”) (1992) Author email: <cube@glas.apc.org>
Authors: Laure Akai
Topics: Individualist anarchism, Individualist, Egoist
Published: 2013-12-24 11:16:48Z

The notion of individualism has varying connotations in Russian and

in American perceptions. An individualist can be understood as someone

who does not understand the need to submit to the collective will, or an

unabashed hedonist, or simply a non-conformist. The most common notion

if individualism seems to be that of a philosophy of unrestricted

personal freedom, regardless of consequence. This philosophy, although a

reality, should not be confused with anarchistic individualism; any

understanding as such is really a perversion of its philosophy which

holds as sacrisanct the fundamental notion of the worth of each

individual.

This misunderstanding of both the terms anarchist and individualist

runs rampant and is evident for example in the categorization of Max

Stirner, perhaps the greatest individualist anarchist thinker, as a

spiritual father of the far right; his classic book “The Ego and Its

Own” has been published in America and abroad as a part in series on

the far right, including fascism. However far from expounding a

philosophy of individualism at all costs, Stirner pointed out that an

individual’s actions should not infringe upon others; such acts would

infringe upon the individual rights of others. It is an important

concept in individualist philosophy that the rights of the individual

are universal.

With the aforementioned as our philosophical premise we can start

an inquiry as to the nature of individualist behaviour and what is not.

First and foremost, a system of economic priveledge is anti-

individualist. Economic priveledge rests on different relations of

power. This can mean a disparagement in access to capital or it can be

monopolization and protectionism. In nearly every case, economic

priveledge relies on the exploitation of others. Strong centralized

power structures can function to ensure the priveledge of an elite.

Economic priveledge is anti-individualist, not only in the sense that

priveledge must be, by its very meaning, exclusive, non-universal but

also due to the fact that it denies others through mechanisms of

protectionism (most commonly the law) and that it most always rests on

the nonwilling exploitation of others.

Thus in far right capitalist ideology, the relation between owner

and worker is rationalized. Every owner believes they have created a job

for their worker and that, if that worker feels exploited, they are free

to get another job or to create their own business. The capitalist is

working from a point of advantage as the system of wage labour is in

place and few even question their relation to the creation of wealth.

The system does not freely allow for people to work outside it, or to

even freely work independently inside it as it uses control of the means

of exchange (money) and protectionism of capital to prevent people from

creating an economy that would cut into its profit margins. The worker

if not free — not free to take her or his share of the profits (as

Americans say, property is 9/10 of the law), nor are they free to

withold their labour as they would be denied access to the means of

exchange. Most assertions of individual rights would result in

reprisals. Fair relations cannot exist in such a rigged framework; in

individualist philosophy, the individual must be able to demand an end

to infringement without fear of reprisal.

The same goes for any situation where ownership is controlled

centrally, bureaucratically and is protected by a political system with

the power of conducting reprisal, most often through law and

imprisonment, but also through other means of denial. (a structure of

priveledge thus becomes very convenient to keep people in order.)

It can also be argued that a system of representative government,

and subsequently, a system of representative law is also anti-

individualist. While one could argue that not everybody wants to

participate in decision making processes and that that therefore,

representation is necessary, one can also see clear examples of the

“representatives” of the people making decisions that do not represent

their desires and in fact encroach on their civil liberties. There is no

system existing where the individual can legally refuse a decision not

representing their wishes once it has been encoded into law. Thus a

young Russian man may be lucky enough to find ways out of military

service — but maybe not. The ethical considerations of the individual

are inconsequential. Representatives have also been known to make laws

which simply are extensions of their moral fetishes; such are America’s

anti-sodomy and anti-adultery laws, which, though rarely enforced, exist

on the books. Putting such abuses aside, representative government can

be a vehicle for the extreme repression of the individual. Laws that

protect the individual (i.e. against murder) are relatively few. Most

laws protect a non-individual entity: government, party, structure,

church, property.

Representative government cannot be changed by an individuals

absorption into it; the structures remain the same. Decision making must

be open to those whose life the decisions effect if they so choose.

In social life too individualist philosophy cannot be seen as mere

hedonism at anybody s expense. The idea (unfortunately too often

people’s misconception of anarchy) that one can indiscriminately go

around killing, raping and doing as they please does not stem from an

anarcho-individualist philosophy. “Your right to swing the frying pan

stops where my face starts,” is a little understanding we have. If you

expect others to respect your rights, you must naturally, logically

extend this respect to others. Doing what you want, when it hurts

others, is not a celebration of individual rights, but of your own

unlimited rights, which, if they infringe seriously on others, must rest

in some power relation.

Social systems of reprisal act to repress the individual. Most

often these systems are based in a moralism of intolerance (for example

like that currently preached by many churches) rather than an ethic of

respect for diversity. The social rights of homosexuals, for example,

are often infringed upon because of some elusive structure of moral

repression whereas their relations, being consensual, have no element of

coercion and therefore infringement in them. An individualist ethic must

be tolerant of difference, both natural and chosen. If somebody wants to

tattoo their face, walk around naked, etc., this must be respected as it

has no bearing on your decisions, for example, to walk around clothed.

Prejudice of all sorts, be it racism, sexism, homophobia, national

chauvinism, has no place in an anarcho-individualist philosophy as it

sees people as members of groups, not as individuals.

Individualist philosophy, therefore, is one of the highest respect

for the individual, not an infantile disorder of the ego, not a lofty

rationalization for carrying out actions which, more likely than not,

are not product of true desires but of forces outside the individual. It

does not preclude forms of human community and cooperation. On the

contrary, an individualist ethic can include the highest forms of

(voluntary) community and cooperation (the anarchist idea of free

association). It is an idea of respect, not disrespect — of the respect

of each individual’s desire for self-realisation, unimpeded, sans power

structures and factors of social interference, and of natural desire,

whatever that might encompass.

Written for the magazine “Osvobohkdyeneyi Leechonostee” (“The Liberation

of the Individual”) (1992)

Home