đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș francisco-j-toro-stateless-environmentalism captured on 2024-08-18 at 23:58:34. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Stateless Environmentalism Subtitle: The Criticism of State by Eco-Anarchist Perspectives Date: 2021 Source: [[https://acme-journal.org/index.php/acme/article/view/1950][acme-journal.org]] Authors: Francisco J Toro Topics: Social ecology, Anarcho primitivism, Environmentalism, Eco anarchism, Environmental, Bioregionalism Published: 2021-10-22 03:18:02Z
The State and its governmental institutions have been dignified in the environmentalist mainstream as
palliative forces to face and solve the excesses and failures of capitalism and neoliberalism towards a
proper environmental management. But this environmental state falls into evident contradictions regards
to its formal commitment with environmentalist purposes. In addition, governmental institutions
contribute to expand a nihilist attitude in the environmentalist actions of the citizenship. Within the
environmentalist strands of anarchism, the matter of State has focused a relevant attention and position.
An early green criticism may be found in the nineteenth century anarchists, in which State has no room
as a violent and centralized force, and corrupting the goodness of the material, reproductive and spiritual
connection of humans with Nature. Most recent eco-anarchist approaches, such as social ecologists,
bioregionalists and anarcho-primitivists have analysed how determinant is State as a responsible agent
in the global environmental crisis and proposed alternatives to this coercive power. This paper is aiming
a) to examine some of the main contributions of the âgreenâ criticism to State from eco-anarchists; and
b) to build a consistent and wide critique of the State, helping to promote a non-statist balanced and fair
relationship between societies and Nature.
The State and governmental institutions have reached a determinant role in the environmental
arena. Specific literature and scholars refer to this as a new stage or process of mutation of the former
disrespectful and harming statist attitudes towards Nature, bonded to the origin of modern nation-states.
This rise of environmental concerns within the national centralized governance is thus named with a
variety of expressions such as âgreen stateâ (Saward 1998; Dryzek et al. 2003; Eckersley 2004; Wilson
2006; Melo-Escrihuela 2008; Huh et al. 2018), âecostateâ (Duit 2011; Craig 2020), âeco-social stateâ
(Koch and Fritz 2014; Jakobsson et al. 2018) or using a broader and all-encompassing approach as
âenvironmental stateâ (Meadowcroft 2014; Duit et al. 2016; Gough 2016; Mol 2016; Hatzisavvidou
2019; Hausknost 2020; Machin 2020).
To a certain extent, responses to environmental claims within the public institutions are in
proportion to their historical legitimacy, understanding the State as âthe most powerful human
mechanism for collective action than can compel obedience and redistribute resourcesâ (Duit et al. 2016,
3). Since the emergence of post-war Welfare States mostly in the developed countries, public institutions
have assumed the prerogative to intercede in the enhancement of standard for the citizenry, reinforcing
the interventionist role of public over particular, corporate, communal and private interests. Thereby, the
transition to an environmental state would be a step forward in the consolidation of the Welfare State
inasmuch as the challenges that must be elucidated intimately affect to social and collective dimensions
of quality of life. In fact, this transformation of the statist paradigm is actually a continuity of the same
administrative procedures and organizational model but disguised as green.
Environmental issues demand regulatory methods, such as a normative framework, sanctions and
taxes in order to guarantee basic dimensions of welfare which rely on environmental parameters; a sort
of measures that coactive and authoritarian polities might implement with quite efficacy. Both developed
and developing nation-states have increasingly placed in their administrative bodies a relevant position
to the management of environmental problems, whether it has or not an equivalent influence to other
remits, such as economy, public security and finances. Furthermore, the environmental agency has been
formed in order to overcome the traditional centralization and thus to face cross-border issues. That is,
the ecological crisis has forced to transform the conventional welfare State configuration by unfolding a
bureaucracy structure which encompasses a variety of entities in a wide range of scales. In the context
of Europe, the EU plays the role of a mega-state or trans-national corpus, commanding main lines of
action in strategic fields, distributing funds and incentives for green practices, and elaborating
environmental policies with a cascade effect all over member countries and regions. But, in addition,
many municipalities and regions, as a result of state decentralization, have been working based on
networks in order to accomplish a proper management of water resources, natural protected areas,
exchange of urban sustainability experiences or climate change collaborative actions.
A statist spirit has also penetrated the environmental praxis by a deliberately spreading of values
and knowledge. The rise of environmental concern within citizenship is, in a great extent, an achievement
of educational campaigns promoted by public institutions and resources, the assumed responsibility in
determining an official and lawful environmentalist discourse. Likewise, quite a few public funds and
budget items have been targeted to stimulate research in scientific advances, with a particular focus on
green technological solutions, driving thus the production of an amount of knowledge in favour to
strategic areas and aims of public governments. This role of public institutions in the sprawl of
environmentalist values, considering its moralistic power over society, is therefore âpart of a continuing
effort to legitimate state environmental interventionâ (Duit et al. 2016, 8).
However, the effectiveness and success of environmental state is equally questioned (Mol 2016)
since it is not working as an isolated political entity, but another actor âdeterminant oneâ in the complex
nexus of globalized market, neoliberal international organisms, cross-national corporations, institutional commitments, NGOs, environmentalist movements, and citizenship. Therefore, the capacity of
administrating and applying environmental policies has been constrained and, at the very best, tends to
have a palliative and corrective character with very little room for manoeuvre. In addition, nation-states
have lost power in their capacity to unilaterally regulate important environmental dues and duties, given
for instance the weakness shown under the influence of market institutions. Furthermore, they usually
contribute to sponsor and promote private and national projects that inflict severe and non-reversible
damages on environment, such as extractivism, hydropower dams, land grabbing and urban sprawl
(Gerber 2011; Borras Jr. et al. 2012; Grajales 2013; Wolford et al. 2013; Constantino 2016; MartĂnez-
Alier and Walter 2016). This shows that environmental states do the management of environmental
challenges through a double standard and commonly have a counterproductive effect. According to the
above scenario, it would be difficult to support the argument that the State is an authorized power in
order to face efficiently environmental issues.
Even bearing in mind these obstacles, the legitimized and gained environmental authority of
states is far to be rejected. My thesis is indeed based on a theoretical background rather than empirical.
There is an extended cliché which echoes in society, political and a significant part of the academic
discourse: the belief that liberal state is a synonym or an equivalent to democracy. And given the urgency
of solutions for environmental issues, it is assumed that âbuilding on the state government structures that
already exist seems to be a more fruitful path to take than any attempt to move beyond or around states
in the quest for environmental sustainabilityâ (Eckersley 2004, 91). In sum, the institution of
environmental state helped to reinforce the legitimacy of liberal state (Eckersley 2004, 140).
Moreover, there is enough evidence and quite a few pros and cons either to idealize or condemn
the role of State along the last six decades of environmental governance. According to Mol the
environmental state was exposed to ups and downs in all this period, gaining a broad international
recognition during the nineties (Mol 2016), but undergone a recent decline along with a âhybridisationâ
(Conca 2005) and âdiversificationâ (Spaargaren and Mol 2008) of environmental authorities. As it was
mentioned above, national governments and other modalities of public power have been the âjudge and
juryâ of the environmental crisis. So, this process of legitimation transcends such evidences, and is
sustained by a kind of imaginary which is widely accepted in diverse forums, such as the academic one.
According to the ecological critique of the administrative state, this is not âthe type of entity that is
capable of systematically prioritizing the achievement of sustainabilityâ (Eckersley 2004, 140). The
green critical theory maintains that âstates are part of the problem rather than the solution to ecological
degradationâ (Eckersley 2004, 90). Yet, it is easy to find in this left-side environmentalist movements â
such as degrowth, eco-marxism and environmental post-structuralismâ a notorious advocacy of
environmental state in spite of their failures, limitations and inefficacy, recognizing it as the lesser of two
evils solution or due to its commonly correspondence with democratic values (Demaria et al. 2013; AriĂšs
2015; Asara et al. 2015; Kallis 2015). Moreover, this legitimation is not uniquely bonded to the process
of mutation into an environmental state, but to the origin and consolidation of modern-state.
Considering this controversy, an eco-anarchist approach may help to question the legitimized
power of environmental state and to identify it as a determinant driving force of the ecological crisis.
Indeed, anarchist thought agglutinates two conditions for this examination: 1) a radical opposition to the
State as an idealistic political organization, based on ontological, scientific and moral precepts; and 2) a
long tradition of critical green thought since the early anarchist intellectuals to the contemporary
libertarians. Within it, diverse perspectives may be distinguished, from the acknowledged early anarchist
geographers as avant-garde environmentalist thinkers, to the appearance of diverse strands in responding
the emergence of environmentalist sensibilities emerged in the mid of twentieth century: social ecology,
liberation ecology, anarcho-primitivism, bioregionalism and deep ecology.
Being cautious, this work does not pretend to canonize the anarchist vision, as the most authorized
voice in order to dismantle the environmental state, for instance, in the line of how R. Goodin excessively
asserts that âgreens are basically libertarians-cum-anarchistsâ (Goodin 1992, 152). The âgreenâ labels an
incredible spectrum of ideologies, from staunch supporters to bitter enemies, of the role of the State in
the environmental agenda. Thereby, greens may encompass both a statist environmentalism, supported
by left-side parties, in proportion to social aims and equity policies, but also approaches from ultra-
neoliberal sectors, which are partisans of non-interventionist tools on the market, in the framework of
green capitalism, but quite far from or even antagonistic to anarchist positions. Yet, I consider green
anarchism and the libertarian thought in general offer a radical and utopian position that may help to
decolonize a kind of state environmentalism, based on moral precepts such as anti-authoritarianism,
social and environmental justice, but also on solid scientific background. Regarding to this green
anarchism or anarchist ecology, it has produced a wide variety of insights, perspectives and theoretical
background which share common points, but they do not form a monolithic and homogenous discourse.
Rather, the different strands concur on similarities but also display divergences in basic aspects such as
the idea of progress, the role of technological advances, the spatial organization of societies and
ontological view. In addition, considering the historical gap, the kind of arguments raised by early
anarchists rarely went straight on the topic of environmental state. As we explained above, the irruption
of this archetypical governance is a contemporary process. Nevertheless, they outlined the main
ontological and theoretical skeleton of anarchist thought and produced interesting reflections by
theorizing on the State in comparison to Nature and pre-statist societies, which are undoubtedly
impregnated of an environmental sensibility. At bottom, they laid the foundations of the modern
environmentalist critique.
Therefore, this work proposes to show that green anarchist thought has potential tools for
analysing the role played by the State in environmental governance, problematizing intrinsic and
structural aspects associated with the State as an anti-governance according to libertarian tradition. But
also, anarchist thought might be ideal in order to decolonize the environmentalist discourse and praxis
from statist attitudes and its extended legitimation. For that, three points will be analysed in order to
question the power, authority and efficacy of State in environmental issues: a) the State as an unnatural
and external institution to the Nature-society relationships; b) its configuration as entropic and
unsustainable spatial model of governance; and c) the production of statist discourse of the idea of Nature
and of its management. In addition, some controversies and divergences will be examined within the
eco-anarchist perspectives, concluding that there is not an undeniable agreement in their basic insights
on State and in their idealization of new alternatives of environmental governance.
The anarchist imaginary has been traditionally tagged with the stereotypical idea of chaos and
licentiousness (Ince and Barrera 2016), whereas State has been associated with order and organization.
This stigma has been strengthened comparing anarchism with primitivism, tribal societies, violent rebels
and convulsed times, analogies that many anarchist partisans have intentionally pretended to evoke. On
the other hand, some hegemonic political theories of Western thought have related these features to the
most ingenuous, mystic, vulnerable, archaic and lower developed stages of history. Instead, states, in
spite of their vicissitudes, are the symbol of modernity, civilized and mature societies. Thus, the
legitimation of State lies especially on this commonplace and, according to this interpretation, a
sustainable society â a sign of green prosperity â must be reached through this governmental filter.
Obviously, this cliché has been contested since very early on by the anarchist thinkers, who,
appealing to scientific and moral precepts, have argued over the abolition of State and the suitability of
non-statist orders. Anarchist ontology sees the State as an unnatural and alien polity when it is compared
to the way in which human societies have organized themselves throughout their historical evolution. In fact, an essential pillar of anarchist utopia is the conception of a social organization in which there is no
place for institutions and organizations that gather power and use it to exploit or oppress society. This is
the most recognized issue of anarchism: their partisans frontally reject any external institution to society
that imposes political authority, hierarchy and domination (Hall 2001). As Black asserts, âmorality is to
the mind what the state is to society: an alien and alienating limitation on libertyâ (Black 2004, 6).
The term âunnaturalâ contains, at first, a moral connotation for anarchists: State would be for
anarchism the least humanized way of organizing a society as it deprives legitimized rights and
aspirations of every individual: freedom, justice, equity within diversity, etc. For the founder of social
ecology, Murray Bookchin (1921â2006), the State is âunnatural and runs counter to the thrust of
evolutionâ (Davidson 2009, 56) and Ted Trainer, anarchist-oriented thinker who champions the âsimpler
wayâ in the conception of more sustainable societies, advocates that âhumans will not reach the social
maturity until they learn to govern themselvesâ (Trainer 2017, 183). These contemporary ideas about the
âunnaturalâ State nourish from the early anarchists. Mikhail Bakunin (1814â1876) categorically asserted
that the State âdenotes violence, oppression, exploitation and injusticeâ (Maximoff 1953, 224), being,
therefore, âa negation of humanityâ (Hall 2011, 376). William Godwin (1756â1836), decades before,
stressed the strong antagonism between the State and society, which affects its different ânatureâ: the
government or state authority reproduces perpetual stagnation while society manifests itself in a constant
flow (Marshall 1992, 206). He idealized the capacity of societies of being more flexible than immobile
states in order to face external changes.
Applying this argument to the performance of government, the coercive power of public
institutions is driven to control, monitor and even punish any attempt at abnormal behaviour outside
established parameters. Yet, societies would be more suitable to adapt to environmental changes than a
heavier and more intricate setting of bureaucratic institutions and normative framework. Based on this
binary ontology and capacity of flexibility, it enables to interpret the genesis of environmental states like
an encounter of forces, as a dialectic conflict between society and State. Indeed, environmental states are
somehow a metamorphosis with regard to the industrial state, assuming a greater responsibility and
transforming institutions, laws and procedures with a green philosophy. However, many of the advances
and enhancements in terms of environmental health, protection and rights are actually the reply to societal
demands, obtained with great effort and as a result of decades of tragedies, costs and sacrifices. Situations
in which society responded through adaptation or self-organized measures before public institutions
could or wanted to confront them. In this regard, and following the antagonistic view State/society, the
latter has forced to change the State performance through claims and vindications. The correspondence,
according to Peter Marshall, is not balanced, as âeven its benign face of welfare creates dependence and
undermines local initiative, mutual aid and self-helpâ (Marshall 2001).
Thus, the capacity of societies in order to implement strategies of voluntary self-sufficiency and
collective-based are dramatically cut when State intervenes, seen through the anarchist lens. Piotr
Kropotkin (1842â1921) asserted that the State, though it is a governmental corpus and normative
framework to enforce order in social interrelationships, is also a source of individualism, by which âin
proportion as the obligations towards the State grew in numbers the citizens were evidently relieved from
their obligations to each otherâ (Kropotkin 1902). Overall, individualist behaviours, in regards to
economic decisions, entail less thought on the moral limits of our actions and practices as ecological
citizens (Melo-Escrihuela 2008). Notwithstanding, a voluntary transition to self-sufficiency requires a
deep and broader sense of citizenship, and even of kinship, as the French geographer ĂlisĂ©e Reclus (1830-
1905) advocated (Reclus 1896), integrating both human individuals as well as non-human life.
Based on Trainerâs insights (Trainer 2017), the minimization of self-government and
voluntariness by imposed authority and representative democracies, might be a reason to delegitimize
state in a double scenario: a) the State still concentrates power and is the authorized administrator of environmental practices; b) the State has lost power in favour to the financial powers and market agents.
In the first scenario, the absence of self-assumed responsibility and action by the citizenship in the context
of representative democracies, might lead to a greater centralization of power and the proliferation of
eco-dictatorships, presuming a probable future of acute resource scarcity and negatively affecting the
distribution of goods (Trainer 2017). In the second one, State would dramatically fall in a nihilist terrain
of neoliberalist attitude, fostering wild competitiveness, individualistic and private interest and degrading
environmental facilities gained in the time of environmental states, i.e., a severe application of green
capitalism. Following an organizational realist approach, eco-anarchist partisans advocate that âstates
are organizations that control (or attempt to control) territories and peopleâ (Skocpol 1989; Eckersley
2004). There are internal necessities performed by the State, such as resource extraction, administration
and coercive control from which society is excluded or reduced to mere passive individuals. This
reinforces the thesis that there are statist interests beside the social ones, which are intentionally hermetic
and hidden to the population (Trainer 2017). Namely the State would have exclusive and private targets
in the environmental performance.
Moreover, the argument of âunnaturalâ State has also received scientific support among the early
anarchist geographers. Basic foundations on ideal society were provided by the geographers E. Reclus
and P. Kropotkin, along with Lev Metchnikoff (1838â1888). Indeed, this scientific anarchism gave
historical depth and biological proofs to non-statist orders (Mac Laughlin 2017). Headed by Kropotkin,
they worked in the conformation of an alternative theory to the most conservative in opposition to the
Darwinian evolutionism, being condensed in his well-known work âThe Mutual Aidâ (Kropotkin 1902).
Its essential argument is that in the success of the evolution, whether human or not, cooperation and
mutualism were more determinant than competition; attitudes that Kropotkin mainly ascribed to the
intraspecific interaction. The cooperation for survival would be the unique solid basis for having an
ethical code towards social progress (Mac Laughlin 2017). Such insight was not a brand-new discovery.
Actually, the theory of mutual aid continued an intellectual tradition of mutualism approach in Russia,
but anarchist oriented (Goodwin 2010) and probably introduced in scientific terms by the own
Metchnikoff (Ferretti and Pelletier 2019), with obvious ideological reminiscences in anarchist thinkers
such as Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1808â1865) or Robert Owen (1771â1858) (Kropotkin 1912). This would
show the State as an ineffective and destructive institution, as it does not cooperate but dominates
exerting its power in unfavourable exchange for society. Such argument adds solidity to the initial idea
that the State is an unnatural form, whereas society precedes the State and, even according to Kropotkin
himself, society is a reality prior to the emergence of the human being: âMan did not create society,
society existed before Manâ (Kropotkin 1902).
The mutual aid thesis reinforces the role of early, primitive and indigenous societies as models
for non-hierarchical and cooperative societies, to which Kropotkin devoted great attention (Kropotkin
1902; 1969) and Reclus considered to have a deeper and more embedded connection with Nature than
modern societies (Reclus 1866). Stateless societies, however, encompass different levels of technical
advances and complexities, according to the social ecologist Murray Bookchin, identifying a libertarian
tradition along the history (Bookchin 1982). These communities lacked an organizational model based
on the hierarchy or vertical domain, but they configured political systems, where authority or the exercise
of power was not given by something external. Needless to say, those anarchies were not arbitrary or
subject to chaos, but had a perfectly structured system, where in addition, the interaction with the
environment, was intimate, emotional and deeply respectful. From this ontological view, ethical
implications are derived, arguing or justifying the defence of coevolution and mutual support as essential
principles of every society, whether human or not. In fact, the political commitment of the anarchist
Kropotkin was preceded by his observations of the natural world (Todes 1989; Goodwin 2010; Mac
Laughlin 2017).
The âunnaturalâ also designates a quality that entails thinking the State as the least suitable form
of social organization to fit in the functioning and integrity of Nature and the human being within it. Not
surprisingly, early anarchists were âecologically orientedâ (Morris 1996), advocating tenets that have
had continuity in the agenda and praxis of contemporary radical environmentalism, such as
decentralization, heterarchical social organization or mutual interdependence. These practices show a
clear dichotomy and antagonism in regard to the Stateâs structure and do not lie exclusively in the
exercise of political dialectics. By exploring the roots of the anarchist movement in 19th century, it is
proven that there is a strong scientific foundation, in which, precisely, the functioning of Nature and the
understanding of its interactions motivate the anarchist utopia and therefore the ideal of a society without
State.
During this time and thanks to the previous works of geographers such as Alexander von
Humboldt (1769â1859), the study and understanding of Nature moves away from the Cartesian
mechanical philosophy to an organicist and harmonic vision of life and environment. This approach
affirmed that unlike the State there is no centralizing force within the âlivingâ component of ecological
systems, âonly interactionâ (Purchase 1994). Along with this, the organizing principle does not come
from external sources but rather it is a self-regulatory behaviour, as Kropotkin argued, where âeverything
is adapted, ordered, and organized for everything elseâ (Purchase 1994, 29). It is not (only) a romantic
claim yearning the wildlife or a contemplative attitude towards the apparent order of Nature. From a
teleological point of view, this equilibrium is not permanent or harmonically achieved without
constrictions or variability. Rather, it is understood in a broader reality at the expense of homeostasis or
local imbalances. In addition, the external source that nourishes natural ecosystems, i.e., solar radiation,
is dissipated to be used at different organizational levels. Using this metabolic model as a reference, the
State would be, however, an inefficient machine. It concentrates power to maintain order but at the
expense of increasing the entropy in its environment, that is, to those administrative units which are
submitted or receive its authority.
In addition, P. Kropotkin largely discussed the spatial strategy of capitalism and its dramatic
effects on environment and social life. In doing so, he was revealing the role of States, that he considered
âalways interfered in the economic life in favour of the capitalist exploiterâ (Kropotkin 1912, 84).
Thereby, statist targets are oriented to a severe centralization and creating disparities in the standard of
living among the population, but also extend social and environmental impacts in the territory. In his
work, âFields, factories and workshopsâ, he advocated for the decentralization of production units, such
as small-scale factories, bonded to the cultivation of fields, which he considered the way to achieve an
ecological balance, an enhancement of life conditions of workers and the creation of a counterbalance
power to the central authority of State (Mac Laughlin 2017). Indeed, for Lewis Mumford, Kropotkin was
a pioneer in a regional conception of sustainable development and organic economic, stressing the mutual
interdependence between cities and villages (Mumford 1961; Mac Laughlin 2017). He complained how
âin industry, as well as in politics, centralisation has so many admires!â (Kropotkin 1901, 179). In a
certain way, Kropotkin was already warning about State as a colonizing force of the welfare imaginary
and social progress that decades later would be filter by an environmentalist sensibility.
Given the above, for eco-anarchists, the State is far to be a suitable structure of power to which
delegate the management of Nature and environmental problems, given its size and design regarding the
eco-social space under its domain. Thus, for bioregionalists, the State is a dysfunctional spatial
configuration and the âtypically large scale of the nation-state as a territorial unit, when combined with
the centralized nature of the state as a decision-making body, ensures that it is insufficiently responsive
to the idiosyncratic needs of specific ecosystemsâ (Davidson 2009, 50). The management of complex,
non-lineal and irreversible changes of environmental problems do not fit well in the labyrinthine bureaucratic framework (Dryzek 1992) and innate features (hierarchy, accumulation of power and
material resources, administrative boundaries) of environmental states. It may also be stressed the
problems associated with the delimitation of administrative units. Bioregionalists insist in the conflict
between political boundaries and ecological-natural divisions. Indeed, Snyder warns in regards to these
frontiers, that âthe lines are quite often arbitrary and serve only to confuse peopleâs sense of natural
associations and relationshipsâ (Snyder 1980, 24â25). That would be a proof of how, in spite of the
creation of supra-national bodies in order to collaborate for the management of cross-national
ecosystems, conflicts between nation-states and administrations on which is the responsible or the ruler
over these areas are far to be resolved.
Alternatives to the entropic âmegamachineâ of State (Mumford 1970) are driven to create either
communities or cultures which would be âintegrated with nature at the level of the particular ecosystemâ
(Gorsline and House 1990). Based in these precepts, the utopianism of Charles Fourier was for many
contemporary anarchists, such as L. Mumford and Murray Bookchin, the first social ecologist ever,
inasmuch as he connected the social order with the laws of Nature (Mumford 1970; Bookchin 1982). If
these laws are properly understood, will âconduct the human race to opulence, sensual pleasures and
global unityâ (Beecher and Bienvenu 1972: 1). In the words of Mumford, it would be to move from
âmegatechnicsâ or âpowerâ to âbiotechnicsâ or âplenitudeâ: âIf we are to prevent megatechnics from
further controlling and deforming every aspect of human culture, we shall be able to do so only with the
aid of a radically different model derived directly, not from machines, but from living organisms and
organic complexes (ecosystems)â (Mumford 1970, 395).
As it may be deduced, and considering the diversity of strands that eco-anarchism has enabled,
the realization of this utopia differs among partisans of those strands. One of the differential factors is
the intensity of the adaptive capacity of the community to the environmental boundaries and biodiversity.
For instance, anarcho-primitivists (J. Zerzan, D. Jensen) mirrors the spirit of early anarchist such as
Henry David Thoreau (1817â1862) and his quest of wilderness and they âdeem âcivilisationâ in all its
various guises to be inherently destructiveâ (Smith 2007, 472). Consequently, they defend a returning to
a more primitive lifestyle. This is supposed to be a kind of tribal organization, achieving a sustaining and
pure connection with Nature. On the other hand, bioregionalists and social ecologists keep the duality
nature/culture in the political sense, and imagine communities based in principles such as
decentralization, self-sufficiency, self-ruling and communal land (Davidson 2009); all of them inspired
by the internal performance of natural ecosystems. They will set the conditions for having non-
hierarchical relations and avoid the inefficacy of accumulated power of statist institutions, its coercive
methods and the delegating responsibilities and rights. Such social utopias would demand a transition
from national-state to local governance, but self-ruling cannot be performed in isolation and autarkical
way (Sale 2000), considering both the permeability of environmental boundaries and the serious
limitation of resources in poorer contexts.
To this regard, some central points are subjected to controversy. For instance, the delimitation of
administrative units based on environmental and natural boundaries are exposed to an enormous
casuistry. This complicates the determination of a proper scale or basic unit to which span the
management of communities. Social ecologists and Murray Bookchin in particular commit to libertarian
municipalism, moulding communities to the ecosystems in which they are located (Bookchin 1974).
Bioregionalists advocate the bioregion as âan important and unique method of demarcating political
spaceâ stressing the importance of âwatershed boundaries (the distribution of rivers) as the primary
method or regional demarcationâ (Purchase 1997). The former has, technically, more problems than the
latter, insofar as the political boundaries of municipalities may be a burden to achieve a proper adaptation
and management of local ecosystems. On the other hand, the bioregion arises the problem of generating
tough constraints to the freedom and internal diversity of population in terms of rude adaptation of available natural goods and environmental thresholds; thereby, and considering a strict application of
this natural edges, population would be condemned to a kind of environmental determinism. In this sense,
Barry notes, âthat would leave some resource-poor economies in a worse position than they need be in
the absence of trade and redistributionâ (Barry 1996, 233), as he considers inappropriate an autarkic
government, to which some bioregionalists and deep-ecology thinkers are partisans (Price 2019). Both
scenarios would justify the existence of trade, charity or barter in order to compensate natural imbalances
between communities, and to get environmental justice between territories, but far from neoliberal and
capitalist codes. In any case, this localist approach, whether forcing previous political demarcations or
creating new ecologically-based ones, would potentially respond to the natural diversity and carrying-
capacity of the environments, and be more flexible than the restricted form of how environmental policies
have been applied by means of statist intervention. This approach would question the existence of same
protocols and procedures in different cities, towns and regions, in order to obey higher-scale guidelines
by states or cross-national organisms, which in the end lead to a standardization of the solutions:
âcountries are becoming increasingly similar in how and when they respond to environmental problemsâ
(Duit et al. 2016, 10).
A hypothetical transition to localism demands to reply to the problem that environmental crisis
is a global matter that inevitably require a respective global environmental governance, in order to have
common agreements and strategies. The same old song that sounds in the situation that environmental
states are experimenting and acting nowadays. Nothing new under the sun. Within the philosophy of
bioregionalism and social ecology coordinating bodies are proposed and both are moving in the line of
federalism. The French anarchist Proudhon was a firm partisan of federalism, and he considered as a
system to emphasize the political autonomy and the social order by means of social contracts and
contractual exchanges of goods and services (Mac Laughlin 2017). Probably stimulated by this
foundational idea, bioregionalists propose a confederation of communities in the shape of
communication and information networks, political deliberative and decision-making body (Sale 2000,
96). Murray Bookchin, distancing from the most autarkic ideal of bioregionalism, advocated âlibertarian
forms of confederalismâ, being âa network of administrative councilsâ, due to âdecentralism (and) self-
sufficiency which (is not enough)â to âachieve a rational ecological societyâ (Bookchin, 1989, 6). Yet,
they look alike statist institutions (Barry 1996; Davidson 2009), and critical scholars together with eco-
anarchist are not very optimistic that bioregions and municipalism by themselves, namely people without
authority, even within coordinated and federal structures, will ensure entirely democratic and real
commitment with environmental issues, without a quota of coercive power (Goldsmith 1978; Miller
1984; Barry 1996; Davidson 2009). In sum, and considering these vicissitudes, an eco-anarchist would
conclude that âa free and ecological society is best organized on the twin pillars of decentralization and
federationâ with âa direct and participatory form of democracyâ (Marshall 2001).
A third aspect of the public legitimation of environmental state resides, once again, in an
ontological premise: the human being has created a second nature, outside our first nature (Marshall
1992, 606). This binary vision is actually an Aristotelian-Hegelian teleological tradition that have
influenced from the early to the contemporary eco-anarchists, but such entities were not conceived as
separated and isolated. For instance, E. Reclus and Murray Bookchin interpreted these two realms as one
emerging from the other. That is, second nature is the product of human society, which subsequently and
simultaneously emerges from the first nature. All their artefacts, technologies, landscapes, political
institutions and ideas are the âconsciousnessâ of the first nature (Reclus 1905â08; Bookchin 1986; Toro
2018), that is, our biological condition and source of material goods. The State would be within the
second nature but, under anarchist precepts, it hinders and distorts our necessary approximation and vital
link with Nature.
Bookchin appealed to a historical analysis of societies and how power and hierarchical relations
have been built up to the present moment. He concluded that the State is ânot only a constellation of
bureaucratic and coercive institutions but also a state of mind, an instilled mentality for ordering realityâ
(Bookchin 1982, 94). In this regard, he understands the State as a psyche that has penetrated the way of
understanding politics. Therefore, according to him, the management of nature has been colonized by a
statist praxis. Since âenvironmentalism does not question the most basic premises of our society based
on domination and hierarchyâ (Marshall 1992, 611), our actions and practices toward Nature are
reproducing hierarchical, coercive and authoritarian attitudes as the State ones; to which we may added
the individualist and selfish behaviours. Even more, there are eco-friendly practices that are not officially
recognized and counted by public institutions, out of control of their protocols or normative framework,
for instance: domestic reutilization and recycling of products -non officially classified waste-, organic
agriculture without the statist guarantee stamp and informal transmission of environmentalist values and
education.
Indeed, the environmental concern of the State and governmental institutions determine, for the
social ecologists, the conception of an official environmentalism, guided by an instrumental sensibility
of Nature. Thus, the managed Nature would be a simple passive habitat composed of objects, where, at
the very best, it must act for the conservation of healthy and pristine redoubts of wild nature and for the
control of pollution (Marshall 1992, 611). This reification of environmental compounds is, for Bookchin,
the most determinant cause of the ecological crisis. It is not due to the State itself, but any institution or
system that coercively or violently fosters, through its authority, obedience, domination and exploitation
of society, whether political, religious, social or even cultural (Bookchin 1982). Such behaviours have
characterized the state intervention aligned with private corporations; involving them in the most severe
damages of twentieth century (McNeil 2000).
Undoubtedly, eco-anarchist thinkers, combining contemporary environmentalism with early
traditions, contemplate violence, injustice, coercion and abuse of power non lined up with a constructive
and carefully attitude toward natural realm (first nature). Bookchin attempted to synthetize such
argument in âEcology of Freedomâ (1982), the title of one of his works. This would mean that a free
society can only be achieved through a more respectful and closer relationship to what Nature offers us.
Not in vain, for Bookchin, the term libertarian has as its source of inspiration the own functioning of the
ecosystem: âthe image of unity in diversity, spontaneity, and complementary relations, free of all
hierarchy and dominationâ (Bookchin 1982, 30). An idea shared with early anarchists such as Reclus
and Kropotkin, for whom Nature would act as a moralizing force and as a dispenser of values and
teachings for fairer and liberating social orders (Reclus 1881; Kropotkin 1893; Toro 2016). Thus, Nature
has to be conceived beyond an instrumental way, i.e., as a simple source of resources and goods. Peaceful
and moralizing attitudes are relevant for deep ecology partisans, betting for a directly experienced
immersion with the natural world (Heckert 2010, 26). For A. Naess, âsupporters of the deep ecology
movement seem to move more in the direction of non-violent anarchism than toward communismâ
(Naess 1989, 156).
The official discourse of statist environmentalism is also supported by the structure and design
of State. For bioregionalists, the spatial configuration of states feed the epistemic disconnection of society
from nature (Davidson 2009, 50). As we argued above, the centralized and hierarchical power of
environmental state directly or indirectly is monopolizing the usage and management of Nature. In doing
so, it is liberating of responsibilities to the society and creating a perceptual and cognitive filter between
the real Nature (first nature) and citizenship. People no longer have to be concerned with manipulating
and caring environmental goods, because all of these practices are a matter of State. Public
environmentalist propaganda is thus mainly diverted to divulgate a biased and partial knowledge and
interrelationship with Nature. Governmental and regulatory institutions will offer solutions and measures that citizenship could and ought to assume (recycling practices, austere habits, use of public transport)
because they are regulated and performed according to a normative apparatus, subsidization and taxes.
Also, wild spaces and natural parks are systematically organized to make a light and comfortable
engagement of society into an iconic and domestic Nature, but keeping everything under the statist
control.
The legitimation of environmental actions of State has an added turn, based in the construction
of discourses and commonplaces. As Ward asserted: âShorn of the metaphysics with which politicians
and philosophers have enveloped it, the state can be defined as a political mechanism using forceâ which
âis directed at the enemy without, but it is aimed at the subject society withinâ (Ward 1996, 24). Not
rarely, Nature, the non-domesticated nature or first nature and its changes and forces we cannot control,
are presented as this external enemy. In the majority of Environmental Summits, states and governments
frequently invocate to a âstruggle against climate changeâ. Certainly, this responds to a deliberative
strategy of evading own responsibilities, and bringing together the most of the public involvement, and
being condescending with the neoliberal powers and institutions.
Green strands of contemporary anarchism are far to reproduce a unique discourse in their
construction of society-Nature relationship utopia, but also in their critiques of the State. It is not
surprising that Bookchin revealed his clear divergence, at least in his early works, with the proposals of
eco-Marxism, just because of the role that the State has to accomplish in an environmental facet. He
argues that the Marxist conception of environment and its justification of statist governance are clearly
capitalist in its understanding of the productive relationship with Nature. There is plenty of evidence
during the contemporary environmental history that pollution and environmental degradation were
something inherent to both capitalist and communist states, as long as the coexistence of these two blocks
existed. On the other hand, historically, there were many samples of sustainable stateless communities,
but it does not mean that contemporary ecological attitudes will be ensured throughout communities that
may be based on bioregional or municipalist organizations.
It is true that social ecology, defended by Bookchin, is not exempt from certain controversies.
For instance, he argued that human beings, through technological advances, ought to transform Nature
as a way to expand opportunities and thus achieve higher levels of freedom and comfort for society: âan
ecotechnology would be use the inexhaustible energy capacities of nature... to provide the
ecocommunity with non-polluting materials or wastes that could be easily recycledâ (Bookchin 1974,
83â84). Anarcho-primitivists and deep ecologists, in a lesser extent, are oppose to a firmly dependence
from technology. Instead, for Bookchin, technology might and has to be emancipatory, but this has not
been proven in such a way in green capitalist states or even along the history. Indeed, the analysis of the
anarchist thinker L. Mumford on âmegamachineâ showed the strong ties between statist power and the
usage of technology in order to control societies and Nature (Mumford 1967; Mumford 1970). Bookchin
saw the State, according to his critical questioning of Marxism, in a transitional period, a period of
austerity and sacrifice. For him, precisely the anarchist society should move from the terrain of necessity
(Marxist view) to the terrain of freedom (Marshall 1992, 609). Through this interpretation, Bookchin is
creating a kind of anarchist cornucopia that does not seem very real in a future scenario of scarcity and
degrowth.
Another controversial position within social ecologists and Bookchin is the omitted responsibility
with non-human species, an issue that predecessors such as E. Reclus understood as nuclear in the
restoration of our links with Nature (Toro 2018). The French geographer conceived non-human and
human life as a great family and even acknowledged its quota of importance in political action. As a
corollary, Reclus inquired into historical samples to illustrate his thesis and showed how animals have a political weight in some non-statist cultures (Reclus 1896). In the same line, anarcho-primitivists pretend
to extend the moral consideration towards animals (Hall 2011), but without questioning a kind of
supremacy of human being: âwhile condemning hierarchical domination and professing rights for all, the
Left fails to take into account the weighty needs and interests of billions of oppressed animalsâ (Best
2009, 191). However, in Bookchinâs thought there is no hint of considering the extension of the political
and moral community to other individuals or forms of existence.
This position, qualified, by himself and other authors, as humanist (Bookchin 1974; 1982;
Marshall 1992; Smith 2007) and clearly anthropocentric, distances him from other eco-anarchist
philosophies. Hence, for example, the internal tensions between social ecology and anarcho-primitivism
(Smith 2007), to which we should also add the deep ecology. The discrepancies lie in the interpretation
of how the human being has evolved until to fall in a planetary global crisis. Bookchinâs vision is more
optimistic, believing that technological development has allowed âand not the control of the means of
production, as Marxism defendsâ to place the human species in an unbeatable situation to build a
cooperativist and free society, within a well-balanced and intimate relationship with Nature. In some of
his works he fell into a certain instrumentalism, probably inheritance of P. Kropotkinâs insights who, in
M. Hallâs opinion, considered that Nature was âsomething that humanity has to grapple with, to fight
and to coloniseâ (Hall 2011, 378); or when Bakunin considered that âMan ... can and should conquer and
master this external world. He, on his part, must subdue it and wrest from it his freedom and humanityâ
(Maximoff 1953). On the other hand, the vision of anarcho-primitivism is that human race tends towards
an increasingly wider and therefore disturbing distance with Nature, which requires a return to a primitive
state or early stages of evolution, in order to recover the link with what offers us subsistence and
durability on this planet. That is, to achieve the abolition of State by a process of rewilding.
In addition, Bookchin showed a considerably dissident attitude, almost derogatory, with those
positions in defence of Nature that make an alleged naive and illusory restoration to Nature, through its
sacralisation, spiritualisation or anthropomorphism. To reinforce this thesis, H. Bull warns that ecological
degradation an all the sins assigned to the State (such as violence, injustice, power abuse) were somehow
already in pre-statist societies. Indeed, for Bookchin, this excess of romanticism has reached the point to
constitute one of the ideological foundations of the most shameful state-totalitarian projects, through the
defence of a naturalistic nationalism, which had its apogee in Nazism: âdeep ecology is subject to the
dangers represented by earlier antirational and intuitionist worldviews that, carried over into the political
realm, have produced antihumanistic and even genocidal movementsâ (Biehl and Bookchin 1995). In
any case, and according to the right conclusion of M. Smith, âdeep ecology âalliesâ cannot be dismissed
as irrational nature mystics sliding down a slippery slope to eco-fascism without engaging in serious
historical distortions and omissionsâ (Smith 2007, 476).
Finally, we may stress the divergence between bioregionalists and social ecologists, especially
notorious in the way of conceiving a green community organization: âBioregionalists tend to be more
committed to the principle of autarky, whereas social ecologists advocate confederal structuresâ
(Davidson 2009, 49). The future management natural resources scarcity is not very far from the irruption
of national autarkic projects, led by coercive and neo-fascist politics, and raised by the society in
representative democracies. This non anarchist scenario show, however, similarities with the
bioregionalist proposal, imagining communities based on the self-management of local resources and the
defence of a patriotic idea of Nature: âdecentralism (and) self-sufficiency... do not constitute a guarantee
that we will achieve a rational ecological society. In fact (these principles) have at one time or another
supported parochial communities, oligarchies, and even despotic regimesâ (Bookchin 1989). For
bioregionalism, the State is a not a requisite, but this does not mean that it must be abolished. It is
understood that âthe quality of social relations within stateless communities is such that the laws,
procedures and institutions of the state are unnecessary for governanceâ (Barry 1996: 114).
After this analysis, the different ecologically-oriented strands of anarchism deal with a central
idea: the incompatibility between free, local and sustainable communities and the State as a hierarchical,
oppressive and coercive body, in order to challenge a more responsible and proper management of
environmental issues. In fact, anarchists may contribute to influence a critical side of environmentalism
which considers the role of environmental state as non-negotiable. Indeed, according to Davidson: âmany
greens have attempted to take on board eco-anarchist criticisms of current state structures when
formulating their own account of what a green state would look likeâ (Davidson 2009, 49). Evidently,
for eco-anarchists, any more sustainable future would involve the dismantling of governmental
institutions. A proper and successful environmental management would demand not bureaucratized and
centralized polities, on the line of libertarian municipalism or bioregionalist confederalism. But,
following Bookchin, it would not be enough its elimination from the political organizations of societies.
In fact, hierarchy and abuse of power are exercised in different strata and areas of society; so, this would
require a process of decolonization of the âstatist imaginaryâ. More extravagant and unrealizable seem
the anarcho-primitivist proposal, though it may be a source of inspiration thinking in biocentric and
ecocentric positions in ethics and politics.
To this regard, it would be intricate to undertake the role of technology in this transition, since
this has been frequently associated to the exercise of bureaucratized power and to a vertical and linear
way of managing problems: standardized procedures, instrumentalization of the use of Nature,
dependency from green technologies to implement solutions, liberation of responsibilities to citizens and
little initiative to reflection, education and household practices. Thus, eco-anarchists should work to
clarify the weight of technology in an emancipatory and sustainable transition and would be
recommendable revisit Lewis Mumfordâs theory about âmegamachineâ (Mumford 1967; Mumford
1970). A deeper reflection and theorization are also missing on how the State and governmental
institutions, as well as the function of the public sphere, have negatively affected the environmental
conception and concerning that society has today. For instance, the analysis political organization of
societies should be complemented and enriched with: the examination of individual versus collective
behaviours in the management of Nature; the exploration of the idea of Nature in pre-statist and statist
societies and; the analysis of how politics of Nature has been determinant in the consolidation of modern
idea of State, etc.
This obviously requires an interpretative framework that integrates approaches involving other
disciplines such as environmental psychology, environmental history, ecological anthropology or
historical geography, along with political ecology. In addition, decolonial approaches of eco-anarchism
and buen vivir are needed to make visible other forms of social organization not mediated by hierarchical
and centralizing structures (Barrera-Bassols and Barrera 2018). Probably, it is time to recycle many of
the insights of eco-anarchists, from the early to the contemporary approaches, in order to build a more
adequate post-statist theory to the current context. Being extraordinarily useful and valued, perhaps there
is too much reverence for these approaches, requiring a necessary and fertile revision. Something
Bookchin dropped when he considered that anarchism, in the analysis of the roots of the ecological crisis,
must go beyond the State. Even more, when, at the present moment, we are facing new ways of
oppression and authority on Internet, by means of, for instance, the use of social networks, the frenetic
production of fake information and the post-truth. In any case, the role of anarchism in a transition to a
fruitful relationship with Nature seems out of doubt and âis thus scientifically vindicated and presented
as the only possible alternative to the threatening ecological extinctionâ (Marshall 1992).
<biblio>
AriĂšs, Paul. 2015. Ătat. In, Giacomo DâAlisa, Federico Demaria, and Giorgios Kallis (eds.),
DĂ©croissance. Vocabulaire pour une nouvelle Ăšre. Neuvy-en-Champagne: Ăditions le passager
clandestine, pp. 231â238.
Asara, Viviana, Iago Otero, Federico Demaria, and Esteve Corbera. 2015. Socially sustainable degrowth
as a social-ecological transformation: repoliticizing sustainability. Sustainability Sciencie, 19, 3, 375-
384.
Barrera-Bassols, NicolĂĄs, and GerĂłnimo Barrera de la Torre. 2018. On âOtherâ geographies and
anarchisms. In, Ferretti, Federico, GerĂłnimo Barrera de la Torre, Anthony Ince and Francisco Toro
(eds.), Historical Geographies of Anarchism. Early Critical Geographers and Present-Day Scientific
Challenges. New York: Routledge, 195â208.
Barry, John. 1996. Green Political Theory: Nature, Virtue and Progress. PhD thesis. Department of
Politics: University of Glasgow.
Beecher, Jonathan and Richard Bienvenu. 1972. The Utopian Vision of Charles Fourier. Boston: Beacon.
Best, Steven. 2009. Rethinking revolution: total liberation, alliance politics and a prolegomena to
resistance movements in the twenty first century. In, Randell Aster et al. (eds.), Contemporary
anarchist studies: an introductory anthology of anarchy in the academy. New York: Routledge, pp.
189â202.
Biehl, Janet and Murray Bookchin. 1995. Theses on social ecology and deep ecology. Available at:
[[http://social-ecology.org/1995/08/theses-on-social-ecology-and-deep-ecology/][social-ecology.org]] (accessed 02
December 2019).
Black, Bob. 2004. Theses on anarchism after post-modernism. Green Anarchy, 16, 6â7.
Bookchin, Murray. 1974. Toward an Ecological Society. Philosophica, 13, 73â85.
Bookchin, Murray. 1982. The Ecology of Freedom. Palo Alto, CA: Cheshire Books.
Bookchin, Murray. 1986. Post-scarcity Anarchism (with a new introduction). Montreal-Buffalo: Black
Rose Books.
Bookchin, Murray. 1989. The Meaning of Confederalism. Green Perspectives, 20. Available at:
[[https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/murray-bookchin-the-meaning-of-confederalism][theanarchistlibrary.org]] (accessed 09
December 2019).
Borras, Saturnino M., Jennifer C. Franco, Sergio GĂłmez, CristĂłbal Kay, and Max Spoor. 2012. Land
grabbing in Latin America and the Caribbean. Journal of Peasant Studies, 39, 3â4, 845â872.
Bull, Hedley. 1979. The stateâs positive role in world affairs. Daedalus, 108, 111â123.
Conca, Ken. 2005. Old states in new bottles? The hybridization of authority in global environmental
governance. In, Barry, John and Robyn Eckersley (eds.), The state and the global ecological crisis.
Cambridge, MA: MIT, pp. 181â205.
Constantino, Agostina. 2016. El capital extranjero y el acaparamiento de tierras conflictos sociales y
acumulaciĂłn por desposesiĂłn en Argentina. Revista de estudios sociales, 55, 137â149.
Craig, Martin P. A. 2020. Greening the State for a sustainable political economy. New Political Economy,
25, 1â4, [[https://doi.org/10.1080/13563467.2018.1526266][doi.org]]
Davidson, Stewart. 2009. Ecoanarchism: a critical defence. Journal of Political Ideologies, 14, 47â67.
Demaria, Federico, François Schneider, Filka Sekulova, and Joan MartĂnez-Alier, J. 2013. What is
Degrowth? From an Activist Slogan to a Social Movement. Environmental Values, 22, 191â215.
Dryzek, John S. 1992. Ecology and discursive democracy: Beyond liberal capitalism and the
administrative state. Capitalism, Nature, Socialism, 3, 18â42.
Dryzek, John S., David Downes, Christian Hunold and David Schlosberg with Hans-Kristian Hernes.
2003. Green States and Social Movements: Environmentalism in the U.S., U.K., Germany, and
Norway. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Duit, Andreas. 2011. Adaptative capacity and the ecostate. In, Boyd, Emily and Carl Folke (eds.),
Adapting Institutions. Governance, Complexity and Social-Ecological Resilience. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 127â147.
Duit, Andreas, Peter H. Feindt, and James Meadowcroft. 2016. Greening Leviathan: the rise of the
environmental state? Environmental Politics, 25, 1â23.
Eckersley, Robyn. 2004. The Green State: Rethinking Democracy, and Sovereignity. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Ferretti, Federico, and Philippe Pelletier. 2019. En los orĂgenes de la geografĂa crĂtica. Espacialidades y
relaciones de dominio en la obra de los geĂłgrafos anarquistas Reclus, Kropotkin y Mechnikov. In
Lobo, Patricia (coord.) Ser territorio. La geografĂa y el anarquismo. Madrid: La Neurosis o Las
Barricadas Ed., 43â73.
Goodin, Robert. 1992. Green Political Theory. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Goodwin, Adam. 2010. Evolution and Anarchism in International Relations: The Challenge of
Kropotkinâs Biological Ontology. Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 39, 417â437.
Gorsline, Jeremiah and Freeman House. 1990. Future primitive. In, Andruss, Van, Christopher Plant,
Judith Plant and Eleanor Wright (eds.), Home! A Bioregional Reader. Philadelphia, PA: New Society
Publishers, 39â41.
Gough, Ian. 2016. Welfare states and environmental states: a comparative analysis. Environmental
Politics, 25, 24â47.
Grajales, Jacobo. 2013. State Involvement, Land Grabbing and Counter-Insurgency in Colombia.
Development and Change, 44, 2, 211â232.
Hall, Matthew. 2011. Beyond the Human: Extending Ecological Anarchism. Environmental Politics, 20,
374â390.
Hatzisavvidou, Sophia. 2019. Inventing the environmental state: neoliberal common sense and the limits
to transformation. Environmental Politics, [[https://doi.org/10.1080/09644016.2019.1684732][doi.org]].
Hausknost, Daniel. 2020. The environmental state and the glass ceiling of transformation. Environmental
Politics, 29, 1, 17â37.
Heckert, Jamie. 2010. Anarchist roots & routes. European Journal of Ecopsychology, 1, 19â36.
Huh, Taewook, Yunyoung Kim and Jiyoung Hailiey Kim. 2018. Towards a Green state: a comparative
study on OECD countries through fuzzy-set analysis. Sustainability, 10, 3181,
[[https://doi.org/10.3390/su10093181][doi.org]].
Ince, Anthony and GerĂłnimo Barrera de la Torre. 2016. For post-statist geographies. Political
Geography, 55, 10â19.
Jakobsson, Niklas, Muttarak Raya and Mi Ah Schoyen. 2018. Dividing the pie in the eco-social state:
Exploring the relationship between public support for environmental and welfare policies.
Environment and Planning C: Politics and Space, 36, 313â339.
Kallis, Giorgos. 2015. In defense of degrowth. Edited by Aaron Vansintjan, Available in
[[https://indefenseofdegrowth.com][indefenseofdegrowth.com]]/
Koch, Max and Martin Fritz. 2014. Building the Eco-social State: do welfare regimes matter? Journal of
Social Policy, 43, 679â703.
Kropotkin, Peter. 1893. On the Teaching of Physiography. The Geographical Journal, 2, 4, 350â359.
Kropotkin, Peter. 1901. Field, factories and workshops. New York: G. P. Putnamâs sons.
Kropotkin, Peter. 1902. Mutual aid: a factor of evolution. London: Heinemann.
Kropotkin, Peter. 1912. Modern science and anarchism. London: Freedom Press.
Kropotkin, Peter. 1969. The state: its historic role. London: Freedom Press.
Machin, Amanda. 2020. Democracy, disagreement, disruption: agonism and the environmental state.
Environmental Politics, 29, 1, 155â172.
Mac Laughlin, Jim. 2017. Kropotkin y la tradiciĂłn intelectual anarquista. Barcelona: Planeta.
Marshall, Peter. 1992. Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism. London: HarperCollins.
Marshall, Peter. 2001. Liberation Ecology. Resurgence 205
MartĂnez-Alier, Joan and Mariana Walter. 2016. Social Metabolism and Conflicts over Extractivism. In,
FĂĄbio de Castro, Barbara Hogenboom, and Michiel Baud (eds.), Environmental Governance in Latin
America. New York: Palgrave MacMillan, pp. 58â85.
Maximoff, Gregori P. 1953. The political philosophy of Bakunin. New York: The Free Press.
McNeill, John R. 2000. Something New Under the Sun: An Environmental History of the Twentieth-
century World. New York: Norton.
Meadowcroft, James. 2012. Greening the State. In, Steinberg, Paul and Stacey VanDeever (eds.),
Comparative environmental politics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 63â88.
Melo-Escrihuela, Carme. 2008. Promoting Ecological Citizenship: Rights, Duties and Political Agency.
ACME: An International Journal for Critical Geographers, 7, 113â34.
Mol, Arthur P. J. 2016. The environmental nation state in decline. Environmental Politics, 25, 48â68.
Morris, Brian. 1996. Ecology and anarchism. Malvern: Images Publishing.
Mumford, Lewis. 1961. The city in history. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World
Mumford, Lewis. 1967. The Myth of the Machine (Vol. I). Technics and Human Development. New
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Mumford, Lewis. 1970. The Myth of the Machine (Vol. II). The Pentagon of Power. New York: Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich.
NĂŠss, Arne. 1989. Ecology, Community, and Lifestyle: Outline of an Ecosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Price, Andy. 2019. Green anarchism. In, Levy, Carl, and Matthew S. Adams (eds.), The Palgrave
Handbook of Anarchism, (online) Palgrave, 281â291.
Purchase, Graham. 1997. Anarchism and Ecology. Montreal: Black Rose Books.
Reclus, ĂlisĂ©e. 1866. Du sentiment de la nature dans les sociĂ©tĂ©s modernes. La Revue des Deux Mondes,
63, 352â381.
Reclus, ĂlisĂ©e. 1881. The History of a Mountain. Translated by Bertha Ness and John Lillie. New York:
Harper & Brothers, Franklin Square.
Reclus, ĂlisĂ©e. 1896. La grande famille. Le Magazine International, January.
Reclus, ĂlisĂ©e. 1905â08. LâHomme et la Terre, 6 vol. Paris: Librairie Universelle.
Sale, Kirkpatrick. 2000. Dwellers in the land: the bioregional vision. London: University of Georgia
Press.
Saward, Michael. 1998. Green state/democratic state. Contemporary Politics, 4, 345â356.
Skocpol, Theda. 1979. States and social revolutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University.
Smith, Mick. 2007. Wild-life: Anarchy, Ecology, and Ethics. Environmental Politics, 16, 470â487.
Snyder, Gary. 1980. The Real Work: Interviews and Talks 1964â1979. New York: New Direction Books.
Spaargaren, Gert and Arthur P. J. Mol. 2008. Greening global consumption: redefining politics and
authority. Global Environmental Change, 18, 3, 350â359.
Todes, Daniel. 1989. Darwin without Malthus: The struggle for existence â in Russian evolutionary
thought. New York: Oxford University Press.
Toro, Francisco. 2016. Educating for Earth consciousness: Ecopedagogy within early anarchist
Geography. In Springer, Simon, Marcelo Lopes de Souza, and Richard J. White (eds.), The
radicalization of pedagogy. Anarchism, Geography and the spirit of revolt. London: Rowman &
Littlefield, 193â221.
Toro, Francisco. 2018. The thought of ĂlisĂ©e Reclus as a source of inspiration for degrowth ethos. In,
Ferretti, Federico, GerĂłnimo Barrera de la Torre, Anthony Ince and Francisco Toro (eds.), Historical
Geographies of Anarchism. Early Critical Geographers and Present-Day Scientific Challenges. New
York: Routledge, 89â112.
Trainer, Ted. 2017. La vĂa de la simplicidad. Hacia un mundo sostenible y justo. Madrid: Trotta.
Ward, Colin. 1996. Anarchy in Action. London: Freedom Press.
Wilson, Harlan. 2006. Environmental democracy and the Green state. Environmental Democracy, 38,
276â294.
Wolford, Wendy, Saturnino M. Borras, Ruth Hall, Ian Scoones and Ben White. 2013. Governing Global
Land Deals: The Role of the State in the Rush for Land. Development and Change, 44, 2, 189â210.
</biblio>