đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș david-graeber-debt captured on 2024-08-18 at 19:48:52. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Debt Subtitle: The First 5,000 Years Date: 2011 Source: epub Authors: David Graeber Topics: Economy, Money, Debt Published: 2020-09-04 14:11:36Z
debt: **noun** 1 a sum of money owed. 2 the state of owing money.
3 a feeling of gratitude for a favour or service.
<em>âOxford English Dictionary</em>
If you owe the bank a hundred thousand dollars, the bank owns you.
If you owe the bank a hundred million dollars, you own the bank.
âAmerican Proverb
Two years ago, by a series of strange coincidences, I found myself attending a garden party at Westminster Abbey. I was a bit uncomfortable. Itâs not that other guests werenât pleasant and amicable, and Father Graeme, who had organized the party, was nothing if not a gracious and charming host. But I felt more than a little out of place. At one point, Father Graeme intervened, saying that there was someone by a nearby fountain whom I would certainly want to meet. She turned out to be a trim, well-appointed young woman who, he explained, was an attorneyââbut more of the activist kind. She works for a foundation that provides legal support for anti-poverty groups in London. Youâll probably have a lot to talk about.â
We chatted. She told me about her job. I told her I had been involved for many years with the global justice movementââanti-globalization movement,â as it was usually called in the media. She was curious: sheâd of course read a lot about Seattle, Genoa, the tear gas and street battles, but ⊠well, had we really accomplished anything by all of that?
âActually,â I said, âI think itâs kind of amazing how much we did manage to accomplish in those first couple of years.â
âFor example?â
âWell, for example, we managed to almost completely destroy the IMF.â
As it happened, she didnât actually know what the IMF was, so I offered that the International Monetary Fund basically acted as the worldâs debt enforcersââYou might say, the high-finance equivalent of the guys who come to break your legs.â I launched into historical background, explaining how, during the â70s oil crisis, OPEC countries ended up pouring so much of their newfound riches into Western banks that the banks couldnât figure out where to invest the money; how Citibank and Chase therefore began sending agents around the world trying to convince Third World dictators and politicians to take out loans (at the time, this was called âgo-go bankingâ); how they started out at extremely low rates of interest that almost immediately skyrocketed to 20 percent or so due to tight U.S. money policies in the early â80s; how, during the â80s and â90s, this led to the Third World debt crisis; how the IMF then stepped in to insist that, in order to obtain refinancing, poor countries would be obliged to abandon price supports on basic foodstuffs, or even policies of keeping strategic food reserves, and abandon free health care and free education; how all of this had led to the collapse of all the most basic supports for some of the poorest and most vulnerable people on earth. I spoke of poverty, of the looting of public resources, the collapse of societies, endemic violence, malnutrition, hopelessness, and broken lives.
âBut what was **your** position?â the lawyer asked.
âAbout the IMF? We wanted to abolish it.â
âNo, I mean, about the Third World debt.â
âOh, we wanted to abolish that too. The immediate demand was to stop the IMF from imposing structural adjustment policies, which were doing all the direct damage, but we managed to accomplish that surprisingly quickly. The more long-term aim was debt amnesty. Something along the lines of the biblical Jubilee. As far as we were concerned,â I told her, âthirty years of money flowing from the poorest countries to the richest was quite enough.â
âBut,â she objected, as if this were self-evident, âtheyâd borrowed the money! Surely one has to pay oneâs debts.â
It was at this point that I realized this was going to be a very different sort of conversation than I had originally anticipated.
Where to start? I could have begun by explaining how these loans had originally been taken out by unelected dictators who placed most of it directly in their Swiss bank accounts, and ask her to contemplate the justice of insisting that the lenders be repaid, not by the dictator, or even by his cronies, but by literally taking food from the mouths of hungry children. Or to think about how many of these poor countries had actually already paid back what theyâd borrowed three or four times now, but that through the miracle of compound interest, it still hadnât made a significant dent in the principal. I could also observe that there was a difference between refinancing loans, and demanding that in order to obtain refinancing, countries have to follow some orthodox free-market economic policy designed in Washington or Zurich that their citizens had never agreed to and never would, and that it was a bit dishonest to insist that countries adopt democratic constitutions and then also insist that, whoever gets elected, they have no control over their countryâs policies anyway. Or that the economic policies imposed by the IMF didnât even work. But there was a more basic problem: the very assumption that debts **have** to be repaid.
Actually, the remarkable thing about the statement âone has to pay oneâs debtsâ is that even according to standard economic theory, it isnât true. A lender is supposed to accept a certain degree of risk. If all loans, no matter how idiotic, were still retrievableâif there were no bankruptcy laws, for instanceâthe results would be disastrous. What reason would lenders have not to make a stupid loan?
âWell, I know that sounds like common sense,â I said, âbut the funny thing is, economically, thatâs not how loans are actually supposed to work. Financial institutions are supposed to be ways of directing resources toward profitable investments. If a bank were guaranteed to get its money back, plus interest, no matter what it did, the whole system wouldnât work. Say I were to walk into the nearest branch of the Royal Bank of Scotland and say âYou know, I just got a really great tip on the horses. Think you could lend me a couple million quid?â Obviously theyâd just laugh at me. But thatâs just because they know if my horse didnât come in, thereâd be no way for them to get the money back. But, imagine there was some law that said they were guaranteed to get their money back no matter what happens, even if that meant, I donât know, selling my daughter into slavery or harvesting my organs or something. Well, in that case, why not? Why bother waiting for someone to walk in who has a viable plan to set up a laundromat or some such? Basically, thatâs the situation the IMF created on a global levelâwhich is how you could have all those banks willing to fork over billions of dollars to a bunch of obvious crooks in the first place.â
I didnât get quite that far, because at about that point a drunken financier appeared, having noticed that we were talking about money, and began telling funny stories about moral hazardâwhich somehow, before too long, had morphed into a long and not particularly engrossing account of one of his sexual conquests. I drifted off.
Still, for several days afterward, that phrase kept resonating in my head.
âSurely one has to pay oneâs debts.â
The reason itâs so powerful is that itâs not actually an economic statement: itâs a moral statement. After all, isnât paying oneâs debts what morality is supposed to be all about? Giving people what is due them. Accepting oneâs responsibilities. Fulfilling oneâs obligations to others, just as one would expect them to fulfill their obligations to you. What could be a more obvious example of shirking oneâs responsibilities than reneging on a promise, or refusing to pay a debt?
It was that very apparent self-evidence, I realized, that made the statement so insidious. This was the kind of line that could make terrible things appear utterly bland and unremarkable. This may sound strong, but itâs hard not to feel strongly about such matters once youâve witnessed the effects. I had. For almost two years, I had lived in the highlands of Madagascar. Shortly before I arrived, there had been an outbreak of malaria. It was a particularly virulent outbreak because malaria had been wiped out in highland Madagascar many years before, so that, after a couple of generations, most people had lost their immunity. The problem was, it took money to maintain the mosquito eradication program, since there had to be periodic tests to make sure mosquitoes werenât starting to breed again and spraying campaigns if it was discovered that they were. Not a lot of money. But owing to IMF-imposed austerity programs, the government had to cut the monitoring program. Ten thousand people died. I met young mothers grieving for lost children. One might think it would be hard to make a case that the loss of ten thousand human lives is really justified in order to ensure that Citibank wouldnât have to cut its losses on one irresponsible loan that wasnât particularly important to its balance sheet anyway. But here was a perfectly decent womanâone who worked for a charitable organization, no lessâwho took it as self-evident that it was. After all, they owed the money, and surely one has to pay oneâs debts.
For the next few weeks, that phrase kept coming back at me. Why debt? What makes the concept so strangely powerful? Consumer debt is the lifeblood of our economy. All modern nation-states are built on deficit spending. Debt has come to be the central issue of international politics. But nobody seems to know exactly what it is, or how to think about it.
The very fact that we donât know what debt is, the very flexibility of the concept, is the basis of its power. If history shows anything, it is that thereâs no better way to justify relations founded on violence, to make such relations seem moral, than by reframing them in the language of debtâabove all, because it immediately makes it seem that itâs the victim whoâs doing something wrong. Mafiosi understand this. So do the commanders of conquering armies. For thousands of years, violent men have been able to tell their victims that those victims owe them something. If nothing else, they âowe them their livesâ (a telling phrase) because they havenât been killed.
Nowadays, for example, military aggression is defined as a crime against humanity, and international courts, when they are brought to bear, usually demand that aggressors pay compensation. Germany had to pay massive reparations after World War I, and Iraq is still paying Kuwait for Saddam Husseinâs invasion in 1990. Yet the Third World debt, the debt of countries like Madagascar, Bolivia, and the Philippines, seems to work precisely the other way around. Third World debtor nations are almost exclusively countries that have at one time been attacked and conquered by European countriesâoften, the very countries to whom they now owe money. In 1895, for example, France invaded Madagascar, disbanded the government of thenâQueen Ranavalona III, and declared the country a French colony. One of the first things General Gallieni did after âpacification,â as they liked to call it then, was to impose heavy taxes on the Malagasy population, in part so they could reimburse the costs of having been invaded, but also, since French colonies were supposed to be fiscally self-supporting, to defray the costs of building the railroads, highways, bridges, plantations, and so forth that the French regime wished to build. Malagasy taxpayers were never asked whether they wanted these railroads, highways, bridges, and plantations, or allowed much input into where and how they were built.[1] To the contrary: over the next half century, the French army and police slaughtered quite a number of Malagasy who objected too strongly to the arrangement (upwards of half a million, by some reports, during one revolt in 1947). Itâs not as if Madagascar has ever done any comparable damage to France. Despite this, from the beginning, the Malagasy people were told they owed France money, and to this day, the Malagasy people are still held to owe France money, and the rest of the world accepts the justice of this arrangement. When the âinternational communityâ does perceive a moral issue, itâs usually when they feel the Malagasy government is being slow to pay their debts.
But debt is not just victorâs justice; it can also be a way of punishing winners who werenât supposed to win. The most spectacular example of this is the history of the Republic of Haitiâthe first poor country to be placed in permanent debt peonage. Haiti was a nation founded by former plantation slaves who had the temerity not only to rise up in rebellion, amidst grand declarations of universal rights and freedoms, but to defeat Napoleonâs armies sent to return them to bondage. France immediately insisted that the new republic owed it 150 million francs in damages for the expropriated plantations, as well as the expenses of outfitting the failed military expeditions, and all other nations, including the United States, agreed to impose an embargo on the country until it was paid. The sum was intentionally impossible (equivalent to about 18 billion dollars), and the resultant embargo ensured that the name âHaitiâ has been a synonym for debt, poverty, and human misery ever since.[2]
Sometimes, though, debt seems to mean the very opposite. Starting in the 1980s, the United States, which insisted on strict terms for the repayment of Third World debt, itself accrued debts that easily dwarfed those of the entire Third World combinedâmainly fueled by military spending. The U.S. foreign debt, though, takes the form of treasury bonds held by institutional investors in countries (Germany, Japan, South Korea, Taiwan, Thailand, the Gulf States) that are in most cases, effectively, U.S. military protectorates, most covered in U.S. bases full of arms and equipment paid for with that very deficit spending. This has changed a little now that China has gotten in on the game (China is a special case, for reasons that will be explained later), but not very muchâeven China finds that the fact it holds so many U.S. treasury bonds makes it to some degree beholden to U.S. interests, rather than the other way around.
So what is the status of all this money continually being funneled into the U.S. treasury? Are these loans? Or is it tribute? In the past, military powers that maintained hundreds of military bases outside their own home territory were ordinarily referred to as âempires,â and empires regularly demanded tribute from subject peoples. The U.S. government, of course, insists that it is not an empireâbut one could easily make a case that the only reason it insists on treating these payments as âloansâ and not as âtributeâ is precisely to deny the reality of whatâs going on.
Now, itâs true that, throughout history, certain sorts of debt, and certain sorts of debtor, have always been treated differently than others. In the 1720s, one of the things that most scandalized the British public when conditions at debtorsâ prisons were exposed in the popular press was the fact that these prisons were regularly divided into two sections. Aristocratic inmates, who often thought of a brief stay in Fleet or Marshalsea as something of a fashion statement, were wined and dined by liveried servants and allowed to receive regular visits from prostitutes. On the âcommon side,â impoverished debtors were shackled together in tiny cells, âcovered with filth and vermin,â as one report put it, âand suffered to die, without pity, of hunger and jail fever.â[3]
In a way you can see current world economic arrangements as a much larger version of the same thing: the U.S. in this case being the Cadillac debtor, Madagascar the pauper starving in the next cellâwhile the Cadillac debtorsâ servants lecture him on how his problems are due to his own irresponsibility.
And thereâs something more fundamental going on here, a philosophical question, even, that we might do well to contemplate. What is the difference between a gangster pulling out a gun and demanding you give him a thousand dollars of âprotection money,â and that same gangster pulling out a gun and demanding you provide him with a thousand-dollar âloanâ? In most ways, obviously, nothing. But in certain ways there **is** a difference. As in the case of the U.S. debt to Korea or Japan, were the balance of power at any point to shift, were America to lose its military supremacy, were the gangster to lose his henchmen, that âloanâ might start being treated very differently. It might become a genuine liability. But the crucial element would still seem to be the gun.
Thereâs an old vaudeville gag that makes the same point even more elegantlyâhere, as improved on by Steve Wright:
I was walking down the street with a friend the other day and a guy with a gun jumps out of an alley and says âstick âem up.â
As I pull out my wallet, I figure, âshouldnât be a total loss.â So I pull out some money, turn to my friend and say, âHey, Fred, hereâs that fifty bucks I owe you.â
The robber was so offended he took out a thousand dollars of his own money, forced Fred to lend it to me at gunpoint, and then took it back again.
In the final analysis, the man with the gun doesnât have to do anything he doesnât want to do. But in order to be able to run even a regime based on violence effectively, one needs to establish some kind of set of rules. The rules can be completely arbitrary. In a way it doesnât even matter what they are. Or, at least, it doesnât matter at first. The problem is, the moment one starts framing things in terms of debt, people will inevitably start asking who really owes what to whom.
Arguments about debt have been going on for at least five thousand years. For most of human historyâat least, the history of states and empiresâmost human beings have been told that they are debtors.[4] Historians, and particularly historians of ideas, have been oddly reluctant to consider the human consequences; especially since this situationâmore than any otherâhas caused continual outrage and resentment. Tell people they are inferior, they are unlikely to be pleased, but this surprisingly rarely leads to armed revolt. Tell people that they are potential equals who have failed, and that therefore, even what they do have they do not deserve, that it isnât rightly theirs, and you are much more likely to inspire rage. Certainly this is what history would seem to teach us. For thousands of years, the struggle between rich and poor has largely taken the form of conflicts between creditors and debtorsâof arguments about the rights and wrongs of interest payments, debt peonage, amnesty, repossession, restitution, the sequestering of sheep, the seizing of vineyards, and the selling of debtorsâ children into slavery. By the same token, for the last five thousand years, with remarkable regularity, popular insurrections have begun the same way: with the ritual destruction of the debt recordsâtablets, papyri, ledgers, whatever form they might have taken in any particular time and place. (After that, rebels usually go after the records of landholding and tax assessments.) As the great classicist Moses Finley often liked to say, in the ancient world, all revolutionary movements had a single program: âCancel the debts and redistribute the land.â[5]
Our tendency to overlook this is all the more peculiar when you consider how much of our contemporary moral and religious language originally emerged directly from these very conflicts. Terms like âreckoningâ or âredemptionâ are only the most obvious, since theyâre taken directly from the language of ancient finance. In a larger sense, the same can be said of âguilt,â âfreedom,â âforgiveness,â and even âsin.â Arguments about who really owes what to whom have played a central role in shaping our basic vocabulary of right and wrong.
The fact that so much of this language did take shape in arguments about debt has left the concept strangely incoherent. After all, to argue with the king, one has to use the kingâs language, whether or not the initial premises make sense.
If one looks at the history of debt, then, what one discovers first of all is profound moral confusion. Its most obvious manifestation is that most everywhere, one finds that the majority of human beings hold simultaneously that (1) paying back money one has borrowed is a simple matter of morality, and (2) anyone in the habit of lending money is evil.
Itâs true that opinions on this latter point do shift back and forth. One extreme possibility might be the situation the French anthropologist Jean-Claude Galey encountered in a region of the eastern Himalayas, where as recently as the 1970s, the low-ranking castesâthey were referred to as âthe vanquished ones,â since they were thought to be descended from a population once conquered by the current landlord caste, many centuries beforeâlived in a situation of permanent debt dependency. Landless and penniless, they were obliged to solicit loans from the landlords simply to find a way to eatânot for the money, since the sums were paltry, but because poor debtors were expected to pay back the interest in the form of work, which meant they were at least provided with food and shelter while they cleaned out their creditorsâ outhouses and reroofed their sheds. For the âvanquishedââas for most people in the world, actuallyâthe most significant life expenses were weddings and funerals. These required a good deal of money, which always had to be borrowed. In such cases it was common practice, Galey explains, for high-caste moneylenders to demand one of the borrowerâs daughters as security. Often, when a poor man had to borrow money for his daughterâs marriage, the security would be the bride herself. She would be expected to report to the lenderâs household after her wedding night, spend a few months there as his concubine, and then, once he grew bored, be sent off to some nearby timber camp, where she would have to spend the next year or two as a prostitute working off her fatherâs debt. Once it was paid off, sheâd return to her husband and begin her married life.[6]
This seems shocking, outrageous even, but Galey does not report any widespread feeling of injustice. Everyone seemed to feel that this was just the way things worked. Neither was there much concern voiced among the local Brahmins, who were the ultimate arbiters in matters of moralityâthough this is hardly surprising, since the most prominent moneylenders were often Brahmins themselves.
Even here, of course, itâs hard to know what people were saying behind closed doors. If a group of Maoist rebels were to suddenly seize control of the area (some do operate in this part of rural India) and round up the local usurers for trial, we might hear all sorts of views expressed.
Still, what Galey describes represents, as I say, one extreme of possibility: one in which the usurers themselves are the ultimate moral authorities. Compare this with, say, medieval France, where the moral status of moneylenders was seriously in question. The Catholic Church had always forbidden the practice of lending money at interest, but the rules often fell into desuetude, causing the Church hierarchy to authorize preaching campaigns, sending mendicant friars to travel from town to town warning usurers that unless they repented and made full restitution of all interest extracted from their victims, they would surely go to Hell.
These sermons, many of which have survived, are full of horror stories of Godâs judgment on unrepentant lenders: stories of rich men struck down by madness or terrible diseases, haunted by deathbed nightmares of the snakes or demons who would soon rend or eat their flesh. In the twelfth century, when such campaigns reached their heights, more direct sanctions began to be employed. The papacy issued instructions to local parishes that all known usurers were to be excommunicated; they were not to be allowed to receive the sacraments, and under no conditions could their bodies be buried on hallowed ground. One French cardinal, Jacques de Vitry, writing around 1210, recorded the story of a particularly influential moneylender whose friends tried to pressure their parish priest to overlook the rules and allow him to be buried in the local churchyard:
Since the dead usurerâs friends were very insistent, the priest yielded to their pressure and said, âLet us put his body on a donkey and see Godâs will, and what He will do with the body. Wherever the donkey takes it, be it a church, a cemetery, or elsewhere, there will I bury it.â The body was placed upon the donkey which without deviating either to right or left, took it straight out of town to the place where thieves are hanged from the gibbet, and with a hearty buck, sent the cadaver flying into the dung beneath the gallows.[7]
Looking over world literature, it is almost impossible to find a single sympathetic representation of a moneylenderâor anyway, a professional moneylender, which means by definition one who charges interest. Iâm not sure there is another profession (executioners?) with such a consistently bad image. Itâs especially remarkable when one considers that unlike executioners, usurers often rank among the richest and most powerful people in their communities. Yet the very name, âusurer,â evokes images of loan sharks, blood money, pounds of flesh, the selling of souls, and behind them all, the Devil, often represented as himself a kind of usurer, an evil accountant with his books and ledgers, or alternately, as the figure looming just behind the usurer, biding his time until he can repossess the soul of a villain who, by his very occupation, has clearly made a compact with Hell.
Historically, there have been only two effective ways for a lender to try to wriggle out of the opprobrium: either shunt off responsibility onto some third party, or insist that the borrower is even worse. In medieval Europe, for instance, lords often took the first approach, employing Jews as surrogates. Many would even speak of âourâ Jewsâthat is, Jews under their personal protectionâthough in practice this usually meant that they would first deny Jews in their territories any means of making a living except by usury (guaranteeing that they would be widely detested), then periodically turn on them, claiming they were detestable creatures, and take the money for themselves. The second approach is of course more common. But it usually leads to the conclusion that both parties to a loan are equally guilty; the whole affair is a shabby business; and most likely, both are damned.
Other religious traditions have different perspectives. In medieval Hindu law codes, not only were interest-bearing loans permissible (the main stipulation was that interest should never exceed principal), but it was often emphasized that a debtor who did not pay would be reborn as a slave in the household of his creditorâor in later codes, reborn as his horse or ox. The same tolerant attitude toward lenders, and warnings of karmic revenge against borrowers, reappear in many strands of Buddhism. Even so, the moment that usurers were thought to go too far, exactly the same sort of stories as found in Europe would start appearing. A Medieval Japanese author recounts oneâhe insists itâs a true storyâabout the terrifying fate of Hiromushime, the wife of a wealthy district governor around 776 ad. An exceptionally greedy woman,
she would add water to the rice wine she sold and make a huge profit on such diluted sakĂ©. On the day she loaned something to someone she would use a small measuring cup, but on the day of collection she used a large one. When lending rice her scale registered small portions, but when she received payment it was in large amounts. The interest that she forcibly collected was tremendousâoften as much as ten or even one hundred times the amount of the original loan. She was rigid about collecting debts, showing no mercy whatsoever. Because of this, many people were thrown into a state of anxiety; they abandoned their households to get away from her and took to wandering in other provinces.[8]
After she died, for seven days, monks prayed over her sealed coffin. On the seventh, her body mysteriously sprang to life:
Those who came to look at her encountered an indescribable stench. From the waist up she had already become an ox with four-inch horns protruding from her forehead. Her two hands had become the hooves of an ox, her nails were now cracked so that they resembled an ox hoofâs instep. From the waist down, however, her body was that of a human. She disliked rice and preferred to eat grass. Her manner of eating was rumination. Naked, she would lie in her own excrement.[9]
Gawkers descended. Guilty and ashamed, the family made desperate attempts to buy forgiveness, canceling all debts owed to them by anybody, donating much of their wealth to religious establishments. Finally, mercifully, the monster died.
The author, himself a monk, felt that the story represented a clear case of premature reincarnationâthe woman was being punished by the law of karma for her violations of âwhat is both reasonable and right.â His problem was that Buddhist scriptures, insofar as they explicitly weighed in on the matter, didnât provide a precedent. Normally, it was debtors who were supposed to be reborn as oxen, not creditors. As a result, when it came time to explain the moral of the story, his exposition grew decidedly confusing:
It is as one sutra says: âWhen we do not repay the things that we have borrowed, our payment becomes that of being reborn as a horse or ox.â âThe debtor is like a slave, the creditor is like a master.â Or again: âa debtor is a pheasant and his creditor a hawk.â If you are in a situation of having granted a loan, do not put unreasonable pressure on your debtor for repayment. If you do, you will be reborn as a horse or an ox and be put to work for him who was in debt to you, and then you will repay many times over.[10]
So which will it be? They canât both end up as animals in each otherâs barns.
All the great religious traditions seem to bang up against this quandary in one form or another. On the one hand, insofar as all human relations involve debt, they are all morally compromised. Both parties are probably already guilty of something just by entering into the relationship; at the very least they run a significant danger of becoming guilty if repayment is delayed. On the other hand, when we say someone acts like they âdonât owe anything to anybody,â weâre hardly describing the person as a paragon of virtue. In the secular world, morality consists largely of fulfilling our obligations to others, and we have a stubborn tendency to imagine those obligations as debts. Monks, perhaps, can avoid the dilemma by detaching themselves from the secular world entirely, but the rest of us appear condemned to live in a universe that doesnât make a lot of sense.
The story of Hiromushime is a perfect illustration of the impulse to throw the accusation back at the accuserâjust as in the story about the dead usurer and the donkey, the emphasis on excrement, animals, and humiliation is clearly meant as poetic justice, the creditor forced to experience the same feelings of disgrace and degradation that debtors are always made to feel. Itâs all a more vivid, more visceral way of asking that same question: âWho really owes what to whom?â
Itâs also a perfect illustration of how the moment one asks the question âWho really owes what to whom?,â one has begun to adopt the creditorâs language. Just as if we donât pay our debts, âour payment becomes that of being reborn as a horse or an oxâ; so if you are an unreasonable creditor, you too will ârepay.â Even karmic justice can thus be reduced to the language of a business deal.
Here we come to the central question of this book: What, precisely, does it mean to say that our sense of morality and justice is reduced to the language of a business deal? What does it mean when we reduce moral obligations to debts? What changes when the one turns into the other? And how do we speak about them when our language has been so shaped by the market? On one level the difference between an obligation and a debt is simple and obvious. A debt is the obligation to pay a certain sum of money. As a result, a debt, unlike any other form of obligation, can be precisely quantified. This allows debts to become simple, cold, and impersonalâwhich, in turn, allows them to be transferable. If one owes a favor, or oneâs life, to another human beingâit is owed to that person specifically. But if one owes forty thousand dollars at 12-percent interest, it doesnât really matter who the creditor is; neither does either of the two parties have to think much about what the other party needs, wants, is capable of doingâas they certainly would if what was owed was a favor, or respect, or gratitude. One does not need to calculate the human effects; one need only calculate principal, balances, penalties, and rates of interest. If you end up having to abandon your home and wander in other provinces, if your daughter ends up in a mining camp working as a prostitute, well, thatâs unfortunate, but incidental to the creditor. Money is money, and a dealâs a deal.
From this perspective, the crucial factor, and a topic that will be explored at length in these pages, is moneyâs capacity to turn morality into a matter of impersonal arithmeticâand by doing so, to justify things that would otherwise seem outrageous or obscene. The factor of violence, which I have been emphasizing up until now, may appear secondary. The difference between a âdebtâ and a mere moral obligation is not the presence or absence of men with weapons who can enforce that obligation by seizing the debtorâs possessions or threatening to break his legs. It is simply that a creditor has the means to specify, numerically, exactly how much the debtor owes.
However, when one looks a little closer, one discovers that these two elementsâthe violence and the quantificationâare intimately linked. In fact itâs almost impossible to find one without the other. French usurers had powerful friends and enforcers, capable of bullying even Church authorities. How else would they have collected debts that were technically illegal? Hiromushime was utterly uncompromising with her debtorsââshowing no mercy whatsoeverââbut then, her husband was the governor. She didnât have to show mercy. Those of us who do not have armed men behind us cannot afford to be so exacting.
The way violence, or the threat of violence, turns human relations into mathematics will crop up again and again over the course of this book. It is the ultimate source of the moral confusion that seems to float around everything surrounding the topic of debt. The resulting dilemmas appear to be as old as civilization itself. We can observe the process in the very earliest records from ancient Mesopotamia; it finds its first philosophical expression in the Vedas, reappears in endless forms throughout recorded history, and still lies underneath the essential fabric of our institutions todayâstate and market, our most basic conceptions of the nature of freedom, morality, socialityâall of which have been shaped by a history of war, conquest, and slavery in ways weâre no longer capable of even perceiving because we can no longer imagine things any other way.
There are obvious reasons why this is a particularly important moment to reexamine the history of debt. September 2008 saw the beginning of a financial crisis that almost brought the entire world economy screeching to a halt. In many ways the world economy did: ships stopped moving across the oceans, and thousands were placed in dry dock. Building cranes were dismantled, as no more buildings were being put up. Banks largely ceased making loans. In the wake of this, there was not only public rage and bewilderment, but the beginning of an actual public conversation about the nature of debt, of money, of the financial institutions that have come to hold the fate of nations in their grip.
But that was just a moment. The conversation never ended up taking place.
The reason that people were ready for such a conversation was that the story everyone had been told for the last decade or so had just been revealed to be a colossal lie. Thereâs really no nicer way to say it. For years, everyone had been hearing of a whole host of new, ultra-sophisticated financial innovations: credit and commodity derivatives, collateralized mortgage obligation derivatives, hybrid securities, debt swaps, and so on. These new derivative markets were so incredibly sophisticated, thatâaccording to one persistent storyâa prominent investment house had to employ astrophysicists to run trading programs so complex that even the financiers couldnât begin to understand them. The message was transparent: leave these things to the professionals. You couldnât possibly get your minds around this. Even if you donât like financial capitalists very much (and few seemed inclined to argue that there was much to like about them), they were nothing if not capable, in fact so preternaturally capable, that democratic oversight of financial markets was simply inconceivable. (Even a lot of academics fell for it. I well remember going to conferences in 2006 and 2007 where trendy social theorists presented papers arguing that these new forms of securitization, linked to new information technologies, heralded a looming transformation in the very nature of time, possibilityâreality itself. I remember thinking: âSuckers!â And so they were.)
Then, when the rubble had stopped bouncing, it turned out that many if not most of them had been nothing more than very elaborate scams. They consisted of operations like selling poor families mortgages crafted in such a way as to make eventual default inevitable; taking bets on how long it would take the holders to default; packaging mortgage and bet together and selling them to institutional investors (representing, perhaps, the mortgage-holdersâ retirement accounts) claiming that it would make money no matter what happened, and allow said investors to pass such packages around as if they were money; turning over responsibility for paying off the bet to a giant insurance conglomerate that, were it to sink beneath the weight of its resultant debt (which certainly would happen), would then have to be bailed out by taxpayers (as such conglomerates were indeed bailed out).[11] In other words, it looks very much like an unusually elaborate version of what banks were doing when they lent money to dictators in Bolivia and Gabon in the late â70s: make utterly irresponsible loans with the full knowledge that, once it became known they had done so, politicians and bureaucrats would scramble to ensure that theyâd still be reimbursed anyway, no matter how many human lives had to be devastated and destroyed in order to do it.
The difference, though, was that this time, the bankers were doing it on an inconceivable scale: the total amount of debt they had run up was larger than the combined Gross Domestic Products of every country in the worldâand it threw the world into a tailspin and almost destroyed the system itself.
Armies and police geared up to combat the expected riots and unrest, but none materialized. But neither have any significant changes in how the system is run. At the time, everyone assumed that, with the very defining institutions of capitalism (Lehman Brothers, Citibank, General Motors) crumbling, and all claims to superior wisdom revealed to be false, we would at least restart a broader conversation about the nature of debt and credit institutions. And not just a conversation.
It seemed that most Americans were open to radical solutions. Surveys showed that an overwhelming majority of Americans felt that the banks should not be rescued, **whatever the economic consequences**, but that ordinary citizens stuck with bad mortgages should be bailed out. In the United States this is quite extraordinary. Since colonial days, Americans have been the population least sympathetic to debtors. In a way this is odd, since America was settled largely by absconding debtors, but itâs a country where the idea that morality is a matter of paying oneâs debts runs deeper than almost any other. In colonial days, an insolvent debtorâs ear was often nailed to a post. The United States was one of the last countries in the world to adopt a law of bankruptcy: despite the fact that in 1787, the Constitution specifically charged the new government with creating one, all attempts were rejected on âmoral groundsâ until 1898.[12] The change was epochal. For this very reason, perhaps, those in charge of moderating debate in the media and legislatures decided that this was not the time. The United States government effectively put a three-trillion-dollar Band-Aid over the problem and changed nothing. The bankers were rescued; small-scale debtorsâwith a paltry few exceptionsâwere not.[13] To the contrary, in the middle of the greatest economic recession since the â30s, we are already beginning to see a backlash against themâdriven by financial corporations who have now turned to the same government that bailed them out to apply the full force of the law against ordinary citizens in financial trouble. âItâs not a crime to owe money,â reports the Minneapolis-St. Paul **StarTribune**, âBut people are routinely being thrown in jail for failing to pay debts.â In Minnesota, âthe use of arrest warrants against debtors has jumped 60 percent over the past four years, with 845 cases in 2009 ⊠In Illinois and southwest Indiana, some judges jail debtors for missing court-ordered debt payments. In extreme cases, people stay in jail until they raise a minimum payment. In January \[2010\], a judge sentenced a Kenney, Ill., man âto indefinite incarcerationâ until he came up with $300 toward a lumber yard debt.â[14]
In other words, we are moving toward a restoration of something much like debtorsâ prisons. Meanwhile, the conversation stopped dead, popular rage against bailouts sputtered into incoherence, and we seem to be tumbling inexorably toward the next great financial catastropheâthe only real question being just how long it will take.
We have reached the point at which the IMF itself, now trying to reposition itself as the conscience of global capitalism, has begun to issue warnings that if we continue on the present course, no bailout is likely to be forthcoming the next time. The public simply will not stand for it, and as a result, everything really will come apart. âIMF Warns Second Bailout Would âThreaten Democracyâ â reads one recent headline.[15] (Of course by âdemocracyâ they mean âcapitalism.â) Surely it means something that even those who feel they are responsible for keeping the current global economic system running, who just a few years ago acted as if they could simply assume the current system would be around forever, are now seeing apocalypse everywhere.
In this case, the IMF has a point. We have every reason to believe that we do indeed stand on the brink of epochal changes.
Admittedly, the usual impulse is to imagine everything around us as absolutely new. Nowhere is this so true as with money. How many times have we been told that the advent of virtual money, the dematerialization of cash into plastic and dollars into blips of electronic information, has brought us to an unprecedented new financial world? The assumption that we were in such uncharted territory, of course, was one of the things that made it so easy for the likes of Goldman Sachs and AIG to convince people that no one could possibly understand their dazzling new financial instruments. The moment one casts matters on a broad historical scale, though, the first thing one learns is that thereâs nothing new about virtual money. Actually, this was the original form of money. Credit system, tabs, even expense accounts, all existed long before cash. These things are as old as civilization itself. True, we also find that history tends to move back and forth between periods dominated by bullionâwhere itâs assumed that gold and silver **are** moneyâand periods where money is assumed to be an abstraction, a virtual unit of account. But historically, credit money comes first, and what we are witnessing today is a return of assumptions that would have been considered obvious common sense in, say, the Middle Agesâor even ancient Mesopotamia.
But history does provide fascinating hints of what we might expect. For instance: in the past, ages of virtual credit money almost invariably involve the creation of institutions designed to prevent everything going haywireâto stop the lenders from teaming up with bureaucrats and politicians to squeeze everybody dry, as they seem to be doing now. They are accompanied by the creation of institutions designed to protect debtors. The new age of credit money we are in seems to have started precisely backwards. It began with the creation of global institutions like the IMF designed to protect not debtors, but creditors. At the same time, on the kind of historical scale weâre talking about here, a decade or two is nothing. We have very little idea what to expect.
This book is a history of debt, then, but it also uses that history as a way to ask fundamental questions about what human beings and human society are or could be likeâwhat we actually do owe each other, what it even means to ask that question. As a result, the book begins by attempting to puncture a series of mythsânot only the Myth of Barter, which is taken up in the first chapter, but also rival myths about primordial debts to the gods, or to the stateâthat in one way or another form the basis of our common-sense assumptions about the nature of economy and society. In that common-sense view, the State and the Market tower above all else as diametrically opposed principles. Historical reality reveals, however, that they were born together and have always been intertwined. The one thing that all these misconceptions have in common, we will find, is that they tend to reduce all human relations to exchange, as if our ties to society, even to the cosmos itself, can be imagined in the same terms as a business deal. This leads to another question: If not exchange, then what? In chapter five, I will begin to answer the question by drawing on the fruits of anthropology to describe a view of the moral basis of economic life; then return to the question of the origins of money to demonstrate how the very principle of exchange emerged largely as an effect of violenceâthat the real origins of money are to be found in crime and recompense, war and slavery, honor, debt, and redemption. That, in turn, opens the way to starting, with chapter eight, an actual history of the last five thousand years of debt and credit, with its great alternations between ages of virtual and physical money. Many of the discoveries here are profoundly unexpected: from the origins of modern conceptions of rights and freedoms in ancient slave law, to the origins of investment capital in medieval Chinese Buddhism, to the fact that many of Adam Smithâs most famous arguments appear to have been cribbed from the works of free-market theorists from medieval Persia (a story which, incidentally, has interesting implications for understanding the current appeal of political Islam). All of this sets the stage for a fresh approach to the last five hundred years, dominated by capitalist empires, and allows us to at least begin asking what might really be at stake in the present day.
For a very long time, the intellectual consensus has been that we can no longer ask Great Questions. Increasingly, itâs looking like we have no other choice.
<em>For every subtle and complicated question, there is a perfectly simple and straightforward answer, which is wrong</em>.
âH.L. Mencken
What is the difference between a mere obligation, a sense that one ought to behave in a certain way, or even that one owes something to someone, and a **debt**, properly speaking? The answer is simple: money. The difference between a debt and an obligation is that a debt can be precisely quantified. This requires money.
Not only is it money that makes debt possible: money and debt appear on the scene at exactly the same time. Some of the very first written documents that have come down to us are Mesopotamian tablets recording credits and debits, rations issued by temples, money owed for rent of temple lands, the value of each precisely specified in grain and silver. Some of the earliest works of moral philosophy, in turn, are reflections on what it means to imagine morality as debtâthat is, in terms of money.
A history of debt, then, is thus necessarily a history of moneyâand the easiest way to understand the role that debt has played in human society is simply to follow the forms that money has taken, and the way money has been used, across the centuriesâand the arguments that inevitably ensued about what all this means. Still, this is necessarily a very different history of money than we are used to. When economists speak of the origins of money, for example, debt is always something of an afterthought. First comes barter, then money; credit only develops later. Even if one consults books on the history of money in, say, France, India, or China, what one generally gets is a history of coinage, with barely any discussion of credit arrangements at all. For almost a century, anthropologists like me have been pointing out that there is something very wrong with this picture. The standard economic-history version has little to do with anything we observe when we examine how economic life is actually conducted, in real communities and marketplaces, almost anywhereâwhere one is much more likely to discover everyone in debt to everyone else in a dozen different ways, and that most transactions take place without the use of currency.
Why the discrepancy?
Some of it is just the nature of the evidence: coins are preserved in the archeological record; credit arrangements usually are not. Still, the problem runs deeper. The existence of credit and debt has always been something of a scandal for economists, since itâs almost impossible to pretend that those lending and borrowing money are acting on purely âeconomicâ motivations (for instance, that a loan to a stranger is the same as a loan to oneâs cousin); it seems important, therefore, to begin the story of money in an imaginary world from which credit and debt have been entirely erased. Before we can apply the tools of anthropology to reconstruct the real history of money, we need to understand whatâs wrong with the conventional account.
Economists generally speak of three functions of money: medium of exchange, unit of account, and store of value. All economic textbooks treat the first as primary. Hereâs a fairly typical extract from **Economics**, by Case, Fair, GĂ€rtner, and Heather (1996):
Money is vital to the working of a market economy. Imagine what life would be like without it. The alternative to a monetary economy is barter, people exchanging goods and services for other goods and services directly instead of exchanging via the medium of money.
How does a barter system work? Suppose you want croissants, eggs and orange juice for breakfast. Instead of going to the grocerâs and buying these things with money, you would have to find someone who has these items and is willing to trade them. You would also have to have something the baker, the orange juice purveyor and the egg vendor want. Having pencils to trade will do you no good if the baker and the orange juice and egg sellers do not want pencils.
A barter system requires a double coincidence of wants for trade to take place. That is, to effect a trade, I need not only have to find someone who has what I want, but that person must also want what I have. Where the range of traded goods is small, as it is in relatively unsophisticated economies, it is not difficult to find someone to trade with, and barter is often used.[16]
This latter point is questionable, but itâs phrased in so vague a way that it would be hard to disprove.
In a complex society with many goods, barter exchanges involve an intolerable amount of effort. Imagine trying to find people who offer for sale all the things you buy in a typical trip to the grocerâs, and who are willing to accept goods that you have to offer in exchange for their goods.
Some agreed-upon medium of exchange (or means of payment) neatly eliminates the double coincidence of wants problem.[17]
Itâs important to emphasize that this is not presented as something that actually happened, but as a purely imaginary exercise. âTo see that society benefits from a medium of exchangeâ write Begg, Fischer and Dornbuch (**Economics**, 2005), âimagine a barter economy.â âImagine the difficulty you would have today,â write Maunder, Myers, Wall, and Miller (**Economics Explained**, 1991), âif you had to exchange your labor directly for the fruits of someone elseâs labor.â âImagine,â write Parkin and King (**Economics**, 1995), âyou have roosters, but you want roses.â[18] One could multiply examples endlessly. Just about every economics textbook employed today sets out the problem the same way. Historically, they note, we know that there was a time when there was no money. What must it have been like? Well, let us imagine an economy something like todayâs, except with no money. That would have been decidedly inconvenient! Surely, people must have invented money for the sake of efficiency.
The story of money for economists always begins with a fantasy world of barter. The problem is where to locate this fantasy in time and space: Are we talking about cave men, Pacific Islanders, the American frontier? One textbook, by economists Joseph Stiglitz and John Driffill, takes us to what appears to be an imaginary New England or Midwestern town:
One can imagine an old-style farmer bartering with the blacksmith, the tailor, the grocer, and the doctor in his small town. For simple barter to work, however, there must be a double coincidence of wants ⊠Henry has potatoes and wants shoes, Joshua has an extra pair of shoes and wants potatoes. Bartering can make them both happier. But if Henry has firewood and Joshua does not need any of that, then bartering for Joshuaâs shoes requires one or both of them to go searching for more people in the hope of making a multilateral exchange. Money provides a way to make multilateral exchange much simpler. Henry sells his firewood to someone else for money and uses the money to buy Joshuaâs shoes.[19]
Again this is just a make-believe land much like the present, except with money somehow plucked away. As a result it makes no sense: Who in their right mind would set up a grocery in such a place? And how would they get supplies? But letâs leave that aside. There is a simple reason why everyone who writes an economics textbook feels they have to tell us the same story. For economists, it is in a very real sense the most important story ever told. It was by telling it, in the significant year of 1776, that Adam Smith, professor of moral philosophy at the University of Glasgow, effectively brought the discipline of economics into being.
He did not make up the story entirely out of whole cloth. Already in 330 bc, Aristotle was speculating along vaguely similar lines in his treatise on politics. At first, he suggested, families must have produced everything they needed for themselves. Gradually, some would presumably have specialized, some growing corn, others making wine, swapping one for the other.[20] Money, Aristotle assumed, must have emerged from such a process. But, like the medieval schoolmen who occasionally repeated the story, Aristotle was never clear as to how.[21]
In the years after Columbus, as Spanish and Portuguese adventurers were scouring the world for new sources of gold and silver, these vague stories disappear. Certainly no one reported discovering a land of barter. Most sixteenth- and seventeenth-century travelers in the West Indies or Africa assumed that all societies would necessarily have their own forms of money, since all societies had governments and all governments issued money.[22]
Adam Smith, on the other hand, was determined to overturn the conventional wisdom of his day. Above all, he objected to the notion that money was a creation of government. In this, Smith was the intellectual heir of the Liberal tradition of philosophers like John Locke, who had argued that government begins in the need to protect private property and operated best when it tried to limit itself to that function. Smith expanded on the argument, insisting that property, money and markets not only existed before political institutions but were the very foundation of human society. It followed that insofar as government should play any role in monetary affairs, it should limit itself to guaranteeing the soundness of the currency. It was only by making such an argument that he could insist that economics is itself a field of human inquiry with its own principles and lawsâthat is, as distinct from, say ethics or politics.
Smithâs argument is worth laying out in detail because it is, as I say, the great founding myth of the discipline of economics.
What, he begins, is the basis of economic life, properly speaking? It is âa certain propensity in human nature ⊠the propensity to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another.â Animals donât do this. âNobody,â Smith observes, âever saw a dog make a fair and deliberate exchange of one bone for another with another dog.â[23] But humans, if left to their own devices, will inevitably begin swapping and comparing things. This is just what humans do. Even logic and conversation are really just forms of trading, and as in all things, humans will always try to seek their own best advantage, to seek the greatest profit they can from the exchange.[24]
It is this drive to exchange, in turn, which creates that division of labor responsible for all human achievement and civilization. Here the scene shifts to another one of those economistsâ faraway fantasylandsâit seems to be an amalgam of North American Indians and Central Asian pastoral nomads:[25]
In a tribe of hunters or shepherds a particular person makes bows and arrows, for example, with more readiness and dexterity than any other. He frequently exchanges them for cattle or for venison with his companions; and he finds at last that he can in this manner get more cattle and venison, than if he himself went to the field to catch them. From a regard to his own interest, therefore, the making of bows and arrows grows to be his chief business, and he becomes a sort of armourer. Another excels in making the frames and covers of their little huts or moveable houses. He is accustomed to be of use in this way to his neighbours, who reward him in the same manner with cattle and with venison, till at last he finds it his interest to dedicate himself entirely to this employment, and to become a sort of house-carpenter. In the same manner a third becomes a smith or a brazier; a fourth a tanner or dresser of hides or skins, the principal part of the clothing of savages âŠ
Itâs only once we have expert arrow-makers, wigwam-makers, and so on that people start realizing thereâs a problem. Notice how, as in so many examples, we have a tendency to slip from imaginary savages to small-town shopkeepers.
But when the division of labor first began to take place, this power of exchanging must frequently have been very much clogged and embarrassed in its operations. One man, we shall suppose, has more of a certain commodity than he himself has occasion for, while another has less. The former consequently would be glad to dispose of, and the latter to purchase, a part of this superfluity. But if this latter should chance to have nothing that the former stands in need of, no exchange can be made between them. The butcher has more meat in his shop than he himself can consume, and the brewer and the baker would each of them be willing to purchase a part of it. But they have nothing to offer in exchange âŠ
In order to avoid the inconveniency of such situations, every prudent man in every period of society, after the first establishment of the division of labor, must naturally have endeavored to manage his affairs in such a manner, as to have at all times by him, besides the peculiar produce of his own industry, a certain quantity of some one commodity or other, such as he imagined that few people would be likely to refuse in exchange for the produce of their industry.[26]
So everyone will inevitably start stockpiling something they figure that everyone else is likely to want. This has a paradoxical effect, because at a certain point, rather than making that commodity less valuable (since everyone already has some) it becomes more valuable (because it becomes, effectively, currency):
Salt is said to be the common instrument of commerce and exchanges in Abyssinia; a species of shells in some parts of the coast of India; dried cod at Newfoundland; tobacco in Virginia; sugar in some of our West India colonies; hides or dressed leather in some other countries; and there is at this day a village in Scotland where it is not uncommon, I am told, for a workman to carry nails instead of money to the bakerâs shop or the ale-house.[27]
Eventually, of course, at least for long-distance trade, it all boils down to precious metals, since these are ideally suited to serve as currency, being durable, portable, and able to be endlessly subdivided into identical portions.
Different metals have been made use of by different nations for this purpose. Iron was the common instrument of commerce among the ancient Spartans; copper among the ancient Romans; and gold and silver among all rich and commercial nations.
Those metals seem originally to have been made use of for this purpose in rude bars, without any stamp or coinage âŠ
The use of metals in this rude state was attended with two very considerable inconveniencies; first with the trouble of weighing; and, secondly, with that of assaying them. In the precious metals, where a small difference in the quantity makes a great difference in the value, even the business of weighing, with proper exactness, requires at least very accurate weights and scales. The weighing of gold in particular is an operation of some nicety âŠ[28]
Itâs easy to see where this is going. Using irregular metal ingots is easier than barter, but wouldnât standardizing the unitsâsay, stamping pieces of metal with uniform designations guaranteeing weight and fineness, in different denominationsâmake things easier still? Clearly it would, and so was coinage born. True, issuing coinage meant governments had to get involved, since they generally ran the mints; but in the standard version of the story, governments have only this one limited roleâto guarantee the money supplyâand tend to do it badly, since throughout history, unscrupulous kings have often cheated by debasing the coinage and causing inflation and other sorts of political havoc in what was originally a matter of simple economic common sense.
Tellingly, this story played a crucial role not only in founding the discipline of economics, but in the very idea that there was something called âthe economy,â which operated by its own rules, separate from moral or political life, that economists could take as their field of study. âThe economyâ is where we indulge in our natural propensity to truck and barter. We are still trucking and bartering. We always will be. Money is simply the most efficient means.
Economists like Karl Menger and Stanley Jevons later improved on the details of the story, most of all by adding various mathematical equations to demonstrate that a random assortment of people with random desires could, in theory, produce not only a single commodity to use as money but a uniform price system. In the process, they also substituted all sorts of impressive technical vocabulary (i.e., âinconveniencesâ became âtransaction costsâ). The crucial thing, though, is that by now, this story has become simple common sense for most people. We teach it to children in schoolbooks and museums. Everybody knows it. âOnce upon a time, there was barter. It was difficult. So people invented money. Then came the development of banking and credit.â It all forms a perfectly simple, straightforward progression, a process of increasing sophistication and abstraction that has carried humanity, logically and inexorably, from the Stone Age exchange of mastodon tusks to stock markets, hedge funds, and securitized derivatives.[29]
It really has become ubiquitous. Wherever we find money, we also find the story. At one point, in the town of Arivonimamo, in Madagascar, I had the privilege of interviewing a Kalanoro, a tiny ghostly creature that a local spirit medium claimed to keep hidden away in a chest in his home. The spirit belonged to the brother of a notorious local loan shark, a horrible woman named Nordine, and to be honest I was a bit reluctant to have anything to do with the family, but some of my friends insistedâsince after all, this was a creature from ancient times. The creature spoke from behind a screen in an eerie, otherworldly quaver. But all it was really interested in talking about was money. Finally, slightly exasperated by the whole charade, I asked, âSo, what did you use for money back in ancient times, when you were still alive?â
The mysterious voice immediately replied, âNo. We didnât use money. In ancient times we used to barter commodities directly, one for the other âŠâ
The story, then, is everywhere. It is the founding myth of our system of economic relations. It is so deeply established in common sense, even in places like Madagascar, that most people on earth couldnât imagine any other way that money possibly could have come about.
The problem is thereâs no evidence that it ever happened, and an enormous amount of evidence suggesting that it did not.
For centuries now, explorers have been trying to find this fabled land of barterânone with success. Adam Smith set his story in aboriginal North America (others preferred Africa or the Pacific). In Smithâs time, at least it could be said that reliable information on Native American economic systems was unavailable in Scottish libraries. But by mid-century, Lewis Henry Morganâs descriptions of the Six Nations of the Iroquois, among others, were widely publishedâand they made clear that the main economic institution among the Iroquois nations were longhouses where most goods were stockpiled and then allocated by womenâs councils, and no one ever traded arrowheads for slabs of meat. Economists simply ignored this information.[30] Stanley Jevons, for example, who in 1871 wrote what has come to be considered the classic book on the origins of money, took his examples straight from Smith, with Indians swapping venison for elk and beaver hides, and made no use of actual descriptions of Indian life that made it clear that Smith had simply made this up. Around that same time, missionaries, adventurers, and colonial administrators were fanning out across the world, many bringing copies of Smithâs book with them, expecting to find the land of barter. None ever did. They discovered an almost endless variety of economic systems. But to this day, no one has been able to locate a part of the world where the ordinary mode of economic transaction between neighbors takes the form of âIâll give you twenty chickens for that cow.â
The definitive anthropological work on barter, by Caroline Humphrey, of Cambridge, could not be more definitive in its conclusions: âNo example of a barter economy, pure and simple, has ever been described, let alone the emergence from it of money; all available ethnography suggests that there never has been such a thing.â[31]
Now, all this hardly means that barter does not existâor even that itâs never practiced by the sort of people that Smith would refer to as âsavages.â It just means that itâs almost never employed, as Smith imagined, between fellow villagers. Ordinarily, it takes place between strangers, even enemies. Let us begin with the Nambikwara of Brazil. They would seem to fit all the criteria: they are a simple society without much in the way of division of labor, organized into small bands that traditionally numbered at best a hundred people each. Occasionally if one band spots the cooking fires of another in their vicinity, they will send emissaries to negotiate a meeting for purposes of trade. If the offer is accepted, they will first hide their women and children in the forest, then invite the men of other band to visit camp. Each band has a chief; once everyone has been assembled, each chief gives a formal speech praising the other party and belittling his own; everyone puts aside their weapons to sing and dance togetherâthough the dance is one that mimics military confrontation. Then, individuals from each side approach each other to trade:
If an individual wants an object he extols it by saying how fine it is. If a man values an object and wants much in exchange for it, instead of saying that it is very valuable he says that it is no good, thus showing his desire to keep it. âThis axe is no good, it is very old, it is very dull,â he will say, referring to his axe which the other wants.
This argument is carried on in an angry tone of voice until a settlement is reached. When agreement has been reached each snatches the object out of the otherâs hand. If a man has bartered a necklace, instead of taking it off and handing it over, the other person must take it off with a show of force. Disputes, often leading to fights, occur when one party is a little premature and snatches the object before the other has finished arguing.[32]
The whole business concludes with a great feast at which the women reappear, but this too can lead to problems, since amidst the music and good cheer, there is ample opportunity for seductions.[33] This sometimes led to jealous quarrels. Occasionally, people would get killed.
Barter, then, for all the festive elements, was carried out between people who might otherwise be enemies and hovered about an inch away from outright warfareâand, if the ethnographer is to be believedâif one side later decided they had been taken advantage of, it could very easily lead to actual wars.
To shift our spotlight halfway around the world to Western Arnhem Land in Australia, where the Gunwinggu people are famous for entertaining neighbors in rituals of ceremonial barter called the **dzamalag**. Here the threat of actual violence seems much more distant. Partly, this is because things are made easier by the existence of a moiety system that embraces the whole region: no one is allowed to marry, or even have sex with, people of their own moiety, no matter where they come from, but anyone from the other is technically a potential match. Therefore, for a man, even in distant communities, half the women are strictly forbidden, half of them fair game. The region is also united by local specialization: each people has its own trade product to be bartered with the others.
What follows is from a description of a **dzamalag** held in the 1940s, as observed by an anthropologist named Ronald Berndt.
Once again, it begins as strangers, after some initial negotiations, are invited into the hostsâ main camp. The visitors in this particular example were famous for their âmuch-prized serrated spearsââtheir hosts had access to good European cloth. The trading begins when the visiting party, which consisted of both men and women, enters the campâs dancing ground of âring place,â and three of them began to entertain their hosts with music. Two men start singing, a third accompanies them on the **didjeridu**. Before long, women from the hostsâ side come and attack the musicians:
Men and women rise and begin to dance. The **dzamalag** opens when two Gunwinggu women of the opposite moiety to the singing men âgive **dzamalagâ** to the latter. They present each man with a piece of cloth, and hit or touch him, pulling him down on the ground, calling him a **dzamalag** husband, and joking with him in an erotic vein. Then another woman of the opposite moiety to the pipe player gives him cloth, hits and jokes with him.
This sets in motion the **dzamalag** exchange. Men from the visiting group sit quietly while women of the opposite moiety come over and give them cloth, hit them, and invite them to copulate; they take any liberty they choose with the men, amid amusement and applause, while the singing and dancing continue. Women try to undo the menâs loin coverings or touch their penises, and to drag them from the âring placeâ for coitus. The men go with their **dzamalag** partners, with a show of reluctance, to copulate in the bushes away from the fires which light up the dancers. They may give the women tobacco or beads. When the women return, they give part of this tobacco to their own husbands, who have encouraged them to go **dzamalag**. The husbands, in turn, use the tobacco to pay their own female **dzamalag** partners âŠ[34]
New singers and musicians appear, are again assaulted and dragged off to the bushes; men encourage their wives ânot to be shy,â so as to maintain the Gunwinggu reputation for hospitality; eventually those men also take the initiative with the visitorsâ wives, offering cloth, hitting them, and leading them off into the bushes. Beads and tobacco circulate. Finally, once participants have all paired off at least once, and the guests are satisfied with the cloth they have acquired, the women stop dancing and stand in two rows and the visitors line up to repay them.
Then visiting men of one moiety dance towards the women of the opposite moiety, in order to âgive them **dzamalag.â** They hold shovel-nosed spears poised, pretending to spear the women, but instead hit them with the flat of the blade. âWe will not spear you, for we have already speared you with our penises.â They present the spears to the women. Then visiting men of the other moiety go through the same actions with the women of their opposite moiety, giving them spears with serrated points. This terminates the ceremony, which is followed by a large distribution of food.[35]
This is a particularly dramatic case, but dramatic cases are revealing. What the Gunwinggu hosts appear to have been able to do here, owing to the relatively amicable relations between neighboring peoples in Western Arnhem Land, is to take all the elements in Nambikwara barter (the music and dancing, the potential hostility, the sexual intrigue), and turn it all into a kind of festive gameâone not, perhaps, without its dangers, but (as the ethnographer emphasizes) considered enormous fun by everyone concerned.
What all such cases of trade through barter have in common is that they are meetings with strangers who will, likely as not, never meet again, and with whom one certainly will not enter into any ongoing relations. This is why a direct one-on-one exchange is appropriate: each side makes their trade and walks away. Itâs all made possible by laying down an initial mantle of sociability, in the form of shared pleasures, music and danceâthe usual base of conviviality on which trade must always be built. Then comes the actual trading, where both sides make a great display of the latent hostility that necessarily exists in any exchange of material goods between strangersâwhere neither party has no particular reason **not** to take advantage of the otherâby playful mock aggression, though in the Nambikwara case, where the mantle of sociability is extremely thin, mock aggression is in constant danger of slipping over into the real thing. The Gunwinggu, with their more relaxed attitude toward sexuality, have quite ingeniously managed to make the shared pleasures and aggression into exactly the same thing.
Recall here the language of the economics textbooks: âImagine a society without money.â âImagine a barter economy.â One thing these examples make abundantly clear is just how limited the imaginative powers of most economists turn out to be.[36]
Why? The simplest answer would be: for there to even be a discipline called âeconomics,â a discipline that concerns itself first and foremost with how individuals seek the most advantageous arrangement for the exchange of shoes for potatoes, or cloth for spears, it must assume that the exchange of such goods need have nothing to do with war, passion, adventure, mystery, sex, or death. Economics assumes a division between different spheres of human behavior that, among people like the Gunwinngu and the Nambikwara, simply does not exist. These divisions in turn are made possible by very specific institutional arrangements: the existence of lawyers, prisons, and police, to ensure that even people who donât like each other very much, who have no interest in developing any kind of ongoing relationship, but are simply interested in getting their hands on as much of the othersâ possessions as possible, will nonetheless refrain from the most obvious expedient (theft). This in turn allows us to assume that life is neatly divided between the marketplace, where we do our shopping, and the âsphere of consumption,â where we concern ourselves with music, feasts, and seduction. In other words, the vision of the world that forms the basis of the economics textbooks, which Adam Smith played so large a part in promulgating, has by now become so much a part of our common sense that we find it hard to imagine any other possible arrangement.
From these examples, it begins to be clear why there are no societies based on barter. Such a society could only be one in which everybody was an inch away from everybody elseâs throat; but nonetheless hovering there, poised to strike but never actually striking, forever. True, barter does sometimes occur between people who do not consider each other strangers, but theyâre usually people who might as well be strangersâthat is, who feel no sense of mutual responsibility or trust, or the desire to develop ongoing relations. The Pukhtun of Northern Pakistan, for instance, are famous for their open-handed hospitality. Barter is what you do with those to whom you are **not** bound by ties of hospitality (or kinship, or much of anything else):
A favorite mode of exchange among men is barter, or **adal-badal** (give and take). Men are always on the alert for the possibility of bartering one of their possessions for something better. Often the exchange is like for like: a radio for a radio, sunglasses for sunglasses, a watch for a watch. However, unlike objects can also be exchanged, such as, in one instance, a bicycle for two donkeys. **Adal-badal** is always practiced with non-relatives and affords men a great deal of pleasure as they attempt to get the advantage over their exchange partner. A good exchange, in which a man feels he has gotten the better of the deal, is cause for bragging and pride. If the exchange is bad, the recipient tries to renege on the deal or, failing that, to palm off the faulty object on someone unsuspecting. The best partner in **adal-badal** is someone who is distant spatially and will therefore have little opportunity to complain.[37]
Neither are such unscrupulous motives limited to Central Asia. They seem inherent to the very nature of barterâwhich would explain the fact that in the century or two before Smithâs time, the English words âtruck and barter,â like their equivalents in French, Spanish, German, Dutch, and Portuguese, literally meant âto trick, bamboozle, or rip off.â[38] Swapping one thing directly for another while trying to get the best deal one can out of the transaction is, ordinarily, how one deals with people one doesnât care about and doesnât expect to see again. What reason is there **not** to try to take advantage of such a person? If, on the other hand, one cares enough about someoneâa neighbor, a friendâto wish to deal with her fairly and honestly, one will inevitably also care about her enough to take her individual needs, desires, and situation into account. Even if you do swap one thing for another, you are likely to frame the matter as a gift.
To illustrate what I mean by this, letâs return to the economics textbooks and the problem of the âdouble coincidence of wants.â When we left Henry, he needed a pair of shoes, but all he had lying around were some potatoes. Joshua had an extra pair of shoes, but he didnât really need potatoes. Since money has not yet been invented, they have a problem. What are they to do?
The first thing that should be clear by now is that weâd really have to know a bit more about Joshua and Henry. Who are they? Are they related? If so, how? They appear to live in a small community. Any two people who have been living their lives in the same small community will have some sort of complicated history with each other. Are they friends, rivals, allies, lovers, enemies, or several of these things at once?
The authors of the original example seem to assume two neighbors of roughly equal status, not closely related, but on friendly termsâthat is, as close to neutral equality as one can get. Even so, this doesnât say much. For example, if Henry was living in a Seneca longhouse, and needed shoes, Joshua would not even enter into it; heâd simply mention it to his wife, whoâd bring up the matter with the other matrons, fetch materials from the longhouseâs collective storehouse, and sew him some. Alternately, to find a scenario fit for an imaginary economics textbook, we might place Joshua and Henry together in a small, intimate community like a Nambikwara or Gunwinggu band.
SCENARIO 1
Henry walks up to Joshua and says âNice shoes!â
Joshua says, âOh, theyâre not much, but since you seem to like them, by all means take them.â
Henry takes the shoes.
Henryâs potatoes are not at issue since both parties are perfectly well aware that if Joshua were ever short of potatoes, Henry would give him some.
And thatâs about it. Of course itâs not clear, in this case, how long Henry will actually get to keep the shoes. It probably depends on how nice they are. If they were just ordinary shoes, this might be the end of the matter. If they are in any way unique or beautiful, they might end up being passed around. Thereâs a famous story that John and Lorna Marshall, who carried out a study of Kalahari Bushmen in the â60s, once gave a knife to one of their favorite informants. They left and came back a year later, only to discover that pretty much everyone in the band had been in possession of the knife at some point in between. On the other hand, several Arab friends confirm to me that in less strictly egalitarian contexts, there is an expedient. If a friend praises a bracelet or bag, you are normally expected to immediately say âtake itââbut if you are really determined to hold on to it, you can always say, âyes, isnât it beautiful? It was a gift.â
But clearly, the authors of the textbook have a slightly more impersonal transaction in mind. The authors seem to imagine the two men as the heads of patriarchal households, on good terms with each other, but who keep their own supplies. Perhaps they live in one of those Scottish villages with the butcher and the baker in Adam Smithâs examples, or a colonial settlement in New England. Except for some reason theyâve never heard of money. Itâs a peculiar fantasy, but letâs see what we can do:
SCENARIO 2
Henry walks up to Joshua and says, âNice shoes!â
Or, perhapsâletâs make this a bit more realisticâHenryâs wife is chatting with Joshuaâs and strategically lets slip that the state of Henryâs shoes is getting so bad heâs complaining about corns.
The message is conveyed, and Joshua comes by the next day to offer his extra pair to Henry as a present, insisting that this is just a neighborly gesture. He would certainly never want anything in return.
It doesnât matter whether Joshua is sincere in saying this. By doing so, Joshua thereby registers a credit. Henry owes him one.
How might Henry pay Joshua back? There are endless possibilities. Perhaps Joshua really does want potatoes. Henry waits a discrete interval and drops them off, insisting that this too is just a gift. Or Joshua doesnât need potatoes now but Henry waits until he does. Or maybe a year later, Joshua is planning a banquet, so he comes strolling by Henryâs barnyard and says âNice pig âŠâ
In any of these scenarios, the problem of âdouble coincidence of wants,â so endlessly invoked in the economics textbooks, simply disappears. Henry might not have something Joshua wants right now. But if the two are neighbors, itâs obviously only a matter of time before he will.[39]
This in turn means that the need to stockpile commonly acceptable items in the way that Smith suggested disappears as well. With it goes the need to develop currency. As with so many actual small communities, everyone simply keeps track of who owes what to whom.
There is just one major conceptual problem hereâone the attentive reader might have noticed. Henry âowes Joshua one.â One what? How do you quantify a favor? On what basis do you say that this many potatoes, or this big a pig, seems more or less equivalent to a pair of shoes? Because even if these things remain rough-and-ready approximations, there must be **some** way to establish that X is roughly equivalent to Y, or slightly worse or slightly better. Doesnât this imply that something like money, at least in the sense of a unit of accounts by which one can compare the value of different objects, already has to exist?
In most gift economies, there actually is a rough-and-ready way to solve the problem. One establishes a series of ranked categories of **types** of thing. Pigs and shoes may be considered objects of roughly equivalent status, one can give one in return for the other; coral necklaces are quite another matter, one would have to give back another necklace, or at least another piece of jewelryâanthropologists are used to referring to these as creating different âspheres of exchange.â[40] This does simplify things somewhat. When cross-cultural barter becomes a regular and unexceptional thing, it tends to operate according to similar principles: there are only certain things traded for certain others (cloth for spears, for example), which makes it easy to work out traditional equivalences. However, this doesnât help us at all with the problem of the origin of money. Actually, it makes it infinitely worse. Why stockpile salt or gold or fish if they can only be exchanged for some things and not others?
In fact, there is good reason to believe that barter is not a particularly ancient phenomenon at all, but has only really become widespread in modern times. Certainly in most of the cases we know about, it takes place between people who are familiar with the use of money, but for one reason or another, donât have a lot of it around. Elaborate barter systems often crop up in the wake of the collapse of national economies: most recently in Russia in the â90s, and in Argentina around 2002, when rubles in the first case, and dollars in the second, effectively disappeared.[41] Occasionally one can even find some kind of currency beginning to develop: for instance, in POW camps and many prisons, inmates have indeed been known to use cigarettes as a kind of currency, much to the delight and excitement of professional economists.[42] But here too we are talking about people who grew up using money and now have to make do without itâexactly the situation âimaginedâ by the economics textbooks with which I began.
The more frequent solution is to adopt some sort of credit system. When much of Europe âreverted to barterâ after the collapse of the Roman Empire, and then again after the Carolingian Empire likewise fell apart, this seems to be what happened. People continued keeping accounts in the old imperial currency, even if they were no longer using coins.[43] Similarly, the Pukhtun men who like to swap bicycles for donkeys are hardly unfamiliar with the use of money. Money has existed in that part of the world for thousands of years. They just prefer direct exchange between equalsâin this case, because they consider it more manly.[44]
The most remarkable thing is that even in Adam Smithâs examples of fish and nails and tobacco being used as money, the same sort of thing was happening. In the years following the appearance of **The Wealth of Nations**, scholars checked into most of those examples and discovered that in just about every case, the people involved were quite familiar with the use of money, and in fact, **were** using moneyâas a unit of account.[45] Take the example of dried cod, supposedly used as money in Newfoundland. As the British diplomat A. Mitchell-Innes pointed out almost a century ago, what Smith describes was really an illusion, created by a simple credit arrangement:
In the early days of the Newfoundland fishing industry, there was no permanent European population; the fishers went there for the fishing season only, and those who were not fishers were traders who bought the dried fish and sold to the fishers their daily supplies. The latter sold their catch to the traders at the market price in pounds, shillings and pence, and obtained in return a credit on their books, with which they paid for their supplies. Balances due by the traders were paid for by drafts on England or France.[46]
It was quite the same in the Scottish village. Itâs not as if anyone actually walked into the local pub, plunked down a roofing nail, and asked for a pint of beer. Employers in Smithâs day often lacked coin to pay their workers; wages could be delayed by a year or more; in the meantime, it was considered acceptable for employees to carry off either some of their own products or leftover work materials, lumber, fabric, cord, and so on. The nails were de facto interest on what their employers owed them. So they went to the pub, ran up a tab, and when occasion permitted, brought in a bag of nails to charge off against the debt. The law making tobacco legal tender in Virginia seems to have been an attempt by planters to oblige local merchants to accept their products as a credit around harvest time. In effect, the law forced all merchants in Virginia to become middlemen in the tobacco business, whether they liked it or not; just as all West Indian merchants were obliged to become sugar dealers, since thatâs what all their wealthier customers brought in to write off against their debt.
The primary examples, then, were ones in which people were improvising credit systems, because actual moneyâgold and silver coinageâwas in short supply. But the most shocking blow to the conventional version of economic history came with the translation, first of Egyptian hieroglyphics, and then of Mesopotamian cuneiform, which pushed back scholarsâ knowledge of written history almost three millennia, from the time of Homer (circa 800 bc), where it had hovered in Smithâs time, to roughly 3500 bc. What these texts revealed was that credit systems of exactly this sort actually **preceded** the invention of coinage by thousands of years.
The Mesopotamian system is the best-documented, more so than that of Pharaonic Egypt (which appears similar), Shang China (about which we know little), or the Indus Valley civilization (about which we know nothing at all). As it happens, we know a great deal about Mesopotamia, since the vast majority of cuneiform documents were financial in nature.
The Sumerian economy was dominated by vast temple and palace complexes. These were often staffed by thousands: priests and officials, craftspeople who worked in their industrial workshops, farmers and shepherds who worked their considerable estates. Even though ancient Sumer was usually divided into a large number of independent city-states, by the time the curtain goes up on Mesopotamian civilization around 3500, temple administrators already appear to have developed a single, uniform system of accountancyâone that is in some ways still with us, actually, because itâs to the Sumerians that we owe such things as the dozen or the 24-hour day.[47] The basic monetary unit was the silver shekel. One shekelâs weight in silver was established as the equivalent of one gur, or bushel of barley. A shekel was subdivided into 60 minas, corresponding to one portion of barleyâon the principle that there were 30 days in a month, and Temple workers received two rations of barley every day. Itâs easy to see that âmoneyâ in this sense is in no way the product of commercial transactions. It was actually created by bureaucrats in order to keep track of resources and move things back and forth between departments.
Temple bureaucrats used the system to calculate debts (rents, fees, loans âŠ) in silver. Silver was, effectively, money. And it did indeed circulate in the form of unworked chunks, ârude barsâ as Smith had put it.[48] In this he was right. But it was almost the only part of his account that was right. One reason was that silver did not circulate very much. Most of it just sat around in Temple and Palace treasuries, some of which remained, carefully guarded, in the same place for literally thousands of years. It would have been easy enough to standardize the ingots, stamp them, create some authoritative system to guarantee their purity. The technology existed. Yet no one saw any particular need to do so. One reason was that while debts were calculated in silver, they did not have to be **paid** in silverâin fact, they could be paid in more or less anything one had around. Peasants who owed money to the Temple or Palace, or to some Temple or Palace official, seem to have settled their debts mostly in barley, which is why fixing the ratio of silver to barley was so important. But it was perfectly acceptable to show up with goats, or furniture, or lapis lazuli. Temples and Palaces were huge industrial operationsâthey could find a use for almost anything.[49]
In the marketplaces that cropped up in Mesopotamian cities, prices were also calculated in silver, and the prices of commodities that werenât entirely controlled by the Temples and Palaces would tend to fluctuate according to supply and demand. But even here, such evidence as we have suggests that most transactions were based on credit. Merchants (who sometimes worked for the Temples, sometimes operated independently) were among the few people who did, often, actually use silver in transactions; but even they mostly did much of their dealings on credit, and ordinary people buying beer from âale women,â or local innkeepers, once again, did so by running up a tab, to be settled at harvest time in barley or anything they might have had at hand.[50]
At this point, just about every aspect of the conventional story of the origins of money lay in rubble. Rarely has an historical theory been so absolutely and systematically refuted. By the early decades of the twentieth century, all the pieces were in place to completely rewrite the history of money. The groundwork was laid by Mitchell-Innesâthe same one Iâve already cited on the matter of the codâin two essays that appeared in New Yorkâs **Banking Law Journal** in 1913 and 1914. In these, Mitchell-Innes matter-of-factly laid out the false assumptions on which existing economic history was based and suggested that what was really needed was a history of debt:
One of the popular fallacies in connection with commerce is that in modern days a money-saving device has been introduced called **credit** and that, before this device was known, all, purchases were paid for in cash, in other words in coins. A careful investigation shows that the precise reverse is true. In olden days coins played a far smaller part in commerce than they do to-day. Indeed so small was the quantity of coins, that they did not even suffice for the needs of the [Medieval English] Royal household and estates which regularly used tokens of various kinds for the purpose of making small payments. So unimportant indeed was the coinage that sometimes Kings did not hesitate to call it all in for re-minting and re-issue and still commerce went on just the same.[51]
In fact, our standard account of monetary history is precisely backwards. We did not begin with barter, discover money, and then eventually develop credit systems. It happened precisely the other way around. What we now call virtual money came first. Coins came much later, and their use spread only unevenly, never completely replacing credit systems. Barter, in turn, appears to be largely a kind of accidental byproduct of the use of coinage or paper money: historically, it has mainly been what people who are used to cash transactions do when for one reason or another they have no access to currency.
The curious thing is that it never happened. This new history was never written. Itâs not that any economist has ever refuted Mitchell-Innes. They just ignored him. Textbooks did not change their storyâeven if all the evidence made clear that the story was simply wrong. People still write histories of money that are actually histories of coinage, on the assumption that in the past, these were necessarily the same thing; periods when coinage largely vanished are still described as times when the economy âreverted to barter,â as if the meaning of this phrase is self-evident, even though no one actually knows what it means. As a result we have next-to-no idea how, say, the inhabitant of a Dutch town in 950 ad actually went about acquiring cheese or spoons or hiring musicians to play at his daughterâs weddingâlet alone how any of this was likely to be arranged in Pemba or Samarkand.[52]
<em>In being born every being is born as debt owed to the gods, the saints, the Fathers and to men. If one makes a sacrifice, it is because of a debt owing to the gods from birth ⊠If one recites a sacred text, it is because of a debt owing to the saints ⊠If one wishes for offspring, it is because of a debt due to the fathers from birth ⊠And if one gives hospitality, it is because it is a debt owing to men</em>.
<em>âSatapatha Brahmana</em> 1.7.12, 1â6
<em>Let us drive away the evil effects of bad dreams, just as we pay off debts</em>.
<em>âRig Veda</em> 8.47.17
The reason that economics textbooks now begin with imaginary villages is because it has been impossible to talk about real ones. Even some economists have been forced to admit that Smithâs Land of Barter doesnât really exist.[53]
The question is why the myth has been perpetuated, anyway. Economists have long since jettisoned other elements of **The Wealth of Nations**âfor instance, Smithâs labor theory of value and disapproval of joint-stock corporations. Why not simply write off the myth of barter as a quaint Enlightenment parable, and instead attempt to understand primordial credit arrangementsâor anyway, something more in keeping with the historical evidence?
The answer seems to be that the Myth of Barter cannot go away, because it is central to the entire discourse of economics.
Recall here what Smith was trying to do when he wrote **The Wealth of Nations**. Above all, the book was an attempt to establish the newfound discipline of economics as a science. This meant that not only did economics have its own peculiar domain of studyâwhat we now call âthe economy,â though the idea that there even was something called an âeconomyâ was very new in Smithâs dayâbut that this economy operated according to laws of much the same sort as Sir Isaac Newton had so recently identified as governing the physical world. Newton had represented God as a cosmic watchmaker who had created the physical machinery of the universe in such a way that it would operate for the ultimate benefit of humans, and then let it run on its own. Smith was trying to make a similar, Newtonian argument.[54] Godâor Divine Providence, as he put itâhad arranged matters in such a way that our pursuit of self-interest would nonetheless, given an unfettered market, be guided âas if by an invisible handâ to promote the general welfare. Smithâs famous invisible hand was, as he says in his **Theory of Moral Sentiments**, the agent of Divine Providence. It was literally the hand of God.[55]
Once economics had been established as a discipline, the theological arguments no longer seemed necessary or important. People continue to argue about whether an unfettered free market really will produce the results that Smith said it would; but no one questions whether âthe marketâ naturally exists. The underlying assumptions that derive from this came to be seen as common senseâso much so that, as Iâve noted, we simply assume that when valuable objects do change hands, it will normally be because two individuals have both decided they would gain a material advantage by swapping them. One interesting corollary is that, as a result, economists have come to see the very question of the presence or absence of money as not especially important, since money is just a commodity, chosen to facilitate exchange, and which we use to measure the value of other commodities. Otherwise, it has no special qualities. Still, in 1958, Paul Samuelson, one of the leading lights of the neoclassical school that still predominates in modern economic thought, could express disdain for what he called âthe social contrivance of money.â âEven in the most advanced industrial economies,â he insisted, âif we strip exchange down to its barest essentials and peel off the obscuring layer of money, we find that trade between individuals and nations largely boils down to barter.â[56] Others spoke of a âveil of moneyâ obscuring the nature of the âreal economyâ in which people produced real goods and services and swapped them back and forth.[57]
Call this the final apotheosis of economics as common sense. Money is unimportant. Economiesââreal economiesââare really vast barter systems. The problem is that history shows that without money, such vast barter systems do not occur. Even when economies ârevert to barter,â as Europe was said to do in the Middle Ages, they donât actually abandon the use of money. They just abandon the use of cash. In the Middle Ages, for instance, everyone continued to assess the value of tools and livestock in the old Roman currency, even if the coins themselves had ceased to circulate.[58]
Itâs money that had made it possible for us to imagine ourselves in the way economists encourage us to do: as a collection of individuals and nations whose main business is swapping things. Itâs also clear that the mere existence of money, in itself, is not enough to allow us see the world this way. If it were, the discipline of economics would have been created in ancient Sumer, or anyway, far earlier than 1776, when Adam Smithâs **The Wealth of Nations** appeared.
The missing element is in fact exactly the thing Smith was attempting to downplay: the role of government policy. In England, in Smithâs day, it became possible to see the market, the world of butchers, ironmongers, and haberdashers, as its own entirely independent sphere of human activity because the British government was actively engaged in fostering it. This required laws and police, but also, specific monetary policies, which liberals like Smith were (successfully) advocating.[59] It required pegging the value of the currency to silver, but at the same time greatly increasing the money supply, and particularly the amount of small change in circulation. This not only required huge amounts of tin and copper, but also the careful regulation of the banks that were, at that time, the only source of paper money. The century before **The Wealth of Nations** had seen at least two attempts to create state-supported central banks, in France and Sweden, that had proven to be spectacular failures. In each case, the would-be central bank issued notes based largely on speculation that collapsed the moment investors lost faith. Smith supported the use of paper money, but like Locke before him, he also believed that the relative success of the Bank of England and Bank of Scotland had been due to their policy of pegging paper money firmly to precious metals. This became the mainstream economic view, so much so that alternative theories of money as creditâthe one that Mitchell-Innes advocatedâwere quickly relegated to the margins, their proponents written off as cranks, and the very sort of thinking that led to bad banks and speculative bubbles in the first place.
It might be helpful, then, to consider what these alternative theories actually were.
Mitchell-Innes was an exponent of what came to be known as the Credit Theory of money, a position that over the course of the nineteenth century had its most avid proponents not in Mitchell-Innesâs native Britain but in the two up-and-coming rival powers of the day, the United States and Germany. Credit Theorists insisted that money is not a commodity but an accounting tool. In other words, it is not a âthingâ at all. You can no more touch a dollar or a deutschmark than you can touch an hour or a cubic centimeter. Units of currency are merely abstract units of measurement, and as the credit theorists correctly noted, historically, such abstract systems of accounting emerged long before the use of any particular token of exchange.[60]
The obvious next question is: If money is a just a yardstick, what then does it measure? The answer was simple: debt. A coin is, effectively, an IOU. Whereas conventional wisdom holds that a banknote is, or should be, a promise to pay a certain amount of âreal moneyâ (gold, silver, whatever that might be taken to mean), Credit Theorists argued that a banknote is simply the promise to pay **something** of the same value as an ounce of gold. But thatâs all that money ever is. Thereâs no fundamental difference in this respect between a silver dollar, a Susan B. Anthony dollar coin made of a copper-nickel alloy designed to look vaguely like gold, a green piece of paper with a picture of George Washington on it, or a digital blip on some bankâs computer. Conceptually, the idea that a piece of gold is really just an IOU is always rather difficult to wrap oneâs head around, but something like this must be true, because even when gold and silver coins were in use, they almost never circulated at their bullion value.
How could credit money come about? Let us return to the economics professorsâ imaginary town. Say, for example, that Joshua were to give his shoes to Henry, and, rather than Henry owing him a favor, Henry promises him something of equivalent value.[61] Henry gives Joshua an IOU. Joshua could wait for Henry to have something useful, and then redeem it. In that case Henry would rip up the IOU and the story would be over. But say Joshua were to pass the IOU on to a third partyâSheilaâto whom he owes something else. He could tick it off against his debt to a fourth party, Lolaânow Henry will owe that amount to her. Hence is money born. Because thereâs no logical end to it. Say Sheila now wishes to acquire a pair of shoes from Edith; she can just hand Edith the IOU, and assure her that Henry is good for it. In principle, thereâs no reason that the IOU could not continue circulating around town for yearsâprovided people continue to have faith in Henry. In fact, if it goes on long enough, people might forget about the issuer entirely. Things like this do happen. The anthropologist Keith Hart once told me a story about his brother, who in the â50s was a British soldier stationed in Hong Kong. Soldiers used to pay their bar tabs by writing checks on accounts back in England. Local merchants would often simply endorse them over to each other and pass them around as currency: once, he saw one of his own checks, written six months before, on the counter of a local vendor covered with about forty different tiny inscriptions in Chinese.
What credit theorists like Mitchell-Innes were arguing is that even if Henry gave Joshua a gold coin instead of a piece of paper, the situation would be essentially the same. A gold coin is a promise to pay something else of equivalent value to a gold coin. After all, a gold coin is not actually useful in itself. One only accepts it because one assumes other people will.
In this sense, the value of a unit of currency is not the measure of the value of an object, but the measure of oneâs trust in other human beings.
This element of trust of course makes everything more complicated. Early banknotes circulated via a process almost exactly like what Iâve just described, except that, like the Chinese merchants, each recipient added his or her signature to guarantee the debtâs legitimacy. But generally, the difficulty in the Chartalist positionâthis is what it came to be called, from the Latin **charta**, or tokenâis to establish why people would continue to trust a piece of paper. After all, why couldnât anyone just sign Henryâs name on an IOU? True, this sort of debt-token system might work within a small village where everyone knew one another, or even among a more dispersed community like sixteenth-century Italian or twentieth-century Chinese merchants, where everyone at least had ways of keeping track of everybody else. But systems like these cannot create a full-blown currency system, and thereâs no evidence that they ever have. Providing a sufficient number of IOUs to allow everyone even in a medium-sized city to be able to carry out a significant portion of their daily transactions in such currency would require millions of tokens.[62] To be able to guarantee all of them, Henry would have to be almost unimaginably rich.
All this would be much less of a problem, however, if Henry were, say, Henry II, King of England, Duke of Normandy, Lord of Ireland, and Count of Anjou.
The real impetus for the Chartalist position, in fact, came out of what came to be known as the âGerman Historical School,â whose most famous exponent was the historian G.F. Knapp, whose **State Theory of Money** first appeared in 1905.[63] If money is simply a unit of measure, it makes sense that emperors and kings should concern themselves with such matters. Emperors and kings are almost always concerned to established uniform systems of weights and measures throughout their kingdoms. It is also true, as Knapp observed, that once established, such systems tend to remain remarkably stable over time. During the reign of the actual Henry II (1154â1189), just about everyone in Western Europe was still keeping their accounts using the monetary system established by Charlemagne some 350 years earlierâthat is, using pounds, shillings, and penceâdespite the fact that some of these coins had never existed (Charlemagne never actually struck a silver pound), none of Charlemagneâs actual shillings and pence remained in circulation, and those coins that did circulate tended to vary enormously in size, weight, purity, and value.[64] According to the Chartalists, this doesnât really matter. What matters is that there is a uniform system for measuring credits and debts, and that this system remains stable over time. The case of Charlemagneâs currency is particularly dramatic because his actual empire dissolved quite quickly, but the monetary system he created continued to be used, for keeping accounts, within his former territories for more than 800 years. It was referred to, in the sixteenth century, quite explicitly as âimaginary money,â and derniers and livres were only completely abandoned, as units of account, around the time of the French Revolution.[65]
According to Knapp, whether or not the actual, physical money stuff in circulation corresponds to this âimaginary moneyâ is not particularly important. It makes no real difference whether itâs pure silver, debased silver, leather tokens, or dried codâprovided the state is willing to accept it in payment of taxes. Because whatever the state was willing to accept, for that reason, became currency. One of the most important forms of currency in England in Henryâs time were notched âtally sticksâ used to record debts. Tally sticks were quite explicitly IOUs: both parties to a transaction would take a hazelwood twig, notch it to indicate the amount owed, and then split it in half. The creditor would keep one half, called âthe stockâ (hence the origin of the term âstock holderâ) and the debtor kept the other, called âthe stubâ (hence the origin of the term âticket stub.â) Tax assessors used such twigs to calculate amounts owed by local sheriffs. Often, though, rather than wait for the taxes to come due, Henryâs exchequer would often sell the tallies at a discount, and they would circulate, as tokens of debt owed to the government, to anyone willing to trade for them.[66]
Modern banknotes actually work on a similar principle, except in reverse.[67] Recall here the little parable about Henryâs IOU. The reader might have noticed one puzzling aspect of the equation: the IOU can operate as money only as long as Henry never pays his debt. In fact this is precisely the logic on which the Bank of Englandâthe first successful modern central bankâwas originally founded. In 1694, a consortium of English bankers made a loan of ÂŁ1,200,000 to the king. In return they received a royal monopoly on the issuance of banknotes. What this meant in practice was they had the right to advance IOUs for a portion of the money the king now owed them to any inhabitant of the kingdom willing to borrow from them, or willing to deposit their own money in the bankâin effect, to circulate or âmonetizeâ the newly created royal debt. This was a great deal for the bankers (they got to charge the king 8 percent annual interest for the original loan and simultaneously charge interest on the same money to the clients who borrowed it), but it only worked as long as the original loan remained outstanding. To this day, this loan has never been paid back. It cannot be. If it ever were, the entire monetary system of Great Britain would cease to exist.[68]
If nothing else, this approach helps solve one of the obvious mysteries of the fiscal policy of so many early kingdoms: Why did they make subjects pay taxes at all? This is not a question weâre used to asking. The answer seems self-evident. Governments demand taxes because they wish to get their hands on peopleâs money. But if Smith was right, and gold and silver became money through the natural workings of the market completely independently of governments, then wouldnât the obvious thing be to just grab control of the gold and silver mines? Then the king would have all the money he could possibly need. In fact, this is what ancient kings would normally do. If there were gold and silver mines in their territory, they would usually take control of them. So what exactly was the point of extracting the gold, stamping oneâs picture on it, causing it to circulate among oneâs subjectsâand then demanding that those same subjects give it back again?
This does seem a bit of a puzzle. But if money and markets do not emerge spontaneously, it actually makes perfect sense. Because this is the simplest and most efficient way to bring markets into being. Let us take a hypothetical example. Say a king wishes to support a standing army of fifty thousand men. Under ancient or medieval conditions, feeding such a force was an enormous problemâunless they were on the march, one would need to employ almost as many men and animals just to locate, acquire, and transport the necessary provisions.[69] On the other hand, if one simply hands out coins to the soldiers and then demands that every family in the kingdom was obliged to pay one of those coins back to you, one would, in one blow, turn oneâs entire national economy into a vast machine for the provisioning of soldiers, since now every family, in order to get their hands on the coins, must find some way to contribute to the general effort to provide soldiers with things they want. Markets are brought into existence as a side effect.
This is a bit of a cartoon version, but it is very clear that markets did spring up around ancient armies; one need only take a glance at Kautilyaâs **Arthasasatra**, the Sassanian âcircle of sovereignty,â or the Chinese âDiscourses on Salt and Ironâ to discover that most ancient rulers spent a great deal of their time thinking about the relation between mines, soldiers, taxes, and food. Most concluded that the creation of markets of this sort was not just convenient for feeding soldiers, but useful in all sorts of ways, since it meant officials no longer had to requisition everything they needed directly from the populace, or figure out a way to produce it on royal estates or royal workshops. In other words, despite the dogged liberal assumptionâagain, coming from Smithâs legacyâthat the existence of states and markets are somehow opposed, the historical record implies that exactly the opposite is the case. Stateless societies tend also to be without markets.
As one might imagine, state theories of money have always been anathema to mainstream economists working in the tradition of Adam Smith. In fact, Chartalism has tended to be seen as a populist underside of economic theory, favored mainly by cranks.[70] The curious thing is that the mainstream economists often ended up actually working for governments and advising such governments to pursue policies much like those the Chartalists describedâthat is, tax policies designed to create markets where they had not existed beforeâdespite the fact that they were in theory committed to Smithâs argument that markets develop spontaneously of their own accord.
This was particularly true in the colonial world. To return to Madagascar for a moment: I have already mentioned that one of the first things that the French general Gallieni, conqueror of Madagascar, did when the conquest of the island was complete in 1901 was to impose a head tax. Not only was this tax quite high, it was also only payable in newly issued Malagasy francs. In other words, Gallieni did indeed print money and then demand that everyone in the country give some of that money back to him.
Most striking of all, though, was language he used to describe this tax. It was referred to as the **âimpĂŽt moralisateur,â** the âeducationalâ or âmoralizing tax.â In other words, it was designedâto adopt the language of the dayâto teach the natives the value of work. Since the âeducational taxâ came due shortly after harvest time, the easiest way for farmers to pay it was to sell a portion of their rice crop to the Chinese or Indian merchants who soon installed themselves in small towns across the country. However, harvest was when the market price of rice was, for obvious reasons, at its lowest; if one sold too much of oneâs crop, that meant one would not have enough left to feed oneâs family for the entire year, and thus be forced to buy oneâs own rice back, on credit, from those same merchants later in the year when prices were much higher. As a result, farmers quickly fell hopelessly into debt (the merchants doubling as loan sharks). The easiest ways to pay back the debt was either to find some kind of cash crop to sellâto start growing coffee, or pineapplesâor else to send oneâs children off to work for wages in the city, or on one of the plantations that French colonists were establishing across the island. The whole project might seem no more than a cynical scheme to squeeze cheap labor out of the peasantry, and it was that, but it was also something more. The colonial government was were also quite explicit (at least in their own internal policy documents), about the need to make sure that peasants had at least some money of their own left over, and to ensure that they became accustomed to the minor luxuriesâparasols, lipstick, cookiesâavailable at the Chinese shops. It was crucial that they develop new tastes, habits, and expectations; that they lay the foundations of a consumer demand that would endure long after the conquerors had left, and keep Madagascar forever tied to France.
Most people are not stupid, and most Malagasy understood exactly what their conquerors were trying to do to them. Some were determined to resist. More than sixty years after the invasion, a French anthropologist, Gerard Althabe, was able to observe villages on the east coast of the island whose inhabitants would dutifully show up at the coffee plantations to earn the money for their poll tax, and then, having paid it, studiously ignore the wares for sale at the local shops and instead turn over any remaining money to lineage elders, who would then use it to buy cattle for sacrifice to their ancestors.[71] Many were quite open in saying that they saw themselves as resisting a trap.
Still, such defiance rarely lasts forever. Markets did gradually take shape, even in those parts of the island where none had previously existed. With them came the inevitable network of little shops. And by the time I got there, in 1990, a generation after the poll tax had finally been abolished by a revolutionary government, the logic of the market had become so intuitively accepted that even spirit mediums were reciting passages that might as well have come from Adam Smith.
Such examples could be multiplied endlessly. Something like this occurred in just about every part of the world conquered by European arms where markets were not already in place. Rather than discovering barter, they ended up using the very techniques that mainstream economics rejected to bring something like the market into being.
Anthropologists have been complaining about the Myth of Barter for almost a century. Occasionally, economists point out with slight exasperation that thereâs a fairly simple reason why theyâre still telling the same story despite all the evidence against it: anthropologists have never come up with a better one.[72] This is an understandable objection, but thereâs a simple answer to it. The reasons why anthropologists havenât been able to come up with a simple, compelling story for the origins of money is because thereâs no reason to believe there could be one. Money was no more ever âinventedâ than music or mathematics or jewelry. What we call âmoneyâ isnât a âthingâ at all, itâs a way of comparing things mathematically, as proportions: of saying one of X is equivalent to six of Y. As such it is probably as old as human thought. The moment we try to get any more specific, we discover that there are any number of different habits and practices that have converged in the stuff we now call âmoney,â and this is precisely the reason why economists, historians, and the rest have found it so difficult to come up with a single definition.
Credit Theorists have long been hobbled by the lack of an equally compelling narrative. This is not to say that all sides in the currency debates that ranged between 1850 and 1950 were not in the habit of deploying mythological weaponry. This was true particularly, perhaps, in the United States. In 1894, the Greenbackers, who pushed for detaching the dollar from gold entirely to allow the government to spend freely on job-creation campaigns, invented the idea of the March on Washingtonâan idea that was to have endless resonance in U.S. history. L. Frank Baumâs book **The Wonderful Wizard of Oz**, which appeared in 1900, is widely recognized to be a parable for the Populist campaign of William Jennings Bryan, who twice ran for president on the Free Silver platformâvowing to replace the gold standard with a bimetallic system that would allow the free creation of silver money alongside gold.[73] As with the Greenbackers, one of the main constituencies for the movement was debtors: particularly, Midwestern farm families such as Dorothyâs, who had been facing a massive wave of foreclosures during the severe recession of the 1890s. According to the Populist reading, the Wicked Witches of the East and West represent the East and West Coast bankers (promoters of and benefactors from the tight money supply), the Scarecrow represented the farmers (who didnât have the brains to avoid the debt trap), the Tin Woodsman was the industrial proletariat (who didnât have the heart to act in solidarity with the farmers), the Cowardly Lion represented the political class (who didnât have the courage to intervene). The yellow brick road, silver slippers, emerald city, and hapless Wizard presumably speak for themselves.[74] âOzâ is of course the standard abbreviation for âounce.â[75] As an attempt to create a new myth, Baumâs story was remarkably effective. As political propaganda, less so. William Jennings Bryan failed in three attempts to win the presidency, the silver standard was never adopted, and few nowadays even remember what **The Wonderful Wizard of Oz** was originally supposed to be about.[76]
For state-money theorists in particular, this has been a problem. Stories about rulers using taxes to create markets in conquered territories, or to pay for soldiers or other state functions, are not particularly inspiring. German ideas of money as the embodiment of national will did not travel very well.
Every time there was a major economic meltdown, however, conventional laissez-faire economics took another hit. The Bryan campaigns were born as a reaction to the Panic of 1893. By the time of the Great Depression of the 1930s, the very notion that the market could regulate itself, so long as the government ensured that money was safely pegged to precious metals, was completely discredited. From roughly 1933 to 1979, every major capitalist government reversed course and adopted some version of Keynesianism. Keynesian orthodoxy started from the assumption that capitalist markets would not really work unless capitalist governments were willing effectively to play nanny: most famously, by engaging in massive deficit âpump-primingâ during downturns. While in the â80s, Margaret Thatcher in Britain and Ronald Reagan in the United States made a great show of rejecting all of this, itâs unclear how much they really did.[77] And in any case, they were operating in the wake of an even greater blow to previous monetary orthodoxy: Richard Nixonâs decision in 1971 to unpeg the dollar from precious metals entirely, eliminate the international gold standard, and introduce the system of floating currency regimes that has dominated the world economy ever since. This meant in effect that all national currencies were henceforth, as neoclassical economists like to put it, âfiat moneyâ backed only by the public trust.
Now, John Maynard Keynes himself was much more open to what he liked to call the âalternative traditionâ of credit and state theories than any economist of that stature (and Keynes is still arguably the single most important economic thinker of the twentieth century) before or since. At certain points he immersed himself in it: he spent several years in the 1920s studying Mesopotamian cuneiform banking records to try to ascertain the origins of moneyâhis âBabylonian madness,â as he would later call it.[78] His conclusion, which he set forth at the very beginning of his **Treatise on Money**, his most famous work, was more or less the only conclusion one could come to if one started not from first principles, but from a careful examination of the historical record: that the lunatic fringe was, essentially, right. Whatever its earliest origins, for the last four thousand years, money has been effectively a creature of the state. Individuals, he observed, make contracts with one another. They take out debts, and they promise payment.
The State, therefore, comes in first of all as the authority of law which enforces the payment of the thing which corresponds to the name or description in the contract. But it comes doubly when, in addition, it claims the right to determine and declare **what thing** corresponds to the name, and to vary its declaration from time to timeâwhen, that is to say it claims the right to re-edit the dictionary. This right is claimed by all modern States and has been so claimed for some four thousand years at least. It is when this stage in the evolution of Money has been reached that Knappâs Chartalismâthe doctrine that money is peculiarly a creation of the Stateâis fully realized ⊠To-day all civilized money is, beyond the possibility of dispute, chartalist.[79]
This does not mean that the state necessarily **creates** money. Money is credit, it can be brought into being by private contractual agreements (loans, for instance). The state merely enforces the agreement and dictates the legal terms. Hence Keynesâ next dramatic assertion: that banks create money, and that there is no intrinsic limit to their ability to do so: since however much they lend, the borrower will have no choice but to put the money back into some bank again, and thus, from the perspective of the banking system as a whole, the total number of debits and credits will always cancel out.[80] The implications were radical, but Keynes himself was not. In the end, he was always careful to frame the problem in a way that could be reintegrated into the mainstream economics of his day.
Neither was Keynes much of a mythmaker. Insofar as the alternative tradition has come up with an answer to the Myth of Barter, it was not from Keynesâ own efforts (Keynes ultimately decided that the origins of money were not particularly important) but in the work of some contemporary neo-Keynesians, who were not afraid to follow some of his more radical suggestions as far as they would go.
The real weak link in state-credit theories of money was always the element of taxes. It is one thing to explain why early states demanded taxes (in order to create markets.) Itâs another to ask âby what right?â Assuming that early rulers were not simply thugs, and that taxes were not simply extortionâand no Credit Theorist, to my knowledge, took such a cynical view even of early governmentâone must ask how they justified this sort of thing.
Nowadays, we all think we know the answer to this question. We pay our taxes so that the government can provide us with services. This starts with security servicesâmilitary protection being, often, about the only service some early states were really able to provide. By now, of course, the government provides all sorts of things. All of this is said to go back to some sort of original âsocial contractâ that everyone somehow agreed on, though no one really knows exactly when or by whom, or why we should be bound by the decisions of distant ancestors on this one matter when we donât feel particularly bound by the decisions of our distant ancestors on anything else.[81] All of this makes sense if you assume that markets come before governments, but the whole argument totters quickly once you realize that they donât.
There is an alternative explanation, one created to be in keeping with the state-credit theory approach. Itâs referred to as âprimordial debt theoryâ and it has been developed largely in France, by a team of researchersânot only economists but anthropologists, historians, and classicistsâoriginally assembled around the figures of Michel Aglietta and Andre OrlĂ©ans,[82] and more recently, Bruno ThĂ©ret, and it has since been taken up by neo-Keynesians in the United States and the United Kingdom as well.[83]
Itâs a position that has emerged quite recently, and at first, largely amidst debates about the nature of the euro. The creation of a common European currency sparked not only all sorts of intellectual debates (does a common currency necessarily imply the creation of a common European state? Or of a common European economy or society? Are these ultimately the same thing?) but dramatic political ones as well. The creation of the euro zone was spearheaded above all by Germany, whose central banks still see their main goal as combating inflation. Whatâs more, tight money policies and the need to balance budgets having been used as the main weapon to chip away welfare-state policies in Europe, it has necessarily become the stake of political struggles between bankers and pensioners, creditors and debtors, just as heated as those of 1890s America.
The core argument is that any attempt to separate monetary policy from social policy is ultimately wrong. Primordial-debt theorists insist that these have always been the same thing. Governments use taxes to create money, and they are able to do so because they have become the guardians of the debt that all citizens have to one another. This debt is the essence of society itself. It exists long before money and markets, and money and markets themselves are simply ways of chopping pieces of it up.
At first, the argument goes, this sense of debt was expressed not through the state, but through religion. To make the argument, Aglietta and OrlĂ©ans fixed on certain works of early Sanskrit religious literature: the hymns, prayers, and poetry collected in the Vedas and the Brahmanas, priestly commentaries composed over the centuries that followed, texts that are now considered the foundations of Hindu thought. Itâs not as odd a choice as it might seem. These texts constitute the earliest known historical reflections on the nature of debt.
Actually, even the very earliest Vedic poems, composed sometime between 1500 and 1200 bc, evince a constant concern with debtâwhich is treated as synonymous with guilt and sin.[84] There are numerous prayers pleading with the gods to liberate the worshipper from the shackles or bonds of debt. Sometimes these seem to refer to debt in the literal senseâRig Veda 10.34, for instance, has a long description of the sad plight of gamblers who âwander homeless, in constant fear, in debt, and seeking money.â Elsewhere itâs clearly metaphorical.
In these hymns, Yama, the god of death, figures prominently. To be in debt was to have a weight placed on you by Death. To be under any sort of unfulfilled obligation, any unkept promise, to gods or to men, was to live in the shadow of Death. Often, even in the very early texts, debt seems to stand in for a broader sense of inner suffering, from which one begs the godsâparticularly Agni, who represents the sacrificial fireâfor release. It was only with the Brahmanas that commentators started trying to weave all this together into a more comprehensive philosophy. The conclusion: that human existence is itself a form of debt.
A man, being born, is a debt; by his own self he is born to Death, and only when he sacrifices does he redeem himself from Death.[85]
Sacrifice (and these early commentators were themselves sacrificial priests) is thus called âtribute paid to Death.â Or such was the manner of speaking. In reality, as the priests knew better than anyone, sacrifice was directed to all the gods, not just DeathâDeath was just the intermediary. Framing things this way, though, did immediately raise the one problem that always comes up, whenever anyone conceives human life through such an idiom. If our lives are on loan, who would actually wish to repay such a debt? To live in debt is to be guilty, incomplete. But completion can only mean annihilation. In this way, the âtributeâ of sacrifice could be seen as a kind of interest payment, with the life of the animal substituting temporarily for whatâs really owed, which is ourselvesâa mere postponement of the inevitable.[86]
Different commentators proposed different ways out of the dilemma. Some ambitious Brahmins began telling their clients that sacrificial ritual, if done correctly, promised a way to break out of the human condition entirely and achieve eternity (since, in the face of eternity, all debts become meaningless.)[87] Another way was to broaden the notion of debt, so that all social responsibilities become debts of one sort or another. Thus two famous passages in the Brahmanas insist that we are born as a debt not just to the gods, to be repaid in sacrifice, but also to the Sages who created the Vedic learning to begin with, which we must repay through study; to our ancestors (âthe Fathersâ), who we must repay by having children; and finally, âto menââapparently meaning humanity as a whole, to be repaid by offering hospitality to strangers.[88] Anyone, then, who lives a proper life is constantly paying back existential debts of one sort or another; but at the same time, as the notion of debt slides back into a simple sense of social obligation, it becomes something far less terrifying than the sense that oneâs very existence is a loan taken against Death.[89] Not least because social obligations always cut both ways. Especially since, once one has oneself fathered children, one is just as much a debtor as a creditor.
What primordial-debt theorists have done is to propose that the ideas encoded in these Vedic texts are not peculiar to a certain intellectual tradition of early Iron Age ritual specialists in the Ganges valley, but that they are essential to the very nature and history of human thought. Consider for example this statement, from an essay by French economist Bruno ThĂ©ret with the uninspiring title âThe Socio-Cultural Dimensions of the Currency: Implications for the Transition to the Euro,â published in the **Journal of Consumer Policy** in 1999:
At the origin of money we have a ârelation of representationâ of death as an invisible world, before and beyond lifeâa representation that is the product of the symbolic function proper to the human species and which envisages birth as an original debt incurred by all men, a debt owing to the cosmic powers from which humanity emerged.
Payment of this debt, which can however never be settled on earthâbecause its full reimbursement is out of reachâtakes the form of sacrifices which, by replenishing the credit of the living, make it possible to prolong life and even in certain cases to achieve eternity by joining the Gods. But this initial belief-claim is also associated with the emergence of sovereign powers whose legitimacy resides in their ability to represent the entire original cosmos. And it is these powers that invented money as a means of settling debtsâa means whose abstraction makes it possible to resolve the sacrificial paradox by which putting to death becomes the permanent means of protecting life. Through this institution, belief is in turn transferred to a currency stamped with the effigy of the sovereignâa money put in circulation but whose return is organized by this other institution which is the tax/settlement of the life debt. So money also takes on the function of a means of payment.[90]
If nothing else, this provides a neat illustration of how different are standards of debate in Europe from those current in the Anglo-American world. One canât imagine an American economist of any stripe writing something like this. Still, the author is actually making a rather clever synthesis here. Human nature does not drive us to âtruck and barter.â Rather, it ensures that we are always creating symbolsâsuch as money itself. This is how we come to see ourselves in a cosmos surrounded by invisible forces; as in debt to the universe.
The ingenious move of course is to fold this back into the state theory of moneyâsince by âsovereign powersâ ThĂ©ret actually means âthe state.â The first kings were sacred kings who were either gods in their own right or stood as privileged mediators between human beings and the ultimate forces that governed the cosmos. This sets us on a road to the gradual realization that our debt to the gods was always, really, a debt to the society that made us what we are.
The âprimordial debt,â writes British sociologist Geoffrey Ingham, âis that owed by the living to the continuity and durability of the society that secures their individual existence.â[91] In this sense it is not just criminals who owe a âdebt to societyââwe are all, in a certain sense, guilty, even criminals.
For instance, Ingham notes that, while there is no actual proof that money emerged in this way, âthere is considerable indirect etymological evidenceâ:
In all Indo-European languages, words for âdebtâ are synonymous with those for âsinâ or âguiltâ, illustrating the links between religion, payment and the mediation of the sacred and profane realms by âmoney.â For example, there is a connection between money (German **Geld**), indemnity or sacrifice (Old English **Geild**), tax (Gothic **Gild**) and, of course, guilt.[92]
Or, to take another curious connection: Why were cattle so often used as money? The German historian Bernard Laum long ago pointed out that in Homer, when people measure the value of a ship or suit of armor, they always measure it in oxenâeven though when they actually exchange things, they never pay for anything in oxen. It is hard to escape the conclusion that this was because an ox was what one offered the gods in sacrifice. Hence they represented absolute value. From Sumer to Classical Greece, silver and gold were dedicated as offerings in temples. Everywhere, money seems to have emerged from the thing most appropriate for giving to the gods.[93]
If the king has simply taken over guardianship of that primordial debt we all owe to society for having created us, this provides a very neat explanation for why the government feels it has the right to make us pay taxes. Taxes are just a measure of our debt to the society that made us. But this doesnât really explain how this kind of absolute life-debt can be converted into **money**, which is by definition a means of measuring and comparing the value of **different** things. This is just as much a problem for credit theorists as for neoclassical economists, even if the problem for them is somewhat differently framed. If you start from the barter theory of money, you have to resolve the problem of how and why you would come to select one commodity to measure just how much you want each of the other ones. If you start from a credit theory, you are left with the problem I described in the first chapter: how to turn a moral obligation into a specific sum of money, how the mere sense of owing someone else a favor can eventually turn into a system of accounting in which one is able to calculate exactly how many sheep or fish or chunks of silver it would take to repay the debt. Or in this case, how do we go from that absolute debt we owe to God to the very specific debts we owe our cousins, or the bartender?
The answer provided by primordial-debt theorists is, again, ingenious. If taxes represent our absolute debt to the society that created us, then the first step toward creating real money comes when we start calculating much more specific debts to society, systems of fines, fees, and penalties, or even debts we owe to specific individuals who we have wronged in some way, and thus to whom we stand in a relation of âsinâ or âguilt.â
This is actually much less implausible than it might sound. One of the puzzling things about all the theories about the origins of money that weâve been looking at so far is that they almost completely ignore the evidence of anthropology. Anthropologists do have a great deal of knowledge of how economies within stateless societies actually workedâhow they still work in places where states and markets have been unable to completely break up existing ways of doing things. There are innumerable studies of, say, the use of cattle as money in eastern or southern Africa, of shell money in the Americas (wampum being the most famous example) or Papua New Guinea, bead money, feather money, the use of iron rings, cowries, spondylus shells, brass rods, or woodpecker scalps.[94] The reason that this literature tends to be ignored by economists is simple: âprimitive currenciesâ of this sort is only rarely used to buy and sell things, and even when they are, never primarily to buy and sell everyday items such as chickens or eggs or shoes or potatoes. Rather than being employed to acquire things, they are mainly used to rearrange relations between people. Above all, to arrange marriages and to settle disputes, particularly those arising from murders or personal injury.
There is every reason to believe that our own money started the same wayâeven the English word âto payâ is originally derived from a word for âto pacify, appeaseââas in, to give someone something precious, for instance, to express just how badly you feel about having just killed his brother in a drunken brawl, and how much you would really like to avoid this becoming the basis for an ongoing blood-feud.[95]
Debt theorists are especially concerned with this latter possibility. This is partly because they tend to skip past the anthropological literature and look at early law codesâtaking inspiration here, from the groundbreaking work of one of the twentieth centuryâs greatest numismatists, Philip Grierson, who in the â70s, first suggested that money might first have emerged from early legal practice. Grierson was an expert in the European Dark Ages, and he became fascinated by what have come to be known as the âBarbarian Law Codes,â established by many Germanic peoples after the destruction of the Roman Empire in the 600s and 700sâGoths, Frisians, Franks, and so onâsoon followed by similar codes published everywhere from Russia to Ireland. Certainly they are fascinating documents. On the one hand, they make it abundantly clear just how wrong are conventional accounts of Europe around this time âreverting to barter.â Almost all of the Germanic law codes use Roman money to make assessments; penalties for theft, for instance, are almost always followed by demands that the thief not only return the stolen property but pay any outstanding rent (or in the event of stolen money, interest) owing for the amount of time it has been in his possession. On the other hand, these were soon followed by law codes by people living in territories that had never been under Roman ruleâin Ireland, Wales, Nordic countries, Russiaâand these are if anything even more revealing. They could be remarkably creative, both in what could be used as a means of payment and on the precise breakdown of injuries and insults that required compensation:
Compensation in the Welsh laws is reckoned primarily in cattle and in the Irish ones in cattle or bondmaids **(cumal)**, with considerable use of precious metals in both. In the Germanic codes it is mainly in precious metal ⊠In the Russian codes it was silver and furs, graduated from marten down to squirrel. Their detail is remarkable, not only in the personal injuries envisionedâspecific compensations for the loss of an arm, a hand, a forefinger, a nail, for a blow on the head so that the brain is visible or bone projectsâbut in the coverage some of them gave to the possessions of the individual household. Title II of the Salic Law deals with the theft of pigs, Title III with cattle, Title IV with sheep, Title V with goats, Title VI with dogs, each time with an elaborate breakdown differentiating between animals of different age and sex.[96]
This does make a great deal of psychological sense. Iâve already remarked how difficult it is to imagine how a system of precise equivalencesâone young healthy milk cow is equivalent to exactly thirty-six chickensâcould arise from most forms of gift exchange. If Henry gives Joshua a pig and feels he has received an inadequate counter-gift, he might mock Joshua as a cheapskate, but he would have little occasion to come up with a mathematical formula for precisely how cheap he feels Joshua has been. On the other hand, if Joshuaâs pig just destroyed Henryâs garden, and especially, if that led to a fight in which Henry lost a toe, and Henryâs family is now hauling Joshua up in front of the village assemblyâthis is precisely the context where people are most likely to become petty and legalistic and express outrage if they feel they have received one groat less than was their rightful due. That means exact mathematical specificity: for instance, the capacity to measure the exact value of a two-year-old pregnant sow. Whatâs more, the levying of penalties must have constantly required the calculation of equivalences. Say the fine is in marten pelts but the culpritâs clan doesnât have any martens. How many squirrel skins will do? Or pieces of silver jewelry? Such problems must have come up all the time and led to at least a rough-and-ready set of rules of thumb over what sorts of valuable were equivalent to others. This would help explain why, for instance, medieval Welsh law codes can contain detailed breakdowns not only of the value of different ages and conditions of milk cow, but of the monetary value of every object likely to be found in an ordinary homestead, down to the cost of each piece of timberâdespite the fact that there seems no reason to believe that most such items could even be purchased on the open market at the time.[97]
There is something very compelling in all this. For one thing, the premise makes a great deal of intuitive sense. After all, we do owe everything we are to others. This is simply true. The language we speak and even think in, our habits and opinions, the kind of food we like to eat, the knowledge that makes our lights switch on and toilets flush, even the style in which we carry out our gestures of defiance and rebellion against social conventionsâall of this, we learned from other people, most of them long dead. If we were to imagine what we owe them as a debt, it could only be infinite. The question is: Does it really make sense to think of this as a debt? After all, a debt is by definition something that we could at least imagine paying back. It is strange enough to wish to be square with oneâs parentsâit rather implies that one does not wish to think of them as parents any more. Would we really want to be square with all humanity? What would that even mean? And is this desire really a fundamental feature of all human thought?
Another way to put this would be: Are primordial-debt theorists **describing** a myth, have they discovered a profound truth of the human condition that has always existed in all societies, and is it simply spelled out particularly clearly in certain ancient texts from Indiaâor are they **inventing** a myth of their own?
Clearly it must be the latter. They are inventing a myth.
The choice of the Vedic material is significant. The fact is, we know almost nothing about the people who composed these texts and little about the society that created them.[98] We donât even know if interest-bearing loans existed in Vedic Indiaâwhich obviously has a bearing on whether priests really saw sacrifice as the payment of interest on a loan we owe to Death.[99] As a result, the material can serve as a kind of empty canvas, or a canvas covered with hieroglyphics in an unknown language, on which we can project almost anything we want to. If we look at other ancient civilizations in which we do know something about the larger context, we find that no such notion of sacrifice as payment is in evidence.[100] If we look through the work of ancient theologians, we find that most were familiar with the idea that sacrifice was a way by which human beings could enter into commercial relations with the gods, but that they felt it was patently ridiculous: If the gods already have everything they want, what exactly do humans have to bargain with?[101] Weâve seen in the last chapter how difficult it is to give gifts to kings. With gods (let alone God) the problem is magnified infinitely. Exchange implies equality. In dealing with cosmic forces, this was simply assumed to be impossible from the start.
The notion that debts to gods were appropriated by the state, and thus became the bases for taxation systems, canât really stand up either. The problem here is that in the ancient world, free citizens didnât usually pay taxes. Generally speaking, tribute was levied only on conquered populations. This was already true in ancient Mesopotamia, where the inhabitants of independent cities did not usually have to pay direct taxes at all. Similarly, as Moses Finley put it, âClassical Greeks looked upon direct taxes as tyrannical and avoided them whenever possible.[102] Athenian citizens did not pay direct taxes of any sort; though the city did sometimes distribute money to its citizens, a kind of reverse taxationâsometimes directly, as with the proceeds of the Laurium silver mines, and sometimes indirectly, as through generous fees for jury duty or attending the assembly. Subject cities, however, did have to pay tribute. Even within the Persian Empire, Persians did not have to pay tribute to the Great King, but the inhabitants of conquered provinces did.[103] The same was true in Rome, where for a very long time, Roman citizens not only paid no taxes but had a right to a share of the tribute levied on others, in the form of the doleâthe âbreadâ part of the famous âbread and circuses.â[104]
In other words, Benjamin Franklin was wrong when he said that in this world nothing is certain except death and taxes. This obviously makes the idea that the debt to one is just a variation on the other much harder to maintain.
None of this, however, deals a mortal blow to the state theory of money. Even those states that did not demand taxes did levy fees, penalties, tariffs, and fines of one sort or another. But it **is** very hard to reconcile with any theory that claims states were first conceived as guardians of some sort of cosmic, primordial debt.
Itâs curious that primordial-debt theorists never have much to say about Sumer or Babylonia, despite the fact that Mesopotamia is where the practice of loaning money at interest was first invented, probably two thousand years before the Vedas were composedâand that it was also the home of the worldâs first states. But if we look into Mesopotamian history, it becomes a little less surprising. Again, what we find there is in many ways the exact opposite of what such theorists would have predicted.
The reader will recall here that Mesopotamian city-states were dominated by vast Temples: gigantic, complex industrial institutions often staffed by thousandsâincluding everyone from shepherds and barge-pullers to spinners and weavers to dancing girls and clerical administrators. By at least 2700 bc, ambitious rulers had begun to imitate them by creating palace complexes organized on similar termsâwith the exception that where the Temples centered on the sacred chambers of a god or goddess, represented by a sacred image who was fed and clothed and entertained by priestly servants as if he or she were a living person. Palaces centered on the chambers of an actual live king. Sumerian rulers rarely went so far as to declare themselves gods, but they often came very close. However, when they did interfere in the lives of their subjects in their capacity as cosmic rulers, they did not do it by imposing public debts, but rather by canceling private ones.[105]
We donât know precisely when and how interest-bearing loans originated, since they appear to predate writing. Most likely, Temple administrators invented the idea as a way of financing the caravan trade. This trade was crucial because while the river valley of ancient Mesopotamia was extraordinarily fertile and produced huge surpluses of grain and other foodstuffs, and supported enormous numbers of livestock, which in turn supported a vast wool and leather industry, it was almost completely lacking in anything else. Stone, wood, metal, even the silver used as money, all had to be imported. From quite early times, then, Temple administrators developed the habit of advancing goods to local merchantsâsome of them private, others themselves Temple functionariesâwho would then go off and sell it overseas. Interest was just a way for the Temples to take their share of the resulting profits.[106] However, once established, the principle seems to have quickly spread. Before long, we find not only commercial loans, but also consumer loansâusury in the classical sense of the term. By c2400 bc it already appears to have been common practice on the part of local officials, or wealthy merchants, to advance loans to peasants who were in financial trouble on collateral and begin to appropriate their possessions if they were unable to pay. It usually started with grain, sheep, goats, and furniture, then moved on to fields and houses, or, alternately or ultimately, family members. Servants, if any, went quickly, followed by children, wives, and in some extreme occasions, even the borrower himself. These would be reduced to debt-peons: not quite slaves, but very close to that, forced into perpetual service in the lenderâs householdâor, sometimes, in the Temples or Palaces themselves. In theory, of course, any of them could be redeemed whenever the borrower repaid the money, but for obvious reasons, the more a peasantâs resources were stripped away from him, the harder that became.
The effects were such that they often threatened to rip society apart. If for any reason there was a bad harvest, large proportions of the peasantry would fall into debt peonage; families would be broken up. Before long, lands lay abandoned as indebted farmers fled their homes for fear of repossession and joined semi-nomadic bands on the desert fringes of urban civilization. Faced with the potential for complete social breakdown, Sumerian and later Babylonian kings periodically announced general amnesties: âclean slates,â as economic historian Michael Hudson refers to them. Such decrees would typically declare all outstanding consumer debt null and void (commercial debts were not affected), return all land to its original owners, and allow all debt-peons to return to their families. Before long, it became more or less a regular habit for kings to make such a declaration on first assuming power, and many were forced to repeat it periodically over the course of their reigns.
In Sumeria, these were called âdeclarations of freedomââand it is significant that the Sumerian word **amargi**, the first recorded word for âfreedomâ in any known human language, literally means âreturn to motherââsince this is what freed debt-peons were finally allowed to do.[107]
Michael Hudson argues that Mesopotamian kings were only in a position to do this because of their cosmic pretensions: in taking power, they saw themselves as literally recreating human society, and so were in a position to wipe the slate clean of all previous moral obligations. Still, this is about as far from what primordial-debt theorists had in mind as one could possibly imagine.[108]
Probably the biggest problem in this whole body of literature is the initial assumption: that we begin with an infinite debt to something called âsociety.â Itâs this debt to society that we project onto the gods. Itâs this same debt that then gets taken up by kings and national governments.
What makes the concept of society so deceptive is that we assume the world is organized into a series of compact, modular units called âsocieties,â and that all people know which one theyâre in. Historically, this is very rarely the case. Imagine I am a Christian Armenian merchant living under the reign of Genghis Khan. What is âsocietyâ for me? Is it the city where I grew up, the society of international merchants (with its own elaborate codes of conduct) within which I conduct my daily affairs, other speakers of Armenian, Christendom (or maybe just Orthodox Christendom), or the inhabitants of the Mongol empire itself, which stretched from the Mediterranean to Korea? Historically, kingdoms and empires have rarely been the most important reference points in peoplesâ lives. Kingdoms rise and fall; they also strengthen and weaken; governments may make their presence known in peopleâs lives quite sporadically, and many people in history were never entirely clear whose government they were actually in. Even until quite recently, many of the worldâs inhabitants were never even quite sure what country they were supposed to be in, or why it should matter. My mother, who was born a Jew in Poland, once told me a joke from her childhood:
There was a small town located along the frontier between Russia and Poland; no one was ever quite sure to which it belonged. One day an official treaty was signed and not long after, surveyors arrived to draw a border. Some villagers approached them where they had set up their equipment on a nearby hill.
âSo where are we, Russia or Poland?â
âAccording to our calculations, your village now begins exactly thirty-seven meters into Poland.â
The villagers immediately began dancing for joy.
âWhy?â the surveyors asked. âWhat difference does it make?â
âDonât you know what this means?â they replied. âIt means weâll never have to endure another one of those terrible Russian winters!â
However, if we are born with an infinite debt to all those people who made our existence possible, but there is no natural unit called âsocietyââthen who or what exactly do we really owe it to? Everyone? Everything? Some people or things more than others? And how do we pay a debt to something so diffuse? Or, perhaps more to the point, who exactly can claim the authority to tell us how we can repay it, and on what grounds?
If we frame the problem that way, the authors of the Brahmanas are offering a quite sophisticated reflection on a moral question that no one has really ever been able to answer any better before or since. As I say, we canât know much about the conditions under which those texts were composed, but such evidence as we do have suggests that the crucial documents date from sometime between 500 and 400 bcâthat is, roughly the time of Socratesâwhich in India appears to have been just around the time that a commercial economy, and institutions like coined money and interest-bearing loans were beginning to become features of everyday life. The intellectual classes of the time were, much as they were in Greece and China, grappling with the implications. In their case, this meant asking: What does it mean to imagine our responsibilities as debts? To whom do we owe our existence?
Itâs significant that their answer did not make any mention either of âsocietyâ or states (though certainly kings and governments certainly existed in early India). Instead, they fixed on debts to gods, to sages, to fathers, and to âmen.â It wouldnât be at all difficult to translate their formulation into more contemporary language. We could put it this way. We owe our existence above all:
âą To the universe, cosmic forces, as we would put it now, to Nature. The ground of our existence. To be repaid through ritual: ritual being an act of respect and recognition to all that beside which we are small.[109]
âą To those who have created the knowledge and cultural accomplishments that we value most; that give our existence its form, its meaning, but also its shape. Here we would include not only the philosophers and scientists who created our intellectual tradition but everyone from William Shakespeare to that long-since-forgotten woman, somewhere in the Middle East, who created leavened bread. We repay them by becoming learned ourselves and contributing to human knowledge and human culture.
âą To our parents, and their parentsâour ancestors. We repay them by becoming ancestors.
âą To humanity as a whole. We repay them by generosity to strangers, by maintaining that basic communistic ground of sociality that makes human relations, and hence life, possible.
Set out this way, though, the argument begins to undermine its very premise. These are nothing like commercial debts. After all, one might repay oneâs parents by having children, but one is not generally thought to have repaid oneâs creditors if one lends the cash to someone else.[110]
Myself, I wonder: Couldnât that really be the point? Perhaps what the authors of the Brahmanas were really demonstrating was that, in the final analysis, our relation with the cosmos is ultimately nothing like a commercial transaction, nor could it be. That is because commercial transactions imply both equality and separation. These examples are all about overcoming separation: you are free from your debt to your ancestors when you become an ancestor; you are free from your debt to the sages when you become a sage, you are free from your debt to humanity when you act with humanity. All the more so if one is speaking of the universe. If you cannot bargain with the gods because they already have everything, then you certainly cannot bargain with the universe, because the universe **is** everythingâand that everything necessarily includes yourself. One could in fact interpret this list as a subtle way of saying that the only way of âfreeing oneselfâ from the debt was not literally repaying debts, but rather showing that these debts do not exist because one is not in fact separate to begin with, and hence that the very notion of canceling the debt, and achieving a separate, autonomous existence, was ridiculous from the start. Or even that the very presumption of positing oneself as separate from humanity or the cosmos, so much so that one can enter into one-to-one dealings with it, is itself the crime that can be answered only by death. Our guilt is not due to the fact that we cannot repay our debt to the universe. Our guilt is our presumption in thinking of ourselves as being in any sense an equivalent to Everything Else that Exists or Has Ever Existed, so as to be able to conceive of such a debt in the first place.[111]
Or let us look at the other side of the equation. Even if it is possible to imagine ourselves as standing in a position of absolute debt to the cosmos, or to humanity, the next question becomes: Who exactly has a right to speak for the cosmos, or humanity, to tell us how that debt must be repaid? If thereâs anything more preposterous than claiming to stand apart from the entire universe so as to enter into negotiations with it, it is claiming to speak for the other side.
If one were looking for the ethos for an individualistic society such as our own, one way to do it might well be to say: we all owe an infinite debt to humanity, society, nature, or the cosmos (however one prefers to frame it), but no one else could possibly tell us how we are to pay it. This at least would be intellectually consistent. If so, it would actually be possible to see almost all systems of established authorityâreligion, morality, politics, economics, and the criminal-justice systemâas so many different fraudulent ways to presume to calculate what cannot be calculated, to claim the authority to tell us how some aspect of that unlimited debt ought to be repaid. Human freedom would then be our ability to decide for ourselves how we want to do so.
No one, to my knowledge, has ever taken this approach. Instead, theories of existential debt always end up becoming ways of justifyingâor laying claim toâstructures of authority. The case of the Hindu intellectual tradition is telling here. The debt to humanity appears only in a few early texts, and is quickly forgotten. Almost all later Hindu commentators ignore it and instead put their emphasis on a manâs debt to his father.[112]
Primordial-debt theorists have other fish to fry. They are not really interested in the cosmos, but actually, in âsociety.â
Let me return again to that word, âsociety.â The reason that it seems like such a simple, self-evident concept is because we mostly use it as a synonym for ânation.â After all, when Americans speak of paying their debt to society, they are not thinking of their responsibilities to people who live in Sweden. Itâs only the modern state, with its elaborate border controls and social policies, that enables us to imagine âsocietyâ in this way, as a single bounded entity. This is why projecting that notion backwards into Vedic or Medieval times will always be deceptive, even though we donât really have another word.
It seems to me that this is exactly what the primordial-debt theorists are doing: projecting such a notion backwards.
Really, the whole complex of ideas they are talking aboutâthe notion that there is this thing called society, that we have a debt to it, that governments can speak for it, that it can be imagined as a sort of secular godâall of these ideas emerged together around the time of the French Revolution, or in its immediate wake. In other words, it was born alongside the idea of the modern nation-state.
We can already see them coming together clearly in the work of Auguste Comte, in early nineteenth-century France. Comte, a philosopher and political pamphleteer now most famous for having first coined the term âsociology,â went so far, by the end of his life, as actually proposing a Religion of Society, which he called Positivism, broadly modeled on Medieval Catholicism, replete with vestments where all the buttons were on the back (so they couldnât be put on without the help of others). In his last work, which he called a âPositivist Catechism,â he also laid down the first explicit theory of social debt. At one point someone asks an imaginary Priest of Positivism what he thinks of the notion of human rights. The priest scoffs at the very idea. This is nonsense, he says, an error born of individualism. Positivism understands only duties. After all:
We are born under a load of obligations of every kind, to our predecessors, to our successors, to our contemporaries. After our birth these obligations increase or accumulate before the point where we are capable of rendering anyone any service. On what human foundation, then, could one seat the idea of ârightsâ?[113]
While Comte doesnât use the word âdebt,â the sense is clear enough. We have already accumulated endless debts before we get to the age at which we can even think of paying them. By that time, thereâs no way to calculate to whom we even owe them. The only way to redeem ourselves is to dedicate ourselves to the service of Humanity as a whole.
In his lifetime, Comte was considered something of a crackpot, but his ideas proved influential. His notion of unlimited obligations to society ultimately crystallized in the notion of the âsocial debt,â a notion taken up among social reformers and, eventually, socialist politicians in many parts of Europe and abroad.[114] âWe are all born as debtors to societyâ: in France the notion of a social debt soon became something of a catchphrase, a slogan, and eventually a clichĂ©.[115] The state, according to this view, was merely the administrator of an existential debt that all of us have to the society that created us, embodied not least in the fact that we all continue to be completely dependent on one another for our existence, even if we are not completely aware of how.
These are also the intellectual and political circles that shaped the thought of Emile Durkheim, the founder of the discipline of sociology that we know today, who in a way did Comte one better by arguing that all gods in all religions are always already projections of societyâso an explicit religion of society would not even be necessary. All religions, for Durkheim, are simply ways of recognizing our mutual dependence on one another, a dependence that affects us in a million ways that we are never entirely aware of. âGodâ and âsocietyâ are ultimately the same.
The problem is that for several hundred years now, it has simply been assumed that the guardian of that debt we owe for all of this, the legitimate representatives of that amorphous social totality that has allowed us to become individuals, must necessarily be the state. Almost all socialist or socialistic regimes end up appealing to some version of this argument. To take one notorious example, this was how the Soviet Union used to justify forbidding their citizens from emigrating to other countries. The argument was always: The USSR created these people, the USSR raised and educated them, made them who they are. What right do they have to take the product of our investment and transfer it to another country, as if they didnât owe us anything? Neither is this rhetoric restricted to socialist regimes. Nationalists appeal to exactly the same kind of argumentsâespecially in times of war. And all modern governments are nationalist to some degree.
One might even say that what we really have, in the idea of primordial debt, is the ultimate nationalist myth. Once we owed our lives to the gods that created us, paid interest in the form of animal sacrifice, and ultimately paid back the principal with our lives. Now we owe it to the Nation that formed us, pay interest in the form of taxes, and when it comes time to defend the nation against its enemies, to offer to pay it with our lives.
This is a great trap of the twentieth century: on one side is the logic of the market, where we like to imagine we all start out as individuals who donât owe each other anything. On the other is the logic of the state, where we all begin with a debt we can never truly pay. We are constantly told that they are opposites, and that between them they contain the only real human possibilities. But itâs a false dichotomy. States created markets. Markets require states. Neither could continue without the other, at least, in anything like the forms we would recognize today.
<em>We will buy the poor for silver, the needy for a pair of sandals</em>.
<em>âAmos</em> 2:6
The reader may have noticed that there is an unresolved debate between those who see money as a commodity and those who see it as an IOU. Which one is it? By now, the answer should be obvious: itâs both. Keith Hart, probably the best-known current anthropological authority on the subject, pointed this out many years ago. There are, he famously observed, two sides to any coin:
Look at a coin from your pocket. On one side is âheadsââthe symbol of the political authority which minted the coin; on the other side is âtailsââthe precise specification of the amount the coin is worth as payment in exchange. One side reminds us that states underwrite currencies and the money is originally a relation between persons in society, a token perhaps. The other reveals the coin as a thing, capable of entering into definite relations with other things.[116]
Clearly, money was not invented to overcome the inconveniences of barter between neighborsâsince neighbors would have no reason to engage in barter in the first place. Still, a system of pure credit money would have serious inconveniences as well. Credit money is based on trust, and in competitive markets, trust itself becomes a scarce commodity. This is particularly true of dealings between strangers. Within the Roman empire, a silver coin stamped with the image of Tiberius might have circulated at a value considerably higher than the value of the silver it contained. Ancient coins invariably circulated at a value higher than their metal content.[117] This was largely because Tiberiusâs government was willing to accept them at face value. However, the Persian government probably wasnât, and the Mauryan and Chinese governments certainly werenât. Very large numbers of Roman gold and silver coins did end up in India and even China; this is presumably the main reason that they were made of gold and silver to begin with.
Whatâs true for a vast empire like Rome or China is obviously all the more true for a Sumerian or Greek city-state, let alone anyone operating within the kind of broken checkerboard of kingdoms, towns, and tiny principalities that prevailed in most of Medieval Europe or India. As Iâve pointed out, often what was inside and what was outside were not especially clear. Within a communityâa town, a city, a guild or religious societyâpretty much anything could function as money, provided everyone knew there was **someone** willing to accept it to cancel out a debt. To offer one particularly striking example, in certain cities in nineteenth-century Siam, small change consisted entirely of porcelain Chinese gaming countersâbasically, the equivalent of poker chipsâissued by local casinos. If one of these casinos went out of business or lost its license, its owners would have to send a crier through the streets banging a gong and announcing that anyone holding such chits had three days to redeem them.[118] For major transactions, of course, currency that was also acceptable outside the community (usually silver or gold again) was ordinarily employed.
In a similar way, English shops, for many centuries, would issue their own wood or lead or leather token money. The practice was often technically illegal, but it continued until relatively recent times. Here is an example from the seventeenth century, by a certain Henry, who had a store at Stony Stratford, Buckinghamshire:
This is clearly a case of the same principle: Henry would provide small change in the form of IOUs redeemable at his own store. As such, they might circulate broadly, at least among anyone who did regular business at that shop. But they were unlikely to travel very far from Stony Stratfordâmost tokens, in fact, never circulated more than a few blocks in any direction. For larger transactions, everyone, including Henry, expected money in a form that would be acceptable anywhere, including in Italy or France.[119]
Throughout most of history, even where we do find elaborate markets, we also find a complex jumble of different sorts of currency. Some of these may have originally emerged from barter between foreigners: the cacao money of Mesoamerica or salt money of Ethiopia are frequently cited examples.[120] Others arose from credit systems, or from arguments over what sort of goods should be acceptable to pay taxes or other debts. Such questions were often matters of endless contestation. One could often learn a lot about the balance of political forces in a given time and place by what sorts of things were acceptable as currency. For instance: in much the same way that colonial Virginia planters managed to pass a law obliging shopkeepers to accept their tobacco as currency, medieval Pomeranian peasants appear to have at certain points convinced their rulers to make taxes, fees, and customs duties, which were registered in Roman currency, actually payable in wine, cheese, peppers, chickens, eggs, and even herringâmuch to the annoyance of traveling merchants, who therefore had to either carry such things around in order to pay the tolls or buy them locally at prices that would have been more advantageous to their suppliers for that very reason.[121] This was in an area with a free peasantry, rather than serfs. They were in a relatively strong political position. In other times and places, the interests of lords and merchants prevailed instead.
Thus money is almost always something hovering between a commodity and a debt-token. This is probably why coinsâpieces of silver or gold that are already valuable commodities in themselves, but that, being stamped with the emblem of a local political authority, became even more valuableâstill sit in our heads as the quintessential form of money. They most perfectly straddle the divide that defines what money is in the first place. Whatâs more, the relation between the two was a matter of constant political contestation.
In other words, the battle between state and market, between governments and merchants is not inherent to the human condition.
Our two origin storiesâthe myth of barter and the myth of primordial debtâmay appear to be about as far apart as they could be, but in their own way, they are also two sides of the same coin. One assumes the other. Itâs only once we can imagine human life as a series of commercial transactions that weâre capable of seeing our relation to the universe in terms of debt.
To illustrate, let me call a perhaps surprising witness, Friedrich Nietzsche, a man able to see with uncommon clarity what happens when you try to imagine the world in commercial terms.
Nietzscheâs **On the Genealogy of Morals** appeared in 1887. In it, he begins with an argument that might well have been taken directly from Adam Smithâbut he takes it a step further than Smith ever dared to, insisting that not just barter, but buying and selling itself, precede any other form of human relationship. The feeling of personal obligation, he observes,
has its origin in the oldest and most primitive personal relationship there is, in the relationship between seller and buyer, creditor and debtor. Here for the first time one person moved up against another person, here an individual **measured himself** against another individual. We have found no civilization still at such a low level that something of this relationship is not already perceptible. To set prices, to measure values, to think up equivalencies, to exchange thingsâthat preoccupied manâs very first thinking to such a degree that in a certain sense itâs what thinking **itself** is. Here the oldest form of astuteness was bred; here, too, we can assume are the first beginnings of manâs pride, his feeling of pre-eminence in relation to other animals. Perhaps our word âmanâ (**manas**) continues to express directly something of **this** feeling of the self: the human being describes himself as a being which assesses values, which values and measures, as the âinherently calculating animal.â Selling and buying, together with their psychological attributes, are even older than the beginnings of any form of social organizations and groupings; out of the most rudimentary form of personal legal rights the budding feeling of exchange, contract, guilt, law, duty, and compensation was instead first **transferred** to the crudest and earliest social structures (in their relationships with similar social structures), along with the habit of comparing power with power, of measuring, of calculating.[122]
Smith, too, we will remember, saw the origins of languageâand hence of human thoughtâas lying in our propensity to âexchange one thing for another,â in which he also saw the origins of the market.[123] The urge to trade, to compare values, is the very thing that makes us intelligent beings, and different from other animals. Society comes laterâwhich means our ideas about responsibilities to other people first take shape in strictly commercial terms.
Unlike with Smith, however, it never occurred to Nietzsche that you could have a world where all such transactions immediately cancel out. Any system of commercial accounting, he assumed, will produce creditors and debtors. In fact, he believed that it was from this very fact that human morality emerged. Note, he says, how the German word **schuld** means both âdebtâ and âguilt.â At first, to be in debt was simply to be guilty, and creditors delighted in punishing debtors unable to repay their loans by inflicting âall sorts of humiliation and torture on the body of the debtor, for instance, cutting as much flesh off as seemed appropriate for the debt.â[124] In fact, Nietzsche went so far as to insist that those original barbarian law codes that tabulated so much for a ruined eye, so much for a severed finger, were not originally meant to fix rates of monetary compensation for the loss of eyes and fingers, but to establish how much of the debtorâs body creditors were allowed to take! Needless to say, he doesnât provide a scintilla of evidence for this (none exists).[125] But to ask for evidence would be to miss the point. We are dealing here not with a real historical argument but with a purely imaginative exercise.
When humans did begin to form communities, Nietzsche continues, they necessarily began to imagine their relationship to the community in these terms. The tribe provides them with peace and security. They are therefore in its debt. Obeying its laws is a way of paying it back (âpaying your debt to societyâ again). But this debt, he says, is also paidâhere tooâin sacrifice:
Within the original tribal cooperativesâweâre talking about primeval timesâthe living generation always acknowledged a legal obligation to the previous generations, and especially to the earliest one which had founded the tribe [âŠ] Here the reigning conviction is that the tribe only **exists** at all only because of the sacrifices and achievements of its ancestorsâand that people have to **pay them back** with sacrifices and achievements. In this people recognize a **debt** which keeps steadily growing because these ancestors in their continuing existence as powerful spirits do not stop giving the tribe new advantages and lending them their power. Do they do this for free? But there is no âfor freeâ for those raw and âspiritually destituteâ ages. What can people give back to them? Sacrifices (at first as nourishment understood very crudely), festivals, chapels, signs of honor, above all, obedienceâfor all customs, as work of oneâs ancestors, are also their statutes and commands. Do people ever give them enough? This suspicion remains and grows.[126]
In other words, for Nietzsche, starting from Adam Smithâs assumptions about human nature means we must necessarily end up with something very much along the lines of primordial-debt theory. On the one hand, it is because of our feeling of debt to the ancestors that we obey the ancestral laws: this is why we feel that the community has the right to react âlike an angry creditorâ and punish us for our transgressions if we break them. In a larger sense, we develop a creeping feeling that we could never really pay back the ancestors, that no sacrifice (not even the sacrifice of our first-born) will ever truly redeem us. We are terrified of the ancestors, and the stronger and more powerful a community becomes, the more powerful they seem to be, until finally, âthe ancestor is necessarily transfigured into a god.â As communities grow into kingdoms and kingdoms into universal empires, the gods themselves come to seem more universal, they take on grander, more cosmic pretentions, ruling the heavens, casting thunderboltsâculminating in the Christian god, who, as the maximal deity, necessarily âbrought about the maximum feeling of indebtedness on earth.â Even our ancestor Adam is no longer figured as a creditor, but as a transgressor, and therefore a debtor, who passes on to us his burden of Original Sin:
Finally, with the impossibility of discharging the debt, people also come up with the notion that it is impossible to remove the penance, the idea that it cannot be paid off (â**eternal** punishmentâ) ⊠until all of a sudden we confront the paradoxical and horrifying expedient with which a martyred humanity found temporary relief, that stroke of genius of **Christianity:** God sacrificing himself for the guilt of human beings, God paying himself back with himself, God as the only one who can redeem man from what for human beings has become impossible to redeemâthe creditor sacrificing himself for the debtor, out of **love** (can people believe that?), out of love for his debtor![127]
It all makes perfect sense if you start from Nietzscheâs initial premise. The problem is that the premise is insane.
There is also every reason to believe that Nietzsche knew the premise was insane; in fact, that this was the entire point. What Nietzsche is doing here is starting out from the standard, common-sense assumptions about the nature of human beings prevalent in his day (and to a large extent, still prevalent)âthat we are rational calculating machines, that commercial self-interest comes before society, that âsocietyâ itself is just a way of putting a kind of temporary lid on the resulting conflict. That is, he is starting out from ordinary bourgeois assumptions and driving them to a place where they can only shock a bourgeois audience.
Itâs a worthy game and no one has ever played it better; but itâs a game played entirely within the boundaries of bourgeois thought. It has nothing to say to anything that lies beyond that. The best response to anyone who wants to take seriously Nietzscheâs fantasies about savage hunters chopping pieces off each otherâs bodies for failure to remit are the words of an actual hunter-gathererâan Inuit from Greenland made famous in the Danish writer Peter Freuchenâs **Book of the Eskimo**. Freuchen tells how one day, after coming home hungry from an unsuccessful walrus-hunting expedition, he found one of the successful hunters dropping off several hundred pounds of meat. He thanked him profusely. The man objected indignantly:
âUp in our country we are human!â said the hunter. âAnd since we are human we help each other. We donât like to hear anybody say thanks for that. What I get today you may get tomorrow. Up here we say that by gifts one makes slaves and by whips one makes dogs.â[128]
The last line is something of an anthropological classic, and similar statements about the refusal to calculate credits and debits can be found through the anthropological literature on egalitarian hunting societies. Rather than seeing himself as human because he could make economic calculations, the hunter insisted that being truly human meant **refusing** to make such calculations, refusing to measure or remember who had given what to whom, for the precise reason that doing so would inevitably create a world where we began âcomparing power with power, measuring, calculatingâ and reducing each other to slaves or dogs through debt.
Itâs not that he, like untold millions of similar egalitarian spirits throughout history, was unaware that humans have a propensity to calculate. If he wasnât aware of it, he could not have said what he did. Of course we have a propensity to calculate. We have all sorts of propensities. In any real-life situation, we have propensities that drive us in several different contradictory directions simultaneously. No one is more real than any other. The real question is which we take as the foundation of our humanity, and therefore, make the basis of our civilization. If Nietzscheâs analysis of debt is helpful to us, then, it is because it reveals that when we start from the assumption that human thought is essentially a matter of commercial calculation, that buying and selling are the basis of human societyâthen, yes, once we begin to think about our relationship with the cosmos, we will necessarily conceive of it in terms of debt.
I do think Nietzsche helps us in another way as well: to understand the concept of redemption. Niezscheâs account of âprimeval timesâ might be absurd, but his description of Christianityâof how a sense of debt is transformed into an abiding sense of guilt, and guilt to self-loathing, and self-loathing to self-tortureâall of this does ring very true.
Why, for instance, do we refer to Christ as the âredeemerâ? The primary meaning of âredemptionâ is to buy something back, or to recover something that had been given up in security for a loan; to acquire something by paying off a debt. It is rather striking to think that the very core of the Christian message, salvation itself, the sacrifice of Godâs own son to rescue humanity from eternal damnation, should be framed in the language of a financial transaction.
Nietzsche might have been starting from the same assumptions as Adam Smith, but clearly the early Christians werenât. The roots of this thinking lie deeper than Smithâs with his nation of shopkeepers. The authors of the Brahmanas were not alone in borrowing the language of the marketplace as a way of thinking about the human condition. Indeed, to one degree or another, all the major world religions do this.
The reason is that all of themâfrom Zoroastrianism to Islamâarose amidst intense arguments about the role of money and the market in human life, and particularly about what these institutions meant for fundamental questions of what human beings owed to one another. The question of debt, and arguments about debt, ran through every aspect of the political life of the time. These arguments were set amidst revolts, petitions, reformist movements. Some such movements gained allies in the temples and palaces. Others were brutally suppressed. Most of the terms, slogans, and specific issues being debated, though, have been lost to history. We just donât know what a political debate in a Syrian tavern in 750 bc was likely to be about. As a result, we have spent thousands of years contemplating sacred texts full of political allusions that would have been instantly recognizable to any reader at the time when they were written, but whose meaning we now can only guess at.[129]
One of the unusual things about the Bible is that it preserves some bits of this larger context. To return to the notion of redemption: the Hebrew words **padah** and **goal**, both translated as âredemption,â could be used for buying back anything one had sold to someone else, particularly the recovery of ancestral land, or to recovering some object held by creditors in way of a pledge.[130] The example foremost in the minds of prophets and theologians seems to have been the last: the redemption of pledges, and especially, of family members held as debt-pawns. It would seem that the economy of the Hebrew kingdoms, by the time of the prophets, was already beginning to develop the same kind of debt crises that had long been common in Mesopotamia: especially in years of bad harvests, the poor became indebted to rich neighbors or to wealthy moneylenders in the towns, they would begin to lose title to their fields and to become tenants on what had been their own land, and their sons and daughters would be removed to serve as servants in their creditorsâ households, or even sold abroad as slaves.[131] The earlier prophets contain allusions to such crises, but the book of Nehemiah, written in Persian times, is the most explicit:[132]
Some also there were that said, âWe have mortgaged our lands, vineyards, and houses, that we might buy corn, because of the dearth.â
There were also those that said, âWe have borrowed money for the kingâs tribute, and that upon our lands and vineyards.
âYet now our flesh is as the flesh of our brethren, our children as their children: and, lo, we bring into bondage our sons and our daughters to be servants, and some of our daughters are brought unto bondage already: neither is it in our power to redeem them; for other men have our lands and vineyards.â
And I was very angry when I heard their cry and these words.
Then I consulted with myself, and I rebuked the nobles, and the rulers, and said unto them, âYe exact usury, every one of his brother.â And I set a great assembly against them.[133]
Nehemiah was a Jew born in Babylon, a former cup-bearer to the Persian emperor. In 444 bc, he managed to talk the Great King into appointing him governor of his native Judaea. He also received permission to rebuild the Temple in Jerusalem that had been destroyed by Nebuchadnezzar more than two centuries earlier. In the course of rebuilding, sacred texts were recovered and restored; in a sense, this was the moment of the creation of what we now consider Judaism.
The problem was that Nehemiah quickly found himself confronted with a social crisis. All around him, impoverished peasants were unable to pay their taxes; creditors were carrying off the children of the poor. His first response was to issue a classic Babylonian-style âclean slateâ edictâhaving himself been born in Babylon, he was clearly familiar with the general principle. All non-commercial debts were to be forgiven. Maximum interest rates were set. At the same time, though, Nehemiah managed to locate, revise, and reissue much older Jewish laws, now preserved in Exodus, Deuteronomy, and Leviticus, which in certain ways went even further, by institutionalizing the principle.[134] The most famous of these is the Law of Jubilee: a law that stipulated that all debts would be automatically cancelled âin the Sabbath yearâ (that is, after seven years had passed), and that all who languished in bondage owing to such debts would be released.[135]
âFreedom,â in the Bible, as in Mesopotamia, came to refer above all to release from the effects of debt. Over time, the history of the Jewish people itself came to be interpreted in this light: the liberation from bondage in Egypt was Godâs first, paradigmatic act of redemption; the historical tribulations of the Jews (defeat, conquest, exile) were seen as misfortunes that would eventually lead to a final redemption with the coming of the Messiahâthough this could only be accomplished, prophets such as Jeremiah warned them, after the Jewish people truly repented of their sins (carrying each other off into bondage, whoring after false gods, the violation of commandments).[136] In this light, the adoption of the term by Christians is hardly surprising. Redemption was a release from oneâs burden of sin and guilt, and the end of history would be that moment when all slates are wiped clean and all debts finally lifted when a great blast from angelic trumpets will announce the final Jubilee.
If so, âredemptionâ is no longer about buying something back. Itâs really more a matter of destroying the entire system of accounting. In many Middle Eastern cities, this was literally true: one of the common acts during debt cancelation was the ceremonial destruction of the tablets on which financial records had been kept, an act to be repeated, much less officially, in just about every major peasant revolt in history.[137]
This leads to another problem: What is possible in the meantime, before that final redemption comes? In one of his more disturbing parables, the Parable of the Unforgiving Servant, Jesus seemed to be explicitly playing with the problem:
Therefore, the kingdom of heaven is like a king who wanted to settle accounts with his servants. As he began the settlement, a man who owed him ten thousand talents was brought to him. Since he was not able to pay, the master ordered that he and his wife and his children and all that he had be sold to repay the debt.
The servant fell on his knees before him. âBe patient with me,â he begged, âand I will pay back everything.â The servantâs master took pity on him, canceled the debt, and let him go.
But when that servant went out, he found one of his fellow servants who owed him a hundred denarii. He grabbed him and began to choke him. âPay back what you owe me!â he demanded.
His fellow servant fell to his knees and begged him, âBe patient with me, and I will pay you back.â
But he refused. Instead, he went off and had the man thrown into prison until he could pay the debt. When the other servants saw what had happened, they were greatly distressed and went and told their master everything that had happened.
Then the master called the servant in. âYou wicked servant,â he said, âI canceled all that debt of yours because you begged me to. Shouldnât you have had mercy on your fellow servant just as I had on you?â In anger his master turned him over to the jailers to be tortured, until he should pay back all he owed.[138]
This is quite an extraordinary text. On one level itâs a joke; in others, it could hardly be more serious.
We begin with the king wishing to âsettle accountsâ with his servants. The premise is absurd. Kings, like gods, canât really enter into relations of exchange with their subjects, since no parity is possible. And this is a king who clearly **is** God. Certainly there can be no final settling of accounts.
So at best we are dealing with an act of whimsy on the kingâs part. The absurdity of the premise is hammered home by the sum the first man brought before him is said to owe. In ancient Judaea, to say someone owes a creditor âten thousand talentsâ would be like now saying someone owes âa hundred billion dollars.â The number is a joke, too; it simply stands in for âa sum no human being could ever, conceivably, repay.â[139]
Faced with infinite, existential debt, the servant can only tell obvious lies: âa hundred billion? Sure, Iâm good for it! Just give me a little more time.â Then, suddenly, apparently just as arbitrarily, the Lord forgives him.
Yet, it turns out, the amnesty has a condition he is not aware of. It is incumbent on his being willing to act in an analogous way to other humansâin this particular case, another servant who owes him (to translate again into contemporary terms), maybe a thousand bucks. Failing the test, the human is cast into hell for all eternity, or âuntil he should pay back all he owed,â which in this case comes down to the same thing.
The parable has long been a challenge to theologians. Itâs normally interpreted as a comment on the endless bounty of Godâs grace and how little He demands of us in comparisonâand thus, by implication, as a way of suggesting that torturing us in hell for all eternity is not as unreasonable as it might seem. Certainly, the unforgiving servant is a genuinely odious character. Still, what is even more striking to me is the tacit suggestion that forgiveness, in this world, is ultimately impossible. Christians practically say as much every time they recite the Lordâs Prayer, and ask God to âforgive us our debts, as we also forgive our debtors.â[140] It repeats the story of the parable almost exactly, and the implications are similarly dire. After all, most Christians reciting the prayer are aware that they do not generally forgive their debtors. Why then should God forgive them their sins?[141]
Whatâs more, there is the lingering suggestion that we really couldnât live up to those standards, even if we tried. One of the things that makes the Jesus of the New Testament such a tantalizing character is that itâs never clear what heâs telling us. Everything can be read two ways. When he calls on his followers to forgive all debts, refuse to cast the first stone, turn the other cheek, love their enemies, to hand over their possessions to the poorâis he really expecting them to do this? Or are such demands just a way of throwing in their faces that, since we are clearly not prepared to act this way, we are all sinners whose salvation can only come in another worldâa position that can be (and has been) used to justify almost anything? This is a vision of human life as inherently corrupt, but it also frames even spiritual affairs in commercial terms: with calculations of sin, penance, and absolution, the Devil and St. Peter with their rival ledger books, usually accompanied by the creeping feeling that itâs all a charade because the very fact that we are reduced to playing such a game of tabulating sins reveals us to be fundamentally unworthy of forgiveness.
World religions, as we shall see, are full of this kind of ambivalence. On the one hand they are outcries against the market; on the other, they tend to frame their objections in commercial termsâas if to argue that turning human life into a series of transactions is not a very good deal. What I think even these few examples reveal, though, is how much is being papered over in the conventional accounts of the origins and history of money. There is something almost touchingly naĂŻve in the stories about neighbors swapping potatoes for an extra pair of shoes. When the ancients thought about money, friendly swaps were hardly the first thing that came to mind.
True, some might have thought about their tab at the local ale-house, or, if they were a merchant or administrator, of storehouses, account books, exotic imported delights. For most, though, what was likely to come to mind was the selling of slaves and ransoming of prisoners, corrupt tax-farmers and the depredations of conquering armies, mortgages and interest, theft and extortion, revenge and punishment, and, above all, the tension between the need for money to create families, to acquire a bride so as to have children, and use of that same money to destroy familiesâto create debts that lead to the same wife and children being taken away. âSome of our daughters are brought unto bondage already: neither is it in our power to redeem them.â One can only imagine what those words meant, emotionally, to a father in a patriarchal society in which a manâs ability to protect the honor of his family was everything. Yet this is what money meant to the majority of people for most of human history: the terrifying prospect of oneâs sons and daughters being carried off to the homes of repulsive strangers to clean their pots and provide the occasional sexual services, to be subject to every conceivable form of violence and abuse, possibly for years, conceivably forever, as their parents waited, helpless, avoiding eye contact with their neighbors, who knew exactly what was happening to those they were supposed to have been able to protect.[142] Clearly this was the worst thing that could happen to anyoneâwhich is why, in the parable, it could be treated as interchangeable with being âturned over to the jailors to be torturedâ for life. And thatâs just from the perspective of the father. One can only imagine how it might have felt to be the daughter. Yet, over the course of human history, untold millions of daughters have known (and in fact many still know) exactly what itâs like.
One might object that this was just assumed to be in the nature of things: like the imposition of tribute on conquered populations, it might have been resented, but it wasnât considered a moral issue, a matter of right and wrong. Some things just happen. This has been the most common attitude of peasants to such phenomena throughout human history. Whatâs striking about the historical record is that in the case of debt crises, this was **not** how many reacted. Many actually did become indignant. So many, in fact, that most of our contemporary language of social justice, our way of speaking of human bondage and emancipation, continues to echo ancient arguments about debt.
Itâs particularly striking because so many other things do seem to have been accepted as simply in the nature of things. One does not see a similar outcry against caste systems, for example, or for that matter, the institution of slavery.[143] Surely slaves and untouchables often experienced at least equal horrors. No doubt many protested their condition. Why was it that the debtorsâ protests seemed to carry such greater moral weight? Why were debtors so much more effective in winning the ear of priests, prophets, officials, and social reformers? Why was it that officials like Nehemiah were willing to give such sympathetic consideration to their complaints, to inveigh, to summon great assemblies?
Some have suggested practical reasons: debt crises destroyed the free peasantry, and it was free peasants who were drafted into ancient armies to fight in wars.[144] No doubt this was a factor; clearly it wasnât the only one. There is no reason to believe that Nehemiah, for instance, in his anger at the usurers, was primarily concerned with his ability to levy troops for the Persian king. It is something more fundamental.
What makes debt different is that it is premised on an assumption of equality.
To be a slave, or lower-caste, is to be intrinsically inferior. We are dealing with relations of unadulterated hierarchy. In the case of debt, we are dealing with two individuals who begin as equal parties to a contract. Legally, at least as far as the contract is concerned, they are the same.
We can add that, in the ancient world, when people who actually were more or less social equals loaned money to one another, the terms appear to have normally been quite generous. Often no interest was charged, or if it was, it was very low. âAnd donât charge me interest,â wrote one wealthy Canaanite to another, in a tablet dated around 1200 bc, âafter all, we are both gentlemen.â[145] Between close kin, many âloansâ were probably, then as now, just gifts that no one seriously expected to recover. Loans between rich and poor were something else again.
The problem was that, unlike status distinctions like caste or slavery, the line between rich and poor was never precisely drawn. One can imagine the reaction of a farmer who went up to the house of a wealthy cousin, on the assumption that âhumans help each other,â and ended up, a year or two later, watching his vineyard seized and his sons and daughters led away. Such behavior could be justified, in legal terms, by insisting that the loan was not a form of mutual aid but a commercial relationshipâa contract is a contract. (It also required a certain reliable access to superior force.) But it could only have felt like a terrible betrayal. Whatâs more, framing it as a breach of contract meant stating that this was, in fact, a moral issue: these two parties **ought** to be equals, but one had failed to honor the bargain. Psychologically, this can only have made the indignity of the debtorâs condition all the more painful, since it made it possible to say that it was his own turpitude that sealed his daughterâs fate. But that just made the motive all the more compelling to throw back the moral aspersions: âOur flesh is as the flesh of our brethren, our children as their children.â We are all the same people. We have a responsibility to take account of one anotherâs needs and interests. How then could my brother do this to me?
In the Old Testament case, debtors were able to marshal a particularly powerful moral argumentâas the authors of Deuteronomy constantly reminded their readers, were not the Jews all slaves in Egypt, and had they not all been redeemed by God? Was it right, when they had all been given this promised land to share, for some to take that land away from others? Was it right for a population of liberated slaves to go about enslaving one aotherâs children?[146] But analogous arguments were being made in similar situations almost everywhere in the ancient world: in Athens, in Rome, and for that matter, in Chinaâwhere legend had it that coinage itself was first invented by an ancient emperor to redeem the children of families who had been forced to sell them after a series of devastating floods.
Through most of history, when overt political conflict between classes did appear, it took the form of pleas for debt cancellationâthe freeing of those in bondage, and usually, a more just reallocation of the land. What we see, in the Bible and other religious traditions, are traces of the moral arguments by which such claims were justified, usually subject to all sorts of imaginative twists and turns, but inevitably, to some degree, incorporating the language of the marketplace itself.
To tell the history of debt, then, is also necessarily to reconstruct how the language of the marketplace has come to pervade every aspect of human lifeâeven to provide the terminology for the moral and religious voices ostensibly raised against it. We have already seen how both Vedic and Christian teachings thus end up making the same curious move: first describing all morality as debt, but then, in their very manner of doing so, demonstrating that morality cannot really be reduced to debt, that it must be grounded in something else.[147]
But what? Religious traditions prefer vast, cosmological answers: the alternative to the morality of debt lies in recognition of continuity with the universe, or life in the expectation of the imminent annihilation of the universe, or absolute subordination to the deity, or withdrawal into another world. My own aims are more modest, so I will take the opposite approach. If we really want to understand the moral grounds of economic life, and by extension, human life, it seems to me that we must start instead with the very small things: the everyday details of social existence, the way we treat our friends, enemies, and childrenâoften with gestures so tiny (passing the salt, bumming a cigarette) that we ordinarily never stop to think about them at all. Anthropology has shown us just how different and numerous are the ways in which humans have been known to organize themselves. But it also reveals some remarkable commonalitiesâfundamental moral principles that appear to exist everywhere, and that will always tend to be invoked, wherever people transfer objects back and forth or argue about what other people owe them.
One of the reasons that human life is so complicated, in turn, is because many of these principles contradict one another. As we will see, they are constantly pulling us in radically different directions. The moral logic of exchange, and hence of debt, is only one; in any given situation, there are likely to be completely different principles that could be brought to bear. In this sense, the moral confusion discussed in the first chapter is hardly new; in a sense, moral thought is founded on this very tension.
To really understand what debt is, then, it will be necessary to understand how itâs different from other sorts of obligation that human beings might have to one anotherâwhich, in turn, means mapping out what those other sorts of obligation actually are. Doing so, however, poses peculiar challenges. Contemporary social theoryâeconomic anthropology includedâoffers surprisingly little help in this regard. Thereâs an enormous anthropological literature on gifts, for instance, starting with the French anthropologist Marcel Maussâs essay of 1925, even on âgift economiesâ that operate on completely different principles than market economiesâbut in the end, almost all this literature concentrates on the exchange of gifts, assuming that whenever one gives a gift, this act incurs a debt, and the recipient must eventually reciprocate in kind. Much as in the case of the great religions, the logic of the marketplace has insinuated itself even into the thinking of those who are most explicitly opposed to it. As a result, I am going to have to start over here, to create a new theory, pretty much from scratch.
Part of the problem is the extraordinary place that economics currently holds in the social sciences. In many ways it is treated as a kind of master discipline. Just about anyone who runs anything important in America is expected to have some training in economic theory, or at least to be familiar with its basic tenets. As a result, those tenets have come to be treated as received wisdom, as basically beyond question (one knows one is in the presence of received wisdom when, if one challenges it, the first reaction is to treat one as simply ignorantââYou obviously have never heard of the Laffer Curveâ; âClearly you need a course in Economics 101ââthe theory is seen as so obviously true that no one who understands it could possibly disagree.) Whatâs more, those branches of social theory that make the greatest claims to âscientific statusââârational choice theory,â for instanceâstart from the same assumptions about human psychology that economists do: that human beings are best viewed as self-interested actors calculating how to get the best terms possible out of any situation, the most profit or pleasure or happiness for the least sacrifice or investmentâcurious, considering experimental psychologists have demonstrated over and over again that these assumptions simply arenât true.[148]
From early on, there were those who wished to create a theory of social interaction grounded in a more generous view of human natureâinsisting that moral life comes down to something more than mutual advantage, that it is motivated above all by a sense of justice. The key term here became âreciprocity,â the sense of equity, balance, fairness, and symmetry, embodied in our image of justice as a set of scales. Economic transactions were just one variant of the principle of balanced exchangeâand one that had a notorious tendency to go awry. But if one examines matters closely, one finds that all human relations are based on some variation on reciprocity.
In the 1950s, â60s and â70s, there was something of a craze for this sort of thing, in the guise of what was then called âexchange theory,â developed in infinite variations, from George Homansâ âSocial Exchange Theoryâ in the United States to Claude Levi-Straussâs Structuralism in France. Levi-Strauss, who became a kind of intellectual god in anthropology, made the extraordinary argument that human life could be imagined as consisting of three spheres: language (which consisted of the exchange of words), kinship (which consisted of the exchange of women), and economics (which consisted of the exchange of things). All three, he insisted, were governed by the same fundamental law of reciprocity.[149]
Levi-Straussâs star is fallen now, and such extreme statements seem, in retrospect, a little bit ridiculous. Still, itâs not as if anyone has proposed a bold new theory to replace all this. Instead, the assumptions have simply retreated into the background. Almost everyone continues to assume that in its fundamental nature, social life is based on the principle of reciprocity, and therefore that all human interaction can best be understood as a kind of exchange. If so, then debt really is at the root of all morality, because debt is what happens when some balance has not yet been restored.
But can all justice really be reduced to reciprocity? Itâs easy enough to come up with forms of reciprocity that donât seem particularly just. âDo unto others as you would wish others to do unto youâ might seem like an excellent foundation for a system of ethics, but for most of us, âan eye for an eyeâ does not evoke justice so much as vindictive brutality.[150] âOne good turn deserves anotherâ is a pleasant sentiment, but âIâll scratch your back, you scratch mineâ is shorthand for political corruption. Conversely, there are relationships that seem clearly moral but appear to have nothing to do with reciprocity. The relation between mother and child is an oft-cited example. Most of us learn our sense of justice and morality first from our parents. Yet it is extremely difficult to see the relation between parent and child as particularly reciprocal.
Would we really be willing to conclude that therefore it is not a moral relationship? That it has nothing to do with justice?
The Canadian novelist Margaret Atwood begins a recent book on debt with a similar paradox:
Nature Writer Ernest Thompson Seton had an odd bill presented to him on his twenty-first birthday. It was a record kept by his father of all the expenses connected with young Ernestâs childhood and youth, including the fee charged by the doctor for delivering him. Even more oddly, Ernest is said to have paid it. I used to think that Mr. Seton Senior was a jerk, but now Iâm wondering.[151]
Most of us wouldnât wonder much. Such behavior seems monstrous, inhuman. Certainly Seton did: he paid the bill, but never spoke to his father again afterward.[152] And in a way, this is precisely why the presentation of such a bill seems so outrageous. Squaring accounts means that the two parties have the ability to walk away from each other. By presenting it, his father suggested heâd just as soon have nothing further to do with him.
In other words, while most of us can imagine what we owe to our parents as a kind of debt, few of us can imagine being able to actually pay itâor even that such a debt ever **should** be paid. Yet if it canât be paid, in what sense is it a âdebtâ at all? And if it is not a debt, what is it?
One obvious place to look for alternatives is in cases of human interaction in which expectations of reciprocity seem to slam into a wall. Nineteenth-century travelersâ accounts, for instance, are full of this sort of thing. Missionaries working in certain parts of Africa would often be astounded by the reactions they would receive when they administered medicines. Hereâs a typical example, from a British missionary in Congo:
A day or two after we reached Vana we found one of the natives very ill with pneumonia. Comber treated him and kept him alive on strong fowl-soup; a great deal of careful nursing and attention was visited on him, for his house was beside the camp. When we were ready to go on our way again, the man was well. To our astonishment he came and asked us for a present, and was as astonished and disgusted as he had made us to be, when we declined giving it. We suggested that it was his place to bring us a present and to show some gratitude. He said to us, âWell indeed! You white men have no shame!â[153]
In the early decades of the twentieth century, the French philosopher Lucien Levy-Bruhl, in an attempt to prove that ânativesâ operated with an entirely different form of logic, compiled a list of similar stories: for instance, of a man saved from drowning who proceeded to ask his rescuer to give him some nice clothes to wear, or another who, on being nursed back to health after having been savaged by a tiger, demanded a knife. One French missionary working in Central Africa insisted that such things happened to him on a regular basis:
You save a personâs life, and you must expect to receive a visit from him before long; you are now under an obligation to him, and you will not get rid of him except by giving him presents.[154]
Now, certainly, there is almost always felt to be something extraordinary about saving a life. Anything surrounding birth and death almost cannot help but partake of the infinite, and, therefore, throw all everyday means of moral calculation askew. This is probably why stories like this had become something of a clichĂ© in America when I was growing up. I remember as a child several times being told that among the Inuit (or sometimes it was among Buddhists, or Chinese, but curiously, never Africans)âthat if one saves someone elseâs life, one is considered responsible for taking care of that person forever. It defies our sense of reciprocity. But somehow, it also makes a weird kind of sense.
We have no way of knowing what was really going on in the minds of the patients in these stories, since we donât know who they were or what sort of expectations they had (how they normally interacted with their doctors, for example). But we can guess. Letâs try a thought experiment. Imagine that we are dealing with a place where, if one man saved anotherâs life, the two became like brothers. Each was now expected to share everything, and to provide for the other when he was in need. If so, the patient would surely notice that his new brother appeared to be extraordinarily wealthy, not in much need of anything, but that he, the patient, was lacking in many things the missionary could provide.
Alternately (and more likely), imagine that we are dealing not with a relationship of radical equality but the very opposite. In many parts of Africa, accomplished curers were also important political figures with extensive clienteles of former patients. A would-be follower thus arrives to declare his political allegiance. What complicates the matter in this case is that followers of great men, in this part of Africa, were in a relatively strong bargaining position. Good henchmen were hard to come by; important people were expected to be generous with followers to keep them from joining some rivalâs entourage instead. If so, asking for a shirt or knife would be a way of asking for confirmation that the missionary does wish to have the man as a follower. Paying him back, in contrast, would be, like Setonâs gesture to his father, an insult: a way of saying that despite the missionary having saved his life, he would just as soon have nothing further to do with him.
This is a thought experimentâbecause we donât really know what the African patients were thinking. The point is that such forms of radical equality and radical inequality do exist in the world, that each carries within it its own kind of morality, its own way of thinking and arguing about the rights and wrongs of any given situation, and these moralities are entirely different than that of tit-for-tat exchange. In the rest of the chapter, I will provide a rough-and-ready way to map out the main possibilities, by proposing that there are three main moral principles on which economic relations can be founded, all of which occur in any human society, and which I will call communism, hierarchy, and exchange.
I will define communism here as any human relationship that operates on the principles of âfrom each according to their abilities, to each according to their needs.â
I admit that the usage here is a bit provocative. âCommunismâ is a word that can evoke strong emotional reactionsâmainly, of course, because we tend to identify it with âcommunistâ regimes. This is ironic, since the Communist parties that ruled over the USSR and its satellites, and that still rule China and Cuba, never described their own systems as âcommunist.â They described them as âsocialist.â âCommunismâ was always a distant, somewhat fuzzy utopian ideal, usually to be accompanied by the withering away of the stateâto be achieved at some point in the distant future.
Our thinking about communism has been dominated by a myth. Once upon a time, humans held all things in commonâin the Garden of Eden, during the Golden Age of Saturn, in Paleolithic hunter-gatherer bands. Then came the Fall, as a result of which we are now cursed with divisions of power and private property. The dream was that someday, with the advance of technology and general prosperity, with social revolution or the guidance of the Party, we would finally be in a position to put things back, to restore common ownership and common management of collective resources. Throughout the last two centuries, Communists and anti-Communists argued over how plausible this picture was and whether it would be a blessing or a nightmare. But they all agreed on the basic framework: communism was about collective property, âprimitive communismâ did once exist in the distant past, and someday it might return.
We might call this âmythic communismââor even, âepic communismââa story we like to tell ourselves. Since the days of the French Revolution, it has inspired millions; but it has also done enormous damage to humanity. Itâs high time, I think, to brush the entire argument aside. In fact, âcommunismâ is not some magical utopia, and neither does it have anything to do with ownership of the means of production. It is something that exists right nowâthat exists, to some degree, in any human society, although there has never been one in which **everything** has been organized in that way, and it would be difficult to imagine how there could be. All of us act like communists a good deal of the time. None of us acts like a communist consistently. âCommunist societyââin the sense of a society organized exclusively on that single principleâcould never exist. But all social systems, even economic systems like capitalism, have always been built on top of a bedrock of actually-existing communism.
Starting, as I say, from the principle of âfrom each according to their abilities, to each according to their needsâ allows us to look past the question of individual or private ownership (which is often little more than formal legality anyway) and at much more immediate and practical questions of who has access to what sorts of things and under what conditions.[155] Whenever it is the operative principle, even if itâs just two people who are interacting, we can say we are in the presence of a sort of communism.
Almost everyone follows this principle if they are collaborating on some common project.[156] If someone fixing a broken water pipe says, âHand me the wrench,â his co-worker will not, generally speaking, say, âAnd what do I get for it?ââeven if they are working for Exxon-Mobil, Burger King, or Goldman Sachs. The reason is simple efficiency (ironically enough, considering the conventional wisdom that âcommunism just doesnât workâ): if you really care about getting something done, the most efficient way to go about it is obviously to allocate tasks by ability and give people whatever they need to do them.[157] One might even say that itâs one of the scandals of capitalism that most capitalist firms, internally, operate communistically. True, they donât tend to operate very democratically. Most often they are organized around military-style top-down chains of command. But there is often an interesting tension here, because top-down chains of command are not particularly efficient: they tend to promote stupidity among those on top, resentful foot-dragging among those on the bottom. The greater the need to improvise, the more democratic the cooperation tends to become. Inventors have always understood this, start-up capitalists frequently figure it out, and computer engineers have recently rediscovered the principle: not only with things like freeware, which everyone talks about, but even in the organization of their businesses. Apple Computers is a famous example: it was founded by (mostly Republican) computer engineers who broke from IBM in Silicon Valley in the 1980s, forming little democratic circles of twenty to forty people with their laptops in each otherâs garages.
This is presumably also why in the immediate wake of great disastersâa flood, a blackout, or an economic collapseâpeople tend to behave the same way, reverting to a rough-and-ready communism. However briefly, hierarchies and markets and the like become luxuries that no one can afford. Anyone who has lived through such a moment can speak to their peculiar qualities, the way that strangers become sisters and brothers and human society itself seems to be reborn. This is important, because it shows that we are not simply talking about cooperation. In fact, **communism is the foundation of all human sociability**. It is what makes society possible. There is always an assumption that anyone who is not actually an enemy can be expected on the principle of âfrom each according to their abilities,â at least to an extent: for example, if one needs to figure out how to get somewhere, and the other knows the way.
We so take this for granted, in fact, that the exceptions are themselves revealing. E.E. Evans-Pritchard, an anthropologist who in the 1920s carried out research among the Nuer, Nilotic pastoralists in southern Sudan, reports his discomfiture when he realized that someone had intentionally given him wrong directions:
On one occasion I asked the way to a certain place and was deliberately deceived. I returned in chagrin to camp and asked the people why they had told me the wrong way. One of them replied, âYou are a foreigner, why should we tell you the right way? Even if a Nuer who was a stranger asked us the way we would say to him, âYou continue straight along that path,â but we would not tell him that the path forked. Why should we tell him? But you are now a member of our camp and you are kind to our children, so we will tell you the right way in future.â[158]
The Nuer are constantly engaged in feuds; any stranger might well turn out to be an enemy there to scout out a good place for an ambush, and it would be unwise to give such a person useful information. Whatâs more, Evans-Pritchardâs own situation was obviously relevant, since he was an agent of the British governmentâthe same government that had recently sent in the RAF to strafe and bomb the inhabitants of this very settlement before forcibly resettling them there. Under the circumstances, the inhabitantsâ treatment of Evans-Pritchard seems quite generous. The main point, though, is that it requires something on this scaleâan immediate threat to life and limb, terror-bombing of civilian populationsâbefore people will ordinarily consider not giving a stranger accurate directions.[159]
Itâs not just directions. Conversation is a domain particularly disposed to communism. Lies, insults, put-downs, and other sorts of verbal aggression are importantâbut they derive most of their power from the shared assumption that people do not ordinarily act this way: an insult does not sting unless one assumes that others will normally be considerate of oneâs feelings, and itâs impossible to lie to someone who does not assume you would ordinarily tell the truth. When we genuinely wish to break off amicable relations with someone, we stop speaking to them entirely.
The same goes for small courtesies like asking for a light, or even for a cigarette. It seems more legitimate to ask a stranger for a cigarette than for an equivalent amount of cash, or even food; in fact, if one has been identified as a fellow smoker, itâs rather difficult to refuse such a request. In such casesâa match, a piece of information, holding the elevatorâone might say the âfrom eachâ element is so minimal that most of us comply without even thinking about it. Conversely, the same is true if another personâs needâeven a strangerâsâis particularly spectacular or extreme: if he is drowning, for example. If a child has fallen onto the subway tracks, we assume that anyone who is capable of helping her up will do so.
I will call this âbaseline communismâ: the understanding that, unless people consider themselves enemies, if the need is considered great enough, or the cost considered reasonable enough, the principle of âfrom each according to their abilities, to each according to their needsâ will be assumed to apply. Of course, different communities apply very different standards. In large, impersonal urban communities, such a standard may go no further than asking for a light or directions. This might not seem like much, but it founds the possibility of larger social relations. In smaller, less impersonal communitiesâespecially those not divided into social classesâthe same logic will likely extend much further: for example, it is often effectively impossible to refuse a request not just for tobacco, but for foodâsometimes even from a stranger; certainly from anyone considered to belong to the community. Exactly one page after describing his difficulties in asking for directions, Evans-Pritchard notes that these same Nuer find it almost impossible, when dealing with someone they have accepted as a member of their camp, to refuse a request for almost any item of common consumption, so that a man or woman known to have anything extra in the way of grain, tobacco, tools, or agricultural implements can be expected to see their stockpiles disappear almost immediately.[160] However, this baseline of openhanded sharing and generosity never extends to everything. Often, in fact, things freely shared are treated as trivial and unimportant for that very reason. Among the Nuer, true wealth takes the form of cattle. No one would freely share their cattle; in fact, young Nuer men learn that they are expected to defend their cattle with their lives; for this reason, cattle are neither bought nor sold.
The obligation to share food, and whatever else is considered a basic necessity, tends to become the basis of everyday morality in a society whose members see themselves as equals. Another anthropologist, Audrey Richards, once described how Bemba mothers, âsuch lax disciplinarians in everything else,â will scold their children harshly if they give one an orange or some other treat and the child does not immediately offer to share it with her friends.[161] But sharing is also, in such societiesâin any, if we really think about itâa major focus of lifeâs pleasures. As a result, the need to share is particularly acute in both the best of times and the worst of times: during famines, for example, but also during moments of extreme plenty. Early missionary accounts of native North Americans almost invariably include awestruck remarks on generosity in times of famine, often to total strangers.[162] At the same time,
On returning from their fishing, their hunting, and their trading, they exchange many gifts; if they have thus obtained something unusually good, even if they have bought it, or if it has been given to them, they make a feast to the whole village with it. Their hospitality towards all sorts of strangers is remarkable.[163]
The more elaborate the feast, the more likely one is to see some combination of free sharing of some things (for instance, food and drink) and careful distribution of others: say, prize meat, whether from game or sacrifice, which is often parceled out according to very elaborate protocols or equally elaborate gift exchange. The giving and taking of gifts often takes on a distinctly gamelike quality, continuous often with the actual games, contests, pageants, and performances that also often mark popular festivals. As with society at large, the shared conviviality could be seen as a kind of communistic base on top of which everything else is constructed. It also helps to emphasize that sharing is not simply about morality, but also about pleasure. Solitary pleasures will always exist, but for most human beings, the most pleasurable activities almost always involve sharing something: music, food, liquor, drugs, gossip, drama, beds. There is a certain communism of the senses at the root of most things we consider fun.
The surest way to know that one is in the presence of communistic relations is that not only are no accounts taken, but it would be considered offensive, or simply bizarre, to even consider doing so. Each village, clan, or nation within the League of the Hodenosaunee, or Iroquois, for example, was divided into two halves.[164] This is a common pattern: in other parts of the world (Amazonia, Melanesia) too, there are arrangements in which members of one side can only marry someone from the other side, or only eat food grown on the other side; such rules are explicitly designed to make each side dependent on the other for some basic necessity of life. Among the Six Iroquois, each side was expected to bury the otherâs dead. Nothing would be more absurd than for one side to complain that, âlast year, we buried five of your dead, but you only buried two of ours.â
Baseline communism might be considered the raw material of sociality, a recognition of our ultimate interdependence that is the ultimate substance of social peace. Still, in most circumstances, that minimal baseline is not enough. One always behaves in a spirit of solidarity more with some people than others, and certain institutions are specifically based on principles of solidarity and mutual aid. First among these are those we love, with mothers being the paradigm of selfless love. Others include close relatives, wives and husbands, lovers, oneâs closest friends. These are the people with whom we share everything, or at least to whom we know we can turn in need, which is the definition of a true friend everywhere. Such friendships may be formalized by a ritual as âbond-friendsâ or âblood brothersâ who cannot refuse each other anything. As a result, any community could be seen as criss-crossed with relations of âindividualistic communism,â one-to-one relations that operate, to varying intensities and degrees, on the basis of âfrom each according to their ability, to each according to their needs.â[165]
This same logic can be, and is, extended within groups: not only cooperative work groups, but almost any in-group will define itself by creating its own sort of baseline communism. There will be certain things shared or made freely available within the group, others that anyone will be expected to provide for other members on request, that one would never share with or provide to outsiders: help in repairing oneâs nets in an association of fisherman, stationery supplies in an office, certain sorts of information among commodity traders, and so forth. Also, certain categories of people we can always call on in certain situations, such as harvesting or moving house.[166] One could go on from here to various forms of sharing, pooling, who gets to call on whom for help with certain tasks: moving, or harvesting, or even, if one is in trouble, providing an interest-free loan. Finally, there are the different sorts of âcommons,â the collective administration of common resources.
The sociology of everyday communism is a potentially enormous field, but one which, owing to our peculiar ideological blinkers, we have been unable to write about because we have been largely unable to see it. Rather than try to further outline it, I will limit myself to three final points.
First, we are not really dealing with reciprocity hereâor at best, only with reciprocity in the broadest sense.[167] What is equal on both sides is the knowledge that the other person **would** do the same for you, not that they necessarily **will**. The Iroquois example brings home clearly what makes this possible: that such relations are based on a presumption of eternity. Society will always exist. Therefore, there will always be a north and a south side of the village. This is why no accounts need be taken. In a similar way, people tend to treat their mothers and best friends as if they will always exist, however well they know it isnât true.
The second point has to do with the famous âlaw of hospitality.â There is a peculiar tension between a common stereotype of what are called âprimitive societiesâ (people lacking both states and markets) as societies in which anyone not a member of the community is assumed to be an enemy, and the frequent accounts of early European travelers awestruck by the extraordinary generosity shown them by actual âsavages.â Granted, there is a certain truth to both sides. Wherever a stranger is a dangerous potential enemy, the normal way to overcome the danger is by some dramatic gesture of generosity whose very magnificence catapults them into that mutual sociality that is the ground for all peaceful social relations. True, when one is dealing with completely unknown quantities, there is often a process of testing. Both Christopher Columbus, in Hispaniola, and Captain Cook, in Polynesia, reported similar stories of islanders who either flee, attack, or offer everythingâbut who often later enter the boats and help themselves to anything they take a fancy to, provoking threats of violence from the crew, who then did their utmost to establish the principle that relations between strange peoples should be mediated instead by ânormalâ commercial exchange.
Itâs understandable that dealings with potentially hostile strangers should encourage an all-or-nothing logic, a tension preserved even in English in the etymology of the words âhost,â âhostile,â âhostage,â and indeed âhospitality,â all of which are derived from the same Latin root.[168] What I want to emphasize here is that all such gestures are simply exaggerated displays of that very âbaseline communismâ that I have already argued is the ground of all human social life. This is why, for instance, the difference between friends and enemies is so often articulated through foodâand often the most commonplace, humble, domestic sorts of food: as in the familiar principle, common in both Europe and the Middle East, that those who have shared bread and salt must never harm one another. In fact, those things that exist above all to be shared often become those things one **cannot** share with enemies. Among the Nuer, so free with food and everyday possessions, if one man murders another, a blood feud follows. Everyone in the vicinity will often have to line up on one side or another, and those on opposite sides are strictly forbidden to eat with anyone on the other, or even to drink from a cup or bowl one of their newfound enemies has previously used, lest terrible results ensue.[169] The extraordinary inconvenience this creates is a major incentive to try to negotiate some sort of settlement. By the same token, it is often said that people who have shared food, or the right, archetypal kind of food, are forbidden to harm one another, however much they might be otherwise inclined to do so. At times, this can take on an almost comical formality, as in the Arab story of the burglar who, while ransacking someoneâs house, stuck his finger in a jar to see if it was full of sugar, only to discover it was full of salt instead. Realizing that he had now eaten salt at the ownerâs table, he dutifully put back everything heâd stolen.
Finally, once we start thinking of communism as a principle of morality rather than just a question of property ownership, it becomes clear that this sort of morality is almost always at play to some degree in any transactionâeven commerce. If one is on sociable terms with someone, itâs hard to completely ignore their situation. Merchants often reduce prices for the needy. This is one of the main reasons why shopkeepers in poor neighborhoods are almost never of the same ethnic group as their customers; it would be almost impossible for a merchant who grew up in the neighborhood to make money, as they would be under constant pressure to give financial breaks, or at least easy credit terms, to their impoverished relatives and school chums. The opposite is true as well. An anthropologist who lived for some time in rural Java once told me that she measured her linguistic abilities by how well she could bargain at the local bazaar. It frustrated her that she could never get it down to a price as low as local people seemed pay. âWell,â a Javanese friend finally had to explain, âthey charge rich Javanese people more, too.â
Once again, we are back to the principle that if the needs (for instance, dire poverty), or the abilities (for instance, wealth beyond imagination), are sufficiently dramatic, then unless there is a complete absence of sociality, some degree of communistic morality will almost inevitably enter into the way people take accounts.[170] A Turkish folktale about the Medieval Sufi mystic Nasruddin Hodja illustrates the complexities thus introduced into the very concept of supply and demand:
One day when Nasruddin was left in charge of the local teahouse, the king and some retainers, who had been hunting nearby, stopped in for breakfast.
âDo you have quail eggs?â asked the king.
âIâm sure I can find some,â answered Nasruddin.
The king ordered an omelet of a dozen quail eggs, and Nasruddin hurried out to look for them. After the king and his party had eaten, he charged them a hundred gold pieces.
The king was puzzled. âAre quail eggs really that rare in this part of the country?â
âItâs not so much quail eggs that are rare around here,â Nasruddin replied. âItâs more visits from kings.â
Communism, then, is based neither in exchange nor in reciprocityâexcept, as I have observed, in the sense that it does involve mutual expectations and responsibilities. Even here, it seems better to use another word (âmutualityâ?) so as to emphasize that exchange operates on entirely different principles; that itâs a fundamentally different kind of moral logic.
Exchange is all about equivalence. Itâs a back-and-forth process involving two sides in which each side gives as good as it gets. This is why one can speak of people exchanging words (if thereâs an argument), blows, or even gunfire.[171] In these examples, itâs not that there is ever an exact equivalenceâeven if there were some way to measure an exact equivalenceâbut more a constant process of interaction tending toward equivalence. Actually, thereâs something of a paradox here: each side in each case is trying to outdo the other, but, unless one side is utterly put to rout, itâs easiest to break the whole thing off when both consider the outcome to be more or less even. When we move to the exchange of material goods, we find a similar tension. Often there is an element of competition; if nothing else, thereâs always that possibility. But at the same time, thereâs a sense that both sides are keeping accounts, and that, unlike what happens in communism, which always partakes of a certain notion of eternity, the entire relationship can be canceled out, and either party can call an end to it at any time.
This element of competition can work in completely different ways. In cases of barter or commercial exchange, when both parties to the transaction are only interested in the value of goods being transacted, they may wellâas economists insist they shouldâtry to seek the maximum material advantage. On the other hand, as anthropologists have long pointed out, when the exchange is of gifts, that is, the objects passing back and forth are mainly considered interesting in how they reflect on and rearrange relations between the people carrying out the transaction, then insofar as competition enters in, it is likely to work precisely the other way aroundâto become a matter of contests of generosity, of people showing off who can give more away.
Let me take these one at a time.
What marks commercial exchange is that itâs âimpersonalâ: who it is that is selling something to us, or buying something from us, should in principle be entirely irrelevant. We are simply comparing the value or two objects. True, as with any principle, in practice, this is rarely completely true. There has to be some minimal element of trust for a transaction to be carried out at all, and, unless one is dealing with a vending machine, that usually requires some outward display of sociality. Even in the most impersonal shopping mall or supermarket, clerks are expected to at least simulate personal warmth, patience, and other reassuring qualities; in a Middle-Eastern bazaar, one might have to go through an elaborate process of establishing a simulated friendship, sharing tea, food, or tobacco, before engaging in similarly elaborate hagglingâan interesting ritual that begins by establishing sociality through baseline communismâand continues with an often prolonged mock battle over prices. Itâs all done on the basis of the assumption that buyer and seller are, at least at that moment, friends (and thus each entitled to feel outraged and indignant at the otherâs unreasonable demands), but itâs all a little piece of theater. Once the object changes hands, there is no expectation that the two will ever have anything to do with each other again.[172]
Most often this sort of hagglingâin Madagascar the term for it literally means âto battle out a saleâ **(miady varotra)**âcan be a source of pleasure in itself.
The first time I visited Analakely, the great cloth market in Madagascarâs capital, I came with a Malagasy friend intent on buying a sweater. The whole process took about four hours. It went something like this: my friend would spot a likely sweater hanging in some booth, ask the price, and then she would begin a prolonged battle of wits with the vendor, invariably involving dramatic displays of insult and indignation, and simulated walkings off in disgust. Often it seemed ninety percent of the argument was spent on a final, tiny difference of a few ariaryâliterally, penniesâthat seemed to become a profound matter of principle on either side, since a merchantâs failure to concede it could sink the entire deal.
The second time I visited Analakely I went with another friend, also a young woman, who had a list of measures of cloth to buy supplied by her sister. At each booth she adopted the same procedure: she simply walked up and asked for the price.
The man would quote her one.
âAll right,â she then asked, âand whatâs your real final price?â
Heâd tell her, and sheâd hand over the money.
âWait a minute!â I asked. âYou can **do** that?
âSure,â she said. âWhy not?â
I explained what had happened with my last friend.
âOh, yeah,â she said. âSome people enjoy that sort of thing.â
Exchange allows us to cancel out our debts. It gives us a way to call it even: hence, to end the relationship. With vendors, one is usually only pretending to have a relationship at all. With neighbors, one might for this very reason prefer **not** to pay oneâs debts. Laura Bohannan writes about arriving in a Tiv community in rural Nigeria; neighbors immediately began arriving bearing little gifts: âtwo ears corn, one vegetable marrow, one chicken, five tomatoes, one handful peanuts.â[173] Having no idea what was expected of her, she thanked them and wrote down in a notebook their names and what they had brought. Eventually, two women adopted her and explained that all such gifts did have to be returned. It would be entirely inappropriate to simply accept three eggs from a neighbor and never bring anything back. One did not have to bring back eggs, but one should bring something back of approximately the same value. One could even bring moneyâthere was nothing inappropriate in thatâprovided one did so at a discreet interval, and above all, that one did not bring the exact cost of the eggs. It had to be either a bit more or a bit less. To bring back nothing at all would be to cast oneself as an exploiter or a parasite. To bring back an exact equivalent would be to suggest that one no longer wishes to have anything to do with the neighbor. Tiv women, she learned, might spend a good part of the day walking for miles to distant homesteads to return a handful of okra or a tiny bit of change, âin an endless circle of gifts to which no one ever handed over the precise value of the object last receivedââand in doing so, they were continually creating their society. There was certainly a trace of communism hereâneighbors on good terms could also be trusted to help each other out in emergenciesâbut unlike communistic relations, which are assumed to be permanent, this sort of neighborliness had to be constantly created and maintained, because any link can be broken off at any time.
There are endless variations on this sort of tit-for-tat, or almost tit-for-tat, gift exchange. The most familiar is the exchange of presents: I buy someone a beer; they buy me the next one. Perfect equivalence implies equality. But consider a slightly more complicated example: I take a friend out to a fancy restaurant for dinner; after a discreet interval, they do the same. As anthropologists have long been in the habit of pointing out, the very existence of such customsâespecially, the feeling that one really **ought** to return the favorâcanât be explained by standard economic theory, which assumes that any human interaction is ultimately a business deal and that we are all self-interested individuals trying to get the most for ourselves for the least cost or least amount of effort.[174] But this feeling is quite real, and it can cause genuine strain for those of limited means trying to keep up appearances. So: Why, if I took a free-market economic theorist out to an expensive dinner, would that economist feel somewhat diminishedâuncomfortably in my debtâuntil he had been able to return the favor? Why, if he were feeling competitive with me, would he be inclined to take me to someplace even more expensive?
Recall the feasts and festivals alluded to above: here, too, there is a base of conviviality and playful (sometimes not so playful) competition. On the one hand, everyoneâs pleasure is enhancedâafter all, how many people would really want to eat a superb meal at a French restaurant all alone? On the other, things can easily slip into games of one-upmanshipâand hence obsession, humiliation, rage ⊠or, as weâll soon see, even worse. In some societies, these games are formalized, but itâs important to stress that such games only really develop between people or groups who perceive themselves to be more or less equivalent in status.[175] To return to our imaginary economist: itâs not clear that he would feel diminished if he received a present, or was taken out to dinner, by just anyone. He would be most likely to feel this way if the benefactor were someone he felt was of roughly equivalent status or dignity: a colleague, for example. If Bill Gates or George Soros took him out to dinner, he would likely conclude that he had indeed received something for nothing and leave it at that. If some ingratiating junior colleague or eager graduate student did the same, heâd be likely to conclude that he was doing the man a favor just by accepting the invitationâif indeed he did accept, which he probably wouldnât.
This, too, appears to be the case wherever we find society divided into fine gradations of status and dignity. Pierre Bourdieu has described the âdialectic of challenge and riposteâ that governs all games of honor among Kabyle Berber men in Algeria, in which the exchange of insults, attacks (in feud or battles), thefts, or threats was seen to follow exactly the same logic as the exchange of gifts.[176] To give a gift is both an honor and a provocation. To respond to one requires infinite artistry. Timing is all-important. So is making the counter-gift just different enough, but also just slightly grander. Above all is the tacit moral principle that one must always pick on someone oneâs own size. To challenge someone obviously older, richer, and more honorable is to risk being snubbed, and hence humiliated; to overwhelm a poor but respectable man with a gift he couldnât possibly pay back is simply cruel, and will do equal damage to your reputation. Thereâs an Indonesian story about that too: about a rich man who sacrificed a magnificent ox to shame a penurious rival; the poor man utterly humiliated him, and won the contest, by calmly proceeding to sacrifice a chicken.[177]
Games like this become especially elaborate when status is to some degree up for grabs. When matters are **too** clear-cut, that introduces its own sorts of problems. Giving gifts to kings is often a particularly tricky and complicated business. The problem here is that one cannot really give a gift fit for a king (unless, perhaps, one is another king), since kings by definition already have everything. On the one hand, one is expected to make a reasonable effort:
Nasruddin was once called up to visit the king. A neighbor saw him hurrying along the road carrying a bag of turnips.
âWhat are those for?â he asked.
âIâve been called to see the king. I thought it would be best to bring some kind of present.â
âYouâre bringing him turnips? But turnips are peasant food! Heâs a king! You should bring him something more appropriate, like grapes.â
Nasruddin agreed, and came to the king carrying a bunch of grapes. The king was not amused. âYouâre giving me grapes? But Iâm a king! This is ridiculous. Take this idiot out and teach him some manners! Throw each and every one of the grapes at him and then kick him out of the palace.â
The emperorâs guards dragged Nasruddin into a side room and began pelting him with grapes. As they did so, he fell on his knees and began crying, âThank you, thank you God, for your infinite mercy!â
âWhy are you thanking God?â they asked. âYouâre being totally humiliated!â
Nasruddin replied, âOh, I was just thinking, âThank God I didnât bring the turnips!â â
On the other hand, to give something that a king does not already have can get you in even greater trouble. One story circulating in the early Roman Empire concerned an inventor who, with great fanfare, presented a glass bowl as a gift to the emperor Tiberius. The emperor was puzzled: What was so impressive about a piece of glass? The man dropped it on the ground. Rather than shattering, it merely dented. He picked it up and simply pushed it back into its former shape.
âDid you tell anyone else how you made this thing?â asked a startled Tiberius.
The inventor assured him that he had not. The emperor therefore ordered him killed, since, if word of how to make unbreakable glass got out, his treasury of gold and silver would soon be worthless.[178]
The best bet when dealing with kings was to make a reasonable effort to play the game, but one that is still bound to fail. The fourteenth-century Arab traveler Ibn Battuta tells of the customs of the King of Sind, a terrifying monarch who took a particular delight in displays of arbitrary power.[179] It was customary for foreign worthies visiting the king to present him with magnificent presents; whatever the gift was, he would invariably respond by presenting the bearer with something many times its value. As a result, a substantial business developed where local bankers would lend money to such visitors to finance particularly spectacular gifts, knowing they could be well repaid from the proceeds of royal one-upmanship. The king must have known about this. He didnât objectâsince the whole point was to show that his wealth exceeded all possible equivalenceâand if he really needed to, he could always expropriate the bankers. They knew that the really important game was not economic, but one of status, and his was absolute.
In exchange, the objects being traded are seen as equivalent. Therefore, by implication, so are the people: at least, at the moment when gift is met with counter-gift, or money changes hands; when there is no further debt or obligation and each of the two parties is equally free to walk away. This in turn implies autonomy. Both principles sit uncomfortably with monarchs, which is the reason that kings generally dislike any sort of exchange.[180] But within that overhanging prospect of potential cancellation, of ultimate equivalence, we find endless variations, endless games one can play. One can demand something from another person, knowing that by doing so, one is giving the other the right to demand something of equivalent value in return. In some contexts, even praising anotherâs possession might be interpreted as a demand of this sort. In eighteenth-century New Zealand, English settlers soon learned that it was not a good idea to admire, say, a particularly beautiful jade pendant worn around the neck of a Maori warrior; the latter would inevitably insist on giving it, not take no for an answer, and then, after a discreet interval, return to praise the settlerâs coat or gun. The only way to head this off was to quickly give him a gift before he could ask for one. Sometimes gifts are offered in order for the giver to be able to make such a demand: if one accepts the present, one is tacitly agreeing to allow the giver to claim whatever he deems equivalent.[181]
All this, in turn, can shade into something very much like barter, directly swapping one thing for anotherâwhich as weâve seen does occur even in what Marcel Mauss liked to refer to as âgift economies,â even if largely between strangers.[182] Within communities, there is almost always a reluctance, as the Tiv example so nicely illustrates, to allow things to cancel outâone reason that if there is money in common usage, people will often either refuse to use it with friends or relatives (which in a village society includes pretty much everyone), or alternately, like the Malagasy villagers in chapter 3, use it in radically different ways.
Exchange, then, implies formal equalityâor at least, the potential for it. This is precisely why kings have such trouble with it.
In contrast, relations of explicit hierarchyâthat is, relations between at least two parties in which one is considered superior to the otherâdo not tend to operate by reciprocity at all. Itâs hard to see because the relation is often justified in reciprocal terms (âthe peasants provide food, the lords provide protectionâ), but the principle by which they operate is exactly the opposite. In practice, hierarchy tends to work by a logic of precedent.
To illustrate what I mean by this, let us imagine a kind of continuum of one-sided social relations, ranging from the most exploitative to the most benevolent. At one extreme is theft, or plunder; on the other selfless charity.[183] Only at these two extremes is it is possible to have material interactions between people who otherwise have no social relation of any kind. Only a lunatic would mug his next-door neighbor. A band of marauding soldiers or nomadic horsemen falling on a peasant hamlet to rape and pillage also obviously have no intention of forming any ongoing relations with the survivors. But in a similar way, religious traditions often insist that the only true charity is anonymousâin other words, not meant to place the recipient in oneâs debt. One extreme form of this, documented in various parts of the world, is the gift by stealth, in a kind of reverse burglary: to literally sneak into the recipientâs house at night and plant oneâs present so no one can know for sure who has left it. The figure of Santa Claus, or Saint Nicholas (who, it must be remembered, was not just the patron saint of children, but also the patron saint of thieves) would appear to be the mythological version of the same principle: a benevolent burglar with whom no social relations are possible and therefore to whom no one could possibly owe anything, in his case, above all, because he does not actually exist.
Observe, however, what happens when one moves just a little bit less far out on the continuum in either direction. I have been told (I suspect it isnât true) that in parts of Belarus, gangs prey so systematically on travelers on trains and busses that they have developed the habit of giving each victim a little token, to confirm that the bearer has already been robbed. Obviously one step toward the creation of a state. Actually, one popular theory of the origins of the state, that goes back at least to the fourteenth-century North African historian Ibn Khaldun, runs precisely along these lines: nomadic raiders eventually systematize their relations with sedentary villagers; pillage turns into tribute, rape turns into the âright of the first nightâ or the carrying off of likely candidates as recruits for the royal harem. Conquest, untrammeled force, becomes systematized, and thus framed not as a predatory relation but as a moral one, with the lords providing protection, and the villagers, their sustenance. But even if all parties assume they are operating by a shared moral code, that even kings cannot do whatever they want but must operate within limits, allowing peasants to argue about the rights and wrongs of just how much of their harvest a kingâs retainers are entitled to carry off, they are very unlikely to frame their calculation in terms of the quality or quantity of protection provided, but rather in terms of custom and precedent: How much did we pay last year? How much did our ancestors have to pay? The same is true on the other side. If charitable donations become the basis for any sort of social relation, it will not be one based on reciprocity. If you give some coins to a panhandler, and that panhandler recognizes you later, it is unlikely that he will give you any moneyâbut he might well consider you more likely to give him money again. Certainly this is true if one donates money to a charitable organization. (I gave money to the United Farm Workers once and I still havenât heard the end of it.) Such an act of one-sided generosity is treated as a precedent for what will be expected afterward.[184] Itâs quite the same if one gives candy to a child.
This is what I mean when I say that hierarchy operates by a principle that is the very opposite of reciprocity. Whenever the lines of superiority and inferiority are clearly drawn and accepted by all parties as the framework of a relationship, and relations are sufficiently ongoing that we are no longer simply dealing with arbitrary force, then relations will be seen as being regulated by a web of habit or custom. Sometimes the situation is assumed to have originated in some founding act of conquest. Or it might been seen as ancestral custom for which there is no need of explanation. But this introduces another complication to the problem of giving gifts to kingsâor to any superior: there is always the danger that it will be treated as a precedent, added to the web of custom, and therefore considered obligatory thereafter. Xenophon claims that in the early days of the Persian Empire, each province vied to send the Great King gifts of its most unique and valuable products. This became the basis of the tribute system: each province was eventually expected to provide the same âgiftsâ every year.[185] Similarly, according to the great Medieval historian Marc Bloch:
[I]n the ninth century, when one day there was a shortage of wine in the royal cellars at Ver, the monks of Saint-Denis were asked to supply the two hundred hogs-heads required. This contribution was thenceforth claimed from them as of right every year, and it required an imperial charter to abolish it. At Ardres, we are told, there was once a bear, the property of the local lord. The inhabitants, who loved to watch it fight with dogs, undertook to feed it. The beast eventually died, but the lord continued to exact the loaves of bread.â[186]
In other words, any gift to a feudal superior, âespecially if repeated three of four times,â was likely to be treated as a precedent and added to the web of custom. As a result, those giving gifts to superiors often insisted on receiving a âletter of non-prejudiceâ legally stipulating that such a gift would not be required in the future. While it is unusual for matters to become quite so formalized, any social relation that is assumed from the start to be unequal will inevitably begin to operate on an analogous logicâif only because, once relations are seen as based on âcustom,â the only way to demonstrate that one has a duty or obligation to do something is to show that one has done it before.
Often, such arrangements can turn into a logic of caste: certain clans are responsible for weaving the ceremonial garments, or bringing the fish for royal feasts, or cutting the kingâs hair. They thus come to be known as weavers or fishermen or barbers.[187] This last point canât be overemphasized because it brings home another truth regularly overlooked: that the logic of identity is, always and everywhere, entangled in the logic of hierarchy. It is only when certain people are placed above others, or where everyone is being ranked in relation to the king, or the high priest, or Founding Fathers, that one begins to speak of people bound by their essential nature: about fundamentally different kinds of human being. Ideologies of caste or race are just extreme examples. It happens whenever one group is seen as raising themselves above others, or placing themselves below others, in such a way that ordinary standards of fair dealing no longer apply.
In fact, something like this happens in a small way even in our most intimate social relations. The moment we recognize someone as a different **sort** of person, either above or below us, then ordinary rules of reciprocity become modified or are set aside. If a friend is unusually generous once, we will likely wish to reciprocate. If she acts this way repeatedly, we conclude she is a generous person, and are hence less likely to reciprocate.[188]
We can describe a simple formula here: a certain action, repeated, becomes customary; as a result, it comes to define the actorâs essential nature. Alternately, a personâs nature may be defined by how others have acted toward him in the past. To be an aristocrat is largely to insist that in the past, others have **treated** you as an aristocrat (since aristocrats donât really do anything in particular, most spend their time simply existing in some sort of putatively superior state), and therefore should continue to do so. Much of the art of being such a person is that of treating oneself in such a manner that it conveys how you expect others to treat you: in the case of actual kings, covering oneself with gold so as to suggest that others do likewise. On the other end of the scale, this is also how abuse becomes self-legitimating. As a former student of mine, Sarah Stillman, pointed out: in the United States, if a middle-class thirteen-year-old girl is kidnapped, raped, and killed, it is considered an agonizing national crisis that everyone with a television is expected to follow for several weeks. If a thirteen-year-old girl is turned out as a child prostitute, raped systematically for years, and ultimately killed, all this is considered unremarkableâreally just the sort of thing one can expect to end up happening to someone like that.[189]
When objects of material wealth pass back and forth between superiors and inferiors as gifts or payments, the key principle seems to be that the sorts of things given on each side should be considered fundamentally different in quality, their relative value impossible to quantifyâthe result being that there is no way to even conceive of a squaring of accounts. Even if Medieval writers insisted on imagining society as a hierarchy in which priests pray for everyone, nobles fight for everyone, and peasants feed everyone, it never even occurred to anyone to establish how many prayers or how much military protection was equivalent to a ton of wheat. Nor did anyone ever consider making such a calculation. Neither is it that âlowlyâ sorts of people are necessarily given lowly sorts of things and vice versa. Sometimes it is quite the opposite. Until recently, just about any notable philosopher, artist, poet, or musician was required to find a wealthy patron for support. Famous works of poetry or philosophy are often prefacedâoddly, to the modern eyeâwith gushing, sycophantic praise for the wisdom and virtue of some long-forgotten earl or count who provided a meager stipend. The fact that the noble patron merely provided room and board, or money, and that the client showed his gratitude by painting the **Mona Lisa**, or composing the **Toccata and Fugue in D Minor**, was in no way seen to compromise the assumption of the nobleâs intrinsic superiority.
There is one great exception to this principle, and that is the phenomenon of hierarchical redistribution. Here, though, rather than giving back and forth the same sorts of things, they give back and forth **exactly** the same thing: as, for instance, when fans of certain Nigerian pop stars throw money onto the stage during concerts, and the pop stars in question make occasional tours of their fansâ neighborhoods tossing (the same) money from the windows of their limos. When this is all thatâs going on, we may speak of an absolutely minimal sort of hierarchy. In much of Papua New Guinea, social life centers on âbig men,â charismatic individuals who spend much of their time coaxing, cajoling, and manipulating in order to acquire masses of wealth to give away again at some great feast. One could, in practice, pass from here to, say, an Amazonian or indigenous North American chief. Unlike big men, their role is more formalized; but actually such chiefs have no power to compel anyone to do anything they donât want to (hence North American Indian chiefsâ famous skill at oratory and powers of persuasion). As a result, they tended to give away far more than they received. Observers often remarked that in terms of personal possessions, a village chief was often the poorest man in the village, such was the pressure on him for constant supply of largesse.
Indeed, one could judge how egalitarian a society really was by exactly this: whether those ostensibly in positions of authority are merely conduits for redistribution, or able to use their positions to accumulate riches. The latter seems most likely in aristocratic societies that add another element: war and plunder. After all, just about anyone who comes into a very large amount of wealth will ultimately give at least part of it awayâoften in grandiose and spectacular ways to large numbers of people. The more of oneâs wealth is obtained by plunder or extortion, the more spectacular and self-aggrandizing will be the forms in which itâs given away.[190] And what is true of warrior aristocracies is all the more true of ancient states, where rulers almost invariably represented themselves as the protectors of the helpless, supporters of widows and orphans, and champions of the poor. The genealogy of the modern redistributive stateâwith its notorious tendency to foster identity politicsâcan be traced back not to any sort of âprimitive communismâ but ultimately to violence and war.
I should underline again that we are not talking about different types of society here (as weâve seen, the very idea that weâve ever been organized into discrete âsocietiesâ is dubious) but moral principles that always coexist everywhere. We are all communists with our closest friends, and feudal lords when dealing with small children. It is very hard to imagine a society where people wouldnât be both.
The obvious question is: If we are all ordinarily moving back and forth between completely different systems of moral accounting, why hasnât anybody noticed this? Why, instead, do we continually feel the need to reframe everything in terms of reciprocity?
Here we must return to the fact that reciprocity is our main way of imagining justice. In particular, it is what we fall back on when weâre thinking in the abstract, and especially when weâre trying to create an idealized picture of society. Iâve already given examples of this sort of thing. Iroquois communities were based on an ethos that required everyone to be attentive to the needs of several different sorts of people: their friends, their families, members of their matrilineal clans, even friendly strangers in situations of hardship. It was when they had to think about society in the abstract that they started to emphasize the two sides of the village, each of which had to bury the otherâs dead. It was a way of imagining communism through reciprocity. Similarly, feudalism was a notoriously messy and complicated business, but whenever Medieval thinkers generalized about it, they reduced all its ranks and orders into one simple formula in which each order contributed its share: âSome pray, some fight, still others work.â[191] Even hierarchy was seen as ultimately reciprocal, despite this formula having nothing to do with the real relations between priests, knights, and peasants really operated on the ground. Anthropologists are familiar with the phenomenon: itâs only when people who have never had occasion to really think about their society or culture as a whole, who probably werenât even aware they were living inside something other people considered a âsocietyâ or a âculture,â are asked to explain how everything works that they say things like âthis is how we repay our mothers for the pain of having raised us,â or puzzle over conceptual diagrams in which clan A gives their women in marriage to clan B who gives theirs to clan C, who gives theirs back to A again, but which never seem to quite correspond to what real people actually do.[192] When trying to imagine a just society, itâs hard not to evoke images of balance and symmetry, of elegant geometries where everything balances out.
The idea that there is something called âthe marketâ is not so very different. Economists will often admit this, if you ask them in the right way. Markets arenât real. They are mathematical models, created by imagining a self-contained world where everyone has exactly the same motivation and the same knowledge and is engaging in the same self-interested calculating exchange. Economists are aware that reality is always more complicated; but they are also aware that to come up with a mathematical model, one always has to make the world into a bit of a cartoon. Thereâs nothing wrong with this. The problem comes when it enables some (often these same economists) to declare that anyone who ignores the dictates of the market shall surely be punishedâor that since we live in a market system, everything (except government interference) is based on principles of justice: that our economic system is one vast network of reciprocal relations in which, in the end, the accounts balance and all debts are paid.
These principles get tangled up in each other and itâs thus often difficult to tell which predominates in a given situationâone reason that itâs ridiculous to pretend we could ever reduce human behavior, economic or otherwise, to a mathematical formula of any sort. Still, this means that some degree of reciprocity can be detected as potentially present in any situation; so a determined observer can always find some excuse to say itâs there. Whatâs more, certain principles appear to have an inherent tendency to slip into others. For instance, a lot of extremely hierarchical relationships can operate (at least some of the time) on communistic principles. If you have a rich patron, you come to him in times of need, and he is expected to help you. But only to a certain degree. No one expects the patron to provide so much help that it threatens to undermine the underlying inequality.[193]
Likewise, communistic relations can easily start slipping into relations of hierarchical inequalityâoften without anyone noticing it. Itâs not hard to see why this happens. Sometimes different peopleâs âabilitiesâ and âneedsâ are grossly disproportionate. Genuinely egalitarian societies are keenly aware of this and tend to develop elaborate safeguards around the dangers of anyoneâsay, especially good hunters, in a hunting societyârising too far above themselves; just as they tend to be suspicious of anything that might make one member of the society feel in genuine debt to another. A member who draws attention to his own accomplishments will find himself the object of mockery. Often, the only polite thing to do if one has accomplished something significant is to instead make fun of oneself. The Danish writer Peter Freuchen, in his **Book of the Eskimo**, described how in Greenland, one could tell what a fine delicacy someone had to offer his guests by how much he belittled it beforehand:
The old man laughed. âSome people donât know much. I am such a poor hunter and my wife a terrible cook who ruins everything. I donât have much, but I think there is a piece of meat outside. It might still be there as the dogs have refused it several times.â
This was such a recommendation in the Eskimo way of backwards bragging that everyoneâs mouths began to water âŠ
The reader will recall the walrus hunter of the last chapter, who took offense when the author tried to thank him for giving him a share of meatâafter all, humans help one another, and once we treat something as a gift, we turn into something less than human: âUp here we say that by gifts one makes slaves and by whips one makes dogs.â[194]
âGiftâ here does **not** mean something given freely, not mutual aid that we can ordinarily expect human beings to provide to one another. To thank someone suggests that he or she might **not** have acted that way, and that therefore the choice to act this way creates an obligation, a sense of debtâand hence, inferiority. Communes or egalitarian collectives in the United States often face similar dilemmas, and they have to come up with their own safeguards against creeping hierarchy. Itâs not that the tendency for communism to slip into hierarchy is inevitableâsocieties like the Inuit have managed to fend it off for thousands of yearsâbut rather, that one must always guard against it.
In contrast, itâs notoriously difficultâoften downright impossibleâto shift relations based on an assumption of communistic sharing to relations of equal exchange. We observe this all the time with friends: if someone is seen as taking advantage of your generosity, itâs often much easier to break off relations entirely than to demand that they somehow pay you back. One extreme example is the Maori story about a notorious glutton who used to irritate fishermen up and down the coast near where he lived by constantly asking for the best portions of their catch. Since to refuse a direct request for food was effectively impossible, they would dutifully turn it over; until one day, people decided enough was enough and killed him.[195]
Weâve already seen how creating a ground of sociability among strangers can often require an elaborate process of testing the othersâ limits by helping oneself to their possessions. The same sort of thing can happen in peacemaking, or even in the creation of business partnerships.[196] In Madagascar, people told me that two men who are thinking of going into business together will often become blood brothers. Blood brotherhood, **fatidra**, consists of an unlimited promise of mutual aid. Both parties solemnly swear that they will never refuse any request from the other. In reality, partners to such an agreement are usually fairly circumspect in what they actually request. But, my friends insisted, when people first make such an agreement, they sometimes like to test it out. One may demand the otherâs house, the shirt off his back, or (everyoneâs favorite example) the right to spend the night with his wife. The only limit is the knowledge that anything one can demand, the other one can too.[197] Here, again, we are talking about an initial establishment of trust. Once the genuineness of the mutual commitment has been confirmed, the ground is prepared, as it were, and the two men can begin to buy and sell on consignment, advance funds, share profits, and otherwise trust that each will look after the otherâs commercial interests from then on. The most famous and dramatic moments, however, are those when relations of exchange threaten to break down into hierarchy: that is, when two parties are acting like equals, trading gifts, or blows, or commodities, or anything else, but one of them does something that completely flips the scale.
Iâve already mentioned the tendency of gift exchange to turn into games of one-upmanship, and how in some societies this potential is formalized in great public contests. This is typical, above all, of what are often called âheroic societiesâ: those in which governments are weak or nonexistent and society is organized instead around warrior noblemen, each with his entourage of loyal retainers and tied to the others by ever-shifting alliances and rivalries. Most epic poetryâfrom the **Iliad** to the **Mahabharata** to **Beowulf**âharkens back to this sort of world, and anthropologists have discovered similar arrangements among the Maori of New Zealand and the Kwakiutl, Tlingit, and Haida of the American Northwest coast. In heroic societies, the throwing of feasts and resulting contests of generosity are often spoken of as mere extensions of war: âfighting with propertyâ or âfighting with food.â Those who throw such feasts often indulge in colorful speeches about how their enemies are thus crushed and destroyed by glorious feats of generosity aimed in their direction (Kwakiutl chiefs liked to speak of themselves as great mountains from which gifts rolled like giant boulders), and of how conquered rivals are thus reducedâmuch as in the Inuit metaphorâto slaves.
Such statements are not to be taken literallyâanother feature of such societies is a highly developed art of boasting.[198] Heroic chiefs and warriors tended to talk themselves up just as consistently as those in egalitarian societies talked themselves down. Itâs not as if someone who loses out in a contest of gift exchange is ever actually reduced to slavery, but he might end up feeling as if he were. And the consequences could be catastrophic. One ancient Greek source describes Celtic festivals where rival nobles would alternate between jousts and contests of generosity, presenting their enemies with magnificent gold and silver treasures. Occasionally this could lead to a kind of checkmate; someone would be faced with a present so magnificent that he could not possibly match it. In this case, the only honorable response was for him to cut his own throat, thus allowing his wealth to be distributed to his followers.[199] Six hundred years later, we find a case from an Icelandic saga of an aging Viking named Egil, who befriended a younger man named Einar, who was still actively raiding. They liked to sit together composing poetry. One day Einar came by a magnificent shield âinscribed with old tales; and between the writing were overlaid spangles of gold with precious stones.â No one had ever seen anything like it. He took it with him on a visit to Egil. Egil was not at home, so Einar waited three days, as was the custom, then hung the shield as a present in the mead-hall and rode off.
Egil returned home, saw the shield, and asked who owned such a treasure. He was told that Einar had visited and given it to him. Then Egil said, âTo hell with him! Does he think Iâm going to stay up all night and compose a poem about his shield? Get my horse, Iâm going to ride after him and kill him.â As Einarâs luck would have it he had left early enough to put sufficient distance between himself and Egil. So Egil resigned himself to composing a poem about Einarâs gift.[200]
Competitive gift exchange, then, does not literally render anyone slaves; it is simply an affair of honor. These are people, however, for whom honor is everything.
The main reason that being unable to pay a debt, especially a debt of honor, was such a crisis was because this **was** how noblemen assembled their entourages. The law of hospitality in the ancient world, for instance, insisted that any traveler must be fed, given shelter, and treated as an honored guestâbut only for a certain length of time. If a guest did not go away, he would eventually become a mere subordinate. The role of such hangers-on has been largely neglected by students of human history. In many periodsâfrom imperial Rome to medieval Chinaâprobably the most important relationships, at least in towns and cities, were those of patronage. Anyone rich and important would find himself surrounded by flunkies, sycophants, perpetual dinner guests, and other sorts of willing dependents. Drama and poetry of the time are full of such characters.[201] Similarly, for much of human history, being respectable and middle-class meant spending oneâs mornings going from door to door, paying oneâs respects to important local patrons. To this day, informal patronage systems still crop up, whenever relatively rich and powerful people feel the need to assemble networks of supportersâa practice well documented in many parts of the Mediterranean, the Middle East, and Latin America. Such relationships seem to consist of a slapdash mix of all three principles that Iâve been mapping out over the course of this chapter; nevertheless, those observing them insist on trying to cast them in the language of exchange and debt.
A final example: in a collection called **Gifts and Spoils**, published in 1971, we find a brief essay by the anthropologist Lorraine Blaxter about a rural department in the French Pyrenees, most of whose inhabitants are farmers. Everyone places a great emphasis on the importance of mutual aidâthe local phrase means âgiving serviceâ **(rendre service)**. People living in the same community should look out for one another and pitch in when their neighbors are having trouble. This is the essence of communal morality, in fact, itâs how one knows that any sort of community exists. So far so good. However, she notes, when someone does a particularly great favor, mutual aid can turn into something else:
If a man in a factory went to the boss and asked for a job, and the boss found him one, this would be an example of someone giving service. The man who got the job could never repay the boss, but he could show him respect, or perhaps give him symbolic gifts of garden produce. If a gift demands a return, and no tangible return is possible, the repayment will be through support or esteem.[202]
Thus does mutual aid slip into inequality. Thus do patron-client relations come into being. We have already observed this. I chose this particular passage because the authorâs phrasing is so weird. It completely contradicts itself. The boss does the man a favor. The man cannot repay the favor. Therefore, the man repays the favor by showing up at the bossâs house with the occasional basket of tomatoes and showing him respect. So which one is it? Can he repay the favor, or not?
Peter Freuchenâs walrus hunter would, no doubt, think he knew exactly what was going on here. Bringing the basket of tomatoes was simply the equivalent of saying âThank you.â It was a way of acknowledging that one owes a debt of gratitude, that gifts had in fact made slaves just as whips make dogs. The boss and the employee are now fundamentally different sorts of people. The problem is that in all other respects, they are not fundamentally different sorts of people. Most likely they are both middle-aged Frenchmen, fathers of families, citizens of the Republic with similar tastes in music, sports, and food. They **ought** to be equals. As a result, even the tomatoes, which are really a token of recognition of the existence of a debt that can never be repaid, has to be represented as if it was itself a kind of repaymentâan interest payment on a loan that could, everyone agrees to pretend, someday be paid back, thus returning the two members to their proper equal status once again.[203]
(Itâs telling that the favor is finding the client a job in a factory, because what happens is not very different from what happens when you get a job in a factory to begin with. A wage-labor contract is, ostensibly, a free contract between equalsâbut an agreement between equals in which both agree that once one of them punches the time clock, they wonât be equals any more.[204] The law does recognize a bit of a problem here; thatâs why it insists that you cannot sell off your equality permanently [you are not free to sell yourself into slavery]. Such arrangements are only acceptable if the bossâs power is not absolute, if it is limited to work time, and if you have the legal right to break off the contract and thereby to restore yourself to full equality, at any time.)
It seems to me that this agreement between equals to no longer be equal (at least for a time) is critically important. It is the very essence of what we call âdebt.â
What, then, is debt?
Debt is a very specific thing, and it arises from very specific situations. It first requires a relationship between two people who do not consider each other fundamentally different sorts of being, who are at least potential equals, who **are** equals in those ways that are really important, and who are not currently in a state of equalityâbut for whom there is some way to set matters straight.
In the case of gift-giving, as weâve seen, this requires a certain equality of status. Thatâs why our economics professor didnât feel any sense of obligationâany debt of honorâif taken out to dinner by someone who ranked either much higher or much lower than himself. With money loans, all that is required is that the two parties be of equal legal standing. (You canât lend money to a child, or to a lunatic. Well, you can, but the courts wonât help you get it back.) Legalârather than moralâdebts have other unique qualities. For instance, they can be forgiven, which isnât always possible with a moral debt.
This means that there is no such thing as a genuinely unpayable debt. If there was no conceivable way to salvage the situation, we wouldnât be calling it a âdebt.â Even the French villager could, conceivably, save his patronâs life, or win the lottery and buy the factory. Even when we speak of a criminal âpaying his debt to society,â we are saying that he has done something so terrible that he has now been banished from that equal status under the law that belongs by natural right to any citizen of his country; however, we call it a âdebtâ because it **can** be paid, equality **can** be restored, even if the cost may be death by lethal injection.
During the time that the debt remains unpaid, the logic of hierarchy takes hold. There is no reciprocity. As anyone who has ever been in jail knows, the first thing the jailors communicate is that nothing that happens in jail has anything to do with justice. Similarly, debtor and creditor confront each other like a peasant before a feudal lord. The law of precedent takes hold. If you bring your creditor tomatoes from the garden, it never occurs to you that he would give something back. He might expect you to do it again, though. But always there is the assumption that the situation is somewhat unnatural, because the debt really ought to be paid.
This is what makes situations of effectively unpayable debt so difficult and so painful. Since creditor and debtor are ultimately equals, if the debtor cannot do what it takes to restore herself to equality, there is obviously something wrong with her; it must be her fault.
This connection becomes clear if we look at the etymology of common words for âdebtâ in European languages. Many are synonyms for âfault,â âsin,â or âguilt;â just as a criminal owes a debt to society, a debtor is always a sort of criminal.[205] In ancient Crete, according to Plutarch, it was the custom for those taking loans to pretend to snatch the money from the lenderâs purse. Why, he wondered? Probably âso that, if they default, they could be charged with violence and punished all the more.â[206] This is why in so many periods of history insolvent debtors could be jailed, or evenâas in early Republican Romeâexecuted.
A debt, then, is just an exchange that has not been brought to completion.
It follows that debt is strictly a creature of reciprocity and has little to do with other sorts of morality (communism, with its needs and abilities; hierarchy, with its customs and qualities). True, if we were really determined, we could argue (as some do) that communism is a condition of permanent mutual indebtedness, or that hierarchy is constructed out of unpayable debts. But isnât this just the same old story, starting from the assumption that all human interactions must be, by definition, forms of exchange, and then performing whatever mental somersaults are required to prove it?
No. All human interactions are not forms of exchange. Only some are. Exchange encourages a particular way of conceiving human relations. This is because exchange implies equality, but it also implies separation. Itâs precisely when the money changes hands, when the debt is cancelled, that equality is restored **and** both parties can walk away and have nothing further to do with each other.
Debt is what happens in between: when the two parties cannot yet walk away from each other, because they are not yet equal. But it is carried out in the shadow of eventual equality. Because achieving that equality, however, destroys the very reason for having a relationship, just about everything interesting happens in between.[207] In fact, just about everything human happens in betweenâeven if this means that all such human relations bear with them at least a tiny element of criminality, guilt, or shame.
For the Tiv women whom I mentioned earlier in the chapter, this wasnât much of a problem. By ensuring that everyone was always slightly in debt to one another, they actually created human society, if a very fragile sort of societyâa delicate web made up of obligations to return three eggs or a bag of okra, ties renewed and recreated, as any one of them could be cancelled out at any time.
Our own habits of civility are not so very different. Consider the custom, in American society, of constantly saying âpleaseâ and âthank you.â To do so is often treated as basic morality: we are constantly chiding children for forgetting to do it, just as the moral guardians of our societyâteachers and ministers, for instanceâdo to everybody else. We often assume that the habit is universal, but as the Inuit hunter made clear, it is not.[208] Like so many of our everyday courtesies, it is a kind of democratization of what was once a habit of feudal deference: the insistence on treating absolutely everyone the way that one used only to have to treat a lord or similar hierarchical superior.
Perhaps this is not so in every case. Imagine we are on a crowded bus, looking for a seat. A fellow passenger moves her bag aside to clear one; we smile, or nod, or make some other little gesture of acknowledgment. Or perhaps we actually say âThank you.â Such a gesture is simply a recognition of common humanity: we are acknowledging that the woman who had been blocking the seat is not a mere physical obstacle but a human being, and that we feel genuine gratitude toward someone we will likely never see again. None of this is generally true when one asks someone across the table to âplease pass the salt,â or when the postman thanks you for signing for a delivery. We think of these simultaneously as meaningless formalities and as the very moral basis of society. Their apparent unimportance can be measured by the fact that almost no one would refuse, on principle, to say âpleaseâ or âthank youâ in just about any situationâeven those who might find it almost impossible to say âIâm sorryâ or âI apologize.â
In fact, the English âpleaseâ is short for âif you please,â âif it pleases you to do thisââit is the same in most European languages (French **si il vous plait**, Spanish **por favor**). Its literal meaning is âyou are under no obligation to do this.â âHand me the salt. Not that I am saying that you have to!â This is not true; there is a social obligation, and it would be almost impossible not to comply. But etiquette largely consists of the exchange of polite fictions (to use less polite language, lies). When you ask someone to pass the salt, you are also giving them an order; by attaching the word âplease,â you are saying that it is not an order. But, in fact, it is.
In English, âthank youâ derives from âthink,â it originally meant, âI will remember what you did for meââwhich is usually not true eitherâbut in other languages (the Portuguese **obrigado** is a good example) the standard term follows the form of the English âmuch obligedââit actually does means âI am in your debt.â The French **merci** is even more graphic: it derives from âmercy,â as in begging for mercy; by saying it you are symbolically placing yourself in your benefactorâs powerâsince a debtor is, after all, a criminal.[209] Saying âyouâre welcome,â or âitâs nothingâ (French **de rien**, Spanish **de nada**)âthe latter has at least the advantage of often being literally trueâis a way of reassuring the one to whom one has passed the salt that you are not actually inscribing a debit in your imaginary moral account book. So is saying âmy pleasureââyou are saying, âNo, actually, itâs a credit, not a debitâyou did **me** a favor because in asking me to pass the salt, you gave me the opportunity to do something I found rewarding in itself!â[210]
Decoding the tacit calculus of debt (âI owe you one,â âNo, you donât owe me anything,â âActually, if anything, itâs me who owes you,â as if inscribing and then scratching off so many infinitesimal entries in an endless ledger) makes it easy to understand why this sort of thing is often viewed not as the quintessence of morality, but as the quintessence of **middle-class** morality. True, by now middle-class sensibilities dominate society. But there are still those who find the practice odd. Those at the very top of society often still feel that deference is owed primarily to hierarchical superiors and find it slightly idiotic to watch postmen and pastry cooks taking turns pretending to treat each other like little feudal lords. At the other extreme, those who grew up in what in Europe are called âpopularâ environmentsâsmall towns, poor neighborhoods, anyplace where there is still an assumption that people who are not enemies will, ordinarily, take care of one anotherâwill often find it insulting to be constantly told, in effect, that there is some chance they might **not** do their job as a waiter or taxi driver correctly, or provide houseguests with tea. In other words, middle-class etiquette insists that we are all equals, but it does so in a very particular way. On the one hand, it pretends that nobody is giving anybody orders (think here of the burly security guard at the mall who appears before someone walking into a restricted area and says, âCan I help you?â); on the other, it treats every gesture of what Iâve been calling âbaseline communismâ as if it were really a form of exchange. As a result, like Tiv neighborhoods, middle-class society has to be endlessly recreated, as a kind of constant flickering game of shadows, the criss-crossing of an infinity of momentary debt relations, each one almost instantly cancelled out.
All of this is a relatively recent innovation. The habit of always saying âpleaseâ and âthank youâ first began to take hold during the commercial revolution of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuriesâamong those very middle classes who were largely responsible for it. It is the language of bureaus, shops, and offices, and over the course of the last five hundred years it has spread across the world along with them. It is also merely one token of a much larger philosophy, a set of assumptions of what humans are and what they owe one another, that have by now become so deeply ingrained that we cannot see them.
Sometimes, at the brink of a new historical era, some prescient soul can see the full implications of what is beginning to happenâsometimes in a way that later generations canât. Let me end with a text by such a person. In Paris, sometime in 1540s, François Rabelaisâlapsed monk, doctor, legal scholarâcomposed what was to become a famous mock eulogy, which he inserted in the third book of his great **Gargantua and Pantagruel**, and which came to be known as âIn Praise of Debt.â
Rabelais places the encomium in the mouth of one Panurge, a wandering scholar and man of extreme classical erudition who, he observes, âknew sixty-three ways of making moneyâthe most honorable and most routine of which was stealing.â[211] The good-natured giant Pantagruel adopts Panurge and even provides him with a respectable income, but it bothers him that Panurge continues to spend money like water and remains up to his ears in debt. Wouldnât it be better, Pantagruel suggests, to be able to pay his creditors?
Panurge responds with horror: âGod forbid that I should ever be out of debt!â Debt is, in fact, the very basis of his philosophy:
Always owe somebody something, then he will be forever praying God to grant you a good, long and blessed life. Fearing to lose what you owe him, he will always be saying good things about you in every sort of company; he will be constantly acquiring new lenders for you, so that you can borrow to pay him back, filling his ditch with other menâs spoil.[212]
Above all else, they will always be praying that you come into money. Itâs like those ancient slaves destined to be sacrificed at their mastersâ funerals. When they wished their master long life and good health, they genuinely meant it! Whatâs more, debt can make you into a kind of god, who can make something (money, well-wishing creditors) out of absolutely nothing.
Worse still: I give myself to bonnie Saint Bobelin if all my life I have not reckoned debts to be, as it were, a connection and colligation between Heaven and Earth (uniquely preserving the lineage of Man without which, I say, all human beings would soon perish) and perhaps to be that great World Soul which, according to the Academics, gives life to all things.
That it really is so, evoke tranquilly in your mind the Idea and Form of a worldâtake if you like the thirtieth of the worlds imagined by Metrodorusâin which there were no debtors or lenders at all. A universe sans debts! Amongst the heavenly bodies there would be no regular course whatsoever: all would be in disarray. Jupiter, reckoning that he owed no debt to Saturn, would dispossess him of his sphere, and with his Homeric chain hold in suspension all the Intelligences, gods, heavens, daemons, geniuses, heroes, devils, earth, sea and all the elements ⊠The Moon would remain dark and bloody; why should the Sun share his light with her? He is under no obligation. The Sun would never shine on their Earth; the heavenly bodies would pour no good influences down upon it.
Between the elements there will be no mutual sharing of qualities, no alternation, no transmutation whatsoever, one will not think itself obliged to the other; it has lent it nothing. From earth no longer will water be made, nor water transmuted into air; from air fire will not be made, and fire will not warm the earth. Earth will bring forth nothing but monsters, Titans, giants. The rain will not rain, the light will shed no light, the wind will not blow, and there will be no summer, no autumn, Lucifer will tear off his bonds and, sallying forth from deepest Hell with the Furies, the Vengeances and the horned devils, will seek to turf the gods of both the greater and lesser nations out from their nests in the heavens.
And whatâs more, if human beings owed nothing to one another, life would âbe no better than a dog-fightââa mere unruly brawl.
Amongst human beings none will save another; it will be no good a man shouting Help! Fire! Iâm drowning! Murder! Nobody will come and help him. Why? Because he has lent nothing: and no one owes him anything. No one has anything to lose by his fire, his shipwreck, his fall, or his death. He has lent nothing. And: he would lend nothing either hereafter.
In short, Faith, Hope and Charity would be banished from this world.
Panurgeâa man without a family, alone, whose entire calling in life was getting large amounts of money and then spending itâserves as a fitting prophet for the world that was just beginning to emerge. His perspective of course is that of a **wealthy** debtorânot one liable to be trundled off to some pestiferous dungeon for failure to pay. Still, what he is describing is the logical conclusion, the **reductio ad absurdum**, which Rabelais as always lays out with cheerful perversity, of the assumptions about the world as exchange slumbering behind all our pleasant bourgeois formalities (which Rabelais himself, incidentally, detestedâthe book is basically a mixture of classical erudition and dirty jokes).
And what he says is true. If we insist on defining all human interactions as matters of people giving one thing for another, then any ongoing human relations can only take the form of debts. Without them, no one would owe anything to anybody. A world without debt would revert to primordial chaos, a war of all against all; no one would feel the slightest responsibility for one another; the simple fact of being human would have no significance; we would all become isolated planets who couldnât even be counted on to maintain our proper orbits.
Pantagruel will have none of it. His own feelings on the matter, he says, can be summed up with one line from the Apostle Paul: âOwe no man anything, save mutual love and affection.â[213] Then, in an appropriately biblical gesture, he declares, âFrom your past debts I shall free you.â
âWhat can I do but thank you?â Panurge replies.
When we return to an examination of conventional economic history, one thing that jumps out is how much has been made to disappear. Reducing all human life to exchange means not only shunting aside all other forms of economic experience (hierarchy, communism), but also ensuring that the vast majority of the human race who are not adult males, and therefore whose day-to-day existence is relatively difficult to reduce to a matter of swapping things in such a way as to seek mutual advantage, melt away into the background.
As a result, we end up with a sanitized view of the way actual business is conducted. The tidy world of shops and malls is the quintessential middle-class environment, but at either the top or the bottom of the system, the world of financiers or of gangsters, deals are often made in ways not so completely different from ways that the Gunwinggu or Nambikwara make themâat least in that sex, drugs, music, extravagant displays of food, and the potential for violence do often play parts.
Consider the case of Neil Bush (George W.âs brother) who, during divorce proceedings with his wife, admitted to multiple infidelities with women who, he claimed, would mysteriously appear at his hotel-room door after important business meetings in Thailand and Hong Kong.
âYou have to admit itâs pretty remarkable,â remarked one of his wifeâs attorneys, âfor a man to go to a hotel-room door and open it and have a woman standing there and have sex with her.â
âIt was very unusual,â Bush replied, admitting however that this had happened to him on numerous occasions.
âWere they prostitutes?â
âI donât know.â[214]
In fact, such things seem almost par for the course when really big money comes into play.
In this light, the economistsâ insistence that economic life begins with barter, the innocent exchange of arrows for teepee frames, with no one in a position to rape, humiliate, or torture anyone else, and that it continues in this way, is touchingly utopian.
As a result, though, the histories we tell are full of blank spaces, and the women in them seem to appear out of nowhere, without explanation, much like the Thai women who appeared at Bushâs door. Recall the passage cited in Chapter Three, from numismatist Philip Grierson, about money in the barbarian law codes:
Compensation in the Welsh laws is reckoned primarily in cattle and in the Irish ones in cattle or bondmaids **(cumal)**, with considerable use of precious metals in both. In the Germanic codes it is mainly in precious metal âŠ[215]
How is it possible to read this passage without immediately stopping at the end of the first line? âBondmaidsâ? Doesnât that mean âslaves?â (It does.) In ancient Ireland, female slaves were so plentiful and important that they came to function as currency. How did that happen? And if we are trying to understand the origins of money, here, isnât the fact that people are using **one another** as currency at all interesting or significant?[216] Yet none of the sources on money remark much on it. It would seem that by the time of the law codes, slave girls were not actually traded, but just used as units of account. Still, they must have been traded at some point. Who were they? How were they enslaved? Were they captured in war, sold by their parents, or reduced to slavery through debt? Were they a major trade item? The answer to all these questions would seem to be yes, but itâs hard to say more because the history remains largely unwritten.[217]
Or letâs return to the parable of the ungrateful servant. âSince he was not able to pay, the master ordered that he and his wife and his children and all that he had be sold to repay the debt.â How did that happen? Note that weâre not even speaking of debt service here (he is already his creditorâs servant), but outright slavery. How did a manâs wife and children come to be considered no different than his sheep and crockeryâas property to be liquidated on the occasion of default? Was it normal for a man in first-century Palestine to be able to sell his wife? (It wasnât.)[218] If he didnât own her, why was someone else allowed to sell her if he couldnât pay his debts?
The same could be asked of the story in Nehemiah. Itâs hard not to empathize with the distress of a father watching his daughter taken off by strangers. On the other hand, one might also ask: Why werenât they taking **him?** The daughter hadnât borrowed any money.
Itâs not as if it is ordinary for fathers in traditional societies to be able to sell their children. This is a practice with a very specific history: it appears in the great agrarian civilizations, from Sumer to Rome to China, right around the time when we also start to see evidence of money, markets, and interest-bearing loans; later, more gradually, it also appears in those surrounding hinterlands that supplied those civilizations with slaves.[219] Whatâs more, if we examine the historical evidence, there seems good reason to believe that the very obsession with patriarchal honor that so defines âtraditionâ in the Middle East and Mediterranean world **itself** arose alongside the fatherâs power to alienate his childrenâas a reaction to what were seen as the moral perils of the market. All of this is treated as somehow outside the bounds of economic history.
Excluding all this is deceptive not only because it excludes the main purposes to which money was actually put in the past, but because it doesnât give us a clear vision of the present. After all, who were those Thai women who so mysteriously appeared at Neil Bushâs hotel door? Almost certainly, they were children of indebted parents. Likely as not, they were contractual debt peons themselves.[220]
Focusing on the sex industry would be deceptive, though. Then as now, most women in debt bondage spend the vast majority of their time sewing, preparing soups, and scouring latrines. Even in the Bible, the admonition in the Ten Commandments not to âcovet thy neighborâs wifeâ clearly referred not to lust in oneâs heart (adultery had already been covered in commandment number seven), but to the prospect of taking her as a debt-peonâin other words, as a servant to sweep oneâs yard and hang out the laundry.[221] In most such matters, sexual exploitation was at best incidental (usually illegal, sometimes practiced anyway, symbolically important.) Again, once we remove some of our usual blinders, we can see that matters have changed far less, over the course of the last five thousand years or so, than we really like to think.
These blinders are all the more ironic when one looks at the anthropological literature on what used to be called âprimitive moneyââthat is, the sort one encounters in places where there are no states or marketsâwhether Iroquois wampum, African cloth money, or Solomon Island feather money, and discovers that such money is used almost exclusively for the kinds of transactions that economists donât like to have to talk about.
In fact, the term âprimitive moneyâ is deceptive for this very reason, since it suggests that we are dealing with a crude version of the kind of currencies we use today. But this is precisely what we donât find. Often, such currencies are never used to buy and sell anything at all.[222] Instead, they are used to create, maintain, and otherwise reorganize relations between people: to arrange marriages, establish the paternity of children, head off feuds, console mourners at funerals, seek forgiveness in the case of crimes, negotiate treaties, acquire followersâalmost anything but trade in yams, shovels, pigs, or jewelry.
Often, these currencies were extremely important, so much so that social life itself might be said to revolve around getting and disposing of the stuff. Clearly, though, they mark a totally different conception of what money, or indeed an economy, is actually about. Iâve decided therefore to refer to them as âsocial currencies,â and the economies that employ them as âhuman economies.â By this I mean not that these societies are necessarily in any way more humane (some are quite humane; others extraordinarily brutal), but only that they are economic systems primarily concerned not with the accumulation of wealth, but with the creation, destruction, and rearranging of human beings.
Historically, commercial economiesâmarket economies, as we now like to call themâare a relative newcomer. For most of human history, human economies predominated. To even begin to write a genuine history of debt, then, we have to start by asking: What sort of debts, what sort of credits and debits, do people accumulate in human economies? And what happens when human economies begin to give away to or are taken over by commercial ones? This is another way of asking the question, âHow do mere obligations turn into debts?ââbut it means not just asking the question in the abstract, but examining the historical record to try to reconstruct what actually did happen.
This is what I will do over the course of the next two chapters. First I will look at the role of money in human economies, then describe what can happen when human economies are suddenly incorporated into the economic orbits of larger, commercial ones. The African slave trade will serve as a particularly catastrophic case in point. Then, in the next chapter, I will return to the first emergence of commercial economies in early civilizations of Europe and the Middle East.
The most interesting theory of the origin of money is the one recently put forward by a French economist-turned-anthropologist named Philippe RospabĂ©. While his work is largely unknown in the English-speaking world, itâs quite ingenious, and it bears directly on our problem. RospabĂ©âs argument is that âprimitive moneyâ was not originally a way to pay debts of any sort. Itâs a way of recognizing the existence of debts that cannot possibly be paid. His argument is worth considering in detail.
In most human economies, money is used first and foremost to arrange marriages. The simplest and probably most common way of doing this was by being presented as what used to be called âbride-priceâ: a suitorâs family would deliver a certain number of dog teeth, or cowries, or brass rings, or whatever is the local social currency, to a womanâs family, and they would present their daughter as his bride. Itâs easy to see why this might be interpreted as buying a women, and many colonial officials in Africa and Oceania in the early part of the twentieth century did indeed come to that conclusion. The practice caused something of a scandal, and by 1926, the League of Nations was debating banning the practice as a form of slavery. Anthropologists objected. Really, they explained, this was nothing like the purchase of, say, an oxâlet alone a pair of sandals. After all, if you buy an ox, you donât have any responsibilities **to** the ox. What you are really buying is the right to dispose of the ox in any way that pleases you. Marriage is entirely different, since a husband will normally have just as many responsibilities toward his wife as his wife will have toward him. Itâs a way of rearranging relations between people. Second of all, if you were really buying a wife, youâd be able to sell her. Finally, the real significance of the payment concerns the status of the womanâs children: if heâs buying anything, itâs the right to call her offspring his own.[223]
The anthropologists ended up winning the argument, and âbride-priceâ was dutifully redubbed âbridewealth.â But they never really answered the question: What is actually happening here? When a Fijian suitorâs family presents a whale tooth to ask for a womanâs hand in marriage, is this an advance payment for the services the woman will provide in cultivating her future husbandâs gardens? Or is he purchasing the future fertility of her womb? Or is this a pure formality, the equivalent of the dollar that has to change hands in order to seal a contract? According to RospabĂ©, itâs none of these. The whale tooth, however valuable, is not a form of payment. It is really an acknowledgment that one is asking for something so uniquely valuable that payment of any sort would be impossible. The only appropriate payment for the gift of a woman is the gift of another woman; in the meantime, all one can do is to acknowledge the outstanding debt.
There are places where suitors say this quite explicitly. Consider the Tiv of Central Nigeria, who we have already met briefly in the last chapter. Most of our information on the Tiv comes from mid-century, when they were still under British colonial rule.[224] Everyone at that time insisted that a proper marriage should take the form of an exchange of sisters. One man gives his sister in marriage to another, that man marries the sister of his newfound brother-in-law. This is the perfect marriage because the only thing one can really give in exchange for a woman is another woman.
Obviously, even if every family had exactly equal numbers of brothers and sisters, things couldnât always work this neatly. Say I marry your sister but you donât want to marry mine (because, say, you donât like her, or because sheâs only five years old). In that case, you become her âguardian,â which means you can claim the right to dispose of her in marriage to someone elseâfor instance, someone whose sister you actually do wish to marry. This system quickly grew into a complex system in which most important men became guardians of numerous âwards,â often scattered over wide areas; they would swap and trade them and in the process accumulate numerous wives for themselves, while less-fortunate men were only able to marry late in life, or not at all.[225]
There was one other expedient. The Tiv at that time used bundles of brass rods as their most prestigious form of currency. Brass rods were only held by men, and never used to buy things in markets (markets were dominated by women); instead, they were exchanged only for things that men considered of higher importance: cattle, horses, ivory, ritual titles, medical treatment, magical charms. It was possible, as one Tiv ethnographer, Akiga Sai, explains, to acquire a wife with brass rods, but it required quite a lot of them. You would need to give two or three bundles of them to her parents to establish yourself as a suitor; then, when you did finally make off with her (such marriages were always first framed as elopements), another few bundles to assuage her mother when she showed up angrily demanding to know what was going on. This would normally be followed by five more to get her guardian to at least temporarily accept the situation, and more still to her parents when she gave birth, if you were to have any chance of their accepting your claims to be the father of her children. That might get her parents off your back, but youâd have to pay off the guardian forever, because you could never really use money to acquire the rights to a woman. Everyone knew that the only thing you can legitimately give in exchange for a woman is another woman. In this case, everyone has to abide by the pretext that a woman will someday be forthcoming. In the meantime, as one ethnographer succinctly puts it, âthe debt can never be fully paid.â[226]
According to RospabĂ©, the Tiv are just making explicit the underlying logic of bridewealth everywhere. The suitor presenting bridewealth is never paying for a woman, or even for the rights to claim her children. That would imply that brass rods, or whaleâs teeth, cowrie shells, or even cattle are somehow the equivalent of a human being, which by the logic of a human economy is obviously absurd. Only a human could ever be considered equivalent to another human. All the more so since, in the case of marriage, we are speaking of something even more valuable than one human life: we are speaking of a human life that also has the capacity to generate new lives.
Certainly, many of those who pay bridewealth are, like the Tiv, quite explicit about all this. Bridewealth money is presented not to settle a debt, but as a kind of acknowledgment that there exists a debt that **cannot** be settled by means of money. Often the two sides will maintain at least the polite fiction that there will, someday, be a recompense in kind: that the suitorâs clan will eventually provide one of its own women, perhaps even that very womanâs daughter or granddaughter, to marry a man of the wifeâs natal clan. Or maybe there will be some arrangement about the disposition of her children; perhaps her clan will get to keep one for itself. The possibilities are endless.
Money, then, begins, as RospabĂ© himself puts it, âas a substitute for life.â[227] One might call it the recognition of a life-debt. This, in turn, explains why itâs invariably the exact same kind of money thatâs used to arrange marriages that is also used to pay wergeld (or âbloodwealthâ as itâs sometimes also called): money presented to the family of a murder victim so as to prevent or resolve a blood-feud. Here the sources are even more explicit. On the one hand, one presents whale teeth or brass rods because the murdererâs kin recognize they owe a life to the victimâs family. On the other, whale teeth or brass rods are in no sense, and can never be, compensation for the loss of a murdered relative. Certainly no one presenting such compensation would ever be foolish enough to suggest that any amount of money could possibly be the âequivalentâ to the value of someoneâs father, sister, or child.
So here again, money is first and foremost an acknowledgment that one owes something much more valuable than money.
In the case of a blood-feud, both parties will also be aware that even a revenge killing, while at least it conforms to the principle of a life for a life, wonât really compensate for the victimâs grief and pain either. This knowledge allows for some possibility of settling the matter without violence. But even here, there is often a feeling that, as in the case of marriage, the **real** solution to the problem is simply being temporarily postponed.
An illustration might be helpful. Among the Nuer, there is a special class of priestly figures who specialize in mediating feuds, referred to in the literature as âleopard-skin chiefs.â If one man murders another, he will immediately seek out one of their homesteads, since such a homestead is treated as an inviolate sanctuary: even the dead manâs family, who will be honor-bound to avenge the murder, will know that they cannot enter it, lest terrible consequences ensue. According to Evans-Pritchardâs classic account, the chief will immediately start trying to negotiate a settlement between the murderer and victimâs families, a delicate business, because the victimâs family will always first refuse:
The chief first finds out what cattle the slayerâs people possess and what they are prepared to pay in compensation.⊠He then visits the dead manâs people and asks them to accept cattle for the life. They usually refuse, for it is a point of honor to be obstinate, but their refusal does not mean that they are unwilling to accept compensation. The chief knows this and insists on their acceptance, even threatening to curse them if they do not give way âŠ[228]
More-distant kin weigh in, reminding everyone of their responsibility to the larger community, of all the trouble that an outstanding feud will cause to innocent relatives, and after a great show of holding out, insisting that it is insulting to suggest that any number of cattle could possibly substitute for the life of a son or brother, they will usually grudgingly accept.[229] In fact, even once the matter has technically been settled, it really hasnâtâit usually takes years to assemble the cattle, and even once they have been paid, the two sides will avoid each other, âespecially at dances, for in the excitement they engender, merely bumping into a man whose kinsman has been slain may cause a fight to break out, because the offense is never forgiven and the score must finally be paid with a life.â[230]
So itâs much the same as with bridewealth. Money does not wipe out the debt. One life can only be paid for with another. At best those paying bloodwealth, by admitting the existence of the debt and insisting that they wish they could pay it, even though they know this is impossible, can allow the matter to be placed permanently on hold.
Halfway around the world, one finds Lewis Henry Morgan describing the elaborate mechanisms set up by the Six Nations of the Iroquois to avoid precisely this state of affairs. In the event one man killed another,
Immediately on the commission of a murder, the affair was taken up by the tribes to which the parties belonged, and strenuous efforts were made to effect a reconciliation, lest private retaliation should lead to disastrous consequences.
The first council ascertained whether the offender was willing to confess his crime, and to make atonement. If he was, the council immediately sent a belt of white wampum, in his name, to the other council, which contained a message to that effect. The latter then endeavored to pacify the family of the deceased, to quiet their excitement, and to induce them to accept the wampum as condonation.[231]
Much as in the case of the Nuer, there were complicated schedules of exactly how many fathoms of wampum were paid over, depending on the status of the victim and the nature of the crime. As with the Nuer, too, everyone insisted that this was **not** payment. The value of the wampum in no sense represented the value of the dead manâs life:
The present of white wampum was not in the nature of a compensation for the life of the deceased, but of a regretful confession of the crime, with a petition for forgiveness. It was a peace-offering, the acceptance of which was pressed by mutual friends âŠ[232]
Actually, in many cases there was also some way to manipulate the system to turn payments meant to assuage oneâs rage and grief into ways of creating a new life that would in some sense substitute for the one that was lost. Among the Nuer, forty cattle were set as the standard fee for bloodwealth. But it was also the standard rate of bridewealth. The logic was this: if a man had been murdered before he was able to marry and produce offspring, itâs only natural that his spirit would be angry. He had been, effectively, robbed of his eternity. The best solution would be to use the cattle paid in settlement to acquire what was called a âghost-wifeâ: a woman who would then be formally married to the dead man. In practice, she was usually paired off with one of the victimâs brothers, but this was not particularly important; it didnât really matter too much who impregnated her, since he would be in no sense the father of her children. Her children would be considered the children of the victimâs ghostâand as a result, any boys among them were seen as having been born with a particular commitment to someday avenge his death.[233]
This latter is unusual. But Nuer appear to have been unusually stubborn about feuds. RospabĂ© provides examples from other parts of the world that are even more telling. Among North African Bedouins, for instance, it sometimes happened that the only way to settle a feud was for the killerâs family to turn over a daughter, who would then marry the victimâs next of kinâhis brother, say. If she bore him a male child, the boy was given the same name as his dead uncle and considered to be, at least in the broadest sense, a substitute for him.[234] The Iroquois, who traced descent in the female line, did not trade women in this fashion. However, they had another, more direct approach. If a man diedâeven of natural causesâhis wifeâs relatives might âput his name upon the mat,â sending off belts of wampum to commission a war party, which would then raid an enemy village to secure a captive. The captive could either be killed, or, if the clan matrons were in a benevolent mood (one could never tell; the grief of mourning is tricky), adopted: this was signified by throwing a belt of wampum around his shoulders, whereon he would be given the name of the deceased and be considered, from that moment on, married to the victimâs wife, the owner of his personal possessions, and in every way, effectively, the exact same person as the dead man used to be.[235]
All of this merely serves to underline RospabĂ©âs basic point, which is that money can be seen, in human economies, as first and foremost the acknowledgment of the existence of a debt that **cannot** be paid.
In a way, itâs all very reminiscent of primordial-debt theory: money emerges from the recognition of an absolute debt to that which has given you life. The difference is that instead of imagining such debts as between an individual and society, or perhaps the cosmos, here they are imagined as a kind of network of dyadic relations: almost everyone in such societies was in a relation of absolute debt to someone else. Itâs not that we owe âsociety.â If there is any notion of âsocietyâ hereâand itâs not clear that there isâsociety **is** our debts.
Obviously, this leads us to the same familiar problem: How does a token of recognition that one cannot pay a debt turn into a form of payment by which a debt can be extinguished? If anything, the problem seems even worse than it was before.
In fact, it isnât. The African evidence clearly shows how such things can happenâthough the answer is a bit unsettling. To demonstrate this, it will be necessary to look at one or two African societies with a closer focus.
Iâll start with the Lele, an African people who had, at the time that Mary Douglas studied them in the 1950s, managed to turn the principle of blood debts into the organizing principle of their entire society.
The Lele were, at that time, a group of perhaps ten thousand souls, living on a stretch of rolling country near the Kasai River in the Belgian Congo, and considered a rude backcountry folk by their richer and more cosmopolitan neighbors, the Kuba and Bushong. Lele women grew maize and manioc; the men thought of themselves as intrepid hunters but spent most of their time weaving and sewing raffia-palm cloth. This cloth was what the area was really known for. It was not only used for every sort of clothing, but also exported: the Lele considered themselves the clothiers of the region, and it was traded with surrounding people to acquire luxuries. Internally, it functioned as a sort of currency. Still, it was not used in markets (there were no markets), and, as Mary Douglas discovered to her great inconvenience, within a village, one couldnât use it to acquire food, tools, tableware, or really much of anything.[236] It was the quintessential social currency.
Informal gifts of raffia cloth smooth all social relations: husband to wife, son to mother, son to father. They resolve occasions of tension, as peace-offerings; they make parting gifts, or convey congratulations. There are also formal gifts of raffia which are neglected only at risk of rupture of the social ties involved. A man, on reaching adulthood, should give 20 cloths to his father. Otherwise he would be ashamed to ask his fatherâs help for raising his marriage dues. A man should give 20 cloths to his wife on each delivery of a child âŠ[237]
Cloth was also used for various fines and fees, and to pay curers. So for instance, if a manâs wife reported a would-be seducer, it was customary to reward her with 20 cloths for her fidelity (it was not required, but not doing so was considered decidedly unwise); if an adulterer was caught, he was expected to pay 50 or 100 cloths to the womanâs husband; if the husband and lover disturbed the peace of the village by fighting before the matter was settled, each would have to pay two in compensation, and so forth.
Gifts tended to flow upward. Young people were always giving little presents of cloth as marks of respect to fathers, mothers, uncles, and the like. These gifts were hierarchical in nature: that is, it never occurred to those receiving them that they should have to reciprocate in any way. As a result, elders, and especially elder men, usually had a few extra pieces lying around, and young men, who could never weave quite enough to meet their needs, would have to turn to them whenever time for some major payment rolled around: for instance, if they had to pay a major fine, or wished to hire a doctor to assist their wife in child-birth, or wanted to join a cult society. They were thus always slightly in debt, or at least slightly beholden, to their elders. But everyone also had a whole range of friends and relatives who they had helped out, and so could turn to for assistance.[238]
Marriage was particularly expensive, since the arrangements usually required getting oneâs hands on several bars of camwood. If raffia cloth was the small change of social life, camwoodâa rare imported wood used for the manufacture of cosmeticsâwas the high-denomination currency. A hundred raffia cloths were equivalent to three to five bars. Few individuals owned much in the way of camwood, usually just little bits to grind up for their own use. Most was kept in each villageâs collective treasury.
This is not to say that camwood was used for anything like bridewealthârather, it was used in marriage negotiations, in which all sorts of gifts were passed back and forth. In fact, there was no bridewealth. Men could not use money to acquire women; nor could they use it to claim any rights over children. The Lele were matrilineal. Children belonged not to their fatherâs clan, but to their motherâs.
There was another way that men gained control over women, however.[239] This was the system of blood debts.
It is a common understanding among many traditional African peoples that human beings do not simply die without a reason. If someone dies, someone must have killed them. If a Lele woman died in childbirth, for example, this was assumed to be because she had committed adultery. The adulterer was thus responsible for the death. Sometimes she would confess on her deathbed, otherwise the facts of the matter would have to be established through divination. It was the same if a baby died. If someone became sick, or slipped and fell while climbing a tree, one would check to see if they had been involved in any quarrel that could be said to have caused the misfortune. If all else failed, one could employ magical means to identify the sorcerer. Once the village was satisfied that a culprit had been identified, that person owed a blood-debt: that is, he owed the victimâs next of kin a human life. The culprit would thus have to transfer over a young woman from his family, his sister or her daughter, to be the victimâs ward, or âpawn.â
As with the Tiv, the system quickly became immensely complicated. Pawnship was inherited. If a woman was someoneâs pawn, so would her children be, and so would her daughtersâ children. This meant that most males were also considered someone elseâs man. Still, no one would accept a male pawn in payment of blood-debts: the whole point was to get hold of a young woman, who would then go on to produce additional pawn children. Douglasâs Lele informants emphasized that any man would naturally want to have many of these as possible:
Ask âWhy do you want to have more pawns?â and they invariably say, âThe advantage of owning pawns is that if you incur a blood-debt, you can settle it by paying one of your pawns, and your own sisters remain free.â Ask, âWhy do you wish your own sisters to remain free?â and they reply, âAh! then if I incur a blood-debt, I can settle it by giving one of them as a pawn âŠâ
Every man is always aware that at any time he is liable for a blood-debt. If any woman he has seduced confesses his name in the throes of child-birth, and subsequently dies, or if her child dies, or if anyone he has quarreled with dies of illness or accident, he may be held responsible ⊠Even if a woman runs away from her husband, and fighting breaks out on her account, the deaths will be laid at her door, and her brother or motherâs brother will have to pay up. Since only women are accepted as blood-compensation, and since compensation is demanded for all deaths, of men as well as of women, it is obvious that there can never be enough to go around. Men fall into arrears in their pawnship obligations, and girls used to be pledged before their birth, even before their mothers were of marriageable age.[240]
In other words, the whole thing turned into an endlessly complicated chess gameâone reason, Douglas remarks, why the term âpawnâ seems singularly apropos. Just about every adult Lele male was both someone elseâs pawn, and engaged in a constant game of securing, swapping, or redeeming pawns. Every major drama or tragedy of village life would ordinarily lead to a transfer of rights in women. Almost all of those women would eventually get swapped again.
Several points need to be emphasized here. First of all, what were being traded were, quite specifically, human lives. Douglas calls them âblood-debts,â but âlife-debtsâ would be more appropriate. Say, for instance, a man is drowning, and another man rescues him. Or say heâs deathly ill but a doctor cures him. In either case, we would likely say one man âowes his lifeâ to the other. So would the Lele, but they meant it literally. Save someoneâs life, they owe you a life, and a life owed had to be paid back. The usual recourse was for a man whose life was saved to turn over his sister as a pawnâor if not that, a different woman; a pawn he had acquired from someone else.
The second point is that nothing could substitute for a human life. âCompensation was based on the principle of equivalence, a life for a life, a person for a person.â Since the value of a human life was absolute, no amount of raffia cloth, or camwood bars, or goats, or transistor radios, or anything else could possibly take its place.
The third and most important point is that in practice, âhuman lifeâ actually meant âwomanâs lifeââor even more specifically, âyoung womanâs life.â Ostensibly this was to maximize oneâs holdings: above all, one wished for a human being who could become pregnant and produce children, since those children would also be pawns. Still, even Mary Douglas, who was in no sense a feminist, was forced to admit that the whole arrangement did seem to operate as if it were one gigantic apparatus for asserting male control over women. This was true above all because women themselves could not own pawns.[241] They could only be pawns. In other words: when it came to life-debts, only men could be either creditors **or** debtors. Young women were thus the credits and the debitsâthe pieces being moved around the chessboardâwhile the hands that moved them were invariably male.[242]
Of course, since almost everyone was a pawn, or had been at some point in their lives, being one could not in itself be much of a tragedy. For male pawns it was in some ways quite advantageous, since oneâs âownerâ had to pay most of oneâs fines and fees and even blood-debts. This is why, as Douglasâs informants uniformly insisted, pawnship had nothing in common with slavery. The Lele did keep slaves, but never very many. Slaves were war captives, usually foreigners. As such they had no family, no one to protect them. To be a pawn, on the other hand, meant to have not one, but two different families to look after you: you still had your own mother and her brothers, but now you also had your âlord.â
For a woman, the very fact that she was the stakes in a game that all men were playing afforded all sorts of opportunities to game the system. In principle, a girl might be born a pawn, assigned to some man for eventual marriage. In practice, however,
a little Lele girl would grow up a coquette. From infancy she was the centre of affectionate, teasing, flirting attention. Her affianced husband never gained more than a very limited control over her ⊠Since men competed with one another for women there was scope for women to manoeuvre and intrigue. Hopeful seducers were never lacking and no woman doubted that she could get another husband if it suited her.[243]
In addition, a young Lele woman had one unique and powerful card to play. Everyone was well aware that, if she completely refused to countenance her situation, she always had the option of becoming a âvillage-wife.â[244]
The institution of village-wife was a peculiarly Lele one. Probably the best way to describe it is to imagine a hypothetical case. Let us say that an old, important man acquires a young woman as pawn through a blood-debt, and he decides to marry her himself. Technically, he has the right to do so, but itâs no fun for a young woman to be an old manâs third or fourth wife. Or, say he decides to offer her in marriage to one of his male pawns in a village far away from her mother and natal home. She protests. He ignores her protestations. She waits for an opportune moment and slips off at night to an enemy village, where she asks for sanctuary. This is always possible: all villages have their traditional enemies. Neither would an enemy village refuse a woman who came to them in such a situation. They would immediately declare her âwife of the village,â who all men living there would then be obliged to protect.
It helps to understand that here, as in many parts of Africa, most older men had several wives. This meant that the pool of women available for younger men was considerably reduced. As our ethnographer explains, the imbalance was a source of considerable sexual tension:
Everyone recognized that the young unmarried men coveted the wives of their seniors. Indeed, one of their pastimes was to plan seductions and the man who boasted of none was derided. Since the old men wished to remain polygynists, with two or three wives, and since adulteries were thought to disrupt the peace of the village, Lele had to make some arrangement to appease their unmarried men.
Therefore, when a sufficient number of them reached the age of eighteen or so, they were allowed to buy the right to a common wife.[245]
After paying an appropriate fee in raffia cloth to the village treasury, they were permitted to build a collective house, and then they were either allotted a wife to put in it, or allowed to form a party that would try to steal one from a rival village. (Or, alternately, if one showed up as a refugee, they would ask the rest of the village for the right to accept her: this was invariably granted.) This common wife is whatâs referred to as a âvillage wife.â The position of village wife was more than respectable. In fact, a newly married village wife was treated very much like a princess. She was not expected to plant or weed in the gardens, fetch wood or water, or even to cook; all household chores were done by her eager young husbands, who provided the best of everything, spending much of their time hunting in the forest vying to bring her the choicest delicacies, or plying her with palm wine. She could help herself to othersâ possessions and was expected to make all sorts of mischief to the bemused indulgence of all concerned. She was also expected to make herself sexually available to all members of the age-setâperhaps ten or twelve different menâat first, pretty much whenever they wanted her.[246]
Over time, a village wife would usually settle down with just three or four of her husbands, and finally, just one. The domestic arrangements were flexible. Nonetheless, in principle, she was married to the village as a whole. If she had children, the village was considered to be their father, and as such expected to bring them up, provide them with resources, and eventually, get them properly married offâwhich is why villages had to maintain collective treasuries full of raffia and camwood bars in the first place. Since at any time a village was likely to have several village wives, it would also have its own children and grandchildren, and therefore be in a position to both demand and pay blood-debts, and thus, to accumulate pawns.
As a result, villages became corporate bodies, collective groups that, like modern corporations, had to be treated as if they were individuals for purposes of law. However there was one key difference. Unlike ordinary individuals, villages could back up their claims with force.
As Douglas emphasizes, this was crucial, because ordinary Lele men were simply not able to do this to one another.[247] In everyday affairs, there was an almost complete lack of any systematic means of coercion. This was the main reason, she notes, that pawnship was so innocuous. There were all sorts of rules, but with no government, no courts, no judges to make authoritative decisions, no group of armed men willing or able to employ the threat of force to back those decisions up, rules were there to be adjusted and interpreted. In the end, everyoneâs feelings had to be taken into account. In everyday affairs, Lele put great stock on gentle and agreeable behavior. Men might have been regularly seized with the urge to throw themselves at each other in fits of jealous rage (often they had good reason to), but they very rarely did. And if a fight did break out, everyone would immediately jump in to break it up and submit the affair to public mediation.[248]
Villages, in contrast, were fortified, and age-sets could be mobilized to act as military units. Here, and only here, did organized violence enter the picture. True, when villages fought, it was also always over women (everyone Douglas talked to expressed incredulity at the very idea that grown men, anywhere, could ever come to blows over anything else). But in the case of villages, it could come to an actual war. If another villageâs elders ignored oneâs claims to a pawn, oneâs young men might organize a raiding party and kidnap her, or carry off some other likely young women to be their collective wife. This might lead to deaths, and to further claims for compensation. âSince it had the backing of force,â Douglas observes drily, âthe village could afford to be less conciliatory towards the wishes of its pawns.â[249]
Itâs at exactly this point, too, where the potential for violence enters, that the great wall constructed between the value of lives and money can suddenly come tumbling down.
Sometimes when two clans were disputing a claim to blood compensation, the claimant might see no hope of getting satisfaction from his opponents. The political system offered no direct means for one man (or clan) to use physical coercion or to resort to superior authority to enforce claims against another. In such a case, rather than abandon his claim to a pawn-woman, he would be ready to take the equivalent in wealth, if he could get it. The usual procedure was to sell his case against the defendants to the only group capable of extorting a pawn by force, that is, to a village.
The man who meant to sell his case to a village asked them for 100 raffia cloths or five bars of camwood. The village raised the amount, either from its treasury, or by a loan from one of its members, and thereby adopted as its own his claim to a pawn.[250]
Once he held the money, his claim was over, and the village, which had now bought it, would proceed to organize a raid to seize the woman in dispute.
In other words, it was **only** when violence was brought into the equation that there was any question of buying and selling people. The ability to deploy force, to cut through the endless maze of preferences, obligations, expectations, and responsibilities that mark real human relationships, also made it possible to overcome what is otherwise the first rule of all Lele economic relationships: that human lives can only be exchanged for other human lives, and never for physical objects. Significantly, the amount paidâa hundred cloths, or an equivalent amount of camwoodâwas also the price of a slave.[251] Slaves were, as I mentioned, war captives. There seem never to have been very many of them; Douglas only managed to locate two descendants of slaves in the 1950s, some twenty-five years after the practice had been abolished.[252] Still, the numbers were not important. The mere fact of their existence set a precedent. The value of a human life could, sometimes, be quantified; but if one was able to move from A = A (one life equals another) to A = B (one life = one hundred cloths), it was only because the equation was established at the point of a spear.
I have dwelt on the Lele in such detail in part because I wanted to convey some sense of why I was using the term âhuman economy,â what life is like inside one, what sort of dramas fill peopleâs days, and how money typically operates in the midst of all this. Lele currencies are, as I say, quintessential social currencies. They are used to mark every visit, every promise, every important moment in a manâs or womanâs life. It is surely significant, too, what the objects used as currency here actually were. Raffia cloth was used for clothing. In Douglasâs day, it was the main thing used to clothe the human body; camwood bars were the source of a red paste that was used as a cosmeticâit was the main substance used as makeup, by both men and women, to beautify themselves each day. These, then, were the materials used to shape peopleâs physical appearance, to make them appear mature, decent, attractive, and dignified to their fellows. They were what turned a mere naked body into a proper social being.
This is no coincidence. In fact, itâs extraordinarily common in what Iâve been calling human economies. Money almost always arises first from objects that are used primarily as adornment of the person. Beads, shells, feathers, dog or whale teeth, gold, and silver are all well-known cases in point. All are useless for any purpose other than making people look more interesting, and hence, more beautiful. The brass rods used by the Tiv might seem an exception, but actually theyâre not: they were used mainly as raw material for the manufacture of jewelry, or simply twisted into hoops and worn at dances. There are exceptions (cattle, for instance), but as a general rule, itâs only when governments, and then markets, enter the picture that we begin to see currencies like barley, cheese, tobacco, or salt.[253]
It also illustrates the peculiar progression of ideas that so often mark human economies. On the one hand, human life is the absolute value. There is no possible equivalent. Whether a life is given or taken, the debt is absolute. In places, this principle is indeed sacrosanct. More often, it is compromised by the elaborate games played by the Tiv, who treat the giving of lives, and the Lele, who treat the taking of lives, as creating debts that can only be paid by delivering another human being. In each case, too, the practice ends up engendering an extraordinarily complex game in which important men end up exchanging women, or at least, rights over their fertility.
But this is already a kind of opening. Once the game exists, once the principle of substitution comes in, there was always the possibility of extending it. When that begins to happen, systems of debt that were premised on creating people canâeven hereâsuddenly become the means of destroying them.
As an example, let us once again return to the Tiv. The reader will recall that if a man did not have a sister or a ward to give in exchange for oneâs wife, it was possible to assuage her parents and guardians by gifts of money. However, such a wife would never be considered truly his. Here too, there was one dramatic exception. A man could buy a slave, a woman kidnapped in a raid from a distant country.[254] Slaves, after all, had no parents, or could be treated as if they didnât; they had been forcibly removed from all those networks of mutual obligation and debt in which ordinary people acquired their outward identities. This was why they could be bought and sold.
Once married, though, a purchased wife would quickly develop new ties. She was no longer a slave, and her children were perfectly legitimateâmore so, in fact, than those of a wife who was merely acquired through the continual payment of brass rods.
We have perhaps a general principle: to make something saleable, in a human economy, one needs to first rip it from its context. Thatâs what slaves are: people stolen from the community that made them what they are. As strangers to their new communities, slaves no longer had mothers, fathers, kin of any sort. This is why they could be bought and sold or even killed: because the **only** relation they had was to their owners. A Lele villageâs ability to organize raids and kidnap a woman from an alien community seems to have been the key to its ability to start trading women for moneyâeven if in their case, they could do so only to a very limited extent. After all, her relatives were not very far away, and they would surely come around demanding an explanation. In the end, someone would have to come up with an arrangement that everyone could live with.[255]
Still, I would also insist that there is something more than this. One gets the distinct sense, in much of the literature, that many African societies were haunted by the awareness that these elaborate networks of debt could, if things went just slightly wrong, be transformed into something absolutely terrible. The Tiv are a dramatic case in point.
Among students of anthropology, the Tiv are mainly famous for the fact that their economic life was divided into what their best-known ethnographers, Paul and Laura Bohannan, referred to as three separate âspheres of exchange.â Ordinary, everyday economic activity was mostly the affair of women. They were the ones who filled the markets, and who trod the paths giving and returning minor gifts of okra, nuts, or fish. Men concerned themselves with what they considered higher things: the kind of transactions that could be conducted using the Tiv currency, which, as with the Lele, consisted of two denominations, a kind of locally made cloth called **tugudu**, widely exported, and, for major transactions, bundles of imported brass rods.[256] These could be used to acquire certain flashy and luxurious things (cows, purchased foreign wives), but they were mainly for the give and take of political affairs, hiring curers, acquiring magic, gaining initiation into cult societies. In political matters, Tiv were even more resolutely egalitarian than the Lele: successful old men with their numerous wives might have lorded it over their sons and other dependants within their own house compounds, but beyond that, there was no formal political organization of any sort. Finally, there was the system of wards, which consisted entirely of menâs rights in women. Hence, the notion of âspheres.â In principle, these three levelsâordinary consumption goods, masculine prestige goods, and rights in womenâwere completely separate. No amount of okra could get you a brass rod, just as, in principle, no number of brass rods could give you full rights to a woman.
In practice, there were ways to game the system. Say a neighbor was sponsoring a feast but was short on supplies; one might come to his aid, then later, discreetly, ask for a bundle or two in repayment. To be able to wheel and deal, to âturn chickens into cows,â as the saying went, and ultimately, broker oneâs wealth and prestige into a way of acquiring wives, required a âstrong heartââthat is, an enterprising and charismatic personality.[257] But âstrong heartâ had another meaning too. There was believed to be a certain actual biological substance called **tsav** that grew on the human heart. This was what gave certain people their charm, their energy, and their powers of persuasion. **Tsav** therefore was both a physical substance and that invisible power that allows certain people to bend others to their will.[258]
The problem wasâand most Tiv of that time appear to have believed that this was **the** problem with their societyâthat it was also possible to augment oneâs **tsav** through artificial means, and this could only be accomplished by consuming human flesh.
Now, I should emphasize right away that there is no reason to believe that any Tiv actually did practice cannibalism. The idea of eating human flesh appears to have disgusted and horrified them as much as it would most Americans. Yet for centuries, most appear to have been veritably obsessed by the suspicion that some of their neighborsâand particularly prominent men who became de facto political leadersâwere, in fact, secret cannibals. Men who built up their **tsav** by such means, the stories went, attained extraordinary powers: the ability to fly, to become impervious to weapons, to be able to send out their souls at night to kill their victims in such a way that their victims did not even know that they were dead, but would wander about, confused and feckless, to be harvested for their cannibal feasts. They became, in short, terrifying witches.[259]
The **mbatsav**, or society of witches, was always looking for new members, and the way to accomplish this was to trick people into eating human flesh. A witch would take a piece of the body of one of his own close relatives, who he had murdered, and place it in the victimâs food. If the man was foolish enough to eat it, he would contract a âflesh-debt,â and the society of witches ensured that flesh-debts are always paid.
Perhaps your friend, or some older man, has noticed that you have a large number of children, or brothers and sisters, and so tricks you into contracting the debt with him. He invites you to eat food in his house alone with him, and when you begin the meal he sets before you two dishes of sauce, one of which contains cooked human flesh âŠ
If you eat from the wrong dish, but you do not have a âstrong heartââthe potential to become a witchâyou will become sick and flee from the house in terror. But if you have that hidden potential, the flesh will begin to work in you. That evening, you will find your house surrounded by screeching cats and owls. Strange noises will fill the air. Your new creditor will appear before you, backed by his confederates in evil. He will tell of how he killed his own brother so you two could dine together, and pretend to be tortured by the thought of having lost his own kin as you sit there, surrounded by your plump and healthy relatives. The other witches will concur, acting as if all this is your own fault. âYou have sought for trouble, and trouble has come upon you. Come and lie down on the ground, that we may cut your throat.â[260]
Thereâs only one way out, and thatâs to pledge a member of your own family as substitute. This is possible, because you will find you have terrible new powers, but they must be used as the other witches demand. One by one, you must kill off your brothers, sisters, children; their bodies will be stolen from their graves by the college of witches, brought back to life just long enough to be properly fattened, tortured, killed again, then carved and roasted for yet another feast.
The flesh debt goes on and on. The creditor keeps on coming. Unless the debtor has men behind him who are very strong in **tsav**, he cannot free himself from the flesh debt until he has given up all his people, and his family is finished. Then he goes himself and lies down on the ground to be slaughtered, and so the debt is finally discharged.[261]
In one sense, itâs obvious whatâs going on here. Men with âstrong heartsâ have power and charisma; using it, they can manipulate debt to turn extra food into treasures, and treasures into wives, wards, and daughters, and thus become the heads of ever-growing families. But that very power and charisma that allows them to do this also makes them run the constant danger of sending the whole process jolting back into a kind of horrific implosion, of creating flesh-debts whereby oneâs family is converted back into food.
Now, if one is simply trying to imagine the worst thing that could possibly happen to someone, surely, being forced to dine on the mutilated corpses of oneâs own children would, anywhere, be pretty high on the list. Still, anthropologists have come to understand, over the years, that every society is haunted by slightly different nightmares, and these differences are significant. Horror stories, whether about vampires, ghouls, or flesh-eating zombies, always seem to reflect some aspect of the tellersâ own social lives, some terrifying potential, in the way they are accustomed to interact with each other, that they do not wish to acknowledge or confront, but also cannot help but talk about.[262]
In the Tiv case, what would that be? Clearly, Tiv did have a major problem with authority. They lived in a landscape dotted with compounds, each organized around a single older man with his numerous wives, children, and assorted hangers-on. Within each compound, that man had near-absolute authority. Outside there was no formal political structure, and Tiv were fiercely egalitarian. In other words: all men aspired to become the masters of large families, but they were extremely suspicious of any form of mastery. Hardly surprising, then, that Tiv men were so ambivalent about the nature of power that they became convinced that the very qualities that allow a man to rise to legitimate prominence could, if taken just a little bit further, turn him into a monster.[263] In fact, most Tiv seemed to assume that most male elders **were** witches, and that if a young person died, they were probably being paid off for a flesh-debt.
But this still doesnât answer the one obvious question: Why is all this framed in terms of debt?
Here a little history is in order. It would appear that the ancestors of the Tiv arrived in the Benue river valley and adjacent lands sometime around 1750âa time when all of whatâs now Nigeria was being torn apart by the Atlantic slave trade. Early stories relate how the Tiv, during their migrations, used to paint their wives and children with what looked like smallpox scars, so that potential raiders would be afraid to carry them off.[264] They established themselves in a notoriously inaccessible stretch of country and offered up ferocious defense against periodic raids from neighboring kingdoms to their north and westâwith which they eventually came to a political rapprochement.[265]
The Tiv, then, were well aware of what was happening all around them. Consider, for example, the case of the copper bars whose use they were so careful to restrict, so as to avoid their becoming an allpurpose form of currency.
Now, copper bars had been used for money in this part of Africa for centuries, and at least in some places, for ordinary commercial transactions, as well. It was easy enough to do: one simply snapped them apart into smaller pieces, or pulled some of them into thin wires, twisted those around to little loops, and one had perfectly serviceable small change for everyday market transactions.[266] Most of the ones current in Tivland since the late eighteenth century, on the other hand, were mass-produced in factories in Birmingham and imported through the port of Old Calabar at the mouth of the Cross River, by slave-traders based in Liverpool and Bristol.[267] In all the country adjoining the Cross Riverâthat is, in the region directly to the south of the Tiv territoryâcopper bars were used as everyday currency. This was presumably how they entered Tivland; they were either carried in by pedlars from the Cross River or acquired by Tiv traders on expeditions abroad. All this, however, makes the fact that the Tiv refused to use copper bars as such a currency doubly significant.
During the 1760s alone, perhaps a hundred thousand Africans were shipped down the Cross River to Calabar and nearby ports, where they were put in chains, placed on British, French, or other European ships, and shipped across the Atlanticâpart of perhaps a million and a half exported from the Bight of Biafra during the whole period of the Atlantic slave trade.[268] Some of them had been captured in wars or raids, or simply kidnapped. The majority, though, were carried off because of debts.
Here, though, I must explain something about the organization of the slave trade.
The Atlantic Slave Trade as a whole was a gigantic network of credit arrangements. Ship-owners based in Liverpool or Bristol would acquire goods on easy credit terms from local wholesalers, expecting to make good by selling slaves (also on credit) to planters in the Antilles and America, with commission agents in the city of London ultimately financing the affair through the profits of the sugar and tobacco trade.[269] Ship-owners would then transport their wares to African ports like Old Calabar. Calabar itself was the quintessential mercantile city-state, dominated by rich African merchants who dressed in European clothes, lived in European-style houses, and in some cases even sent their children to England to be educated.
On arrival, European traders would negotiate the value of their cargoes in the copper bars that served as the currency of the port. In 1698, a merchant aboard a ship called the **Dragon** noted the following prices he managed to establish for his wares:
one bar iron | 4 copper bars |
one bunch of beads | 4 copper bars |
five rangoes[270] | 4 copper bars |
one basin No. 1 | 4 copper bars |
one tankard | 3 copper bars |
one yard linen | 1 copper bar |
six knives | 1 copper bar |
one brass bell No. 1 | 3 copper bars[271] |
By the height of the trade fifty years later, British ships were bringing in large quantities of cloth (both products of the newly created Manchester mills and calicoes from India), and iron and copper ware, along with incidental goods like beads, and also, for obvious reasons, substantial numbers of firearms.[272] The goods were then advanced to African merchants, again on credit, who assigned them to their own agents to move upstream.
The obvious problem was how to secure the debt. The trade was an extraordinarily duplicitous and brutal business, and slave raiders were unlikely to be dependable credit risksâespecially when dealing with foreign merchants who they might never see again.[273] As a result, a system quickly developed in which European captains would demand security in the form of pawns.
The sort of âpawnsâ we are talking about here are clearly quite different from the kind we encountered among the Lele. In many of the kingdoms and trading towns of West Africa, the nature of pawnship appears to have already undergone profound changes by the time Europeans showed up on the scene around 1500âit had become, effectively, a kind of debt peonage. Debtors would pledge family members as surety for loans; the pawns would then become dependents in the creditorsâ households, working their fields and tending to their household choresâtheir persons acting as security while their labor, effectively, substituted for interest.[274] Pawns were not slaves; they were not, like slaves, cut off from their families; but neither were they precisely free.[275] In Calabar and other ports, masters of slaving ships, on advancing goods to their African counterparts, soon developed the custom of demanding pawns as securityâfor instance, two of the merchantsâ own dependents for every three slaves to be delivered, preferably including at least one member of the merchantsâ families.[276] This was in practice not much different than demanding the surrender of hostages, and at times it created major political crises when captains, tired of waiting for delayed shipments, decided to take off with a cargo of pawns instead.
Upriver, debt pawns also played a major part in the trade. In one way, the area was a bit unusual. In most of West Africa, the trade ran through major kingdoms such as Dahomey or Asante to make wars and impose draconian punishmentsâone very common expedient for rulers was to manipulate the justice system, so that almost any crime came to be punishable by enslavement, or by death with the enslavement of oneâs wife and children, or by outrageously high fines which, if one could not pay them, would cause the defaulter and his family to be sold as slaves. In another way, it is unusually revealing, since the lack of any larger government structures made it easier to see what was really happening. The pervasive climate of violence led to the systematic perversion of all the institutions of existing human economies, which were transformed into a gigantic apparatus of dehumanization and destruction.
In the Cross River region, the trade seems to have seen two phases. The first was a period of absolute terror and utter chaos, in which raids were frequent, and anyone traveling alone risked being kidnapped by roving gangs of thugs and sold to Calabar. Before long, villages lay abandoned; many people fled into the forest; men would have to form armed parties to work the fields.[277] This period was relatively brief. The second began when representatives of local merchant societies began to establish themselves in communities up and down the region, offering to restore order. The most famous of these was the Aro Confederacy, who called themselves, âChildren of God.â[278] Backed by heavily armed mercenaries and the prestige of their famous Oracle at Arochukwu, they established a new and notoriously harsh justice system.[279] Kidnappers were hunted down and themselves sold as slaves. Safety was restored to roads and farmsteads. At the same time, Aro collaborated with local elders to create a code of ritual laws and penalties so comprehensive and severe that everyone was at constant risk of falling afoul of them.[280] Anyone who violated one would be turned over to the Aro for transport to the coast, with their accuser receiving their price in copper bars.[281] According to some contemporary accounts, a man who simply disliked his wife and was in need of brass rods could always come up with some reason to sell her, and the village eldersâwho received a share of the profitsâwould almost invariably concur.[282] The most ingenious trick of the merchant societies, though, was to assist in the dissemination of a secret society, called Ekpe. Ekpe was most famous for sponsoring magnificent masquerades and for initiating its members into arcane mysteries, but it also acted as a secret mechanism for the enforcement of debts.[283] In Calabar itself, for example, the Ekpe society had access to a whole range of sanctions, starting with boycotts (all members were forbidden to conduct trade with a defaulting debtor), fines, seizure of property, arrest, and finally, executionâwith the most hapless victims left tied to trees, their lower jaws removed, as a warning to others.[284] It was ingenious, particularly, because such societies always allowed anyone to buy in, rising though the nine initiatory grades if they could pay the feeâthese also exacted, of course, in the brass rods the merchants themselves supplied. In Calabar, the fee schedule for each grade looked like this:[285]
In other words, it was quite expensive. But membership quickly became the chief mark of honor and distinction everywhere. Entry fees were no doubt less exorbitant in small, distant communities, but the effect was still the same: thousands ended up in debt to the merchants, whether for the fees required for joining, or for the trade goods they supplied (mostly cloth and metal put to use creating the gear and costumes for the Ekpe performancesâdebts that they thus themselves became responsible for enforcing on themselves. These debts, too, were regularly paid in people, ostensibly yielded up as pawns.)
How did it work in practice? It appears to have varied a great deal from place to place. In the Afikpo district, on a remote part of the upper Cross River, for instance, we read that everyday affairsâthe acquisition of food, for exampleâwas conducted, as among the Tiv, âwithout trade or the use of money.â Brass rods, supplied by the merchant societies, were used to buy and sell slaves, but otherwise mostly as a social currency, âused for gifts and for payments in funerals, titles, and other ceremonies.â[286] Most of those payments, titles, and ceremonies were tied to the secret societies that the merchants had also brought to the area. All this does sound a bit like the Tiv arrangement, but the presence of the merchants ensured that the effects were very different:
In the old days, if anybody got into trouble or debt in the upper parts of the Cross River, and wanted ready money, he used generally to âpledgeâ one or more of his children, or some other members of his family or household, to one of the Akunakuna traders who paid periodical visits to his village. Or he would make a raid on some neighboring village, seize a child, and sell him or her to the same willing purchaser.[287]
The passage only makes sense if one recognizes that debtors were also, owing to their membership in the secret societies, collectors. The seizing of a child is a reference to the local practice of âpanyarring,â current throughout West Africa, by which creditors despairing of repayment would simply sweep into the debtorâs community with a group of armed men and seize anythingâpeople, goods, domestic animalsâthat could be easily carried off, then hold it hostage as security.[288] It didnât matter if the people or goods had belonged to the debtor, or even the debtorâs relatives. A neighborâs goats or children would do just as well, since the whole point was to bring social pressure on whoever owed the money. As William Bosman put it, âIf the Debtor be an honest man and the Debt just, he immediately endeavours by the satisfaction of his Creditors to free his Countrymen.â[289] It was actually a quite sensible expedient in an environment with no central authority, where people tended to feel an enormous sense of responsibility toward other members of their community and very little responsibility toward anyone else. In the case of the secret society cited above, the debtor would, presumably, be calling in his own debtsâreal or imaginedâto those outside the organization, in order not to have to send off members of his own family.[290]
Such expedients were not always effective. Often debtors would be forced to pawn more and more of their own children or dependents, until finally there was no recourse but to pawn themselves.[291] And of course, at the height of the slave trade, âpawningâ had become little more than a euphemism. The distinction between pawns and slaves had largely disappeared. Debtors, like their families before them, ended up turned over to the Aro, then to the British, and finally, shackled and chained, crowded into tiny slaving vessels and sent off to be sold on plantations across the sea.[292]
If the Tiv, then, were haunted by the vision of an insidious secret organization that lured unsuspecting victims into debt traps, whereby they themselves became the enforcers of debts to be paid with the bodies of their children, and ultimately, themselvesâone reason was because this was, literally happening to people who lived a few hundred miles away. Nor is the use of the phrase âflesh-debtâ in any way inappropriate. Slave-traders might not have been reducing their victims to meat, but they were certainly reducing them to nothing more than bodies. To be a slave was to be plucked from oneâs family, kin, friends, and community, stripped of oneâs name, identity, and dignity; of everything that made one a person rather than a mere human machine capable of understanding orders. Neither were most slaves offered much opportunity to develop enduring human relations. Most that ended up in Caribbean or American plantations, though, were simply worked to death.
What is remarkable is that all this was done, the bodies extracted, through the very mechanisms of the human economy, premised on the principle that human lives are the ultimate value, to which nothing could possibly compare. Instead, all the same institutionsâfees for initiations, means of calculating guilt and compensation, social currencies, debt pawnshipâwere turned into their opposite; the machinery was, as it were, thrown into reverse; and, as the Tiv also perceived, the gears and mechanisms designed for the creation of human beings collapsed on themselves and became the means for their destruction.
I do not want to leave the reader with the impression that what I am describing here is in any way peculiar to Africa. One could find the exact same things happening wherever human economies came into contact with commercial ones (and particularly, commercial economies with advanced military technology and an insatiable demand for human labor).
Remarkably similar things can be observed throughout Southeast Asia, particularly amongst hill and island people living on the fringes of major kingdoms. As the premier historian of the region, Anthony Reid, has pointed out, labor throughout Southeast Asia has long been organized above all through relations of debt bondage.
Even in relatively simple societies little penetrated by money, there were ritual needs for substantial expendituresâthe payment of bride-price for marriage and the slaughter of a buffalo at the death of a family member. It is widely reported that such ritual needs are the most common reason why the poor become indebted to the rich âŠ[293]
For instance, one practice, noted from Thailand to Sulawesi, is for a group of poor brothers to turn to a rich sponsor to pay for the expenses of one brotherâs marriage. Heâs then referred to as their âmaster.â This is more like a patron-client relation than anything else: the brothers might be obliged to do the occasional odd job, or appear as his entourage on occasions when he has to make a good impressionânot much more. Still, technically, he owns their children, and âcan also repossess the wife he provided if his bondsmen fail to carry out his obligations.â[294]
Elsewhere, we hear similar stories to those in Africaâof peasants pawning themselves or members of their families, or even gambling themselves into bondage; of principalities where penalties invariably took the form of heavy fines. âFrequently, of course, these fines could not be paid, and the condemned man, often accompanied by his dependants, became the bondsman of the ruler, of the injured party, or of whoever was able to pay his fine for him.â[295] Reid insists that most of this was relatively innocuousâin fact, poor men might take out loans for the express purpose of becoming debtors to some wealthy patron, who could provide them with food during hard times, a roof, a wife. Clearly this was not âslaveryâ in the ordinary sense. That is, unless the patron decided to ship some of his dependents off to creditors of his own in some distant city like Majapahit or Ternate, whereupon they might find themselves toiling in some grandeeâs kitchen or pepper plantation like any other slave.
Itâs important to point this out because one of the effects of the slave trade is that people who donât actually live in Africa are often left with an image of that continent as an irredeemably violent, savage placeâan image that has had disastrous effects on those who do live there. It might be fitting, then, to consider the history of one place that is usually represented as the polar opposite: Bali, the famous âland of ten thousand templesââan island often pictured in anthropological texts and tourist brochures as if it were inhabited exclusively by placid, dreamy artists who spend their days arranging flowers and practicing synchronized dance routines.
In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, Bali had not yet obtained this reputation. At the time, it was still divided among a dozen tiny, squabbling kingdoms in an almost perpetual state of war. In fact, its reputation among the Dutch merchants and officials ensconced in nearby Java was almost exactly the opposite of what it is today. Balinese were considered a rude and violent people ruled by decadent, opium-addicted nobles whose wealth was based almost exclusively on their willingness to sell their subjects to foreigners as slaves. By the time the Dutch were fully in control in Java, Bali had been turned largely into a reservoir for the export of human beingsâyoung Balinese women in particular being in great demand in cities through the region as both prostitutes and concubines.[296] As the island was drawn into the slave trade, almost the entire social and political system of the island was transformed into an apparatus for the forcible extraction of women. Even within villages, ordinary marriages took the form of âmarriage by captureââsometimes staged elopements, sometimes real forcible kidnappings, after which the kidnappers would pay a womanâs family to let the matter drop.[297] If a woman was captured by someone genuinely important, though, no compensation would be offered. Even in the 1960s, elders recalled how attractive young women used to be hidden away by their parents,
forbidden to bear towering offerings to temple festivals, lest they be espied by a royal scout and hustled into the closely protected female quarters of the palace, where the eyes of male visitors were restricted to foot level. For there was slim chance a girl would become a legitimate low-caste wife **(penawing)** of the raja ⊠More likely after affording a few yearsâ licentious satisfaction, she would degenerate into a slave-like servant.[298]
Or, if she did rise to such a position that the high-caste wives began to see her as a rival, she might be either poisoned or shipped off overseas to end up servicing soldiers at some Chinese-run bordello in Jogjakarta, or changing bedpans in the house of a French plantation-owner in the Indian Ocean island of Reunion.[299] Meanwhile, royal law codes were rewritten in all the usual ways, with the exception that here, the force of law was directed above all and explicitly against women. Not only were criminals and debtors to be enslaved and deported, but any married man was granted the power to renounce his wife, and by doing so render her, automatically, property of the local ruler, to be disposed of as he wished. Even a woman whose husband died before she had produced male offspring would to be handed over to the palace to be sold abroad.[300]
As Adrian Vickers explains, even Baliâs famous cockfightsâso familiar to any first-year anthropology studentâwere originally promoted by royal courts as a way of recruiting human merchandise:
Kings even helped put people into debt by staging large cockfights in their capitals. The passion and extravagance encouraged by this exciting sport led many peasants to bet more than they could afford. As with any gambling, the hope of great wealth and the drama of a contest fuelled ambitions which few could afford and at the end of the day, when the last spur had sunk into the chest of the last rooster, many peasants had no home and family to return to. They, and their wives and children, would be sold to Java.[301]
I began this book by asking a question: How is it that moral obligations between people come to be thought of as debts, and as a result, end up justifying behavior that would otherwise seem utterly immoral?
I began this chapter by beginning to propose an answer: by making a distinction between commercial economies and what I call âhuman economiesââthat is, those where money acts primarily as a social currency, to create, maintain, or sever relations between people rather than to purchase things. As RospabĂ© so cogently demonstrated, it is the peculiar quality of such social currencies that they are never quite equivalent to people. If anything, they are a constant reminder that human beings can never be equivalent to anythingâeven, ultimately, to one another. This is the profound truth of the blood-feud. No one can ever really forgive the man who killed his brother because every brother is unique. Nothing could substituteânot even some other man given the same name and status as your brother, or a concubine who will bear a son who will be named after your brother, or a ghost-wife who will bear a child pledged to someday avenge his death.
In a human economy, each person is unique, and of incomparable value, because each is a unique nexus of relations with others. A woman may be a daughter, sister, lover, rival, companion, mother, age-mate, and mentor to many different people in different ways. Each relation is unique, even in a society in which they are sustained through the constant giving back and forth of generic objects such as raffia cloth or bundles of copper wire. In one sense, those objects make one who one isâa fact illustrated by the way the objects used as social currencies are so often things otherwise used to clothe or decorate the human body, that help make one who one is in the eyes of others. Still, just as our clothes donât really make us who we are, a relationship kept alive by the giving and taking of raffia is always something more than that.[302] This means that the raffia, in turn, is always something less. This is why I think RospabĂ© was right to emphasize the fact that in such economies, money can never substitute for a person: money is a way of acknowledging that very fact, that the debt cannot be paid. But even the notion that a person can substitute for a person, that one sister can somehow be equated with another, is by no means self-evident. In this sense, the term âhuman economyâ is double-edged. These are, after all, **economies:** that is, systems of exchange in which qualities are reduced to quantities, allowing calculations of gain and lossâeven if those calculations are simply a matter (as in sister exchange) of 1 equals 1, or (as in the feud) of 1 minus 1 equals 0.
How is this calculability effectuated? How does it become possible to treat people as if they are identical? The Lele example gave us a hint: to make a human being an object of exchange, one woman equivalent to another for example, requires first of all ripping her from her context; that is, tearing her away from that web of relations that makes her the unique conflux of relations that she is, and thus, into a generic value capable of being added and subtracted and used as a means to measure debt. This requires a certain violence. To make her equivalent to a bar of camwood takes even more violence, and it takes an enormous amount of sustained and systematic violence to rip her so completely from her context that she becomes a slave.
I should be clear here. I am not using the word âviolenceâ metaphorically. I am not speaking merely of conceptual violence, but of the literal threat of broken bones and bruised flesh; of punches and kicks; in much the same way that when the ancient Hebrews spoke of their daughters in âbondage,â they were not being poetic, but talking about literal ropes and chains.
Most of us donât like to think much about violence. Those lucky enough to live relatively comfortable, secure lives in modern cities tend either to act as if it does not exist or, when reminded that it does, to write off the larger world âout thereâ as a terrible, brutal place, with not much that can be done to help it. Either instinct allows us not to have to think about the degree to which even our own daily existence is defined by violence or at least the threat of violence (as Iâve often noted, think about what would happen if you were to insist on your right to enter a university library without a properly validated ID), and to overstate the importanceâor at least the frequencyâof things like war, terrorism, and violent crime. The role of force in providing the framework for human relations is simply more explicit in what we call âtraditional societiesââeven if in many, actual physical assault by one human on another occurs less often than in our own. Hereâs a story from the Bunyoro kingdom, in East Africa:
Once a man moved into a new village. He wanted to find out what his neighbors were like, so in the middle of the night he pretended to beat his wife very severely, to see if the neighbors would come and remonstrate with him. But he did not really beat her; instead he beat a goatskin, while his wife screamed and cried out that he was killing her. Nobody came, and the very next day the man and his wife packed up and left that village and went to find some other place to live.[303]
The point is obvious. In a proper village, the neighbors should have rushed in, held him back, demanded to know what the woman could possibly have done to deserve such treatment. The dispute would become a collective concern that ended in some sort of collective settlement. This is how people ought to live. No reasonable man or woman would want to live in a place where neighbors donât look after one another.
In its own way itâs a revealing story, charming even, but one must still ask: How would a communityâeven one the man in the story would have considered a proper communityâhave reacted if they thought **she** was beating **him?[304]** I think we all know the answer. The first case would have led to concern; the second would have led to ridicule. In Europe in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, young villagers used to put on satirical skits making fun of husbands beaten by their wives, even to parade them about the town mounted backwards on an ass for everyone to jeer at.[305] No African society, as far as I know, went quite this far. (Neither did any African society burn as many witchesâWestern Europe at that time was a particularly savage place.) Yet as in most of the world, the assumption that the one sort of brutality was at least potentially legitimate, and that the other was not, was the framework within which relations between the sexes took place.[306]
What I want to emphasize is that there is a direct relation between that fact and the possibility of trading lives for one another. Anthropologists are fond of making diagrams to represent preferential marriage patterns. Sometimes, these diagrams can be quite beautiful:[307]
<em>Ideal pattern of bilateral cross-cousin marriage</em>
Sometimes they merely have a certain elegant simplicity, as in this diagram on an instance of Tiv sister exhange:[308]
Human beings, left to follow their own desires, rarely arrange themselves in symmetrical patterns. Such symmetry tends to be bought at a terrible human price. In the Tiv case, Akiga is actually willing to describe it:
Under the old system an elder who had a ward could always marry a young girl, however senile he might be, even if he were a leper with no hands or feet; no girl would dare to refuse him. If another man were attracted by his ward he would take his own and give her to the old man by force, in order to make an exchange. The girl had to go with the old man, sorrowfully carrying his goat-skin bag. If she ran back to her home her owner caught her and beat her, then bound her and brought her back to the elder. The old man was pleased, and grinned till he showed his blackened molars. âWherever you go,â he told her, âyou will be brought back here to me; so stop worrying, and settle down as my wife.â The girl fretted, till she wished the earth might swallow her. Some women even stabbed themselves to death when they were given to an old man against their will; but in spite of all, the Tiv did not care.[309]
The last line says everything. Citing it might seem unfair (the Tiv did, evidently, care enough to elect Akiga to be their first parliamentary representative, knowing he supported legislation to outlaw such practices), but it serves nicely to bring home the real point: that certain sorts of violence **were** considered morally acceptable.[310] No neighbors would rush in to intervene if a guardian was beating a runaway ward. Or if they did, it would be to insist that he use more gentle means to return her to her rightful husband. And it was because women knew that this is how their neighbors, or even parents, would react that âexchange marriageâ was possible.
This is what I mean by people âripped from their contexts.â
The Lele were fortunate enough to have largely escaped the devastations of the slave trade; the Tiv were sitting practically on the teeth of the shark, and they had to make heroic efforts to keep the threat at bay. Nonetheless, in both cases there were mechanisms for forcibly removing young women from their homes, and it was precisely this that made them exchangeableâthough in each case too, a principle stipulated that a woman could only be exchanged for another woman. The few exceptions, when women could be exchanged for other things, emerged directly from war and slaveryâthat is, when the level of violence was significantly ratcheted up.
The slave trade, of course, represented violence on an entirely different scale. We are speaking here of destruction of genocidal proportions, in world-historic terms, comparable only to events like the destruction of New World civilizations or the Holocaust. Neither do I mean in any way to blame the victims: we need only imagine what would be likely to happen in our own society if a group of space aliens suddenly appeared, armed with undefeatable military technology, infinite wealth, and no recognizable moralityâand announced that they were willing to pay a million dollars each for human workers, no questions asked. There will always be at least a handful of people unscrupulous enough to take advantage of such a situationâand a handful is all it takes.
Groups like the Aro Confederacy represent an all-too-familiar strategy, deployed by fascists, mafias, and right-wing gangsters everywhere: first unleash the criminal violence of an unlimited market, in which everything is for sale and the price of life becomes extremely cheap; then step in, offering to restore a certain measure of orderâthough one which in its very harshness leaves all the most profitable aspects of the earlier chaos intact. The violence is preserved within the structure of the law. Such mafias, too, almost invariably end up enforcing a strict code of honor in which morality becomes above all a matter of paying oneâs debts.
Were this a different book, I might reflect here on the curious parallels between the Cross River societies and Bali, both of which saw a magnificent outburst of artistic creativity (Cross River Ekpe masks were a major influence on Picasso) that took the form, above all, of an efflorescence of theatrical performance, replete with intricate music, splendid costumes, and stylized danceâa kind of alternative political order as imaginary spectacleâat the exact moment that ordinary life became a game of constant peril in which any misstep might lead to being sent away. What was the link between the two? Itâs an interesting question, but not one we can really answer here. For present purposes, the crucial question has to be: How common was this? The African slave trade was, as I mentioned, an unprecedented catastrophe, but commercial economies had already been extracting slaves from human economies for thousands of years. It is a practice as old as civilization. The question I want to ask is: To what degree is it actually constitutive of civilization itself?
I am not speaking strictly of slavery here, but of that process that dislodges people from the webs of mutual commitment, shared history, and collective responsibility that make them what they are, so as to make them exchangeableâthat is, to make it possible to make them subject to the logic of debt. Slavery is just the logical end-point, the most extreme form of such disentanglement. But for that reason it provides us with a window on the process as a whole. Whatâs more, owing to its historical role, slavery has shaped our basic assumptions and institutions in ways that we are no longer aware of and whose influence we would probably never wish to acknowledge if we were. If we have become a debt society, it is because the legacy of war, conquest, and slavery has never completely gone away. Itâs still there, lodged in our most intimate conceptions of honor, property, even freedom. Itâs just that we can no longer see that itâs there.
In the next chapter, I will begin to describe how this happened.
<em>ur<sub>5</sub> [HAR] :: n., liver; spleen; heart, soul; bulk, main body; foundation; loan; obligation; interest; surplus, profit; interest-bearing debt; repayment; slave-woman</em>.
âearly Sumerian dictionary[311]
<em>It is just to give each what is owed</em>.
âSimonides
In the last chapter, I offered a glimpse of how human economies, with their social currenciesâwhich are used to measure, assess, and maintain relationships between people, and only perhaps incidentally to acquire material goodsâmight be transformed into something else. What we discovered was that we cannot begin to think about such questions without taking into account the role of sheer physical violence. In the case of the African slave trade, this was primarily violence imposed from outside. Nonetheless, its very suddenness, its very brutality, provides us with a sort of freeze-frame of a process that must have occurred in a much slower, more haphazard fashion in other times and places. This is because there is every reason to believe that slavery, with its unique ability to rip human beings from their contexts, to turn them into abstractions, played a key role in the rise of markets everywhere.
What happens, then, when the same process happens more slowly? It would seem that much of this history is permanently lostâsince in both the ancient Middle East and the ancient Mediterranean, most of the really critical moments seem to have occurred just before the advent of written records. Still, the broad outlines can be reconstructed. The best way to do so, I believe, is to start from a single, odd, vexed concept: the concept of honor, which can be treated as a kind of artifact, or even as a hieroglyphic, a fragment preserved from history that seems to compress into itself the answer to almost everything weâve been trying to understand. On the one hand, violence: men who live by violence, whether soldiers or gangsters, are almost invariably obsessed with honor, and assaults on honor are considered the most obvious justification for acts of violence. On the other, debt. We speak both of debts of honor, and honoring oneâs debts; in fact, the transition from one to the other provides the best clue to how debts emerge from obligations; even as the notion of honor seemed to echo a defiant insistence that financial debts are not really the most important ones; an echo, here, of arguments that, like those in the Vedas and the Bible, go back to the very dawn of the market itself. Even more disturbingly, since the notion of honor makes no sense without the possibility of degradation, reconstructing this history reveals how much our basic concepts of freedom and morality took shape within institutionsânotably, but not only, slaveryâthat weâd sooner not have to think about at all.
To underscore some of the paradoxes surrounding the concept and bring home whatâs really at stake here, let us consider the story of one man who survived the Middle Passage: Olaudah Equiano, born sometime around 1745 in a rural community somewhere within the confines of the Kingdom of Benin. Kidnapped from his home at the age of eleven, Equiano was eventually sold to British slavers operating in the Bight of Biafra, from whence he was conveyed first to Barbados, then to a plantation in colonial Virginia.
Equianoâs further adventuresâand there were manyâare narrated in his autobiography, **The Interesting Narrative of the Life of Olaudah Equiano: or, Gustavus Vassa, the African**, published in 1789. After spending much of the Seven Yearsâ War hauling gunpowder on a British frigate, he was promised his freedom, denied his freedom, sold to several ownersâwho regularly lied to him, promising his freedom, and then broke their wordâuntil he passed into the hands of a Quaker merchant in Pennsylvania, who eventually allowed him to purchase his freedom. Over the course of his later years he was to become a successful merchant in his own right, a best-selling author, an Arctic explorer, and eventually, one of the leading voices of English Abolitionism. His eloquence and the power of his life story played significant parts in the movement that led to the British abolition of the slave trade in 1807.
Readers of Equianoâs book are often troubled by one aspect of the story: that for most of his early life, he was not opposed to the institution of slavery. At one point, while saving money to buy his freedom, he even briefly took a job that involved purchasing slaves in Africa. Equiano only came around to an abolitionist position after converting to Methodism and falling in with religious activists against the trade. Many have asked: Why did it take him so long? Surely if anyone had reason to understand the evils of slavery, he did.
The answer seems, oddly, to lie in the manâs very integrity. One thing that comes through strikingly in the book is that this was not only a man of endless resourcefulness and determination, but above all, a man of honor. Yet this created a terrible dilemma. To be made a slave is to be stripped of any possible honor. Equiano wished above all else to regain what had been taken from him. The problem is that honor is, by definition, something that exists in the eyes of others. To be able to recover it, then, a slave must necessarily adopt the rules and standards of the society that surrounds him, and this means that, in practice at least, he cannot absolutely reject the institutions that deprived him of his honor in the first place.
It strikes me that this experienceâof only being able to restore oneâs lost honor, to regain the ability to act with integrity by acting in accord with the terms of a system that one knows, through deeply traumatic personal experience, to be utterly unjustâis itself one of the most profoundly violent aspects of slavery. It is another example, perhaps, of the need to argue in the masterâs language, but here taken to insidious extremes.
All societies based on slavery tend to be marked by this agonizing double consciousness: the awareness that the highest things one has to strive for are also, ultimately, wrong; but at the same time, the feeling that this is simply the nature of reality. This might help explain why throughout most of history, when slaves did rebel against their masters, they rarely rebelled against slavery itself. But the flip side of this is that even slave-owners seemed to feel that the whole arrangement was somehow fundamentally perverse or unnatural. First-year Roman law students, for instance, were made to memorize the following definition:
slavery
is an institution according to the law of nations whereby one person falls under the property rights of another, contrary to nature.[312]
At the very least, there was always seen to be something disreputable and ugly about slavery. Anyone too close to it was tainted. Slave-traders particularly were scorned as inhuman brutes. Throughout history, moral justifications for slavery are rarely taken particularly seriously even by those who espouse them. For most of human history, most people saw slavery much as we see war: a tawdry business, to be sure, but one would have to be naĂŻve indeed to imagine it could simply be eliminated.
So what is slavery? Iâve already begun to suggest an answer in the last chapter. Slavery is the ultimate form of being ripped from oneâs context, and thus from all the social relationships that make one a human being. Another way to put this is that the slave is, in a very real sense, dead.
This was the conclusion of the first scholar to carry out a broad historical survey of the institution, an Egyptian sociologist named Ali âAbd al-Wahid Wafi, in Paris in 1931.[313] Everywhere, he observes, from the ancient world to then-present-day South America, one finds the same list of possible ways whereby a free person might be reduced to slavery:
1) By the law of force
a. By surrender or capture in war
b. By being the victim of raiding or kidnapping
2) As legal punishment for crimes (including debt)
3) Through paternal authority (a fatherâs sale of his children)
4) Through the voluntary sale of oneâs self[314]
Everywhere, too, capture in war is considered the only way that is considered absolutely legitimate. All the others were surrounded by moral problems. Kidnapping was obviously criminal, and parents would not sell children except under desperate circumstances.[315] We read of famines in China so severe that thousands of poor men would castrate themselves, in the hope that they might sell themselves as eunuchs at courtâbut this was also seen as the sign of total social breakdown.[316] Even the judicial process could easily be corrupted, as the ancients were well awareâespecially when it came to enslavement for debt.
On one level, al-Wahidâs argument is just an extended apologia for the role of slavery in Islamâwidely criticized, since Islamic law never eliminated slavery, even when the institution largely vanished in the rest of the Medieval world. True, he argues, Mohammed did not forbid the practice, but still, the early Caliphate was the first government we know of that actually succeeded in eliminating all these practices (judicial abuse, kidnappings, the sale of offspring) that had been recognized as social problems for thousands of years, and to limit slavery strictly to prisoners of war.
The bookâs most enduring contribution, though, lay simply in asking: What do all these circumstances have in common? Al-Wahidâs answer is striking in its simplicity: one becomes a slave in situations where one would otherwise have died. This is obvious in the case of war: in the ancient world, the victor was assumed to have total power over the vanquished, including their women and children; all of them could be simply massacred. Similarly, he argued, criminals were condemned to slavery only for capital crimes, and those who sold themselves, or their children, normally faced starvation.[317]
This is not just to say, though, that a slave was seen as owing his master his life since he would otherwise be dead.[318] Perhaps this was true at the moment of his or her enslavement. But after that, a slave could not owe debts, because in almost every important sense, a slave **was** dead. In Roman law, this was quite explicit. If a Roman soldier was captured and lost his liberty, his family was expected to read his will and dispose of his possessions. Should he later regain his freedom, he would have to start over, even to the point of remarrying the woman who was now considered his widow.[319]
In West Africa, according to one French anthropologist, the same principles applied:
Once he had been finally removed from his own milieu through capture the slave was considered as socially **dead**, just as if he had been vanquished and killed in combat. Among the Mande, at one time, prisoners of war brought home by the conquerors were offered **dege** (millet and milk porridge)âbecause it was held that a man should not die on an empty stomachâand then presented with their arms so that they could kill themselves. Anyone who refused was slapped on the face by his abductor and kept as a captive: he had accepted the contempt which deprived him of personality.[320]
Tiv horror stories about men who are dead but do not know it or who are brought back from the grave to serve their murderers, and Haitian zombie stories, all seem to play on this essential horror of slavery: the fact that itâs a kind of living death.
In a book called **Slavery and Social Death**âsurely the most profound comparative study of the institution yet writtenâOrlando Patterson works out exactly what it has meant to be so completely and absolutely ripped from oneâs context.[321] First of all, he emphasizes, slavery is unlike any other form of human relation because it is not a moral relation. Slave-owners might dress it up in all sorts of legalistic or paternalistic language, but really this is just window-dressing and no one really believes it; really, it is a relation based purely on violence; a slave must obey because if he doesnât, he can be beaten, tortured, or killed, and everyone is perfectly well aware of this. Second of all, being socially dead means that a slave has no binding moral relations with anyone else: he is alienated from his ancestors, community, family, clan, city; he cannot make contracts or meaningful promises, except at the whim of his master; even if he acquires a family, it can be broken up at any time. The relation of pure force that attached him to his master was hence the only human relationship that ultimately mattered. As a resultâand this is the third essential elementâthe slaveâs situation was one of utter degradation. Hence the Mande warriorâs slap: the captive, having refused his one final chance to save his honor by killing himself, must recognize that he will now be considered an entirely contemptible being.[322]
Yet at the same time, this ability to strip others of their dignity becomes, for the master, the foundation of his honor. As Patterson notes, there have been placesâthe Islamic world affords numerous examplesâwhere slaves are not even put to work for profit; instead, rich men make a point of surrounding themselves with battalions of slave retainers simply for reasons of status, as tokens of their magnificence and nothing else.
It seems to me that this is precisely what gives honor its notoriously fragile quality. Men of honor tend to combine a sense of total ease and self-assurance, which comes with the habit of command, with a notorious jumpiness, a heightened sensitivity to slights and insults, the feeling that a man (and it is almost always a man) is somehow reduced, humiliated, if any âdebt of honorâ is allowed to go unpaid. This is because honor is not the same as dignity. One might even say: honor is surplus dignity. It is that heightened consciousness of power, and its dangers, that comes from having stripped away the power and dignity of others; or at the very least, from the knowledge that one is capable of doing so. At its simplest, honor is that excess dignity that must be defended with the knife or sword (violent men, as we all know, are almost invariably obsessed with honor). Hence the warriorâs ethos, where almost anything that could possibly be seen as a sign of disrespectâin inappropriate word, an inappropriate glanceâis considered a challenge, or can be treated as such. Yet even where overt violence has largely been put out of the picture, wherever honor is at issue, it comes with a sense that dignity **can** be lost, and therefore must be constantly defended.
The result is that to this day, âhonorâ has two contradictory meanings. On the one hand, we can speak of honor as simple integrity. Decent people honor their commitments. This is clearly what âhonorâ meant for Equiano: to be an honorable man meant to be one who speaks the truth, obeys the law, keeps his promises, is fair and conscientious in his commercial dealings.[323] His problem was that honor simultaneously meant something else, which had everything to do with the kind of violence required to reduce human beings to commodities to begin with.
The reader might be asking: But what does all this have to do with the origins of money? The answer is, surprisingly: everything. Some of the most genuinely archaic forms of money we know about appear to have been used precisely as measures of honor and degradation: that is, the value of money was, ultimately, the value of the power to turn others into money. The curious puzzle of the **cumal**âthe slave-girl money of medieval Irelandâwould appear to be a dramatic illustration.
For much of its early history, Irelandâs situation was not very different than that in many of the African societies we looked at in the end of the last chapter. It was a human economy perched uncomfortably on the fringe of an expanding commercial one. Whatâs more, at certain periods there was a very lively slave trade. As one historian put it, âIreland has no mineral wealth, and foreign luxury goods could be bought by Irish kings mainly for two export goods, cattle and people.â[324] Hardly surprising, perhaps, that cattle and people were the two major denominations of the currency. Still, by the time our earliest records kick in, around 600AD, the slave trade appears to have died off, and slavery itself was a waning institution, coming under severe disapproval from the Church.[325] Why, then, were cumal still being used as units of account, to tally up debts that were actually paid out in cows, and in cups and brooches and other objects made of silver, or, in the case of minor transactions, sacks of wheat or oats? And thereâs an even more obvious question: Why **women?** There were plenty of male slaves in early Ireland, yet no one seems ever to have used them as money.
Most of what we know about the economy of early Medieval Ireland comes from legal sourcesâa series of law codes, drawn up by a powerful class of jurists, dating roughly from the seventh to ninth centuries ad. These, however, are exceptionally rich. Ireland at that time was still very much a human economy. It was also a very rural one: people lived in scattered homesteads, not unlike the Tiv, growing wheat and tending cattle. The closest there were to towns were a few concentrations around monasteries. There appears to have been a near total absence of markets, except for a few on the coastâpresumably, mainly slave or cattle marketsâfrequented by foreign ships.[326]
As a result, money was employed almost exclusively for social purposes: gifts; fees to craftsmen, doctors, poets, judges, and entertainers; various feudal payments (lords gave gifts of cattle to clients who then had to regularly supply them with food). The authors of the law codes didnât even know how to put a price on most goods of ordinary useâpitchers, pillows, chisels, slabs of bacon, and the like; no one seems ever to have paid money for them.[327] Food was shared in families or delivered to feudal superiors, who laid it out in sumptuous feasts for friends, rivals, and retainers. Anyone needing a tool or furniture or clothing either went to a kinsman with the relevant craft skills or paid someone to make it. The objects themselves were not for sale. Kings, in turn, assigned tasks to different clans: this one was to provide them with leather, this one poets, this one shields ⊠precisely the sort of unwieldy arrangement that markets were later developed to get around.[328]
Money could be loaned. There was a highly complex system of pledges and sureties to guarantee that debtors delivered what they owed. Mainly, though, it was used for paying fines. These fines are endlessly and meticulously elaborated in the codes, but what really strikes the contemporary observer is that they were carefully graded by rank. This is true of almost all the âBarbarian Law Codesââthe size of the penalties usually has at least as much do with the status of the victim as it does with the nature of the injuryâbut only in Ireland were things mapped out quite so systematically.
The key to the system was a notion of honor: literally âface.â[329] Oneâs honor was the esteem one had in the eyes of others, oneâs honesty, integrity, and character, but also oneâs power, in the sense of the ability to protect oneself, and oneâs family and followers, from any sort of degradation or insult. Those who had the highest degree of honor were literally sacred beings: their persons and possessions were sacrosanct. What was so unusual about Celtic systemsâand the Irish one went further with this than any otherâwas that honor could be precisely quantified. Every free person had his or her âhonor priceâ: the price that one had to pay for an insult to the personâs dignity. These varied. The honor price of a king, for instance, was seven cumal, or seven slave girlsâthis was the standard honor price for any sacred being, the same as a bishop or master poet. Since (as all sources hasten to point out) slave girls were not normally paid as such, this would mean, in the case of an insult to such a personâs dignity, one would have to pay twenty-one milk cows or twenty-one ounces of silver.[330] The honor price of a wealthy peasant was two and a half cows, of a minor lord, that, plus half a cow additionally for each of his free dependentsâand since a lord, to remain a lord, had to have at least five of these, that brought him up to at least five cows total.[331]
Honor price is not to be confused with wergeldâthe actual price of a man or womanâs life. If one killed a man, one paid goods to the value of seven cumals, in recompense for killing him, to which one then added his honor price, for having offended against his dignity (by killing him). Interestingly, only in the case of a king are the blood price and his honor price the same.
There were also payments for injury: if one wounds a manâs cheek, one pays his honor price plus the price of the injury. (A blow to the face was, for obvious reasons, particularly egregious.) The problem was how to calculate the injury, since this varied according to both the physical damage and status of the injured party. Here, Irish jurists developed the ingenious expedient of measuring different wounds with different varieties of grain: a cut on the kingâs cheek was measured in grains of wheat, on that of a substantial farmer in oats, on that of a smallholder merely in peas. One cow was paid for each.[332] Similarly, if one stole, say, a manâs brooch or pig, one had to pay back three brooches or three pigsâplus his honor price, for having violated the sanctity of his homestead. Attacking a peasant under the protection of a lord was the same as raping a manâs wife or daughter, a violation of the honor not of the victim, but of the man who should have been able to protect them.
Finally, one had to pay the honor price if one simply insulted someone of any importance: say, by turning the person away at a feast, inventing a particularly embarrassing nickname (at least, if it caught on), or humiliating the person through the use of satire.[333] Mockery was a refined art in Medieval Ireland, and poets were considered close to magicians: it was said that a talented satirist could rhyme rats to death, or at the very least, raise blisters on the faces of victims. Any man publicly mocked would have no choice but to defend his honor; and, in Medieval Ireland, the value of that honor was precisely defined.
I should note that while twenty-one cows might not seem like much when we are dealing with kings, Ireland at the time had about 150 kings.[334] Most had only a couple of thousand subjects, though there were also higher-ranking, provincial kings for whom the honor price was double.[335] Whatâs more, since the legal system was completely separate from the political one, jurists, in theory, had the right the demote anyoneâincluding a kingâwho had committed a dishonorable act. If a nobleman turned a worthy man away from his door or feast, sheltered a fugitive, or ate steak from an obviously stolen cow, or even if he allowed himself to be satirized and did not take the offending poet to court, his price could be lowered to that of a commoner. But the same was true of a king who ran away in battle, or abused his powers, or even was caught working in the fields or otherwise engaging in tasks beneath his dignity. A king who did something utterly outrageousâmurdered one of his own relatives, for exampleâmight end up with no honor price at all, which meant not that people could say anything they liked about the king, without fear of recompense, but that he couldnât stand as surety or witness in court, as oneâs oath and standing in law was also determined by oneâs honor price. This didnât happen often, but it did happen, and legal wisdom made sure to remind people of it: the list, contained in one famous legal text, of the âseven kings who lost their honor price,â was meant to ensure that everyone remembered that no matter how sacred and powerful, anyone could fall.
Whatâs unusual about the Irish material is that itâs all spelled out so clearly. This is partly because Irish law codes were the work of a class of legal specialists who seem to have turned the whole thing almost into a form of entertainment, devoting endless hours to coming up with every possible abstract possibility. Some of the provisos are so whimsical (âif stung by another manâs bee, one must calculate the extent of the injury, but also, if one swatted it in the process, subtract the replacement value of the beeâ) that one has to assume they were simply jokes. Still, as a result, the moral logic that lies behind any elaborate code of honor is laid out here in startling honesty. What about women? A free woman was honored at precisely 50 percent of the price of her nearest male relative (her father, if alive; if not, her husband). If she was dishonored, her price was payable to that relative. Unless, that is, she was an independent landholder. In that case, her honor price was the same as that of a man. And unless she was a woman of easy virtue, in which case it was zero, since she had no honor to outrage. What about marriage? A suitor paid the value of the wifeâs honor to her father and thus became its guardian. What about serfs? The same principle applied: when a lord acquired a serf, he bought out that manâs honor price, presenting him with its equivalent in cows. From that moment on, if anyone insulted or injured the serf, it was seen an attack on the lordâs honor, and it was up to the lord to collect the attendant fees. Meanwhile the lordâs honor price was notched upward as a result of gathering another dependent: in other words, he literally absorbs his new vassalâs honor into his own.[336]
All this, in turn, makes it possible to understand both something of the nature of honor, and why slave girls were kept as units for reckoning debts of honor even at a time whenâowing no doubt to church influenceâthey no longer actually changed hands. At first sight it might seem strange that the honor of a nobleman or king should be measured in slaves, since slaves were human beings whose honor was zero. But if oneâs honor is ultimately founded on oneâs ability to extract the honor of others, it makes perfect sense. The value of a slave is that of the honor that has been extracted from them.
Sometimes, one comes on a single haphazard detail that gives the game away. In this case it comes not from Ireland but from the Dimetian Code in Wales, written somewhat later but operating on much the same principles. At one point, after listing the honors due to the seven holy sees of the Kingdom of Dyfed, whose bishops and abbots were the most exalted and sacred creatures in the kingdom, the text specifies that
Whoever draws blood from an abbot of any one of those principal seats before mentioned, let him pay seven pounds; and a female of his kindred to be a washerwoman, as a disgrace to the kindred, and to serve as a memorial to the payment of the honor price.[337]
A washerwoman was the lowest of servants, and the one turned over in this case was to serve for life. She was, in effect, reduced to slavery. Her permanent disgrace was the restoration of the abbotâs honor. While we cannot know if some similar institution once lay behind the habit of reckoning the honor of Irish âsacredâ beings in slave-women, the principle is clearly the same. Honor is a zero-sum game. A manâs ability to protect the women of his family is an essential part of that honor. Therefore, forcing him to surrender a woman of his family to perform menial and degrading chores in anotherâs household is the ultimate blow to his honor. This, in turn, makes it the ultimate reaffirmation of the honor of he who takes it away.
What makes Medieval Irish laws seem so peculiar from our perspective is that their exponents had not the slightest discomfort with putting an exact monetary price on human dignity. For us, the notion that the sanctity of a priest or the majesty of a king could be held equivalent to a million fried eggs or a hundred thousand haircuts is simply bizarre. These are precisely the things that ought to be considered beyond all possibility of quantification. If Medieval Irish jurists felt otherwise, it was because people at that time did not use money to buy eggs or haircuts.[338] It was the fact that it was still a human economy, in which money was used for social purposes, that it was possible to create such an intricate system whereby it was possible not just to measure but to add and subtract specific quantities of human dignityâand in doing so, provide us with a unique window into the true nature of honor itself.
The obvious question is: What happens to such an economy when people do begin to use the same money used to measure dignity to buy eggs and haircuts? As the history of ancient Mesopotamia and the Mediterranean world reveals, the result was a profoundâand enduringâmoral crisis.
In ancient Greek, the word for âhonorâ was **tÄ«me**. In Homerâs time, the term appears to have been used much like the Irish term âhonor priceâ: it referred both to the glory of the warrior and the compensation paid as damages in case of injury or insult. Yet with the rise of markets over the next several centuries, the meaning of the word **tÄ«me** began to change. On the one hand, it became the word for âpriceââas in, the price of something one buys in the market. On the other, it referred to an attitude of complete contempt for markets.
Actually, this is still the case today:
In Greece the word âtimiâ means honor, which has been typically seen as the most important value in Greek village society. Honor is often characterized in Greece as an open-handed generosity and blatant disregard for monetary costs and counting. And yet the same word also means âpriceâ as in the price of a pound of tomatoes.[339]
The word âcrisisâ literally refers to a crossroads: it is the point where things could go either of two different ways. The odd thing about the crisis in the concept of honor is that it never seems to have been resolved. Is honor the willingness to pay oneâs monetary debts? Or is it the fact that one does not feel that monetary debts are really that important? It appears to be both at the same time.
Thereâs also the question of what men of honor actually **do** think is important. When most of us think of a Mediterranean villagerâs sense of honor, we donât think so much of a casual attitude toward money as of a veritable obsession with premarital virginity. Masculine honor is caught up not even so much in a manâs ability to protect his womenfolk as in his ability to protect their sexual reputations, to respond to any suggestion of impropriety on the part of his mother, wife, sister, or daughter as if it were a direct physical attack on his own person. This is a stereotype, but itâs not entirely unjustified. One historian who went through fifty years of police reports about knife-fights in nineteenth-century Ionia discovered that virtually every one of them began when one party publicly suggested that the otherâs wife or sister was a whore.[340]
So, why the sudden obsession with sexual propriety? It doesnât seem to be there in the Welsh or Irish material. There, the greatest humiliation was to see your sister or daughter reduced to scrubbing someone elseâs laundry. What is it, then, about the rise of money and markets that cause so many men to become so uneasy about sex?[341]
This is a difficult question, but at the very least, one can imagine how the transition from a human economy to a commercial one might cause certain moral dilemmas. What happens, for instance, when the same money once used to arrange marriages and settle affairs of honor can also be used to pay for the services of prostitutes?
As weâll see, there is reason to believe that it is in such moral crises that we can find the origin not only of our current conceptions of honor, but of patriarchy itself. This is true, at least, if we define âpatriarchyâ in its more specific Biblical sense: the rule of fathers, with all the familiar images of stern bearded men in robes, keeping a close eye over their sequestered wives and daughters, even as their children kept a close eye over their flocks and herds, familiar from the book of Genesis.[342] Readers of the Bible had always assumed that there was something primordial in all this; that this was simply the way desert people, and thus the earliest inhabitants of the Near East, had always behaved. This was why the translation of Sumerian, in the first half of the twentieth century, came as something of a shock.
In the very earliest Sumerian texts, particularly those from roughly 3000 to 2500 bc, women are everywhere. Early histories not only record the names of numerous female rulers, but make clear that women were well represented among the ranks of doctors, merchants, scribes, and public officials, and generally free to take part in all aspects of public life. One cannot speak of full gender equality: men still outnumbered women in all these areas. Still, one gets the sense of a society not so different than that which prevails in much of the developed world today. Over the course of the next thousand years or so, all this changes. The place of women in civic life erodes; gradually, the more familiar patriarchal pattern takes shape, with its emphasis on chastity and premarital virginity, a weakening and eventually wholesale disappearance of womenâs role in government and the liberal professions, and the loss of womenâs independent legal status, which renders them wards of their husbands. By the end of the Bronze Age, around 1200 bc, we begin to see large numbers of women sequestered away in harems and (in some places, at least), subjected to obligatory veiling.
In fact, this appears to reflect a much broader worldwide pattern. It has always been something of a scandal for those who like to see the advance of science and technology, the accumulation of learning, economic growthââhuman progress,â as we like to call itâas necessarily leading to greater human freedom, that for women, the exact opposite often seems to be the case. Or at least, has been the case until very recent times. A similar gradual restriction on womenâs freedoms can be observed in India and China. The question is, obviously, Why? The standard explanation in the Sumerian case has been the gradual infiltration of pastoralists from the surrounding deserts who, presumably, always had more patriarchal mores. There was, after all, only a narrow strip of land along the Tigris and Euphrates rivers that could support intensive irrigation works, and hence, urban life. Civilization was thus from early times surrounded by a fringe of desert people, who lived much like those described in Genesis and spoke the same Semitic languages. It is undeniably true that, over the course of time, the Sumerian language was gradually replacedâfirst by Akkadian, then by Amorite, then by Aramaic languages, and finally, most recently of all, by Arabic, which was also brought to Mesopotamia and the Levant by desert pastoralists. While all this did, clearly, bring with it profound cultural changes as well, itâs not a particularly satisfying explanation.[343] Former nomads appear to have been willing to adapt to urban life in any number of other ways. Why not that one? And itâs very much a local explanation and does nothing, really, to explain the broader pattern. Feminist scholarship has instead tended to emphasize the growing scale and social importance of war, and the increasing centralization of the state that accompanied it.[344] This is more convincing. Certainly, the more militaristic the state, the harsher its laws tended to be toward women. But I would add another, complementary argument. As I have emphasized, historically, war, states, and markets all tend to feed off one another. Conquest leads to taxes. Taxes tend to be ways to create markets, which are convenient for soldiers and administrators. In the specific case of Mesopotamia, all of this took on a complicated relation to an explosion of debt that threatened to turn all human relationsâand by extension, womenâs bodiesâinto potential commodities. At the same time, it created a horrified reaction on the part of the (male) winners of the economic game, who over time felt forced to go to greater and greater lengths to make clear that **their** women could in no sense be bought or sold.
A glance at the existing material on Mesopotamian marriage gives us a clue as to how this might have happened.
It is common anthropological wisdom that bridewealth tends to be typical of situations where population is relatively thin, land not a particularly scarce resource, and therefore, politics are all about controlling labor. Where population is dense and land at a premium, one tends to instead find dowry: adding a woman to the household is adding another mouth to feed, and rather than being paid off, a brideâs father is expected to contribute something (land, wealth, money âŠ) to help support his daughter in her new home.[345] In Sumerian times, for instance, the main payment at marriage was a huge gift of food paid by the groomâs father to the brideâs, destined to provide a sumptuous feast for the wedding.[346] Before long, however, this seems to have split into two payments, one for the wedding, another to the womanâs father, calculatedâand often paidâin silver.[347] Wealthy women sometimes appear to have ended up with the money: at least, many appear to have to worn silver arm and leg rings of identical denominations.
However as time went on, this payment, called the **terhatum**, often began to take on the qualities of a simple purchase. It was referred to as âthe price of a virginâânot a mere metaphor, since the illegal deflowering of a virgin was considered a property crime against her father.[348] Marriage was referred to as âtaking possessionâ of a woman, the same word one would use for the seizure of goods.[349] In principle, a wife, once possessed, owed her husbands strict obedience, and often could not seek a divorce even in cases of physical abuse.
For women with wealthy or powerful parents, all this remained largely a matter of principle, modified considerably in practice. Merchantsâ daughters, for example, typically received substantial cash dowries, with which they could go into business in their own right, or act as partners to their husbands. However, for the poorâthat is, most peopleâmarriage came more and more to resemble a simple cash transaction.
Some of this must have been an effect of slavery: while actual slaves were rarely numerous, the very existence of a class of people with no kin, who were simply commodities, did make a difference. In Nuzi, for instance, âthe brideprice was paid in domestic animals and silver amounting to a total value of 40 shekels of silverâââto which the author drily adds, âthere is some evidence that it was equal to the price of a slave girl.â[350] This must have been making things uncomfortably obvious. Itâs in Nuzi, too, where we happen to have unusually detailed records, that we find examples of rich men paying cut-rate âbridepriceâ to impoverished families to acquire a daughter who they would then adopt, but who would in fact be either kept as a concubine or nursemaid, or married to one of their slaves.[351]
Still, the really critical factor here was debt. As I pointed out in the last chapter, anthropologists have long emphasized that paying bridewealth is not the same as buying a wife. After allâand this was one of the clinching arguments, remember, in the original 1930s League of Nations debateâif a man were really buying a woman, wouldnât he also be able to sell her? Clearly African and Melanesian husbands were not able to sell their wives to some third party. At most, they could send them home and demand back their bridewealth.[352]
A Mesopotamian husband couldnât sell his wife either. Or, normally he couldnât. Still, everything changed the moment he took out a loan. Since if he did, it was perfectly legalâas weâve seenâto use his wife and children as surety, and if he was unable to pay, they could then be taken away as debt pawns in exactly the same way that he could lose his slaves, sheep, and goats. What this also meant was that honor and credit became, effectively, the same thing: at least for a poor man, oneâs creditworthiness was precisely oneâs command over oneâs household, and (the flip side, as it were) relations of domestic authority, relations that in principle meant ones of care and protection, became property rights that could indeed be bought and sold.
Again, for the poor, this meant that family members became commodities that could be rented or sold. Not only could one dispose of daughters as âbridesâ to work in rich menâs households, tablets in Nuzi show that one could now hire out family members simply by taking out a loan: there are recorded cases of men sending their sons or even wives as âpawnsâ for loans that were clearly just advance payment for employment in the lenderâs farm or cloth workshop.[353]
The most dramatic and enduring crisis centered on prostitution. Itâs actually not entirely clear, from the earliest sources, whether one can speak here of âprostitutionâ at all. Sumerian temples do often appear to have hosted a variety of sexual activities. Some priestesses, for instance, were considered to be married to or otherwise dedicated to gods. What this meant in practice seems to have varied considerably. Much as in the case of the later **devadasis**, or âtemple dancersâ of Hindu India, some remained celibate; others were permitted to marry but were not to bear children; others were apparently expected to find wealthy patrons, becoming in effect courtesans to the elite. Still others lived in the temples and had the responsibility to make themselves sexually available to worshippers on certain ritual occasions.[354] One thing the early texts do make clear is that all such women were considered extraordinarily important. In a very real sense, they were the ultimate embodiments of civilization. After all, the entire machinery of the Sumerian economy ostensibly existed to support the temples, which were considered the households of the gods. As such, they represented the ultimate possible refinement in everything from music and dance to art, cuisine, and graciousness of living. Temple priestesses and spouses of the gods were the highest human incarnations of this perfect life.
Itâs also important to emphasize that Sumerian men do not appear, at least in this earliest period, to have seen anything troubling about the idea of their sisters having sex for money. To the contrary, insofar as prostitution did occur (and remember, it could not have been nearly so impersonal, cold-cash a relation in a credit economy), Sumerian religious texts identify it as among the fundamental features of human civilization, a gift given by the gods at the dawn of time. Procreative sex was considered natural (after all, animals did it). Non-procreative sex, sex for pleasure, was divine.[355]
The most famous expression of this identification of prostitute and civilization can be found in the story of Enkidu in the epic of Gilgamesh. In the beginning of the story, Enkidu is a monsterâa naked and ferocious âwild manâ who grazes with the gazelles, drinks at the watering place with wild cattle, and terrorizes the people of the city. Unable to defeat him, the citizens finally send out a courtesan who is also a priestess of the goddess Ishtar. She strips before him, and they make love for six days and seven nights. Afterward, Enkiduâs former animal companions run away from him. After she explains that he has now learned wisdom and become like a God (she is, after all, a divine consort), he agrees to put on clothing and come to live in the city like a proper, civilized human being.[356]
Already, in the earliest version of the Enkidu story, though, one can detect a certain ambivalence. Much later, Enkidu is sentenced to death by the gods, and his immediate reaction is to condemn the courtesan for having brought him from the wilds in the first place: he curses her to become a common streetwalker or tavern keeper, living among vomiting drunks, abused and beaten by her clients. Then, later, he regrets his behavior and blesses her instead. But that trace of ambivalence was there from the beginning, and over time, it grew more powerful. From early times, Sumerian and Babylonian temple complexes were surrounded by far less glamorous providers of sexual servicesâindeed, by the time we know much about them, they were the center of veritable red-light districts full of taverns with dancing girls, men in drag (some of them slaves, some runaways), and an almost infinite variety of prostitutes. There is an endlessly elaborate terminology whose subtleties are long since lost to us. Most seem to have doubled as entertainers: tavern-keepers doubled as musicians; male transvestites were not only singers and dancers, but often performed knife-throwing acts. Many were slaves put to work by their masters, or women working off religious vows or debts, or debt bondswomen, or, for that matter, women escaping debt bondage with no place else to go. Over time, many of the lower-ranking temple women were either bought as slaves or debt peons as well, and there might have often been a blurring of roles between priestesses who performed erotic rituals and prostitutes owned by the temple (and hence, in principle, by the god), sometimes lodged within the temple compound itself, whose earnings added to the temple treasuries.[357] Since most everyday transactions in Mesopotamia were not cash transactions, once has to assume that it was the same with prostitutesâlike the tavern-keepers, many of whom seem to have been former prostitutes, they developed ongoing credit relations with their clientsâand this must have meant that most were less like what we think of as streetwalkers and more like courtesans.[358] Still, the origins of commercial prostitution appear to have been caught up in a peculiar mixture of sacred (or once-sacred) practice, commerce, slavery, and debt.
âPatriarchyâ originated, first and foremost, in a rejection of the great urban civilizations in the name of a kind of purity, a reassertion of paternal control against great cities like Uruk, Lagash, and Babylon, seen as places of bureaucrats, traders, and whores. The pastoral fringes, the deserts and steppes away from the river valleys, were the places to which displaced, indebted farmers fled. Resistance, in the ancient Middle East, was always less a politics of rebellion than a politics of exodus, of melting away with oneâs flocks and familiesâoften before both were taken away.[359] There were always tribal peoples living on the fringes. During good times, they began to take to the cities; in hard times, their numbers swelled with refugeesâfarmers who effectively became Enkidu once again. Then, periodically, they would create their own alliances and sweep back into the cities once again as conquerors. Itâs difficult to say precisely how they imagined their situation, because itâs only in the Old Testament, written on the other side of the Fertile Crescent, that one has any record of the pastoral rebelsâ points of view. But nothing there mitigates against the suggestion that the extraordinary emphasis we find there on the absolute authority of fathers, and the jealous protection of their fickle womenfolk, were made possible by, but at the same time a protest against, this very commoditization of people in the cities that they fled.
The worldâs Holy Booksâthe Old and New Testaments, the Koran, religious literature from the Middle Ages to this dayâecho this voice of rebellion, combining contempt for the corrupt urban life, suspicion of the merchant, and often, intense misogyny. One need only think of the image of Babylon itself, which has become permanently lodged in the collective imagination as not only the cradle of civilization, but also the Place of Whores. Herodotus echoed popular Greek fantasies when he claimed that every Babylonian maiden was obliged to prostitute herself at the temple, so as to raise the money for her dowry.[360] In the New Testament, Saint Peter often referred to Rome as âBabylon,â and the Book of Revelation provides perhaps the most vivid image of what he meant by this when it speaks of Babylon, âthe great whore,â sitting âupon a scarlet colored beast, full of names of blasphemyâ:
17:4 And the woman was arrayed in purple and scarlet color, and decked with gold and precious stones and pearls, having a golden cup in her hand full of abominations and filthiness of her fornication:
17:5 And upon her forehead was a name written, mystery, babylon the great, the mother of harlots and abominations of the earth.[361]
Such is the voice of patriarchal hatred of the city, and of the angry millennial voices of the fathers of the ancient poor.
Patriarchy as we know it seems to have taken shape in a see-sawing battle between the newfound elites and newly dispossessed. Much of my own analysis here is inspired by the brilliant work of feminist historian Gerda Lerner, who, in an essay on the origins of prostitution, observed:
Another source for commercial prostitution was the pauperization of farmers and their increasing dependence on loans in order to survive periods of famine, which led to debt slavery. Children of both sexes were given up for debt pledges or sold for âadoption.â Out of such practices, the prostitution of female family members for the benefit of the head of the family could readily develop. Women might end up as prostitutes because their parents had to sell them into slavery or because their impoverished husbands might so use them. Or they might become self-employed as a last alternative to enslavement. With luck, they might in this profession be upwardly mobile through becoming concubines.
By the middle of the second millennium B.C., prostitution was well established as a likely occupation for the daughters of the poor. As the sexual regulation of women of the propertied class became more firmly entrenched, the virginity of respectable daughters became a financial asset for the family. Thus, commercial prostitution came to be seen as a social necessity for meeting the sexual needs of men. What remained problematic was how to distinguish clearly and permanently between respectable and non-respectable women.
This last point is crucial. The most dramatic known attempt to solve the problem, Lerner observes, can be found in a Middle Assyrian law code dating from somewhere between 1400 and 1100 bc, which is also the first known reference to veiling in the history of the Middle Eastâand also, Lerner emphasizes, first to make the policing of social boundaries the responsibility of the state.[362] It is not surprising that this takes place under the authority of perhaps the most notoriously militaristic state in the entire ancient Middle East.
The code carefully distinguishes among five classes of women. Respectable women (either married ladies or concubines), widows, and daughters of free Assyrian menââmust veil themselvesâ when they go out on the street. Prostitutes and slaves (and prostitutes are now considered to include unmarried temple servants as well as simple harlots) are not allowed to wear veils. The remarkable thing about the laws is that the punishments specified in the code are not directed at respectable women who do not wear veils, but against prostitutes and slaves who do. The prostitute was to be publicly beaten fifty times with staves and have pitch poured on her head; the slave girl was to have her ears cut off. Free men proven to have knowingly abetted an impostor would also be thrashed and put to a monthâs forced labor.
Presumably in the case of respectable women, the law was assumed to be self-enforcing: as what respectable woman would wish to go out on the street in the guise of a prostitute?
When we refer to ârespectableâ women, then, we are referring to those whose bodies could not, under any conditions, be bought or sold. Their physical persons were hidden away and permanently relegated to some manâs domestic sphere; when they appeared in public veiled, they were effectively still ostentatiously walking around, even in public, inside such a sphere.[363] Women who could be exchanged for money, on the other hand, must be instantly recognizable as such.
The Assyrian law code is one isolated instance; veils certainly did not become obligatory everywhere after 1300 bc. But it provides a window on developments that were happening, however unevenly, even spasmodically, across the region, propelled by the intersection of commerce, class, defiant assertions of male honor, and the constant threat of the defection of the poor. States seem to have played a complex dual role, simultaneously fostering commoditization and intervening to ameliorate its effects: enforcing the laws of debt and rights of fathers, and offering periodic amnesties. But the dynamic also led, over the course of millennia, to a systematic demotion of sexuality itself from a divine gift and embodiment of civilized refinement to one of its more familiar associations: with degradation, corruption, and guilt.
Here I think we have the explanation for that general decline of womenâs freedoms that may be observed in all the great urban civilizations for so much of their history. In all of them, similar things were happening, even if in each case, the pieces came together in different ways.
The history of China, for instance, saw continual and largely unsuccessful government campaigns to eradicate both brideprice and debt slavery, and periodic scandals over the existence of âmarkets in daughters,â including the outright sale of girls as daughters, wives, concubines, or prostitutes (at the buyerâs discretion) continue to this day.[364] In India, the caste system allowed what were otherwise differences between rich and poor to be made formal and explicit. Brahmins and other members of the upper castes jealously sequestered their daughters, and married them off with lavish dowries, while the lower castes practiced brideprice, allowing members of the higher (âtwice-bornâ) castes to scoff at them for selling their daughters. The twice-born were likewise largely protected from falling into debt bondage, while for much of the rural poor, debt dependency was institutionalized, with the daughters of poor debtors, predictably, often dispatched to brothels or to the kitchens or laundries of the rich.[365] In either case, between the push of commoditization, which fell disproportionally on daughters, and the pull of those trying to reassert patriarchal rights to âprotectâ women from any suggestion that they might be commoditized, womenâs formal and practical freedoms appear to have been gradually but increasingly restricted and effaced. As a result, notions of honor changed too, becoming a kind of protest against the implications of the market, even as at the same time (like the world religions) they came to echo that market logic in endless subtle ways.
Nowhere, however, are our sources as rich and detailed as they are for ancient Greece. This is partly because a commercial economy arrived there so late, almost three thousand years later than in Sumer. As a result, Classical Greek literature gives us a unique opportunity to observe the transformation as it was actually taking place.
The world of the Homeric epics is one dominated by heroic warriors who are disdainful of trade. In many ways, it is strikingly reminiscent of medieval Ireland. Money existed, but it was not used to buy anything; important men lived their lives in pursuit of honor, which took material form in followers and treasure. Treasures were given as gifts, awarded as prizes, carried off as loot.[366] This is no doubt how **tÄ«me** first came to mean both âhonorâ and âpriceââin such a world, no one sensed any sort of contradiction between the two.[367]
All this was to change dramatically when commercial markets began to develop two hundred years later. Greek coinage seem to have been first used mainly to pay soldiers, as well as to pay fines and fees and payments made to and by the government, but by about 600 bc, just about every Greek city-state was producing its own coins as a mark of civic independence. It did not take long, though, before coins were in common use in everyday transactions. By the fifth century, in Greek cities, the **agora**, the place of public debate and communal assembly, also doubled as a marketplace.
One of the first effects of the arrival of a commercial economy was a series of debt crises, of the sort long familiar from Mesopotamia and Israel. âThe poor,â as Aristotle succinctly put it in his **Constitution of the Athenians**, âtogether with their wives and children, were enslaved to the rich.â[368] Revolutionary factions emerged, demanding amnesties, and most Greek cities were at least for a while taken over by populist strongmen swept into power partly by the demand for radical debt relief. The solution most cities ultimately found, however, was quite different than it had been in the Near East. Rather than institutionalize periodic amnesties, Greek cities tended to adopt legislation limiting or abolishing debt peonage altogether, and then, to forestall future crises, they would turn to a policy of expansion, shipping off the children of the poor to found military colonies overseas. Before long, the entire coast from Crimea to Marseille was dotted with Greek cities, which served, in turn, as conduits for a lively trade in slaves.[369] The sudden abundance of chattel slaves, in turn, completely transformed the nature of Greek society. First and most famously, it allowed even citizens of modest means to take part in the political and cultural life of the city and have a genuine sense of citizenship. But this, in turn, drove the old aristocratic classes to develop more and more elaborate means of setting themselves off from what they considered the tawdriness and moral corruption of the new democratic state.
When the curtain truly goes up on Greece, in the fifth century, we find everybody arguing about money. For the aristocrats, who wrote most of the surviving texts, money was the embodiment of corruption. Aristocrats disdained the market. Ideally, a man of honor should be able to raise everything he needed on his own estates, and never have to handle cash at all.[370] In practice, they knew this was impossible. Yet at every point they tried to set themselves apart from the values of the ordinary denizens of the marketplace: to contrast the beautiful gold and silver beakers and tripods they gave one another at funerals and weddings with the vulgar hawking of sausages or charcoal; the dignity of the athletic contests for which they endlessly trained with commonersâ vulgar gambling; the sophisticated and literate courtesans who attended to them at their drinking clubs, and common prostitutes **(porne)**âslave-girls housed in brothels near the agora, brothels often sponsored by the democratic polis itself as a service to the sexual needs of its male citizenry. In each case, they placed a world of gifts, generosity, and honor above sordid commercial exchange.[371]
This resulted in a slightly different play of push and pull than we saw in Mesopotamia. On the one hand, we see a culture of aristocratic protest against what they saw as the lowly commercial sensibilities of ordinary citizens. On the other hand, we see an almost schizophrenic reaction on the part of the ordinary citizens themselves, who simultaneously tried to limit or even ban aspects of aristocratic culture and to imitate aristocratic sensibilities. Pederasty is an excellent case in point here. On the one hand, man-boy love was seen as the quintessential aristocratic practiceâit was the way, in fact, that young aristocrats would ordinarily become initiated into the privileges of high society. As a result, the democratic polis saw it as politically subversive and made sexual relations between male citizens illegal. At the same time, almost everyone began to practice it.
The famous Greek obsession with male honor that still informs so much of the texture of daily life in rural communities in Greece hearkens back not so much to Homeric honor but to this aristocratic rebellion against the values of the marketplace, which everyone, eventually, began to make their own.[372] The effects on women, though, were even more severe than they had been in the Middle East. Already by the age of Socrates, while a manâs honor was increasingly tied to disdain for commerce and assertiveness in public life, a womanâs honor had come to be defined in almost exclusively sexual terms: as a matter of virginity, modesty, and chastity, to the extent that respectable women were expected to be shut up inside the household and any woman who played a part in public life was considered for that reason a prostitute, or tantamount to one.[373] The Assyrian habit of veiling was not widely adopted in the Middle East, but it **was** adopted in Greece. As much as it flies in the face of our stereotypes about the origins of âWesternâ freedoms, women in democratic Athens, unlike those of Persia or Syria, were expected to wear veils when they ventured out in public.[374]
Money, then, had passed from a measure of honor to a measure of everything that honor was not. To suggest that a manâs honor could be bought with money became a terrible insultâthis despite the fact that, since men were often taken in war or even by bandits or pirates and held for ransom, they often did go through dramas of bondage and redemption not unlike those experienced by so many Middle Eastern women. One particularly striking way of hammering it homeâactually, in this case, almost literallyâwas by branding ransomed prisoners with the mark of their own currency, much as if today some imaginary foreign kidnapper, after having received the ransom money for an American victim, made a point of burning a dollar sign onto the victimâs forehead before returning him.[375]
One question that isnât clear from all this is, Why? Why had money, in particular, become such a symbol of degradation? Was it all because of slavery? One might be tempted to conclude that it was: perhaps the newfound presence of thousands of utterly degraded human beings in ancient Greek cities made any suggestion that a free man (let alone a free woman) might in any sense be bought or sold particularly insulting. But this is clearly not the case. Our discussion of the slave money of Ireland showed that the possibility of the utter degradation of a human being was in no sense a threat to heroic honorâin a way, it was its very essence. Homeric Greeks do not appear to have been any different. It seems hardly coincidental that the quarrel between Agamemnon and Achilles that sets off the action of the **Iliad**, generally considered to be the first great work of Western literature, is a dispute over honor between two heroic warriors over the disposition of a slave girl.[376] Agamemnon and Achilles were also well aware that it would only take an unfortunate turn in battle, or perhaps a shipwreck, for either of them to wind up as a slave. Odysseus barely escapes being enslaved on several occasions in the **Odyssey**. Even in the third century ad, the Roman emperor Valerian (253â260 ad), defeated at the Battle of Edessa, was captured and spent the last years of his life as the footstool that the Sassanian emperor Shapur I used to mount his horse. Such were the perils of war. All this was essential to the nature of martial honor. A warriorâs honor is his willingness to play a game on which he stakes everything. His grandeur is directly proportional to how far he can fall.
Was it, then, that the advent of commercial money threw traditional social hierarchies into disarray? Greek aristocrats often spoke this way, but the complaints seem rather disingenuous. Surely it was money that allowed such a polished aristocracy to exist in the first place.[377] Rather, the thing that really seemed to bother them about money was simply that they wanted it so much. Since money could be used to buy just about anything, everybody wanted it. That is: it was desirable **because** it was non-discriminating. One could see how the metaphor of the **porne** might seem particularly appropriate. A woman âcommon to the peopleââas the poet Archilochos put itâis available to everyone. In principle, we shouldnât be attracted to such an undiscriminating creature. In fact, of course, we are.[378] And nothing was both so undiscriminating, and so desirable, as money. True, Greek aristocrats would ordinarily insist that they were not attracted to common **porne**, and that the courtesans, flute-girls, acrobats, and beautiful boys that frequented their symposia were not really prostitutes at all (though at times they also admitted that they really were), they also struggled with the fact that their own high-minded pursuits, such as chariot-racing, outfitting ships for the navy, and sponsoring tragic dramas, required the exact same coins as the ones used to buy cheap perfume and pies for a fishermanâs wifeâthe only real difference being that their pursuits tended to require a lot more of them.[379]
We might say, then, that money introduced a democratization of desire. Insofar as everyone wanted money, everyone, high and low, was pursuing the same promiscuous substance. But even more: increasingly, they did not just want money. They needed it. This was a profound change. In the Homeric world, as in most human economies, we hear almost no discussion of those things considered necessary to human life (food, shelter, clothing) because it is simply assumed that everybody has them. A man with no possessions could, at the very least, become a retainer in some rich manâs household. Even slaves had enough to eat.[380] Here too, the prostitute was a potent symbol for what had changed, since while some of the denizens of brothels were slaves, others were simply poor; the fact that their basic needs could no longer be taken for granted were precisely what made them submit to othersâ desires. This extreme fear of dependency on othersâ whims lies at the basis of the Greek obsession with the self-sufficient household.
All this lies behind the unusually assiduous efforts of the male citizens of Greek city-statesâlike the later Romansâto insulate their wives and daughters from both the dangers and the freedoms of the marketplace. Unlike their equivalents in the Middle East, they do not seem to have offered them as debt pawns. Neither, at least in Athens, was it legal for the daughters of free citizens to be employed as prostitutes.[381] As a result, respectable women became invisible, largely removed from the high dramas of economic and political life.[382] If anyone was enslaved for debt, it was normally the debtor. Even more dramatically, it was ordinarily **male** citizens who accused one another of prostitutionâwith Athenian politicians regularly asserting that their rivals, when they were young boys being plied with gifts from their male suitors, were really trading sex for money, and hence deserved to lose their civic freedoms.[383]
It might be helpful here, to return to the principles laid out in chapter five. What we see above all is the erosion both of older forms of hierarchyâthe Homeric world of great men with their retainersâand, at the same time, of older forms of mutual aid, with communistic relations increasingly being confined to the interior of the household.
Itâs the formerâthe erosion of hierarchyâthat really seems to have been at stake in the âdebt crisesâ that struck so many Greek cities around 600 bc, right around the time that commercial markets were first taking shape.[384] When Aristotle spoke of the Athenian poor as falling slave to the rich, what he appears to have meant was that in harsh years, many poor farmers fell into debt; as a result they ended up as sharecroppers on their own property, dependents. Some were even sold abroad as slaves. This led to unrest and agitation, and also to demands for clean slates, for the freeing of those held in bondage, and for the redistribution of agricultural land. In a few cases it led to outright revolution. In Megara, we are told, a radical faction that seized power not only made interest-bearing loans illegal, but did so retroactively, forcing creditors to make restitution of all interest they had collected in the past.[385] In other cities, populist tyrants seized power on promises to abrogate agricultural debts.
On the face of it, all this doesnât seem all that surprising: the moment when commercial markets developed, Greek cities quickly developed all the social problems that had been plaguing Middle Eastern cities for millennia: debt crises, debt resistance, political unrest. In reality, things are not so clear. For one thing, for the poor to be âenslaved to the rich,â in the loose sense that Aristotle seems to be using, was hardly a new development. Even in Homeric society, it was assumed as a matter of course that rich men would live surrounded by dependents and retainers, drawn from the ranks of the dependent poor. The critical thing, though, about such relations of patronage is that they involved responsibilities on both sides. A noble warrior and his humble client were assumed to be fundamentally different sorts of people, but both were also expected to take account of each otherâs (fundamentally different) needs. Transforming patronage into debt relationsâtreating, say, an advance of seed corn as a **loan**, let alone an interest-bearing loanâchanged all this.[386] Whatâs more, it did so in two completely contradictory respects. On the one hand, a loan implies no ongoing responsibilities on the part of the creditor. On the other, as I have continually emphasized, a loan does assume a certain formal, legal equality between contractor and contractee. It assumes that they are, at least in some ways on some level, fundamentally the same kind of person. This is certainly about the most ruthless and violent form of equality imaginable. But the fact it was conceived as equality before the market made such arrangements even more difficult to endure.[387]
The same tensions can be observed between neighbors, who in farming communities tend to give, lend, and borrow things amongst themselvesâanything from sieves and sickles, to charcoal and cooking oil, to seed corn or oxen for plowing. On the one hand, such giving and lending were considered essential parts of the basic fabric of human sociability in farm communities, on the other, overly demanding neighbors were a notorious irritantâone that could only have grown worse when all parties are aware of precisely how much it would have cost to buy or rent the same items that were being given away. Again, one of the best ways to get a sense of what were considered everyday dilemmas for Mediterranean peasants is to look at jokes. Late stories from across the Aegean in Turkey echo exactly the same concerns:
Nasruddinâs neighbor once came by ask if he could borrow his donkey for an unexpected errand. Nasruddin obliged, but the next day the neighbor was back againâhe needed to take some grain to be milled. Before long he was showing up almost every morning, barely feeling he needed a pretext. Finally, Nasruddin got fed up, and one morning told him his brother had already come by and taken the donkey.
Just as the neighbor was leaving he heard a loud braying sound from the yard.
âHey, I thought you said the donkey wasnât here!â
âLook, who are you going to believe?â asked Nasruddin. âMe, or some animal?â
With the appearance of money, it could also become unclear what was a gift, and what a loan. On the one hand, even with gifts, it was always considered best to return something slightly better than one had received.[388] On the other hand, friends do not charge one another interest, and any suggestion that they might was sure to rankle. So whatâs the difference between a generous return gift and an interest payment? This is the basis of one of the most famous Nasruddin stories, one that appears to have provided centuries of amusement for peasants across the Mediterranean basin and adjoining regions. (It is also, I might note, a play on the fact that in many Mediterranean languages, Greek included, the word for âinterestâ literally means âoffspring.â)
One day Nasruddinâs neighbor, a notorious miser, came by to announce he was throwing a party for some friends. Could he borrow some of Nasruddinâs pots? Nasruddin didnât have many but said he was happy to lend whatever he had. The next day the miser returned, carrying Nasruddinâs three pots, and one tiny additional one.
âWhatâs that?â asked Nasrudddin.
âOh, thatâs the offspring of the pots. They reproduced during the time they were with me.â
Nasruddin shrugged and accepted them, and the miser left happy that he had established a principle of interest. A month later Nasruddin was throwing a party, and he went over to borrow a dozen pieces of his neighborâs much more luxurious crockery. The miser complied. Then he waited a day. And then another âŠ
On the third day, the miser came by and asked what had happened to his pots.
âOh, them?â Nasruddin said sadly. âIt was a terrible tragedy. They died.â[389]
In a heroic system, it is only debts of honorâthe need to repay gifts, to exact revenge, to rescue or redeem friends or kinsmen fallen prisonerâthat operate completely under a logic of tit-for-tat exchange. Honor is the same as credit; itâs oneâs ability to keep oneâs promises, but also, in the case of a wrong, to âget even.â As the last phrase implies, it was a monetary logic, but money, or anyway money-like relations, are confined to this. Gradually, subtly, without anyone completely understanding the full implications of what was happening, what had been the essence of moral relations turned into the means for every sort of dishonest stratagem.
We know a little about it from trial speeches, many of which have survived. Here is one from the fourth century, probably around 365 bc. Apollodorus was a prosperous but low-born Athenian citizen (his father, a banker, had begun life as a slave) who, like many such gentlemen, had acquired a country estate. There he made a point of making friends with his closest neighbor, Nicostratus, a man of aristocratic origins, though currently of somewhat straitened means. They acted as neighbors normally did, giving and borrowing small sums, lending each other animals or slaves, minding each otherâs property when one was away. Then one day Nicostratus ran into a piece of terrible luck. While trying to track down some runaway slaves, he was himself captured by pirates and held for ransom at the slave market on the island of Aegina. His relatives could only assemble part of the price, so he was forced to borrow the rest from strangers in the market. These appear to have been professionals who specialized in such loans, and their terms were notoriously harsh: if not repaid in *thirty* days, the sum doubled; if not repaid at all, the debtor became the slave of the man who had put up the money for his redemption.
Tearfully, Nicostratus appealed to his neighbor. All his possessions were already pledged now to one creditor or another; he knew Apollodorus wouldnât have that much cash lying around, but could his dear friend possibly put up something of his own by way of security? Apollodorus was moved. He would be happy to forgive all debts Nicostratus already owed him, but the rest would be difficult. Still, he would do his best. In the end, he arranged to himself take a loan from an acquaintance of his, Arcesas, on the security of his town-house, at 16 percent annual interest, so as to be able to satisfy Nicostratusâs creditors while Nicostratus himself arranged a friendly, no-interest **eranos** loan from his own relatives. But before long, Apollodorus began to realize that he had been set up. The impoverished aristocrat had decided to take advantage of his nouveau-riche neighbor; he was actually working with Arcesas and some of Apollodorusâs enemies to have him falsely declared a âpublic debtor,â that is, someone who had defaulted on an obligation to the public treasury. This would have first of all meant that he would lose his right to take anyone to court (i.e., his deceivers, to recover the money), and second, would give them a pretext to raid his house to remove his furniture and other possessions. Presumably, Nicostratus had never felt especially comfortable being in debt to a man he considered his social inferior. Rather like Egil the Viking, who would rather kill his friend Einar than have to compose an elegy thanking him for an overly magnificent gift, Nicostratus appears to have concluded that it was more honorable, or anyway more bearable, to try to extract the money from his lowly friend through force and fraud than to spend the rest of his life feeling beholden. Before long, things had indeed descended to outright physical violence, and the whole matter ended up in court.[390]
The story has everything. We see mutual aid: the communism of the prosperous, the expectation that if the need is great enough, or the cost manageable enough, friends and neighbors will help one another.[391] And most did, in fact, have circles of people who would pool money if a crisis did arise: whether a wedding, a famine, or a ransom. We also see the omnipresent danger of predatory violence that reduces human beings to commodities, and by doing so introduces the most cutthroat kinds of calculation into economic lifeânot just on the part of the pirates, but even more so, perhaps, on those moneylenders lurking by the market offering stiff credit terms to anyone who came to ransom their relatives but found themselves caught short, and who then could appeal to the state to allow them to hire men with weapons to enforce the contract. We see heroic pride, which sees too great an act of generosity as itself a kind of belittling assault. We see the ambiguity among gifts, loans, and commercial credit arrangements. Neither does the way things played out in this case seem particularly unusual, except perhaps for Nicostratusâs extraordinarily ingratitude. Prominent Athenians were always borrowing money to pursue their political projects; less-prominent ones were constantly worrying about their debts, or how to collect from their own debtors.[392] Finally, there is another, subtler element here. While everyday market transactions, at shops or stalls in the agora, were here as elsewhere typically conducted on credit, the mass production of coinage permitted a degree of anonymity for transactions that, in a pure credit regime, simply could not exist.[393] Pirates and kidnappers do business in cashâyet the loan sharks at Aeginaâs marketplace could not have operated without them. It is on this same combination of illegal cash business, usually involving violence, and extremely harsh credit terms, also enforced through violence, that innumerable criminal underworlds have been constructed ever since.
In Athens, the result was extreme moral confusion. The language of money, debt, and finance provided powerfulâand ultimately irresistibleâways to think about moral problems. Much as in Vedic India, people started talking about life as a debt to the gods, of obligations as debts, about literal debts of honor, of debt as sin and of vengeance as debt collection.[394] Yet if debt was moralityâand certainly at the very least it was in the interest of creditors, who often had little legal recourse to compel debtors to pay up, to insist that it wasâwhat was one to make of the fact that money, that very thing that seemed capable of turning morality into an exact and quantifiable science, also seemed to encourage the very worst sorts of behavior?
It is from such dilemmas that modern ethics and moral philosophy begin. I think this is true quite literally. Consider Platoâs **Republic**, another product of fourth-century Athens. The book begins when Socrates visits an old friend, a wealthy arms manufacturer, at the port of Piraeus. They get into a discussion of justice, which begins when the old man proposes that money cannot be a bad thing, since it allows those who have it to be just, and that justice consists in two things: telling the truth, and always paying oneâs debts.[395] The proposal is easily demolished. What, Socrates asks, if someone lent you his sword, went violently insane, and then asked for it back (presumably, so he could kill someone)? Clearly it can never be right to arm a lunatic whatever the circumstances.[396] The old man cheerfully shrugs the problem off and heads off to attend to some ritual, leaving his son to carry on the argument.
The son, Polemarchus, switches gears: clearly his father hadnât meant âdebtâ in the literal sense of returning what one has borrowed. He meant it more in the sense of giving people what is owed to them; repaying good with good and evil with evil; helping oneâs friends and hurting oneâs enemies. Demolishing this one takes a little more work (are we saying justice plays no part in determining who oneâs friends and enemies are? If so, wouldnât someone who decided he had no friends, and therefore tried to hurt everyone, be a just man? And even if you did have some way to say for certain that oneâs enemy really is an intrinsically bad person and deserves harm, by harming him, do you not thus make him worse? Can turning bad people into even worse people really be an example of justice?) but it is eventually accomplished. At this point a Sophist, Thrasymachos, enters and denounces all of the debaters as milky-eyed idealists. In reality, he says, all talk of âjusticeâ is mere political pretext, designed to justify the interests of the powerful. And so it should be, because insofar as justice exists, it is simply that: the interest of the powerful. Rulers are like shepherds. We like to think of them as benevolently tending their flocks, but what do shepherds ultimately **do** with sheep? They kill and eat them, or sell the meat for money. Socrates responds by pointing out that Thrasymachos is confusing the art of tending sheep with the art of profiting from them. The art of medicine aims to improve health, whether or not doctors get paid for practicing it. The art of shepherding aims to ensure the well-being of sheep, whether or not the shepherd (or his employer) is also a businessman who knows how to extract a profit from them. Just so with the art of governance. If such an art exists, it must have its own intrinsic aim apart from any profit one might also get from it, and what can this be other than the establishment of social justice? Itâs only the existence of money, Socrates suggests, that allows us to imagine that words like âpowerâ and âinterestâ refer to universal realities that can be pursued in their own right, let alone that all pursuits are really ultimately the pursuit of power, advantage, or self-interest.[397] The question, he said, is how to ensure that those who hold political office will do so not for gain, but rather for honor.
I will leave off here. As we all know, Socrates eventually gets around to offering some political proposals of his own, involving philosopher kings; the abolition of marriage, the family, and private property; selective human breeding boards. (Clearly, the book was meant to annoy its readers, and for more than two thousand years, it has succeeded brilliantly.) What I want to emphasize, though, is the degree to which what we consider our core tradition of moral and political theory today springs from this question: What does it mean to pay our debts? Plato presents us first with the simple, literal businessmanâs view. When this proves inadequate, he allows it to be reframed in heroic terms. Perhaps all debts are really debts of honor after all.[398] But heroic honor no longer works in a world where (as Apollodorus sadly discovered) commerce, class, and profit have so confused everything that peoplesâ true motives are never clear. How do we even know who our enemies are? Finally, Plato presents us with cynical realpolitik. Maybe nobody really owes anything to anybody. Maybe those who pursue profit for its own sake have it right after all. But even that does not hold up. We are left with a certainty that existing standards are incoherent and self-contradictory, and that **some** sort of radical break would be required in order to create a world that makes any logical sense. But most of those who seriously consider a radical break along the lines that Plato suggested have come to the conclusion that there might be far worse things than moral incoherence. And there we have stood, ever since, in the midst of an insoluble dilemma.
Itâs not surprising that these issues weighed on Platoâs mind. Not seven years before, he had taken an ill-fated sea cruise and wound up being captured and, supposedly like Nicostratus, offered for sale on the auction block at Aegina. However, Plato had better luck. A Libyan philosopher of the Epicurean school, one Annikeris, happened to be in the market at the time. He recognized Plato and ransomed him. Plato felt honor-bound to try to repay him, and his Athenian friends assembled twenty minas in silver with which to do so, but Annikeris refused to accept the money, insisting that it was his honor to be able to benefit a fellow lover of wisdom.[399] As indeed it was: Annikeris has been remembered, and celebrated, for his generosity ever since. Plato went on to use the twenty minas to buy land for a school, the famous Academy. And while he hardly showed the same ingratitude as Nicostratus, one does rather get the impression that even Plato wasnât especially happy about the fact that his subsequent career was, in a sense, made possible by his debt to a man who he probably considered an extremely minor philosopherâand Annikeris wasnât even Greek! At least this would help explain why Plato, otherwise the inveterate name-dropper, never mentioned Annikeris. We know of his existence only from later biographers.[400]
If Platoâs work testifies to how profoundly the moral confusion introduced by debt has shaped our traditions of thought, Roman law reveals how much it has shaped even our most familiar institutions.
German legal theorist Rudolf von Jhering famously remarked that ancient Rome had conquered the world three times: the first time through its armies, the second through its religion, the third through its laws.[401] He might have added: each time more thoroughly. The Empire, after all, only spanned a tiny portion of the globe; the Roman Catholic Church has spread farther; Roman law has come to provide the language and conceptual underpinnings of legal and constitutional orders everywhere. Law students from South Africa to Peru are expected to spend a good deal of their time memorizing technical terms in Latin, and it is Roman law that provides almost all our basic conceptions about contract, obligation, torts, property, and jurisdictionâand, in a broader sense, of citizenship, rights, and liberties on which political life, too, is based.
This was possible, Jhering held, because, the Romans were the first to turn jurisprudence into a genuine science. Perhapsâbut for all that, it remains true that Roman law has a few notoriously quirky features, some so odd that they have confused and confounded jurists ever since Roman law was revived in Italian universities in the High Middle Ages. The most notorious of these is the unique way it defines property. In Roman law, property, or **dominium**, is a relation between a person and a thing, characterized by absolute power of that person over that thing. This definition has caused endless conceptual problems. First of all, itâs not clear what it would mean for a human to have a ârelationâ with an inanimate object. Human beings can have relations with one another. But what would it mean to have a ârelationâ with a thing? And if one did, what would it mean to give that relation legal standing? A simple illustration will suffice: imagine a man trapped on a desert island. He might develop extremely personal relationships with, say, the palm trees growing on that island. If heâs there too long, he might well end up giving them all names and spending half his time having imaginary conversations with them. Still, does he **own** them? The question is meaningless. Thereâs no need to worry about property rights if noone else is there.
Clearly, then, property is not really a relation between a person and a thing. Itâs an understanding or arrangement between people concerning things. The only reason that we sometimes fail to notice this is that in many casesâparticularly when we are talking about our rights over our shoes, or cars, or power toolsâwe are talking of rights held, as English law puts it, âagainst all the worldââthat is, understandings between ourselves and everyone else on the planet, that they will all refrain from interfering with our possessions, and therefore allow us to treat them more or less any way we like. A relation between one person and everyone else on the planet is, understandably, difficult to conceive as such. Itâs easier to think of it as a relationship with a thing. But even here, in practice this freedom to do as one likes turns out to be fairly limited. To say that the fact that I own a chainsaw gives me an âabsolute powerâ to do anything I want with it is obviously absurd. Almost anything I might think of doing with a chainsaw outside my own home or land is likely to be illegal, and there are only a limited number of things I can really do with it inside. The only thing âabsoluteâ about my rights to a chainsaw is my right to prevent anyone **else** from using it.[402]
Nonetheless, Roman law does insist that the basic form of property is private property, and that private property is the ownerâs absolute power to do anything he wants with his possessions. Twelfth-century Medieval jurists came to refine this into three principles, **usus** (use of the thing), **fructus** (fruits, i.e., enjoyment of the products of the thing), and **abusus** (abuse or destruction of the thing), but Roman jurists werenât even interested in specifying that much, since in a certain way, they saw the details as lying entirely outside the domain of law. In fact, scholars have spent a great deal of time debating whether Roman authors actually considered private property to be a right **(ius),[403]** for the very reason that rights were ultimately based on agreements between people, and oneâs power to dispose of oneâs property was not: it was just oneâs natural ability to do whatever one pleased when social impediments were absent.[404]
If you think about it, this really is an odd place to start in developing a theory of property law. It is probably fair to say that, in any part of the world, in any period of history, whether in ancient Japan or Machu Picchu, someone who had a piece of string was free to twist it, knot it, pull it apart, or toss it in the fire more or less as they had a mind to. Nowhere else did legal theorists appear to have found this fact in any way interesting or important. Certainly no other tradition makes it the very basis of property lawâsince, after all, doing so made almost all actual law little more than a series of exceptions.
How did this come about? And why? The most convincing explanation Iâve seen is Orlando Pattersonâs: the notion of absolute private property is really derived from slavery. One can imagine property not as a relation between people, but as a relation between a person and a thing, if oneâs starting point is a relation between two people, one of whom is also a thing. (This is how slaves were defined in Roman law: they were people who were also a **res**, a thing.)[405] The emphasis on absolute power begins to make sense as well.[406]
The word **dominium**, meaning absolute private property, was not particularly ancient.[407] It only appears in Latin in the late Republic, right around the time when hundreds of thousands of captive laborers were pouring into Italy, and when Rome, as a consequence, was becoming a genuine slave society.[408] By 50 bc, Roman writers had come to simply assume that workersâwhether the farmworkers harvesting peas in countryside plantations, the muleteers delivering those peas to shops in the city, or the clerks keeping count of themâwere someone elseâs property. The existence of millions of creatures who were simultaneously persons and things created endless legal problems, and much of the creative genius of Roman law was spent in working out the endless ramifications. One need only flip open a casebook of Roman law to get a sense of these. This is from the second-century jurist Ulpian:
Again, Mela writes that if some persons were playing ball and one of them, hitting the ball quite hard, knocked it against a barberâs hands, and in this way the throat of a slave, whom the barber was shaving, was cut by a razor pressed against it, then who is the person with whom the culpability lay is liable under the Lex Aquilia [the law of civil damages]? Proclus says that the culpability lies with the barber; and indeed, if he was shaving at a place where games are normally played or where traffic was heavy, there is reason to fault him. But it would not be badly held that if someone entrusts himself to a barber who has a chair in a dangerous place, he should have himself to blame.[409]
In other words, the master cannot claim civil damages against the ballplayers or barber for destroying his property if the real problem was that he bought a stupid slave. Many of these debates might strike us as profoundly exotic (could you be accused of theft for merely convincing a slave to run away? If someone killed a slave who was also your son, could you take your sentimental feelings toward him into account in assessing damages, or would you have to stick to his market value?)âbut our contemporary tradition of jurisprudence is founded directly on such debates.[410]
As for **dominium**, the word is derived from **dominus**, meaning âmasterâ or âslave-owner,â but ultimately from **domus**, meaning âhouseâor âhousehold.â Itâs of course related to the English term âdomestic,â which even now can be used either to mean âpertaining to private life,â or to refer to a servant who cleans the house. **Domus** overlaps somewhat in meaning with **familia**, âfamilyââbut, as proponents of âfamily valuesâ might be interested to know, **familia** itself ultimately derives from the word **famulus**, meaning âslave.â A family was originally all those people under the domestic authority of a **paterfamilias**, and that authority was, in early Roman law at least, conceived as absolute.[411] A man did not have total power over his wife, since she was still to some degree under the protection of her own father, but his children, slaves, and other dependents were his to do with as he wantedâat least in early Roman law, he was perfectly free to whip, torture, or sell them. A father could even execute his children, provided he found them to have committed capital crimes.[412] With his slaves, he didnât even need that excuse.
In creating a notion of **dominium**, then, and thus creating the modern principle of absolute private property, what Roman jurists were doing first of all was taking a principle of domestic authority, of absolute power over people, defining some of those people (slaves) as things, and then extending the logic that originally applied to slaves to geese, chariots, barns, jewelry boxes, and so forthâthat is, to every other sort of thing that the law had anything to do with.
It was quite extraordinary, even in the ancient world, for a father to have the right to execute his slavesâlet alone his children. No one is quite sure why the early Romans were so extreme in this regard. Itâs telling, though, that the earliest Roman debt law was equally unusual in its harshness, since it allowed creditors to execute insolvent debtors.[413] The early history of Rome, like the histories of early Greek city-states, was one of continual political struggle between creditors and debtors, until the Roman elite eventually figured out the principle that most successful Mediterranean elites learned: that a free peasantry means a more effective army, and that conquering armies can provide war captives who can do anything debt bondsmen used to do, and therefore, a social compromiseâallowing limited popular representation, banning debt slavery, channeling some of the fruits of empire into social-welfare paymentsâwas actually in their interest. Presumably, the absolute power of fathers developed as part of this whole constellation in the same way as weâve seen elsewhere. Debt bondage reduced family relations to relations of property; social reforms retained the new power of fathers but protected them from debt. At the same time, the increasing influx of slaves soon meant that any even moderately prosperous household was likely to contain slaves. This meant that the logic of conquest extended into the most intimate aspects of everyday life. Conquered people poured oneâs bath and combed oneâs hair. Conquered tutors taught oneâs children about poetry. Since slaves were sexually available to owners and their families, as well as to their friends and dinner guests, it is likely that most Romansâ first sexual experience was with a boy or girl whose legal status was conceived as that of a defeated enemy.[414]
Over time, this became more and more of a legal fictionâactual slaves were much more likely to have been paupers sold by parents, unfortunates kidnapped by pirates or bandits, victims of wars or judicial process among barbarians at the fringes of the empire, or children of other slaves.[415] Still, the fiction was maintained.
What made Roman slavery so unusual, in historical terms, was a conjuncture of two factors. One was its very arbitrariness. In dramatic contrast with, say plantation slavery in the Americas, there was no sense that certain people were naturally inferior and therefore destined to be slaves. Instead, slavery was seen as a misfortune that could happen to anyone.[416] As a result, there was no reason that a slave might not be in every way superior to his or her master: smarter, with a finer sense of morality, better taste, and a greater understanding of philosophy. The master might even be willing to acknowledge this. There was no reason not to, since it had no effect on the nature of the relationship, which was simply one of power.
The second was the absolute nature of this power. There are many places where slaves are conceived as war captives, and masters as conquerors with absolute powers of life and deathâbut usually, this is something of an abstract principle. Almost everywhere, governments quickly move to limit such rights. At the very least, emperors and kings will insist that they are the only ones with the power to order others put to death.[417] But under the Roman Republic there was no emperor; insofar as there was a sovereign body, it was the collective body of the slave-owners themselves. Only under the early Empire do we see any legislation limiting what owners could do to their (human) property: the first being a law of the time of the emperor Tiberius (dated 16 ad) stipulating that a master had to obtain a magistrateâs permission before ordering a slave publicly torn apart by wild beasts.[418] However, the absolute nature of the masterâs powerâthe fact that in this context, he effectively **was** the stateâalso meant that there were also, at first, no restrictions on manumission: a master could liberate his slave, or even adopt him or her, wherebyâsince liberty meant nothing outside of membership in a communityâthat slave automatically became a Roman citizen. This led to some very peculiar arrangements. In the first century ad, for example, it was not uncommon for educated Greeks to have themselves sold into slavery to some wealthy Roman in need of a secretary, entrust the money to a close friend or family member, and then, after a certain interval, buy themselves back, thus obtaining Roman citizenship. This despite the fact that, during such time as they were slaves, if their owner decided to, say, cut one of his secretaryâs feet off, legally, he would have been perfectly free to do so.[419]
The relation of **dominus** and slave thus brought a relation of conquest, of absolute political power into the household (in fact, made it the essence of the household). Itâs important to emphasize that this was not a moral relation on either side. A well-known legal formula, attributed to a Republican lawyer named Quintus Haterius, brings this home with particular clarity. With the Romans as with the Athenians, for a male to be the object of sexual penetration was considered unbefitting to a citizen. In defending a freedman accused of continuing to provide sexual favors to his former master, Haterius coined an aphorism that was later to become something of a popular dirty joke: **impudicitia in ingenuo crimen est, in servo necessitas, in liberto officium** (âto be the object of anal penetration is a crime in the freeborn, a necessity for a slave, a duty for a freedmanâ).[420] What is significant here is that sexual subservience is considered the âdutyâ only of the freedman. It is not considered the âdutyâ of a slave. This is because, again, slavery was not a moral relation. The master could do what he liked, and there was nothing the slave could do about it.
The most insidious effect of Roman slavery, however, is that through Roman law, it has come to play havoc with our idea of human freedom. The meaning of the Roman word **libertas** itself changed dramatically over time. As everywhere in the ancient world, to be âfreeâ meant, first and foremost, not to be a slave. Since slavery means above all the annihilation of social ties and the ability to form them, freedom meant the capacity to make and maintain moral commitments to others. The English word âfree,â for instance, is derived from a German root meaning âfriend,â since to be free meant to be able to make friends, to keep promises, to live within a community of equals. This is why freed slaves in Rome became citizens: to be free, by definition, meant to be anchored in a civic community, with all the rights and responsibilities that this entailed.[421]
By the second century ad, however, this had begun to change. The jurists gradually redefined **libertas** until it became almost indistinguishable from the power of the master. It was the right to do absolutely anything, with the exception, again, of all those things one could not do. Actually, in the **Digest**, the definitions of freedom and slavery appear back to back:
Freedom is the natural faculty to do whatever one wishes that is not prevented by force or law. Slavery is an institution according to the law of nations whereby one person becomes private property **(dominium)** of another, contrary to nature.[422]
Medieval commentators immediately noticed the problem here.[423] But wouldnât this mean that everyone is free? After all, even slaves are free to do absolutely anything theyâre actually permitted to do. To say a slave is free (except insofar as he isnât) is a bit like saying the earth is square (except insofar as it is round), or that the sun is blue (except insofar as it is yellow), or, again, that we have an absolute right to do anything we wish with our chainsaw (except those things that we canât.)
In fact, the definition introduces all sorts of complications. If freedom is natural, then surely slavery is unnatural, but if freedom and slavery are just matters of degree, then, logically, would not **all** restrictions on freedom be to some degree unnatural? Would not that imply that society, social rules, in fact even property rights, are unnatural as well? This is precisely what many Roman jurists did concludeâthat is, when they did venture to comment on such abstract matters, which was only rarely. Originally, human beings lived in a state of nature where all things were held in common; it was war that first divided up the world, and the resultant âlaw of nations,â the common usages of mankind that regulate such matters as conquest, slavery, treaties, and borders, that was first responsible for inequalities of property as well.[424]
This in turn meant that there was no intrinsic difference between private property and political powerâat least, insofar as that power was based in violence. As time went on, Roman emperors also began claiming something like **dominium**, insisting that within their dominions, they had absolute freedomâin fact, that they were not bound by laws.[425] At the same time, as Roman society shifted from a republic of slave-holders to arrangements that increasingly resembled later feudal Europe, with magnates on their great estates surrounded by dependent peasants, debt servants, and an endless variety of slavesâwith whom they could largely do as they pleased. The barbarian invasions that overthrew the empire merely formalized the situation, largely eliminating chattel slavery, but at the same time introducing the notion that the noble classes were really descendants of the Germanic conquerors, and that the common people were inherently subservient.
Still, even in this new Medieval world, the old Roman concept of freedom remained. Freedom was simply power. When Medieval political theorists spoke of âliberty,â they were normally referring to a lordâs right to do whatever he wanted within his own domains. This was, again, usually assumed to be not something originally established by agreement, but a mere fact of conquest: one famous English legend holds that when, around 1290, King Edward I asked his lords to produce documents to demonstrate by what right they held their franchises (or âlibertiesâ), the Earl Warenne presented the king only with his rusty sword.[426] Like Roman **dominium**, it was less a right than a power, and a power exercised first and foremost over peopleâwhich is why in the Middle Ages it was common to speak of the âliberty of the gallows,â meaning a lordâs right to maintain his own private place of execution.
By the time Roman law began to be recovered and modernized in the twelfth century, the term **dominium** posed a particular problem, since it had come, in ordinary church Latin of the time, to be used equally for âlordshipâ and âprivate property.â Medieval jurists spent a great deal of time and argument establishing whether there was indeed a difference between the two. It was a particularly thorny problem because, if property rights really were, as the **Digest** insisted, a form of absolute power, it was very difficult to see how anyone could have it but a kingâor even, for certain jurists, God.[427]
This is not the place to describe the resulting arguments, but I feel itâs important to end here because in a way, it brings us full circle and allows us to understand precisely how Liberals like Adam Smith were able to imagine the world the way they did. This is a tradition that assumes that liberty is essentially the right to do what one likes with oneâs own property. In fact, not only does it make property a right; it treats rights themselves as a form of property. In a way, this is the greatest paradox of all. We are so used to the idea of âhavingâ rightsâthat rights are something one can possessâthat we rarely think about what this might actually mean. In fact (as Medieval jurists were well aware), one manâs right is simply anotherâs obligation. My right to free speech is othersâ obligation not to punish me for speaking; my right to a trial by a jury of my peers is the responsibility of the government to maintain a system of jury duty. The problem is just the same as it was with property rights: when we are talking about obligations owed by everyone in the entire world, itâs difficult to think about it that way. Itâs much easier to speak of âhavingâ rights and freedoms. Still, if freedom is basically our right to own things, or to treat things as if we own them, then what would it mean to âownâ a freedomâwouldnât it have to mean that our right to own property is **itself** a form of property? That does seem unnecessarily convoluted. What possible reason would one have to want to define it this way?[428]
Historically, there is a simpleâif somewhat disturbingâanswer to this. Those who have argued that we are the natural owners of our rights and liberties have been mainly interested in asserting that we should be free to give them away, or even to sell them.
Modern ideas of rights and liberties are derived from what, from the time when Jean Gerson, Rector of the University of Paris, began to lay them out around 1400, building on Roman law concepts, came to be known as ânatural rights theory.â As Richard Tuck, the premier historian of such ideas, has long noted, it is one of the great ironies of history that this was always a body of theory embraced not by the progressives of that time, but by conservatives. âFor a Gersonian, liberty was property and could be exchanged in the same way and in the same terms as any other propertyââsold, swapped, loaned, or otherwise voluntarily surrendered.[429] It followed that there could be nothing intrinsically wrong with, say, debt peonage, or even slavery. And this is exactly what natural-rights theorists came to assert. In fact, over the next centuries, these ideas came to be developed above all in Antwerp and Lisbon, cities at the very center of the emerging slave trade. After all, they argued, we donât really know whatâs going on in the lands behind places like Calabar, but there is no intrinsic reason to assume that the vast majority of the human cargo conveyed to European ships had not sold themselves, or been disposed of by their legal guardians, or lost their liberty in some other perfectly legitimate fashion. No doubt some had not, but abuses will exist in any system. The important thing was that there was nothing inherently unnatural or illegitimate about the idea that freedom **could** be sold.[430]
Before long, similar arguments came to be employed to justify the absolute power of the state. Thomas Hobbes was the first to really develop this argument in the seventeenth century, but it soon became commonplace. Government was essentially a contract, a kind of business arrangement, whereby citizens had voluntarily given up some of their natural liberties to the sovereign. Finally, similar ideas have become the basis of that most basic, dominant institution of our present economic life: wage labor, which is, effectively, the renting of our freedom in the same way that slavery can be conceived as its sale.[431]
Itâs not only our freedoms that we own; the same logic has come to be applied even to our own bodies, which are treated, in such formulations, as really no different than houses, cars, or furniture. We own ourselves, therefore outsiders have no right to trespass on us.[432] Again, this might seem an innocuous, even a positive notion, but it looks rather different when we take into consideration the Roman tradition of property on which it is based. To say that we own ourselves is, oddly enough, to cast ourselves as both master and slave simultaneously. âWeâ are both owners (exerting absolute power over our property), and yet somehow, at the same time, the things being owned (being the object of absolute power). The ancient Roman household, far from having been forgotten in the mists of history, is preserved in our most basic conception of ourselvesâand, once again, just as in property law, the result is so strangely incoherent that it spins off into endless paradoxes the moment one tries to figure out what it would actually mean in practice. Just as lawyers have spent a thousand years trying to make sense of Roman property concepts, so have philosophers spent centuries trying to understand how it could be possible for us to have a relation of domination over ourselves. The most popular solutionâto say that each of us has something called a âmindâ and that this is completely separate from something else, which we can call âthe body,â and that the first thing holds natural dominion over the secondâflies in the face of just about everything we now know about cognitive science. Itâs obviously untrue, but we continue to hold onto it anyway, for the simple reason that none of our everyday assumptions about property, law, and freedom would make any sense without it.[433]
The first four chapters of this book describe a dilemma. We donât really know how to think about debt. Or, to be more accurate, we seem to be trapped between imagining society in the Adam Smith mode, as a collection of individuals whose only significant relations are with their own possessions, happily bartering one thing for another for the sake of mutual convenience, with debt almost entirely abolished from the picture, and a vision in which debt is everything, the very substance of all human relationsâwhich of course leaves everyone with the uncomfortable sense that human relations are somehow an intrinsically tawdry business, that our very responsibilities to one another are already somehow necessarily based in sin and crime. Itâs not an appealing set of alternatives.
In the last three chapters I have tried to show that there is another way of looking at things, and then to describe how it is that we got here. This is why I developed the concept of human economies: ones in which what is considered really important about human beings is the fact that they are each a unique nexus of relations with othersâtherefore, that no one could ever be considered exactly equivalent to anything or anyone else. In a human economy, money is not a way of buying or trading human beings, but a way of expressing just how much one cannot do so.
I then went on to describe how all this can begin to break down: how humans can become objects of exchange: first, perhaps, women given in marriage; ultimately, slaves captured in war. What all these relations have in common, I observed, was violence. Whether it is Tiv girls being tied up and beaten for running away from their husbands, or husbands being herded into slave ships to die on faraway plantations, that same principle always applies: it is only by the threat of sticks, ropes, spears, and guns that one can tear people out of those endlessly complicated webs of relationship with others (sisters, friends, rivals âŠ) that render them unique, and thus reduce them to something that can be traded.
All of this, it is important to emphasize, can happen in places where markets in ordinary, everyday goodsâclothing, tools, foodstuffsâdo not even exist. In fact, in most human economies, oneâs most important possessions could never be bought and sold for the same reasons that people canât: they are unique objects, caught up in a web of relationships with human beings.[434]
My old professor John Comaroff used to tell a story about carrying out a survey in Natal, in South Africa. He had spent most of a week driving from homestead to homestead in a jeep with a box full of questionnaires and a Zulu-speaking interpreter, driving past apparently endless herds of cattle. After about six days, his interpreter suddenly started and pointed into the middle of one herd. âLook!â he said. âThatâs the same cow! That one thereâwith the red spot on its back. We saw it three days ago in a place ten miles from here. I wonder what happened? Did someone get married? Or maybe there was a settlement to some dispute.â
In human economies, when this ability to rip people from their contexts does appear, it is most often seen as an end in itself. One can already see a hint of this among the Lele. Important men would occasionally acquire war captives from far away as slaves, but it was almost always to be sacrificed at their funeral.[435] The squelching of one manâs individuality was seen as somehow swelling the reputation, the social existence, of the other.[436] In what Iâve been calling heroic societies, of course this kind of addition and subtraction of honor and disgrace is lifted from a somewhat marginal practice to become the very essence of politics. As endless epics, sagas, and eddas attest, heroes become heroes by making others small. In Ireland and Wales, we can observe how this very ability to degrade others, to remove unique human beings from their hearths and families and thus render them anonymous units of accountingâthe Irish slave-girl currency, the Welsh washerwomenâis itself the highest expression of honor.
In heroic societies, the role of violence is not hiddenâitâs glorified. Often, it can form the basis of oneâs most intimate relations. In the **Iliad**, Achilles sees nothing shameful in his relation with his slave-girl, Briseis, whose husband and brothers he killed; he refers to her as his âprize of honor,â but almost in the very same breath, he also insists that, just any decent man must love and care for his household dependents, âso I from my heart loved this one, even though I won her with my spear.â[437]
That such relations of intimacy can often develop between men of honor and those they have stripped of their dignity, history can well attest. After all, the annihilation of any possibility of equality also eliminates any question of debt, of any relation other than power. It allows a certain clarity. This is presumably why emperors and kings have such a notorious tendency to surround themselves with slaves or eunuchs.
There is something more here, though. If one looks across the expanse of history, one cannot help but notice a curious sense of identification between the most exalted and the most degraded; particularly, between emperors and kings, and slaves. Many kings surround themselves with slaves, appoint slave ministersâthere have even been, as with the Mamluks in Egypt, actual dynasties of slaves. Kings surround themselves with slaves for the same reason that they surround themselves with eunuchs: because the slaves and criminals have no families or friends, no possibility of other loyaltiesâor at least that, in principle, they shouldnât. But in a way, kings should really be like that too. As many an African proverb emphasizes: a proper king has no relatives either, or at least, he acts as if he does not.[438] In other words, the king and slave are mirror images, in that unlike normal human beings who are defined by their commitments to others, they are defined **only** by relations of power. They are as close to perfectly isolated, alienated beings as one can possibly become.
At this point we can finally see whatâs really at stake in our peculiar habit of defining ourselves simultaneously as master and slave, reduplicating the most brutal aspects of the ancient household in our very concept of ourselves, as masters of our freedoms, or as owners of our very selves. It is the only way that we can imagine ourselves as completely isolated beings. There is a direct line from the new Roman conception of libertyânot as the ability to form mutual relationships with others, but as the kind of absolute power of âuse and abuseâ over the conquered chattel who make up the bulk of a wealthy Roman manâs householdâto the strange fantasies of liberal philosophers like Hobbes, Locke, and Smith, about the origins of human society in some collection of thirty- or forty-year-old males who seem to have sprung from the earth fully formed, then have to decide whether to kill each other or begin to swap beaver pelts.[439]
European and American intellectuals, it is true, have spent much of the last two hundred years trying to flee from the more disturbing implications of this tradition of thought. Thomas Jefferson, that owner of many slaves, chose to begin the Declaration of Independence by directly contradicting the moral basis of slavery, writing âwe hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, and that they are endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable Rights âŠââthus undercutting simultaneously any argument that Africans were racially inferior, and also that they or their ancestors could ever have been justly and legally deprived of their freedom. In doing so, however, he did not propose some radically new conception of rights and liberties. Neither have subsequent political philosophers. For the most part, weâve just kept the old ones, but with the word ânotâ inserted here and there. Most of our most precious rights and freedoms are a series of exceptions to an overall moral and legal framework that suggests we shouldnât really have them in the first place.
Formal slavery has been eliminated, but (as anyone who works from nine to five can testify) the idea that you can alienate your liberty, at least temporarily, endures. In fact, it determines what most of us have to do for most of our waking hours, except, usually, on weekends. The violence has been largely pushed out of sight.[440] But this is largely because weâre no longer able to imagine what a world based on social arrangements that did not require the continual threat of tasers and surveillance cameras would even look like.
<em>Bullion is the accessory of war, and not of peaceful trade</em>.
One might well ask: If our political and legal ideas really are founded on the logic of slavery, then how did we ever eliminate slavery? Of course, a cynic might argue that we havenât; weâve just relabeled it. The cynic would have a point: an ancient Greek would certainly have seen the distinction between a slave and an indebted wage laborer as, at best, a legalistic nicety.[441] Still, even the elimination of formal chattel slavery has to be considered a remarkable achievement, and it is worthwhile to wonder how it was accomplished. Especially since it was not just accomplished once. The truly remarkable thing, if one consults the historical record, is that slavery has been eliminatedâor effectively eliminatedâmany times in human history.
In Europe, for instance, the institution largely vanished in the centuries following the collapse of the Roman empireâan historical achievement rarely recognized by those of us used to referring to these events as the beginning of âthe Dark Ages.â[442] No one is quite sure how it happened. Most agree that the spread of Christianity must have had something to do with it, but that canât have been the direct cause, since the Church itself was never explicitly opposed to the institution and in many cases defended it. Instead, the abolition appears to have happened **despite** the attitudes of both the intellectuals and the political authorities of the time. Yet it did happen, and it had lasting effects. On the popular level, slavery remained so universally detested that even a thousand years later, when European merchants started trying to revive the trade, they discovered that their compatriots would not countenance slaveholding in their own countriesâone reason why planters were eventually obliged to acquire their slaves in Africa and set up plantations in the New World.[443] It is one of the great ironies of history that modern racismâprobably the single greatest evil of our last two centuriesâhad to be invented largely because Europeans continued to refuse to listen to the arguments of the intellectuals and jurists and did not accept that anyone they believed to be a full and equal human being could ever be justifiably enslaved.
Whatâs more, the demise of ancient slavery was not limited to Europe. Remarkably, right around the same timeâin the years around 600 adâwe find almost exactly the same thing happening in India and China, where, over the course of centuries, amidst much unrest and confusion, chattel slavery largely ceased to exist. What all this suggests is that moments of historical opportunityâmoments when meaningful change is possibleâfollow a distinct, even a cyclical pattern, one that has long been far more coordinated across geographical space than we would ever have imagined. There is a shape to the past, and it is only by understanding it that we can begin to have a sense of the historical opportunities that exist in the present.
The easiest way to make these cycles visible is to reexamine exactly the phenomenon weâve been concerned with over the course of this book: the history of money, debt, and credit. The moment we begin to map the history of money across the last five thousand years of Eurasian history, startling patterns begin to emerge. In the case of money, one event stands out above all others: the invention of coinage. Coinage appears to have arisen independently in three different places, almost simultaneously: on the Great Plain of northern China, in the Ganges river valley of northeast India, and in the lands surrounding the Aegean Sea, in each case, between roughly 600 and 500 bc. This wasnât due to some sudden technological innovation: the technologies used in making the first coins were, in each case, entirely different.[444] It was a social transformation. Why this happened in exactly this way is an historical mystery. But this much we know: for some reason, in Lydia, India, and China, local rulers decided that whatever longstanding credit systems had existed in their kingdoms were no longer adequate, and they began to issue tiny pieces of precious metalsâmetals that had previously been used largely in international commerce, in ingot formâand to encourage their subjects to use them in day-to-day transactions.
From there, the innovation spread. For more than a thousand years, states everywhere started issuing their own coinage. But then, right around 600 ad, about the time that slavery was disappearing, the whole trend was suddenly thrown into reverse. Cash dried up. Everywhere, there was a movement back to credit once again.
If we look at Eurasian history over the course of the last five thousand years, what we see is a broad alternation between periods dominated by credit money and periods in which gold and silver come to dominateâthat is, those during which at least a large share of transactions were conducted with pieces of valuable metal being passed from hand to hand.
Why? The single most important factor would appear to be war. Bullion predominates, above all, in periods of generalized violence. Thereâs a very simple reason for that. Gold and silver coins are distinguished from credit arrangements by one spectacular feature: they can be stolen. A debt is, by definition, a record, as well as a relation of trust. Someone accepting gold or silver in exchange for merchandise, on the other hand, need trust nothing more than the accuracy of the scales, the quality of the metal, and the likelihood that someone else will be willing to accept it. In a world where war and the threat of violence are everywhereâand this appears to have been an equally accurate description of Warring States China, Iron Age Greece, and pre-Mauryan Indiaâthere are obvious advantages to making oneâs transactions simple. This is all the more true when dealing with soldiers. On the one hand, soldiers tend to have access to a great deal of loot, much of which consists of gold and silver, and will always seek a way to trade it for the better things in life. On the other, a heavily armed itinerant soldier is the very definition of a poor credit risk. The economistsâ barter scenario might be absurd when applied to transactions between neighbors in the same small rural community, but when dealing with a transaction between the resident of such a community and a passing mercenary, it suddenly begins to make a great deal of sense.
For much of human history, then, an ingot of gold of silver, stamped or not, has served the same role as the contemporary drug dealerâs suitcase full of unmarked bills: an object without a history, valuable because one knows it will be accepted in exchange for other goods just about anywhere, no questions asked. As a result, while credit systems tend to dominate in periods of relative social peace, or across networks of trust (whether created by states or, in most periods, transnational institutions like merchant guilds or communities of faith), in periods characterized by widespread war and plunder, they tend to be replaced by precious metal. Whatâs more, while predatory lending goes on in every period of human history, the resulting debt crises appear to have the most damaging effects at times when money is most easily convertible into cash.
As a starting point to any attempt to discern the great rhythms that define the current historical moment, let me propose the following breakdown of Eurasian history according to the alternation between periods of virtual and metal money. The cycle begins with the Age of the First Agrarian Empires (3500â800 bc), dominated by virtual credit money. This is followed by the Axial Age (800 bc-600 ad), which will be covered in the next chapter, and which saw the rise of coinage and a general shift to metal bullion. The Middle Ages (600â1450 ad), which saw a return to virtual credit money, will be covered in chapter 10; chapter 11 will cover the next turn of the cycle, the Age of Capitalist Empires, which began around 1450 with a massive planetary switch back to gold and silver bullion, and which could only really be said to have ended in 1971, when Richard Nixon announced that the U.S. dollar would no longer be redeemable in gold. This marked the beginning of yet another phase of virtual money, one which has only just begun, and whose ultimate contours are, necessarily, invisible. Chapter 12, the final chapter, will be devoted to applying the insights of history to understanding what it might mean and the opportunities it might throw open.
We have already had occasion to note the predominance of credit money in Mesopotamia, the earliest urban civilization that we know about. In the great temple and palace complexes, not only did money serve largely as an accounting measure rather than physically changing hands, merchants and tradespeople developed credit arrangements of their own. Most of these took the physical form of clay tablets, inscribed with some obligation of future payment, that were then sealed inside clay envelopes and marked with the borrowerâs seal. The creditor would keep the envelope as a surety, and it would be broken open on repayment. In some times or places at least, these **bullae** appear to have become what we would now call negotiable instruments, since the tablet inside did not simply record a promise to pay the original lender, but was designated âto the bearerââin other words, a tablet recording a debt of five shekels of silver (at prevailing rates of interest) could circulate as the equivalent of a five-shekel promissory noteâthat is, as money.[445]
We donât know how often this happened; how many hands such tablets would typically pass through, how many transactions were based on credit, how often merchants actually did weigh out silver in rough chunks to buy and sell their merchandise, or when they were most likely to do so. No doubt all this varied over time. Promissory notes usually circulated within merchant guilds, or between inhabitants of the relatively well-off urban neighborhoods where people knew one another well enough to trust them to be accountable, but not so well that they could rely on one another for more traditional forms of mutual aid.[446] We know even less about the marketplaces frequented by ordinary Mesopotamians, except that tavern-keepers operated on credit, and hawkers and operators of market stalls probably did as well.[447]
The origins of interest will forever remain obscure, since they preceded the invention of writing. The terminology for interest in most ancient languages is derived from some word for âoffspring,â causing some to speculate that it originates in loans of livestock, but this seems a bit literal-minded. More likely, the first widespread interest-bearing loans were commercial: temples and palaces would forward wares to merchants and commercial agents, who would then trade them in nearby mountain kingdoms or on trading expeditions overseas.[448]
The practice is significant because it implies a fundamental lack of trust. After all, why not simply demand a share in the profits? This seems more fair (a merchant who came back bankrupt would probably have little means of paying anyway), and profit-sharing partnerships of this sort became common practice in the later Middle East.[449] The answer seems to be that profit-sharing partnerships were typically contracted between merchants, or anyway people of similar background and experience who had ways of keeping track of one another. Palace or temple bureaucrats and world-roaming merchant adventurers had little in common, and the bureaucrats seem to have concluded that one could not normally expect a merchant returned from a far-off land to be entirely honest about his adventures. A fixed interest rate would render irrelevant whatever elaborate tales of robbery, shipwreck, or attacks by winged snakes or elephants a creative merchant might have concocted. The return was fixed in advance.
This connection between borrowing and lying, incidentally, is an important one to history. Herodotus remarked about the Persians: âTo tell a lie is considered by them the greatest disgrace, and next to that to be in debt ⊠especially because they think that one in debt must of necessity tell lies.â[450] (Later, Herodotus reported a story told to him by a Persian about the origins of the gold that the Persians had acquired in India: they stole it from the nests of giant ants.)[451] Jesusâs parable of the unforgiving servant makes a joke out of the matter (âTen thousand talents? No problem. Just give me a little more timeâ), but even here, one can see how such endless falsehoods contributed to a broader sense that a world in which moral relations are conceived as debts is also, while in certain ways entertaining, necessarily a world of corruption, guilt, and sin.
By the time of the earliest Sumerian documents, this world may not yet have arrived. Still, the principle of lending at interest, even compound interest, was already familiar to everyone. In 2402 bc, for instance, a royal inscription by King Enmetena of Lagashâone of the earliest we haveâcomplains that his enemy, the King of Umma, had been occupying a huge stretch of farmland that had rightfully belonged to Lagash for decades. He announces: if one were to calculate the rental fees for all that land, then the interest that would have been due on that rent, compounded annually, it would reveal that Umma now owes Lagash four and a half trillion liters of barley. The sum was, as in the parable, intentionally preposterous.[452] It was just an excuse to start a war. Still, he wanted everyone to know that he knew exactly how to do the math.
Usuryâin the sense of interest-bearing consumer loansâwas also well established by Enmetenaâs time. The king ultimately had his war and won it, and two years later, fresh off his victory, he was forced to publish another edict: this one, a general debt cancellation within his kingdom. As he later boasted, âhe instituted freedom **(amargi)** in Lagash. He restored the child to its mother, and the mother to her child; he cancelled all interest due.â[453] This was, in fact, the very first such declaration we have on recordâand the first time in history that the word âfreedomâ appears in a political document.
Enmetenaâs text is a bit vague on the details, but a half-century later, when his successor Uruinimgina declared a general amnesty during the New Yearâs ceremonies of 2350 bc, the terms are all spelled out, and they conform to what was to become typical of such amnesties: cancelling not only all outstanding loans, but all forms of debt servitude, even those based on failure to pay fees or criminal penaltiesâthe only thing excepted being commercial loans.
Similar declarations are to be found again and again, in Sumerian and later Babylonian and Assyrian records, and always with the same theme: the restoration of âjustice and equity,â the protection of widows and orphans, to ensureâas Hammurabi was to put it when he abolished debts in Babylon in 1761 bcââthat the strong might not oppress the weak.â[454] In the words of Michael Hudson,
The designated occasion for clearing Babyloniaâs financial slate was the New Year festival, celebrated in the spring. Babylonian rulers oversaw the ritual of âbreaking the tablets,â that is, the debt records, restoring economic balance as part of the calendrical renewal of society along with the rest of nature. Hammurabi and his fellow rulers signaled these proclamations by raising a torch, probably symbolizing the sun-god of justice Shamash, whose principles were supposed to guide wise and fair rulers. Persons held as debt pledges were released to rejoin their families. Other debtors were restored cultivation rights to their customary lands, free of whatever mortgage liens had accumulated.[455]
Over the next several thousand years, this same listâcancelling the debts, destroying the records, reallocating the landâwas to become the standard list of demands of peasant revolutionaries everywhere. In Mesopotamia, rulers appear to have headed off the possibility of unrest by instituting such reforms themselves, as a grand gesture of cosmic renewal, a recreation of the social universeâin Babylonia, during the same ceremony in which the king reenacts his god Mardukâs creation of the physical universe. The history of debt and sin was wiped out, and it was time to begin again. But itâs also clear what they saw as the alternative: the world plunged into chaos, with farmers defecting to swell the ranks of nomadic pastoralists, and ultimately, if the breakdown continued, returning to overrun the cities and destroy the existing economic order entirely.
Egypt represents an interesting contrast, since for most of its history, it managed to avoid the development of interest-bearing debt entirely.
Egypt was, like Mesopotamia, extraordinarily rich by ancient standards, but it was also a self-contained society, a river running through a desert, and far more centralized than Mesopotamia. The pharaoh was a god, and the state and temple bureaucracies had their hands in everything: there were a dazzling array of taxes and a continual distribution of allotments, wages, and payments from the state. Here, too, money clearly arose as a means of account. The basic unit was the **deben**, or âmeasureââoriginally referring to measures of grain, and later of copper or silver. A few records make clear the catch-as-catch-can nature of most transactions:
In the 15th year of Ramses II [c. 1275 BC] a merchant offered the Egyptian lady Erenofre a Syrian slave girl whose price, no doubt after bargaining, was fixed at 4 **deben** 1 **kite** [about 373 grams] of silver. Erenofre made up a collection of clothes and blankets to the value of 2 **deben** 2 1/3 **kite**âthe details are set out in the recordâand then borrowed a miscellany of objects from her neighborsâbronze vessels, a pot of honey, ten shirts, ten **deben** of copper ingotsâtill the price was made up.[456]
Most merchants were itinerant, either foreigners or commercial agents for the owners of large estates. Thereâs not much evidence for commercial credit, however; loans in Egypt were still more likely to take the form of mutual aid between neighbors.[457]
Substantial, legally enforceable loans, the kind that can lead to the loss of lands or family members, are documented, but they appear to have been rareâand much less pernicious, as the loans did not bear interest. Similarly, we do occasionally hear of debt-bondservants, and even debt slaves, but these seem to have been unusual phenomena and thereâs no suggestion that matters ever reached crisis proportions, as they so regularly did in Mesopotamia and the Levant.[458]
In fact, for the first several thousand years, we seem to be in a somewhat different world, where debt really was a matter of âguiltâ and treated largely as a criminal matter:
When a debtor failed to repay his debt on time, his creditor could take him to court, where the debtor would be required to promise to pay in full by a specific date. As part of his promiseâwhich was under oathâthe debtor also pledged to undergo 100 blows and/or repay twice the amount of the original loan if he failed to pay by the date specified.[459]
The âand/orâ is significant. There was no formal distinction between a fine and a beating. In fact, the entire purpose of the oath (rather like the Cretan custom of having a borrower pretend to snatch the money) seems to have been to create the justification for punitive action: so the debtor could be punished as **either** a perjurer or a thief.[460]
By the time of the New Kingdom (1550â1070) there is more evidence for markets, but itâs only by the time we reach the Iron Age, just before Egypt was absorbed into the Persian empire, that we begin to see evidence for Mesopotamian-style debt crises. Greek sources, for instance, record that the Pharaoh Bakenranef (reigned 720â715 bc) issued a decree abolishing debt bondage and annulling all outstanding liabilities, since âhe felt it would be absurd for a soldier, perhaps at the moment when he was setting forth to fight for his fatherland, to be hauled off to prison by his creditor for an unpaid loanââwhich, if true, is also one of the earliest mentions of a debt prison.[461] Under the Ptolemies, the Greek dynasty that ruled Egypt after Alexander, periodic clean slates had become institutionized. Itâs well known that the Rosetta Stone, written both in Greek and Egyptian, proved to be the key that made it possible to translate Egyptian hieroglyphics. Few are aware of what it actually says. The stela was originally raised to announce an amnesty, both for debtors and for prisoners, declared by Ptolemy V in 196 bc.[462]
We can say almost nothing about Bronze Age India, since its writing remains indecipherable, and not much more about Early China. What little we do knowâmainly culled from dribs and drabs in later literary sourcesâsuggests that the earliest Chinese states were far less bureaucratic than their western cousins.[463] There being no centralized temple or palace system with priests and administrators managing the storerooms and recording inputs and outputs, there was also little incentive to create a single, uniform unit of account. Instead, the evidence suggests a different path, with social currencies of various sorts still holding sway in the countryside and being converted to commercial purposes in dealings between strangers.
Later sources recall that early rulers âused pearls and jade as their superior method of payment, gold as their middle method of payment, and knives and spades as their lower method of payment.â[464] The author can only be talking about gifts here, and hierarchical ones at that: kings and great magnates rewarding their followers for services in theory rendered voluntarily. In most places, long strings of cowrie shells figure prominently, but even here, though we often hear of âthe cowrie money of early China,â and itâs easy enough to find texts in which the value of sumptuous gifts are **measured** in cowries, itâs never clear whether people were really carrying them around to buy and sell things in the marketplace.[465]
The most likely interpretation is that they were carrying the shells, but for a long time marketplaces themselves were of minor significance, so this use was not nearly as important as the usual uses for social currencies: marriage presents, fines, fees, and tokens of honor.[466] At any rate, all sources insist that there was a wide variety of currencies in circulation. As David Scheidel, one of the premier contemporary scholars of early money, notes:
In pre-imperial China, money took the form of cowrie shells, both originals andâincreasinglyâbronze imitations, tortoise shells, weighed gold and (rarely) silver bars, and most notablyâfrom at least 1000 BC onwardâutensil money in the shape of spade blades and knives made of bronze.[467]
These were most often used between people who didnât know each other very well. For tabulating debts between neighbors, with local vendors, or with anything having to do with the government, people appear to have employed a variety of credit instruments: later Chinese historians claimed that the earliest of these were knotted strings, rather like the Inca **khipu** system, and then later, notched strips of wood or bamboo.[468] As in Mesopotamia, these appear to have long predated writing.
We donât really know when the practice of lending at interest first reached China either, or whether Bronze Age China came to see the same sorts of debt crises as occurred in Mesopotamia, but there are tantalizing hints in later documents.[469] For instance, later Chinese legends about the origin of coinage ascribed the invention to emperors trying to relieve the effects of natural disasters. One early Han text reports:
In ancient times, during the floods of Yu and the droughts of Tang, the common people became so exhausted that they were forced to borrow from one another in order to obtain food and clothing. [Emperor] Yu coined money for his people from the gold of Mount Li and [Emperor] Tang did likewise from the copper of Mount Yan. Therefore the world called them benevolent.[470]
Other versions are a little more explicit. The **Guanzi**, a collection that in early imperial China became the standard primer on political economy, notes âThere were people who lacked even gruel to eat, and who were forced to sell their children. To rescue these people, Tang coined money.â[471]
The story is clearly fanciful (the real origins of coined money were at least a thousand years later), and it is very hard to know what to make of it. Could this reflect a memory of children being taken away as debt sureties? On the face of it, it seems more like starving people selling their children outrightâa practice that was later to become commonplace in certain periods of Chinese history.[472] But the juxtaposition of loans and the sale of children is suggestive, especially considering what was happening on the other side of Asia at exactly the same time. The **Guanzi** later goes on to explain that these same rulers instituted the custom of retaining 30 percent of the harvest in public granaries for redistribution in emergencies, so as to ensure that this would never happen again. In other words, they began to set up just the kind of bureaucratic storage facilities that, in places like Egypt and Mesopotamia, had been responsible for creating money as a unit of account to begin with.
<em>Let us designate this period as the âaxial age.â Extraordinary events are crowded into this period. In China lived Confucius and Lao Tse, all the trends in Chinese philosophy arose ⊠In India it was the age of the Upanishads and of Buddha; as in China, all philosophical trends, including skepticism and materialism, sophistry and nihilism, were developed</em>.
The phrase "The Axial Age" was coined by the German existentialist philosopher Karl Jaspers.[473] In the course of writing a history of philosophy, Jaspers became fascinated by the fact that figures like Pythagoras (570â495 bc), the Buddha (563â483 bc), and Confucius (551â479 bc), were all alive at exactly the same time, and that Greece, India, and China, in that period, all saw a sudden efflorescence of debate between contending intellectual schools, each group apparently, unaware of the othersâ existence. Like the simultaneous invention of coinage, why this happened had always been a puzzle. Jaspers wasnât entirely sure himself. To some extent, he suggested, it must have been an effect of similar historical conditions. For most of the great urban civilizations of the time, the early Iron Age was a kind of pause between empires, a time when political landscapes were broken into a checkerboard of often diminutive kingdoms and city-states, most often at constant war externally and locked in constant political debate within. Each case witnessed the development of something akin to a drop-out culture, with ascetics and sages fleeing to the wilderness or wandering from town to town seeking wisdom; in each, too, they were eventually reabsorbed into the political order as a new kind of intellectual or spiritual elite, whether as Greek sophists, Jewish prophets, Chinese sages, or Indian holy men.
Whatever the reasons, the result, Jaspers argued, was the first period in history in which human beings applied principles of reasoned inquiry to the great questions of human existence. He observed that all these great regions of the world, China, India, and the Mediterranean, saw the emergence of remarkably parallel philosophical trends, from skepticism to idealismâin fact, almost the entire range of positions about the nature of the cosmos, mind, action, and the ends of human existence that have remained the stuff of philosophy to this day. As one of Jaspersâ disciples later put itâoverstating only slightlyââno really new ideas have been added since that time.â[474]
For Jaspers, the period begins with the Persian prophet Zoroaster, around 800 bc, and ends around 200 bc, to be followed by a Spiritual Age that centers on figures like Jesus and Mohammed. For my own purposes, I find it more useful to combine the two. Let us define the Axial Age, then, as running from 800 bc to 600 ad.[475] This makes the Axial Age the period that saw the birth not only of all the worldâs major philosophical tendencies, but also, all of todayâs major world religions: Zoroastrianism, Prophetic Judaism, Buddhism, Jainism, Hinduism, Confucianism, Taoism, Christianity, and Islam.[476]
The attentive reader may have noticed that the core period of Jasperâs Axial ageâthe lifetimes of Pythagoras, Confucius, and the Buddhaâcorresponds almost exactly to the period in which coinage was invented. Whatâs more, the three parts of the world where coins were first invented were also the very parts of the world where those sages lived; in fact, they became the epicenters of Axial Age religious and philosophical creativity: the kingdoms and city-states around the Yellow River in China, the Ganges valley in northern India, and the shores of the Aegean Sea.
What was the connection? We might start by asking: What is a coin? The normal definition is that a coin is a piece of valuable metal, shaped into a standardized unit, with some emblem or mark inscribed to authenticate it. The worldâs first coins appear to have been created within the kingdom of Lydia, in western Anatolia (now Turkey), sometime around 600 bc.[477] These first Lydian coins were basically just round lumps of electrumâa gold-silver alloy that occurred naturally in the nearby Pactolus Riverâthat had been heated, then hammered with some kind of insignia. The very first, stamped only with a few letters, appear to have been manufactured by ordinary jewelers, but these disappeared almost instantly, replaced by coins manufactured in a newly established royal mint. Greek cities on the Anatolian coast soon began to strike their own coins, and they came to be adopted in Greece itself; the same thing occurred in the Persian Empire after it absorbed Lydia in 547 bc.
In both India and China, we can observe the same pattern: invented by private citizens, coinage was quickly monopolized by the state. The first Indian money, which seems to have appeared at some point in the sixth century, consisted of bars of silver trimmed down to uniform weights, then punch-marked with some kind of official symbol.[478] Most of the examples discovered by archaeologists contain numerous additional counter-punches, presumably added much in the way that a check or other credit instrument is endorsed before being transferred. This strongly suggests that they were being handled by people used to dealing with more abstract credit instruments.[479] Much early Chinese coinage also shows signs of having evolved directly from social currencies: some were in fact cast bronze in the shape of cowries, though others took the shape of diminutive knives, disks, or spades. In every case, local governments quickly stepped inâpresumably within the space of about a generation.[480] However, since in each of the three areas there was a plethora of tiny states, this meant that each ended up with a wide variety of different currency systems. For example, around 700 bc, northern India was still divided into Janapadas or âtribal territories,â some of them monarchies and some republics, and in the sixth century there were still at least sixteen major kingdoms. In China, this was the period where the old Zhou Empire first devolved into vying principalities (the âSpring and Autumnâ period, 722â481 bc), then splintered into the chaos of the âWarring Statesâ (475â221 bc.) Like the Greek city-states, all of the resulting kingdoms, no matter how diminutive, aspired to issue their own official currency.
Recent scholarship has shed a great deal of light on how this must have happened. Gold, silver, and bronzeâthe materials from which coins were madeâhad long been the media of international trade; but until that time, only the rich had actually had much in their possession. A typical Sumerian farmer may well have never had occasion to hold a substantial piece of silver in his hand, except perhaps at his wedding. Most precious metals took the form of wealthy womenâs anklets and heirloom chalices presented by kings to their retainers, or it was simply stockpiled in temples, in ingot form, as sureties for loans. Somehow, during the Axial Age, all this began to change. Large amounts of silver, gold, and copper were dethesaurized, as the economic historians like to say; it was removed from the temples and houses of the rich and placed in the hands of ordinary people, was broken into tinier pieces, and began to be used in everyday transactions.
How? Israeli Classicist David Schaps provides the most plausible suggestion: most of it was stolen. This was a period of generalized warfare, and it is in the nature of war that precious things are plundered.
Soldiers who plunder may indeed go first for the women, the alcoholic drinks, or the food, but they will also be looking around for things of value that are easily portable. A long-term standing army will tend to accumulate many things that are valuable and portableâand the most valuable and portable items are precious metals and precious stones. It may well have been the protracted wars among the states of these areas that first produced a large population of people with precious metal in their possession and a need for everyday necessities âŠ
Where there are people who want to buy there will be people willing to sell, as innumerable tracts on black markets, drug dealing, and prostitution point out ⊠The constant warfare of the archaic age of Greece, of the Janapadas of India, of the Warring States of China, was a powerful impetus for the development of market trade, and in particular for market trade based on the exchange of precious metal, usually in small amounts. If plunder brought precious metal into the hands of the soldiers, the market will have spread it through the population.[481]
Now, one might object: but surely, war and plunder were nothing new. The Homeric epics, for instance, show a well-nigh obsessive interest in the division of the spoils. True, but what the Axial Age also sawâagain, equally in China, India, and the Aegeanâwas the rise of a new kind of army, made up not of aristocratic warriors and their retainers, but trained professionals. The period when the Greeks began to use coinage, for instance, was also the period when they developed their famous phalanx tactics, which required constant drill and training of the hoplite soldiers. The results were so extraordinarily effective that Greek mercenaries were soon being sought after from Egypt to Crimea. But unlike the Homeric retainers, who could simply be ignored, an army of trained mercenaries needs to be rewarded in some meaningful way. One could perhaps provide them all with livestock, but livestock are hard to transport; or with promissory notes, but these would be worthless in the mercenariesâ own country. Allowing each a tiny share of the plunder does seem an obvious solution.
These new armies were, directly or indirectly, under the control of governments, and it took governments to turn these chunks of metal into genuine currency. The main reason for this is simply scale: to create enough coins that the people could begin to use them in everyday transactions required mass production on a scale far beyond the abilities of local merchants or smiths.[482] Of course we have already seen why governments might have incentive to do so: the existence of markets was highly convenient for governments, and not just because it made it so much easier for them to provision large standing armies. By insisting that only their own coins were acceptable as fees, fines, or taxes, governments were able to overwhelm the innumerable social currencies that already existed in their hinterlands, and to establish something like uniform national markets.
Actually, one theory is that the very first Lydian coins were invented explicitly to pay mercenaries.[483] This might help explain why the Greeks, who supplied most of the mercenaries, so quickly became accustomed to the use of coins, and why the use of coinage spread so quickly across the Hellenic world, so that by 480 bc there were at least one hundred mints operating in different Greek cities, even though at that time, none of the great trading nations of the Mediterranean had as yet showed the slightest interest in them. The Phoenicians, for example, were considered the greatest merchants and bankers of antiquity.[484] They were also great inventors, having been the first to develop both the alphabet and the abacus. Yet for centuries after the invention of coinage, they preferred to continue conducting business as they always had, with unwrought ingots and promissory notes.[485] Phoenician cities struck no coins until 365 bc, and while Carthage, the great Phoenician colony in North Africa that came to dominate commerce in the Western Mediterranean, did so a bit earlier, it was only when âforced to do so to pay Sicilian mercenaries; and its issues were marked in Punic, âfor the people of the camp.â â[486]
On the other hand, in the extraordinary violence of the Axial Age, being a âgreat trading nationâ (rather than, say, an aggressive military power like Persia, Athens, or Rome) was not, ultimately, a winning proposition. The fate of the Phoenician cities is instructive. Sidon, the wealthiest, was destroyed by the Persian emperor Artaxerxes III after a revolt in 351 bc. Forty thousand of its inhabitants are said to have committed mass suicide rather than surrender. Nineteen years later, Tyre was destroyed after a prolonged siege by Alexander: ten thousand died in battle, and the thirty thousand survivors were sold into slavery. Carthage lasted longer, but when Roman armies finally destroyed the city in 146 bc, hundreds of thousands of Carthaginians were said to have been raped and slaughtered, and fifty thousand captives put on the auction block, after which the city itself was razed and its fields sowed with salt.
All this may bring home something of the level of violence amidst which Axial Age thought developed.[487] But it also leaves us asking: What exactly was the ongoing relation among coinage, military power, and this unprecedented outpouring of ideas?
Here again our best information is from the Mediterranean world, and I have already provided some of its outlines. Comparing Athensâwith its far-flung naval empireâand Rome, we can immediately detect striking similarities. In each city, history begins with a series of debt crises. In Athens, the first crisis, the one that culminated in Solonâs reforms of 594 bc, was so early that coinage could hardly have been a factor. In Rome, too, the earliest crises seem to have proceeded the advent of currency. Rather, in each case, coinage became a solution. In brief, one might say that these conflicts over debt had two possible outcomes. The first was that the aristocrats could win, and the poor remain âslaves of the richââwhich in practice meant that most people would end up clients of some wealthy patron. Such states were generally militarily ineffective.[488] The second was that popular factions could prevail, institute the usual popular program of redistribution of lands and safeguards against debt peonage, thus creating the basis for a class of free farmers whose children would, in turn, be free to spend much of their time training for war.[489]
Coinage played a critical role in maintaining this kind of free peasantryâsecure in their landholding, not tied to any great lord by bonds of debt. In fact, the fiscal policies of many Greek cities amounted to little more than elaborate systems for the distribution of loot. Itâs important to emphasize that few ancient cities, if any, went so far as to outlaw predatory lending, or even debt peonage, entirely. Instead, they threw money at the problem. Gold, and especially silver, were acquired in war, or mined by slaves captured in war. Mints were located in temples (the traditional place for depositing spoils), and city-states developed endless ways to distribute coins, not only to soldiers, sailors, and those producing arms or outfitting ships, but to the populace generally, as jury fees, fees for attending public assemblies, or sometimes just as outright distributions, as Athens did most famously when they discovered a new vein of silver in the mines at Laurium in 483 bc. At the same time, insisting that the same coins served as legal tender for all payments due to the state guaranteed that they would be in sufficient demand that markets would soon develop.
Many of the political crises in ancient Greek cities similarly turned on the distribution of the spoils. Here is another incident recorded in Aristotle, who provides a conservative take on the origins of a coup in the city of Rhodes around 391 bc (âdemagoguesâ here refers to the leaders of the democracy):
The demagogues needed money to pay the people for attending the assembly and serving on juries; for if the people did not attend, the demagogues would lose their influence. They raised at least some of the money they needed by preventing the disbursement of the money due the trireme [warship] commanders under their contracts with the city to build and fit triremes for the Rhodian navy. Since the trireme commanders were not paid, they were unable in turn to pay their suppliers and workers, who sued the trireme commanders. To escape these lawsuits the trireme commanders banded together and overthrew the democracy.[490]
It was slavery, though, that made all this possible. As the figures concerning Sidon, Tyre, and Carthage suggest, enormous numbers of people were being enslaved in many of these conflicts, and, of course, many slaves ended up working in the mines, producing even more gold, silver, and copper. (The mines in Laurium reportedly employed ten to twenty thousand of them.)[491]
Geoffrey Ingham calls the resulting system a âmilitary-coinage complexââthough I think it would be more accurate to call it a âmilitary-coinage-slavery complex.â[492] Anyway, that describes rather nicely how it worked in practice. When Alexander set out to conquer the Persian Empire, he borrowed much of the money with which to pay and provision his troops, and he minted his first coins, used to pay his creditors and continue to support the money, by melting down gold and silver plundered after his initial victories.[493] However, an expeditionary force needed to be paid, and paid well: Alexanderâs army, which numbered some 120,000 men, required half a ton of silver a day just for wages. For this reason, conquest meant that the existing Persian system of mines and mints had to be reorganized around providing for the invading army; and ancient mines, of course, were worked by slaves. In turn, most slaves in mines were war captives. Presumably most of the unfortunate survivors of the siege of Tyre ended up working in such mines. One can see how this process might feed upon itself.[494]
Alexander was also the man responsible for destroying what remained of the ancient credit systems, since not only the Phoenicians but also the old Mesopotamian heartland had resisted the new coin economy. His armies not only destroyed Tyre; they also dethesaurized the gold and silver reserves of Babylonian and Persian temples, the security on which their credit systems were based, and insisted that all taxes to his new government be paid in his own money. The result was to ârelease the accumulated specie of century onto the market in a matter of months,â something like 180,000 talents, or in contemporary terms, an estimated $285 billion.[495]
The Hellenistic successor kingdoms established by Alexanderâs generals, from Greece to India, employed mercenaries rather than national armies, but the story of Rome is, again, similar to that of Athens. Its early history, as recorded by official chroniclers like Livy, is one of continual struggles between patricians and plebians, and of continual crises over debt. Periodically, these would lead to what were called moments of âthe secession of the plebs,â when the commoners of the city abandoned their fields and workshops, camped outside the city, and threatened mass defectionâan interesting halfway point between the popular revolts of Greece and the strategy of exodus typically pursued in Egypt and Mesopotamia. Here, too, the patricians were ultimately faced with a decision: they could use agricultural loans to gradually turn the plebian population into a class of bonded laborers on their estates, or they could accede to popular demands for debt protection, preserve a free peasantry, and employ the younger sons of free farm families as soldiers.[496] As the prolonged history of crises, secessions, and reforms makes clear, the choice was made grudgingly.[497] The plebs practically had to force the senatorial class to take the imperial option. Still, they did, and over time they gradually presided over the establishment of a welfare system that recycled at least a share of the spoils to soldiers, veterans, and their families.
It seems significant, in this light, that the traditional date of the first Roman coinageâ338 bcâis almost exactly the date when debt bondage was finally outlawed (326 bc).[498] Again, coinage, minted from war spoils, didnât cause the crisis. It was used as a solution.
In fact, the entire Roman empire, at its height, could be understood as a vast machine for the extraction of precious metals and their coining and distribution to the militaryâcombined with taxation policies designed to encourage conquered populations to adopt coins in their everyday transactions. Even so, for most of its history, use of coins was heavily concentrated in two regions: in Italy and a few major cities, and on the frontiers, where the legions were actually stationed. In areas where there were neither mines nor military operations, older credit systems presumably continued to operate.
I will add one final note here. In Greece as in Rome, attempts to solve the debt crisis through military expansion were always, ultimately, just ways of fending off the problemâand they only worked for a limited period of time. When expansion stopped, everything returned to as it had been before. Actually, itâs not clear that all forms of debt bondage were ever entirely eliminated even in cities like Athens and Rome. In cities that were not successful military powers, without any source of income to set up welfare policies, debt crises continued to flare up every century or soâand they often became far more acute than they ever had in the Middle East, because there was no mechanism, short of outright revolution, to declare a Mesopotamian-style clean slate. Large populations, even in the Greek world, did, in fact, sink to the rank of serfs and clients.[499]
Athenians, as weâve seen, seemed to assume that a gentleman normally lived a step or two ahead of his creditors. Roman politicians were little different. Of course much of the debt was money that members of the senatorial class owed to each other: in a way, itâs just the usual communism of the rich, extending credit to one another on easy terms that they would never think to offer others. Still, under the late Republic, history records many intrigues and conspiracies hatched by desperate debtors, often aristocrats driven by relentless creditors to make common cause with the poor.[500] If we hear less about this sort of thing happening under the emperors, itâs probably because there were fewer opportunities for protest; what evidence we have suggests that if anything, the problem got much worse.[501] Around 100 ad, Plutarch wrote about his own country as if it were under foreign invasion:
And as King Darius sent to the city of Athens his lieutenants Datis and Artaphernes with chains and cords, to bind the prisoners they should take; so these usurers, bringing into Greece boxes full of schedules, bills, and obligatory contracts, as so many irons and fetters for the shackling of poor criminals âŠ
For at the very delivery of their money, they immediately ask it back, taking it up at the same moment they lay it down; and they let out that again to interest which they take for the use of what they have before lent.
So that they laugh at those natural philosophers who hold that nothing can be made of nothing and of that which has no existence; but with them usury is made and engendered of that which neither is nor ever was.[502]
The works of the early Christian fathers likewise resound with endless descriptions of the misery and desperation of those caught in rich lendersâ webs. In the end, through this means, that small window of freedom that had been created by the plebs was completely undone, and the free peasantry largely eliminated. By the end of the empire, most people in the countryside who werenât outright slaves had become, effectively, debt peons to some rich landlord; a situation in the end legally formalized by imperial decrees binding peasants to the land.[503] Without a free peasantry to form the basis for the army, the state was forced to rely more and more on arming and employing Germanic barbarians from across the imperial frontiersâwith results I need hardly relate.
In most ways, India could not be more different as a civilization than the ancient Mediterraneanâbut to a remarkable degree, the same basic pattern repeats itself there as well.
The Bronze Age civilization of the Indus Valley collapsed sometime around 1600 bc; it would be about a thousand years before India saw the emergence of another urban civilization. When it did, that civilization was centered on the fertile plains that surrounded the Ganges farther east. Here too we observe, at first, a checkerboard of different sorts of government, from the famous âKsatriya republicsâ with a populace in arms and urban democratic assemblies, to elective monarchies, to centralized empires like Kosala and Magadha.[504] Both Gautama (the future Buddha), and Mahavira (the founder of Jainism) were born in one of the republics, though both ultimately found themselves teaching within the great empires, whose rulers often became patrons of wandering ascetics and philosophers.
Both kingdoms and republics produced their own silver and copper coinage, but in some ways the republics were more traditional, since the self-governing âpopulace in armsâ consisted of the traditional Ksatriya or warrior caste, who typically held their lands in common and had them worked by serfs or slaves.[505] The kingdoms, on the other hand, were founded on a fundamentally new institution: a trained, professional army, open to young men of a wide variety of backgrounds, their equipment supplied by central authorities (soldiers were obliged to check their arms and armor when they entered cities), and provided with generous salaries.
Whatever their origins, here too, coins and markets sprung up above all to feed the machinery of war. Magadha, which ultimately came out on top, did so largely because it controlled most of the mines. Kautilyaâs **Arthasastra**, a political treatise written by one of the chief ministers for the Mauryan dynasty that succeeded it (321â185 bc), stated the matter precisely: âThe treasury is based upon mining, the army upon the treasury; he who has army and treasury may conquer the whole wide earth.â[506] The government drew its personnel first of all from a landed class, which provided trained administrators, but even more, full-time soldiers: the salaries of each rank of soldier and administrator were carefully stipulated. These armies could be huge. Greek sources report that Magadha could put to the field a force of 200,000 infantry, 20,000 horses, and about 4,000 elephantsâand that Alexanderâs men mutinied rather than have to face them. Whether on campaign or in garrison, they were inevitably accompanied by a range of different sorts of camp followersâpetty traders, prostitutes, and hired servantsâwhich, with the soldiers, seems to have been the very medium through which a cash economy had originally taken form.[507] By Kautilyaâs time, a few hundred years later, the state was inserting itself into every aspect of the process: Kautilya suggests paying soldiers apparently generous wages, then secretly replacing hawkers with government agents who could charge them twice the normal rates for supplies, as well as organizing prostitutes under a ministry in which they could be trained as spies, so as to make detailed reports on their clientsâ loyalties.
Thus was the market economy, born of war, gradually taken over by the government. Rather than stifle the spread of currency, the process seems to have doubled and even tripled it: the military logic was extended to the entire economy, the government systematically setting up its granaries, workshops, trading houses, warehouses, and jails, staffed by salaried officials, and all selling products on the market so as to collect the pieces of silver paid off to soldiers and officials and put them back into the royal treasuries again.[508] The result was a monetarization of daily life unlike anything India was to see for another two thousand years.[509]
Something similar seems to have happened with slavery, which was quite commonplace at the time of the rise of the great armiesâagain, unlike almost any other point in Indian historyâbut was gradually brought under government control.[510] By Kautilyaâs time, most war captives were not sold in marketplaces but relocated to government villages on newly reclaimed land. They were not allowed to leave, and these government villages were, at least according to the regulations, remarkably dreary places: veritable work camps, with all forms of festive entertainment officially prohibited. Slave hirelings were mostly convicts, rented by the state during their terms.
With their armies, spies, and administration controlling everything, the new Indian kings evinced little interest in the old priestly caste and its Vedic ritual, though many kept up a lively interest in the new philosophical and religious ideas that seem to have been cropping up everywhere at the time. As time went on, however, the war machine began to sputter. Itâs not clear exactly why this happened. By the time of emperor AĆoka (273â232 bc), the Mauryan dynasty controlled almost all of present-day India and Pakistan, but the Indian version of the military-coinage-slavery complex was showing definite signs of strain. Perhaps the clearest sign was the debasement of the coinage, which over the course of two centuries or so had gone from almost pure silver to about fifty percent copper.[511]
AĆoka, famously, began his reign in conquest: in 265 bc, destroying the Kalingas, one of the last remaining Indian republics, in a war in which hundreds of thousands of human beings were, according to his own account, killed or carried off into slavery. AĆoka later claimed to have been so disturbed and haunted by the carnage that he renounced war altogether, embraced Buddhism, and declared that from that time on, his kingdom would be governed by principles of **ahimsa**, or nonviolence. âHere in my kingdom,â he declared in an edict inscribed on one of the great granite pillars in his capital of Patna, which so dazzled the Greek ambassador Megasthenes, âno living being must be killed and sacrificed.â[512] Such a statement obviously canât be taken literally: AĆoka might have replaced sacrificial ritual with vegetarian feasts, but he didnât abolish the army, abandon capital punishment, or even outlaw slavery. But his rule marked a revolutionary shift in ethos. Aggressive war was abandoned, and much of the army does seems to have been demobilized, along with the network of spies and state bureaucrats, with the new, proliferating mendicant orders (Buddhists, Jains, and also world-renouncing Hindus) given official state support to preach to the villages on questions of social morality. AĆoka and his successors diverted substantial resources to these religious orders, with the result that, over the next centuries, thousands of stupas and monasteries were built across the subcontinent.[513]
AĆokaâs reforms are useful to contemplate here because they help reveal just how mistaken some of our basic assumptions are: particularly, that money equals coins, and that more coins in circulation means more commerce and a greater role for private merchants. In reality, the Magadha state promoted markets but had been suspicious of private merchants, seeing them largely as competitors.[514] Merchants had been among the earliest and most ardent supporters of the new religions (Jains, owing to their rigorous enforcement of rules against harm to any living creature, were obliged to become, effectively, a mercantile caste). Mercantile interests fully supported AĆokaâs reforms. Yet the result was not an increase in the use of cash in everyday affairs but exactly the opposite.
Early Buddhist economic attitudes have long been considered a bit mysterious. On the one hand, monks could not own property as individuals; they were expected to live an austere communistic life with little more than a robe and begging bowl as personal possessions, and they were strictly forbidden to so much as touch anything made of gold or silver. On the other hand, however suspicious of precious metals, Buddhism had always had a liberal attitude toward credit arrangements. It is one of the few of the great world religions that has never formally condemned usury.[515] Taken in the context of the times, however, thereâs nothing particularly mysterious about any of this. It makes perfect sense for a religious movement that rejected violence and militarism, but that was in no way opposed to commerce.[516] As we shall see, while AĆokaâs own empire was not long to endure, soon to be replaced by a succession of ever weaker and mostly smaller states, Buddhism took root. The decline of the great armies eventually led to the near-disappearance of coinage, but also to a veritable efflorescence of increasingly sophisticated forms of credit.
Until about 475 bc, northern China was still nominally an empire, but the emperors had devolved into figureheads and a series of de facto kingdoms had emerged. The period from 475 to 221 bc is referred as the âWarring States periodâ; at that point, even the pretense of unity was cast aside. Ultimately, the country was reunited by the state of Qin, who established a dynasty that was then immediately overthrown by a series of massive popular insurrections, ushering in the Han dynasty (206 bc-220 ad), founded by a previously obscure rural constable and peasant leader named Liu Bao, who was the first Chinese leader to adopt the Confucian ideology, exam system, and pattern of civil administration that were to continue for almost two thousand years.
Still, the golden age of Chinese philosophy was the period of chaos that preceded unification, and this followed the typical Axial Age pattern: the same fractured political landscape, the same rise of trained, professional armies and the creation of coined money largely in order to pay them.[517] We also see the same government policies designed to encourage the development of markets, chattel slavery on a scale not seen before or since in Chinese history, the appearance of itinerant philosophers and religious visionaries, battling intellectual schools, and eventually, attempts by political leaders to transform the new philosophies into religions of state.[518]
There were also significant differences, starting with the currency system. China never minted gold or silver coins. Merchants used precious metals in the form of bullion, but the coins in actual circulation were basically small change: cast bronze disks, usually with a hole in the middle so that they could be strung together. Such strings of âcashâ were produced in extraordinary numbers, and very large amounts had to be assembled for large-scale transactions: when wealthy men wished to make donations to temples, for instance, they had to use oxcarts to carry the money. The most plausible explanation is that, especially after unification, Chinese armies were enormousâsome Warring States armies numbered up to a millionâbut not nearly as professional or well paid as those of kingdoms farther west, and from Qin and Han times on, rulers were careful to ensure that this remained the case, to make sure the army never became an independent power base.[519]
There was also a notable difference in that the new religious and philosophical movements in China were from their very beginnings also social movements. Elsewhere, they only gradually became so. In ancient Greece, philosophy began with cosmological speculation; philosophers were more likely to be individual sages, perhaps surrounded by a few ardent disciples, as founders of movements.[520] Under the Roman empire, schools of philosophy like the Stoics, Epicureans, Neo-Platonists did become movements of a sort: at least in the sense that they had thousands of educated adherents, who âpracticedâ philosophy not only by reading, writing, and debating, but even more by meditation, diet, and exercise. Still, philosophical movements were basically confined to the civic elite; it was only with the rise of Christianity and other religious movements that philosophy moved beyond it.[521] One can observe a similar evolution in India, from individual Brahman world-renouncers, forest sages, and wandering mendicants with theories about the nature of the soul or the composition of the material universe; to philosophical movements of the Buddhists, Jains, ÄjÄ«vika, and others mostly long forgotten; to, finally, mass religious movements with thousands of monks, shrines, schools, and networks of lay supporters.
In China, while many of the founders of the âhundred schoolsâ of philosophy that blossomed under the Warring States were wandering sages who spent their days moving from city to city trying to catch the ears of princes, others were leaders of social movements from the very start. Some of these movements didnât even have leaders, like the School of the Tillers, an anarchist movement of peasant intellectuals who set out to create egalitarian communities in the cracks and fissures between states.[522] The Mohists, egalitarian rationalists whose social base seems to have been urban artisans, not only were philosophically opposed to war and militarism, but organized battalions of military engineers who would actively discourage conflicts by volunteering to fight in any war against the side of the aggressor. Even the Confucians, for all the importance they attached to courtly ritual, were in their early days mainly known for their efforts in popular education.[523]
What is one to make of all this? The popular education campaigns of the period perhaps provide a clue. The Axial Age was the first time in human history when familiarity with the written word was no longer limited to priests, administrators, and merchants, but had become necessary to full participation in civic life. In Athens, it was taken for granted that only a country bumpkin would be entirely illiterate.
Without mass literacy, neither the emergence of mass intellectual movements, nor the spread of Axial Age ideas would have been possible. By the end of the period, these ideas had produced a world where even the leaders of barbarian armies descending on the Roman empire felt obliged to take a position on the question of the Mystery of the Trinity, and where Chinese monks could spend time debating the relative merits of the eighteen schools of Classical Indian Buddhism.
No doubt the growth of markets played a role too, not only helping to free people from the proverbial shackles of status or community, but encouraging a certain habit of rational calculation, of measuring inputs and outputs, means and ends, all of which must inevitably have found some echoes in the new spirit of rational inquiry that begins to appear in all the same times and places. Even the word ârationalâ is telling: it derives, of course, from âratioââhow many of X go into Yâa sort of mathematical calculation previously used mainly by architects and engineers, but which, with the rise of markets, everyone who didnât want to get cheated at the marketplace had to learn how to do. Still, we must be careful here. After all, money in itself was nothing new. Sumerian farmers and tradesmen were already perfectly capable of making such calculations in 3500 bc; but none, as far as we know, were so impressed that they concluded, like Pythagoras, that mathematical ratios were the key to understanding the nature of the universe and the movement of celestial bodies, and that all things were ultimately composed of numbersâand they certainly hadnât formed secret societies based on sharing this understanding, debating and purging and excommunicating one another.[524]
To understand what had changed, we have to look, again, at the particular **kind** of markets that were emerging at the beginning of the Axial Age: impersonal markets, born of war, in which it was possible to treat even neighbors as if they were strangers.
Within human economies, motives are assumed to be complex. When a lord gives a gift to a retainer, there is no reason to doubt that it is inspired by a genuine desire to benefit that retainer, even if it is also a strategic move designed to ensure loyalty, and an act of magnificence meant to remind everyone else that he is great and the retainer small. There is no sense of contradiction here. Similarly, gifts between equals are usually fraught with many layers of love, envy, pride, spite, communal solidarity, or any of a dozen other things. Speculating on such matters is a major form of daily entertainment. Whatâs missing, though, is any sense that the most selfish (âself-interestedâ) motive is necessarily the real one: those speculating on hidden motives are just as likely to assume that someone is secretly trying to help a friend or harm an enemy as to acquire some advantage for him- or herself.[525] Neither is any of this likely to have changed much in the rise of early credit markets, where the value of an IOU was as much dependent on assessments of its issuerâs character as on his disposable income, and motives of love, envy, pride, etc. could never be completely set aside.
Cash transactions between strangers were different, and all the more so when trading is set against a background of war and emerges from disposing of loot and provisioning soldiers; when one often had best not ask where the objects traded came from, and where no one is much interested in forming ongoing personal relationships anyway. Here, transactions really do become simply a figuring-out of how many of X will go for how many of Y, of calculating proportions, estimating quality, and trying to get the best deal for oneself. The result, during the Axial Age, was a new way of thinking about human motivation, a radical simplification of motives that made it possible to begin speaking of concepts like âprofitâ and âadvantageââand imagining that this is what people are **really** pursuing, in every aspect of existence, as if the violence of war or the impersonality of the marketplace has simply allowed them to drop the pretense that they ever cared about anything else. It was this, in turn, that allowed human life to seem like it could be reduced to a matter of means-to-end calculation, and hence something that could be examined using the same means that one used to study the attraction and repulsion of celestial bodies.[526] If the underlying assumption very much resembles those of contemporary economists, itâs no coincidenceâbut with the difference that, in an age when money, markets, states, and military affairs were all intrinsically connected, money was needed to pay armies to capture slaves to mine gold to produce money; when âcutthroat competitionâ often did involve the literal cutting of throats, it never occurred to anyone to imagine that selfish ends could be pursued by peaceful means. Certainly, this picture of humanity does begin to appear, with startling consistency, across Eurasia, wherever we also see coinage and philosophy appear.
China provides an unusually transparent case in point. Already in Confuciusâs time, Chinese thinkers were speaking of the pursuit of profit as the driving force in human life. The actual term used was **li**, a word first used to refer to the increase of grain one harvests from a field over and above what one originally planted (the pictogram represents a sheaf of wheat next to a knife).[527] From there it came to mean commercial profit, and thence, a general term for âbenefitâ or âpayback.â The following story, which purports to tell the reaction of a merchantâs son named LĂŒ Buwei on learning that an exiled prince was living nearby, illustrates the progression nicely:
On returning home, he said to his father, âWhat is the profit on investment that one can expect from plowing fields?â
âTen times the investment,â replied his father.
âAnd the return on investment in pearls and jades is how much?â
âA hundredfold.â
âAnd the return on investment from establishing a ruler and securing the state would be how much?â
âIt would be incalculable.â[528]
LĂŒ adopted the princeâs cause and eventually contrived to make him King of Qin. He went on to became first minister for the kingâs son, Qin Shi Huang, helping him defeat the other Warring States to became the first Emperor of China. We still have a compendium of political wisdom that LĂŒ commissioned for the new emperor, which contains such military advice as the following:
As a general principle, when an enemyâs army comes, it seeks some profit. Now if they come and find the prospect of death instead, they will consider running away the most profitable thing to do. When all oneâs enemies consider running to be the most profitable thing to do, no blades will cross.
This is the most essential point in military matters.[529]
In such a world, heroic considerations of honor and glory, vows to gods or desire for vengeance, were at best weaknesses to be manipulated. In the numerous manuals on statecraft produced at the time, everything was cast as a matter of recognizing interest and advantage, calculating how to balance that which will profit the ruler against that which will profit the people, determining when the rulerâs interests are the same as the peopleâs and when they contradict.[530] Technical terms drawn from politics, economics, and military strategy (âreturn on investment,â âstrategic advantageâ) blended and overlapped.
The predominant school of political thought under the Warring States was that of the Legalists, who insisted that in matters of statecraft, a rulerâs interests were the only consideration, even if rulers would be unwise to admit this. Still, the people could be easily manipulated, since they had the same motivations: the peopleâs pursuit of profit, wrote Lord Shang, is utterly predictable, âjust like the tendency of water to flow downhill.â[531] Shang was harsher than most of his fellow Legalists in that he believed that widespread prosperity would ultimately harm the rulerâs ability to mobilize his people for war, and therefore that terror was the most efficient instrument of governance, but even he insisted that this regime be clothed as a regime of law and justice.
Wherever the military-coinage-slavery complex began to take hold, we find political theorists propounding similar ideas. Kautilya was no different: the title of his book, the **Arthasastra**, is usually translated as âmanual of statecraft,â since it consists of advice to rulers, but its more literal translation is âthe science of material gain.â[532] Like the Legalists, Kautilya emphasized the need to create a pretext that governance was a matter of morality and justice, but in addressing the rulers themselves, he insisted that âwar and peace are considered solely from the point of view of profitââof amassing wealth to create a more effective army, of using the army to dominate markets and control resources to amass more wealth, and so on.[533] In Greece weâve already met Thrasymachos. True, Greece was slightly different. Greek city-states did not have kings, and the collapse of private interests and affairs of state was in principle universally denounced as tyranny. Still, in practice, what this meant was that city-states, and even political factions, ended up acting in precisely the same coldly calculating way as Indian or Chinese sovereigns. Anyone who has ever read Thucydidesâ Melian dialogueâin which Athenian generals present the population of a previously friendly city with elegantly reasoned arguments for why the Athenians have determined that it is to the advantage of their empire to threaten them with collective massacre if they are not willing to become tribute-paying subjects, and why it is equally in the interests of the Melians to submitâis aware of the results.[534]
Another striking feature of this literature is its resolute materialism. Goddesses and gods, magic and oracles, sacrificial ritual, ancestral cults, even caste and ritual status systems all either disappear or are sidelined, no longer treated as ends in themselves but as yet mere tools to be used for the pursuit of material gain.
That intellectuals willing to produce such theories should win the ears of princes is hardly surprising. Neither is it particularly surprising that other intellectuals should have been so offended by this sort of cynicism that they began to make common cause with the popular movements that inevitably began to form against those princes. But as is so often the case, oppositional intellectuals were faced with two choices: either adopt the reigning terms of debate, or try to come up with a diametrical inversion. Mo Di, the founder of Mohism, took the first approach. He turned the concept of li, profit, into something more like âsocial utility,â and then he attempted to demonstrate that war itself is, by definition, an unprofitable activity. For example, he wrote, campaigns can only be fought in spring and autumn, and each had equally deleterious effects:
If in the spring then the people miss their sowing and planting, if in the autumn, they miss their reaping and harvesting. Even if they miss only one season, then the number of people who will die of cold and hunger is incalculable. Now let us calculate the armyâs equipment, the arrows, standards, tents, armor, shields, and sword hilts; the number of these which will break and perish and not come back ⊠So also with oxen and horses âŠ[535]
His conclusion: if one could add up the total costs of aggression in human lives, animal lives, and material damage, one would be forced to the conclusion that they never outweighed the benefitsâeven for the victor. In fact, Mo Di took this sort of logic so far that he ended up arguing that the only way to optimize the overall profit of humanity was to abandon the pursuit of private profit entirely and adopt a principle of what he called âuniversal loveââessentially arguing that if one takes the principle of market exchange to its logical conclusion, it can only lead to a kind of communism.
The Confucians took the opposite approach, rejecting the initial premise. A good example is most of the opening of Menciusâ much-remembered conversation with King Hui:
âVenerable Sir,â the King greeted him, âsince you have not counted a thousand miles too far to come here, may I suppose that you also have something with which you may profit my kingdom?â
Mencius replied:
âWhy must Your Majesty necessarily use this word âprofitâ? What I have are only these two topics: benevolence and righteousness, and nothing else.â[536]
Still, the end-point was roughly the same. The Confucian ideal of ren, of humane benevolence, was basically just a more complete inversion of profit-seeking calculation than Mo Diâs universal love; the main difference was that the Confucians added a certain aversion to calculation itself, preferring what might almost be called an art of decency. Taoists were later to take this even further with their embrace of intuition and spontaneity. All were so many attempts to provide a mirror image of market logic. Still, a mirror image is, ultimately, just that: the same thing, only backwards. Before long we end up with an endless maze of paired oppositesâegoism versus altruism, profit versus charity, materialism versus idealism, calculation versus spontaneityânone of which could ever have been imagined except by someone starting out from pure, calculating, self-interested market transactions.[537]
<em>As in the near presence of death, despise poor flesh, this refuse of blood and bones, this web and tissue of nerves and veins and arteries</em>.
âMarcus Aurelius, **Meditations 2.2**
<em>Taking pity on the hungry wolf, Wenshuang announced, âI do not covet this filthy bag of meat. I give it over to you that I may quickly acquire a body of more enduring strength. This donation will help benefit us both.â</em>
<em>âDiscourse on the Pure Land 21.12</em>
As Iâve already observed, China was unusual because philosophy there began with debates about ethics and only later turned to speculations about the nature of the cosmos. In both Greece and India, cosmological speculation came first. In each, too, questions about the nature of the physical universe quickly give way to speculation about mind, truth, consciousness, meaning, language, illusion, world-spirits, cosmic intelligence, and the fate of the human soul.
This particular maze of mirrors is so complex and dazzling that itâs extraordinarily difficult to discern the starting pointâthat is, what, precisely, is being reflected back and forth. Here anthropology can be helpful, as anthropologists have the unique advantage of being able to observe how human beings who have not previously been part of these conversations react when first exposed to Axial Age concepts. Every now and then too, we are presented with moments of exceptional clarity: ones that reveal the essence of our own thought to be almost exactly the opposite of what we thought it to be.
Maurice Leenhardt, a Catholic missionary who had spent many long years teaching the Gospel in New Caledonia, experienced such a moment in the 1920s, when he asked one of his students, an aged sculptor named Boesoou, how he felt about having been introduced to spiritual ideas:
Once, waiting to assess the mental progress of the Canaques I had taught for many years, I risked the following suggestion: âIn short, we introduced the notion of the spirit to your way of thinking?â
He objected, âSpirit? Bah! You didnât bring us the spirit. We already knew the spirit existed. We have always acted in accord with the spirit. What youâve brought us is the body.â[538]
The notion that humans had souls appeared to Boesoou to be self-evident. The notion that there was such a thing as the body, apart from the soul, a mere material collection of nerves and tissuesâlet alone that the body is the prison of the soul; that the mortification of the body could be a means to the glorification or liberation of the soulâall this, it turns out, struck him as utterly new and exotic.
Axial Age spirituality, then, is built on a bedrock of materialism. This is its secret; one might almost say, the thing that has become invisible to us.[539] But if one looks at the very beginnings of philosophical inquiry in Greece and Indiaâthe point when there was as yet no difference between what weâd now call âphilosophyâ and what weâd now call âscienceââthis is exactly what one finds. âTheory,â if we can call it that, begins with the questions: âWhat substance is the world made of?â âWhat is the underlying material behind the physical forms of objects in the world?â âIs everything made up of varying combinations of certain basic elements (earth, air, water, fire, stone, motion, mind, number âŠ), or are these basic elements just the forms taken by some even more elementary substance (for instance, as NyÄya and later Democritus proposed, atomic particles âŠ)â[540] In just about every case, some notion of God, Mind, Spirit, some active organizing principle that gave form to and was not itself substance, emerged as well. But this was the kind of spirit that, like Leenhardtâs God, only emerges in relation to inert matter.[541]
To connect this impulse, too, with the invention of coinage might seem like pushing things a bit far but, at least for the Classical world, there is an emerging scholarly literatureâfirst set off by Harvard literary theorist Marc Shell, and more recently set forth by British classicist Richard Seaford in a book called **Money and the Early Greek Mindâ**that aims to do exactly that.[542]
In fact, some of the historical connections are so uncannily close that they are very hard to explain any other way. Let me give an example. After the first coins were minted around 600 bc in the kingdom of Lydia, the practice quickly spread to Ionia, the Greek cities of the adjacent coast. The greatest of these was the great walled metropolis of Miletus, which also appears to have been the first Greek city to strike its own coins. It was Ionia, too, that provided the bulk of the Greek mercenaries active in the Mediterranean at the time, with Miletus their effective headquarters. Miletus was also the commercial center of the region, and, perhaps, the first city in the world where everyday market transactions came to be carried out primarily in coins instead of credit.[543] Greek philosophy, in turn, begins with three men: Thales, of Miletus (c. 624 bcâc. 546 bc), Anaximander, of Miletus (c. 610 bcâc. 546 bc), and Anaximenes, of Miletus (c. 585 bcâc. 525 bc)âin other words, men who were living in that city at exactly the time that coinage was first introduced.[544] All three are remembered chiefly for their speculations on the nature of the physical substance from which the world ultimately sprang. Thales proposed water, Anaximenes, air. Anaximander made up a new term, **apeiron**, âthe unlimited,â a kind of pure abstract substance that could not itself be perceived but was the material basis of everything that could be. In each case, the assumption was that this primal substance, by being heated, cooled, combined, divided, compressed, extended, or set in motion, gave rise to the endless particular stuffs and substances that humans actually encounter in the world, from which physical objects are composedâand was also that into which all those forms would eventually dissolve.
It was something that could turn into everything. As Seaford emphasizes, so was money. Gold, shaped into coins, is a material substance that is also an abstraction. It is both a lump of metal and something more than a lump of metalâitâs a drachma or an obol, a unit of currency which (at least if collected in sufficient quantity, taken to the right place at the right time, turned over to the right person) could be exchanged for absolutely any other object whatsoever.[545]
For Seaford, what was genuinely new about coins was their double-sidedness: the fact that they were both valuable pieces of metal and, at the same time, something more. At least within the communities that created them, ancient coins were always worth more than the gold, silver, or copper of which they were composed. Seaford refers to this extra value by the inelegant term âfiduciarity,â which comes from the term for public trust, the confidence a community places in its currency.[546] True, at the height of Classical Greece, when there were hundreds of city-states producing different currencies according to a number of different systems of weights and denominations, merchants often did carry scales and treat coinsâparticularly foreign coinsâlike so many chunks of silver, just as Indian merchants seem to have treated Roman coins; but within a city, that cityâs currency had a special status, since it was always acceptable at face value when used to pay taxes, public fees, or legal penalties. This is, incidentally, why ancient governments were so often able to introduce base metal into their coins without leading to immediate inflation; a debased coin might have lost value when traded overseas, but at home, it was still worth just as much when purchasing a license, or entering the public theater.[547] This is also why, during publc emergencies, Greek city-states would occasionally strike coins made entirely of bronze or tin, which everyone would agree, while the emergency lasted, to treat as if they were really made of silver.[548]
This is the key to Seafordâs argument about materialism and Greek philosophy. A coin was a piece of metal, but by giving it a particular shape, stamped with words and images, the civic community agreed to make it something more. But this power was not unlimited. Bronze coins could not be used forever; if one debased the coinage, inflation would eventually set in. It was as if there was a tension there, between the will of the community and the physical nature of the object itself. Greek thinkers were suddenly confronted with a profoundly new type of object, one of extraordinary importanceâas evidenced by the fact that so many men were willing to risk their lives to get their hands on itâbut whose nature was a profound enigma.
Consider this word, âmaterialism.â What does it mean to adopt a âmaterialistâ philosophy? What is âmaterial,â anyway? Normally, we speak of âmaterialsâ when we refer to objects that we wish to make into something else. A tree is a living thing. It only becomes âwoodâ when we begin to think about all the other things you could carve out of it. And of course you can carve a piece of wood into almost anything. The same is true of clay, or glass, or metal. Theyâre solid and real and tangible, but also abstractions, because they have the potential to turn into almost anything elseâor, not precisely that; one canât turn a piece of wood into a lion or an owl, but one can turn it into an image of a lion or an owlâit can take on almost any conceivable form. So already in any materialist philosophy, we are dealing with an opposition between form and content, substance and shape; a clash between the idea, sign, emblem, or model in the creatorâs mind, and the physical qualities of the materials on which it is to be stamped, built, or imposed, from which it will be brought into reality.[549] With coins this rises to an even more abstract level because that emblem can no longer be conceived as the model in one personâs head, but is rather the mark of a collective agreement. The images stamped on Greek coins (Miletusâ lion, Athensâ owl) were typically the emblems of the cityâs god, but they were also a kind of collective promise, by which citizens assured one another that not only would the coin be acceptable in payment of public debts, but in a larger sense, that everyone would accept them, for any debts, and thus, that they could be use to acquire anything anyone wanted.
The problem is that this collective power is not unlimited. It only really applies within the city. The farther you go outside, into places dominated by violence, slavery, and warâthe sort of place where even philosophers taking a cruise might end up on the auction blockâthe more it turns into a mere lump of precious metal.[550]
The war between Spirit and Flesh, then, between the noble Idea and ugly Reality, the rational intellect versus stubborn corporeal drives and desires that resist it, even the idea that peace and community are not things that emerge spontaneously but that need to be stamped onto our baser material natures like a divine insignia stamped into base metalâall those ideas that came to haunt the religious and philosophical traditions of the Axial Age, and that have continued to surprise people like Boesoou ever sinceâcan already be seen as inscribed in the nature of this new form of money.
It would be foolish to argue that all Axial Age philosophy was simply a meditation on the nature of coinage, but I think Seaford is right to argue that this is a critical starting place: one of the reasons that the pre-Socratic philosophers began to frame their questions in the peculiar way they did, asking (for instance): What are Ideas? Are they merely collective conventions? Do they exist, as Plato insisted, in some divine domain beyond material existence? Or do they exist in our minds? Or do our minds themselves ultimately partake of that divine immaterial domain? And if they do, what does this say about our relation to our bodies?
In India and China, the debate took different forms, but materialism was always the starting point. We only know the ideas of most truly materialist thinkers from the works of their intellectual enemies: as is the case with the Indian king PÄyÄsi, who enjoyed debating Buddhist and Jain philosophers, taking the position that the soul does not exist, that human bodies are nothing but particular configurations of air, water, earth, and fire, their consciousness the result of the elementsâ mutual interaction, and that when we die, the elements simply dissolve.[551] Clearly, though, such ideas were commonplace. Even the Axial Age religions are often startlingly lacking in the plethora of supernatural forces seen before and after: as witnessed by continued debates over whether Buddhism even **is** a religion, since it rejects any notion of a supreme being, or whether Confuciusâ admonitions that one should continue to venerate oneâs ancestors was merely a way of encouraging filial piety, or based on a belief that dead ancestors did, in some sense, continue to exist. The fact that we have to ask says everything. Yet at the same time, what endures, above all, from that ageâin institutional termsâare what we call the âworld religions.â
What we see then is a strange kind of back-and-forth, attack and riposte, whereby the market, the state, war, and religion all continually separate and merge with one another. Let me summarize it as briefly as I can:
1) Markets appear to have first emerged, in the Near East at least, as a side effect of government administrative systems. Over time, however, the logic of the market became entangled in military affairs, where it became almost indistinguishable from the mercenary logic of Axial Age warfare, and then, finally, that logic came to conquer government itself; to define its very purpose.
2) As a result: everywhere we see the military-coinage-slavery complex emerge, we also see the birth of materialist philosophies. They are materialist, in fact, in both senses of the term: in that they envision a world made up of material forces, rather than divine powers, and in that they imagine the ultimate end of human existence to be the accumulation of material wealth, with ideals like morality and justice being reframed as tools designed to satisfy the masses.
3) Everywhere, too, we find philosophers who react to this by exploring ideas of humanity and the soul, attempting to find a new foundation for ethics and morality.
4) Everywhere some of these philosophers made common cause with social movements that inevitably formed in the face of these new and extraordinarily violent and cynical elites. The result was something new to human history: popular movements that were also intellectual movements, due to the assumption that those opposing existing power arrangements did so in the name of some kind of theory about the nature of reality.
5) Everywhere, these movements were first and foremost peace movements, in that they rejected the new conception of violence, and especially aggressive war, as the foundation of politics.
6) Everywhere too, there seems to have been an initial impulse to use the new intellectual tools provided by impersonal markets to come up with a new basis for morality, and everywhere, it foundered. Mohism, with its notion of social profit, flourished briefly and then collapsed. It was replaced by Confucianism, which rejected such ideas outright. We have already seen that reimagining moral responsibility in terms of debtâan impulse that cropped up in both Greece and Indiaâwhile almost inevitable given the new economic circumstances, seems to prove uniformly unsatisfying.[552] The stronger impulse is to imagine another world where debtâand with it, all other worldly connectionsâcan be entirely annihilated, where social attachments are seen as forms of bondage; just as the body is a prison.
7) Rulersâ attitudes changed over time. At first, most appear to have affected an attitude of bemused tolerance toward the new philosophical and religious movements while privately embracing some version of cynical realpolitik, But as warring cities and principalities were replaced by great empires, and especially, as those empires began to reach the limits of their expansion, sending the military-coinage-slavery complex into crisis, all this suddenly changed. In India, AĆoka tried to re-found his kingdom on Buddhism; in Rome, Constantine turned to the Christians; in China, the Han emperor Wu-Ti (157â87 BC), faced with a similar military and financial crisis, adopted Confucianism as the philosophy of state. Of the three, only Wu Ti was ultimately successful: the Chinese empire endured, in one form or another, for two thousand years, almost always with Confucianism as its official ideology. In Constantineâs case the Western empire fell apart, but the Roman church endured. AĆokaâs project could be said to be the least successful. Not only did his empire fall apart, replaced by an endless series of weaker, usually fragmentary kingdoms, but Buddhism itself was largely driven out of his one-time territories, though it did establish itself much more firmly in China, Nepal, Tibet, Sri Lanka, Korea, Japan, and much of Southeast Asia.
8) The ultimate effect was a kind of ideal division of spheres of human activity that endures to this day: on the one hand the market, on the other, religion. To put the matter crudely: if one relegates a certain social space simply to the selfish acquisition of material things, it is almost inevitable that soon someone else will come to set aside another domain in which to preach that, from the perspective of ultimate values, material things are unimportant; that selfishnessâor even the selfâare illusory, and that to give is better than to receive. If nothing else, it is surely significant that all the Axial Age religions emphasized the importance of charity, a concept that had barely existed before. Pure greed and pure generosity are complementary concepts; neither could really be imagined without the other; both could only arise in institutional contexts that insisted on such pure and single-minded behavior; and both seem to have appeared together wherever impersonal, physical, cash money also appeared on the scene.
As for the religious movements: it would be easy enough to write them off as escapist, as promising the victims of the Axial Age empires liberation in the next world as a way of letting them accept their lot in this one, and convincing the rich that all they really owed the poor were occasional charitable donations. Radical thinkers almost invariably do write them off in this way. Surely, the willingness of the governments themselves to eventually embrace them would seem to support this conclusion. But the issue is more complicated. First of all, there is something to be said for escapism. Popular uprisings in the ancient world usually ended in the massacre of the rebels. As Iâve already observed, physical escape, such as via exodus or defection, has always been the most effective response to oppressive conditions since the earliest times we know about. Where physical escape is not possible, what, exactly, is an oppressed peasant supposed to do? Sit and contemplate her misery? At the very least, otherworldly religions provided glimpses of radical alternatives. Often they allowed people to create other worlds within this one, liberated spaces of one sort or another. It is surely significant that the only people who succeeded in abolishing slavery in the ancient world were religious sects, such as the Essenesâwho did so, effectively, by defecting from the larger social order and forming their own utopian communities.[553] Or, in a smaller but more enduring example: the democratic city-states of northern India were all eventually stamped out by the great empires (Kautilya provides extensive advice on how to subvert and destroy democratic constitutions), but the Buddha admired the democratic organization of their public assemblies and adopted it as the model for his followers.[554] Buddhist monasteries are still called **sangha**, the ancient name for such republics, and continue to operate by the same consensus-finding process to this day, preserving a certain egalitarian democratic ideal that would otherwise have been entirely forgotten.
Finally, the larger historical achievements of these movements are not, in fact, insignificant. As they took hold, things began to change. Wars became less brutal and less frequent. Slavery faded as an institution, to the point at which, by the Middle Ages, it had become insignificant or even nonexistent across most of Eurasia. Everywhere too, the new religious authorities began to seriously address the social dislocations introduced by debt.
<em>Artificial wealth comprises the things which of themselves satisfy no natural need, for example money, which is a human contrivance</em>.
If the Axial Age saw the emergence of complementary ideals of commodity markets and universal world religions, the Middle Ages were the period in which those two institutions began to merge.
Everywhere, the age began with the collapse of empires. Eventually, new states formed, but in these new states, the nexus between war, bullion, and slavery was broken; conquest and acquisition for their own sake were no longer celebrated as the end of all political life. At the same time, economic life, from the conduct of international trade to the organization of local markets, came to fall increasingly under the regulation of religious authorities. One result was a widespread movement to control, or even forbid, predatory lending. Another was a return, across Eurasia, to various forms of virtual credit money.
Granted, this is not the way weâre used to thinking of the Middle Ages. For most of us, âMedievalâ remains a synonym for superstition, intolerance, and oppression. Yet for most of the earthâs inhabitants, it could only be seen as an extraordinary improvement over the terrors of the Axial Age.
One reason for our skewed perception is that weâre used to thinking of the Middle Ages as something that happened primarily in Western Europe, in territories that had been little more than border outposts of the Roman Empire to begin with. According to the conventional wisdom, with the collapse of the empire, the cities were largely abandoned and the economy âreverted to barter,â taking at least five centuries to recover. Even for Europe, though, this is based on a series of unquestioned assumptions that, as Iâve said, crumble the moment one starts seriously poking at them. Chief among them is the idea that the absence of coins means the absence of money. True, the destruction of the Roman war machine also meant that Roman coins went out of circulation; and the few coins produced within the Gothic or Frankish kingdoms that established themselves over the ruins of the old empire were largely fiduciary in nature.[555] Still, a glance at the âbarbarian law codesâ reveals that even at the height of the Dark Ages, people were still carefully keeping accounts in Roman money as they calculated interest rates, contracts, and mortgages. Again, cities shriveled, and many were abandoned, but even this was something of a mixed blessing. Certainly, it had a terrible effect on literacy; but one must also bear in mind that ancient cities could only be maintained by extracting resources from the countryside. Roman Gaul, for instance, had been a network of cities, connected by the famous Roman roads to an endless succession of slave plantations, which were owned by the urban grandees.[556] After around 400 ad, the population of the towns declined radically, but the plantations also disappeared. In the following centuries, many came to be replaced by manors, churches, and even later, castlesâwhere new local lords extracted their own dues from the surrounding farmers. But one need only do the math: since Medieval agriculture was no less efficient than ancient agriculture (in fact, it rapidly became a great deal more so), the amount of work required to feed a handful of mounted warriors and clergymen could not possibly have been anything like that required to feed entire cities. However oppressed Medieval serfs might have been, their plight was nothing compared with that of their Axial Age equivalents.
Still, the Middle Ages proper are best seen as having begun not in Europe but in India and China, between 400 and 600 ad, and then sweeping across much of the western half of Eurasia with the advent of Islam. They only really reached Europe four hundred years later. Let us begin our story, then, in India.
I left off in India with AĆokaâs embrace of Buddhism, but I noted that ultimately, his project foundered. Neither his empire nor his church was to endure. It took a good deal of time, however, for this failure to occur.
The Mauryans represented a high watermark of empire. The next five hundred years saw a succession of kingdoms, most of them strongly supportive of Buddhism. Stupas and monasteries sprang up everywhere, but the states that sponsored them grew weaker and weaker; centralized armies dissolved; soldiers, like officials, increasingly came to be paid by land grants rather than salaries. As a result, the number of coins in circulation steadily declined.[557] Here too, the early Middle Ages witnessed a dramatic decline of cities: where the Greek ambassador Megasthenes described AĆokaâs capital of Patna as the largest city in the world of his day, Medieval Arab and Chinese travelers described India as a land of endless tiny villages.
As a result, most historians have come to write, much as they do in Europe, of a collapse of the money economy; of commerce becoming a âreversion to barter.â Here too, this appears to be simply untrue. What vanished were the military means to extract resources from the peasants. In fact, Hindu law-books written at the time show increasing attention to credit arrangements, with a sophisticated language of sureties, collateral, mortgages, promissory notes, and compound interest.[558] One need only consider how the Buddhist establishments popping up all over India during these centuries were funded. While the earliest monks were wandering mendicants, owning little more than their begging bowls, early Medieval monasteries were often magnificent establishments with vast treasuries. Still, in principle, their operations were financed almost entirely through credit.
The key innovation was the creation of what were called the âperpetual endowmentsâ or âinexhaustible treasuries.â Say a lay supporter wished to make a contribution to her local monastery. Rather than offering to provide candles for a specific ritual, or servants to attend to the upkeep of the monastic grounds, she would provide a certain sum of moneyâor something worth a great deal of moneyâthat would then be loaned out in the name of the monastery, at the accepted 15-percent annual rate. The interest on the loan would then be earmarked for that specific purpose.[559] An inscription discovered at the Great Monastery of Sanci sometime around 450 ad provides a handy illustration. A woman named Harisvamini donates the relatively modest sum of twelve **dinaras** to the âNoble Community of Monks.â[560] The text carefully inscribes how the income is to be divided up: the interest on five of the dinaras was to provide daily meals for five different monks, the interest from another three would pay to light three lamps for the Buddha, in memory of her parents, and so forth. The inscription ends by saying that this was a permanent endowment, âcreated with a document in stone to last as long as the moon and the sunâ: since the principal would never be touched, the contribution would last forever.[561]
Some of these loans presumably went to individuals, others were commercial loans to âguilds of bamboo-workers, braziers, and potters,â or to village assemblies.[562] We have to assume that in most cases the money is an accounting unit: what were really being transacted were animals, wheat, silk, butter, fruit, and all the other goods whose appropriate rates of interest were so carefully stipulated in the law-codes of the time. Still, large amounts of gold did end up flowing into monastic coffers. When coins go out of circulation, after all, the metal doesnât simply disappear. In the Middle Agesâand this seems to have been true across Eurasiaâthe vast majority of it ended up in religious establishments, churches, monasteries, and temples, either stockpiled in hoards and treasuries or gilded onto or cast into altars, sanctums, and sacred instruments. Above all, it was shaped into images of gods. As a result, those rulers who did try to put an Axial Ageâstyle coinage system back into circulationâinvariably, to fund some project of military expansionâoften had to pursue self-consciously anti-religious policies in order to do so. Probably the most notorious was one Harsa, who ruled Kashmir from 1089 to 1101 ad, who is said to have appointed an officer called the âSuperintendent for the Destruction of the Gods.â According to later histories, Harsa employed leprous monks to systematically desecrate divine images with urine and excrement, thus neutralizing their power, before dragging them off to be melted down.[563] He is said to have destroyed more than four thousand Buddhist establishments before being betrayed and killed, the last of his dynastyâand his miserable fate was long held out as an example of where the revival of the old ways was likely to lead one in the end.
For the most part, then, the gold remained sacrosanct, laid up in the sacred placesâthough in India, over time these were increasingly Hindu ones, not Buddhist. What we now see as traditional Hindu-village India appears to have been largely a creation of the early Middle Ages. We do not know precisely how it happened. As kingdoms continued to rise and fall, the world inhabited by kings and princes became increasingly distant from that of most peopleâs everyday affairs. During much of the period immediately following the collapse of the Mauryan empire, for instance, much of India was governed by foreigners.[564] Apparently, this increasing distance allowed local Brahmins to begin reshaping the newâincreasingly ruralâsociety along strictly hierarchical principles.
They did it above all by seizing control of the administration of law. The DharmaĆÄstra, law-codes produced by Brahmin scholars between roughly 200 bc and 400 ad, give us a good idea of the new vision of society. In it, old ideas like the Vedic conception of a debt to gods, sages, and ancestors were resuscitatedâbut now, they applied only and specifically to Brahmins, whose duty and privilege it was to stand in for all humanity before the forces that controlled the universe.[565] Far from being required to attain learning, members of the inferior classes were forbidden to do so: the Laws of Manu, for instance, set down that any Sudra (the lowest caste, assigned to farming and material production) who so much as listened in on the teaching of the law or sacred texts should have molten lead poured into their ears; on the occasion of a repeat offense, have their tongues cut out.[566] At the same time Brahmins, however ferociously they guarded their privileges, also adopted aspects of once-radical Buddhist and Jain ideas like karma, reincarnation, and **ahimsa**. Brahmins were expected to refrain from any sort of physical violence, and even to become vegetarians. In alliance with representatives of the old warrior caste, they also managed to win control of most of the land in the ancient villages. Artisans and craftsmen fleeing the decline or destruction of cities often ended up as suppliant refugees, and, gradually, low-caste clients. The result were increasingly complex local patronage systems in the countrysideâ**jajmani** systems, as they came to be knownâwhere the refugees provided services for the landowning castes, who took on many of the roles once held by the state, providing protection and justice, extracting labor dues, and so onâbut also protected local communities from actual royal representatives.[567]
This latter function is crucial. Foreign visitors were later to be awed by the self-sufficiency of the traditional Indian village, with its elaborate system of landowning castes, farmers, and such âservice castesâ as barbers, smiths, tanners, drummers, and washermen, all arranged in hierarchical order, each seen as making its own unique and necessary contribution to their little society, all of it typically operating entirely without the use of metal currency. It was only possible for those reduced to the status of Sudras and Untouchables to have a chance of accepting their lowly position because the exaction of local landlords was, again, on nothing like the same scale as that under earlier governmentsâunder which villagers had to support cities of upwards of a million peopleâand because the village community became an effective means of holding the state and its representatives at least partially at bay.
We donât know the mechanisms that brought this world about, but the role of debt was surely significant. The creation of thousands of Hindu temples alone must have involved hundreds of thousands, even millions, of interest-bearing loansâsince, while Brahmins were themselves forbidden to lend money at interest, temples were not. We can already see, in the earliest of the new law-codes, the Laws of Manu, the way that local authorities were struggling to reconcile old customs like debt peonage and chattel slavery with the desire to establish an overarching hierarchical system in which everyone knew their place. The Laws of Manu carefully classify slaves into seven types depending on how they were reduced to slavery (war, debt, self-sale âŠ) and explain the conditions under which each might be emancipatedâbut then go on to say that Sudras can never really be emancipated, since, after all, they were created to serve the other castes.[568] Similarly, where earlier codes had established a 15-percent annual rate of interest, with exceptions for commercial loans,[569] the new codes organized interest by caste: stating that one could charge a maximum of 2 percent a month for a Brahmin, 3 percent for a Ksatriya (warrior), 4 percent for a Vaisya (merchant), and 5 percent for a Sudraâwhich is the difference between 24 percent annually on the one extreme and a hefty 60 percent on the other.[570] The laws also identify five different ways interest can be paid, of which the most significant for our concerns is âbodily interestâ: physical labor in the creditorâs house or fields, to be rendered until such time as the principal is cleared. Even here, though, caste considerations were paramount. No one could be forced into the service of anyone of lower caste; moreover, since debts were enforceable on a debtorâs children and even grandchildren, âuntil the principal is clearedâ could mean quite some timeâas the Indian historian R.S. Sharma notes, such stipulations âremind us of the present practice according to which several generations of the same family have been reduced to the position of hereditary ploughmen in consideration of some paltry sum advanced to them.â[571]
Indeed, India has become notorious as a country in which a very large part of the working population is laboring in effective debt peonage to a landlord or other creditor. Such arrangements became even easier over time. By about 1000 ad, restrictions on usury by members of the upper castes in Hindu law-codes largely disappeared. On the other hand, 1000 ad was about the same time that Islam appeared in Indiaâa religion dedicated to eradicating usury altogether. So at the very least we can say that these things never stopped being contested. And even Hindu law of that time was far more humane than almost anything found in the ancient world. Debtors were not, generally speaking, reduced to slavery, and there is no widespread evidence of the selling of women or children. In fact, overt slavery had largely vanished from the countryside by this time. And debt peons were not even pawns, exactly; by law, they were simply paying interest on a freely contracted agreement. Even when that took generations, the law stipulated that even if the principal was never paid, in the third generation, they would be freed.
There is a peculiar tension here: a kind of paradox. Debt and credit arrangements may well have played a crucial role in creating the Indian village system, but they could never really become their basis. It might have made a certain sense to declare that, just as Brahmins had to dispatch their debts to the gods, everyone should be, in a certain sense, in debt to those above them. But in another sense, that would have completely subverted the very idea of caste, which was that the universe was a vast hierarchy in which different sorts of people were assumed to be of fundamentally different natures, that these ranks and grades were fixed forever, and that when goods and services moved up and down the hierarchy, they followed not principles of exchange at all but (as in all hierarchical systems) custom and precedent. The French anthropologist Louis Dumont made the famous argument that one cannot even really talk about âinequalityâ here, because to use that phrase implies that one believes people should or could be equal, and this idea was completely alien to Hindu conceptions.[572] For them to have imagined their responsibilities as debts would have been profoundly subversive, since debts are by definition arrangements between equalsâat least in the sense that they are equal parties to a contractâthat could and should be repaid.[573]
Politically, it is never a particularly good idea to first tell people they are your equals, and then humiliate and degrade them. This is presumably why peasant insurrections, from Chiapas to Japan, have so regularly aimed to wipe out debts, rather than focus on more structural issues like caste systems, or even slavery.[574] The British Raj discovered this to their occasional chagrin when they used debt peonageâsuperimposed on the caste systemâas the basis of their labor system in colonial India. Perhaps the paradigmatic popular insurrection was the Deccan riots of 1875, when indebted farmers rose up to seize and systematically destroy the account books of local money-lenders. Debt peonage, it would appear, is far more likely to inspire outrage and collective action than is a system premised on pure inequality.
By Medieval standards, India was unusual for resisting the appeal of the great Axial Age religions, but we observe the basic pattern: the decline of empire, armies, and cash economy, the rise of religious authorities, independent of the state, who win much of their popular legitimacy through their ability to regulate emerging credit systems.
China might be said to represent the opposite extreme. This was the one place where a late Axial Age attempt to yoke empire and religion together was a complete success. True, here as elsewhere, there was an initial period of breakdown: after the collapse of the Han dynasty around 220 ad, the central state broke apart, cities shrank, coins disappeared, and so on. But in China this was only temporary. As Max Weber long ago pointed out, once one sets up a genuinely effective bureaucracy, itâs almost impossible to get rid of it. And the Chinese bureaucracy was uniquely effective. Before long, the old Han system reemerged: a centralized state, run by Confucian scholar-gentry trained in the literary classics, selected through a national exam system, working in meticulously organized national and regional bureaus where the money supply, like other economic matters, was continually monitored and regulated. Chinese monetary theory was always chartalist. This was partly just an effect of size: the empire and its internal market were so huge that foreign trade was never especially important; therefore, those running the government were well aware that they could turn pretty much anything into money, simply by insisting that taxes be paid in that form.
The two great threats to the authorities were always the same: the nomadic peoples to the north (who they systematically bribed, but who nonetheless periodically swept over and conquered sections of China) and popular unrest and rebellion. The latter was almost constant, and on a scale unknown anywhere else in human history. There were decades in Chinese history when the rate of recorded peasant uprisings was roughly 1.8 **per hour.**[575] Whatâs more, such uprisings were frequently successful. Most of the most famous Chinese dynasties that were not the product of barbarian invasion (the Yuan or Qing) were originally peasant insurrections (the Han, Tang, Sung, and Ming). In no other part of the world do we see anything like this. As a result, Chinese statecraft ultimately came down to funneling enough resources to the cities to feed the urban population and keep the nomads at bay, without causing a notoriously contumacious rural population to rise up in arms. The official Confucian ideology of patriarchal authority, equal opportunity, promotion of agriculture, light taxes, and careful government control of merchants seemed expressly designed to appeal to the interests and sensibilities of a (potentially rebellious) rural patriarch.[576]
One need hardly add that in these circumstances, limiting the depredations of the local village loan sharkâthe traditional bane of rural familiesâwas a constant government concern. Over and over we hear the same familiar story: peasants down on their luck, whether due to natural disaster or the need to pay for a parentâs funeralâwould fall into the hands of predatory lenders, who would seize their fields and houses, forcing them to work or pay rent in what had once been their own lands; the threat of rebellion would then drive the government to institute a dramatic program of reforms. One of the first we know about came in the form of a coup dâĂ©tat in 9 ad, when a Confucian official named Wang Mang seized the throne to deal (so he claimed) with a nationwide debt crisis. According to proclamations made at the time, the practice of usury had caused the effective tax rate (that is, the amount of the average peasantâs harvest that ended up being carried off by someone else) to rise from just over 3 percent, to 50 percent.[577] In reaction, Wang Mang instituted a program reforming the currency, nationalizing large estates, promoting state-run industriesâincluding public granariesâand banning private holding of slaves. Wang Mang also established a state loan agency that would offer interest-free funeral loans for up to ninety days for those caught unprepared by the death of relatives, as well as long-term loans of 3 percent monthly or 10 percent annual income rates for commercial or agricultural investments.[578] âWith this scheme,â one historian remarks, âWang was confident that all business transactions would be under his scrutiny and the abuse of usury would be forever eradicated.â[579]
Needless to say, it was not, and later Chinese history is full of similar stories: widespread inequality and unrest followed by the appointment of official commissions of inquiry, regional debt relief (either blanket amnesties or annulments of all loans in which interest had exceeded the principal), cheap grain loans, famine relief, laws against the selling of children.[580] All this became the standard fare of government policy. It was very unevenly successful; it certainly did not create an egalitarian peasant utopia, but it prevented any widespread return to Axial Age conditions.
We are used to thinking of such bureaucratic interventionsâparticularly the monopolies and regulationsâas state restriction on âthe marketââowing to the prevailing prejudice that sees markets as quasi-natural phenomena that emerge by themselves, and governments as having no role other than to squelch or siphon from them. I have repeatedly pointed out how mistaken this is, but China provides a particularly striking example. The Confucian state may have been the worldâs greatest and most enduring bureaucracy, but it actively promoted markets, and as a result, commercial life in China soon became far more sophisticated, and markets more developed, than anywhere else in the world.
This despite the fact that Confucian orthodoxy was overtly hostile to merchants and even the profit motive itself. Commercial profit was seen as legitimate only as compensation for the labor that merchants expended in transporting goods from one place to another, but never as fruits of speculation. What this meant in practice was that they were pro-market but anti-capitalist.
Again, this seems bizarre, since weâre used to assuming that capitalism and markets are the same thing, but, as the great French historian Fernand Braudel pointed out, in many ways they could equally well be conceived as opposites. While markets are ways of exchanging goods through the medium of moneyâhistorically, ways for those with a surplus of grain to acquire candles and vice versa (in economic shorthand, C-M-Câ, for commodity-money-other commodity)âcapitalism is first and foremost the art of using money to get more money (M-C-Mâ). Normally, the easiest way to do this is by establishing some kind of formal or de facto monopoly. For this reason, capitalists, whether merchant princes, financiers, or industrialists, invariably try to ally themselves with political authorities to limit the freedom of the market, so as to make it easier for them to do so.[581] From this perspective, China was for most of its history the ultimate anti-capitalist market state.[582] Unlike later European princes, Chinese rulers systematically refused to team up with would-be Chinese capitalists (who always existed). Instead, like their officials, they saw them as destructive parasitesâthough, unlike the usurers, ones whose fundamentally selfish and antisocial motivations could still be put to use in certain ways. In Confucian terms, merchants were like soldiers. Those drawn to a career in the military were assumed to be driven largely by a love of violence. As individuals, they were not good people; but they were also necessary to defend the frontiers. Similarly, merchants were driven by greed and basically immoral; yet if kept under careful administrative supervision, they could be made to serve the public good.[583] Whatever one might think of the principles, the results are hard to deny. For most of its history, China maintained the highest standard of living in the worldâeven England only really overtook it in perhaps the 1820s, well past the time of the Industrial Revolution.[584]
Confucianism is not precisely a religion, perhaps; it is usually considered more an ethical and philosophical system. So China too could be considered something of a departure from the common Medieval pattern, whereby commerce was, almost everywhere, brought under the control of religion. But it wasnât a complete departure. One need only consider the remarkable economic role of Buddhism in this same period. Buddhism had arrived in China through the Central Asia caravan routes and in its early days was largely a religion promoted by merchants, but in the chaos following the collapse of the Han dynasty in 220 ad, it began to take popular roots. The Liang (502â557) and Tang (618â907) dynasties saw outbreaks of passionate religious fervor, in which thousands of rural young people across China would renounce their farms, shops, and families to seek ordination as Buddhist monks and nuns; where merchants or landed magnates pledged their entire fortunes to the propagation of the Dharma; building projects hollowed out whole mountains to create bodhisattvas and giant statues of the Buddha; and pageants where monks and devotees ritually burned their heads and hands or, in some instances, set themselves on fire. By the midâfifth century, there were dozens of such spectacular suicides; they became, as one historian put it âa macabre kind of fashion.â[585]
Historians differ over their meaning. Certainly the passions unleashed provided a dramatic alternative to the staid orthodoxy of the Confucian literati, but itâs also surprising, to say the least, to see this in a religion promoted above all by the commercial classes. The French Sinologist Jacques Gernet observes:
It is clear that these suicides, so contrary to traditional morality, aimed to redeem the sins of all beings, to compel the gods and men at one and the same time. And they were staged: usually, in the fifth century, a pyre was erected on a mountain. The suicide took place in the presence of a large crowd uttering lamentations and bringing forward rich offerings. People of all social ranks attended the spectacle together. After the fire had burned out, the ashes of the monk were collected and a stupa, a new place of worship, was created to house them.[586]
Gernetâs picture of dozens of Christ-like redeemers seems overstated, but the precise meaning of these suicides was unclearâand widely debatedâeven in the Middle Ages. Some contemporaries saw them as the ultimate expression of contempt for the body; others as recognition of the illusory nature of the self and all material attachments; yet others, as the ultimate form of charity, the giving of that which can only be most precious, oneâs very physical existence, as a sacrifice to the benefit of all living things; a sentiment that one tenth-century biographer expressed in the following verses:
To give away the thing that is difficult to part with,
Is the best offering amongst the alms.
Let this impure and sinful body,
Turn into something like a diamond.[587]
That is, an object of eternal value, an investment that can bear fruit for all eternity.
I draw attention to this because this sentiment provides an elegant illustration of a problem that seems to have first appeared in the world with notions of pure charity that always seemed to accompany Axial Age religions, and which provided endless philosophical conundrums. In human economies, it does not appear to have occurred to anyone that any act **could** be either purely selfish or purely altruistic. As I noted in chapter five, an act of absolute selfless giving can only also be absolutely antisocialâhence in a way, inhuman. It is merely the mirror image of an act of theft or even murder; hence, it makes a certain sort of sense that suicide be conceived as the ultimate selfless gift. Yet this is the door that necessarily opens as soon as one develops a notion of âprofitâ and then tries to conceive its opposite.
This tension seems to hang over the economic life of Medieval Chinese Buddhism, which, true to its commercial origins, retained a striking tendency to employ the language of the marketplace. âOne purchases felicity, and sells oneâs sins,â wrote one monk, âjust as in commercial operations.â[588] Nowhere was this so true as in those schools, such as the School of the Three Stages, that adopted the notion of âkarmic debtââthat each of the sins of oneâs accumulated past lives continues as a debt needing to be discharged. An obscure and unusual view in classical Indian Buddhism, the notion of karmic debt took on a powerful new life in China.[589] As one Three Stages text puts it, we all know that insolvent debtors will be reborn as animals or slaves; but in reality, we are all insolvent debtors, because acquiring the money to repay our temporal debts necessarily means acquire new, spiritual ones, since every means of acquiring wealth will necessarily involve exploiting, damaging, and causing suffering to other living beings.
Some use their power and authority as officials in order to bend the law and seize wealth. Some prosper in the marketplace ⊠They engage in an excess of lies and cheat and extort profits from others. Still others, farmers, burn the mountains and marshes, flood the fields, plough and mill, destroying the nests and burrows of animals âŠ
There is no avoiding the fact of our past debts, and it is difficult to comprehend the number of separate lives it would require if you wanted to pay them one by one.[590]
As Gernet remarks, the idea of life as an endless burden of debt would surely have struck a chord with Chinese villagers, for whom this was all too often literally true; but, as he also points out, like their counterparts in ancient Israel, they were also familiar with that sense of sudden liberation that came with official amnesties. There was a way to achieve that too. All that was required was to make regular donations to some monasteryâs Inexhaustible Treasury. The moment one does so, the debts from every one of oneâs past lives are instantly blotted out. The author even provides a little parable, not unlike Jesusâs parable of the ungrateful servant, but far more optimistic. How, it might be asked, would a poor manâs tiny contribution possibly have such cosmic effects?
Answer: In a parable it is like a poor man burdened by a debt of one thousand strings of coins to another person. He always suffers from his debt, and the poor man is afraid whenever the debt-master comes to collect.
He visits the rich manâs house and confesses he is beyond the time-limit and begs forgiveness for his offenseâhe is poor and without a station in life. He tells him that each day he makes a single coin he will return it to the rich man. On hearing this, the rich man is very pleased and forgives him for being overdue; moreover, the poor man is not dragged away to jail.
Giving to the Inexhaustible Storehouse is also like this.[591]
One might almost call this salvation on the installment planâbut the implication is that the payments shall be made, like the interest payments on the wealth when it is subsequently loaned out, for all eternity.
Other schools concentrated not on karmic debt, but on oneâs debt to oneâs parents. Where Confucians built their system of morality above all on filial piety to fathers, Chinese Buddhists were primarily concerned with mothers; with the care and suffering required in raising, feeding, and educating children. A motherâs kindness is unlimited, her selflessness absolute; this was seen to be embodied above all in the act of breastfeeding, the fact that mothers transform their very flesh and blood into milk; they feed their children with their own bodies. In doing so, however, they allow unlimited love to be precisely quantified. One author calculated that the average infant absorbs precisely 180 pecks of motherâs milk in its first three years of life, and this constitutes its debt as an adult. The figure soon became canonical. To repay this milk debt, or indeed oneâs debt to oneâs parents more generally, was simply impossible. âIf you stacked up jewels from the ground up to the twenty-eighth heaven,â wrote one Buddhist author, âit would not compareâ with the value of your parentâs nurturance.[592] Even if you were to âcut your own flesh to offer her three times a day for four billion years,â wrote another, âit would not pay back even a single dayâ of what your mother did for you.[593]
The solution, however, is the same: donating money to the Inexhaustible Treasuries. The result was an elaborate cycle of debts and forms of redemption. A man begins with an unpayable milk-debt. The only thing of comparable value is the Dharma, the Buddhist truth itself. One can thus repay oneâs parents by bringing them to Buddhism; indeed, this can be done even after death, when oneâs mother will otherwise wind up as a hungry ghost in hell. If one makes a donation to the Inexhaustible Treasuries in her name, sutras will be recited for her; she will be delivered; the money, in the meantime, will be put partly to work as charity, as pure gift, but partly, too, as in India, as interest-bearing loans, earmarked for specific purposes for the furtherance of Buddhist education, ritual, or monastic life.
The Chinese Buddhist approach to charity was nothing if not multifaceted. Festivals often led to vast outpourings of contributions, with wealthy adherents vying with one another in generosity, often driving their entire fortunes to the monasteries, in the forms of oxcarts laden with millions of strings of cashâa kind of economic self-immolation that paralleled the spectacular monastic suicides. Their contributions swelled the Inexhaustible Treasuries. Some would be given to the needy, particularly in times of hardship. Some would be loaned. One practice that hovered between charity and business was providing peasants with alternatives to the local moneylender. Most monasteries had attendant pawnshops where the local poor could place some valuable possessionâa robe, a couch, a mirrorâin hock in exchange for low-interest loans.[594] Finally, there was the business of the monastery itself: that portion of the Inexhaustible Treasury turned over to the management of lay brothers, and either put out at loan or invested. Since monks were not allowed to eat the products of their own fields, the fruit or grain had to be put on the market, further swelling monastic revenues. Most monasteries came to be surrounded not only by commercial farms but veritable industrial complexes of oil presses, flour mills, shops, and hostels, often with thousands of bonded workers.[595] At the same time, the Treasuries themselves becameâas Gernet was perhaps the first to point outâthe worldâs first genuine forms of concentrated finance capital. They were, after all, enormous concentrations of wealth managed by what were in effect monastic corporations, which were constantly seeking new opportunities for profitable investment. They even shared the quintessential capitalist imperative of continual growth; the Treasuries had to expand, since according to Mahayana doctrine, genuine liberation would not be possible until the whole world embraced the Dharma.[596]
This was precisely the situationâhuge concentrations of capital interested in nothing more than profitâthat Confucian economic policy was supposed to prevent. Still, it took some time for Chinese governments to recognize the threat. Government attitudes veered back and forth. At first, especially in the chaotic years of the early Middle Ages, monks were welcomedâeven given generous land grants and provided with convict laborers to reclaim forests and marshes, and tax-exempt status for their business enterprises.[597] A few emperors converted, and while most of the bureaucracy kept the monks at armâs length, Buddhism became especially popular with court women, as well as with eunuchs and many scions of wealthy families. As time went on, though, administrators turned from seeing monks as a boon to rural society to its potential ruination. Already, by 511 ad, there were decrees condemning monks for diverting grain that was supposed to be used for charitable purposes to high-interest loans, and altering debt contractsâa government commission had to be appointed to review the accounts and nullify any loans in which interest was found to have exceeded principal. In 713 ad we have another decree, confiscating two Inexhaustible Treasuries of the Three Stages sect, whose members they accused of fraudulent solicitation.[598] Before long there were major campaigns of government repression, at first often limited to certain regions, but over time, more often empire-wide. During the most severe, carried out in 845 ad, a total of 4,600 monasteries were razed along with their shops and mills, 260,000 monks and nuns forcibly defrocked and returned to their familiesâbut at the same time, according to government reports, 150,000 temple serfs released from bondage.
Whatever the real reasons behind the waves of repression (and these were no doubt many), the official reason was always the same: a need to restore the money supply. The monasteries were becoming so large, and so rich, administrators insisted, that China was simply running out of metal:
The great repressions of Buddhism under the Chou emperor Wu between 574 and 577, under Wu-tsung in 842â845, and finally in 955, presented themselves primarily as measures of economic recovery: each of them provided an opportunity for the imperial government to procure the necessary copper for the minting of new coins.[599]
One reason is that monks appear to have been systematically melting down strings of coins, often hundreds of thousands at a time, to build colossal copper or even gilded copper statues of the Buddhaâalong with other objects such as bells and copper chimes, or even such extravagances as mirrored halls or gilded copper roof tiles. The result, according to official commissions of inquiry, was economically disastrous: the price of metals would soar, coinage disappear, and rural marketplaces cease to function, even as those rural people whose children had not become monks often fell deeper into debt to the monasteries.
It perhaps stands to reason that Chinese Buddhism, a religion of merchants that then took popular roots, should have developed in this direction: a genuine theology of debt, even perhaps a practice of absolute self-sacrifice, of abandoning everything, oneâs fortune or even oneâs life, that ultimately led to collectively managed finance capital. The reason that the result seems so weird, so full of paradoxes, is that it is again an attempt to apply the logic of exchange to questions of Eternity.
Recall an idea from earlier in the book: exchange, unless itâs an instantaneous cash transaction, creates debts. Debts linger over time. If you imagine all human relations as exchange, then insofar as people do have ongoing relations with one another, those relations are laced with debt and sin. The only way out is to annihilate the debt, but then social relations vanish too. This is quite in accord with Buddhism, whose ultimate aim is indeed the attainment of âemptiness,â absolute liberation, the annihilation of all human and material attachments, since these are all ultimately causes of suffering. For Mahayana Buddhists, however, absolute liberation cannot be achieved by any one being independently; the liberation of each depends on all the others; therefore, until the end of time, such matters are in a certain sense always in suspension.
In the meantime, exchange dominates: âOne purchases felicity, and sells oneâs sins, just as in commercial operations.â Even acts of charity and self-sacrifice are not purely generous; one is purchasing âmeritâ from the bodhisattvas.[600] The notion of infinite debt comes in when this logic slams up against the Absolute, or, one might perhaps better say, against something that utterly defies the logic of exchange. Because there are things that do. This would explain, for instance, the odd urge to first quantify the exact amount of milk one has absorbed at oneâs motherâs breast, and then to say that there is no conceivable way to repay it. Exchange implies interaction between equivalent beings. Your mother, on the other hand, is not an equivalent being. She created you out of her own flesh. This is exactly the point that I suggested the Vedic authors were subtly trying to make when they talked about âdebtsâ to the gods: of course you cannot really âpay your debt to the universeââthat would imply that (1) you and (2) everything that exists (including you) are in some sense equivalent entities. This is clearly absurd. The closest you can come to repayment is to simply recognize that fact. Such recognition is the true meaning of sacrifice. Like RospabĂ©âs original money, a sacrificial offering is not a way to pay a debt, but a way to acknowledge the impossibility of the idea that there could ever be repayment:
The parallel was not missed in certain mythological traditions. According to one famous Hindu myth, two gods, the brothers Kartikeya and Ganesha, had a quarrel over who should be the first to marry. Their mother Parvati suggested a contest: the winner would be the one to most quickly circle the entire universe. Kartikeya set off on the back of a giant peacock. It took him three years to transverse the limits of the cosmos. Ganesha bided his time, then, finally, walked in a circle around his mother, remarking, âYou are the universe to me.â
Iâve also argued that any system of exchange is always necessarily founded on something else, something that, in its social manifestation at least, is ultimately communism. With all those things that we treat as eternal, that we assume will always be thereâour motherâs love, true friendship, sociality, humanity, belonging, the existence of the cosmosâno calculation is necessary, or even ultimately possible; insofar as there is give and take, they follow completely different principles. What, then, happens to such absolute and unlimited phenomena when one tries to imagine the world as a set of transactionsâas exchange? Generally, one of two things. We either ignore or deify them. (Mothers, and caregiving women in general, are a classic case in point.) Or we do both. What we treat as eternal in our actual relations with one another vanishes and reappears as an abstraction, an absolute.[601] In the case of Buddhism, this was framed as the inexhaustible merit of bodhisatt-vas, who exist, in a certain sense, outside of time. They are at once the model for the Inexhaustible Treasuries, and also their practical foundation: one can only repay oneâs endless karmic debt, or oneâs infinite milk-debt, by drawing on this equally infinite pool of redemption, which, in turn, becomes the basis for the actual material funds of the monasteries, which are equally eternalâa pragmatic form of communism, in fact, since they were vast pools of wealth collectively owned and collectively managed: the center of vast projects of human cooperation, which were assumed to be similarly eternal. Yet at the same timeâhere I think Gernet is rightâthis communism became the basis, in turn, of something very much like capitalism. The reason was, above all, the need for constant expansion. Everythingâeven charityâwas an opportunity to proselytize; the Dharma had to grow, ultimately, to encompass everyone and everything, in order to effect the salvation of all living beings.
The Middle Ages were marked by a general move toward abstraction: real gold and silver ended up largely in churches, monasteries, and temples, money became virtual again, and at the same time, the tendency everywhere was to set up overarching moral institutions meant to regulate the process and, in particular, to establish certain protections for debtors.
China was unusual in that it was one place where an Axial Age empire managed to surviveâthough at first, only barely. Chinese governments did manage to keep coins in circulation in most places most of the time. This was made easier by their reliance exclusively on small-denomination coins made of bronze. Even so, it clearly took enormous efforts.
As usual, we donât know a lot about how everyday economic transactions took place, but what we do know suggests that in small-scale transactions, coins were probably most often used in dealing with strangers. As elsewhere, local shopkeepers and merchants extended credit. Most accounts seem to have been kept through the use of tally sticks, strikingly similar to those used in England, except that rather than hazelwood they were usually made of a split piece of notched bamboo. Here, too, the creditor took one half, and the debtor held the other; they were joined at the moment of repayment, and often broken afterward to mark the cancellation of the debt.[602] To what degree were they transferable? We donât really know. Most of what we do know is from casual references in texts that are mainly about something else: anecdotes, jokes, and poetic allusions. The great collection of Taoist wisdom, the **Leizi**, probably written during the Han dynasty, contains one such:
There was a man of Sung who was strolling in the street and picked up a half tally someone had lost. He took it home and stored it away, and secretly counted the indentations of the broken edge. He told a neighbor: âI shall be rich any day now.â[603]
Rather like someone who finds a key and figures âjust as soon as I can figure out which lock âŠâ[604] Another story tells of how Liu Bang, a bibulous local constable and future founder of the Han dynasty, used to go on all-night drinking binges, running up enormous tabs. Once, while he lay collapsed in a drunken stupor in a wine-shop, the owner saw a dragon hovering over his headâa sure sign of future greatnessâand immediately âbroke the tally,â forgiving him his accumulated drinking debts.[605]
Tallies werenât just used for loans, but for any sort of contractâwhich is why early paper contracts also had to be cut in half and one half kept by each party.[606] With paper contracts, there was a definite tendency for the creditorâs half to function as an IOU and thus become transferable. By 806 ad, for instance, right around the apogee of Chinese Buddhism, merchants moving tea over long distances from the far south of the country and officials transporting tax payments to the capital, all of them concerned with the dangers of carrying bullion over long distances, began to deposit their money with bankers in the capital and devised a system of promissory notes. They were called âFlying Cash,â also divided in half, like tallies, and redeemable for cash in their branches in the provinces. They quickly started passing from hand to hand and operated something like currency. The government first tried to forbid their use, then a year or two laterâand this became a familiar pattern in Chinaâwhen it realized that it could not suppress them, switched gears and established a bureau empowered to issue such notes themselves.[607]
By the early Song dynasty (960â1279 ad), local banking operations all over China were running similar operations, accepting cash and bullion for safekeeping and allowing depositors to use their receipts as promissory notes, as well as trading in government coupons for salt and tea. Many of these notes came to circulate as de facto money.[608] The government, as usual, first tried to ban the practice, then control it (granting a monopoly to sixteen leading merchants), then, finally, set up a government monopolyâthe Bureau of Exchange Medium, established in 1023âand before long, aided by the newly invented printing press, was operating factories in several cities employing thousands of workers and producing literally millions of notes.[609]
At first, this paper money was meant to circulate for a limited time (notes would expire after two, then three, then seven years), and was redeemable in bullion. Over time, especially as the Song came under increasing military pressure, the temptation to simply print money with little or no backup became overwhelmingâand, moreover, Chinese governments were rarely completely willing to accept their own paper money for tax purposes. Combine this with the fact that the bills were worthless outside China, and itâs rather surprising that the system worked at all. Certainly, inflation was a constant problem and the money would have to be recalled and reissued. Occasionally the whole system would break down, but then people would resort to their own expedients: âprivately issued tea checks, noodle checks, bamboo tallies, wine tallies, etc.â[610] Still, the Mongols, who ruled China from 1271 to 1368 ad, chose to maintain the system, and it was only abandoned in the seventeenth century.
This is important to note because the conventional account tends to represent Chinaâs experiment with paper money as a failure, even, for Metallists, proof that âfiat money,â backed only by state power, will always eventually collapse.[611] This is especially odd, since the centuries when paper money was in use are usually considered the most economically dynamic in Chinese history. Surely, if the United States government was eventually forced to abandon the use of federal reserve notes in 2400 ad, no one would be arguing that this showed that the very idea was always intrinsically unworkable. Nonetheless, the main point Iâd like to emphasize here is that terms like âfiat money,â however common, are deceptive. Almost all of the new forms of paper money that emerged were not originally created by governments at all; they were simply ways of recognizing and expanding the use of credit instruments that emerged from everyday economic transactions. If it was only China that developed paper money in the Middle Ages, this was largely because only in China was there a government large and powerful enough, but also, sufficiently suspicious of its mercantile classes, to feel it had to take charge of such operations.
<em>Prices depend on the will of Allah; it is he who raises and lowers them</em>.
âAttributed to the Prophet Mohammed
<em>The profit of each partner must be in proportion to the share of each in the adventure</em>.
âIslamic legal precept
For most of the Middle Ages, the economic nerve center of the world economy and the source of its most dramatic financial innovations was neither China nor India, but the West, which, from the perspective of the rest of the world, meant the world of Islam. During most of this period, Christendom, lodged in the declining empire of Byzantium and the obscure semi-barbarous principalities of Europe, was largely insignificant.
Since people who live in Western Europe have so long been in the habit of thinking of Islam as the very definition of âthe East,â itâs easy to forget that, from the perspective of any other great tradition, the difference between Christianity and Islam is almost negligible. One need only pick up a book on, say, Medieval Islamic philosophy to discover disputes between the Baghdad Aristoteleans and the neo-Pythagoreans in Basra, or Persian Neo-Platonistsâessentially, scholars doing the same work of trying to square the revealed religion tradition beginning with Abraham and Moses with the categories of Greek philosophy, and doing so in a larger context of mercantile capitalism, universalistic missionary religion, scientific rationalism, poetic celebrations of romantic love, and periodic waves of fascination with mystical wisdom from the East.
From a world-historical perspective, it seems much more sensible to see Judaism, Christianity, and Islam as three different manifestations of the same great Western intellectual tradition, which for most of human history has centered on Mesopotamia and the Levant, extending into Europe as far as Greece and into Africa as far as Egypt, and sometimes farther west across the Mediterranean or down the Nile. Economically, most of Europe was until perhaps the High Middle Ages in exactly the same situation as most of Africa: plugged into the larger world economy, if at all, largely as an exporter of slaves, raw materials, and the occasional exotica (amber, elephant tusks âŠ), and importer of manufactured goods (Chinese silks and porcelain, Indian calicoes, Arab steel). To get a sense of comparative economic development (even if the examples are somewhat scattered over time), consider the following table:[612]
Populations and Tax Revenue, 350 BCâ1200 AD
Whatâs more, for most of the Middle Ages, Islam was not only the core of Western civilization; it was its expansive edge, working its way into India, expanding in Africa and Europe, sending missionaries and winning converts across the Indian Ocean.
The prevailing Islamic attitude toward law, government, and economic matters was the exact opposite of that prevalent in China. Confucians were suspicious of governance through strict codes of law, preferring to rely on the inherent sense of justice of the cultivated scholarâa scholar who was simply assumed to also be a government official. Medieval Islam, on the other hand, enthusiastically embraced law, which was seen as a religious institution derived from the Prophet, but tended to view government, more often than not, as an unfortunate necessity, an institution that the truly pious would do better to avoid.[613]
In part this was because of the peculiar nature of Islamic government. The Arab military leaders who, after Mohammedâs death in 632 ad, conquered the Sassanian empire and established the Abbasid Caliphate, always continued to see themselves as people of the desert, and never felt entirely part of the urban civilizations they had come to rule. This discomfort was never quite overcomeâon either side. It took the bulk of the population several centuries to convert to the conquerorâs religion, and even when they did, they never seem to have really identified with their rulers. Government was seen as military powerânecessary, perhaps, defend the faith, but fundamentally exterior to society.
In part, too, it was because of the peculiar alliance between merchants and common folk that came to be aligned against them. After Caliph al-Maâmumâs abortive attempt to set up a theocracy in 832 ad, the government took a hands-off position on questions of religion. The various schools of Islamic law were free to create their own educational institutions and maintain their own separate system of religious justice. Crucially, it was the **ulema**, the legal scholars, who were the principal agents in the conversion of the bulk of the empireâs population to Islam in Mesopotamia, Syria, Egypt, and North Africa in those same years.[614] Butâlike the elders in charge of guilds, civic associations, commercial sodalities, and religious brotherhoodsâthey did their best to keep the government, with its armies and ostentation, at armâs length.[615] âThe best princes are those who visit religious teachers,â one proverb put it, âthe worst religious teachers are the those who allow themselves to be visited by princes.â[616] A Medieval Turkish story brings it home even more pointedly:
The king once summoned Nasruddin to court.
âTell me,â said the king, âyou are a mystic, a philosopher, a man of unconventional understandings. I have become interested in the issue of value. Itâs an interesting philosophical question. How does one establish the true worth of a person, or an object? Take me for example. If I were to ask you to estimate my value, what would you say?â
âOh,â Nasruddin said, âIâd say about two hundred dinars.â
The emperor was flabbergasted. âWhat?! But this belt Iâm wearing is worth two hundred dinars!â
âI know,â said Nasruddin. âActually, I was taking the value of the belt into consideration.â
This disjuncture had profound economic effects. It meant that the Caliphate, and later Muslim empires, could operate in many ways much like the old Axial Age empiresâcreating professional armies, waging wars of conquest, capturing slaves, melting down loot and distributing it in the form of coins to soldiers and officials, demanding that those coins be rendered back as taxesâbut at the same time, without having nearly the same effects on ordinary peopleâs lives.
Over the course of the wars of expansion, for example, enormous quantities of gold and silver were indeed looted from palaces, temples, and monasteries and stamped into coinage, allowing the Caliphate to produce gold dinars and silver dirhams of remarkable purityâthat is, with next to no fiduciary element, the value of each coin corresponding almost precisely to its weight in precious metal.[617] As a result, they were able to pay their troops extraordinarily well. A soldier in the Caliphâs army, for example, received almost four times the wages once received by a Roman legionary.[618] We can, perhaps, speak of a kind of âmilitary-coinage-slaveryâ complex hereâbut it existed in a kind of bubble. Wars of expansion, and trade with Europe and Africa, did produce a fairly constant flow of slaves, but in dramatic contrast to the ancient world, very few of them ended up laboring in farms or workshops. Most ended up as decoration in the houses of the rich, or, increasingly over time, as soldiers. Over the course of the Abbasid dynasty (750â1258 ad) in fact, the empire came to rely, for its military forces, almost exclusively on Mamluks, highly trained military slaves captured or purchased from the Turkish steppes. The policy of employing slaves as soldiers was maintained by all of the Islamic successor states, including the Mughals, and culminated in the famous Mamluk sultanate in Egypt in the thirteenth century, but historically, it was unprecedented.[619] In most times and places slaves are, for obvious reasons, the very last people to be allowed anywhere near weapons. Here it was systematic. But in a strange way, it also made perfect sense: if slaves are, by definition, people who have been severed from society, this was the logical consequence of the wall created between society and the Medieval Islamic state.[620]
Religious teachers appear to have done everything they could to prop up the wall. One reason for the recourse to slave soldiers was their tendency to discourage the faithful from serving in the military (since it might mean fighting fellow believers). The legal system that they created also ensured that it was effectively impossible for Muslimsâor for that matter Christian or Jewish subjects of the Caliphateâto be reduced to slavery. Here al-Wahid seems to have been largely correct. Islamic law took aim at just about all the most notorious abuses of earlier, Axial Age societies. Slavery through kidnapping, judicial punishment, debt, and the exposure or sale of children, even through the voluntary sale of oneâs own personâall were forbidden, or rendered unenforceable.[621] Likewise with all the other forms of debt peonage that had loomed over the heads of poor Middle Eastern farmers and their families since the dawn of recorded history. Finally, Islam strictly forbade usury, which it interpreted to mean any arrangement in which money or a commodity was lent at interest, for any purpose whatsoever.[622]
In a way, one can see the establishment of Islamic courts as the ultimate triumph of the patriarchal rebellion that had begun so many thousands of years before: of the ethos of the desert or the steppe, real or imagined, even as the faithful did their best to keep the heavily armed descendants of actual nomads confined to their camps and palaces. It was made possible by a profound shift in class alliances. The great urban civilizations of the Middle East had always been dominated by a de facto alliance between administrators and merchants, both of whom kept the rest of the population either in debt peonage or in constant peril of falling into it. In converting to Islam, the commercial classes, so long the arch-villains in the eyes of ordinary farmers and townsfolk, effectively agreed to change sides, abandon all their most hated practices, and become instead the leaders of a society that now defined itself against the state.
It was possible because from the beginning, Islam had a positive view toward commerce. Mohammed himself had begun his adult life as a merchant; and no Islamic thinker ever treated the honest pursuit of profit as itself intrinsically immoral or inimical to faith. Neither did the prohibitions against usuryâwhich for the most part were scrupulously enforced, even in the case of commercial loansâin any sense mitigate against the growth of commerce, or even the development of complex credit instruments.[623] To the contrary, the early centuries of the Caliphate saw an immediate efflorescence in both.
Profits were still possible because Islamic jurists were careful to allow for certain service fees, and other considerationsânotably, allowing goods bought on credit to be priced slightly higher than those bought for cashâthat ensured that bankers and traders still had an incentive to provide credit services.[624] Still, these incentives were never enough to allow banking to become a full-time occupation: instead, almost any merchant operating on a sufficiently large scale could be expected to combine banking with a host of other moneymaking activities. As a result, credit instruments soon became so essential to trade that almost anyone of prominence was expected to keep most of his or her wealth on deposit, and to make everyday transactions, not by counting out coins, but by inkpot and paper. Promissory notes were called **sakk**, âchecksâ, or **ruqâa**, ânotes.â Checks could bounce. One German historian, picking through a multitude of old Arabic literary sources, recounts that:
About 900 a great man paid a poet in this way, only the banker refused the check, so that the disappointed poet composed a verse to the effect that he would gladly pay a million on the same plan. A patron of the same poet and singer (936) during a concert wrote a check in his favor on a banker for five hundred dinars. When paying, the banker gave the poet to understand that it was customary to charge one dirham discount on each dinar, i.e., about ten per cent. Only if the poet would spend the afternoon and evening with him, he would make no deduction âŠ
By about 1000 the banker had made himself indispensable in Basra: every trader had his banking account, and paid only in checks on his bank in the bazaar.âŠ[625]
Checks could be countersigned and transferred, and letters of credit (**suftaja**) could travel across the Indian Ocean or the Sahara.[626] If they did not turn into de facto paper money, it was because, since they operated completely independent of the state (they could not be used to pay taxes, for instance), their value was based almost entirely on trust and reputation.[627] Appeal to the Islamic courts was generally voluntary or mediated by merchant guilds and civic associations. In such a context, having a famous poet compose verses making fun of you for bouncing a check was probably the ultimate disaster.
When it came to finance, instead of interest-bearing investments, the preferred approach was partnerships, where (often) one party would supply the capital, the other carry out the enterprise. Instead of fixed return, the investor would receive a share of the profits. Even labor arrangements were often organized on a profit-sharing basis.[628] In all such matters, reputation was crucialâin fact, one lively debate in early commercial law was over the question of whether reputation could (like land, labor, money, or other resources) itself be considered a form of capital. It sometimes happened that merchants would form partnerships with no capital at all, but only their good names. This was called âpartnership of good reputation.â As one legal scholar explained:
As for the credit partnership, it is also called the âpartnership of the pennilessâ (**sharika al-mafalis**). It comes about when two people form a partnership without any capital in order to buy on credit and then sell. It is designated by this name partnership of good reputations because their capital consists of their status and good reputations; for credit is extended only to him who has a good reputation among people.[629]
Some legal scholars objected to the idea that such a contract could be considered legally binding, since it was not based on an initial outlay of material capital; others considered it legitimate, provided the partners make an equitable partition of the profitsâsince reputation cannot be quantified. The remarkable thing here is the tacit recognition that, in a credit economy that operates largely without state mechanisms of enforcement (without police to arrest those who commit fraud, or bailiffs to seize a debtorâs property), a significant part of the value of a promissory note is indeed the good name of the signatory. As Pierre Bourdieu was later to point out in describing a similar economy of trust in contemporary Algeria: itâs quite possible to turn honor into money, almost impossible to convert money into honor.[630]
These networks of trust, in turn, were largely responsible for the spread of Islam over the caravan routes of Central Asia and the Sahara, and especially across the Indian Ocean, the main conduit of Medieval world trade. Over the course of the Middle Ages, the Indian Ocean effectively became a Muslim lake. Muslim traders appear to have played a key role in establishing the principle that kings and their armies should keep their quarrels on dry land; the seas were to be a zone of peaceful commerce. At the same time, Islam gained a toehold in trade emporia from Aden to the Moluccas because Islamic courts were so perfectly suited to provide those functions that made such ports attractive: means of establishing contracts, recovering debts, creating a banking sector capable of redeeming or transferring letters of credit.[631] The level of trust thereby created between merchants in the great Malay entrepĂŽt Malacca, gateway to the spice islands of Indonesia, was legendary. The city had Swahili, Arab, Egyptian, Ethiopian, and Armenian quarters, as well as quarters for merchants from different regions of India, China, and Southeast Asia. Yet it was said that its merchants shunned enforceable contracts, preferring to seal transactions âwith a handshake and a glance at heaven.â[632]
In Islamic society, the merchant became not just a respected figure, but a kind of paragon: like the warrior, a man of honor able to pursue far-flung adventures; unlike him, able to do so in a fashion damaging to no one. The French historian Maurice Lombard draws a striking, if perhaps rather idealized, picture of him âin his stately town-house, surrounded by slaves and hangers-on, in the midst of his collections of books, travel souvenirs, and rare ornaments,â along with his ledgers, correspondence, and letters of credit, skilled in the arts of double-entry book-keeping along with secret codes and ciphers, giving alms to the poor, supporting places of worship, perhaps, dedicating himself to the writing of poetry, while still able to translate his general creditworthiness into great capital reserves by appealing to family and partners.[633] Lombardâs picture is to some degree inspired by the famous **Thousand and One Nights** description of Sindbad, who, having spent his youth in perilous mercantile ventures to faraway lands, finally retired, rich beyond dreams, to spend the rest of his life amidst gardens and dancing girls, telling tall tales of his adventures. Hereâs a glimpse, from the eyes of a humble porter (also named Sindbad) when first summoned to see him by the masterâs page:
He found it to be a goodly mansion, radiant and full of majesty, till he brought him to a grand sitting room wherein he saw a company of nobles and great lords seated at tables garnished with all manner of flowers and sweet-scented herbs, besides great plenty of dainty viands and fruits dried and fresh and confections and wines of the choicest vintages. There also were instruments of music and mirth and lovely slave girls playing and singing. All the company was ranged according to rank, and in the highest place sat a man of worshipful and noble aspect whose bearded sides hoariness had stricken, and he was stately of stature and fair of favor, agreeable of aspect and full of gravity and dignity and majesty. So Sindbad the Porter was confounded at that which he beheld and said in himself, âBy Allah, this must be either some kingâs palace, or a piece of Paradise!â[634]
Itâs worth quoting not only because it represents a certain ideal, a picture of the perfect life, but because thereâs no real Christian parallel. It would be impossible conceive of such an image appearing in, say, a Medieval French romance.
The veneration of the merchant was matched by what can only be called the worldâs first popular free-market ideology. True, one should be careful not to confuse ideals with reality. Markets were ever entirely independent from the government. Islamic regimes did employ all the usual strategies of manipulating tax policy to encourage the growth of markets, and they periodically tried to intervene in commercial law.[635] Still, there was a very strong popular feeling that they shouldnât. Once freed from its ancient scourges of debt and slavery, the local bazaar had become, for most, not a place of moral danger, but the very opposite: the highest expression of the human freedom and communal solidarity, and thus to be protected assiduously from state intrusion.
There was a particular hostility to anything that smacked of price-fixing. One much-repeated story held that the Prophet himself had refused to force merchants to lower prices during a shortage in the city of Medina, on the grounds that doing so would be sacrilegious, since, in a free-market situation, âprices depend on the will of God.â[636] Most legal scholars interpreted Mohammedâs decision to mean that any government interference in market mechanisms should be considered similarly sacrilegious, since markets were designed by God to regulate themselves.[637]
If all this bears a striking resemblance to Adam Smithâs âinvisible handâ (which was also the hand of Divine Providence), it might not be a complete coincidence. In fact, many of the specific arguments and examples that Smith uses appear to trace back directly to economic tracts written in Medieval Persia. For instance, not only does his argument that exchange is a natural outgrowth of human rationality and speech already appear both in both Ghazali (1058â1111 ad), and Tusi (1201â1274 ad); both use exactly the same illustration: that no one has ever observed two dogs exchanging bones.[638] Even more dramatically, Smithâs most famous example of division of labor, the pin factory, where it takes eighteen separate operations to produce one pin, already appears in Ghazaliâs **Ihya**, in which he describes a needle factory, where it takes twenty-five different operations to produce a needle.[639]
The differences, however, are just as significant as the similarities. One telling example: like Smith, Tusi begins his treatise on economics with a discussion of the division of labor; but where for Smith, the division of labor is actually an outgrowth of our ânatural propensity to truck and barterâ in pursuit of individual advantage, for Tusi, it was an extension of mutual aid:
Let us suppose that each individual were required to busy himself with providing his own sustenance, clothing, dwelling-place and weapons, first acquiring the tools of carpentry and the smithâs trade, then readying thereby tools and implements for sowing and reaping, grinding and kneading, spinning and weaving ⊠Clearly, he would not be capable of doing justice to any one of them. But when men render aid to each other, each one performing one of these important tasks that are beyond the measure of his own capacity, and observing the law of justice in transactions by giving greatly and receiving in exchange of the labor of others, then the means of livelihood are realized, and the succession of the individual and the survival of the species are assured.[640]
As a result, he argues, divine providence has arranged us to have different abilities, desires, and inclinations. The market is simply one manifestation of this more general principle of mutual aid, of the matching of, abilities (supply) and needs (demand)âor to translate it into my own earlier terms, it is not only founded on, but is itself an extension of the kind of baseline communism on which any society must ultimately rest.
All this is not to say that Tusi was in any sense a radical egalitarian. Quite the contrary. âIf men were equal,â he insists, âthey would all perish.â We need differences between rich and poor, he insisted, just as much as we need differences between farmers and carpenters. Still, once you start from the initial premise that markets are primarily about cooperation rather than competitionâand while Muslim economic thinkers did recognize and accept the need for market competition, they never saw competition as its essence[641]âthe moral implications are very different. Nasruddinâs story about the quail eggs might have been a joke, but Muslim ethicists did often enjoin merchants to drive a hard bargain with the rich so they could charge less, or pay more, when dealing with the less fortunate.[642]
Ghazaliâs take on the division of labor is similar, and his account of the origins of money is if anything even more revealing. It begins with what looks much like the myth of barter, except that, like all Middle Eastern writers, he starts not with imaginary primitive tribesmen, but with strangers meeting in an imaginary marketplace.
Sometimes a person needs what he does not own and he owns what he does not need. For example, a person has saffron but needs a camel for transportation and one who owns a camel does not presently need that camel but he wants saffron. Thus, there is the need for an exchange. However, for there to be an exchange, there must be a way to measure the two objects, for the camel-owner cannot give the whole camel for a quantity of saffron. There is no similarity between saffron and camel so that equal amount of that weight and form can be given. Likewise is the case of one who desires a house but owns some cloth or desires a slave but owns socks, or desires flour but possesses a donkey. These goods have no direct proportionality so one cannot know how much saffron will equal a camelâs worth. Such barter transactions would be very difficult.[643]
Ghazali also notes that there might also be a problem of one person not even needing what the other has to offer, but this is almost an afterthought; for him, the real problem is conceptual. How do you compare two things with no common qualities? His conclusion: it can only be done by comparing both to a third thing with no qualities at all. For this reason, he explains, God created dinars and dirhams, coins made out of gold and silver, two metals that are otherwise no good for anything:
<em>Dirhams</em> and <em>dinars</em> are not created for any particular purpose; they are useless by themselves; they are just like stones. They are created to circulate from hand to hand, to govern and to facilitate transactions. They are symbols to know the value and grades of goods.[644]
They can be symbols, units of measure, because of this very lack of usefulness, indeed lack of any particular feature other than value:
A thing can only be exactly linked to other things if it has no particular special form or feature of its ownâfor example, a mirror that has no color can reflect all colors. The same is the case with moneyâit has no purpose of its own, but it serves as medium for the purpose of exchanging goods.[645]
From this it also follows that lending money at interest must be illegitimate, since it means using money as an end in itself: âMoney is not created to earn money.â In fact, he says, âin relation to other goods, **dirhams** and **dinars** are like prepositions in a sentence,â words that, as the grammarians inform us, are used to give meaning to other words, but can only do because they have no meaning in themselves. Money is a thus a unit of measure that provides a means of assessing the value of goods, but also one that operates as such only if it stays in constant motion. To enter in monetary transactions in order to obtain even more money, even if itâs a matter of M-C-Mâ, let alone M-Mâ, would be, according to Ghazali, the equivalent of kidnapping a postman.[646]
Whereas Ghazali speaks only of gold and silver, what he describesâmoney as symbol, as abstract measure, having no qualities of its own, whose value is only maintained by constant motionâis something that would never have occurred to anyone were it not in an age when it was perfectly normal for money to be employed in purely virtual form.
Much of our free-market doctrine, then, appears to have been originally borrowed piecemeal from a very different social and moral universe.[647] The mercantile classes of the Medieval Near West had pulled off an extraordinary feat. By abandoning the usurious practices that had made them so obnoxious to their neighbors for untold centuries before, they were able to becomeâalongside religious teachersâthe effective leaders of their communities: communities that are still seen as organized, to a large extent, around the twin poles of mosque and bazaar.[648] The spread of Islam allowed the market to become a global phenomenon, operating largely independent of governments, according to its own internal laws. But the very fact that this was, in a certain way, a genuine free market, not one created by the government and backed by its police and prisonsâa world of handshake deals and paper promises backed only by the integrity of the signerâmeant that it could never really become the world imagined by those who later adopted many of the same ideas and arguments: one of purely self-interested individuals vying for material advantage by any means at hand.
<em>Where there is justice in war, there is also justice in usury</em>.
âSaint Ambrose
Europe, as I mentioned, came rather late to the Middle Ages and for most of it was something of a hinterland. Still, the period began much as it did elsewhere, with the disappearance of coinage. Money retreated into virtuality. Everyone continued to calculate costs in Roman currency, then, later, in Carolingian âimaginary moneyââthe purely conceptual system of pounds, shillings, and pence used across Western Europe to keep accounts well into the seventeenth century.
Local mints did gradually come back into operation, producing coins in an endless variety of weight, purity, and denominations. How these related to the pan-European system, though, was a matter of manipulation. Kings regularly issued decrees revaluing their own coins in relation to the money of account, âcrying upâ the currency by, say, declaring that henceforth, one of their **ecus** or **escudos** would no longer be worth 1/12 but now 1/8 of a shilling (thus effectively raising taxes) or âcrying downâ the value of their coins by doing the reverse (thus effectively reducing their debts).[649] The real gold or silver content of coins was endlessly readjusted, and currencies were frequently called in for re-minting. Meanwhile, most everyday transactions dispensed with cash entirely, operating through tallies, tokens, ledgers, or transactions in kind. As a result, when the Scholastics came to address such matters in the thirteenth century, they quickly adopted Aristotleâs position that money was a mere social convention: that it was, basically, whatever human beings decided that it was.[650]
All this fit the broader Medieval pattern: actual gold and silver, such of it as was still around, was increasingly laid up in sacred places; as centralized states disappeared, the regulation of markets was increasingly in the hands of the Church.
At first, the Catholic attitudes toward usury were just as harsh as Muslim ones, and attitudes toward merchants, considerably harsher. In the first case, they had little choice, as many Biblical texts were quite explicit. Consider Exodus 22:25:
If you lend money to My people, to the poor among you, you are not to act as a creditor to him; you shall not charge him interest.
Both the Psalms (15:5, 54:12) and Prophets (Jeremiah 9.6, Nehemiah 5:11) were explicit in assigning usurers to death and hellfire. Whatâs more, the early Christian Fathers, who laid the foundation of Church teachings on social issues in the waning years of the Roman empire, were writing amidst the ancient worldâs last great debt crisis, one that was effectively in the process of destroying the empireâs remaining free peasantry.[651] While few were willing to condemn slavery, all condemned usury.
Usury was seen above all as an assault on Christian charity, on Jesusâs injunction to treat the poor as they would treat the Christ himself, giving without expectation of return and allowing the borrower to decide on recompense (Luke 6:34â35). In 365 ad, for instance, St. Basil delivered a sermon on usury in Cappadocia that set the standard for such issues:
The Lord gave His own injunction quite plainly in the words, âfrom him that would borrow of thee turn not thou away.â[652]
But what of the money lover? He sees before him a man under stress of necessity bent to the ground in supplication. He sees him hesitating at no act, no words, of humiliation. He sees him suffering undeserved misfortune, but he is merciless. He does not reckon that he is a fellow-creature. He does not give in to his entreaties. He stands stiff and sour. He is moved by no prayers; his resolution is broken by no tears. He persists in refusal âŠ[653]
That is, until the suppliant mentions âinterest.â
Basil was particularly offended by the crass dishonesty by which moneylenders operated; their abuse of Christian fellowship. The man in need comes seeking a friend, the rich man pretends to be one. In fact heâs a secret enemy, and everything he says is a lie. Witness, St. Basil said, how the rich man will always at first swear mighty oaths that he has no money to his name:
Then the suppliant mentions interest, and utters the word security. All is changed. The frown is relaxed; with a genial smile he recalls old family connection. Now it is âmy friend.â
âI will see,â says he, âif I have any money by me. Yes, there is that sum which a man I know has left in my hands on deposit for profit. He stipulated a very heavy rate of interest. However, I shall certainly take something off, and give it to you on better terms.â With pretences of this kind and talk like this he fawns on the wretched victim, and induces him to swallow the bait. Then he binds him with a written security, adds loss of liberty to the trouble of his pressing poverty, and is off. The man who has made himself responsible for interest that he cannot pay has accepted voluntary slavery for life.[654]
The borrower, coming home with his newfound money, at first rejoices. But quickly, âthe money slips away,â interest accumulates, and his possessions are sold off. Basil grows poetic in describing the debtorâs plight. Itâs as if time itself has become his enemy. Every day and night conspires against him, as they are the parents of interest. His life becomes a âsleepless daze of anxious uncertainty,â as he is humiliated in public; while at home, he is constantly hiding under the couch at every unexpected knock on the door, and can barely sleep, startled awake by nightmare visions of his creditor standing over his pillow.[655]
Probably the most famous ancient homily on usury, though, was Saint Ambroseâs **De Tobia**, pronounced over several days in Milan in 380 bc. He reproduces the same vivid details as Basil: fathers forced to sell their children, debtors who hanged themselves out of shame. Usury, he observes, must be considered a form of violent robbery, even murder.[656] Ambrose, though, added one small proviso that was later to have enormous influence. His sermon was the first to carefully examine every Biblical reference to moneylending, which meant that he had to address the one problem later authors always had to struggle withâthe fact that, in the Old Testament, usury is not quite forbidden to everyone. The key sticking point is always Deuteronomy 23:19â20:
Thou shalt not lend upon usury to thy brother; usury of money, usury of victuals, usury of any thing that is lent upon usury.
Unto a stranger thou mayest lend upon usury; but unto thy brother thou shalt not lend upon usury.
So who then is this âstrangerâ or (a better translation of the Hebrew **nokri**, âforeignerâ)? Presumably, one against whom robbery and murder would have been justified as well. After all, the ancient Jews lived amidst tribes like the Amalekites, on whom God had specifically instructed them to make war. If by extracting interest one is, as he puts it, fighting without a sword, then it is only legitimate to do so from those âwhom it would not be a crime to kill.â[657] For Ambrose, living in Milan, all this was something of a technicality. He included all Christians and all those subject to Roman law as âbrothersâ; there werenât, then, lot of Amalekites around.[658] Later, the âException of St. Ambrose,â as it came to be known, was to become extremely important.
All of these sermonsâand there were many of themâleft certain critical questions unanswered. What **should** the rich man do when receiving a visit from his troubled neighbor? True, Jesus had said to give without expectation of return, but it seemed unrealistic to expect most Christians to do that. And even if they did, what sort of ongoing relationships would that create? St. Basil took the radical position. God had given us all things in common, and he had specifically instructed the rich to give their possessions to the poor. The communism of the Apostlesâwho pooled all their wealth, and took freely what they neededâwas thus the only proper model for a truly Christian society.[659] Few of the other Christian Fathers were willing to take things this far. Communism was the ideal, but in this fallen and temporary world, they argued, it was simply unrealistic. The Church must accept existing property arrangements, but also come up with spiritual arguments to encourage the rich to nonetheless act with Christian charity. Many of these employed distinctly commercial metaphors. Even Basil was willing to indulge in this sort of thing:
Whenever you provide for the destitute on account of the Lord, it is both a gift and a loan. It is a gift because you entertain no hope in recovering it, a loan because of our Lordâs munificence in paying you back on his behalf, when, having taken a small sum for the poor, he will give you back a vast sum in return. âFor he who takes pity on the poor, lends to God.â[660]
Since Christ is in the poor, a gift of charity is a loan to Jesus, to be repaid with interest inconceivable on earth.
Charity, however, is a way of maintaining hierarchy, not undermining it. What Basil is talking about here really has nothing to do with debt, and playing with such metaphors seems ultimately to serve only to underline the fact that the rich man doesnât **owe** the poor suppliant anything, any more than God is in any way legally bound to save the soul of anyone who feeds a beggar. âDebtâ here dissolves into a pure hierarchy (hence, âthe Lordâ) where utterly different beings provide each other utterly different kinds of benefit. Later theologians were to explicitly confirm this: human beings live in time, noted St. Thomas Aquinas, so it makes sense to say that sin is a debt of punishment we owe to God. But God lives outside of time. By definition, he cannot owe anything to anyone. His grace can therefore only be a gift given with no obligation.[661]
This, in turn, provides an answer to the question: What are they really asking the rich man to do? The Church opposed usury, but it had little to say about relations of feudal dependency, where the rich man provides charity and the poor suppliant shows his gratitude in other ways. Neither, when these kinds of arrangements began to emerge across the Christian West, did the Church offer significant objections.[662] Former debt peons were gradually transformed into serfs or vassals. In some ways, the relationship was not much different, since vassalage was, in theory, a voluntary, contractual relationship. Just as a Christian has to be able to freely choose to submit himself to âthe Lord,â so did a vassal have to agree to make himself someone elseâs man. All this proved perfectly consonant with Christianity.
Commerce, on the other hand, remained a problem. There was not much of a leap between condemning usury as the taking of âwhatever exceeds the amount loanedâ and condemning any form of profit-taking. ManyâSaint Ambrose among themâwere willing to take that leap. Where Mohammed declared that an honest merchant deserved a place by the seat of God in heaven, men like Ambrose wondered if an âhonest merchantâ could actually exist. Many held that one simply could not be both a merchant and a Christian.[663] In the early Middle Ages, this was not a pressing issueâespecially since so much commerce was conducted by foreigners. The conceptual problems, however, were never resolved. What did it mean that one could only lend to âstrangersâ? Was it just usury, or was even commerce tantamount to war?
Probably the most notorious, and often catastrophic, way that this problem worked itself out in the High Middle Ages was in relations between Christians and Jews. In the years since Nehemiah, Jewish attitudes toward lending had themselves changed. In the time of Augustus, Rabbi Hillel had effectively rendered the sabbatical year a dead letter, by allowing two parties to place a rider on any particular loan contract agreeing that it would not apply. While both the Torah and the Talmud stand opposed to loans on interest, exceptions were made in dealing with Gentilesâparticularly as, over the course of the eleventh and twelfth centuries, European Jews were excluded from almost any other line of work.[664] This in turn made it harder to contain the practice, as witnessed in the common joke, current in twelfth-century ghettos to justify usury between Jews. It consisted, it is said, of reciting Deuteronomy 23:20 in interrogative tones to make it mean the opposite of its obvious sense: âUnto a foreigner thou mayest lend upon usury, but unto thy brother thou shalt not lend upon usury?â[665]
On the Christian side, in 1140 ad the âException of Saint Ambroseâ found its way into Gratianâs **Decretum**, which came to be considered the definitive collection of canon law. At the time, economic life fell very much under the jurisdiction of the Church. While that might appear to leave Jews safely outside the system, in reality, matters were more complicated. For one thing, while both Jews and Gentiles would occasionally attempt to make recourse to the Exception, the prevailing opinion was that it only really applied to Saracens or others with whom Christendom was literally at war. After all, Jews and Christians lived in the same towns and villages. If one were to concede that the Exception allowed Jews and Christians the right to lend to each other at interest, it would also mean that they had the right to murder one another.[666] No one really wanted to say that. On the other hand, real relations between Christians and Jews often did seem to skate perilously close to this unfortunate idealâthough obviously the actual murder (apart from mere economic aggression) was all on one side.
In part this was due to the habit of Christian princes of exploiting, for their own purposes, the fact that Jews did sit slightly outside the system. Many encouraged Jews to operate as moneylenders, under their protection, simply because they also knew that protection could be withdrawn at any time. The kings of England were notorious in this regard. They insisted that Jews be excluded from merchant and craft guilds, but granted them the right to charge extravagant rates of interest, backing up the loans by the full force of law.[667] Debtors in Medieval England were regularly thrown in prisons until their families settled with the creditor.[668] Yet the same regularly happened to the Jews themselves. In 1210 ad, for example, King John ordered a tallage, or emergency levy, to pay for his wars in France and Ireland. According to one contemporary chronicler âall the Jews throughout England, of both sexes, were seized, imprisoned, and tortured severely, in order to do the kingâs will with their money.â Most who where put to torture offered all they had and moreâbut on that occasion, one particularly wealthy merchant, a certain Abraham of Bristol, who the king decided owed him ten thousand marks of silver (a sum equivalent to about a sixth of Johnâs total annual revenue), became famous for holding out. The king therefore ordered that one of his molars be pulled out daily, until he paid. After seven had been extracted, Abraham finally gave in.[669]
Johnâs successor, Henry III (1216â1272 ad), was in the habit of turning over Jewish victims to his brother the Earl of Cornwall, so that, as another chronicler put it, âthose whom one brother had flayed, the other might embowel.â[670] Such stories about the extraction of Jewish teeth, skin, and intestines are, I think, important to bear in mind when thinking about Shakespeareâs imaginary Merchant of Venice demanding his âpound of flesh.â[671] It all seems to have been a bit of a guilty projection of terrors that Jews had never really visited on Christians, but that had been directed the other way around.
The terror inflicted by kings carried in it a peculiar element of identification: the persecutions and appropriations were an extension of the logic whereby kings effectively treated debts owed to Jews as ultimately owed to themselves, even setting up a branch of the Treasury (âthe Exchequer of the Jewsâ) to manage them.[672] This was of course much in keeping with the popular English impression of their kings as themselves a group of rapacious Norman foreigners. But it also gave the kings the opportunity to periodically play the populist card, dramatically snubbing or humiliating their Jewish financiers, turning a blind eye or even encouraging pogroms by townsfolk who chose to take the Exception of Saint Ambrose literally, and treat moneylenders as enemies of Christ who could be murdered in cold blood. Particularly gruesome massacres occurred in Norwich in 1144 ad, and in France, in Blois in 1171. Before long, as Norman Cohn put it, âwhat had once been a flourishing Jewish culture had turned into a terrorized society locked in perpetual warfare with the greater society around it.â[673]
One mustnât exaggerate the Jewish role in lending. Most Jews had nothing to do with the business, and those who did were typically bit players, making minor loans of grain or cloth for a return in kind. Others werenât even really Jews. Already in the 1190s, preachers were complaining about lords who would work hand in glove with Christian moneylenders claiming they were âour Jewsââand thus under their special protection.[674] By the 1100s, most Jewish moneylenders had long since been displaced by Lombards (from Northern Italy) and Cahorsins (from the French town of Cahors)âwho established themselves across Western Europe, and became notorious rural usurers.[675]
The rise of rural usury was itself a sign of a growing free peasantry (there had been no point in making loans to serfs, since they had nothing to repossess). It accompanied the rise of commercial farming, urban craft guilds, and the âcommercial revolutionâ of the High Middle Ages, all of which finally brought Western Europe to a level of economic activity comparable to that long since considered normal in other parts of the world. The Church quickly came under considerable popular pressure to do something about the problem, and at first, it did try to tighten the clamps. Existing loopholes in the usury laws were systematically closed, particularly the use of mortgages. These latter began as an expedient: as in Medieval Islam, those determined to dodge the law could simply present the money, claim to be buying the debtorâs house or field, and then ârentâ it back to the debtor until the principal was repaid. In the case of a mortgage, the house was in theory not even purchased but pledged as security, but any income from it accrued to the lender. In the eleventh century this became a favorite trick of monasteries. In 1148 it was made illegal: henceforth, all income was to be subtracted from the principal. Similarly, in 1187 merchants were forbidden to charge higher prices when selling on creditâthe Church thereby going much further than any school of Islamic law ever had. In 1179 usury was made a mortal sin and usurers were excommunicated and denied Christian burial.[676] Before long, new orders of itinerant friars like the Franciscans and Dominicans organized preaching campaigns, traveling town to town, village to village, threatening moneylenders with the loss of their eternal souls if they did not make restitution to their victims.
All this was echoed by a heady intellectual debate in the newly founded universities, not so much as to whether usury was sinful and illegal, but precisely why. Some argued that it was theft of anotherâs material possessions; others that it constituted a theft of time, charging others for something that belonged only to God. Some held that it embodied the sin of Sloth, since like the Confucians, Catholic thinkers usually held that a merchantâs profit could only be justified as payment for his labor (i.e., in transporting goods to wherever they were needed), whereas interest accrued even if the lender did nothing at all. Soon the rediscovery of Aristotle, who returned in Arabic translation (and the influence of Muslim sources like Ghazali and Ibn Sina), added new arguments: that treating money as an end in itself defied its true purpose; that charging interest was unnatural, in that it treated mere metal as if it were a living thing that could breed or bear fruit.[677]
But as the Church authorities soon discovered, when one starts something like this, itâs very hard to keep a lid on it. Soon, new popular religious movements were appearing everywhere, and many took up the same direction so many had in late Antiquity, not only challenging commerce but questioning the very legitimacy of private property. Most were labeled heresies and violently suppressed, but many of the same arguments were taken up amongst the mendicant orders themselves. By the thirteenth century, the great intellectual debate was between the Franciscans and the Dominicans over âapostolic povertyââbasically, over whether Christianity could be reconciled with property of any sort.
At the same time, the revival of Roman lawâwhich, as weâve seen, began from the assumption of absolute private propertyâput new intellectual weapons in the hands of those who wished to argue that, at least in the case of commercial loans, usury laws should be relaxed. The great discovery in this case was the notion of **interesse**, which is where our word âinterestâ originally comes from: a compensation for loss suffered because of late payment.[678] The argument soon became that if a merchant made a commercial loan even for some minimal period (say, a month), it was not usurious for him to charge a percentage for each month afterward, since this was a penalty, not rental for the money, and it was justified as compensation for the profit he **would** have made, had he placed it in some profitable investment, as any merchant would ordinarily be expected to do.[679]
The reader may be wondering how it could have been possible for usury laws to move in two opposite directions simultaneously. The answer would seem to be that politically, the situation in Western Europe was remarkably chaotic. Most kings were weak, their holdings fractured and uncertain; the Continent was a checkerboard of baronies, principalities, urban communes, manors, and church estates. Jurisdictions were constantly being renegotiatedâusually by war. Merchant capitalism of the sort long familiar in the Muslim Near West only really managed to establish itselfâquite late, compared with the situation in the rest of the Medieval worldâwhen merchant capitalists managed to secure a political foothold in the independent city-states of northern Italyâmost famously, Venice, Florence, Genoa, and Milanâfollowed by the German cities of the Hanseatic League.[680] Italian bankers ultimately managed to free themselves from the threat of expropriation by themselves taking over governments, and by doing so, acquiring their own court systems (capable of enforcing contracts) and even more critically, their own armies.[681]
What jumps out, in comparison with the Muslim world, are these links of finance, trade, and violence. Whereas Persian and Arab thinkers assumed that the market emerged as an extension of mutual aid, Christians never completely overcame the suspicion that commerce was really an extension of usury, a form of fraud only truly legitimate when directed against oneâs mortal enemies. Debt was, indeed, sinâon the part of both parties to the transaction. Competition was essential to the nature of the market, but competition was (usually) nonviolent warfare. There was a reason why, as Iâve already observed, the words for âtruck and barterâ in almost all European languages were derived from terms meaning âswindle,â âbamboozle,â or âdeceive.â Some disdained commerce for that reason. Others embraced it. Few would have denied that the connection was there.
One need only examine the way that Islamic credit instrumentsâor for that matter, the Islamic ideal of the merchant adventurerâwere eventually adopted to see just how intimate this connection really was.
It is often held that the first pioneers of modern banking were the Military Order of the Knights of the Temple of Solomon, commonly known as the Knights Templar. A fighting order of monks, they played a key role in financing the Crusades. Through the Templars, a lord in southern France might take out a mortgage on one of his tenements and receive a âdraftâ (a bill of exchange, modeled on the Muslim **suftaja**, but written in a secret code) redeemable for cash from the Temple in Jerusalem. In other words, Christians appear to have first adopted Islamic financial techniques to finance attacks against Islam.
The Templars lasted from 1118 to 1307, but they finally went the way of so many Medieval trading minorities: King Phillip IV, deep in debt to the order, turned on them, accusing them of unspeakable crimes; their leaders were tortured and ultimately killed, and their wealth was expropriated.[682] Much of the problem was that they lacked a powerful home base. Italian banking houses such as the Bardi, Peruzzi, and Medici did much better. In banking history, the Italians are most famous for their complex joint-stock organization and for spearheading the use of Islamic-style bills of exchange.[683] At first these were simple enough: basically just a form of long-distance money-changing. A merchant could present a certain amount in florins to a banker in Italy and receive a notarized bill registering the equivalent in the international money of account (Carolingian derniers), due in, say, three monthsâ time, and then after it came due, either he or his agent could cash it for an equivalent amount of local currency in the Champagne fairs, which were both the great yearly commercial emporia, and great financial clearing houses, of the European High Middle Ages. But they quickly morphed into a plethora of new, creative forms, mainly a way of navigatingâor even profiting fromâthe endlessly complicated European currency situation.[684]
Most of the capital for these banking enterprises derived from the Mediterranean trade in Indian Ocean spices and Eastern luxuries. Yet unlike the Indian Ocean, the Mediterranean was a constant war zone. Venetian galleys doubled as both merchant vessels and warships, replete with cannon and marines, and the differences between trade, crusade, and piracy often depended on the balance of forces at any given moment.[685] The same was true on land: where Asian empires tended to separate the sphere of warriors and merchants, in Europe they often overlapped:
All up and down Central Europe, from Tuscany to Flanders, from Brabant to Livonia, merchants not only supplied warriorsâas they did all over Europeâthey sat in governments that made war and, sometimes, buckled on armor and went into battle themselves. Such places make a long list: not only Florence, Milan, Venice, and Genoa, but also Augsburg, Nuremberg, Strasbourg, and Zurich; not only LĂŒbeck, Hamburg, Bremen, and Danzig, but also Bruges, Ghent, Leiden, and Cologne. Some of themâFlorence, Nuremberg, Siena, Bern, and Ulm come to mindâbuilt considerable territorial states.[686]
The Venetians were only the most famous in this regard. They created a veritable mercantile empire over the course of the eleventh century, seizing islands like Crete and Cyprus and establishing sugar plantations that eventuallyâanticipating a pattern eventually to become all too familiar in the New Worldâcame to be staffed largely by African slaves.[687] Genoa soon followed suit; one of their most lucrative businesses was raiding and trading along the Black Sea to acquire slaves to sell to the Mamluks in Egypt or to work mines leased from the Turks.[688] The Genoese republic was also the inventor of a unique mode of military financing, which might be known as war by subscription, whereby those planning expeditions sold shares to investors in exchange for the rights to an equivalent percentage of the spoils. It was precisely the same galleys, with the same âmerchant adventurersâ aboard, who would eventually pass through the pillars of Hercules to follow the Atlantic coast to Flanders or the Champagne fairs, carrying cargoes of nutmeg or cayenne, silks and woolen goodsâalong with the inevitable bills of exchange.[689]
It would be instructive, I think, to pause a moment to think about this term, âmerchant adventurer.â Originally it just meant a merchant who operated outside his own country. It was around this same time, however, at the height of the fairs of Champagne and the Italian merchant empires, between 1160 and 1172, that the term âadventureâ began to take on its contemporary meaning. The man most responsible for it was the French poet Chretien de Troyes, author of the famous Arthurian romancesâmost famous, perhaps, for being the first to tell the story of Sir Percival and the Holy Grail. The romances were a new sort of literature featuring a new sort of hero, the âknight-errant,â a warrior who roamed the world in search of, precisely, âadventureââin the contemporary sense of the word: perilous challenges, love, treasure, and renown. Stories of knightly adventure quickly became enormously popular, Chretein was followed by innumerable imitators, and the central characters in the storiesâArthur and Guinevere, Lancelot, Gawain, Percival, and the restâbecame known to everyone, as they are still. This courtly ideal of the gallant knight, the quest, the joust, romance and adventure, remains central to our image of the Middle Ages.[690]
The curious thing is that it bears almost no relation to reality. Nothing remotely like a real âknight-errantâ ever existed. âKnightsâ had originally been a term for freelance warriors, drawn from the younger or, often, bastard sons of the minor nobility. Unable to inherit, many were forced to band together to seek their fortunes. Many became little more than roving bands of thugs, in an endless pursuit of plunderâprecisely the sort of people who made merchantsâ lives so dangerous. Culminating in the twelfth century, there was a concerted effort to bring this dangerous population under the control of the civil authorities: not only the code of chivalry, but the tournament, the joustâall these were more than anything else ways of keeping them out of trouble, as it were, in part by setting knights against each other, in part by turning their entire existence into a kind of stylized ritual.[691] The ideal of the lone wandering knight, in search of some gallant adventure, on the other hand, seems to have come out of nowhere.
This is important, since it lies at the very heart of our image of the Middle Agesâand the explanation, I think, is revealing. We have to recall that merchants had begun to achieve unprecedented social and even political power around this time, but that, in dramatic contrast to Islam, where a figure like Sindbadâthe successful merchant adventurerâcould serve as a fictional exemplar of the perfect life, merchants, unlike warriors, were never seen as paragons of much of anything.
Itâs likely no coincidence that Chretien was living in Troyes, at the very heartland of the Champagne fairs that had become, in turn, the commercial hub of Western Europe.[692] While he appears to have modeled his vision of Camelot on the elaborate court life under his patron Henri the Liberal (1152â1181), Count of Champagne, and his wife Marie, daughter of Eleanor of Aquitaine, the real court was staffed by low-born **commerçants**, who served as serjeants of the fairsâleaving most real knights in the role of onlookers, guards, orâat tournamentsâentertainers.
This is not to say that tournaments did not become a kind of economic focus in their own right, according to one early twentieth-century Medievalist, Amy Kelly:
The biographer of Guillaume le Marechal gives an idea of how this rabble of courtly routiers amused itself on the jousting fields of western Europe. To the tournaments, occurring in a brisk season about twice a month from Pentecost to the feast of St John, flocked the young bloods, sometimes three thousand strong, taking possession of the nearest town. Thither also flocked horse dealers from Lombardy and Spain, from Brittany and the Low Countries, as well as armorers, haberdashers for man and beast, usurers, mimes and story-tellers, acrobats, necromancers, and other gentlemen of the lists, the field, the road. Entertainers of every stripe found liberal patronage ⊠There were feasts in upper chambers, and forges rang in the smithies all night long. Brawls with grisly incidentsâa cracked skull, a gouged eyeâoccurred as the betting progressed and the dice flew. To cry up their champions in the field came ladies of fair name and others of no name at all.
The hazards, the concourse, the prizes, keyed men to the pitch of war. The stakes were magnificent, for the victor held his prize, horse and man, for ransom. And for these ransoms fiefs went in gage or the hapless victim fell into the hands of usurers, giving his men, and in extremity, himself, as hostages. Fortunes were made and lost on the point of a lance and many a motherâs son failed to ride home.[693]
So, it was not only that the merchants supplied the materials that made the fairs possible; Since vanquished knights technically owed their lives to the victors, merchants ended up, in their capacity as moneylenders, making good business out of liquidating their assets. Alternately, a knight might borrow vast sums to outfit himself in magnificence, hoping to impress some fair lady (with handsome dowry) with his victories; others, to take part in the continual whoring and gambling that always surrounded such events. Losers would end up having to sell their armor and horses, and this created the danger that they would go back to being highwaymen, foment pogroms (if their creditors were Jews) or, if they had lands, make new fiscal demands on those unfortunate enough to live on them.
Others turned to war, which itself tended to drive the creation of new markets.[694] In one of the most dramatic of such incidents, in November 1199, a large number of knights at a tournament at the castle of Ăcry in Champagne, sponsored by Henryâs son, Theobald, were seized by a great religious passion, abandoned their games, and swore a vow to instead retake the Holy Land. The crusader army then proceeded to commission the Venetian fleet for transport in exchange for a promise of a 50-percent share in all resulting profits. In the end, rather than proceeding to the Holy Land, they ended up sacking the (much wealthier, Orthodox) Christian city of Constantinople after a prolonged and bloody siege. A Flemish count named Baldwin was installed as âLatin Emperor of Constantinople,â but attempting to govern a city that had been largely destroyed and stripped of everything of value ensured that he and his barons soon ended up in great financial difficulties. In a gigantic version of what was happening on the small scale in so many tournaments, they were ultimately reduced to stripping the metal off the church roofs and auctioning holy relics to pay back their Venetian creditors. By 1259, Baldwin had sunk to the point of taking out a mortgage on his own son, who was taken back to Venice as security for a loan.[695]
All this does not really answer the question: Whence, then, this image of the solitary knight-errant, wandering the forests of a mythic Albion, challenging rivals, confronting ogres, fairies, wizards, and mysterious beasts? The answer should be clear by now. Really, this is just a sublimated, romanticized image of the traveling merchants themselves: men who did, after all, set off on lonely ventures through wilds and forests, whose outcome was anything but certain.[696]
And what of the Grail, that mysterious object that all the knights-errant were ultimately seeking? Oddly enough, Richard Wagner, composer of the opera **Parzifal**, first suggested that the Grail was a symbol inspired by the new forms of finance.[697] Where earlier epic heroes sought after, and fought over, piles of real, concrete gold and silverâthe Nibelungâs hoardâthese new ones, born of the new commercial economy, pursued purely abstract forms of value. No one, after all, knew precisely what the Grail was. Even the epics disagree: sometimes itâs a plate, sometimes a cup, sometimes a stone. (Wolfram von Eschenbach imagined it to be a jewel knocked from Luciferâs helmet in a battle at the dawn of time.) In a way it doesnât matter. The point is that itâs invisible, intangible, but at the same time of infinite, inexhaustible value, containing everything, capable of making the wasteland flower, feeding the world, providing spiritual sustenance, and healing wounded bodies. Marc Shell even suggested that it would best be conceived as a blank check, the ultimate financial abstraction.[698]
<em>Each of us is a mere symbolon of a man, the result of bisection, like the flat fish, two out of one, and each of us is constantly searching for his corresponding symbolon</em>.
âPlato, **The Symposium**
There is one way that Wagner got it wrong: the introduction of financial abstraction was not a sign that Europe was leaving the Middle Ages, but that it was finally, belatedly, entering it.
Wagnerâs not really to blame here. Almost everyone gets this wrong, because the most characteristic Medieval institutions and ideas arrived so late in Europe that we tend to mistake them for the first stirrings of modernity. Weâve already seen this with bills of exchange, already in use in the East by 700 or 800 ad, but only reaching Europe several centuries later. The independent universityâperhaps the quintessential Medieval institutionâis another case in point. Nalanda was founded in 427 ad, and there were independent institutions of higher learning all over China and the Near West (from Cairo to Constantinople) centuries before the creation of similar institutions in Oxford, Paris, and Bologna.
If the Axial Age was the age of materialism, the Middle Ages were above all else the age of transcendence. The collapse of the ancient empires did not, for the most part, lead to the rise of new ones.[699] Instead, once-subversive popular religious movements were catapulted into the status of dominant institutions. Slavery declined or disappeared, as did the overall level of violence. As trade picked up, so did the pace of technological innovation; greater peace brought greater possibilities not only for the movement of silks and spices, but also of people and ideas. The fact that monks in Medieval China could devote themselves to translating ancient treatises in Sanskrit, and that students in madrasas in Medieval Indonesia could debate legal terms in Arabic, is testimony to the profound cosmopolitanism of the age.
Our image of the Middle Ages as an âage of faithââand hence, of blind obedience to authorityâis a legacy of the French Enlightenment. Again, it makes sense only if you think of the âMiddle Agesâ as something that happened primarily in Europe. Not only was the Far West an unusually violent place by world standards, the Catholic Church was extraordinarily intolerant. Itâs hard to find many Medieval Chinese, Indian, or Islamic parallels, for example, to the burning of âwitchesâ or the massacre of heretics. More typical was the pattern that prevailed in certain periods of Chinese history, when it was perfectly acceptable for a scholar to dabble in Taoism in his youth, become a Confucian in middle age, then become a Buddhist on retirement. If there is an essence to Medieval thought, it lies not in blind obedience to authority, but rather in a dogged insistence that the values that govern our ordinary daily affairsâparticularly those of the court and marketplaceâare confused, mistaken, illusory, or perverse. True value lay elsewhere, in a domain that cannot be directly perceived, but only approached through study or contemplation. But this in turn made the faculties of contemplation, and the entire question of knowledge, an endless problem. Consider for example the great conundrum, pondered by Muslim, Christian, and Jewish philosophers alike: What does it mean to simultaneously say that we can only know God through our faculties of Reason, but that Reason itself partakes of God? Chinese philosophers were struggling with similar conundrums when they asked, âDo we read the classics or do the classics read us?â Almost all the great intellectual debates of the age turned on this question in one way or another. Is the world created by our minds, or our minds by the world?
We can see the same tensions within predominant theories of money. Aristotle had argued that gold and silver had no intrinsic value in themselves, and that money therefore was just a social convention, invented by human communities to facilitate exchange. Since it had âcome about by agreement, therefore it is within our power to change it or render it uselessâ if we all decide that thatâs what we want to do.[700] This position gained little traction in the materialist intellectual environment of the Axial Age, but by the later Middle Ages, it had become standard wisdom. Ghazali was among the first to embrace it. In his own way he took it even further, insisting that the fact that a gold coin has no intrinsic value **is** the basis of its value as money, since this very lack of intrinsic value is what allows it to âgovern,â measure, and regulate the value of other things. But at the same time, Ghazali denied that money was a social convention. It was given us by God.[701]
Ghazali was a mystic, and a political conservative, so one might argue that he ultimately shied away from the most radical implications of his own ideas. But one could also ask whether, in the Middle Ages, arguing that money was an arbitrary social convention was really all that radical a position. After all, when Christian and Chinese thinkers insisted that it was, it was almost always as a way of saying that money is whatever the king or the emperor wished it to be. In that sense, Ghazaliâs position was perfectly consonant with the Islamic desire to protect the market from political interference by saying that it fell properly under the aegis of religious authorities.
The fact that Medieval money took such abstract, virtual formsâchecks, tallies, paper moneyâmeant that questions like these (âWhat does it mean to say that money is a symbol?â) cut to the core of the philosophical issues of the day. Nowhere is this so true as in the history of the word âsymbolâ itself. Here we encounter some parallels so extraordinary that they can only be described as startling.
When Aristotle argued that coins are merely social conventions, the term he used was **symbolon**âfrom which our own word âsymbolâ is derived. Symbolon was originally the Greek word for âtallyââan object broken in half to mark a contract or agreement, or marked and broken to record a debt. So our word âsymbolâ traces back originally to objects broken to record debt contracts of one sort or another. This is striking enough. Whatâs really, remarkable, though, is that the contemporary Chinese word for âsymbol,â fu, or **fu hao**, has almost exactly the same origin.[702]
Letâs start with the Greek term **âsymbolon.â** Two friends at dinner might create a symbolon if they took some objectâa ring, a knucklebone, a piece of crockeryâand broke it in half. Any time in the future when either of them had need of the otherâs help, they could bring their halves as reminders of the friendship. Archeologists have found hundreds of little broken friendship tablets of this sort in Athens, often made of clay. Later they became ways of sealing a contract, the object standing in the place of witnesses.[703] The word was also used for tokens of every sort: those given to Athenian jurors entitling them to vote, or tickets for admission to the theater. It could be used refer to money too, but only if that money had no intrinsic value: bronze coins whose value was fixed only by local convention.[704] Used for written documents, a symbolon could also be passport, contract, commission, or receipt. By extension, it came to mean: omen, portent, symptom, or finally, in the now-familiar sense, symbol.
The path to the latter appears to have been twofold. Aristotle fixed on the fact that a tally could be anything: what the object was didnât matter; all that mattered was that there was a way to break it in half. It is exactly so with language: words are sounds we use to refer to objects, or to ideas, but the relation is arbitrary: thereâs no particular reason, for example, that English-speakers should choose âdogâ to refer to an animal and âgodâ to refer to a deity, rather than the other way around. The only reason is social convention: an agreement between all speakers of a language that this sound shall refer to that thing. In this sense, all words were arbitrary tokens of agreement.[705] So, of course, is moneyâfor Aristotle, not only worthless bronze coins that we agree to treat as if they were worth a certain amount, but all money, even gold, is just a symbolon, a social convention.[706]
All this came to seem almost commonsensical in the thirteenth century of Thomas Aquinas, when rulers could change the value of currency simply by issuing a decree. Still, Medieval theories of symbols derived less from Aristotle than from the Mystery Religions of Antiquity, where âsymbolonâ came to refer to certain cryptic formulae or talismans that only initiates could understand.[707] It thus came to mean a concrete token, perceptible to the senses, that could only be understood in reference to some hidden reality entirely beyond the domain of sensory experience.[708]
The theorist of the symbol whose work was most widely read and respected in the Middle Ages was a sixth-century Greek Christian mystic whose real name has been lost to history, but who is known by his pseudonym Dionysius the Areopagite.[709] Dionysius took up the notion in this latter sense to confront what was to become the great intellectual problem of the age: How is it possible for humans to have knowledge of God? How can we, whose knowledge is confined to what our senses can perceive of the material universe, have knowledge of a being whose nature is absolutely alien to that material universeââthat infinity beyond being,â as he puts it, âthat oneness that is beyond intelligenceâ?[710] It would be impossible were it not for the fact that God, being all-powerful, can do anything, and therefore, just as he places his own body in the Eucharist, so can he reveal himself to our minds through an endless variety of material shapes. Intriguingly, Dionysius warns us that we cannot begin to understand how symbols work until we rid ourselves of the notion that divine things are likely to be beautiful. Images of luminous angels and celestial chariots are only likely to confuse us, since we will be tempted to imagine that thatâs what heaven is actually like, and in fact we cannot possibly conceive of what heaven is like. Instead, effective symbols are, like the original symbolon, homely objects selected apparently at random; often, ugly, ridiculous things, whose very incongruity reminds us that they are **not** God; of the fact that God âtranscends all materiality,â even as, in another sense, they are God.[711] But the notion that they are in any sense tokens of agreement between equals is gone entirely. Symbols are gifts, absolute, free, hierarchical gifts, presented by a being so far above us that any thought of reciprocity, debt, or mutual obligation is simply inconceivable.[712]
Compare the Greek dictionary above to the following, from a Chinese dictionary:
FU. To agree with, to tally. The two halves of a tally.
âą evidence; proof of identity, credentials
âą to fulfill a promise, to keep oneâs word
âą to reconcile
âą the mutual agreement between Heavenâs appointment and human affairs
âą a tally, a check
âą an imperial seal or stamp
âą a warrant, a commission, credentials
âą like fitting the two halves of a tally, in exact agreement
âą a symbol, a sign âŠ[713]
The evolution is almost exactly the same. Like **symbola, fu** can be tallies, contracts, official seals, warrants, passports, or credentials. As promises, they can embody an agreement, a debt contract, or even a relation of feudal vassalageâsince a minor lord agreeing to become another manâs vassal would split a tally just as he would if borrowing grain or money. The common feature seems to be a contract between two parties that begin as equal, in which one agrees to become subordinate. Later, as the state became more centralized, we mainly hear about fu presented to officials as a means of conveying order: the official would take the left half with him when posted to the provinces, and when the emperor wished to send an important command, he would send the right half with the messenger to make sure that the official knew it was actually the imperial will.[714]
Weâve already seen how paper money seems to have developed from paper versions of such debt contracts, ripped in half and reunited. For Chinese theorists, of course, Aristotleâs argument that money was simply a social convention was hardly radical; it was simply assumed. Money was whatever the emperor established it to be. Though even here there was a slight proviso, as evidenced in the entry above, that âfuâ could also refer to âthe mutual agreement between heavenâs appointment and human affairs.â Just as officials were appointed by the emperor, the emperor was ultimately appointed by a higher power, and he could only rule effectively as long as he kept its mandate, which is why propitious omens were called âfu,â signs that heaven approved of the ruler, just as natural disasters were a sign that he had strayed.[715]
Here Chinese ideas did grow a bit closer to the Christian ones. But Chinese conceptions of the cosmos had one crucial difference: since there was no emphasis on the absolute gulf between our world and the one beyond it, contractual relations with the gods were by no means out of the question. This was particularly true in Medieval Taoism, where monks were ordained through a ceremony called ârending the tally,â ripping apart a piece of paper that represented a contract with heaven.[716] It was the same with the magical talismans, also called âfu,â which an adept might receive from his master. These were literally tallies: the adept kept one; the other half was said to be retained by the gods. Such talismanic fu took the form of diagrams, said to represent a form of celestial writing, comprehensible only to the gods, which committed them to assist the bearer, often giving the adept the right to call on armies of divine protectors with whose help he could slay demons, cure the sick, or otherwise attain miraculous powers. But they could also become, like Dionysiusâ symbola, objects of contemplation, by which oneâs mind can ultimately attain some knowledge of the invisible world beyond our own.[717]
Many of the most compelling visual symbols to emerge from Medieval China trace back to such talismans: the River Symbol, or, for that matter, the yin-yang symbol that seems to have developed out of it.[718] Just looking at a yin-yang symbol, it is easy enough to imagine the left and right (sometimes, too, called âmaleâ and âfemaleâ) halves of a tally.
A tally does away with the need for witnesses; if the two surfaces agree, then everyone knows that the agreement between the contracting parties exists as well. This is why Aristotle saw it as a fit metaphor for words: word A corresponds to concept B because there is a tacit agreement that we shall act as if it does. The striking thing about tallies is that even though they might begin as simple tokens of friendship and solidarity, in almost all the later examples, what the two parties actually agree to create is a relation of inequality: of debt, obligation, subordination to anotherâs orders. This is in turn what makes it possible to use the metaphor for the relation between the material world and that more powerful world that ultimately gives it meaning. The two sides are the same. Yet what they create is absolute difference. Hence for a Medieval Christian mystic, as for Medieval Chinese magicians, symbols could be literal fragments of heavenâeven if for the first, they provided a language whereby one could have some understanding of beings one could not possibly interact with; while for the second, they provided a way of interacting, even making practical arrangements, with beings whose language one could not possibly understand.
On one level, this is just another version of the dilemmas that always arise when we try to reimagine the world through debtâthat peculiar agreement between two equals that they shall no longer be equals, until such time as they become equals once again. Still, the problem took on a peculiar piquancy in the Middle Ages, when the economy became, as it were, spiritualized. As gold and silver migrated to holy places, ordinary transactions everywhere came to be carried out primarily through credit. Inevitably, arguments about wealth and markets became arguments about debt and morality, and arguments about debt and morality became arguments about the nature of our place in the universe. As weâve seen, the solutions varied considerably. Europe and India saw a return to hierarchy: society became a ranked order of Priests, Warriors, Merchants, and Farmers (or in Christendom, just Priests, Warriors, and Farmers). Debts between the orders were considered threatening because they implied the potential of equality, and they often led to outright violence. In China, in contrast, the principle of debt often became the governing principle of the cosmos: karmic debts, milk-debts, debt contracts between human beings and celestial powers. From the point of view of the authorities, all these led to excess, and potentially to vast concentrations of capital that might throw the entire social order out of balance. It was the responsibility of government to intervene constantly to keep markets running smoothly and equitably, thus avoiding new outbreaks of popular unrest. In the world of Islam, where theologians held that God recreated the entire universe at every instant, market fluctuations were instead seen as merely another manifestation of divine will.
The striking thing is that the Confucian condemnation of the merchant, and the Islamic celebration of the merchant, ultimately led to the same thing: prosperous societies with flourishing markets, but where the elements never came together to create the great merchant banks and industrial firms that were to become the hallmark of modern capitalism. Itâs especially striking in the case of Islam. Certainly, the Islamic world produced figures who would be hard to describe as anything but capitalists. Large-scale merchants were referred to as **sÄhib al-mÄl**, âowners of capital,â and legal theorists spoke freely about the creation and expansion of capital funds. At the height of the Caliphate, some of these merchants were in possession of millions of dinars and seeking profitable investment. Why did nothing like modern capitalism emerge? I would highlight two factors. First, Islamic merchants appear to have taken their free-market ideology seriously. The marketplace did not fall under the direct supervision of the government; contracts were made between individualsâideally, âwith a handshake and a glance at heavenââand thus honor and credit became largely indistinguishable. This is inevitable: you canât have cutthroat competition where there is no one stopping people from literally cutting one anotherâs throats. Second, Islam also took seriously the principle, later enshrined in classical economic theory but only unevenly observed in practice, that profits are the reward for risk. Trading enterprises were assumed to be, quite literally, adventures, in which traders exposed themselves to the dangers of storm and shipwreck, savage nomads, forests, steppes, and deserts, exotic and unpredictable foreign customs, and arbitrary governments. Financial mechanisms designed to avoid these risks were considered impious. This was one of the objections to usury: if one demands a fixed rate of interest, the profits are guaranteed. Similarly, commercial investors were expected to share the risk. This made most of the forms of finance and insurance that were to later develop in Europe impossible.[719]
In this sense the Buddhist monasteries of early Medieval China represent the opposite extreme. The Inexhaustible Treasuries were inexhaustible because, by continually lending their money out at interest and never otherwise touching their capital, they could guarantee effectively risk-free investments. That was the entire point. By doing so, Buddhism, unlike Islam, produced something very much like what we now call âcorporationsââentities that, through a charming legal fiction, we imagine to be persons, just like human beings, but immortal, never having to go through all the human untidiness of marriage, reproduction, infirmity, and death. To put it in properly Medieval terms, they are very much like angels.
Legally, our notion of the corporation is very much a product of the European High Middle Ages. The legal idea of a corporation as a âfictive personâ (**persona ficta**)âa person who, as Maitland, the great British legal historian, put it, âis immortal, who sues and is sued, who holds lands, has a seal of his own, who makes regulations for those natural persons of whom he is composedâ[720]âwas first established in canon law by Pope Innocent IV in 1250 ad, and one of the first kinds of entities it applied to were monasteriesâas also to universities, churches, municipalities, and guilds.[721]
The idea of the corporation as an angelic being is not mine, incidentally. I borrowed it from the great Medievalist Ernst Kantorowicz, who pointed out that all this was happening right around the same time that Thomas Aquinas was developing the notion that angels were really just the personification of Platonic Ideas.[722] âAccording to the teachings of Aquinas,â he notes, âevery angel represented a species.â
Little wonder then that finally the personified collectives of the jurists, which were juristically immortal species, displayed all the features otherwise attributed to angels ⊠The jurists themselves recognized that there was some similarity between their abstractions and the angelic beings. In this respect, it may be said that the political and legal world of thought of the later Middle Ages began to be populated by immaterial angelic bodies, large and small: they were invisible, ageless, sempiternal, immortal, and sometimes even ubiquitous; and they were endowed with a **corpus intellectuale** or **mysticum** [an intellectual or mystical body] which could stand any comparison with the âspiritual bodiesâ of the celestial beings.[723]
All this is worth emphasizing because while we are used to assuming that thereâs something natural or inevitable about the existence of corporations, in historical terms, they are actually strange, exotic creatures. No other great tradition came up with anything like it.[724] They are the most peculiarly European addition to that endless proliferation of metaphysical entities so characteristic of the Middle Agesâas well as the most enduring.
They have, of course, changed a great deal over time. Medieval corporations owned property, and they often engaged in complex financial arrangements, but in no case were they profit-seeking enterprises in the modern sense. The ones that came closest were, perhaps unsurprisingly, monastic ordersâabove all, the Cisterciansâwhose monasteries became something like the Chinese Buddhist ones, surrounded by mills and smithies, practicing rationalized commercial agriculture with a workforce of âlay brothersâ who were effectively wage laborers, spinning and exporting wool. Some even talk about âmonastic capitalism.â[725] Still, the ground was only really prepared for capitalism in the familiar sense of the term when the merchants began to organize themselves into eternal bodies as a way to win monopolies, legal or de facto, and avoid the ordinary risks of trade. An excellent case in point was the Society of Merchant Adventurers, charted by King Henry IV in London in 1407, who, despite the romantic-sounding name, were mainly in the business of buying up British woolens and selling them in the Flanders fairs. They were not a modern joint-stock company, but a rather old-fashioned Medieval merchant guild, but they provided a structure whereby older, more substantial merchants could simply provide loans to younger ones, and they managed to secure enough of an exclusive control over the woolen trade that substantial profits were pretty much guaranteed.[726] When such companies began to engage in armed ventures overseas, though, a new era of human history might be said to have begun.
<em>âEleven pesos, then; and as you canât pay me the eleven pesos, that makes another eleven pesosâtwenty-two in all: eleven for the serape and the petate and eleven because you canât pay. Is that right, Crisiero?â</em>
<em>Crisiero had no knowledge of figures, so it was very natural that he said, âThat is right, patrĂłn.â</em>
<em>Don Arnulfo was a decent, honorable man. Other landowners were a good deal less softhearted with their peons</em>.
<em>âThe shirt is five pesos. Right? Very well. And as you canât pay for it, thatâs five pesos. And as you remain in my debt for the five pesos, thatâs five pesos. And as I shall never have the money from you, thatâs five pesos. So that makes five and five and five and five. Thatâs twenty pesos. Agreed?â</em>
<em>âYes, patrĂłn, agreed.â</em>
<em>The peon can get the shirt nowhere else when he needs one. He can get credit nowhere but from his master, for whom he works and from whom he can never get away as long as he owes him a centavo</em>.
The epoch that began with what weâre used to calling the âAge of Explorationâ was marked by so many things that were genuinely newâthe rise of modern science, capitalism, humanism, the nation-stateâthat it may seem odd to frame it as just another turn of an historical cycle. Still, from the perspective Iâve been developing in this book, that is what it was.
The era begins around 1450 with a turn away from virtual currencies and credit economies and back to gold and silver. The subsequent flow of bullion from the Americas sped the process immensely, sparking a âprice revolutionâ in Western Europe that turned traditional society upside-down. Whatâs more, the return to bullion was accompanied by the return of a whole host of other conditions that, during the Middle Ages, had been largely suppressed or kept at bay: vast empires and professional armies, massive predatory warfare, untrammeled usury and debt peonage, but also materialist philosophies, a new burst of scientific and philosophical creativityâeven the return of chattel slavery. It was in no way a simple repeat performance. All the Axial Age pieces reappeared, but they came together in an entirely different way.
The 1400s are a peculiar period in European history. It was a century of endless catastrophe: large cities were regularly decimated by the Black Death; the commercial economy sagged and in some regions collapsed entirely; whole cities went bankrupt, defaulting on their bonds; the knightly classes squabbled over the remnants, leaving much of the countryside devastated by endemic warfare. Even in geopolitical terms Christendom was staggering, with the Ottoman Empire not only scooping up what remained of Byzantium but pushing steadily into central Europe, its forces expanding on land and sea.
At the same time, from the perspective of many ordinary farmers and urban laborers, times couldnât have been much better. One of the perverse effects of the bubonic plague, which killed off about one-third of the European workforce, was that wages increased dramatically. It didnât happen immediately, but this was largely because the first reaction of the authorities was to enact legislation freezing wages, or even attempting to tie free peasants back to the land again. Such efforts were met with powerful resistance, culminating in a series of popular uprisings across Europe. These were squelched, but the authorities were also forced to compromise. Before long, so much wealth was flowing into the hands of ordinary people that governments had to start introducing new laws forbidding the lowborn to wear silks and ermine, and to limit the number of feast days, which, in many towns and parishes, began eating up one-third or even half of the year. The fifteenth century is, in fact, considered the heyday of Medieval festive life, with its floats and dragons, maypoles and church ales, its Abbots of Unreason and Lords of Misrule.[727]
Over the next centuries, all this was to be destroyed. In England, the festive life was systematically attacked by Puritan reformers; then eventually by reformers everywhere, Catholic and Protestant alike. At the same time its economic basis in popular prosperity dissolved.
Why this happened has been a matter of intense historical debate for centuries. This much we know: it began with a massive inflation. Between 1500 and 1650, for instance, prices in England increased 500 percent, but wages rose much more slowly, so that in five generations, real wages fell to perhaps 40 percent of what they had been. The same thing happened everywhere in Europe.
Why? The favorite explanation, ever since a French lawyer named Jean Bodin first proposed it in 1568, was the vast influx of gold and silver that came pouring into Europe after the conquest of the New World. As the value of precious metals collapsed, the argument went, the price of everything else skyrocketed, and wages simply couldnât keep up.[728] There is some evidence to support this. The height of popular prosperity around 1450 did correspond to a period when bullionâand therefore, coinâwas in particularly short supply.[729] The lack of cash played havoc with international trade in particular; in the 1460s, we hear of ships full of wares forced to turn back from major ports, as no one had any cash on hand to buy from them. The problem only started to turn around later in the decade, with a sudden burst of silver mining in Saxony and the Tirol, followed by the opening of new sea routes to the Gold Coast of West Africa. Then came the conquests of CortĂ©s and Pizarro. Between 1520 and 1640, untold tons of gold and silver from Mexico and Peru were transported across the Atlantic and Pacific in Spanish treasure ships.
The problem with the conventional story is that very little of that gold and silver lingered very long in Europe. Most of the gold ended up in temples in India, and the overwhelming majority of the silver bullion was ultimately shipped off to China. The latter is crucial. If we really want to understand the origins of the modern world economy, the place to start is not in Europe at all. The real story is of how China abandoned the use of paper money. Itâs a story worth telling briefly, because very few people know it.
After the Mongols conquered China in 1271, they kept the system of paper money in place, and even made occasional (if usually disastrous) attempts to introduce it in the other parts of their empire. In 1368, however, they were overthrown by another of Chinaâs great popular insurrections, and a former peasant leader was once again installed in power.
During their century of rule, the Mongols had worked closely with foreign merchants, who became widely detested. Partly as a result, the former rebels, now the Ming dynasty, were suspicious of commerce in any form, and they promoted a romantic vision of self-sufficient agrarian communities. This had some unfortunate consequences. For one thing, it meant the maintenance of the old Mongol tax system, paid in labor and in kind; especially since that, in turn, was based on a quasi-caste system in which subjects were registered as farmers, craftsmen, or soldiers and forbidden to change their jobs. This proved extraordinarily unpopular. While government investment in agriculture, roads, and canals did set off a commercial boom, much of this commerce was technically illegal, and taxes on crops were so high that many indebted farmers began to flee their ancestral lands.[730]
Typically, such floating populations can be expected to seek just about anything but regular industrial employment; here as in Europe, most preferred a combination of odd jobs, peddling, entertainment, piracy, or banditry. In China, many also turned prospector. There was a minor silver rush, with illegal mines cropping up everywhere. Uncoined silver ingots, instead of official paper money and strings of bronze coins, soon became the real money of the off-the-books informal economy. When the government attempted to shut down illegal mines in the 1430s and 1440s, their efforts sparked local insurrections, in which miners would make common cause with displaced peasants, seize nearby cities, and sometimes threaten entire provinces.[731]
In the end, the government gave up even trying to suppress the informal economy. Instead, they swung the other way entirely: stopped issuing paper money, legalized the mines, allowed silver bullion to become the recognized currency for large transactions, and even gave private mints the authority to produce strings of cash.[732] This, in turn, allowed the government to gradually abandon the system of labor exactions and substitute a uniform tax system payable in silver.
Effectively, the Chinese government had gone back to its old policy of encouraging markets and merely intervening to prevent any undue concentrations of capital. It quickly proved spectacularly successful, and Chinese markets boomed. Indeed, many speak of the Ming as having accomplished something almost unique in world history: this was a time when the Chinese population was exploding, but living standards markedly improved.[733] The problem was that the new policy meant that the regime had to ensure an abundant supply of silver in the country, so as to keep its price low and minimize popular unrestâbut as it turned out, the Chinese mines were very quickly exhausted. In the 1530s, new silver mines were discovered in Japan, but these were exhausted in a decade or two as well. Before long, China had to turn to Europe and the New World.
Now, since Roman times, Europe had been exporting gold and silver to the East: the problem was that Europe had never produced much of anything that Asians wanted to buy, so it was forced to pay in specie for silks, spices, steel, and other imports. The early years of European expansion were largely attempts to gain access either to Eastern luxuries or to new sources of gold and silver with which to pay for them. In those early days, Atlantic Europe really had only one substantial advantage over its Muslim rivals: an active and advanced tradition of naval warfare, honed by centuries of conflict in the Mediterranean. The moment when Vasco da Gama entered the Indian Ocean in 1498, the principle that the seas should be a zone of peaceful trade came to an immediate end. Portuguese flotillas began bombarding and sacking every port city they came across, then seizing control of strategic points and extorting protection money from unarmed Indian Ocean merchants for the right to carry on their business unmolested.
At almost exactly the same time, Christopher Columbusâa Genoese mapmaker seeking a short-cut to Chinaâtouched land in the New World, and the Spanish and Portuguese empires stumbled into the greatest economic windfall in human history: entire continents full of unfathomable wealth, whose inhabitants, armed only with Stone Age weapons, began conveniently dying almost as soon as they arrived. The conquest of Mexico and Peru led to the discovery of enormous new sources of precious metal, and these were exploited ruthlessly and systematically, even to the point of largely exterminating the surrounding populations to extract as much precious metal as quickly as possible. As Kenneth Pomeranz has recently pointed out, none of this would have been possible were it not for the practically unlimited Asian demand for precious metals.
Had China in particular not had such a dynamic economy that changing its metallic base could absorb the staggering quantities of silver mined in the New World over three centuries, those mines might have become unprofitable within a few decades. The massive inflation of silver-denominated prices in Europe from 1500 to 1640 indicates a shrinking value for the metal there even with Asia draining off much of the supply.[734]
By 1540, a silver glut caused a collapse in prices across Europe; the American mines would, at this point, simply have stopped functioning, and the entire project of American colonization foundered, had it not been for the demand from China.[735] Treasure galleons moving toward Europe soon refrained from unloading their cargoes, instead rounding the horn of Africa and proceeding across the Indian Ocean toward Canton. After 1571, with the foundation of the Spanish city of Manila, they began to move directly across the Pacific. By the late sixteenth century, China was importing almost fifty tons of silver a year, about 90 percent of its silver, and by the early seventeenth century, 116 tons, or over 97 percent.[736] Huge amounts of silk, porcelain, and other Chinese products had to be exported to pay for it. Many of these Chinese products, in turn, ended up in the new cities of Central and South America. This Asian trade became the single most significant factor in the emerging global economy, and those who ultimately controlled the financial leversâparticularly Italian, Dutch, and German merchant bankersâbecame fantastically rich.
But how exactly did the new global economy cause the collapse of living standards in Europe? One thing we do know: it clearly was **not** by making large amounts of precious metal available for everyday transactions. If anything, the effect was the opposite. While European mints were stamping out enormous numbers of rials, thalers, ducats, and doubloons, which became the new medium of trade from Nicaragua to Bengal, almost none found their way into the pockets of ordinary Europeans. Instead, we hear constant complaints about the shortage of currency. In England:
For much of the Tudor period the circulating medium was so small that the taxable population simply did not have sufficient coin in which to pay the benevolences, subsidies, and tenths levied upon them, and time and time again household plate, the handiest near money that most people possessed, had to be surrendered.[737]
This was the case in most of Europe. Despite the massive influx of metal from the Americas, most families were so low on cash that they were regularly reduced to melting down the family silver to pay their taxes.
This was because taxes **had** to be paid in metal. Everyday business in contrast continued to be transacted much as it had in the Middle Ages, by means of various forms of virtual credit money: tallies, promissory notes, or, within smaller communities, simply by keeping track of who owed what to whom. What really caused the inflation is that those who ended up in control of the bullionâgovernments, bankers, large-scale merchantsâwere able to use that control to begin changing the rules, first by insisting that gold and silver **were** money, and second by introducing new forms of credit-money for their own use while slowly undermining and destroying the local systems of trust that had allowed small-scale communities across Europe to operate largely without the use of metal currency.
This was a political battle, even if it was also a conceptual argument about the nature of money. The new regime of bullion money could only be imposed through almost unparalleled violenceânot only overseas, but at home as well. In much of Europe, the first reaction to the âprice revolutionâ and accompanying enclosures of common lands was not very different from what had so recently happened in China: thousands of one-time peasants fleeing or being forced out of their villages to become vagabonds or âmasterless men,â a process that culminated in popular insurrections. The reaction of European governments, however, was entirely different. The rebellions were crushed, and this time, no subsequent concessions were forthcoming. Vagabonds were rounded up, exported to the colonies as indentured laborers, and drafted into colonial armies and naviesâor, eventually, set to work in factories at home.
Almost all of this was carried out through a manipulation of debt. As a result, the very nature of debt, too, became once again one of the principal bones of contention.
No doubt scholars will never stop arguing about the reasons for the great âprice revolutionââlargely because itâs not clear what kind of tools can be applied. Can we really use the methods of modern economics, which were designed to understand how contemporary economic institutions operate, to describe the political battles that led to the creation of those very institutions?
This is not just a conceptual problem. There are moral dangers here. To take what might seem an âobjective,â macro-economic approach to the origins of the world economy would be to treat the behavior of early European explorers, merchants, and conquerors as if they were simply rational responses to opportunitiesâas if this were just what anyone would have done in the same situation. This is what the use of equations so often does: make it seem perfectly natural to assume that, if the price of silver in China is twice what it is in Seville, and inhabitants of Seville are capable of getting their hands on large quantities of silver and transporting it to China, then clearly they will, even if doing so requires the destruction of entire civilizations. Or if there is a demand for sugar in England, and enslaving millions is the easiest way to acquire labor to produce it, then it is inevitable that some will enslave them. In fact, history makes it quite clear that this is not the case. Any number of civilizations have probably been in a position to wreak havoc on the scale that the European powers did in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries (Ming China itself was an obvious candidate), but almost none actually did so.[738]
Consider, for instance, how the gold and silver from the American mines were extracted. Mining operations began almost immediately upon the fall of the Aztec capital of TenochtitlĂĄn in 1521. While we are used to assuming that the Mexican population was devastated simply as an effect of newly introduced European diseases, contemporary observers felt that the dragooning of the newly conquered natives to work in the mines was at least equally responsible.[739] In **The Conquest of America**, Tzvetan Todorov offers a compendium of some of the most chilling reports, mostly from Spanish priests and friars who, even when committed in principle to the belief that the extermination of the Indians was the judgment of God, could not disguise their horror at scenes of Spanish soldiers testing the blades of their weapons by eviscerating random passers-by, and tearing babies off their motherâs backs to be eaten by dogs. Such acts might perhaps be written off as what one would expect when a collection of heavily armed menâmany of violent criminal backgroundâare given absolute impunity; but the reports from the mines imply something far more systematic. When Fray Toribio de Motolinia wrote of the ten plagues that he believed God had visited on the inhabitants of Mexico, he listed smallpox, war, famine, labor exactions, taxes (which caused many to sell their children to moneylenders, others to be tortured to death in cruel prisons), and the thousands who died in the building of the capital city. Above all, he insisted, were the uncountable numbers who died in the mines:
The eighth plague was the slaves whom the Spaniards made in order to put them to work in the mines. At first those who were already slaves of the Aztecs were taken; then those who had given evidence of insubordination; finally all those who could be caught. During the first years after the conquest, the slave traffic flourished, and slaves often changed master. They produced so many marks on their faces, in addition to the royal brand, that they had their faces covered with letters, for they bore the marks of all who had bought and sold them.
The ninth plague was the service in the mines, to which the heavily laden Indians traveled sixty leagues or more to carry provisions ⊠When their food gave out they died, either at the mines or on the road, for they had no money to buy food and there was no one to give it to them. Some reached home in such a state that they died soon after. The bodies of those Indians and of the slaves who died in the mines produced such a stench that it caused a pestilence, especially at the mines of Oaxaca. For half a league around these mines and along a great part of the road one could scarcely avoid walking over dead bodies or bones, and the flocks of birds and crows that came to fatten themselves upon the corpses were so numerous that they darkened the sun.â[740]
Similar scenes were reported in Peru, where whole regions were depopulated by forced service in the mines, and Hispaniola, where the indigenous population was eradicated entirely.[741]
When dealing with conquistadors, we are speaking not just of simple greed, but greed raised to mythic proportions. This is, after all, what they are best remembered for. They never seemed to get enough. Even after the conquest of TenochtitlĂĄn or Cuzco, and the acquisition of hitherto-unimaginable riches, the conquerors almost invariably regrouped and started off in search of more treasure.
Moralists throughout the ages have inveighed against the endlessness of human greed, just as they have against our supposedly endless lust for power. What history actually reveals, though, is that while humans may be justly accused of having a proclivity to accuse **others** of acting like conquistadors, few really act this way themselves. Even for the most ambitious of us, our dreams are more like Sindbadâs: to have adventures, to acquire the means to settle down and live an enjoyable life, and then, to enjoy it. Max Weber of course argued that the essence of capitalism is the urgeâwhich he thought first appeared in Calvinismânever to settle down, but to engage in endless expansion. But the conquistadors were good Medieval Catholics, even if ones usually drawn from the most ruthless and unprincipled elements of Spanish society. Why the unrelenting drive for more and more and more?
It might help, I think, to go back to the very onset of HernĂĄn CortĂ©sâs conquest of Mexico: What were his immediate motives? CortĂ©s had migrated to the colony of Hispaniola in 1504, dreaming of glory and adventure, but for the first decade and a half, his adventures had largely consisted of seducing other peopleâs wives. In 1518, however, he managed to finagle his way into being named commander of an expedition to establish a Spanish presence on the mainland. As Bernal DĂaz del Castillo, who accompanied him, later wrote, around this time
He began to adorn himself and be more careful of his appearance than before. He wore a plume of feathers, with a medallion and a gold chain, and a velvet cloak trimmed with loops of gold. In fact he looked like a bold and gallant Captain. However, he had no money to defray the expenses I have spoken about, for at the time he was very poor and much in debt, despite the fact that he had a good estate of Indians and was getting gold from the mines. But all this he spent on his person, on finery for his wife, whom he had recently married, and on entertaining guests âŠ
When some merchant friends of his heard that he had obtained his command as Captain General, they lent him four thousand gold pesos in coin and another four thousand in goods secured on his Indians and estates. He then ordered two standards and banners to be made, worked in gold with the royal arms and a cross on each side with a legend which said, âComrades, let us follow the sign of the Holy Cross with true faith, and through it we shall conquer.â[742]
In other words, heâd been living beyond his means, got himself in trouble, and decided, like a reckless gambler, to double down and go for broke. Unsurprising, then, that when the governor at the last minute decided to cancel the expedition, CortĂ©s ignored him and sailed for the mainland with six hundred men, offering each an equal share in the expeditionâs profits. On landing he burned his boats, effectively staking everything on victory.
Let us skip, then, from the beginning of DĂazâs book to its final chapter. Three years later, through some of the most ingenious, ruthless, brilliant, and utterly dishonorable behavior by a military leader ever recorded, CortĂ©s had his victory. After eight months of grueling house-to-house warfare and the death of perhaps a hundred thousand Aztecs, TenochtitlĂĄn, one of the greatest cities of the world, lay entirely destroyed. The imperial treasury was secured, and the time had come, then, for it to be divided in shares amongst the surviving soldiers.
Yet according to DĂaz, the result among the men was outrage. The officers connived to sequester most of the gold, and when the final tally was announced, the troops learned that they would be receiving only fifty to eighty pesos each. Whatâs more, the better part of their shares was immediately seized again by the officers in their capacity of creditorsâsince CortĂ©s had insisted that the men be billed for any replacement equipment and medical care they had received during the siege. Most found they had actually lost money on the deal. DĂaz writes:
We were all very deeply in debt. A crossbow was not to be purchased for less than forty or fifty pesos, a musket cost one hundred, a sword fifty, and a horse from 800 to 1000 pesos, and above. Thus extravagantly did we have to pay for everything! A surgeon, who called himself Mastre Juan, who had tended some very bad wounds, charged wildly inflated fees, and so did a quack named Murcia, who was an apothecary and a barber and also treated wounds, and there were thirty other tricks and swindles for which payment was demanded of our shares as soon as we received them.
Serious complaints were made about this, and the only remedy that CortĂ©s provided was to appoint two trustworthy persons who knew the prices of goods and could value anything that we had bought on credit. An order went out that whatever price was placed on our purchases or the surgeonâs cures must be accepted, but that if we had no money, our creditors must wait two years for payment.[743]
Spanish merchants soon arrived charging wildly inflated prices for basic necessities, causing further outrage, until:
Our general becoming weary of the continual reproaches which were thrown out against him, saying he had stolen everything for himself, and the endless petitions for loans and advance in pay, determined at once to get rid of the most troublesome fellows, by forming settlements in those provinces which appeared most eligible for this purpose.[744]
These were the men who ended up in control of the provinces, and who established local administration, taxes, and labor regimes. Which makes it a little easier to understand the descriptions of Indians with their faces covered by names like so many counter-endorsed checks, or the mines surrounded by miles of rotting corpses. We are not dealing with a psychology of cold, calculating greed, but of a much more complicated mix of shame and righteous indignation, and of the frantic urgency of debts that would only compound and accumulate (these were, almost certainly, interest-bearing loans), and outrage at the idea that, after all they had gone through, they should be held to owe anything to begin with.
And what of CortĂ©s? He had just pulled off perhaps the greatest act of theft in world history. Certainly, his original debts had now been rendered inconsequential. Yet he somehow always seemed to find himself in new ones. Creditors were already starting to repossess his holdings while he was off on an expedition to Honduras in 1526; on his return, he wrote the Emperor Charles V that his expenses were such that âall I have received has been insufficient to relive me from misery and poverty, being at the moment I write in debt for upwards of five hundred ounces of gold, without possessing a single peso towards it.â[745] Disingenuous, no doubt (CortĂ©s at the time owned his own personal palace), but only a few years later, he was reduced to pawning his wifeâs jewelry to help finance a series of expeditions to California, hoping to restore his fortunes. When those failed to turn a profit, he ended up so besieged by creditors that he had to return to Spain to petition the emperor in person.[746]
If all this seems suspiciously reminiscent of the fourth Crusade, with its indebted knights stripping whole foreign cities of their wealth and still somehow winding up only one step ahead of their creditors, there is a reason. The financial capital that backed these expeditions came from more or less the same place (if in this case Genoa, not Venice). Whatâs more, that relationship, between the daring adventurer on the one hand, the gambler willing to take any sort of risk, and on the other, the careful financier, whose entire operations are organized around producing steady, mathematical, inexorable growth of income, lies at the very heart of what we now call âcapitalism.â
As a result, our current economic system has always been marked by a peculiar dual character. Scholars have long been fascinated by Spanish debates that ensued, in Spanish universities like Santander, about the humanity of the Indians (Did they have souls? Could they have legal rights? Was it legitimate to forcibly enslave them?), just as they have argued about the real attitudes of the conquistadors (was it contempt, revulsion, or even grudging admiration for their adversaries?)[747] The real point is that at the key moments of decision, none of this mattered. Those making the decisions did not feel they were in control anyway; those who were did not particularly care to know the details. To take a telling example: after the earliest years of the gold and silver mines described by Motolinia, where millions of Indians were simply rounded up and marched off to their deaths, colonists settled on a policy of debt peonage: the usual trick of demanding heavy taxes, lending money at interest to those who could not pay, and then demanding that the loans be repaid with work. Royal agents regularly attempted to forbid such practices, arguing that the Indians were now Christian and that this violated their rights as loyal subjects of the Spanish crown. But as with almost all such royal efforts to act as protector of the Indians, the result was the same. Financial exigencies ended up taking precedence. Charles V himself was deeply in debt to banking firms in Florence, Genoa, and Naples, and gold and silver from the Americas made up perhaps one-fifth of his total revenue. In the end, despite a lot of initial noise and the (usually quite sincere) moral outrage on the part of the kingâs emissaries, such decrees were either ignored or, at best, enforced for a year or two before being allowed to slip into abeyance.[748]
All of this helps explain why the Church had been so uncompromising in its attitude toward usury. It was not just a philosophical question; it was a matter of moral rivalry. Money always has the potential to become a moral imperative unto itself. Allow it to expand, and it can quickly become a morality so imperative that all others seem frivolous in comparison. For the debtor, the world is reduced to a collection of potential dangers, potential tools, and potential merchandise.[749] Even human relations become a matter of cost-benefit calculation. Clearly this is the way the conquistadors viewed the worlds that they set out to conquer.
It is the peculiar feature of modern capitalism to create social arrangements that essentially force us to think this way. The structure of the corporation is a telling case in pointâand it is no coincidence that the first major joint-stock corporations in the world were the English and Dutch East India companies, ones that pursued that very same combination of exploration, conquest, and extraction as did the conquistadors. It is a structure designed to eliminate all moral imperatives but profit. The executives who make decisions can argueâand regularly doâthat, if it were their own money, of course they would not fire lifelong employees a week before retirement, or dump carcinogenic waste next to schools. Yet they are morally bound to ignore such considerations, because they are mere employees whose only responsibility is to provide the maximum return on investment for the companyâs stockholders. (The stockholders, of course, are not given any say.)
The figure of CortĂ©s is instructive for another reason. We are speaking of a man who, in 1521, had conquered a kingdom and was sitting atop a vast pile of gold. Neither did he have any intention of giving it awayâeven to his followers. Five years later, he was claiming to be a penniless debtor. How was this possible?
The obvious answer would be: CortĂ©s was not a king, he was a subject of the King of Spain, living within the legal structure of a kingdom that insisted that, if he were not good at managing his money, he would lose it. Yet as weâve seen, the kingâs laws could be ignored in other cases. Whatâs more, even kings were not entirely free agents. Charles V was continually in debt, and when his son Philip IIâhis armies fighting on three different fronts at onceâattempted the old Medieval trick of defaulting, all his creditors, from the Genoese Bank of St. George to the German Fuggers and Welsers, closed ranks to insist that he would receive no further loans until he started honoring his commitments.[750]
Capital, then, is not simply money. It is not even just wealth that can be turned into money. But neither is it just the use of political power to help one use oneâs money to make more money. CortĂ©s was trying to do exactly that: in classical Axial Age fashion, he was attempting to use his conquests to acquire plunder, and slaves to work the mines, with which he could pay his soldiers and suppliers cash to embark on even further conquests. It was a tried-and-true formula. But for all the other conquistadors, it provided a spectacular failure.
This would seem to mark the difference. In the Axial Age, money was a tool of empire. It might have been convenient for rulers to promulgate markets in which everyone would treat money as an end in itself; at times, rulers might have even come to see the whole apparatus of government as a profit-making enterprise; but money always remained a political instrument. This is why when the empires collapsed and armies were demobilized, the whole apparatus could simply melt away. Under the newly emerging capitalist order, the logic of money was granted autonomy; political and military power were then gradually reorganized around it. True, this was a financial logic that could never have existed without states and armies behind it in the first place. As we have seen in the case of Medieval Islam, under genuine free-market conditionsâin which the state is not involved in regulating the market in any significant way, even in enforcing commercial contractsâpurely competitive markets will not develop, and loans at interest will become effectively impossible to collect. It was **only** the Islamic prohibition against usury, really, that made it possible for them to create an economic system that stood so far apart from the state.
Martin Luther was making this very point in 1524, right around the time that Cortés was first beginning to have trouble with his creditors. It is all very well, Luther said, for us to imagine that all might live as true Christians, in accordance with the dictates of the Gospel. But in fact there are few who are really capable of acting this way:
Christians are rare in this world; therefore the world needs a strict, hard, temporal government that will compel and constrain the wicked not to rob and to return what they borrow, even though a Christian ought not to demand it, or even hope to get it back. This is necessary in order that the world not become a desert, peace may not perish, and trade and society not be utterly destroyed; all of which would happen if we were to rule the world according to the Gospel and not drive and compel the wicked, by laws and the use of force, to do what is right ⊠Let no one think that the world can be ruled without blood; the sword of the ruler must be red and bloody; for the world will and must be evil, and the sword is Godâs rod and vengeance upon it.[751]
âNot to rob and to return what they borrowââa telling juxtaposition, considering that in Scholastic theory, lending money at interest had itself been considered theft.
And Luther **was** referring to interest-bearing loans here. The story of how he got to this point is telling. Luther began his career as a reformer in 1520 with fiery campaigns against usury; in fact, one of his objections to the sale of Church indulgences was that it was itself a form of spiritual usury. These positions won him enormous popular support in towns and villages. However, he soon realized that heâd unleashed a genie that threatened to turn the whole world upside-down. More radical reformers appeared, arguing that the poor were not morally obliged to repay the interest on usurious loans, and proposing the revival of Old Testament institutions like the sabbatical year. They were followed by outright revolutionary preachers who began once again questioning the very legitimacy of aristocratic privilege and private property. In 1525, the year after Lutherâs sermon, there was a massive uprising of peasants, miners, and poor townsfolk across Germany: the rebels, in most cases, representing themselves as simple Christians aiming to restore the true communism of the Gospels. Over a hundred thousand were slaughtered. Already in 1524, Luther had a sense that matters were spilling out of control and that he would have to choose sides: in that text, he did so. Old Testament laws like the Sabbatical year, he argued, are no longer binding; the Gospel merely describes ideal behavior; humans are sinful creatures, so law is necessary; while usury is a sin, a four to five-percent rate of interest is currently legal under certain circumstances; and while collecting that interest is sinful, under **no** circumstances is it legitimate to argue that for that reason, borrowers have the right to break the law.[752]
The Swiss Protestant reformer Zwingli was even more explicit. God, he argued, gave us the divine law: to love thy neighbor as thyself. If we truly kept this law, humans would give freely to one another, and private property would not exist. However, Jesus excepted, no human being has ever been able to live up to this pure communistic standard. Therefore, God has also given us a second, inferior, human law, to be enforced by the civil authorities. While this inferior law cannot compel us to act as we really ought to act (âthe magistrate can force no one to lend out what belongs to him without hope of recompense or profitâ)âat least it can make us follow the lead of the apostle Paul, who said: âPay all men what you owe.â[753]
Soon afterward, Calvin was to reject the blanket ban on usury entirely, and by 1650, almost all Protestant denominations had come to agree with his position that a reasonable rate of interest (usually five percent) was not sinful, provided the lenders act in good conscience, do not make lending their exclusive business, and do not exploit the poor.[754] (Catholic doctrine was slower to come around, but it did ultimately accede by passive acquiescence.)
If one looks at how all this was justified, two things jump out. First, Protestant thinkers all continued to make the old Medieval argument about **interesse:** that âinterestâ is really compensation for the money that the lender **would** have made had he been able to place his money in some more profitable investment. Originally, this logic was just applied to commercial loans. Increasingly, it was now applied to all loans. Far from being unnatural, then, the growth of money was now treated as completely expected. All money was assumed to be capital.[755] Second, the assumption that usury is something that one properly practices on oneâs enemies, and therefore, by extension, that all commerce partakes something of the nature of war, never entirely disappears. Calvin, for instance, denied that Deuteronomy only referred to the Amalekites; clearly, he said, it meant that usury was acceptable when dealing with Syrians or Egyptians; indeed with all nations with whom the Jews traded.[756] The result of opening the gates was, at least tacitly, to suggest that one could now treat **anyone**, even a neighbor, as a foreigner.[757] One need only observe how European merchant adventurers of the day actually were treating foreigners, in Asia, Africa, and the Americas, to understand what this might mean in practice.
Or, one might look closer to home. Take the story of another well-known debtor of the time, the Margrave Casimir of Brandenburg-Ansbach (1481â1527), of the famous Hohenzollern dynasty:
Casimir was the son of Margrave Friedrich the Elder of Brandenburg, who has come to be known as one of the âmad princesâ of the German Renaissance. Sources differ on just how mad he actually was. One contemporary chronicle describes him as âsomewhat deranged in his head from too much racing and jousting;â most agree that he was given to fits of inexplicable rage, as well as to the sponsorship of wild, extravagant festivals, said often to have degenerated into wild bacchanalian orgies.[758]
All agree, however, that he was poor at managing his money. At the beginning of 1515, Friedrich was in such financial troubleâhe is said to have owed 200,000 guildersâthat he alerted his creditors, mostly fellow nobles, that he might soon be forced to temporarily suspend interest payments on his debts. This seems to have caused a crisis of faith, and within a matter of weeks, his son Casimir staged a palace coupâmoving, in the early hours of February 26, 1515, to seize control of the castle of Plassenburg while his father was distracted with the celebration of Carnival, then forcing him to sign papers abdicating for reason of mental infirmity. Friedrich spent the rest of his life confined in Plassenburg, denied all visitors and correspondence. When at one point his guards requested that the new Margrave provide a couple guilders so he could pass the time gambling with them, Casimir made a great public show of refusal, stating (ridiculously, of course) that his father had left his affairs in such disastrous shape that he could not possibly afford to.[759]
Casimir dutifully doled out governorships and other prize offices to his fatherâs creditors. He tried to get his house in order, but this proved surprisingly difficult. His enthusiastic embrace of Lutherâs reforms in 1521 clearly had as much to do with the prospect of getting his hands on Church lands and monastic assets than with any particular religious fervor. Yet at first, the disposition of Church property remained moot, and Casimir himself compounded his problems by running up gambling debts of his own said to have amounted to nearly 50,000 guilders.[760]
Placing his creditors in charge of the civil administration had predictable effects: increasing exactions on his subjects, many of whom became hopelessly indebted themselves. Unsurprisingly, Casimirâs lands in the Tauber Valley in Franconia became one of the epicenters of the revolt of 1525. Bands of armed villagers assembled, declaring they would obey no law that did not accord with âthe holy word of God.â At first, the nobles, isolated in their scattered castles, offered little resistance. The rebel leadersâmany of them local shopkeepers, butchers, and other prominent men from nearby townsâbegan with a largely orderly campaign of tearing down castle fortifications, their knightly occupants being offered guarantees of safety if they cooperated, agreed to abandon their feudal privileges, and swore oaths to abide by the rebelsâ Twelve Articles. Many complied. The real venom of the rebels was reserved for cathedrals and monasteries, dozens of which were sacked, pillaged, and destroyed.
Casimirâs reaction was to hedge his bets. At first he bided his time, assembling an armed force of about two thousand experienced soldiers, but refusing to intervene as rebels pillaged several nearby monasteries; in fact, negotiating with the various rebel bands in such apparent good faith that many believed he was preparing to join them âas a Christian brother.â[761] In May, however, after the knights of the Swabian League defeated the rebels of the Christian Union to the south, Casimir swung into action, his forces brushing aside poorly disciplined rebel bands to sweep through his own territories like a conquering army, burning and pillaging villages and towns, slaughtering women and children. In every town he set up punitive tribunals, and seized all looted property, which he kept, even as his men also expropriated any wealth still to be found in the regionâs cathedrals, ostensibly as emergency loans to pay his troops.
It seems significant that Casimir was, of all the German princes, both the longest to waver before intervening, and the most savagely vengeful once he did. His forces became notorious not only for executing accused rebels, but systematically chopping off the fingers of accused collaborators, his executioner keeping a grim ledger of amputated body parts for later reimbursementâa kind of carnal inversion of the account ledgers that had caused him so much trouble in his life. At one point, in the town of Kitzingen, Casimir ordered the gouging out of the eyes of fifty-eight burghers who had, he declared, ârefused to look at him as their lord.â Afterward he received the following bill:[762]
80 beheaded | |
69 eyes put out or fingers cut off | 114œ fl. |
from this to deduct | |
Received from the Rothenburgers | 10 fl. |
Received from Ludwig von Hutten | 2 fl. |
Remainder | |
Plus 2 monthsâ pay at 8 fl. per month | 16 fl. |
Total | 118œ fl. |
[Signed] Augustin, the executioner, who the Kitzingers call âMaster Ouch.â
The repression eventually inspired Casimirâs brother Georg (later known as âthe Piousâ) to write a letter asking him if Casimir was intending to take up a tradeâsince, as Georg gently reminded him, he could not very well continue to be a feudal overlord if his peasants were all dead.[763]
With such things happening, it is hardly surprising that men like Thomas Hobbes came to imagine the basic nature of society as a war of all against all, from which only the absolute power of monarchs could save us. At the same time, Casimirâs behaviorâcombining as it does a general attitude of unprincipled, cold-blooded calculation with outbursts of almost inexplicably vindictive crueltyâseems, like that of CortĂ©sâs angry foot soldiers when unleashed on the Aztec provinces, to embody something essential about the psychology of debt. Or, more precisely, perhaps, about the debtor who feels he has done nothing to deserve being placed in his position: the frantic urgency of having to convert everything around oneself into money, and rage and indignation at having been reduced to the sort of person who would do so.
<em>Of all the beings that have existence only in the minds of men, nothing is more fantastical and nice than Credit; it is never to be forced; it hangs upon opinion; it depends upon our passions of hope and fear; it comes many times unsought-for, and often goes away without reason; and once lost, it is hardly to be quite recovered</em>.
<em>He that has lost his credit is dead to the world</em>.
The peasantsâ visions of communistic brotherhood did not come out of nowhere. They were rooted in real daily experience: of the maintenance of common fields and forests, of everyday cooperation and neighborly solidarity. It is out of such homely experience of everyday communism that grand mythic visions are always built.[764] Obviously, rural communities were also divided, squabbling places, since communities always areâbut insofar as they are communities at all, they are necessarily founded on a ground of mutual aid. The same, incidentally, can be said of members of the aristocracy, who might have fought endlessly over love, land, honor, and religion, but nonetheless still cooperated remarkably well with one another when it really mattered (most of all, when their position as aristocrats was threatened); just as the merchants and bankers, much as they competed with one another, managed to close ranks when it really mattered. This is what I refer to as the âcommunism of the rich,â and it is a powerful force in human history.[765]
The same, as weâve seen repeatedly, applies to credit. There are always different standards for those one considers friends or neighbors. The inexorable nature of interest-bearing debt, and the alternately savage and calculating behavior of those enslaved to it, are typical above all of dealings between strangers: itâs unlikely that Casimir felt much more kinship with his peasants than CortĂ©s did with the Aztecs (in fact, most likely less, since Aztec warriors were at least aristocrats). Inside the small towns and rural hamlets, where the state was mostly far away, Medieval standards survived intact, and âcreditâ was just as much a matter of honor and reputation as it had ever been. The great untold story of our current age is of how these ancient credit systems were ultimately destroyed.
Recent historical research, notably that of Craig Muldrew, who has sifted through thousands of inventories and court cases from sixteenth- and seventeenth-century England, has caused us to revise almost all our old assumptions about what everyday economic life at that time was like. Of course, very little of the American gold and silver that reached Europe actually ended up in the pockets of ordinary farmers, mercers, or haberdashers.[766] The lionâs share stayed in the coffers of either the aristocracy or the great London merchants, or else in the royal treasury.[767] Small change was almost nonexistent. As Iâve already pointed out, in the poorer neighborhoods of cities or large towns, shopkeepers would issue their own lead, leather, or wooden token money; in the sixteenth century this became something of a fad, with artisans and even poor widows producing their own currency as a way to make ends meet.[768] Elsewhere, those frequenting the local butcher, baker, or shoemaker would simply put things on the tab. The same was true of those attending weekly markets, or selling neighbors milk or cheese or candle-wax. In a typical village, the only people likely to pay cash were passing travelers, and those considered riff-raff: paupers and neâer-do-wells so notoriously down on their luck that no one would extend credit to them. Since everyone was involved in selling something, however just about everyone was both creditor and debtor; most family income took the form of promises from other families; everyone knew and kept count of what their neighbors owed one another; and every six months or year or so, communities would held a general public âreckoning,â cancelling debts out against each other in a great circle, with only those differences then remaining when all was done being settled by use of coin or goods.[769]
The reason that this upends our assumptions is that weâre used to blaming the rise of capitalism on something vaguely called âthe marketââthe breakup of older systems of mutual aid and solidarity, and the creation of a world of cold calculation, where everything had its price. Really, English villagers appear to have seen no contradiction between the two. On the one hand, they believed strongly in the collective stewardship of fields, streams, and forests, and the need to help neighbors in difficulty. On the other hand, markets were seen as a kind of attenuated version of the same principle, since they were entirely founded on trust. Much like the Tiv women with their gifts of yams and okra, neighbors assumed they ought to be constantly slightly in debt to one another. At the same time, most seem to have been quite comfortable with the idea of buying and selling, or even with market fluctuations, provided it didnât get to the point of threatening honest familiesâ livelihoods.[770] Even when loans at interest began to be legalized in 1545, that did not ruffle too many feathers, as long as it took place within that same larger moral framework: lending was considered an appropriate vocation, for example, for widows with no other source of income, or as a way for neighbors to share in the profits from some minor commercial venture. William Stout, a Quaker merchant from Lancashire, spoke glowingly of Henry Coward, the tradesman in whose shop he first apprenticed:
My master then had a full trade of groceries, ironmongerware, and several other goods, and very much respected and trusted, not only by the people of his own religious profession, but by all others of all professions and circumstances ⊠His credit was so much, that any who had money to dispose of lodged it with him to put out to interest or to make use of it.[771]
In this world, trust was everything. Most money literally was trust, since most credit arrangements were handshake deals. When people used the word âcredit,â they referred above all to a reputation for honesty and integrity; and a man or womanâs honor, virtue, and respectability, but also, reputation for generosity, decency, and good-natured sociability, were at least as important considerations when deciding whether to make a loan as were assessments of net income.[772] As a result, financial terms became indistinguishable from moral ones. One could speak of others as âworthies,â as âa woman of high estimationâ or âa man of no account,â and equally of âgiving creditâ to someoneâs words when one believes what they say (âcreditâ is from the same root as âcreedâ or âcredibilityâ), or of âextending creditâ to them, when one takes them at their word that they will pay one back.
One should not idealize the situation. This was a highly patriarchal world: a manâs wife or daughterâs reputation for chastity was as much a part of his âcreditâ as his own reputation for kindness or piety. Whatâs more, almost all people below the age of 30, male or female, were employed as servants in someone elseâs householdâas farmhands, milkmaids, apprenticesâand as such, were of âno accountâ at all.[773] Finally, those who lost credibility in the eyes of the community became, effectively, pariahs, and descended into the criminal or semi-criminal classes of rootless laborers, beggars, harlots, cutpurses, hawkers, pedlars, fortune-tellers, minstrels, and other such âmasterless menâ or âwomen of ill repute.â[774]
Cold cash was employed largely between strangers, or when paying rents, tithes, and taxes to landlords, bailiffs, priests, and other superiors. The landed gentry and wealthy merchants, who eschewed handshake deals, would often use cash with one another, especially to pay off bills of exchange drawn on London markets.[775] Above all, gold and silver were used by the government to purchase arms and pay soldiers, and amongst the criminal classes themselves. This meant that coins were most likely to be used both by the sort of people who ran the legal systemâthe magistrates, constables, and justices of the peaceâand by those violent elements of society they saw it as their business to control.
Over time, this led to an increasing disjuncture of moral universes. For most, who tried to avoid entanglement in the legal system just as much as they tried to avoid the affairs of soldiers and criminals, debt remained the very fabric of sociability. But those who spent their working lives within the halls of government and great commercial houses gradually began to develop a very different perspective, whereby cash exchange was normal and it was debt that came to be seen as tinged with criminality.
Each perspective turned on a certain tacit theory of the nature of society. For most English villagers, the real font and focus of social and moral life was not so much the church as the local ale-houseâand community was embodied above all in the conviviality of popular festivals like Christmas or May Day, with everything that such celebrations entailed: the sharing of pleasures, the communion of the senses, all the physical embodiment of what was called âgood neighborhood.â Society was rooted above in the âlove and amityâ of friends and kin, and it found expression in all those forms of everyday communism (helping neighbors with chores, providing milk or cheese for old widows) that were seen to flow from it. Markets were not seen as contradicting this ethos of mutual aid. It was, much as it was for Tusi, an extension of mutual aidâand for much the same reason: because it operated entirely through trust and credit.[776]
England might not have produced a great theorist like Tusi, but one can find the same assumptions echoed in most of the Scholastic writers, as for instance in Jean Bodinâs **De Republica**, widely circulated in English translation after 1605. âAmity and friendship,â Bodin wrote, âare the foundation of all human and civil societyââthey constitute that âtrue, natural justiceâ on which the whole legal structure of contracts, courts, and even government must necessarily be built.[777] Similarly, when economic thinkers reflected on the origins of the money, they spoke of âtrusting, exchanging, and trading.â[778] It was simply assumed that human relations came first.
As a result, all moral relations came to be conceived as debts. âForgive us our debtsââthis was the period, the very end of the Middle Ages, that this translation of the Lordâs Prayer gained such universal popularity. Sins are debts to God: unavoidable, but perhaps manageable, since at the end of time our moral debts and credits will be all canceled out against each other in Godâs final Reckoning. The notion of debt inserted itself into even the most intimate of human relations. Like the Tiv, Medieval villagers would sometimes refer to âflesh debts,â but the notion was completely different: it referred to the right of either partner in a marriage to demand sex from the other, which in principle either could do whenever he or she desired. The phrase âpaying oneâs debtsâ thus developed connotations, much as the Roman phrase âdoing oneâs dutyâ had, centuries before. Geoffrey Chaucer even makes a pun out of âtallyâ (French: **taille**) and âtailâ in the Shipmanâs Tale, a story about a woman who pays her husbandâs debts with sexual favors: âand if so I be faille, I am youre wyf, score it upon my taille.â[779]
Even London merchants would occasionally appeal to the language of sociability, insisting that in the final analysis, all trade is built on credit, and credit is really just an extension of mutual aid. In 1696, for instance, Charles Davenant wrote that even if there were a general collapse of confidence in the credit system, it could not last long, because eventually, when people reflected on the matter and realized that credit is simply an extension of human society,
They will find, that no trading nation ever did subsist, and carry on its business by real stock [that is, just coin and merchandise]; that trust and confidence in each other, are as necessary to link and hold a people together, as obedience, love, friendship, or the intercourse of speech. And when experience has taught man how weak he is, depending only on himself, he will be willing to help others, and call upon the assistance of his neighbors, which of course, by degrees, must set credit again afloat.[780]
Davenant was an unusual merchant (his father was a poet). More typical of his class were men like Thomas Hobbes, whose **Leviathan**, published in 1651, was in many ways an extended attack on the very idea that society is built on any sort of prior ties of communal solidarity.
Hobbes might be considered the opening salvo of the new moral perspective, and it was a devastating one. When **Leviathan** came out, itâs not clear what scandalized its readers more: its relentless materialism (Hobbes insisted that humans were basically machines whose actions could be understood by one single principle: that they tended to move toward the prospect of pleasure and away from the prospect of pain), or its resultant cynicism (if love, amity, and trust are such powerful forces, Hobbes asked, why is it that even within our families, we lock our most valuable possessions in strongboxes?) Still, Hobbesâ ultimate argumentâthat humans, being driven by self-interest, cannot be trusted to treat each other justly of their own accord, and therefore that society only emerges when they come to realize that it is to their long-term advantage to give up a portion of their liberties and accept the absolute power of the Kingâdiffered little from arguments that theologians like Martin Luther had been making a century earlier. Hobbes simply substituted scientific language for biblical references.[781]
I want to draw particular attention to the underlying notion of âself-interest.â[782] It is in a real sense the key to the new philosophy. The term first appears in English right around Hobbesâ time, and it is, indeed, directly borrowed from **interesse**, the Roman law term for interest payments. When it was first introduced, most English authors seemed to view the idea that all human life can be explained as the pursuit of self-interest as a cynical, foreign, Machiavellian idea, one that sat uncomfortably with traditional English mores. By the eighteenth century, most in educated society accepted it as simple common sense.
But why âinterestâ? Why make a general theory of human motivation out of a word that originally meant âpenalty for late payment on a loanâ?
Part of the termâs appeal was that it derived from bookkeeping. It was mathematical. This made it seem objective, even scientific. Saying we are all really pursuing our own self-interest provides a way to cut past the welter of passions and emotions that seem to govern our daily existence, and to motivate most of what we actually observe people to do (not only out of love and amity, but also envy, spite, devotion, pity, lust, embarrassment, torpor, indignation, and pride) and discover that, despite all this, most really important decisions are based on the rational calculation of material advantageâwhich means that they are fairly predictable as well. âJust as the physical world is ruled by the laws of movement,â wrote HelvĂ©tius, in a passage reminiscent of Lord Shang, âno less is the moral universe ruled by laws of interest.â[783] And of course it was on this assumption that all the quadratic equations of economic theory could ultimately be built.[784]
The problem is that the origin of the concept is not rational at all. Its roots are theological, and the theological assumptions underpinning it never really went away. âSelf-interestâ is first attested to in the writings of the Italian historian Francesco Guicciadini (who was, in fact, a friend of Machiavelli), around 1510, as a euphemism for St. Augustineâs concept of âself-love.â For Augustine, the âlove of Godâ leads us to benevolence toward our fellows; self-love, in contrast, refers to the fact that, since the Fall of Man, we are cursed by endless, insatiable desires for self-gratificationâso much so that, if left to our own devices, we will necessarily fall into universal competition, even war. Substituting âinterestâ for âloveâ must have seemed an obvious move, since the assumption that love is the primary emotion was precisely what authors like Guicciadini were trying to get away from. But it kept that same assumption of insatiable desires under the guise of impersonal math, since what is âinterestâ but the demand that money **never cease** to grow? The same was true when it became the term for investmentsââI have a twelve-percent interest in that ventureââit is money placed in the continual pursuit of profit.[785] The very idea that human beings are motivated primarily by âself-interest,â then, was rooted in the profoundly Christian assumption that we are all incorrigible sinners; left to our own devices, we will not simply pursue a certain level of comfort and happiness and then stop to enjoy it; we will never cash in the chips, like Sindbad, let alone question why we need to buy chips to begin with. And as Augustine already anticipated, infinite desires in a finite world means endless competition, which in turn is why, as Hobbes insisted, our only hope of social peace lies in contractual arrangements and strict enforcement by the apparatus of the state.
The story of the origins of capitalism, then, is not the story of the gradual destruction of traditional communities by the impersonal power of the market. It is, rather, the story of how an economy of credit was converted into an economy of interest; of the gradual transformation of moral networks by the intrusion of the impersonalâand often vindictiveâpower of the state. English villagers in Elizabethan or Stuart times did not like to appeal to the justice system, even when the law was in their favorâpartly on the principle that neighbors should work things out with one another, but mainly, because the law was so extraordinarily harsh. Under Elizabeth, for example, the punishment for vagrancy (unemployment) was, for first offense, to have oneâs ears nailed to a pillory; for repeat offenders, death.[786]
The same was true of debt law, especially since debts could often, if the creditor was sufficiently vindictive, be treated as a crime. In Chelsea around 1660,
Margaret Sharples was prosecuted for stealing cloth, âwhich she had converted into a petticoat for her own wearing,â from Richard Bennettâs shop. Her defense was that she had bargained with Bennettâs servant for the cloth, âbut having not money sufficient in her purse to pay for it, took it away with purpose to pay for it so soon as she could: and that she afterwards agreed with Mr Bennett of a price for it.â Bennett confirmed that this was so: after agreeing to pay him 22 shillings, Margaret âdelivered a hamper with goods in it as a pawn for security of the money, and four shillings ninepence in money.â But âsoon after he disliked upon better consideration to hold agreement with her: and delivered the hamper and goods back,â and commenced formal legal proceedings against her.[787]
As a result, Margaret Sharples was hanged.
Obviously, it was the rare shopkeeper who wished to see even his most irritating client on the gallows. Therefore decent people tended to avoid the courts entirely. One of the most interesting discoveries of Craig Muldrewâs research is that the more time passed, the less true this became.
Even in the late Middle Ages, in the case of really large loans, it was not unusual for creditors to lodge claims in local courtsâbut this was really just a way of ensuring that there was a public record (remember that most people at the time were illiterate). Debtors were willing to go along with the proceedings in part, it would seem, because if there was any interest being charged, it meant that if they did default, the lender was just as guilty in the eyes of the law as they were. Less than one-percent of these cases were ever brought to judgment.[788] The legalization of interest began to change the nature of the playing field. In the 1580s, when interest-bearing loans began to become common between villagers, creditors also began to insist on the use of signed, legal bonds; this led to such an explosion of appeals to the courts that in many small towns, almost every household seemed to be caught up in debt litigation of some sort or other. Only a tiny proportion of these suits were ever brought to judgment, either: the usual expedient was still to rely on the simple threat of punishment to encourage debtors to settle out of court.[789] Still, as a result, the fear of debtorâs prisonâor worseâcame to hang over everyone, and sociability itself came to take on the color of crime. Even Mr. Coward, the kindly shopkeeper, was eventually laid low. His good credit itself became a problem, especially as he felt honor-bound to use it to help the less fortunate:
He also dealt in merchandise with loose partners, and became concerned much with persons of declining circumstances, where neither profit nor credit could be got; and he gave uneasiness to his wife, by his frequenting some houses of no good character. And she was a very indolent woman, and drew money privately from him, and his circumstances became so burdensome that he daily expected to be made a prisoner. Which, with the shame of forfeiting his former reputation, it drew him into despair and broke his heart, so that he kept to his house for some time and died of grief and shame.[790]
It is perhaps not surprising, when one consults contemporary sources about what those prisons were like, particularly for those who were not of aristocratic origins. Mr. Coward would surely have known, as the conditions at the most notorious, like Fleet and Marshalsea, caused periodic scandals when exposed in parliament or the popular press, filling the papers with stories of shackled debtors âcovered with filth and vermin, and suffered to die, without pity, of hunger and jail fever,â as the aristocratic rouĂ©s placed in the elite side of the same jails lived lives of comfort, visited by manicurists and prostitutes.[791]
The criminalization of debt, then, was the criminalization of the very basis of human society. It cannot be overemphasized that in a small community, everyone normally was both lender and borrower. One can only imagine the tensions and temptations that must have existed in a communitiesâand communities, much though they are based on love, in fact, **because** they are based on love, will always also be full of hatred, rivalry and passionâwhen it became clear that with sufficiently clever scheming, manipulation, and perhaps a bit of strategic bribery, they could arrange to have almost anyone they hated imprisoned or even hanged. What was it that Richard Bennett really had against Margaret Sharples? Weâll never know the back-story, but itâs a pretty safe bet that there was one. The effects on communal solidarity must have been devastating. The sudden accessibility of violence really did threaten to transform what had been the essence of sociality into a war of all against all.[792] Itâs not surprising then, that by the eighteenth century, the very notion of personal credit had acquired a bad name, with both lenders and borrowers considered equally suspect.[793] The use of coinsâat least among those who had access to themâhad come to seem moral in itself.
Understanding all this allows us to see some of the European authors considered in earlier chapters in an entirely new light. Take Panurgeâs encomium on debt: it turns out that the real joke is not the suggestion that debt ties communities together (any English or French peasant of the day would have simply assumed this), or even that **only** debt ties communities together; it is putting the sentiment in the mouth of a wealthy scholar whoâs really an inveterate criminalâthat is, holding up popular morality as a mirror to make fun of the very upper classes who claimed to disapprove of it. Or consider Adam Smith:
It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own necessities but of their advantages.[794]
The bizarre thing here is that, at the time Smith was writing, this simply wasnât true.[795] Most English shopkeepers were still carrying out the main part of their business on credit, which meant that customers appealed to their benevolence all the time. Smith could hardly have been unaware of this. Rather, he is drawing a utopian picture. He wants to imagine a world in which everyone used cash, in part because he agreed with the emerging middle-class opinion that the world would be a better place if everyone really did conduct themselves this way, and avoid confusing and potentially corrupting ongoing entanglements. We should all just pay the money, say âpleaseâ and âthank you,â and leave the store. Whatâs more, he uses this utopian image to make a larger point: that even if all businesses operated like the great commercial companies, with an eye only to self-interest, it wouldnât matter. Even the ânatural selfishness and rapacityâ of the rich, with all their âvain and insatiable desiresâ will still, through the logic of the invisible hand, lead to the benefit of all.[796]
In other words, Smith simply imagined the role of consumer credit in his own day, just as he had his account of the origins of money.[797] This allowed him to ignore the role of both benevolence **and** malevolence in economic affairs; both the ethos of mutual aid that forms the necessary foundation of anything that would look like a free market (that is, one which is not simply created and maintained by the state), **and** the violence and sheer vindictiveness that had actually gone into creating the competitive, self-interested markets that he was using as his model.
Nietzsche, in turn, was taking up Smithâs premises, that life is exchange, but laying bare everything (the torture, murder, mutilation) that Smith preferred not to have to talk about. Now that we have seen just a little of the social context, itâs difficult to read Nietzscheâs otherwise puzzling descriptions of ancient hunters and herdsmen keeping accounts of debts and demanding each othersâ eyes and fingers without immediately thinking of Casimirâs executioner, who actually did present his master with a bill for gouged eyes and severed fingers. What he is really describing is what it took to produce a world in which the son of a prosperous middle-class reverend, such as himself, could simply assume that all human life is premised on calculated, self-interested exchange.
One reason that historians took so long to notice the elaborate popular-credit systems of Tudor and Stuart England is that intellectuals of the time spoke about money in the abstract; they rarely mentioned it. For the educated classes, âmoneyâ soon came to mean gold and silver. Most wrote as if it could be taken for granted that gold and silver had always been used as money for all nations in history and, presumably, always would be.
This not only flew in the face of Aristotle; it directly contradicted the discoveries of European explorers of the time, who were finding shell money, bead money, feather money, salt money, and an endless variety of other currencies everywhere they went.[798] Yet all this just caused economic thinkers to dig in their heels. Some appealed to alchemy to argue that the monetary status of gold and silver had a natural basis: gold (which partook of the sun) and silver (which partook of the moon) were the perfected, eternal forms of metal toward which all baser metals tend to evolve.[799] Most, however, didnât feel that much explanation was required; the intrinsic value of precious metals was simply self-evident. As a result, when royal advisors or London pamphleteers discussed economic problems, the issues they debated were always the same: How do we keep bullion from leaving the country? What do we do about the crippling shortage of coin? For most, questions like âHow do we maintain trust in local credit systems?â simply did not arise.
This was even more extreme in Britain than on the Continent, where âcrying upâ or âcrying downâ the currency was still an option. In Britain, after a disastrous attempt at devaluation under the Tudors, such expedients were abandoned. Henceforth, debasement became a moral issue. For the government to mix base metal into the pure eternal substance of a coin was clearly wrong. So, to a lesser extent, was coin-clipping, a near-universal practice in England, which might be thought of as a kind of popular version of devaluation, since it involved secretly shaving silver off the edges of coins and then pressing them down so they seemed like they were still the original size.
Whatâs more, those new forms of virtual money that began to emerge in the new age were firmly rooted in these same assumptions. This is critical, because it helps explain what might otherwise seem a bizarre contradiction: How is it that this age of ruthless materialism, in which the notion that money was a social convention was definitively rejected, also saw the rise of paper money, along with a whole host of new credit instruments and forms of financial abstraction that have become so typical of modern capitalism? True, most of theseâchecks, bonds, stocks, annuitiesâhad their origins in the metaphysical world of the Middle Ages. Yet in this new age, they underwent an enormous efflorescence.
If one looks at the actual history, though, it quickly becomes clear that all of these new forms of money in no way undermined the assumption that money was founded on the âintrinsicâ value of gold and silver: in fact, they reinforced it. What seems to have happened is that, once credit became unlatched from real relations of trust between individuals (whether merchants or villagers), it became apparent that money could, in effect, be produced simply by saying it was there; but that, when this is done in the amoral world of a competitive marketplace, it would almost inevitably lead to scams and confidence games of every sortâcausing the guardians of the system to periodically panic, and seek new ways to latch the value of the various forms of paper back onto gold and silver.
This is the story normally told as âthe origins of modern banking.â From our perspective, though, what it reveals is just how closely bound together war, bullion, and these new credit instruments were. One need only consider the paths **not** traveled. For instance: there was no intrinsic reason why a bill of exchange couldnât be endorsed over to a third party, then become generally transferableâthus, in effect turning it into a form of paper money. This is how paper money first emerged in China. In Medieval Europe there were periodic movements in that direction, but for a variety of reasons, they did not go far.[800] Alternately, bankers can produce money by issuing book credits for more than they have on cash reserve. This is considered the very essence of modern banking, and it can lead to the circulation of private bank notes.[801] Some moves were made in this direction as well, especially in Italy, but it was a risky proposition, since there was always the danger of depositors panicking and making a run, and most Medieval governments threatened extremely harsh penalties on bankers unable to make restitution in such cases: as witnessed by the example of Francesch Castello, beheaded in front of his own bank in Barcelona in 1360.[802]
Where bankers effectively controlled Medieval governments, it proved safer and more profitable to manipulate the governmentâs own finances. The history of modern financial instruments, and the ultimate origins of paper money, really begin with the issuing of municipal bondsâa practice begun by the Venetian government in the twelfth century when, needing a quick infusion of income for military purposes, it levied a compulsory loan on its taxpaying citizens, for which it promised each of them five percent annual interest, and allowed the âbondsâ or contracts to become negotiable, thus, creating a market in government debt. They [the Venetian government?] tended to be quite meticulous about interest payments, but since the bonds had no specific date of maturity, their market prices often fluctuated wildly with the cityâs political and military fortunes, and so did resulting assessments of the likelihood that they would be able to be repaid. Similar practices quickly spread to the other Italian states and to northern European merchant enclaves as well: the United Provinces of Holland financed their long war of independence against the Hapsburgs (1568â1648) largely through a series of forced loans, though they floated numerous voluntary bond issues as well.[803]
Forcing taxpayers to make a loan is, in one sense, simply demanding that they pay their taxes early; but when the Venetian state first agreed to pay interestâand in legal terms, this was again **interesse**, a penalty for late paymentâit was in principle penalizing itself for not immediately giving the money back. Itâs easy to see how this might raise all sorts of questions about the legal and moral relation between people and government. Ultimately, the commercial classes in those mercantile republics that pioneered these new forms of financing did end up seeing themselves as owning the government more than they saw themselves as being in its debt. Not only the commercial classes: by 1650, a majority of Dutch households held at least a little government debt.[804] However, the true paradox only appears when one begins to âmonetizeâ this debtâthat is, to take government promises to pay and allow them to circulate as currency.
While already by the sixteenth century, merchants were using bills of exchange to settle debts, government debt bondsâ**rentes, juros**, annuitiesâwere the real credit money of the new age. Itâs here that we have to look for the real origins of the âprice revolutionâ that hammered once-independent townsfolk and villagers into the ground and opened the way for most of them to ultimately be reduced to wage laborers, working for those who had access to these higher forms of credit. Even in Seville, where the treasure fleets from the New World first touched port in the Old, bullion was not much used in day-to-day transactions. Most of it was taken directly to the warehouses of Genoese bankers operating from the port and stored for shipment east. But in the process, it became the basis for complex credit schemes whereby the value of the bullion was loaned to the emperor to fund military operations, in exchange for papers entitling the bearer to interest-bearing annuities from the governmentâpapers that could in turn be traded as if they were money. By such means, bankers could almost endlessly multiply the actual value of gold and silver they held. Already in the 1570s, we hear of fairs in places like Medina del Campo, not far from Seville, that had become âveritable factories of certificates,â with transactions carried out exclusively through paper.[805] Since whether the Spanish government would actually pay their debts, or how regularly, were always slightly uncertain, the bills would tend to circulate at a discountâespecially as **juros** began circulating throughout the rest of Europeâcausing continual inflation.[806]
It was only with the creation of the Bank of England in 1694 that one can speak of genuine paper money, since its banknotes were in no sense bonds. They were rooted, like all the others, in the kingâs war debts. This canât be emphasized enough. The fact that money was no longer a debt owed **to** the king, but a debt owed **by** the king, made it very different than what it had been before. In many ways it had become a mirror image of older forms of money.
The reader will recall that the Bank of England was created when a consortium of forty London and Edinburgh merchantsâmostly already creditors to the crownâoffered King William III a ÂŁ1.2 million loan to help finance his war against France. In doing so, they also convinced him to allow them in return to form a corporation with a monopoly on the issuance of banknotesâwhich were, in effect, promissory notes for the money the king now owed them. This was the first independent national central bank, and it became the clearinghouse for debts owed between smaller banks; the notes soon developed into the first European national paper currency. Yet the great public debate of the time, a debate about the very nature of money, was about not paper but metal. The 1690s were a time of crisis for British coinage. The value of silver had risen so high that new British coins (the mint had recently developed the âmilled edgeâ familiar from coins nowadays, which made them clip-proof) were actually worth less than their silver content, with predictable results. Proper silver coins vanished; all that remained in circulation were the old clipped ones, and these were becoming increasingly scarce. Something had to be done. A war of pamphlets ensued, which came to a head in 1695, one year after the founding of the bank. Charles Davenantâs essay on credit, which Iâve already cited, was actually part of this particular pamphlet-war: he proposed that Britain move to a pure credit money based on public trust, and he was ignored. The Treasury proposed to call in the coinage and reissue it at a 20- to 25-percent lower weight, so as to bring it back below the market price for silver. Many who supported this position took explicitly Chartalist positions, insisting that silver has no intrinsic value anyway, and that money is simply a measure established by the state.[807] The man who won the argument, however, was John Locke, the Liberal philosopher, at that time acting as advisor to Sir Isaac Newton, then Warden of the Mint. Locke insisted that one can no more make a small piece of silver worth more by relabeling it a âshillingâ than one can make a short man taller by declaring there are now fifteen inches in a foot. Gold and silver had a value recognized by everyone on earth; the government stamp simply attested to the weight and purity of a coin, andâas he added in words veritably shivering with indignationâfor governments to tamper with this for their own advantage was just as criminal as the coin-clippers themselves:
The use and end of the public stamp is only to be a guard and voucher of the quality of silver which men contract for; and the injury done to the public **faith**, in this point, is that which in clipping and false coining heightens the **robbery** into **treason.[808]**
Therefore, he argued, the only recourse was to recall the currency and restrike it at exactly the same value that it had before.
This was done, and the results were disastrous. In the years immediately following, there was almost no coinage in circulation; prices and wages collapsed; there was hunger and unrest. Only the wealthy were insulated, since they were able to take advantage of the new credit money, trading back and forth portions of the kingâs debt in the form of banknotes. The value of these notes, too, fluctuated a bit at first, but eventually stabilized once they were made redeemable in precious metals. For the rest, the situation only really improved once paper money, and, eventually, smaller-denomination currency, became more widely available. The reforms proceeded top-down, and very slowly, but they did proceed, and they gradually came to create the world where even ordinary, everyday transactions with butchers and bakers were carried out in polite, impersonal terms, with small change, and therefore it became possible to imagine everyday life itself as a matter of self-interested calculation.
Itâs easy enough to see why Locke would adopt the position that he did. He was a scientific materialist. For him, âfaithâ in governmentâas in the quote aboveâwas not the citizensâ belief that the government will keep its promises, but simply that it wonât lie to them; that it would, like a good scientist, give them accurate information, and who wanted to see human behavior as founded in natural laws thatâlike the laws of physics that Newton had so recently describedâwere higher than those of any mere government. The real question is why the British government agreed with him and resolutely stuck to this position despite all the immediate disasters. Soon afterward, in fact, Britain adopted the gold standard (in 1717) and the British Empire maintained it, and with it the notion that gold and silver **were** money, down to its final days.
True, Lockeâs materialism also came to be broadly acceptedâeven to be the watchword of the age.[809] Mainly, though, the reliance on gold and silver seemed to provide the only check on the dangers involved with the new forms of credit-money, which multiplied very quicklyâespecially once ordinary banks were allowed to create money too. It soon became apparent that financial speculation, unmoored from any legal or community constraints, was capable of producing results that seemed to verge on insanity. The Dutch Republic, which pioneered the development of stock markets, had already experienced this in the tulip mania of 1637âthe first of a series of speculative âbubbles,â as they came to be known, in which future prices would first be bid through the ceiling by investors and then collapse. A whole series of such bubbles hit the London markets in the 1690s, in almost every case built around a new joint-stock corporation formed, in imitation of the East India Company, around some prospective colonial venture. The famous South Sea Bubble in 1720âin which a newly formed trading company, granted a monopoly of trade with the Spanish colonies, bought up a considerable portion of the British national debt and saw its shares briefly skyrocket before collapsing in ignominyâwas only the culmination. Its collapse was followed the next year by the collapse of John Lawâs famous Banque Royale in France, another central-bank experimentâsimilar to the Bank of Englandâthat grew so quickly that within a few years it had absorbed all the French colonial trading companies, and most of the French crownâs own debt, issuing its own paper money, before crashing into nothingness in 1721, sending its chief executive fleeing for his life. In each case, this was followed by legislation: in Britain, to forbid the creation of new joint-stock companies (other than for the building of turnpikes and canals), and in France, to eliminate paper money based in government debt entirely.
Itâs unsurprising, then, that Newtonian economics (if we may call it that)âthe assumption that one cannot simply create money, or even, really, tinker with itâcame to be accepted by almost everyone. There had to be some solid, material foundation to all this, or the entire system would go insane. True, economists were to spend centuries arguing about what that foundation might be (was it really gold, or was it land, human labor, the utility or desirability of commodities in general?) but almost no one returned to anything like the Aristotelian view.
Another way to look at this might be to say that the new age came to be increasingly uncomfortable with the political nature of money. Politics, after all, is the art of persuasion; the political is that dimension of social life in which things really do become true if enough people believe them. The problem is that in order to play the game effectively, one can never acknowledge this: it may be true that, if I could convince everyone in the world that I was the King of France, I would in fact become the King of France; but it would never work if I were to admit that this was the only basis of my claim. In this sense, politics is very similar to magicâone reason both politics and magic tend, just about everywhere, to be surrounded by a certain halo of fraud. These suspicions were widely vaunted at the time. In 1711, the satirical essayist Joseph Addison penned a little fantasy about the Bank of Englandâsâand as a result, the British monetary systemâsâdependence on public faith in the political stability of the throne. (The Act of Settlement of 1701 was the bill that guaranteed the royal succession, and a sponge was a popular symbol for default). In a dream, he said,
I saw Public Credit, set on her throne in the Grocerâs Hall, the Great Charter over her head, the Act of Settlement full in her view. Her touch turned everything to gold. Behind her seat, bags filled with coin were piled up to the ceiling. On her right the door flies open. The Pretender rushes in, a sponge in one hand, and in the other a sword, which he shakes at the Act of Settlement. The beautiful Queen sinks down fainting. The spell by which she has turned all things around her into treasure is broken. The money bags shrink like pricked bladders. The piles of gold pieces are turned into bundles of rags or faggots of wooden tallies.[810]
If one does not believe in the king, then the money vanishes with him.
Thus kings, magicians, markets, and alchemists all fused in the public imagination during this era, and we still talk about the âalchemyâ of the market, or âfinancial magicians.â In Goetheâs **Faust** (1808), he actually has his heroâin his capacity as alchemist-magicianâpay a visit to the Holy Roman Emperor. The Emperor is sinking under the weight of endless debts that he has piled up paying for the extravagant pleasures of his court. Faust, and his assistant, Mephistopheles, convince him that he can pay off his creditors by creating paper money. Itâs represented as an act of pure prestidigitation. âYou have plenty of gold lying somewhere underneath your lands,â notes Faust. âJust issue notes promising your creditors youâll give it to them later. Since no one knows how much gold there really is, thereâs no limit to how much you can promise.â[811]
This kind of magical language almost never appears in the Middle Ages.[812] It would appear that itâs only in a resolutely materialist age that this ability to simply produce things by saying that they are there comes to be seen as a scandalous, even diabolical. And the surest sign that one has entered such a materialist age is precisely the fact that it is seen so. We have already observed Rabelais, at the very beginning of the age, reverting to language almost identical to that used by Plutarch when he railed against moneylenders in Roman timesââlaughing at those natural philosophers who hold that nothing can be made of nothing,â as they manipulate their books and ledgers to demand back money they never actually had. Panurge just turned it around: no, itâs by borrowing that I make something out of nothing, and become a kind of god.
But consider the following lines, often attributed to Lord Josiah Charles Stamp, director of the Bank of England:
The modern banking system manufactures money out of nothing. The process is perhaps the most astounding piece of sleight of hand that was ever invented. Banking was conceived in iniquity and born in sin. Bankers own the earth; take it away from them, but leave them with the power to create credit, and with the stroke of a pen they will create enough money to buy it back again ⊠If you wish to remain slaves of Bankers, and pay the cost of your own slavery, let them continue to create deposits.[813]
It seems extremely unlikely that Lord Stamp ever really said this, but the passage has been cited endlesslyâin fact, itâs probably the single most often-quoted passage by critics of the modern banking system. However apocryphal, it clearly strikes a chord, and apparently for the same reason: bankers are creating something out of nothing. They are not only frauds and magicians. They are evil, because theyâre playing God.
But thereâs a deeper scandal than mere prestidigitation. If Medieval moralists did not raise such objections, it was not just because they were comfortable with metaphysical entities. They had a much more fundamental problem with the market: greed. Market motives were held to be inherently corrupt. The moment that greed was validated, and unlimited profit was considered a perfectly viable end in itself, this political, magical element became a genuine problem, because it meant that even those actorsâthe brokers, stock-jobbers, tradersâwho effectively made the system run had no convincing loyalty to anything, even to the system itself.
Hobbes, who first developed this vision of human nature into an explicit theory of society, was well aware of this greed dilemma. It formed the basis of his political philosophy. Even, he argued, if we are all rational enough to understand that itâs in our long-term interest to live in peace and security, our short-term interests are often such that killing and plundering are the most obviously profitable courses to take, and all it takes is a few to cast aside their scruples to create utter insecurity and chaos. This was why he felt that markets could only exist under the aegis of an absolutist state, which would force us to keep our promises and respect one anotherâs property. But what happens when weâre talking about a market in which it is state debts and state obligations themselves that are being traded; when one cannot really speak of a state monopoly on force because one is operating in an international market where the primary currency is bonds that the state depends on for its very ability to marshal military force?
Having made incessant war on all remaining forms of the communism of the poor, even to the point of criminalizing credit, the masters of the new market system discovered that they had no obvious justification left to maintain even the communism of the richâthat level of cooperation and solidarity required to keep the economic system running. True, for all its endless strains and periodic breakdowns, the system has held out so far. But as recent events have dramatically testified, it has never been resolved.
We are used to seeing modern capitalism (along with modern traditions of democratic government) as emerging only later: with the Age of Revolutionsâthe industrial revolution, the American and French revolutionsâa series of profound breaks at the end of the eighteenth century that only became fully institutionalized after the end of the Napoleonic Wars. Here we come face to face with a peculiar paradox. It would seem that almost all elements of financial apparatus that weâve come to associate with capitalismâcentral banks, bond markets, short-selling, brokerage houses, speculative bubbles, securization, annuitiesâcame into being not only before the science of economics (which is perhaps not too surprising), but also before the rise of factories, and wage labor itself.[814] This is a genuine challenge to familiar ways of thinking. We like to think of the factories and workshops as the âreal economy,â and the rest as superstructure, constructed on top of it. But if this were really so, then how can it be that the superstructure came first? Can the dreams of the system create its body?
All this raises the question of what âcapitalismâ is to begin with, a question on which there is no consensus at all. The word was originally invented by socialists, who saw capitalism as that system whereby those who own capital command the labor of those who do not. Proponents, in contrast, tend to see capitalism as the freedom of the marketplace, which allows those with potentially marketable visions to pull resources together to bring those visions into being. Just about everyone agrees, however, that capitalism is a system that demands constant, endless growth. Enterprises have to grow in order to remain viable. The same is true of nations. Just as five percent per annum was widely accepted, at the dawn of capitalism, as the legitimate commercial rate of interestâthat is, the amount that any investor could normally expect her money to be growing by the principle of **interesse**âso is five percent now the annual rate at which any nationâs GDP really ought to grow. What was once an impersonal mechanism that compelled people to look at everything around them as a potential source of profit has come to be considered the only objective measure of the health of the human community itself.
Starting from our baseline date of 1700, then, what we see at the dawn of modern capitalism is a gigantic financial apparatus of credit and debt that operatesâin practical effectâto pump more and more labor out of just about everyone with whom it comes into contact, and as a result produces an endlessly expanding volume of material goods. It does so not just by moral compulsion, but above all by using moral compulsion to mobilize sheer physical force. At every point, the familiar but peculiarly European entanglement of war and commerce reappearsâoften in startling new forms. The first stock markets in Holland and Britain were based mainly in trading shares of the East and West India companies, which were both military and trading ventures. For a century, one such private, profit-seeking corporation governed India. The national debts of England, France, and the others were based in money borrowed not to dig canals and erect bridges, but to acquire the gunpowder needed to bombard cities and to construct the camps required for the holding of prisoners and the training of recruits. Almost all the bubbles of the eighteenth century involved some fantastic scheme to use the proceeds of colonial ventures to pay for European wars. Paper money was debt money, and debt money was war money, and this has always remained the case. Those who financed Europeâs endless military conflicts also employed the governmentâs police and prisons to extract ever-increasing productivity from the rest of the population.
As everybody knows, the world market system initiated by the Spaniards and Portuguese empires first arose in the search for spices. It soon settled into three broad trades, which might be labeled the arms trade, the slave trade, and the drug trade. The last refers mostly to soft drugs, of course, like coffee, tea, and the sugar to put in them, and tobacco, but distilled liquor first appears at this stage of human history as well, and as we all know, Europeans had no compunctions about aggressively marketing opium in China as a way of finally putting an end to the need to export bullion. The cloth trade only came later, after the East India Company used military force to shut down the (more efficient) Indian cotton export trade. One need only take a glance at the book that preserves Charles Davenantâs 1696 essay on credit and human fellowship: **The political and commercial works of that celebrated writer Charles DâAvenant: relating to the trade and revenue of England, the Plantation trade, the East-India trade and African trade**. âObedience, love, and friendshipâ might suffice to govern relations between fellow Englishmen, then, but in the colonies, it was mainly just obedience.
As Iâve described, the Atlantic slave trade can be imagined as a giant chain of debt-obligations, stretching from Bristol to Calabar to the headwaters of the Cross River, where the Aro traders sponsored their secret societies; just as in the Indian Ocean trade, similar chains connected Utrecht to Capetown to Jakarta to the Kingdom of Gelgel, where Balinese kings arranged their cockfights to lure their own subjects to gamble their freedom away. In either case, the end product was the same: human beings so entirely ripped from their contexts, and hence so thoroughly dehumanized, that they were placed outside the realm of debt entirely.
The middlemen in these chains, the various commercial links of the debt chain that connected the stock-jobbers in London with the Aro priests in Nigeria, pearl divers in the Aru islands of Eastern Indonesia, Bengali tea plantations, or Amazonian rubber-tappers, give one the impression of having been sober, calculating, unimaginative men. At either end of the debt chain, the whole enterprise seemed to turn on the ability to manipulate fantasies, and to run a constant peril of slipping into what even contemporary observers considered varieties of phantasmagoric madness. On the one end were the periodic bubbles, propelled in part by rumor and fantasy and in part by the fact that just about everyone in cities like Paris and London with any disposable cash would suddenly become convinced that they would somehow be able to profit from the fact that everyone else was succumbing to rumor and fantasy.
Charles MacKay has left us some immortal descriptions of the first of these, the famous âSouth Sea Bubbleâ of 1710. Actually, the South Sea Company itself (which grew so large that at one point it bought up most of the national debt) was just the anchor for what happened, a giant corporation, its stock constantly ballooning in value, that seemed, to put it in contemporary terms, âtoo big to fail.â It soon became the model for hundreds of new start-up offerings:
Innumerable joint-stock companies started up everywhere. They soon received the name Bubbles, the most appropriate imagination could devise ⊠Some of them lasted a week or a fortnight, and were no more heard of, while others could not even live out that span of existence. Every evening produced new schemes, and every morning new projects. The highest of the aristocracy were as eager in this hot pursuit of gain as the most plodding jobber in Cornhill.[815]
The author lists, as arbitrary examples, eighty-six schemes, ranging from the manufacture of soap or sailcloth, the provision of insurance for horses, to a method to âmake deal-boards out of sawdust.â Each issued stock; each issue would appear, then be scooped up and avidly traded back and forth in taverns, coffee-houses, alleys, and haberdasheries across the city. In every case their price was quickly bid through the ceilingâeach new buyer betting, effectively, that he or she could unload them to some even more gullible sucker before the inevitable collapse. Sometimes people bid on cards and coupons that would allow them no more than the right to bid on other shares later. Thousands grew rich. Thousands more were ruined.
The most absurd and preposterous of all, and which shewed, more completely than any other, the utter madness of the people, was one started by an unknown adventurer, entitled âA **company for the carrying on of an undertaking of great advantage, but nobody to know what it is.â**
The man of genius who essayed this bold and successful inroad upon public credulity merely stated in his prospectus that the required capital was half a million, in five thousand shares of 1001. each, deposit 21. per share. Each subscriber, paying his deposit, would be entitled to 1001. per annum per share. How this immense profit was to be obtained, he would not condescend to inform them at that time, but promised that in a month the full particulars would be duly announced, and call made for the remaining 981. of the subscription. Next morning, at nine oâclock, this great man opened an office in Cornhill. Crowds beset his door, and when he shut up at three oâclock, he found that no less than one thousand shares had been subscribed for, and the deposits paid.
He was philosopher enough to be contented with his venture, and set off that same evening for the Continent. He was never heard of again.[816]
If one is to believe MacKay, the entire population of London conceived the simultaneous delusion, not that money could really be manufactured out of nothing, but that other people were foolish enough to believe that it couldâand that, by that very fact, they actually could make money out of nothing after all.
Moving to the other side of the debt chain, we find fantasies ranging from the charming to the apocalyptic. In the anthropological literature, there is everything from the beautiful âsea wivesâ of Aru pearl divers, who will not yield up the treasures of the ocean unless courted with gifts bought on credit from local Chinese shops,[817] to the secret markets where Bengali landlords purchase ghosts to terrorize insubordinate debt peons; to Tiv flesh-debts, a fantasy of human society cannibalizing itself; to finally, occasions at which, the Tiv nightmare appears to have very nearly become true.[818] One the most famous and disturbing was the great Putumayo scandal of 1909â1911, in which the London reading public was shocked to discover that the agents of the subsidiary of a British rubber company operating in the Peruvian rainforest had created their very own Heart of Darkness, exterminating tens of thousands of Huitoto Indiansâwho the agents insisted on referring to only as âcannibalsââin scenes of rape, torture, and mutilation that recalled the very worst of the conquest four hundred years earlier.[819]
In the debates that followed, the first impulse was to blame everything on a system whereby the Indians were said to have been caught in a debt trap, made completely dependent on the company store:
The root of the whole evil was the so called **patron** or âpeonageâ systemâa variety of what used to be called in England the âtruck systemââby which the employee, forced to buy all his supplies at the employerâs store, is kept hopelessly in debt, while by law he is unable to leave his employment until his debt is paid ⊠The **peon** is thus, as often as not, a **de facto** slave; and since in the remoter regions of the vast continent there is no effective government, he is wholly at the mercy of his master.[820]
The âcannibalsâ who ended up flogged to death, crucified, tied up and used for target practice, or hacked to pieces with machetes for failure to bring in sufficient quantities of rubber, had, the story went, fallen into the ultimate debt trap; seduced by the wares of the companyâs agents, theyâd ended up bartering away their very lives.
A later Parliamentary inquiry discovered that the real story was nothing of the sort. The Huitoto had not been tricked into becoming debt peons at all. It was the agents and overseers sent into the region who were, much like the conquistadors, deeply indebtedâin their case, to the Peruvian company that had commissioned them, which was ultimately receiving its own credit from London financiers. These agents had certainly arrived with every intention of extending that web of credit to include the Indians, but discovering the Huitoto to have no interest in the cloth, machetes, and coins they had brought to trade with them, theyâd finally given up and just started rounding Indians up and forcing them to accept loans at gunpoint, then tabulating the amount of rubber they owed.[821] Many of the Indians massacred, in turn, had simply been trying to run away.
In reality, then, the Indians had been reduced to slavery; itâs just that, by 1907, no one could openly admit this. A legitimate enterprise had to have some moral basis, and the only morality the company knew was debt. When it became clear that the Huitoto rejected the premise, everything went haywire, and the company ended up, like Casimir, caught in a spiral of indignant terror that ultimately threatened to wipe out its very economic basis.
It is the secret scandal of capitalism that at no point has it been organized primarily around free labor.[822] The conquest of the Americas began with mass enslavement, then gradually settled into various forms of debt peonage, African slavery, and âindentured serviceââthat is, the use of contract labor, workers who had received cash in advance and were thus bound for five-, seven-, or ten-year terms to pay it back. Needless to say, indentured servants were recruited largely from among people who were already debtors. In the 1600s there were at times almost as many white debtors as African slaves working in southern plantations, and legally they were at first in almost the same situation, since in the beginning, plantation societies were working within a European legal tradition that assumed slavery did not exist, so even Africans in the Carolinas were classified, as contract laborers.[823] Of course this later changed when the idea of âraceâ was introduced. When African slaves were freed, they were replaced, on plantations from Barbados to Mauritius, with contract laborers again: though now ones recruited mainly in India or China. Chinese contract laborers built the North American railroad system, and Indian âcooliesâ built the South African mines. The peasants of Russia and Poland, who had been free landholders in the Middle Ages, were only made serfs at the dawn of capitalism, when their lords began to sell grain on the new world market to feed the new industrial cities to the west.[824] Colonial regimes in Africa and Southeast Asia regularly demanded forced labor from their conquered subjects, or, alternately, created tax systems designed to force the population into the labor market through debt. British overlords in India, starting with the East India Company but continuing under Her Majestyâs government, institutionalized debt peonage as their primary means of creating products for sale abroad.
This is a scandal not just because the system occasionally goes haywire, as it did in the Putumayo, but because it plays havoc with our most cherished assumptions about what capitalism really isâparticularly that, in its basic nature, capitalism has something to do with freedom. For the capitalists, this means the freedom of the marketplace. For most workers, it means free labor. Marxists have questioned whether wage labor is ultimately free in any sense (since someone with nothing to sell but his or her body cannot in any sense be considered a genuinely free agent), but they still tend to assume that free wage labor is the basis of capitalism. And the dominant image in the history of capitalism is the English workingman toiling in the factories of the industrial revolution, and this image can be traced forward to Silicon Valley, with a straight line in between. All those millions of slaves and serfs and coolies and debt peons disappear, or if we must speak of them, we write them off as temporary bumps along the road. Like sweatshops, this is assumed to be a stage that industrializing nations had to pass through, just as it is still assumed that all those millions of debt peons and contract laborers and sweatshop workers who still exist, often in the same places, will surely live to see their children become regular wage laborers with health insurance and pensions, and **their** children, doctors and lawyers and entrepreneurs.
When one looks at the actual history of wage labor, even in countries like England, that picture begins to melt away. In most of Medieval northern Europe, wage labor had been mainly a lifestyle phenomenon. From roughly the age of twelve or fourteen to roughly twenty-eight or thirty, everyone was expected to be employed as a servant in someone elseâs householdâusually on a yearly contract basis, for which they received room, board, professional training, and usually a wage of some sortâuntil they accumulated enough resources to marry and set up a household of their own.[825] The first thing that âproletarianizationâ came to mean was that millions of young men and women across Europe found themselves effectively stuck in a kind of permanent adolescence. Apprentices and journeymen could never become âmasters,â and thus, never actually grow up. Eventually, many began to give up and marry earlyâto the great scandal of the moralists, who insisted that the new proletariat were starting families they could not possibly support.[826]
There is, and has always been, a curious affinity between wage labor and slavery. This is not just because it was slaves on Caribbean sugar plantations who supplied the quick-energy products that powered much of early wage laborersâ work; not just because most of the scientific management techniques applied in factories in the industrial revolution can be traced back to those sugar plantations; but also because both the relation between master and slave, and between employer and employee, are in principle impersonal: whether youâve been sold or youâre simply rented yourself out, the moment money changes hands, **who** you are is supposed to be unimportant; all thatâs important is that you are capable of understanding orders and doing what youâre told.[827]
This is one reason, perhaps, that in principle, there was always a feeling that both the buying of slaves and the hiring of laborers should really not be on credit, but should employ cash. The problem, as Iâve noted, was that for most of the history of British capitalism, the cash simply didnât exist. Even when the Royal Mint began to produce smaller-denomination silver and copper coins, the supply was sporadic and inadequate. This is how the âtruck systemâ developed to begin with: during the industrial revolution, factory owners would often pay their workers with tickets or vouchers good only in local shops, with whose owners they had some sort of informal arrangement, or, in more isolated parts of the country, which they owned themselves.[828] Traditional credit relations with oneâs local shopkeeper clearly took on an entirely new complexion once the shopkeeper was effectively an agent of the boss. Another expedient was to pay workers at least partly in kindâand notice the very richness of the vocabulary for the sorts of things one was assumed to be allowed to appropriate from oneâs workplace, particularly from the waste, excess, and side products: cabbage, chips, thrums, sweepings, buggings, gleanings, sweepings, potchings, vails, poake, coltage, knockdowns, tinge.[829] âCabbage,â for instance, was the cloth left over from tailoring, âchipsâ the pieces of board that dockworkers had the right to carry from their workplace (any piece of timber less than two feet long), âthrumsâ were taken from the warping-bars of looms, and so on. And of course we have already heard about payment in the form of cod, or nails.
Employers had a final expedient: wait for the money to show up, and in the meantime, donât pay anythingâleaving their employees to get by with **only** what they could scrounge from their shop floors, or what their families could finagle in outside employment, receive in charity, preserve in savings pools with friends and families, or, when all else failed, acquire on credit from the loan sharks and pawnbrokers who rapidly came to be seen as the perennial scourge of the working poor. The situation became such that, by the nineteenth century, any time a fire destroyed a London pawnshop, working-class neighborhoods would brace for the wave of domestic violence that would inevitably ensue when many a wife was forced to confess that sheâd long since secretly hocked her husbandâs Sunday suit.[830]
We are, nowadays, used to associating factories eighteen months in arrears for wages with a nation in economic free-fall, such as occurred during the collapse of the Soviet Union; but owing to the hard-money policies of the British government, who were always concerned above all to ensure that their paper money didnât float away in another speculative bubble, in the early days of industrial capitalism, such a situation was in no way unusual. Even the government was often unable to find the cash to pay its own employees. In eighteenth-century London, the Royal Admiralty was regularly over a year behind in paying the wages of those who labored at the Deptford docksâone reason that they were willing to tolerate the appropriation of chips, not to mention hemp, canvas, steel bolts, and cordage. In fact, as Linebaugh has shown, the situation only really began to take recognizable form around 1800, when the government stabilized its finances, began paying cash wages on schedule, and therefore tried to abolish the practice of what was now relabeled âworkplace pilferingââwhich, meeting outraged resistance on the part of the dockworkers, was made punishable by whipping and imprisonment. Samuel Bentham, the engineer put in charge of reforming the dockyards, had to turn them into a regular police state in order to be able to institute a regime of pure wage laborâto which purpose he ultimately conceived the notion of building a giant tower in the middle to guarantee constant surveillance, an idea that was later borrowed by his brother Jeremy for the famous Panopticon.[831]
Men like Smith and Bentham were idealists; even utopians. To understand the history of capitalism, however, we have to begin by realizing that the picture we have in our heads, of workers who dutifully punch the clock at 8:00 a.m. and receive regular remuneration every Friday, on the basis of a temporary contract that either party is free to break off at any time, began as a utopian vision, was only gradually put into effect even in England and North America, and has never, at any point, been the main way of organizing production for the market, ever, anywhere.
This is actually why Smithâs work is so important. He created the vision of an imaginary world almost entirely free of debt and credit, and therefore, free of guilt and sin; a world where men and women were free to simply calculate their interests in full knowledge that everything had been prearranged by God to ensure that it will serve the greater good. Such imaginary constructs are of course what scientists refer to as âmodels,â and thereâs nothing intrinsically wrong with them. Actually I think a fair case can be made that we cannot think without them. The problem with such modelsâat least, it always seems to happen when we model something called âthe marketââis that, once created, we have a tendency to treat them as objective realities, or even fall down before them and start worshipping them as gods. âWe must obey the dictates of the market!â
Karl Marx, who knew quite a bit about the human tendency to fall down and worship our own creations, wrote **Das Capital** in an attempt to demonstrate that, even if we do start from the economistsâ utopian vision, so long as we also allow some people to control productive capital, and, again, leave others with nothing to sell but their brains and bodies, the results will be in many ways barely distinguishable from slavery, and the whole system will eventually destroy itself. What everyone seems to forget is the âas ifâ nature of his analysis.[832] Marx was well aware that there were far more bootblacks, prostitutes, butlers, soldiers, pedlars, chimneysweeps, flower girls, street musicians, convicts, nannies, and cab drivers in the London of his day than there were factory workers. He was never suggesting that thatâs what the world was actually like.
Still, if there is anything that the last several hundred years of world history have shown, itâs that utopian visions can have a certain appeal. This is as true of Adam Smithâs as of those ranged against it. The period from roughly 1825 to 1975 is a brief but determined effort on the part of a large number of very powerful peopleâwith the avid support of many of the least powerfulâto try to turn that vision into something like reality. Coins and paper money were, finally, produced in sufficient quantities that even ordinary people could conduct their daily lives without appeal to tickets, tokens, or credit. Wages started to be paid on time. New sorts of shops, arcades, and galleries appeared, where everyone paid in cash, or alternately, as time went on, by means of impersonal forms of credit like installment plans. As a result, the old puritanical notion that debt was sin and degradation began to take a profound hold on many of those who came to consider themselves the ârespectableâ working classes, who often took freedom from the clutches of the pawnbroker and loan shark as a point of pride, which separated them from drunkards, hustlers, and ditch-diggers as surely as the fact that they werenât missing teeth.
Speaking as someone brought up in that sort of working-class family (my brother died at the age of 53, having refused to his dying day to acquire a credit card), I can attest to the degree that, for those who spend most of their waking hours working at someone elseâs orders, the ability to pull out a wallet full of banknotes that are unconditionally oneâs own can be a compelling form of freedom. Itâs not surprising that so many of the economistsâ assumptionsâmost of those for which I have been taking them to task over the course of this bookâhave been embraced by the leaders of the historic workersâ movements, so much so that they have come to shape our visions of what alternatives to capitalism might be like. The problem is not justâas I demonstrated in chapter 7âthat it is rooted in a deeply flawed, even perverse, conception of human freedom. The real problem is that, like all utopian dreams, it is impossible. We could no more have a universal world market than we could have a system in which everyone who wasnât a capitalist was somehow able to become a respectable, regularly paid wage laborer with access to adequate dental care. A world like that has never existed and never could exist. Whatâs more, the moment that even the prospect that this might happen begins to materialize, the whole system starts to come apart.
Let us return, finally, to where we began: with Cortés and the Aztec treasure. The reader might have asked herself, What did happen to it? Did Cortés really steal it from his own men?
The answer seems to be that by the time the siege was over, there was very little of it left. Cortés seems to have gotten his hands on much of it long before the siege even began. A certain portion he had won by gambling.
This story, too, is in Bernal DĂaz, and it is strange and puzzling, but also, I suspect, profound. Let me fill in some of the gaps in our story. After burning his boats, CortĂ©s began to assemble an army of local allies, which was easy to do because the Aztecs were widely hated, and then he began to march on the Aztec capital. Moctezuma, the Aztec emperor, who had been monitoring the situation closely, concluded that he needed to at least figure out what sort of people he was dealing with, so he invited the entire Spanish force (only a few hundred men) to be his official guests in TenochtitlĂĄn. This eventually led to a series of palace intrigues during which CortĂ©sâs men briefly held the emperor hostage before being forcibly expelled.
During the time when Moctezuma was being held captive in his own palace, he and CortĂ©s passed a good deal of their time playing an Aztec game called **totoloque**. They played for gold, and CortĂ©s, of course, cheated. At one point, Moctezumaâs men brought the matter to the kingâs attention, but the king just laughed and made a joke of itâneither was he concerned later when Pedro de Alvarado, CortĂ©sâs chief lieutenant, began cheating even more flagrantly, demanding gold for each point lost and when he lost, paying only in worthless pebbles. Why Moctezuma behaved so has remained something of an historical mystery. DĂaz took it as a gesture of lordly magnanimity, perhaps even a way of putting the petty-minded Spaniards in their place.[833]
One historian, Inga Clenninden, suggests an alternate interpretation. Aztec games, she notes, tended to have a peculiar feature: there was always a way that, by a freak stroke of luck, one could achieve total victory. This seems to have been true, for instance, of their famous ball games. Observers always wonder, viewing the tiny stone hoops set high above the court, how anyone could ever possibly have managed to score. The answer seems to be: they didnât, at least not that way. Normally the game had nothing to do with the hoop. The game was played between two opposing squads, attired as for battle, knocking the ball back and forth:
The normal method of scoring was through the slow accumulation of points. But that process could be dramatically preempted. To send the ball through one of the ringsâa feat, given the size of the ball and the ring, presumably rarer than a hole in one in golfâgave instant victory, ownership of all the goods wagered, and the right to pillage the cloaks of the onlookers.[834]
Whoever scored the point won everything, down to the audienceâs clothing.
There were similar rules in board games, such as Cortés and Moctezuma were playing: if, by some freak stroke of luck, one of the dice landed on its edge, the game was over, and the winner took everything. This, Clenninden suggests, must have been what Moctezuma was really waiting for. After all, he was clearly in the middle of extraordinary events. Strange creatures had appeared, apparently from nowhere, with unheard-of powers. Rumors of epidemics, of the destruction of nearby nations, had presumably already reached him. If ever there was a time that some grandiose revelation was due from the gods, then surely this was it.
Such an attitude does seem to fit perfectly with the spirit of Aztec culture gleaned from its literature, which exuded a sense of impending catastrophe, perhaps astrologically determined, just possibly avoidableâbut probably not. Some have suggested that Aztecs must have somehow been aware that they were a civilization skating on the brink of ecological catastrophe; others, that the apocalyptic tone is retrospectiveâsince, after all, what we know of Aztec literature is almost entirely gleaned from men and women who actually did experience its complete destruction. Still, there does seem to be a certain frantic quality in certain Aztec practicesâthe sacrifice of as many as tens of thousands of war prisoners, most notably in the apparent belief that, were the Sun not continually fed with human hearts, it would die and world with itâthat itâs hard to explain in any other way.
If Clenninden is right, for Moctezuma, he and Cortés were not simply gambling for gold. Gold was trivial. The stakes were the entire universe.
Moctezuma was above all a warrior, and all warriors are gamblers; but unlike CortĂ©s, he was clearly in every way a man of honor. As weâve also seen, the quintessence of a warriorâs honor, which is a greatness that can only come from the destruction and degradation of others, is his willingness to throw himself into a game where he risks that same destruction and degradation himselfâand, unlike CortĂ©s, to play graciously, and by the rules.[835] When the time came, it meant being willing to stake everything.
He did. And as it turns out, nothing happened. No die landed on its edge. Cortés continued to cheat, the gods sent no revelation, and the universe was eventually destroyed.
If thereâs something to be learned hereâand as I say, I think there isâit is that there may be a deeper, more profound relation between gambling and apocalypse. Capitalism is a system that enshrines the gambler as an essential part of its operation, in a way that no other ever has; yet at the same time, capitalism seems to be uniquely incapable of conceiving of its own eternity. Could these two facts be linked?
I should be more precise here. Itâs not entirely true that capitalism is incapable of conceiving of its own eternity. On the one hand, its exponents do often feel obliged to present it as eternal, because they insist that is it is the only possible viable economic system: one that, as they still sometimes like to say, âhas existed for five thousand years and will exist for five thousand more.â On the other hand, it does seem that the moment a significant portion of the population begins to actually believe this, and particularly, starts treating credit institutions as if they really will be around forever, everything goes haywire. Note here how it was the most sober, cautious, responsible capitalist regimesâthe seventeenth-century Dutch Republic, the eighteenth-century British Commonwealthâthe ones most careful about managing their public debtâthat saw the most bizarre explosions of speculative frenzy, the tulip manias and South Sea bubbles.
Much of this seems to turn on the nature of national deficits and credit money. The national debt is, as politicians have complained practically since these things first appeared, money borrowed from future generations. Still, the effects have always been strangely double-edged. On the one hand, deficit financing is a way of putting even more military power in the hands of princes, generals, and politicians; on the other, it suggests that government owes something to those it governs. Insofar as our money is ultimately an extension of the public debt, then whenever we buy a newspaper or a cup of coffee, or even place a bet on a horse, we are trading in promises, representations of something that the government will give us at some time in the future, even if we donât know exactly what it is.[836]
Immanuel Wallerstein likes to point out that the French Revolution introduced several profoundly new ideas in politicsâideas which, fifty years before the revolution, the vast majority of educated Europeans would have written off as crazy, but which, fifty years afterward, just about anyone felt they had to at least pretend they thought were true. The first is that social change is inevitable and desirable: that the natural direction of history is for civilization to gradually improve. The second is that the appropriate agent to manage such change is the government. The third is that the government gains its legitimacy from an entity called âthe people.â[837] Itâs easy to see how the very idea of a national debtâa promise of continual future improvement (at the very least, five percent annual improvement) made by government to peopleâmight itself have played a role in inspiring such a revolutionary new perspective. Yet at the same time, when one looks at what men like Mirabeau, Voltaire, Diderot, SiĂ©yesâthe **philosophes** who first proposed that notion of what we now call âcivilizationââwere actually arguing about in the years immediately leading up to the revolution, it was even more about the danger of apocalyptic catastrophe, of the prospect of civilization as they knew it being destroyed by default and economic collapse.
Part of the problem was the obvious one: the national debt is, first, born of war; second, it is not owed to all the people equally, but above all to capitalistsâand in France at that time, âcapitalistâ meant, specifically, âthose who held pieces of the national debt.â The more democratically inclined felt that the entire situation was opprobrious. âThe modern theory of the perpetuation of debt,â Thomas Jefferson wrote, around this same time, âhas drenched the earth with blood, and crushed its inhabitants under burdens ever accumulating.â[838] Most Enlightenment thinkers feared that it promised even worse. Intrinsic to the new, âmodernâ notion of impersonal debt, after all, was the possibility of bankruptcy.[839] Bankruptcy, at that time, was indeed something of a personal apocalypse: it meant prison, the dissolution of oneâs estate; for the least fortunate, it meant torture, starvation, and death. What national bankruptcy would mean, at that point in history, nobody knew. There were simply no precedents. Yet as nations fought greater and bloodier wars, and their debts escalated geometrically, default began to appear unavoidable.[840] Abbe SieyĂ©s first put forward his great scheme for representative government, for instance, primarily as a way of reforming the national finances, to fend off the inevitable catastrophe. And when it happened, what would it look like? Would the money become worthless? Would military regimes seize power, regimes across Europe be likewise forced to default and fall like dominos, plunging the continent into endless barbarism, darkness, and war? Many were already anticipating the prospect of the Terror long before the revolution itself.[841]
Itâs a strange story because we are used to thinking of the Enlightenment as the dawn of a unique phase of human optimism, borne on assumptions that the advance of science and human knowledge would inevitably make life wiser, safer, and better for everyoneâa naĂŻve faith said to have peaked in the Fabian socialism of the 1890s, only to be annihilated in the trenches of World War I. In fact, even the Victorians were haunted by the dangers of degeneration and decline. Most of all, Victorians shared the near-universal assumption that capitalism itself would not be around forever. Insurrection seemed imminent. Many Victorian capitalists operated under the sincere belief that they might, at any moment, find themselves hanging from trees. In Chicago, for instance, a friend once took me on a drive down a beautiful old street, full of mansions from the 1870s: the reason, he explained, that it looked like that, was that most of Chicagoâs rich industrialists of the time were so convinced that the revolution was immanent that they collectively relocated along the road that led to the nearest military base. Almost none of the great theorists of capitalism, from anywhere on the political spectrum, from Marx to Weber, to Schumpeter, to von Mises, felt that capitalism was likely to be around for more than another generation or two at the most.
One could go further: the moment that the fear of imminent social revolution no longer seemed plausible, by the end of World War II, we were immediately presented with the specter of nuclear holocaust.[842] Then, when that no longer seemed plausible, we discovered global warming. This is not to say that these threats were not, and are not, real. Yet it does seem strange that capitalism feels the constant need to imagine, or to actually manufacture, the means of its own imminent extinction. Itâs in dramatic contrast to the behavior of the leaders of socialist regimes, from Cuba to Albania, who, when they came to power, immediately began acting as if their system would be around foreverâironically enough, considering they in fact turned out to be something of an historical blip.
Perhaps the reason is because what was true in 1710 is still true. Presented with the prospect of its own eternity, capitalismâor anyway, financial capitalismâsimply explodes. Because if thereâs no end to it, thereâs absolutely no reason not to generate creditâthat is, future moneyâinfinitely. Recent events would certainly seem to confirm this. The period leading up to 2009 was one in which many began to believe that capitalism really was going to be around forever; at the very least, no one seemed any longer to be able to imagine an alternative. The immediate effect was a series of increasingly reckless bubbles that brought the whole apparatus crashing down.
<em>Look at all these bums: If only there were a way of finding out how much they owe</em>.
<em>âRepo Man</em> (1984)
<em>Free your mind of the idea of deserving, of the idea of earning, and you will begin to be able to think</em>.
On August 15, 1971, United States President Richard Nixon announced that foreign-held U.S. dollars would no longer be convertible into goldâthus stripping away the last vestige of the international gold standard.[843] This was the end of a policy that had been effective since 1931, and confirmed by the Bretton Woods accords at the end of World War II: that while United States citizens might no longer be allowed to cash in their dollars for gold, all U.S. currency held outside the country was to be redeemable at the rate of $35 an ounce. By doing so, Nixon initiated the regime of free-floating currencies that continues to this day.
The consensus among historians is that Nixon had little choice. His hand was forced by the rising costs of the Vietnam Warâone that, like all capitalist wars, had been financed by deficit spending. The United States was in possession of a large proportion of the worldâs gold reserves in its vaults in Fort Knox (though increasingly less in the late 1960s, as other governments, most famously Charles de Gaulleâs France, began demanding gold for their dollars); most poorer countries, in contrast, kept their reserves in dollars. The immediate effect of Nixonâs unpegging the dollar was to cause the price of gold to skyrocket; it hit a peak of $600 an ounce in 1980. This of course had the effect of causing U.S. gold reserves to increase dramatically in value. The value of the dollar, as denominated in gold, plummeted. The result was a massive net transfer of wealth from poor countries, which lacked gold reserves, to rich ones, like the United States and Great Britain, that maintained them. In the United States, it also set off persistent inflation.
Whatever Nixonâs reasons, though, once the global system of credit money was entirely unpegged from gold, the world entered a new phase of financial historyâone that nobody completely understands. While I was growing up in New York, I would hear occasional rumors of secret gold vaults underneath the Twin Towers in Manhattan. Supposedly, these vaults contained not just the U.S. gold reserves, but those of all the major economic powers. The gold was said to be kept in the form of bars, piled up in separate vaults, one for each country, and every year, when the balance of accounts was calculated, workmen with dollies would adjust the stocks accordingly, carting, say, a few million in gold out of the vault marked âBrazilâ and transfering them to the one marked âGermany,â and so on.
Apparently a lot of people had heard these stories. At least, right after the Towers were destroyed on September 11, 2001, one of the first questions many New Yorkers asked was: What happened to the money? Was it safe? Were the vaults destroyed? Presumably, the gold had melted. Was this the real aim of the attackers? Conspiracy theories abounded. Some spoke of legions of emergency workers secretly summoned to make their way through miles of overheated tunnels, desperately carting off tons of bullion even as rescue workers labored overhead. One particularly colorful conspiracy theory suggested that the entire attack was really staged by speculators who, like Nixon, expected to see the value of the dollar crash and that of gold to skyrocketâeither because the reserves had been destroyed, or because they themselves had laid prior plans to steal them.[844]
The truly remarkable thing about this story is that, after having believed it for years, and then, in the wake of 9/11, having been convinced by some more knowing friends that it was all a great myth (âNo,â one of them said resignedly, as if to a child, âthe United States keeps its gold reserves in Fort Knoxâ), I did a little research and discovered that, no, actually, itâs true. The United States treasuryâs gold reserves are indeed kept at Fort Knox, but the Federal Reserveâs gold reserves, and those of more than one hundred other central banks, governments, and organizations, are stored in vaults under the Federal Reserve building at 33 Liberty Street in Manhattan, two blocks away from the Towers. At roughly five thousand metric tons (266 million troy ounces), these combined reserves represent, according to the Fedâs own website, somewhere between one-fifth and one-quarter of all the gold that has ever been taken from the earth.
The gold stored at the Federal Reserve Bank of New York is secured in a most unusual vault. It rests on the bedrock of Manhattan Islandâone of the few foundations considered adequate to support the weight of the vault, its door, and the gold insideâeighty feet below street level and fifty feet below sea level ⊠To reach the vault, bullionladen pallets must be loaded into one of the Bankâs elevators and sent down five floors below street level to the vault floor ⊠If everything is in order, the gold is either moved to one or more of the vaultâs 122 compartments assigned to depositing countries and official international organizations or placed on shelves. âGold stackers,â using hydraulic lifts, do indeed shift them back and forth between compartments to balance credits and debts, though the vaults have only numbers, so even the workers donât know who is paying whom.[845]
There is no reason to believe, however, that these vaults were in any way affected by the events of September 11, 2001.
Reality, then, has become so odd that itâs hard to guess which elements of grand mythic fantasies are really fantasy, and which are true. The image of collapsed vaults, the melted bullion, of secret workers scurrying deep below Manhattan with underground forklifts evacuating the world economyâall this turns out not to be. But is it entirely surprising that people were willing to consider it?[846]
In America, the banking system since the days of Thomas Jefferson has shown a remarkable capacity to inspire paranoid fantasies: whether centering on Freemasons, or Elders of Zion, or the Secret Order of the Illuminati, or the Queen of Englandâs drug-money-laundering operations, or any of a thousand other secret conspiracies and cabals. Itâs the main reason why it took so long for an American central bank to be established to begin with. In a way thereâs nothing surprising here. The United States has always been dominated by a certain market populism, and the ability of banks to âcreate money out of nothingââand even more, to prevent anyone else from doing soâhas always been the bugaboo of market populists, since it directly contradicts the idea that markets are a simple expression of democratic equality. Still, since Nixonâs floating of the dollar, it has become evident that itâs **only** the wizard behind the screen who seems to be maintaining the viability of the whole arrangement. Under the free-market orthodoxy that followed, we have all being asked, effectively, to accept that âthe marketâ is a self-regulating system, with the rising and falling of prices akin to a force of nature, and simultaneously to ignore the fact that, in the business pages, it is simply assumed that markets rise and fall mainly in anticipation of, or reaction to, decisions regarding interest rates by Alan Greenspan, or Ben Bernanke, or whoever is currently the chairman of the Federal Reserve.[847]
One element, however, tends to go flagrantly missing in even the most vivid conspiracy theories about the banking system, let alone in official accounts: that is, the role of war and military power. Thereâs a reason why the wizard has such a strange capacity to create money out of nothing. Behind him, thereâs a man with a gun.
True, in one sense, heâs been there from the start. I have already pointed out that modern money is based on government debt, and that governments borrow money in order to finance wars. This is just as true today as it was in the age of King Phillip II. The creation of central banks represented a permanent institutionalization of that marriage between the interests of warriors and financiers that had already begun to emerge in Renaissance Italy, and that eventually became the foundation of financial capitalism.[848]
Nixon floated the dollar in order to pay for the cost of a war in which, during the period of 1970â1972 alone, he ordered more than four million tons of explosives and incendiaries dropped on cities and villages across Indochinaâcausing one senator to dub him âthe greatest bomber of all time.â[849] The debt crisis was a direct result of the need to pay for the bombs, or to be more precise, the vast military infrastructure required to deliver them. This was what was causing such an enormous strain on the U.S. gold reserves. Many hold that by floating the dollar, Nixon converted the U.S. currency into pure âfiat moneyââmere pieces of paper, intrinsically worthless, that were treated as money only because the United States government insisted that it should be. In that case, one could well argue that U.S. military power was now the only thing backing up the currency. In a certain sense this is true, but the notion of âfiat moneyâ assumes that money really âwasâ gold in the first place. Really we are dealing with another variation of credit money.
Contrary to popular belief, the U.S. government canât âjust print money,â because American money is not issued by the government at all, but by private banks, under the aegis of the Federal Reserve System. The Federal Reserveâdespite the nameâis technically not part of the government at all, but a peculiar sort of public-private hybrid, a consortium of privately owned banks whose chairman is appointed by the United States president, with Congressional approval, but which otherwise operates without public oversight. All dollar bills in circulation in America are âFederal Reserve Notesââthe Fed issues them as promissory notes, and commissions the U.S. mint to do the actual printing, paying it four cents for each bill.[850] The arrangement is just a variation of the scheme originally pioneered by the Bank of England, whereby the Fed âloansâ money to the United States government by purchasing treasury bonds, and then monetizes the U.S. debt by lending the money thus owed by the government to other banks.[851] The difference is that while the Bank of England originally loaned the king gold, the Fed simply whisks the money into existence by saying that itâs there. Thus, itâs the Fed that has the power to print money.[852] The banks that receive loans from the Fed are no longer permitted to print money themselves, but they are allowed to create virtual money by making loans at a fractional reserve rate established by the Fedâthough in the wake of the current credit crisis, at time of this writing, there has been a move to remove even these restrictions.
All this is a bit of a simplification: monetary policy is endlessly arcane, and it does sometimes seem, intentionally so. (Henry Ford once remarked that if ordinary Americans ever found out how the banking system really worked, there would be a revolution tomorrow.) What is remarkable for present purposes is not so much that American dollars are created by banks, but that one apparently paradoxical result of Nixonâs floating the currency was that these bank-created dollars themselves replaced gold as the worldâs reserve currency: that is, as the ultimate store of value in the world, yielding the United States enormous economic advantages.
Meanwhile, the U.S. debt remains, as it has been since 1790, a war debt: the United States continues to spend more on its military than do all other nations on earth put together, and military expenditures are not only the basis of the governmentâs industrial policy; they also take up such a huge proportion of the budget that by many estimations, were it not for them, the United States would not run a deficit at all.
The U.S. military, unlike any other, maintains a doctrine of global power projection: that it should have the ability, through roughly 800 overseas military bases, to intervene with deadly force absolutely anywhere on the planet. In a way, though, land forces are secondary; at least since World War II, the key to U.S. military doctrine has always been a reliance on air power. The United States has fought no war in which it did not control the skies, and it has relied on aerial bombardment far more systematically than any other militaryâin its recent occupation of Iraq, for instance, even going so far as to bomb residential neighborhoods of cities ostensibly under its own control. The essence of U.S. military predominance in the world is, ultimately, the fact that it can, at will, drop bombs, with only a few hoursâ notice, at absolutely any point on the surface of the planet.[853] No other government has ever had anything remotely like this sort of capability. In fact, a case could well be made that it is this very power that holds the entire world monetary system, organized around the dollar, together.
Because of United States trade deficits, huge numbers of dollars circulate outside the country; and one effect of Nixonâs floating of the dollar was that foreign central banks have little they can do with these dollars except to use them to buy U.S. treasury bonds.[854] This is what is meant by the dollar becoming the worldâs âreserve currency.â These bonds are, like all bonds, supposed to be loans that will eventually mature and be repaid, but as economist Michael Hudson, who first began observing the phenomenon in the early â70s, noted, they never really do:
To the extent that these Treasury IOUs are being built into the worldâs monetary base they will not have to be repaid, but are to be rolled over indefinitely. This feature is the essence of Americaâs free financial ride, a tax imposed at the entire globeâs expense.[855]
Whatâs more, over time, the combined effect of low interest payments and the inflation is that these bonds actually depreciate in valueâadding to the tax effect, or as I preferred to put it in the first chapter, âtribute.â Economists prefer to call it âseigniorage.â The effect, though, is that American imperial power is based on a debt that will neverâcan neverâbe repaid. Its national debt has become a promise, not just to its own people, but to the nations of the entire world, that everyone knows will not be kept.
At the same time, U.S. policy was to insist that those countries relying on U.S. treasury bonds as their reserve currency behaved in exactly the opposite way as they did: observing tight money policies and scrupulously repaying their debts.
As Iâve already observed, since Nixonâs time, the most significant overseas buyers of U.S. treasury bonds have tended to be banks in countries that were effectively under U.S. military occupation. In Europe, Nixonâs most enthusiastic ally in this respect was West Germany, which then hosted more than three hundred thousand U.S. troops. In more recent decades the focus has shifted to Asia, particularly the central banks of countries like Japan, Taiwan, and South Koreaâagain, all U.S. military protectorates. Whatâs more, the global status of the dollar is maintained in large part by the fact that it is, again since 1971, the only currency used to buy and sell petroleum, with any attempt by OPEC countries to begin trading in any currency stubbornly resisted by OPEC members Saudi Arabia and Kuwaitâalso U.S. military protectorates. When Saddam Hussein made the bold move of singlehandedly switching from the dollar to the euro in 2000, followed by Iran in 2001, this was quickly followed by American bombing and military occupation.[856] How much Husseinâs decision to buck the dollar really weighed into the U.S. decision to depose him is impossible to know, but no country in a position to make a similar switch can ignore the possibility. The result, among policymakers particularly in the global South, is widespread terror.[857]
In all this, the advent of the free-floating dollar marks not a break with the alliance of warriors and financiers on which capitalism itself was originally founded, but its ultimate apotheosis. Neither has the return to virtual money led to a great return to relations of honor and trust: quite the contrary. By 1971, the change had only just begun. The American Express card, the first general-purpose credit card, had been invented a mere thirteen years before, and the modern national credit-card system had only really come into being with the advent of Visa and MasterCard in 1968. Debit cards were later, creatures of the 1970s, and the current, largely cashless economy only came into being in the 1990s. All of these new credit arrangements were mediated not by interpersonal relations of trust but by profit-seeking corporations, and one of the earliest and greatest political victories of the U.S. credit-card industry was the elimination of all legal restrictions on what they could charge as interest.
If history holds true, an age of virtual money should mean a movement away from war, empire-building, slavery, and debt peonage (waged or otherwise), and toward the creation of some sort of overarching institutions, global in scale, to protect debtors. What we have seen so far is the opposite. The new global currency is rooted in military power even more firmly than the old was. Debt peonage continues to be the main principle of recruiting labor globally: either in the literal sense, in much of East Asia or Latin America, or in the subjective sense, whereby most of those working for wages or even salaries feel that they are doing so primarily to pay off interest-bearing loans. The new transportation and communications technologies have just made it easier, making it possible to charge domestics or factory workers thousands of dollars in transportation fees, and then have them work off the debt in distant countries where they lack legal protections.[858] Insofar as overarching grand cosmic institutions have been created that might be considered in any way parallel to the divine kings of the ancient Middle East or the religious authorities of the Middle Ages, they have not been created to protect debtors, but to enforce the rights of creditors. The International Monetary Fund is only the most dramatic case in point here. It stands at the pinnacle of a great, emerging global bureaucracyâthe first genuinely global administrative system in human history, enshrined not only in the United Nations, the World Bank, and the World Trade Organization, but also the endless host of economic unions and trade organizations and non-governmental organizations that work in tandem with themâcreated largely under U.S. patronage. All of them operate on the principle that (unless one is the United States Treasury), âone has to pay oneâs debtsââsince the specter of default by any country is assumed to imperil the entire world monetary system, threatening, in Addisonâs colorful image, to turn all the worldâs sacks of (virtual) gold into worthless sticks and paper.
All true. Still, we are speaking of a mere forty years here. But Nixonâs gambit, what Hudson calls âdebt imperialism,â has already come under considerable strain. The first casualty was precisely the imperial bureaucracy dedicated to the protection of creditors (other than those that were owed money by the United States). IMF policies of insisting that debts be repaid almost exclusively from the pockets of the poor were met by an equally global movement of social rebellion (the so-called âanti-globalization movementââthough the name is profoundly deceptive), followed by outright fiscal rebellion in both East Asia and Latin America. By 2000, East Asian countries had begun a systematic boycott of the IMF. In 2002, Argentina committed the ultimate sin: they defaultedâand got away with it. Subsequent U.S. military adventures were clearly meant to terrify and overawe, but they do not appear to have been very successful: partly because, to finance them, the United States had to turn not just to its military clients, but increasingly, to China, its chief remaining military rival. After the near-total collapse of the U.S. financial industry, which despite having been very nearly granted rights to make up money at will, **still** managed to end up with trillions in liabilities it could not pay, bringing the world economy to a standstill, eliminating even the pretense that debt imperialism guaranteed stability.
Just to give a sense of how extreme a financial crisis we are talking about, here are some statistical charts culled from the pages of the St. Louis Federal Reserve web page.[859]
Here is the amount of U.S. debt held overseas:
Meanwhile, private U.S. banks reacted to the crash by abandoning any pretense that we are dealing with a market economy, shifting all available assets into the coffers of the Federal Reserve itself, which purchased U.S. Treasuries:
Allowing them, through yet another piece of arcane magic that none of us could possibly understand, to end up, after an initial near-$400-billion dip, with far larger reserves than they had ever had before.
At this point, some U.S. creditors clearly feel they are finally in a position to demand that their own political agendas be taken into account.
CHINA WARNS U.S. ABOUT DEBT MONETIZATION
Seemingly everywhere he went on a recent tour of China, Dallas Fed President Richard Fisher was asked to deliver a message to Federal Reserve Chairman Ben Bernanke: âstop creating credit out of thin air to purchase U.S. Treasuries.â[860]
Again, itâs never clear whether the money siphoned from Asia to support the U.S. war machine is better seen as âloansâ or as âtribute.â Still, the sudden advent of China as a major holder of U.S. treasury bonds has clearly altered the dynamic. Some might question why, if these really are tribute payments, the United Statesâ major rival would be buying treasury bonds to begin withâlet alone agreeing to various tacit monetary arrangements to maintain the value of the dollar, and hence, the buying power of American consumers.[861] But I think this is a perfect case in point of why taking a very long-term historical perspective can be so helpful.
From a longer-term perspective, Chinaâs behavior isnât puzzling at all. In fact itâs quite true to form. The unique thing about the Chinese empire is that it has, since the Han dynasty at least, adopted a peculiar sort of tribute system whereby, in exchange for recognition of the Chinese emperor as world-sovereign, they have been willing to shower their client states with gifts far greater than they receive in return. The technique seems to have been developed almost as a kind of trick when dealing with the ânorthern barbariansâ of the steppes, who always threatened Chinese frontiers: a way to overwhelm them with such luxuries that they would become complacent, effeminate, and unwarlike. It was systematized in the âtribute tradeâ practiced with client states like Japan, Taiwan, Korea, and various states of Southeast Asia, and for a brief period from 1405 to 1433, it even extended to a world scale, under the famous eunuch admiral Zheng He. He led a series of seven expeditions across the Indian Ocean, his great âtreasure fleetââin dramatic contrast to the Spanish treasure fleets of a century laterâcarrying not only thousands of armed marines, but endless quantities of silks, porcelain, and other Chinese luxuries to present to those local rulers willing to recognize the authority of the emperor.[862] All this was ostensibly rooted in an ideology of extraordinary chauvinism (âWhat could these barbarians possibly have that we really need, anyway?â), but, applied to Chinaâs neighbors, it proved extremely wise policy for a wealthy empire surrounded by much smaller but potentially troublesome kingdoms. In fact, it was such wise policy that the U.S. government, during the Cold War, more or less had to adopt it, creating remarkably favorable terms of trade for those very statesâKorea, Japan, Taiwan, certain favored allies in Southeast Asiaâthat had been the traditional Chinese tributaries; in this case, in order to contain China.[863]
Bearing all this in mind, the current picture begins to fall easily back into place. When the United States was far and away the predominant world economic power, it could afford to maintain Chinese-style tributaries. Thus these very states, alone amongst U.S. military protectorates, were allowed to catapult themselves out of poverty and into first-world status.[864] After 1971, as U.S. economic strength relative to the rest of the world began to decline, they were gradually transformed back into a more old-fashioned sort of tributary. Yet Chinaâs getting in on the game introduced an entirely new element. There is every reason to believe that, from Chinaâs point of view, this is the first stage of a very long process of reducing the United States to something like a traditional Chinese client state. And of course, Chinese rulers are not, any more than the rulers of any other empire, motivated primarily by benevolence. There is always a political cost, and what that headline marked was the first glimmerings of what that cost might ultimately be.
All that I have said so far merely serves to underline a reality that has come up constantly over the course of this book: that money has no essence. Itâs not âreallyâ anything; therefore, its nature has always been and presumably always will be a matter of political contention. This was certainly true throughout earlier stages of U.S. history, incidentallyâas the endless nineteenth-century battles between goldbugs, greenbackers, free bankers, bi-metallists and silverites so vividly attestâor, for that matter, the fact that American voters were so suspicious of the very idea of central banks that the Federal Reserve system was only created on the eve of World War I, three centuries after the Bank of England. Even the monetization of the national debt is, as Iâve already noted, double-edged. It can be seenâas Jefferson saw itâas the ultimate pernicious alliance of warriors and financiers; but it also opened the way to seeing government itself as a moral debtor, of freedom as something literally owed to the nation. Perhaps no one put it so eloquently as Martin Luther King Jr., in his âI Have a Dreamâ speech, delivered on the steps of the Lincoln Memorial in 1963:
In a sense weâve come to our nationâs capital to cash a check. When the architects of our republic wrote the magnificent words of the Constitution and the Declaration of Independence, they were signing a promissory note to which every American was to fall heir. This note was a promise that all men, yes, black men as well as white men, would be guaranteed the âunalienable Rightsâ of âLife, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness.â It is obvious today that America has defaulted on this promissory note, insofar as her citizens of color are concerned. Instead of honoring this sacred obligation, America has given the Negro people a bad check, a check which has come back marked âinsufficient funds.â
One can see the great crash of 2008 in the same lightâas the outcome of years of political tussles between creditors and debtors, rich and poor. True, on a certain level, it was exactly what it seemed to be: a scam, an incredibly sophisticated Ponzi scheme designed to collapse in the full knowledge that the perpetrators would be able to force the victims to bail them out. On another level it could be seen as the culmination of a battle over the very definition of money and credit.
By the end of World War II, the specter of an imminent working-class uprising that had so haunted the ruling classes of Europe and North America for the previous century had largely disappeared. This was because class war was suspended by a tacit settlement. To put it crudely: the white working class of the North Atlantic countries, from the United States to West Germany, were offered a deal. If they agreed to set aside any fantasies of fundamentally changing the nature of the system, then they would be allowed to keep their unions, enjoy a wide variety a social benefits (pensions, vacations, health care âŠ), and, perhaps most important, through generously funded and ever-expanding public educational institutions, know that their children had a reasonable chance of leaving the working class entirely. One key element in all this was a tacit guarantee that increases in workersâ productivity would be met by increases in wages: a guarantee that held good until the late 1970s. Largely as a result, the period saw both rapidly rising productivity and rapidly rising incomes, laying the basis for the consumer economy of today.
Economists call this the âKeynesian eraâ since it was a time in which John Maynard Keynesâ economic theories, which already formed the basis of Rooseveltâs New Deal in the United States, were adopted by industrial democracies pretty much everywhere. With them came Keynesâ rather casual attitude toward money. The reader will recall that Keynes fully accepted that banks do, indeed, create money âout of thin air,â and that for this reason, there was no intrinsic reason that government policy should not encourage this during economic downturns as a way of stimulating demandâa position that had long been dear to the heart of debtors and anathema to creditors.
Keynes himself had in his day been known to make some fairly radical noises, for instance calling for the complete elimination of that class of people who lived off other peopleâs debtsâthe âthe euthanasia of the rentier,â as he put itâthough all he really meant by this was their elimination through a gradual reduction of interest rates. As in so much of Keynesianism, this was much less radical than it first appeared. Actually it was thoroughly in the great tradition of political economy, hearkening back to Adam Smithâs ideal of a debtless utopia but especially David Ricardoâs condemnation of landlords as parasites, their very existence inimical to economic growth. Keynes was simply proceeding along the same lines, seeing rentiers as a feudal holdover inconsistent with the true spirit of capital accumulation. Far from a revolution, he saw it as the best way of avoiding one:
I see, therefore, the rentier aspect of capitalism as a transitional phase which will disappear when it has done its work. And with the disappearance of its rentier aspect much else in it besides will suffer a sea-change. It will be, moreover, a great advantage of the order of events which I am advocating, that the euthanasia of the rentier, of the functionless investor, will be nothing sudden ⊠and will need no revolution.[865]
When the Keynesian settlement was finally put into effect, after World War II, it was offered only to a relatively small slice of the worldâs population. As time went on, more and more people wanted in on the deal. Almost all of the popular movements of the period from 1945 to 1975, even perhaps revolutionary movements, could be seen as demands for inclusion: demands for political equality that assumed equality was meaningless without some level of economic security. This was true not only of movements by minority groups in North Atlantic countries who had first been left out of the dealâsuch as those for whom Dr. King spokeâbut what were then called ânational liberationâ movements from Algeria to Chile, or, finally, and perhaps most dramatically, in the late 1960s and 1970s, feminism. At some point in the â70s, things reached a breaking point. It would appear that capitalism, as a system, simply cannot extend such a deal to everyone. Quite possibly it wouldnât even remain viable if all its workers were free wage laborers; certainly it will never be able to provide everyone in the world the sort of life lived by, say, a 1960s auto worker in Michigan or Turin with his own house, garage, and children in collegeâand this was true even before so many of those children began demanding less stultifying lives. The result might be termed a crisis of inclusion. By the late 1970s, the existing order was clearly in a state of collapse, plagued simultaneously by financial chaos, food riots, oil shock, widespread doomsday prophecies of the end of growth and ecological crisisâall of which, it turned out, proved to be ways of putting the populace on notice that all deals were off.
The moment that we start framing the story this way, itâs easy to see that the next thirty years, the period from roughly 1978 to 2009, follows nearly the same pattern. Except that the deal, the settlement, had changed. Certainly, when both Ronald Reagan in the United States and Margaret Thatcher in the UK launched a systematic attack on the power of labor unions, as well as on the legacy of Keynes, it was a way of explicitly declaring that all previous deals were off. Everyone could now have political rightsâeven, by the 1990s, most everyone in Latin America and Africaâbut political rights were to become economically meaningless. The link between productivity and wages was chopped to bits: productivity rates have continued to rise, but wages have stagnated or even atrophied:[866]
This was accompanied, at first, by a return to âmonetarismâ: the doctrine that even though money was no longer in any way based in gold, or in any other commodity, government and central-bank policy should be primarily concerned with carefully controlling the money supply to ensure that it acted **as if** it were a scarce commodity. Even as, at the same time, the financialization of capital meant that most money being invested in the marketplace was completely detached from any relation to production of commerce at all, but had become pure speculation.
All this is not to say that the people of the world were not being offered something: just that, as I say, the terms had changed. In the new dispensation, wages would no longer rise, but workers were encouraged to buy a piece of capitalism. Rather than euthanize the rentiers, **everyone** could now become rentiersâeffectively, could grab a chunk of the profits created by their own increasingly dramatic rates of exploitation. The means were many and familiar. In the United States, there were 401(k) retirement accounts and an endless variety of other ways of encouraging ordinary citizens to play the market; but at the same time, encouraging them to borrow. One of the guiding principles of Thatcherism and Reaganism alike was that economic reforms would never gain widespread support unless ordinary working people could at least aspire to owning their own homes; to this was added, by the 1990s and 2000s, endless mortgage-refinancing schemes that treated houses, whose value it was assumed would only rise, âlike ATMsââas the popular catchphrase had it, though it turns out, in retrospect, it was really more like credit cards. Then there was the proliferation of actual credit cards, juggled against one another. Here, for many, âbuying a piece of capitalismâ slithered undetectably into something indistinguishable from those familiar scourges of the working poor: the loan shark and the pawnbroker. It did not help here that in 1980, U.S. federal usury laws, which had previously limited interest to between 7 and 10 percent, were eliminated by act of Congress. Just as the United States had managed to largely get rid of the problem of political corruption by making the bribery of legislators effectively legal (it was redefined as âlobbyingâ), so the problem of loan-sharking was brushed aside by making real interest rates of 25 percent, 50 percent, or even in some cases (for instance for payday loans) 120 percent annually, once typical only of organized crime, perfectly legalâand therefore, enforceable no longer by just hired goons and the sort of people who place mutilated animals on their victimsâ doorsteps, but by judges, lawyers, bailiffs, and police.[867]
Any number of names have been coined to describe the new dispensation, from the âdemocratization of financeâ to the âfinancialization of everyday life.â[868] Outside the United States, it came to be known as âneoliberalism.â As an ideology, it meant that not just the market, but capitalism (I must continually remind the reader that these are not the same thing) became the organizing principle of almost everything. We were all to think of ourselves as tiny corporations, organized around that same relationship of investor and executive: between the cold, calculating math of the banker, and the warrior who, indebted, has abandoned any sense of personal honor and turned himself into a kind of disgraced machine.
In this world, âpaying oneâs debtsâ can well come to seem the very definition of morality, if only because so many people fail to do it. For instance, it has become a regular feature of many sorts of business in America that large corporations or even some small businesses, faced with a debt, will almost automatically simply see what happens if they do not payâcomplying only if reminded, goaded, or presented with some sort of legal writ. In other words, the principle of honor has thus been almost completely removed from the marketplace.[869] As a result, perhaps, the whole subject of debt becomes surrounded by a halo of religion.
Actually, one might even speak of a double theology, one for the creditors, another for the debtors. It is no coincidence that the new phase of American debt imperialism has also been accompanied by the rise of the evangelical right, whoâin defiance of almost all previously existing Christian theologyâhave enthusiastically embraced the doctrine of âsupply-side economics,â that creating money and effectively giving it to the rich is the most Biblically appropriate way to bring about national prosperity. Perhaps the most ambitious theologian of the new creed was George Gilder, whose book **Wealth and Poverty** became a best-seller in 1981, at the very dawn of what came to be known as the Reagan Revolution. Gilderâs argument was that those who felt that money could not simply be created were mired in an old-fashioned, godless materialism that did not realize that just as God could create something out of nothing, His greatest gift to humanity was creativity itself, which proceeded in exactly the same way. Investors can indeed create value out of nothing by their willingness to accept the risk entailed in placing their faith in othersâ creativity. Rather than seeing the imitation of Godâs powers of creation **ex nihilo** as hubris, Gilder argued that it was precisely what God intended: the creation of money was a gift, a blessing, a channeling of grace; a promise, yes, but not one that can be fulfilled, even if the bonds are continually rolled over, because through faith (âin God we trustâ again) their value becomes reality:
Economists who themselves do not believe in the future of capitalism will tend to ignore the dynamics of chance and faith that largely will determine that future. Economists who distrust religion will always fail to comprehend the modes of worship by which progress is achieved. Chance is the foundation of change and the vessel of the divine.[870]
Such effusions inspired evangelists like Pat Robertson to declare supply-side economics âthe first truly divine theory of money-creation.â[871]
Meanwhile, for those who could not simply create money, there was a quite different theological dispensation. âDebt is the new fat,â Margaret Atwood recently remarked, struck by how much the advertisements that surround her daily on the bus in her native Toronto had abandoned their earlier attempts to make riders panic about the creeping terrors of sexual unattractiveness, but instead turned to providing advice on how to free oneself from the much more immediate terrors of the repo man:
There are even debt TV shows, which have a familiar religious-revival ring to them. There are accounts of shopaholic binges during which you donât know what came over you and everything was a blur, with tearful confessions by those whoâve spent themselves into quivering insomniac jellies of hopeless indebtedness, and have resorted to lying, cheating, stealing, and kiting cheques between bank accounts as a result. There are testimonials by families and loved ones whose lives have been destroyed by the debtorâs harmful behaviour. There are compassionate but severe admonitions by the television host, who here plays the part of priest or revivalist. Thereâs a moment of seeing the light, followed by repentance and a promise never to do it again. Thereâs a penance imposedâ**snip, snip** go the scissors on the credit cardsâfollowed by a strict curb-on-spending regimen; and finally, if all goes well, the debts are paid down, the sins are forgiven, absolution is granted, and a new day dawns, in which a sadder but more solvent man you rise the morrow morn.[872]
Here, risk-taking is in no sense the vessel of the divine. Quite the opposite. But for the poor itâs always different. In a way, what Atwood describes might be seen as the perfect inversion of the prophetic voice of Reverend Kingâs âI Have a Dreamâ speech: whereas the first postwar age was about collective claims on the nationâs debt to its humblest citizens, the need for those who have made false promises to redeem themselves, now those same humble citizens are taught to think of themselves as sinners, seeking some kind of purely individual redemption to have the right to any sort of moral relations with other human beings at all.
At the same time, there is something profoundly deceptive going on here. All these moral dramas start from the assumption that personal debt is ultimately a matter of self-indulgence, a sin against oneâs loved onesâand therefore, that redemption must necessarily be a matter of purging and restoration of ascetic self-denial. Whatâs being shunted out of sight here is first of all the fact that **everyone** is now in debt (U.S. household debt is now estimated at on average 130 percent of income), and that very little of this debt was accrued by those determined to find money to bet on the horses or toss away on fripperies. Insofar as it was borrowed for what economists like to call discretionary spending, it was mainly to be given to children, to share with friends, or otherwise to be able to build and maintain relations with other human beings that are based on **something** other than sheer material calculation.[873] One must go into debt to achieve a life that goes in any way beyond sheer survival.
Insofar as there is a politics, here, it seems a variation on a theme seen since the dawn of capitalism. Ultimately, itâs sociality itself thatâs treated as abusive, criminal, demonic. To this, most ordinary Americansâincluding Black and Latino Americans, recent immigrants, and others who were formerly excluded from creditâhave responded with a stubborn insistence on continuing to love one another. They continue to acquire houses for their families, liquor and sound systems for parties, gifts for friends; they even insist on continuing to hold weddings and funerals, regardless of whether this is likely to send them skirting default or bankruptcyâapparently figuring that, as long as everyone now has to remake themselves as miniature capitalists, why shouldnât they be allowed to create money out of nothing too?
Granted, the role of discretionary spending itself should not be exaggerated. The chief cause of bankruptcy in America is catastrophic illness; most borrowing is simply a matter of survival (if one does not have a car, one cannot work); and increasingly, simply being able to go to college now almost necessarily means debt peonage for at least half oneâs subsequent working life.[874] Still, it is useful to point out that for real human beings survival is rarely enough. Nor should it be.
By the 1990s, the same tensions had begun to reappear on a global scale, as the older penchant for loaning money for grandiose, state-directed projects like the Aswan Dam gave way to an emphasis on microcredit. Inspired by the success of the Grameen Bank in Bangladesh, the new model was to identify budding entrepreneurs in poor communities and provide them with small low-interest loans. âCredit,â the Grameen Bank insisted, âis a human right.â At the same time the idea was to draw on the âsocial capitalââthe knowledge, networks, connections, and ingenuity that the poor people of the world are already using to get by in difficult circumstancesâand convert it into a way of generating even more (expansive) capital, able to grow at 5 to 20 percent annually.
As anthropologists like Julia Elyachar discovered, the result is double-edged. As one unusually candid NGO consultant explained to her in Cairo in 1995:
Money is empowerment. This is empowerment money. You need to be big, need to think big. Borrowers here can be imprisoned if they donât pay, so why be worried?
In America we get ten offers for credit cards in the mail every day. You pay incredible real interest rates for that credit, something like 40 percent. But the offer is there, so you get the card, and stuff your wallet full of credit cards. You feel good. It should be the same thing here, why not help them get into debt? Do I really care what they use the money for, as long as they pay the loan back?[875]
The very incoherence of the quote is telling. The only unifying theme seems to be: people **ought** to be in debt. Itâs good in itself. Itâs empowering. Anyway, if they end up too empowered, we can also have them arrested. Debt and power, sin and redemption, become almost indistinguishable. Freedom is slavery. Slavery is freedom. During her time in Cairo, Elyachar witnessed young graduates of an NGO training program go on strike for their right to receive start-up loans. At the same time, just about everyone involved took it for granted that most of their fellow students, not to mention everyone else involved in the program, was corrupt and exploiting the system as their personal cash cow. Here too, aspects of economic life that had been based on longstanding relations of trust were, through the intrusion of credit bureaucracies, becoming effectively criminalized.
Within another decade, the entire projectâeven in South Asia, where it beganâbegan to appear suspiciously similar to the U.S. subprime mortgage crisis: all sorts of unscrupulous lenders piled in, all sorts of deceptive financial appraisals were passed off to investors, interest accumulated, borrowers tried to collectively refuse payment, lenders began sending in goons to seize what little wealth they had (corrugated tin roofs, for example), and the end result has been an epidemic of suicides by poor farmers caught in traps from which their families could never, possibly, escape.[876]
Just as in the 1945â1975 cycle, this new one culminated in another crisis of inclusion. It proved no more possible to really turn everyone in the world into micro-corporations, or to âdemocratize creditâ in such a way that every family that wanted to could have a house (and if you think about it, if we have the means to build them, why shouldnât they? are there families who donât âdeserveâ houses?) than it had been to allow all wage laborers to have unions, pensions, and health benefits. Capitalism doesnât work that way. It is ultimately a system of power and exclusion, and when it reaches the breaking point, the symptoms recur, just as they had in the 1970s: food riots, oil shock, financial crisis, the sudden startled realization that the current course was ecological unsustainable, attendant apocalyptic scenarios of every sort.
In the wake of the subprime collapse, the U.S. government was forced to decide who really gets to make money out of nothing: the financiers, or ordinary citizens. The results were predictable. Financiers were âbailed out with taxpayer moneyââwhich basically means that their imaginary money was treated as if it were real. Mortgage holders were, overwhelmingly, left to the tender mercies of the courts, under a bankruptcy law that Congress had a year before (rather suspiciously presciently, one might add) made far more exacting against debtors. Nothing was altered. All major decisions were postponed. The Great Conversation that many were expecting never happened.
We live, now, at a genuinely peculiar historical juncture. The credit crisis has provided us with a vivid illustration of the principle set out in the last chapter: that capitalism cannot really operate in a world where people believe it will be around forever.
For most of the last several centuries, most people assumed that credit could not be generated infinitely because they assumed that the economic system itself was unlikely to endure forever. The future was likely to be fundamentally different. Yet somehow, the anticipated revolutions never happened. The basic structures of financial capitalism largely remained in place. Itâs only now, at the very moment when itâs becoming increasingly clear that current arrangements are not viable, that we suddenly have hit the wall in terms of our collective imagination.
There is very good reason to believe that, in a generation or so, capitalism itself will no longer existâmost obviously, as ecologists keep reminding us, because itâs impossible to maintain an engine of perpetual growth forever on a finite planet, and the current form of capitalism doesnât seem to be capable of generating the kind of vast technological breakthroughs and mobilizations that would be required for us to start finding and colonizing any other planets. Yet faced with the prospect of capitalism actually ending, the most common reactionâeven from those who call themselves âprogressivesââis simply fear. We cling to what exists because we can no longer imagine an alternative that wouldnât be even worse.
How did we get here? My own suspicion is that we are looking at the final effects of the militarization of American capitalism itself. In fact, it could well be said that the last thirty years have seen the construction of a vast bureaucratic apparatus for the creation and maintenance of hopelessness, a giant machine designed, first and foremost, to destroy any sense of possible alternative futures. At its root is a veritable obsession on the part of the rulers of the worldâin response to the upheavals of the 1960s and 1970sâwith ensuring that social movements cannot be seen to grow, flourish, or propose alternatives; that those who challenge existing power arrangements can never, under any circumstances, be perceived to win.[877] To do so requires creating a vast apparatus of armies, prisons, police, various forms of private security firms and police and military intelligence apparatus, and propaganda engines of every conceivable variety, most of which do not attack alternatives directly so much as create a pervasive climate of fear, jingoistic conformity, and simple despair that renders any thought of changing the world seem an idle fantasy. Maintaining this apparatus seems even more important, to exponents of the âfree market,â even than maintaining any sort of viable market economy. How else can one explain what happened in the former Soviet Union? One would ordinarily have imagined that the end of the Cold War would have led to the dismantling of the army and the KGB and rebuilding the factories, but in fact what happened was precisely the other way around. This is just an extreme example of what has been happening everywhere. Economically, the apparatus is pure dead weight; all the guns, surveillance cameras, and propaganda engines are extraordinarily expensive and really produce nothing, and no doubt itâs yet another element dragging the entire capitalist system downâalong with producing the illusion of an endless capitalist future that laid the groundwork for the endless bubbles to begin with. Finance capital became the buying and selling of chunks of that future, and economic freedom, for most of us, was reduced to the right to buy a small piece of oneâs own permanent subordination.
In other words, there seems to have been a profound contradiction between the political imperative of establishing capitalism as the only possible way to manage anything, and capitalismâs own unacknowledged need to limit its future horizons lest speculation, predictably, go haywire. Once it did, and the whole machine imploded, we were left in the strange situation of not being able to even imagine any other way that things might be arranged. About the only thing we can imagine is catastrophe.
To begin to free ourselves, the first thing we need to do is to see ourselves again as historical actors, as people who can make a difference in the course of world events. This is exactly what the militarization of history is trying to take away.
Even if we are at the beginning of the turn of a very long historical cycle, itâs still largely up to us to determine how itâs going to turn out. For instance: the last time we shifted from a bullion economy to one of virtual credit money, at the end of the Axial Age and the beginning of the Middle Ages, the immediate shift was experienced largely as a series of great catastrophes. Will it be the same this time around? Presumably a lot depends on how consciously we set out to ensure that it wonât be. Will a return to virtual money lead to a move away from empires and vast standing armies, and to the creation of larger structures limiting the depredations of creditors? There is good reason to believe that all these things will happenâand if humanity is to survive, they will probably have toâbut we have no idea how long it will take, or what, if it does, it would really look like. Capitalism has transformed the world in many ways that are clearly irreversible. What I have been trying to do in this book is not so much to propose a vision of what, precisely, the next age will be like, but to throw open perspectives, enlarge our sense of possibilities; to begin to ask what it would mean to start thinking on a breadth and with a grandeur appropriate to the times.
Let me give an example. Iâve spoken of two cycles of popular movements since World War II: the first (1945â1978), about demanding the rights of national citizenship, the second (1978â2008), over access to capitalism itself. It seems significant here that in the Middle East, in the first round, those popular movements that most directly challenged the global status quo tended to be inspired by Marxism; in the second, largely, some variation on radical Islam. Considering that Islam has always placed debt at the center of its social doctrines, itâs easy to understand the appeal. But why not throw things open even more widely? Over the last five thousand years, there have been at least two occasions when major, dramatic moral and financial innovations have emerged from the country we now refer to as Iraq. The first was the invention of interest-bearing debt, perhaps sometime around 3000 bc; the second, around 800 ad, the development of the first sophisticated commercial system that explicitly rejected it. Is it possible that we are due for another? For most Americans, it will seem an odd question, since most Americans are used to thinking of Iraqis either as victims or fanatics (this is how occupying powers always think about the people they occupy), but it is worthy of note that the most prominent working-class Islamist movement opposed to the U.S. occupation, the Sadrists, take their name from one of the founders of contemporary Islamic economics, Muhammad Baqir al-Sadr. True, much of what has since come to pass for Islamic economics nowadays has proved decidedly unimpressive.[878] Certainly in no sense does it pose a direct challenge to capitalism. Still, one has to assume that among popular movements of this sort, all kinds of interesting conversations about, say, the status of wage labor must be taking place. Or perhaps itâs naĂŻve to look for any new breakthrough from the puritanical legacy of the old patriarchal rebellion. Perhaps it will come out of feminism. Or Islamic feminism. Or from some as yet completely unexpected quarter. Whoâs to say? The one thing we can be confident of is that history is not over, and that surprising new ideas will certainly emerge.
The one thing thatâs clear is that new ideas wonât emerge without the jettisoning of much of our accustomed categories of thoughtâwhich have become mostly sheer dead weight, if not intrinsic parts of the very apparatus of hopelessnessâand formulating new ones. This is why I spent so much of this book talking about the market, but also about the false choice between state and market that so monopolized political ideology for the last centuries that it made it difficult to argue about anything else.
The real history of markets is nothing like what weâre taught to think it is. The earlier markets that we are able to observe appear to be spillovers, more or less; side effects of the elaborate administrative systems of ancient Mesopotamia. They operated primarily on credit. Cash markets arose through war: again, largely through tax and tribute policies that were originally designed to provision soldiers, but that later became useful in all sorts of other ways besides. It was only the Middle Ages, with their return to credit systems, that saw the first manifestations of what might be called market populism: the idea that markets could exist beyond, against, and outside of states, as in those of the Muslim Indian Oceanâan idea that was later to reappear in China with the great silver revolts of the fifteenth century. It usually seems to arise in situations where merchants, for one reason or another, find themselves making common cause with common people against the administrative machinery of some great state. But market populism is always riddled with paradoxes, because it still does depend to some degree on the existence of that state, and above all, because it requires founding market relations, ultimately, in something other than sheer calculation: in the codes of honor, trust, and ultimately community and mutual aid, more typical of human economies.[879] This in turn means relegating competition to a relatively minor element. In this light, we can see that what Adam Smith ultimately did, in creating his debt-free market utopia, was to fuse elements of this unlikely legacy with that unusually militaristic conception of market behavior characteristic of the Christian West. In doing so he was surely prescient. But like all extraordinarily influential writers, he was also just capturing something of the emerging spirit of his age. What we have seen ever since is an endless political jockeying back and forth between two sorts of populismâstate and market populismâwithout anyone noticing that they were talking about the left and right flanks of exactly the same animal.
The main reason that weâre unable to notice, I think, is that the legacy of violence has twisted everything around us. War, conquest, and slavery not only played the central role in converting human economies into market ones; there is literally no institution in our society that has not been to some degree affected. The story told at the end of chapter 7, of how even our conceptions of âfreedomâ itself came to be transformed, through the Roman institution of slavery, from the ability to make friends, to enter into moral relations with others, into incoherent dreams of absolute power, is only perhaps the most dramatic instanceâand most insidious, because it leaves it very hard to imagine what meaningful human freedom would even be like.[880]
If this book has shown anything, itâs exactly how much violence it has taken, over the course of human history, to bring us to a situation where itâs even possible to imagine that thatâs what life is really about. Especially when one considers how much of our own daily experience flies directly in the face of it. As Iâve emphasized, communism may be the foundation of all human relationsâthat communism that, in our own daily life, manifests itself above all in what we call âloveââbut thereâs always some sort of system of exchange, and usually, a system of hierarchy built on top of it. These systems of exchange can take an endless variety of forms, many perfectly innocuous. Still, what we are speaking of here is a very particular type of calculating exchange. As I pointed out in the very beginning: the difference between owing someone a favor, and owing someone a debt, is that the amount of a debt can be precisely calculated. Calculation demands equivalence. And such equivalenceâespecially when it involves equivalence between human beings (and it always seems to start that way, because at first, human beings are always the ultimate values)âonly seems to occur when people have been forcibly severed from their contexts, so much so that they can be treated as identical to something else, as in: âseven martin skins and twelve large silver rings for the return of your captured brother,â âone of your three daughters as surety for this loan of one hundred and fifty bushels of grainâ âŠ
This in turn leads to that great embarrassing fact that haunts all attempts to represent the market as the highest form of human freedom: that historically, impersonal, commercial markets originate in theft. More than anything else, the endless recitation of the myth of barter, employed much like an incantation, is the economistsâ way of fending off any possibility of having to confront it. But even a momentâs reflection makes it obvious. Who was the first man to look at a house full of objects and to immediately assess them only in terms of what he could trade them in for in the market likely to have been? Surely, he can only have been a thief. Burglars, marauding soldiers, then perhaps debt collectors, were the first to see the world this way. It was only in the hands of soldiers, fresh from looting towns and cities, that chunks of gold or silverâmelted down, in most cases, from some heirloom treasure, that like the Kashmiri gods, or Aztec breastplates, or Babylonian womenâs ankle bracelets, was both a work of art and a little compendium of historyâcould become simple, uniform bits of currency, with no history, valuable precisely for their lack of history, because they could be accepted anywhere, no questions asked. And it continues to be true. Any system that reduces the world to numbers can only be held in place by weapons, whether these are swords and clubs, or nowadays, âsmart bombsâ from unmanned drones.
It can also only operate by continually converting love into debt. I know my use of the word âloveâ here is even more provocative, in its own way, than âcommunism.â Still, itâs important to hammer the point home. Just as markets, when allowed to drift entirely free from their violent origins, invariably begin to grow into something different, into networks of honor, trust, and mutual connectedness, so does the maintenance of systems of coercion constantly do the opposite: turn the products of human cooperation, creativity, devotion, love, and trust back into numbers once again. In doing so, they make it possible to imagine a world that is nothing more than a series of cold-blooded calculations. Even more, by turning human sociality itself into debts, they transform the very foundations of our beingâsince what else are we, ultimately, except the sum of the relations we have with othersâinto matters of fault, sin, and crime, and making the world into a place of iniquity that can only be overcome by completing some great cosmic transaction that will annihilate everything.
Trying to flip things around by asking, âWhat do we owe society?â or even trying to talk about our âdebt to natureâ or some other manifestation of the cosmos is a false solutionâreally just a desperate scramble to salvage something from the very moral logic that has severed us from the cosmos to begin with. In fact, itâs if anything the culmination of the process, the process brought to a point of veritable dementia, since itâs premised on the assumption that weâre so absolutely, thoroughly disentangled from the world that we can just toss all other human beingsâor all other living creatures, even, or the cosmosâin a sack, and then start negotiating with them. Itâs hardly surprising that the end result, historically, is to see our life itself as something we hold on false premises, a loan long since overdue, and therefore, to see existence itself as criminal. Insofar as thereâs a real crime here, though, itâs fraud. The very premise is fraudulent. What could possibly be more presumptuous, or more ridiculous, than to think it would be possible to negotiate with the grounds of oneâs existence? Of course it isnât. Insofar as it is indeed possible to come into any sort of relation with the Absolute, we are confronting a principle that exists outside of time, or human-scale time, entirely; therefore, as Medieval theologians correctly recognized, when dealing with the Absolute, there can be no such thing as debt.
Much of the existing economic literature on credit and banking, when it turns to the kind of larger historical questions treated in this book, strikes me as little more than special pleading. True, earlier figures like Adam Smith and David Ricardo were suspicious of credit systems, but already by the midânineteenth century, economists who concerned themselves with such matters were largely in the business of trying to demonstrate that, despite appearances, the banking system really was profoundly democratic. One of the more common arguments was that it was really a way of funneling resources from the âidle rich,â who, too unimaginative to do the work of investing their own money, entrusted it to others, to the âindustrious poorââwho had the energy and initiative to produce new wealth. This justified the existence of banks, but it also strengthened the hand of populists who demanded easy money policies, protections for debtors, and so onâsince, if times were rough, why should the industrious poor, the farmers and artisans and small businessmen, be the ones to suffer?
This gave rise to a second line of argument: that no doubt the rich were the major creditors in the ancient world, but now the situation has been reversed. So Ludwig von Mises, writing in the 1930s, around the time when Keynes was calling for the euthanasia of the rentiers:
Public opinion has always been biased against creditors. It identifies creditors with the idle rich and debtors with the industrious poor. It abhors the former as ruthless exploiters and pities the latter as innocent victims of oppression. It considers government action designed to curtail the claims of the creditors as measures extremely beneficial to the immense majority at the expense of a small minority of hardboiled usurers. It did not notice at all that nineteenth-century capitalist innovations have wholly changed the composition of the classes of creditors and debtors. In the days of Solon the Athenian, of ancient Romeâs agrarian laws, and of the Middle Ages, the creditors were by and large the rich and the debtors the poor. But in this age of bonds and debentures, mortgage banks, saving banks, life insurance policies, and social security benefits, the masses of people with more moderate income are rather themselves creditors.[881]
Whereas the rich, with their leveraged companies, are now the principal debtors. This is the âdemocratization of financeâ argument and it is nothing new: whenever there are some people calling for the elimination of the class that lives by collecting interest, there will be others to object that this will destroy the livelihood of widows and pensioners.
The remarkable thing is that nowadays, defenders of the financial system are often prepared to use both arguments, appealing to one or the other according to the rhetorical convenience of the moment. On the one hand, we have âpunditsâ like Thomas Friedman, celebrating the fact that âeveryoneâ now owns a piece of Exxon or Mexico, and that rich debtors are therefore answerable to the poor. On the other, Niall Ferguson, author of **The Ascent of Money**, published in 2009, can still announce as one of his major discoveries that:
Poverty is not the result of rapacious financiers exploiting the poor. It has much more to do with the lack of financial institutions, with the absence of banks, not their presence. Only when borrowers have access to efficient credit networks can they escape from the clutches of loan sharks, and only when savers can deposit their money in reliable banks can it be channeled from the idle rich to the industrious poor.[882]
Such is the state of the conversation in the mainstream literature. My purpose here has been less to engage with it directly than to show how it has consistently encouraged us to ask the wrong questions. Letâs take this last paragraph as an illustration. What is Ferguson really saying here? Poverty is caused by a lack of credit. Itâs only if the industrious poor have access to loans from stable, respectable banksârather than to loan sharks, or, presumably, credit card companies, or payday loan operations, which now charge loan-shark ratesâthat they can rise out of poverty. So actually Ferguson is not really concerned with âpovertyâ at all, just with the poverty of some people, those who are industrious and thus do not deserve to be poor. What about the non-industrious poor? They can go to hell, presumably (quite literally, according to many branches of Christianity). Or maybe their boats will be lifted somewhat by the rising tide. Still, thatâs clearly incidental. Theyâre undeserving, since theyâre not industrious, and therefore what happens to them is really beside the point.
For me, this is exactly whatâs so pernicious about the morality of debt: the way that financial imperatives constantly try to reduce us all, despite ourselves, to the equivalent of pillagers, eyeing the world simply for what can be turned into moneyâand then tell us that itâs only those who are willing to see the world as pillagers who deserve access to the resources required to pursue anything in life **other** than money. It introduces moral perversions on almost every level. (âCancel all student loan debt? But that would be unfair to all those people who struggled for years to pay back their student loans!â Let me assure the reader that, as someone who struggled for years to pay back his student loans and finally did so, this argument makes about as much sense as saying it would be âunfairâ to a mugging victim not to mug their neighbors too.)
The argument might perhaps make sense if one agreed with the underlying assumptionâthat work is by definition virtuous, since the ultimate measure of humanityâs success as a species is its ability to increase the overall global output of goods and services by at least 5 percent per year. The problem is that it is becoming increasingly obvious that if we continue along these lines much longer, weâre likely to destroy everything. That giant debt machine that has, for the last five centuries, reduced increasing proportions of the worldâs population to the moral equivalent of conquistadors would appear to be coming up against its social and ecological limits. Capitalismâs inveterate propensity to imagine its own destruction has morphed, in the last half-century, into scenarios that threaten to bring the rest of the world down with it. And thereâs no reason to believe that this propensity is ever going to go away. The real question now is how to ratchet things down a bit, to move toward a society where people can live more by working less.
I would like, then, to end by putting in a good word for the non-industrious poor.[883] At least they arenât hurting anyone. Insofar as the time they are taking time off from work is being spent with friends and family, enjoying and caring for those they love, theyâre probably improving the world more than we acknowledge. Maybe we should think of them as pioneers of a new economic order that would not share our current oneâs penchant for self-destruction.
In this book I have largely avoided making concrete proposals, but let me end with one. It seems to me that we are long overdue for some kind of Biblical-style Jubilee: one that would affect both international debt and consumer debt. It would be salutary not just because it would relieve so much genuine human suffering, but also because it would be our way of reminding ourselves that money is not ineffable, that paying oneâs debts is not the essence of morality, that all these things are human arrangements and that if democracy is to mean anything, it is the ability to all agree to arrange things in a different way. It is significant, I think, that since Hammurabi, great imperial states have invariably resisted this kind of politics. Athens and Rome established the paradigm: even when confronted with continual debt crises, they insisted on legislating around the edges, softening the impact, eliminating obvious abuses like debt slavery, using the spoils of empire to throw all sorts of extra benefits at their poorer citizens (who, after all, provided the rank and file of their armies), so as to keep them more or less afloatâbut all in such a way as never to allow a challenge to the principle of debt itself. The governing class of the United States seems to have taken a remarkably similar approach: eliminating the worst abuses (e.g., debtorsâ prisons), using the fruits of empire to provide subsidies, visible and otherwise, to the bulk of the poulation; in more recent years, manipulating currency rates to flood the country with cheap goods from China, but never allowing anyone to question the sacred principle that we must all pay our debts.
At this point, however, the principle has been exposed as a flagrant lie. As it turns out, we donât âallâ have to pay our debts. Only some of us do. Nothing would be more important than to wipe the slate clean for everyone, mark a break with our accustomed morality, and start again.
What is a debt, anyway? A debt is just the perversion of a promise. It is a promise corrupted by both math and violence. If freedom (real freedom) is the ability to make friends, then it is also, necessarily, the ability to make real promises. What sorts of promises might genuinely free men and women make to one another? At this point we canât even say. Itâs more a question of how we can get to a place that will allow us to find out. And the first step in that journey, in turn, is to accept that in the largest scheme of things, just as no one has the right to tell us our true value, no one has the right to tell us what we truly owe.
[1] With the predictable results that they werenât actually built to make it easier for Malagasy people to get around in their own country, but mainly to get products from the plantations to ports to earn foreign exchange to pay for building the roads and railways to begin with.
[2] The United States, for example, only recognized the Republic of Haiti in 1860. France doggedly held on to the demand and the Republic of Haiti was finally forced to pay the equivalent of $21 billion between 1925 and 1946, during most of which time they were under U.S. military occupation.
[3] Hallam 1866 V: 269â70. Since the government did not feel it appropriate to pay for the upkeep of improvidents, prisoners were expected to furnish the full cost of their own imprisonment. If they couldnât, they simply starved to death.
[4] If we consider tax responsibilities to be debts, itâs the overwhelming majorityâand if nothing else the two are closely related, since over the course history, the need to assemble money for tax payments has always been the most frequent reason for falling into debt.
[5] Finley 1960:63; 1963:24; 1974:80; 1981:106; 1983:108. And these are only the ones I managed to track down. What he says for Greece and Rome would appear to be equally true of Japan, India, or China.
[6] Galey 1983.
[7] Jacques de Vitry, in Le Goff 1990:64.
[8] Kyokai, **Record of Miraculous Events in Japan** (c. 822 ad), Tale 26, cited in LaFleur 1986:36. Also Nakamura 1996:257â59.
[9] ibid:36
[10] ibid:37.
[11] Simon Johnson, the IMFâs chief economist at the time, put it concisely in a recent article in **The Atlantic:** âRegulators, legislators, and academics almost all assumed that the managers of these banks knew what they were doing. In retrospect, they didnât. AIGâs Financial Products division, for instance, made $2.5 billion in pretax profits in 2005, largely by selling underpriced insurance on complex, poorly understood securities. Often described as âpicking up nickels in front of a steamroller,â this strategy is profitable in ordinary years, and catastrophic in bad ones. As of last fall, AIG had outstanding insurance on more than $400 billion in securities. To date, the U.S. government, in an effort to rescue the company, has committed about $180 billion in investments and loans to cover losses that AIGâs sophisticated risk modeling had said were virtually impossible.â (Johnson 2010) Johnson of course passes over the possibility that AIG knew perfectly well what was eventually going to happen, but simply didnât care, since they knew the steamroller was going to flatten someone else.
[12] In contrast, England already had a national bankruptcy law in 1571. An attempt to create a U.S. federal bankruptcy law in 1800 foundered; there was one briefly in place between 1867 and 1878, aimed to relieve indebted Civil War veterans, but it was eventually abolished on moral grounds (see Mann 2002 for a good recent history). Bankruptcy reform in America is more likely to make the terms harsher than the other way around, as with the 2005 reforms, which Congress passed, on industry urgings, just before the great credit crash.
[13] The mortgage relief fund set up after the bailout, for example, has only provided aid to a tiny percentage of claimants, and there has been no movement toward liberalization of bankruptcy laws that had, in fact, been made far harsher, under financial industry pressure, in 2005, just two years before the meltdown.
[14] âIn Jail for Being in Debt,â Chris Serres & Glenin Howatt, Minneapolis-St. Paul **Star Tribune**, June 9, 2010, [[http://www.startribune.com/local/95692619.html][www.startribune.com/local/95692619.html]].
[15] âIMF warns second bailout would âthreaten democracy.â â Angela Jameson and Elizabeth Judge, [[http://www.business.timesonline.co.uk/tol/business/economics/article6928147.ece#cid=OTC-RSS&attr=1185799][business.timesonline.co.uk/tol/business/economics/article6928147.ece#cid=OTC-RSS&attr=1185799]], accessed November 25, 2009
[16] Case, Fair, GĂ€rtner, & Heather 1996:564. Emphasis in the original.
[17] op cit.
[18] Begg, Fischer, and Dornbuch (2005:384); Maunder, Myers, Wall, and Miller (1991:310); Parkin & King (1995:65).
[19] Stiglitz and Driffill 2000:521. Emphasis again in the original.
[20] Aristotle **Politics I**.9.1257
[21] Neither is it clear we are really speaking of barter here. Aristotle used the term **mĂ©tadosis**, which in his day normally meant âsharingâ or âsharing out.â Since Smith, this has usually been translated âbarter,â but as Karl Polanyi (1957a:93) has long since emphasized, this is probably inaccurate, unless Aristotle was introducing an entirely new meaning for the term. Theorists of the origin of Greek money from Laum (1924) to Seaford (2004) have emphasized that customs of apportioning goods (e.g., war booty, sacrificial meat), probably did play a key role in the development of Greek currency. (For a critique of the Aristotelian tradition, which does assume Aristotle is talking about barter, see Fahazmanesh 2006.)
[22] See Jean-Michel Servet (1994, 2001) for this literature. He also notes that in the eighteenth century, these accounts suddenly vanished, to be replaced by endless sightings of âprimitive barterâ in accounts of Oceania, Africa, and the Americas.
[23] **Wealth of Nations I**.2.1â2. As weâll see, the line seems to be taken from much older sources.
[24] âIf we should enquire into the principle of human mind on which this disposition of trucking is founded, it is clearly the natural inclination every one has to persuade. The offering of a shilling, which to us appears to have so plain and simple meaning, is in reality offering an argument to persuade one to do so and so as it is for his interestâ **(Lectures on Jurisprudence**, 56) Itâs fascinating to note that the assumption that the notion that exchange is the basis of our mental functions, and manifests itself both in language (as the exchange of words) and economics (as the exchange of material goods) goes back to Smith. Most anthropologists attribute it to Claude Levi-Strauss (1963:296).
[25] The reference to shepherds implies he may be referring to another part of the world, but elsewhere his examples, for instance of trading deer for beaver, make it clear heâs thinking of the Northeast woodlands of North America.
[26] Wealth of Nations I.4.2.
[27] Wealth of Nations I.4.3.
[28] Wealth of Nations I.4.7.
[29] The idea of an historical sequence from barter to money to credit actually seems to appear first in the lectures of an Italian banker named Bernardo Davanzati (1529â1606; so Waswo 1996); it was developed as an explicit theory by German economic historians: Bruno Hildebrand (1864), who posited a prehistoric stage of barter, an ancient stage of coinage, and then, after some reversion to barter in the Middle Ages, a modern stage of credit economy. It took canonical form in the work of his student, Karl BĂŒcher (1907). The sequence has now become universally accepted common sense, and it reappears in at least tacit form in Marx, and explicitly in Simmelâagain, despite the fact that almost all subsequent historical research has proved it wrong.
[30] Though they did make an impression on many others. Morganâs work in particular (1851, 1877, 1881), which emphasized both collective property rights and the extraordinary importance of women, with womenâs councils largely in control of economic life, so impressed many radical thinkersâincluded Marx and Engelsâthat they became the basis of a kind of counter-myth, of primitive communism and primitive matriarchy.
[31] Anne Chapman (1980) goes if anything further, noting that if pure barter is to be defined as concerned only with swapping objects, and not with rearranging relations between people, itâs not clear that it has ever existed. See also Heady 2005.
[32] Levi-Strauss 1943; the translation is from Servet 1982:33.
[33] One must imagine the temptation for a sexual variety must be fairly strong, for young men and women accustomed to spending almost all of their time with maybe a dozen other people the same age.
[34] Berndt 1951:161, cf. Gudeman 2001: 124â25, who provides an analysis quite similar to my own.
[35] Berndt 1951:162.
[36] Though as we will note later, itâs not exactly as if international business deals now never involve music, dancing, food, drugs, high-priced hookers, or the possibility of violence. For a random example underlining the last two, see Perkins 2005.
[37] Lindholm 1982:116.
[38] Servet 2001:20-21 compiles an enormous number of such terms.
[39] The point is so obvious that itâs amazing it hasnât been made more often. The only classical economist Iâm aware of who appears to have considered the possibility that deferred payments might have made barter unnecessary is Ralph Hawtrey (1928:2, cited in Einzig 1949:375). All others simply assume, for no reason, that all exchanges even between neighbors must have necessarily been what economists like to call âspot trades.â
[40] Bohannan 1955, Barth 1969. cf. Munn 1986, Akin & Robbins 1998. A good summary of the concept can be found in Gregory 1982:48â49. Gregory gives one example of a highland Papua New Guinea system with six ranks of valuables, with live pigs and cassowary birds on the top rank, âpearl-shell pendants, pork sides, stone axes, cassowary-plume headdresses, and cowrie-shell headbandsâ on the second, and so on. Ordinarily items of items of consumption are confined to the last two, which consist of luxury foods and staple vegetable foods, respectively.
[41] See Servet 1998, Humphries 1985.
[42] The classic essay here is Radford 1945.
[43] In the 1600s, at least, actually called the old Carolingian denominations âimaginary moneyââeveryone persisting in using pounds, shillings, and pence (or livres, deniers, and sous) for the intervening 800 years, despite the fact that for most of that period, actual coins were entirely different, or simply didnât exist (Einaudi 1936).
[44] Other examples of barter coexisting with money: Orlove 1986; Barnes & Barnes 1989.
[45] One of the disadvantages of having your book becomes a classic is that often, people will actually check out such examples. (One of the advantages is that even if they discover you were mistaken, people will continue to cite you as an authority anyway.)
[46] Innes 1913:378. He goes on to observe: âA momentâs reflection shows that a staple commodity could not be used as money, because **ex hypothesi**, the medium of exchange is equally receivable by all members of the community. Thus if the fishers paid for their supplies in cod, the traders would equally have to pay for their cod in cod, an obvious absurdity.â
[47] The temples appear to have come first; the palaces, which became increasingly important over time, took over their system of administration.
[48] Smith was not dreaming about these: the current technical term for such ingots is âhacksilberâ (e.g., Balmuth 2001).
[49] Compare Grierson 1977:17 for Egyptian parallels.
[50] e.g., Hudson 2002:25, 2004:114
[51] Innes 1913:381
[52] Peter Spuffordâs monumental **Money and Its Use in Medieval Europe** (1988), which devotes hundreds of pages to gold and silver mining, mints, and debasement of coinage, makes only two or three mentions of various sorts of lead or leather token money or minor credit arrangements by which ordinary people appear to have conducted the overwhelming majority of their daily transactions. About these, he says, âwe can know next to nothingâ (1988:336). An even more dramatic example is the tally-stick, of which we will hear a good deal: the use of tallies instead of cash was widespread in the Middle Ages, but there has been almost no systematic research on the subject, especially outside England.
[53] Heinsohn & Steiger (1989) even suggest the main reason their fellow economists havenât abandoned the story is that anthropologists have not yet provided an equally compelling alternative. Still, almost all histories of money continue to begin with fanciful accounts of barter. Another expedient is to fall back on pure circular definitions: if âbarterâ is an economic transaction that does not employ currency, then any economic transaction that doesnât involve currency, whatever its form or content, must be barter. Glyn Davies (1996:11â13) thus describes even Kwakiutl potlatches as âbarter.â
[54] We often forget that there was a strong religious element in all this. Newton himself was in no sense an atheistâin fact, he tried to use his mathematical abilities to confirm that the world really had been created, as Bishop Ussher had earlier argued, sometime around October 23, 4004 bc.
[55] Smith first uses the phrase âinvisible handâ in his **Astronomy** (III.2), but in **Theory of Moral Sentiments** IV.1.10, he is explicit that the invisible hand of the market is that of âProvidence.â On Smithâs theology in general see Nicholls 2003:35â43; on its possible connection to Medieval Islam, see chapter 10 below.
[56] Samuelson 1948:49. See Heinsohn and Steiger 1989 for a critique of this position; also Ingham 2004.
[57] Pigou 1949. Boianovsky 1993 provides a history of the term.
[58] âWe do not know of any economy in which systematic barter takes place without the presence of moneyâ (Fayazmanesh 2006:87)âby which he means, in the sense of money of account.
[59] On the government role of fostering the âself-regulating marketâ in general, see Polanyi 1949. The standard economic orthodoxy, that if the government just gets out of the way, a market will naturally emerge, without any need to create appropriate legal, police, and political institutions first, was dramatically disproved when free-market ideologues tried to impose this model in the former Soviet Union in the 1990s.
[60] Innes as usual puts it nicely: âThe eye has never seen, nor the hand touched a dollar. All that we can touch or see is a promise to pay or satisfy a debt due for an amount called a dollar.â In the same way, he notes, âAll our measures are the same. No one has ever seen on ounce or a foot or an hour. A foot is the distance between two fixed points, but neither the distance nor the points have a corporeal existenceâ (1914:155).
[61] Note that this does assume some means of calculating such valuesâthat is, that money of account of some sort already exists. This might seem obvious, but remarkable numbers of anthropologists seem to have missed it.
[62] To give some sense of scale, even the relatively circumscribed commercial city-state of Hong Kong currently has roughly $23.3 billion in circulation. At roughly 7 million people, thatâs more than three thousand Hong Kong dollars per inhabitant.
[63] âState theory may be traced to the early nineteenth century and to [Adam] Mullerâs **New Theory of Money**, which attempted to explain money value as an expression of communal trust and national will, and culminated in [G.F.] Knappâs **State Theory of Money**, first published in German in 1905. Knapp considered it absurd to attempt to understand money âwithout the idea of the state.â Money is not a medium that emerges from exchange. It is rather a means for accounting for and settling debts, the most important of which are tax debtsâ (Ingham 2004:47.) Inghamâs book is an admirable statement of the Chartalist position, and much of my argument here can be found in much greater detail in it. However, as will later become apparent, I also part company with him in certain respects.
[64] In French: livres, sous, and deniers.
[65] Einaudi 1936. Cipolla (1967) calls it âghost money.â
[66] On tallies: Jenkinson 1911, 1924; Innes 1913; Grandell 1977; Baxter 1989; Stone 2005.
[67] Snell (1919:240) notes that kings while touring their domains would sometimes seize cattle or other goods by right of âpreemptionâ and then pay in tallies, but it was very difficult to get their representatives to later pay up: âSubjects were compelled to sell; and the worst of it was that the Kingâs purveyors were in the habit of paying not in cash down, but by means of an exchequer tally, or a beating ⊠In practice it was found no easy matter to recover under this system, which lent itself to the worst exactions, and is the subject of numerous complaints in our early popular poetry.â
[68] It is also interesting to note, in this regard, that the Bank of England still kept their own internal accounts using tally sticks in Adam Smithâs time, and only abandoned the practice in 1826.
[69] See Engels (1978) for a classic study of this sort of problem.
[70] Appealing particularly to debtors, who were understandably drawn to the idea that debt is simply a social arrangement that was in no sense immutable but created by government policies that could just as easily be reshuffledânot to mention, who would benefit from inflationary policies.
[71] On the tax, Jacob 1987; for the Betsimisaraka village study, Althabe 1968; for analogous Malagasy case studies, Fremigacci 1976, Rainibe 1982, Schlemmer 1983, Feeley-Harnik 1991. For colonial tax policy in Africa more generally, Forstater 2005, 2006.
[72] So, for instance, Heinsohn & Steiger 1989:188â189.
[73] Silver was mined in the Midwest itself, and adopting bi-metallism, with both gold and silver as potential backing for currency, was seen as a move in the direction of free credit money, and to allow for the creation of money by local banks. The late nineteenth century saw the first creation of modern corporate capitalism in the United States and it was fervently resisted, with the centralization of the banking system being a major field of struggle, and mutualismâpopular democratic (not profit oriented) banking and insurance arrangementsâone of the main forms of resistance. The bi-metallists were the more moderate successors of the Greenbackers, who called for a currency detached from money altogether, such as Lincoln briefly imposed in wartime (Dighe (2002) provides a good summary of the historical background.)
[74] They only became ruby slippers in the movie.
[75] Some have even suggested that Dorothy herself represents Teddy Roosevelt, since syllabically, âdor-o-theeâ is the same as âthee-o-dorâ, only backwards.
[76] See Littlefield 1963 and Rockoff 1990 for a detailed argument about **The Wizard of Oz** as âmonetary allegory.â Baum never admitted that the book had a political subtext, but even those who doubt he put one in intentionally (e.g., Parker 1994; cf. Taylor 2005) admit that such a meaning was quickly attributed to itâthere were already explicit political references in the stage version of 1902, only two years after the bookâs original publication.
[77] Reagan could as easily be argued to be a practitioner of extreme military Keynesianism, using the Pentagonâs budget to create jobs and drive economic growth; anyway, monetary orthodoxy was abandoned very quickly even rhetorically among those actually managing the system.
[78] See Ingham 2000.
[79] Keynes 1930: 4â5
[80] The argument is referred to as the paradox of banking. To provide an extremely simplified version: say there was only one bank. Even if that bank were to make you a loan of a trillion dollars based on no assets of its own of any kind whatever, you would ultimately end up putting the money back into the bank again, which would mean that the bank would now have one trillion in debt, and one trillion in working assets, perfectly balancing each other out. If the bank was charging you more for the loan than it was giving you in interest (which banks always do), it would also make a profit. The same would be true if you spent the trillionâwhoever ended up with the money would still have to put it into the bank again. Keynes pointed out the existence of multiple banks didnât really change anything, provided bankers coordinated their efforts, which, in fact, they always do.
[81] I might note that this assumption echoes the logic of neoclassical economic theory, which assumes that all basic institutional arrangements that define the context of economic activity were agreed to by all parties at some imaginary point in the past, and that since then, everything has and will always continue to exist in equilibrium. Interestingly, Keynes explicitly rejected this assumption in his theory of money (Davidson 2006). Contemporary social contract theorists incidentally make a similar argument, that thereâs no need to assume that this actually happened; itâs enough to say it could have and act as if it did.
[82] Aglietta is a Marxist, and one of the founders of the âRegulation School,â OrlĂ©ans, an adherent of the âeconomics of conventionâ favored by Thevenot and Boltanski. Primordial debt theory has been mainly developed by a group of researchers surrounding economists Michel Aglietta and AndrĂ© OrlĂ©ans, first in **La Violence de la Monnaie** (1992), which employed a psychoanalytic, Giradian framework, and then in a volume called **Sovereignty, Legitimacy and Money** (1995) and a collection called **Sovereign Money** (Aglietta, Andreau, etc. 1998), co-edited by eleven different scholars. The latter two volumes abandon the Girardian framework for a Dumontian one. In recent years the main exponent of this position has been another Regulationist, Bruno ThĂ©ret (1992, 1995, 2007, 2008). Unfortunately almost none of this material has ever been translated into English, though a summary of many of Agliettaâs contributions can be found in Grahl (2000).
[83] For instance, Randall Wray (1990, 1998, 2000) and Stephanie Bell (1999, 2000) in the United States, or Geoffrey Ingham (1996, 1999, 2004) in the United Kingdom. Michael Hudson and others in the ISCANEE group have taken up elements of the idea, but have never to my knowledge fully embraced it.
[84] **<verbatim>*rna</verbatim>**. Malamoud (1983:22) notes that already in the earliest text it had both the meaning of âgoods received in return for the promise to hand back either the goods themselves or something of at least equivalent valueâ, as well as âcrimeâ or âfault.â So also Olivelle 1993:48, who notes **<verbatim>*rna</verbatim>** âcan mean fault, crime, or guiltâoften at the same time.â It is not however the same as the word for âduty.â For a typical example of early prayers for release from debt, see Atharva Veda Book 6 Hymns 117, 118, and 119.
[85] **Satapatha Brahmana** 3.6.2.16
[86] As Sylvain LĂ©vi, Marcel Maussâs mentor, remarked, if one takes the Brahmanic doctrine seriously, âthe only authentic sacrifice would be suicideâ (1898:133; so also A.B. Keith 1925:459). But of course no one actually took things that far.
[87] More precisely, it offered the sacrificer a way to break out of a world in which everything, including himself, was a creation of the gods, to fashion an immortal, divine body, ascend into heaven, and thus be âborn into a world he made himselfâ **(Satapatha Brahmana** VI:2.2.27) where all debts could be repaid, buy back his abandoned mortal body from the gods (see, i.e., LĂ©vi 1898:130â32, Malamoud 1983:31â32). This is certainly one of the most ambitious claims ever made for the efficacy of sacrifice, but some priests in China around that time were making similar claims (Puett 2002).
[88] Translated âsaintsâ in the text with which I began the chapter, but since it refers to the authors of the sacred texts, the usage seems appropriate.
[89] I am fusing here two slightly different versions: one in **Tattiriya Sarphita** (6.3.10.5), which says that all Brahmans are born **with** a debt, but only lists gods, Fathers, and sages, leaving out the duty of hospitality, and the other in **Satapatha Brahmana** (1.7.2.1â6) that says all men are born **as** a debt, listing all fourâbut which seems really to be referring to males of twice-born castes. For a full discussion: see Malamoud 1983 and Olivelle 1993:46-55, also Malamoud 1998.
[90] ThĂ©ret 1999:60â61
[91] âThe ultimate discharge of this fundamental debt is sacrifice of the living to appease and express gratitude to the ancestors and deities of the cosmosâ (Ingham 2004:90).
[92] op cit. He cites Hudson 2002:102â3, on the terms for âguiltâ or âsin,â but as weâll see the point goes back to Grierson (1977:22â23).
[93] Laum 1924. His argument about the origin of money in Greece in temple distributions is intriguing and has found contemporary exponents in Seaford (2004) and partly in Hudson (e.g., 2003) but is really a theory of the origin of coinage.
[94] More than I would ever dream of trying to cite. There are two standard survey works on âprimitive money,â by Quiggin and by Einzig, both of which, curiously, came out in 1949. Both are outdated in their analysis but contain a great deal of useful material.
[95] English âpayâ is from French **payer**, which in turn is derived from Latin **pacare**, âto pacify,â âto make peace with.â **Pacare** in turn is related to **pacere**, âto come to terms with an injured partyâ (Grierson 1977:21).
[96] Grierson 1977:20.
[97] In fact, as Grierson notes, the authors often seemed to be intentionally making fun of themselves, as in the Irish text that specifies that one can demand compensation for a bee-sting, but only if one first deducts the cost of the dead bee (Grierson 1977:26).
[98] We have plenty of myths and hymns from ancient Mesopotamia, too, for instanceâbut most were discovered in the ruins of ancient libraries that were also full of records of court trials, business contracts, and personal correspondence. In the case of the oldest Sanskrit texts, religious literature is all we have. Whatâs more, since these were texts passed on verbatim from teacher to student for thousands of years, we canât even say with any precision when and where they were written.
[99] Interest-bearing loans certainly existed in Mesopotamia, but they only appear in Egypt in Hellenistic times, and in the Germanic world even later. The text speaks of âthe tribute that I owe to Yama,â which **could** refer to âinterest,â but the comprehensive review of early Indian legal sources in Kaneâs **History of Dharmasastra** (1973 III:411â461) comes to no clear conclusion on when interest first appeared; Kosambi (1994:148) estimates that it might have appeared in 500 bc but admits this is a guess.
[100] Mesopotamia, Egypt, and China come most immediately to mind. The notion that life is a loan from the gods does occur elsewhere: it seems to crop up spontaneously in ancient Greece, around the same time as money and interest-bearing loans do. âWe are all owed as a debt to death,â wrote the poet Simonides, around 500 bc. âThe sentiment that life was a loan to be repaid by death [became] an almost proverbial sayingâ (Millet 1991a:6). No Greek author to my knowledge connects this explicitly to sacrifice, though one could conceivably argue that Platoâs character Cephalus does so implicitly in one passage of the **Republic** (331d).
[101] Hubert and Mauss (1964) provide a good survey of the ancient literature in this regard.
[102] Finley 1981:90
[103] This was something of a legalistic distinction; what it really meant in practice was that funds levied in Persia were technically considered âgifts,â but it shows the power of the principle (Briant 2006:398â99)
[104] Pharaonic Egypt and imperial China certainly did levy direct taxes, in money, kind, or labor, in different proportions at different times. In early India, the **gana-sangha** republics do not seem to have demanded taxes of their citizens, but the monarchies that ultimately replaced them did (Rhys Davies 1922:198â200). My point is that taxes were not inevitable and were often seen as marks of conquest.
[105] I am following what I believe is still the predominant view; though at least in some places Palaces were in charge of pretty much everything from quite early on, and Temples quite subordinate (see Maekawa 1973â1974). There is lively debate about this, as with the balance of temple, palace, clan, and individual holdings in different times and places, but I have avoided going into such debates, however interesting, unless they have a direct bearing on my argument.
[106] I am following Hudsonâs interpretation (2002), though othersâe.g. Steinkeller 1981, Mieroop 2002:64âsuggest that interest may have instead originated in rental fees.
[107] For a good summary, Hudson 1993, 2002. The meaning of **amargi** is first noted in Falkenstein (1954), see also Kramer (1963:79, Lemche (1979:16n34).
[108] In ancient Egypt there were no loans at interest, and we know relatively little about other early empires, so we donât know how unusual this was. But the Chinese evidence is at the very least suggestive. Chinese theories of money were always resolutely Chartalist; and in the standard story about the origins of coinage, since at least Han times, the mythic founder of the Shang dynasty, upset to see so many families having to sell their children during famines, created coins so that the government could redeem the children and return them to their families (see chapter 8, below).
[109] What is sacrifice, after all, but a recognition that an act such as taking an animalâs life, even if necessary for our sustenance, is not an act to be taken lightly, but with an attitude of humility before the cosmos?
[110] Unless the recipient is owed money by the creditor, allowing everyone to cancel their debts in a circle. This might seem an extraneous point, but the circular cancellation of debts in this way seems to have been quite a common practice in much of history: see, for instance, the description of âreckoningsâ in chapter 11 below.
[111] I am not ascribing this position to the authors of the Brahmanas necessarily; only pursuing what I take to be the internal logic of the argument, in dialogue with its authors.
[112] Malamoud 1983:32.
[113] Comte 1891:295
[114] In France, particularly by political thinkers like Alfred FouillĂ© and LĂ©on Bourgeois. The latter, leader of the Radical Party in the 1890s, made the notion of social debt one of the conceptual foundations for what his philosophy of âsolidarismââa form of radical republicanism that, he argued, could provide a kind of middle-ground alternative to both revolutionary Marxism and free-market liberalism. The idea was to overcome the violence of class struggle by appealing to a new moral system based on the notion of a shared debt to societyâof which the state, of course, was merely the administrator and representative (Hayward 1959, Donzelot 1994, Jobert 2003). Emile Durkheim too was a Solidarist politically.
[115] As a slogan, the expression is generally attributed to Charles Gide, the late-nineteenth-century French cooperativist, but became common in Solidarist circles. It became an important principle in Turkish socialist circles at the time (Aydan 2003), and, I have heard, though I have not been able to verify, in Latin America.
[116] Hart 1986:638.
[117] The technical term for this is âfiduciarity,â the degree to which its value is based not on metal content but public trust. For a good discussion of the fiduciarity of ancient currencies, see Seaford 2004:139â146. Almost all metal coins were overvalued. If the government set the value below that of the metal, of course, people would simply melt them down; if itâs set at exactly the metal value, the results are usually deflationary. As Bruno ThĂ©ret (2008:826â27) points out, although Lockeâs reforms, which set the value of the British sovereign at exactly its weight in silver, were ideologically motivated, they had disastrous economic effects. Obviously, if coinage is debased or the value otherwise set too high in relation to the metal content, this can produce inflation. But the traditional view, where, say, the Roman currency was ultimately destroyed by debasement, is clearly false, since it took centuries for inflation to occur (Ingham 2004:102â3).
[118] Einzig 1949:104; similar gambling chits, in this case made of bamboo, were used in Chinese towns in the Gobi desert (ibid: 108).
[119] On English token money, see Williamson 1889; Whiting 1971; Mathias 1979b.
[120] On cacao, Millon 1955; on Ethopian salt money, Einzig 1949:123â26. Both Karl Marx (1857:223, 1867:182) and Max Weber (1978:673â74) were of the opinion that money had emerged from barter between societies, not within them. Karl BĂŒcher (1904), and arguably Karl Polanyi (1968), held something close to this position, at least insofar as they insisted that modern money emerged from **external** exchange. Inevitably there must have been some sort of mutually reinforcing process between currencies of trade and the local accounting system. Insofar as we can talk about the âinventionâ of money in its modern sense, presumably this would be the place to look, though in places like Mesopotamia this must have happened long before the use of writing, and hence the history is effectively lost to us.
[121] Einzig (1949:266), citing Kulischer (1926:92) and Ilwof (1882:36).
[122] **Genealogy of Morals**, 2.8.
[123] As I remarked earlier, both Adam Smith and Nietzsche thus anticipate Levi-Straussâs famous argument that language is the âexchange of words.â The remarkable thing here is that so many have managed to convince themselves that in all this, Nietzsche is providing a radical alternative to bourgeois ideology, even to the logic of exchange. Deleuze and Guattari, most embarrassingly, insist that âthe great book of modern ethnology is not so much Maussâ **The Gift** as Nietzscheâs **On the Genealogy of Morals**. At least it should be,â since, they say, Nietzsche succeeds in interpreting âprimitive societyâ in terms of debt, where Mauss still hesitates to break with the logic of exchange (1972:224â25). On their inspiration, Sarthou-Lajus (1997) has written philosophy of debt as an alternative to bourgeois ideologies of exchange, that, she claims, assume the prior autonomy of the person. Of course what Nietzsche proposes is not an alternative at all. Itâs another aspect of the same thing. All this is a vivid reminder of how easy it is to mistake radicalized forms of our own bourgeois tradition as alternatives to it (Bataille \[1993\], who Deleuze and Guattari praise as another alternative to Mauss in the same passage, is another notorious example of this sort of thing).
[124] **Genealogy of Morals** 2.5.
[125] Nietzsche had clearly been reading too much Shakespeare. There is no record of the mutilation of debtors in the ancient world; there was a good deal of mutilation of slaves, but they were by definition people who could not be in debt. Mutilation for debt is occasionally attested to in the Medieval period, but as weâll see, Jews tended to be the victims, since they were largely without rights, and certainly not the perpetrators. Shakespeare turned the story around.
[126] **Genealogy of Morals** 2.19.
[127] **Genealogy of Morals** 2.21.
[128] Freuchen 1961:154. Itâs not clear what language this was said in, considering that Inuit did not actually have an institution of slavery. Itâs also interesting because the passage would not make sense unless there were **some** contexts in which gift exchange **did** operate, and therefore, debts accrued. What the hunter is emphasizing is that it was felt important that this logic did not extend to the basic means of human existence, such as food.
[129] To take an example, the Ganges Valley in the Buddhaâs time was full of arguments about the relative merits of monarchical and democratic constitutions. Gautama, though the son of a king, sided with the democrats, and many of the decision-making techniques used in democratic assemblies of the time remain preserved in the organization of Buddhist monasteries (Muhlenberger & Paine 1997.) Were it not for this we would not know anything about them, or even be entirely sure that such democratic polities existed.
[130] For instance, buying back oneâs ancestral land (Leviticus 25:25, 26) or anything one had given to the Temple (Leviticus 27).
[131] Here too, in the case of complete insolvency, the debtor might lose his own freedom as well. See Houston (2006) for a good survey of the contemporary literature on economic conditions in the time of the prophets. I here follow a synthesis of his and Michael Hudsonâs (1993) reconstruction.
[132] See for instance, Amos 2.6, 8.2, and Isaiah 58.
[133] Nehemiah 5:3â7.
[134] There continues to be intense scholarly debate about whether these laws were in fact invented by Nehemiah and his priestly allies (especially Ezra), and whether they were ever actually enforced in any period: see Alexander 1938; North 1954; Finkelstein 1961, 1965; Westbrook 1971; Lemke 1976, 1979; Hudson 1993; Houston 1996 for a few examples. At first there were similar debates about whether Mesopotamian âclean statesâ were actually enforced, until overwhelming evidence was produced that they were. The bulk of the evidence now indicates that the laws in Deuteronomy were enforced as well, though we can never know for certain how effectively.
[135] âEvery seventh year you shall make a cancellation. The cancellation shall be as follows: every creditor is to release the debts that he has owing to him by his neighborâ (Deuteronomy 15:1â3). Those held in debt bondage were also freed. Every 49 (or in some readings 50) years came the Jubilee, when all family land was to be returned to its original owners, and even family members who had been sold as slaves set free (Leviticus 25:9).
[136] Unsurprisingly, since the need to borrow was most often sparked by the need to pay taxes imposed by foreign conquerors.
[137] Hudson notes in Babylonian, clean slates were âcalled hubullum (debt) masaâum (to wash), literally âa washing away of the debt [records],â that is, a dissolving of the clay tablets on which financial obligations were inscribedâ (1993:19).
[138] Matthew 18: 23â34.
[139] To give a sense of the figures involved, ten thousand talents in gold is roughly equivalent to the entire Roman tax receipts from their provinces in whatâs now the Middle East. A hundred denarii is 1/60 of one talent, and therefore worth 600,000 times less.
[140] **OpheilÄma** in the Greek original, which meant âthat which is owed,â âfinancial debts,â and by extension, âsin.â This was apparently used to translate the Aramaic **hoyween**, which also meant both âdebtâ and, by extension, âsin.â The English here (as in all later Bible citations) follows the King James version, which in this case is itself based on a 1381 translation of the Lordâs prayer by John Wycliffe. Most readers will probably be more familiar with 1559 Book of Common Prayer version that substitutes âAnd forgive us our trespasses, as we forgive them that trespass against us.â However, the original is quite explicitly âdebts.â
[141] Changing these to âspiritual debtsâ doesnât really change the problem.
[142] The prospect of sexual abuse in these situations clearly weighed heavily on the popular imagination. âSome of our daughters are brought unto bondage alreadyâ protested the Israelites to Nehemiah. Technically, daughters taken in debt bondage were not, if virgins, expected to be sexually available to creditors who did not wish to marry them or marry them to their sons (Exodus 21:7â9; Wright 2009:130â33) though chattel slaves were sexually available (see Hezser 2003), and often the roles blurred in practice; even where laws theoretically protected them, fathers must often have had little means to protect them or cause those laws to be enforced. The Roman historian Livyâs account of the abolition of debt bondage in Rome in 326 bc, for instance, featured a handsome young man named Caius Publilius placed in bondage for a debt heâd inherited from his father, and who was savagely beaten for refusing the sexual advances of his creditor (Livy 8.28). When he appeared on the streets and announced what had happened to him, crowds gathered and marched on the Senate to demand that they abolish the institution.
[143] Particularly if the slaves were foreigners captured in war. As weâll see, the common belief that there were no moral objections to slavery in the ancient world is false. There were plenty. But aside from certain radicals such as the Essenes, the institution was accepted as an unfortunate necessity.
[144] Hudson (2002:37) cites the Greek historian Diodorus Siculus (i.79) who attributes this motive to the Egyptian pharaoh Bakenranef, though he too emphasizes that military considerations were not the only ones, but that cancellations reflected broader feelings about justice.
[145] Oppenheim 1964:88. Oppenheim suggests that interest-free loans were more common in the Levant, and that in Mesopotamia social equals were more likely to charge each other interest but on easier terms, citing an Old Assyrian merchant who speaks of âthe rate one brother charges anotherâ (op cit). In ancient Greece, friendly loans between social equals were known as **eranos** loans, usually of sums raised by an impromptu mutual-aid society and not involving the payment of interest (Jones 1956:171â73; Vondeling 1961; Finley 1981:67â68; Millet 1991:153â155). Aristocrats often made such loans to one another, but so did groups of slaves trying to pool money to buy back their freedom (Harrill 1998:167). This tendency, for mutual aid to be most marked at the very top and very bottom of the social scale is a consistent pattern to this day.
[146] Hence the constant invocation of the phrase âyour brother,â particularly in Deuteronomy, e.g., âyou shall not lend at interest to your brotherâ (23:20).
[147] As weâll see in chapter seven, Plato begins **The Republic** in exactly the same way.
[148] For a polite but devastating assessment, see Kahneman 2003.
[149] Homans 1958, also Blau 1964; Levi-Strauss 1963:296. In anthropology, the first to propose reciprocity as a universal principle was Richard Thurnwald (1916), but it was made famous by Malinowski (1922).
[150] One reason no known law code has ever been known to enforce the principle; the penalty was always there to be commuted to something else.
[151] Atwood (2008:1). The author then proceeds to explore the nature of our sense of economic morality by comparing the behavior of caged apes with middle-class Canadian children to argue that all human relations are indeed either exchange or forcible appropriation (ibid:49). Despite the brilliance of many of its arguments, the result is a rather sad testimony to how difficult it is for the scions of the North Atlantic professional classes not to see their own characteristic ways of imagining the world as simple human nature.
[152] Setonâs father, a failed shipping magnate turned accountant, was, Seton later wrote, so cold and abusive that his son spent much of his youth in the woods trying to avoid him; after paying the debtâwhich incidentally came to $537.50, a tidy but not insurmountable sum in 1881âhe changed his name and spent much of the rest of his life trying to develop more healthy child-rearing techniques.
[153] Rev. W.H. Beatley in Levy-Bruhl 1923:411
[154] Rev. Fr. Bulléon, in Levy-Bruhl 1923:425
[155] This phrase was not coined by Marx, incidentally, but was apparently a slogan current in the early French workersâ movement, first appearing in print in the work of socialist Louis Blanc in 1839. Marx only took up the phrase in his **Critique of the Gotha Programme** in 1875, and even then used it in a rather idiosyncratic way: for the principle he imagined could apply on the level of society as a whole once technology had reached the point of guaranteeing absolute material abundance. For Marx, âcommunismâ was both the political movement aiming to bring about such a future society, and that society itself. I am drawing here more on the alternate strain of revolutionary theory, evident most famously perhaps in Peter Kropotkinâs **Mutual Aid** (1902).
[156] At least, unless there is some specific reason not toâfor instance, a hierarchical division of labor that says some people get coffee and others do not.
[157] What this means of course is that command economiesâputting government bureaucracies in charge of coordinating every aspect of the production and distribution of goods and services within a given national territoryâtends to be much less efficient than other available alternatives. This is obviously true, though if it âjust doesnât workâ at all, itâs hard to imagine how states like the Soviet Union could have existed, let alone maintain themselves as world powers, in the first place.
[158] Evans-Pritchard 1940:182
[159] Similarly, a middle-class pedestrian would be unlikely to ask a gang member for directions, and might even run in fear if one approached him to ask for the time, but this is again because of an assumption of a tacit state of war existing between them.
[160] Ibid, p. 183.
[161] Richards 1939:197. Max Gluckman, remarking on such customs, concludes that insofar as it is possible to speak of âprimitive communism,â it exists in consumption, rather than production, which tends to be much more individually organized (1971:52).
[162] A typical example: âif a cabin of hungry people meets another whose provisions are not entirely exhausted, the latter share with the newcomers the little which remains to them without waiting to be asked, although they expose themselves thereby to the same danger of perishing as those whom they help âŠâ Lafitau 1974 Volume II:61.
[163] Jesuit Relations (1635) 8:127, cited in DelĂąge 1993:54.
[164] This is a common arrangement in certain parts of the world (particularly the Andes, Amazonia, insular Southeast Asia, and Melanesia), and invariably there is some rule whereby each half is dependent on the other for something considered essential to human life. One can only marry someone from the other side of the village, or maybe one can only eat pigs raised on the other side, or perhaps one side needs people from the other side to sponsor the rituals that initiate its male children into manhood.
[165] As I have suggested elsewhere, Graeber 2001:159â60; cf. Mauss 1947: 104â5.
[166] Iâm side-stepping the whole question of one-sided examples discussed in Graeber 2001:218.
[167] Marshall Sahlins (1972) coined the phrase âgeneralized reciprocityâ to describe this sort of relation, on the principle that if everything circulates freely, eventually, all accounts will balance out. Marcel Mauss was already making such an argument in lectures back in the 1930s (1947), but he also recognized the problems: while this might be true of Iroquois moieties, some relationships never balance outâfor instance, between mother and child. His solution, âalternating reciprocityââthat we repay our parents by having children ourselvesâis clearly drawn from his study of the Vedas, but it ultimately demonstrates that if one has already decided that all relations are based on reciprocity, one can always define the term so broadly as to make it true.
[168] **Hostis:** see Benveniste 1972:72. The Latin terminology concerning hospitality emphasizes the absolute mastery of the house by its (male) owner as the precondition of any act of hospitality; Derrida (2000, 2001) argues that this points to a central contradiction in the very concept of hospitality, since it implies an already-existing absolute dominium or power over others, the kind that might be seen as taking its most exploitative form in Lotâs offering his own daughters up to a crowd of Sodomites to dissuade them from raping his houseguests. However, this same principle of hospitality can be equally well documented in societiesâsuch as the Iroquoisâthat were anything but patriarchal.
[169] Evans-Pritchard 1940:154, 158.
[170] This is of course one reason why the very rich like to associate mainly with one another.
[171] In a less hostile vein one can speak of an exchange of prisoners, notes, or compliments.
[172] A good source on haggling: Uchendo 1967.
[173] Bohannan 1964:47.
[174] Not even a real business deal, since these may often involve a great deal of collective wining and dining and giving of presents. More the sort of imaginary business deal that appears in economics textbooks.
[175] One need only glance at the vast anthropological literature on âcompetitive feastingâ: e.g., Valeri 2001.
[176] Bourdieu 1965 is the key text, but he repeats the main points in Bourdieu 1990:98â101.
[177] Onvlee 1980:204.
[178] Petronius 51; Pliny **Natural History** 36.195; Dio 57.21.5â7.
[179] âThis king is of all men the most addicted to the making of gifts and the shedding of blood. His gate is never without some poor man enriched or some living man executed.â
[180] Or even the very rich. Nelson Rockefeller, for example, used to pride himself on never carrying a wallet. He didnât need one. Every now and then when he was working late and wanted cigarettes, he would borrow some from the security people at the desk at Rockefeller Center, who would then be able to boast that they had lent a Rockefeller money and would rarely ask for it back. In contrast, âthe sixteenth-century Portuguese monarch Dom Manuel, newly rich from the Indies trade, adopted the title âLord of the Conquest, Navigation, and Commerce of Ethiopia, Arabia, Persia, and India.â Others called him the âgrocer king.â (Ho 2004:227).
[181] See Graeber 2001:175â76.
[182] Even between strangers itâs a bit unusual: as Servet (1981, 1982) has emphasized, most âprimitive tradeâ takes place through trade partnership and specialized regional middlemen.
[183] I frame things this way because I am mainly interested here in economics. If we were thinking simply of human relations, I suppose one might say that at one extreme is killing, and at the other, giving birth.
[184] In fact, it seems essential to the nature of charity that, like a gifts to a king, it can never lead to reciprocity. Even if it turns out that the pathetic-looking beggar is really a god wandering the earth in mortal form, or Harun al-Rashid, your reward will be entirely disproportionate. Or consider all those stories about drunken millionaires on a binge who, when they got their life back together, hand out fancy cars or houses to their earlier benefactors. Itâs easier to imagine a panhandler giving you a fortune than returning an exact equivalent to the dollar that you gave him.
[185] Xenophon **Cyropedia** VIII.6, Herodotus 3.8.9; see Briant 2006:193â194, 394â404, who acknowledges that something broadly along these lines probably did take place, with a more impromptu gift system under Cyrus and Cambyses being systematized under Darius.
[186] Marc Bloch (1961:114â15), who adds âevery act, especially if it was repeated three or four times, was likely to be transformed into a precedentâeven if in the first instance it had been exceptional or even frankly unlawful.â
[187] The approach is often identified with British anthropologist A.M. Hocart (1936). The important thing is that this does not necessarily mean that these became their main or exclusive occupations: most of the time, such people remained simple farmers like everybody else. Yet what they did for the king, or later, on ritual occasions, for the community, was seen as defining their essential nature, their identity within the whole.
[188] In fact, we may become indignant at her for an act of stinginess we would never even consider stingy in anyone elseâespecially, ourselves.
[189] A version has been published as: Sarah Stillman, âThe missing white girl syndrome: disappeared women and media activismâ (Stillman, 2007): [[http://www.publications.oxfam.org.uk/oxfam/display.asp?K=002J1246&sf_01=cat_class&st_01=620&sort=SORT_DATE/d&m=84&dc=719][publications.oxfam.org.uk/oxfam/display.asp?K=002J1246&sf_01=cat_class&st_01=620&sort=SORT_DATE/d&m=84&dc=719]]
[190] Karatani (2003:203â205) makes this point compellingly. The Kwakiutl and other First Nations of the Northwest Coast are something of an intermediary caseâaristocratic, but at least in the period we know about, using non-coercive means to gather resources (though Codere 1950.)
[191] Georges Duby (1980) provides the definitive history of this concept, which goes back to much older Indo-European ideas.
[192] For a typical example of imaginary reciprocity between father and son, see Oliver 1955:230. Anthropological theory buffs will notice that I am here endorsing Edmund Leachâs (1961) position on the âcirculating connubiumâ problem. He later applied the same argument to the famous âkula chainâ (1983).
[193] Actually, there are hierarchical relations that are explicitly self-subverting: the one between teacher and student, for example, since if the teacher is successful in passing her knowledge to the student, there is no further basis for inequality.
[194] Freuchen 1961: 154. Itâs not clear what the original language was here, considering that the Inuit did not have an institution of slavery. Also, the passage would not make sense unless there were **some** contexts in which gift exchange did operate, and therefore, in which debts accrued. What the hunter is emphasizing is that it was felt important that this logic did not extend to basic needs like food.
[195] Firth 1959:411â12 (also in Graeber 2001:175). His name was Tei Reinga.
[196] For one famous example: Chagnon 1996:170â76.
[197] Similarly, two groups might form an alliance by contracting a âjoking relation,â in which any member of one could at least in theory make similar outrageous demands of the other (HĂ©bert 1958).
[198] Marcel Mauss, in his famous âEssay on the Giftâ (1924), often did, and the results have sometimes confused debate for generations to come.
[199] Mauss 1925, the Greek source being Posidonius. As usual one does not know how literally to take this account. Mauss thought it likely accurate; I suspect it might have happened once or twice.
[200] As retold by William Ian Miller (1993:15â16). The first quote is directly from the original, Egilâs Saga, chapter 78. Egil remained ambivalent about the shield: he later took it to a wedding party and contrived to drop it into a vat of sour whey. Afterward, concluding it was ruined, he stripped it for its raw materials.
[201] See, for instance, Wallace-Hadrill 1989.
[202] Blaxter 1971:127â28.
[203] Another anthropologist, for instance, defines patron-client relations as âlong-term contracted relations in which the clientâs support is exchanged for the patronâs protection; there is an ideology which is morally charged and appears to rule out strict, open accounting, but both parties keep some tacit rough account; the goods and services exchanged are not similar, and there is no implication of fair exchange or balance of satisfactions, since the client is markedly weaker in power and needs the patron more than he is needed by himâ (Loizos 1977:115). Again, it both is and isnât an exchange, itâs both a matter of accounting and not a matter of accounting.
[204] Itâs exactly the same if one takes a job at a doughnut shop; legally, it must be a free contract between equals, even if in order to be able to say this we have to maintain the charming legal fiction that one of them is an imaginary person named âKrispy Kreme.â
[205] For instance the word âshould,â in English, originally derives from German **schuld**, meaning âguilt, fault, debt.â Benveniste provides similar examples from other Indo-European languages (1963:58). East Asian languages such as Chinese and Japanese rarely conflate the actual words, but a similar identification of debt with sin, shame, guilt, and fault can be easily documented (Malamoud 1988).
[206] Plutarch **Moralia** 303 B, also discussed in Finley 1981:152, Millett 1991a:42. Similarly, St. Thomas Aquinas made it a matter of Catholic doctrine that sins were âdebts of punishmentâ owed to God.
[207] This is one reason why itâs so easy to dress up other sorts of relationships as debts. Say one wishes to help out a friend in desperate need of money but doesnât want to embarrass her. Usually, the easiest way to do it is to provide the money and then insist that itâs a loan (and then let both parties conveniently forget it ever happened). Or think of all the times and places where the rich acquire servants by advancing what is ostensibly a loan.
[208] One could argue that some equivalent of âpleaseâ and âthank youâ could be identified in any human language, if one were determined to find them, but then the terms you find are often used so differentlyâfor instance, only in ritual contexts, or to hierarchical superiorsâthat itâs hard to attach much significance to the fact. It is significant that over the last century or so just about every human language that is used in offices or to make transactions in shops has had to create terms that do function as an exact equivalent of the English âplease,â âthank you,â and âyouâre welcome.â
[209] In Spanish one first asks a favor **(por favor)**, and then says **gracias**, in order affirm you recognize one has been done for you, since it derives from the Latin word **gratia**, meaning âinfluence, or favor.â âAppreciateâ is more monetary: if you say âI really appreciate your doing that for me,â you are using a word that derives from Latin **appretiare**, âto set a price.â
[210] âYouâre welcome,â first documented in Shakespeareâs time, derives from Old English **wilcuma, wil** being âpleasureâ and **cuma** being âguest.â This is why people are still welcomed into a house. It is thus like âbe my guest,â implying that, no, if there is an obligation itâs on my part, as any host is obliged to be generous to guests, and that dispatching such obligations is a pleasure in itself. Still, itâs significant that moralists rarely chide anyone for failure to say âyouâre welcomeââthat one is much more optional.
[211] Book I.12. This and other quotes are from the 2006 Penguin Screech translation, in this case, p. 86.
[212] Compare the Medieval Arab philosopher Ibn Miskaway: âThe creditor desires the well-being of the debtor in order to get his money back rather than because of his love for him. The debtor, on the other hand, does not take great interest in the creditor.â (in Hosseini 2003:36).
[213] Appropriate, since Panurgeâs entire discourse is nothing but a comical elaboration of Marcelo Ficinoâs argument that the entire universe is driven by the power of love.
[214] From: Peter Carlson, âThe Relatively Charmed Life of Neil Bush,â **The Washington Post**, Sunday December 28, 2003, Page D01.
[215] Grierson 1977:20.
[216] To be fair to Grierson, he does later suggest that slavery played an important part in the origins of moneyâthough he never speculates about the gender, which seems significant: slave girls also served as the highest denomination of currency in Medieval Iceland (Williams 1937), and in the Rig Veda, great gifts and payments are regularly designated in âgold, cattle, and slave girlsâ (Chakravarti 1985:56â57). By the way, I say âyoungâ because elsewhere, when slaves are used as monetary units, the unit is assumed to be a slave about 18â20 years old. A **cumal** was considered the equivalent in value of three milch cows or six heifers.
[217] On **cumal** see Nolan 1926, Einzig 1949:247â48, Gerriets 1978, 1981, 1985, Patterson 1982:168â69, Kelly 1998:112â13. Most merely emphasize that **cumal** were just used as units of account and we donât know anything about earlier practices. Itâs notable, though, that in the law codes, when several different commodities are used as units of account, they will include that countryâs most significant exports, and trade currency (thatâs why in Russian codes, the units were fur and silver). This would imply a significant trade in female slaves in the period just before written records.
[218] So Bender 1996.
[219] Here I am drawing on the detailed ethnographic survey work of Alain Testart (2000, 2001, 2002). Testart does a magnificent job synthesizing the evidence, though he tooâas weâll see in the next chapterâhas some equally strange blind spots in his conclusions.
[220] âAlthough the rhetorical phrase âselling oneâs daughter into prostitutionâ has wide currency ⊠the actual arrangement is more often presented as either a loan to the family or an advance payment for the girlâs (usually unspecified or misrepresented) services. The interest on these âloansâ is often 100 percent, and the principal may be increased by other debtsâfor living expenses, medical care, bribes to officialsâaccrued once the girl has begun workâ (Bishop & Robinson 1998:105).
[221] So Michael Hudson (cited in Wray 1999), but itâs clear enough if one looks at the language of the original: âThou shalt not covet thy neighbourâs house, thou shalt not covet thy neighbourâs wife, nor his manservant, nor his maidservant, nor his ox, nor his ass, nor any thing that is thy neighbourâsâ (Exodus 20:17, Deuteronomy 5:21).
[222] Wampum is a good example: Indians never seem to have used it to buy things from other members of the same community, although it was regularly used in conducting trade with settlers (see Graeber 2001:117â150). Others, like Yurok shell money or some Papuan currencies, are widely used as currencies in addition to their social functions, but the first seems to have emerged from the second.
[223] The most important texts on the âbrideprice debateâ: Evans-Pritchard 1931, Raglan 1931, Gray 1968, Comaroff 1980, Valeri 1994. One reason why Evans-Pritchard originally proposed to change the name from âbridepriceâ to âbridewealthâ because the League of Nations had in 1926 outlawed the practice as a form of slavery (Guyer 1994).
[224] On Tiv kinship and economy: Duggan 1932; Abraham 1933; Downes 1933; Akiga 1939; L. Bohannan 1952; P. Bohannan 1955, 1957, 1959; P. & L. Bohannan 1953, 1968, Tseayo 1975; Keil 1979.
[225] Akiga Sai 1939:106 for a good analysis of how this could happen. For a later comparative reanalysis in regional perspective, see Fardon 1984, 1985.
[226] Paul Bohannan puts it: âThe **kem** relationship of debt between a man and his wifeâs guardian is never broken, because **kem** is perpetual, the debt can never be fully paid.â (1957:73.) Otherwise the account is from Akiga (1939:126â127).
[227] Rospabé 1993:35.
[228] Evans-Pritchard 1940:153.
[229] As the ethnographer puts it, âthat they are accepting the cattle only in order to honour him and not because they are ready to take cattle for the life of their dead kinsman.â (1940:153)
[230] Op cit 154â155.
[231] Morgan 1851:332. Morgan, a lawyer by training, is using a technical term here, âcondonation,â which the Oxford English Dictionary defines as âthe voluntary overlooking of an offence.â
[232] Morgan 1851:333. The baseline was five fathoms for a man, ten for a woman, but other factors might intervene (T. Smith 1983:236; Morgan 1851:331â34; Parker 1926). On âmourning warsâ see Richter 1983; the expression âputting his name upon the matâ is from Fenton 1978:315. Incidentally I am assuming itâs a man who dies, since these are the examples in the sources. Itâs not clear if the same was done for women who died naturally.
[233] Evans-Pritchard 1940:155, 1951:109â11; Howell 1954:71â80, Gough 1971, Hutchinson 1996:62, 175â76.
[234] Rospabe 1995:47â48, citing Peters 1947.
[235] On mourning war: Richter 1983. Interestingly, something similar occurred among the Nambikwara. I mentioned in chapter 3 that the feasts held after barter could lead to seductions and jealous murders; Levi-Strauss adds that the ordinary way of resolving such murders is for the killer to marry the victimâs wife, adopt his children, and thus, effectively, become the person the victim used to be (1943:123).
[236] Though people did use them to commission certain fancy craft goods (say, musical instruments) from specialists in other villages (1963:54â55).
[237] Douglas 1958: 112; also 1982:43.
[238] Douglas (1963:58) estimates that a successful man will have spent at minimum 300 raffia cloths in payments, and given away at least 300 more as gifts, by the time he reached full social maturity.
[239] As anthropologists often note, the fact that one traces descent through the female line does not necessarily mean that women themselves have a lot of power. It can; it did among the Iroquois, and it does among Minangkabau right now. But it doesnât necessarily.
[240] Douglas 1963:144â45, which is an adoption of 1960:3â4.
[241] She was in fact a conservative Catholic, married a Tory economist, and tended to look with disdain on all liberal concerns.
[242] As if to hammer this home, a man was actually considered to be owed a life-debt for fathering female children (Douglas 1963:115)âthat could only be paid by allowing him to take one of his own daughtersâ daughters as a pawn. This only makes sense if we assume a principle that only men can be owed a life, and therefore, in the case of women, the creation of life was assumed to be given free. Men, as noted, could be pawns and many were, but they were never traded.
[243] Douglas 1966:150.
[244] On âvillage-wives,â see particularly Douglas 1951, also 1963:128â40.
[245] Douglas 1963:76; compare 1951:11. The author is clearly simply repeating her informantsâ explanation for the custom: the Lele didnât âhave toâ make such an arrangement; in fact, most African societies did not.
[246] Some village wives were literally princesses, since chiefsâ daughters invariably chose to marry age-sets in this way. The daughters of chiefs were allowed to have sex with anyone they wanted, regardless of age-set, and also had the right to refuse sex, which ordinary village wives did not. Princesses of this sort were rare: there were only three chiefs in all Lele territory. Douglas estimates that the number of Lele women who became village wives, on the other hand, was about 10 percent (1951).
[247] For instance: 1960:4, 1963:145â46, 168â73, 1964:303. Obviously, men could sometimes put a great deal of physical pressure on women, at least, if everyone else agreed they had a moral right to do so, but even here Douglas emphasizes most women had a good deal of room for maneuver.
[248] On peacefulness, particularly, 1963:70â71.
[249] 1963:170.
[250] 1963:171.
[251] Cost of slaves: 1963:36, 1982:46â47.
[252] Partly, though, this was because the main purpose of male slaves was to be sacrificed at important menâs funerals (1963:36).
[253] See Graeber 2001, chapter 4. The great exception might seem to be the cattle money of the Nuer, and similar pastoral peoples. Yet even these were arguably adornment of the person of a sort.
[254] Akiga Sai 1939: 121, 158â60.
[255] So too when Tiv practiced marriage by capture: Akiga Sai (1939:137â41).
[256] Here Iâm drawing on the classic âspheres of exchangeâ analysis by Paul Bohannan (1955, 1959), supplemented by Dorward (1976) and Guyer (2004:27â31).
[257] So Akiga Sai 1939:241; P. Bohannan 1955:66, P. & L. Bohannnan 1968:233, 235. As charisma in general: East in Akiga Sai 1939:236, Downes 1971:29.
[258] See Abraham 1933:26; Akiga Sai 1939:246; P. Bohannan 1958:3; Downes 1971:27.
[259] On witches in general: P. Bohannan 1957:187â88, 1958; Downes 1971: 32â25. On flesh debts (or **ikipindi):** Abraham 1933:81â84; Downes 1971:36â40.
[260] Akiga Sai 1939:257.
[261] Akiga Sai 1939:260.
[262] Following here Wilson 1951.
[263] Paul Bohannan (1958:4) makes a similar but not identical argument.
[264] Tiv migration stories (e.g. Abraham 1933:17â26; Akiga & Bohannan 1954; P. Bohannan 1954) do not explicitly say this, but they could easily be read this way. Akigaâs story (1939:137) about Tiv migrants painting what looked like sores on their womenâs bodies so raiders would not take them is particularly suggestive. Despite their lack of government, Tiv did have a notoriously effective war organization, and as Abrahams notes (1933:19), managed to successfully play the Fulani and Jukun against each other by intervening in their own wars with each other.
[265] Some of these raids were not entirely unsuccessful. For a while, it would appear, the nearby Jukun kingdom, which made several ultimately unsuccessful efforts to incorporate the Tiv in the eighteenth century, appear to have been selling Tiv captives to slave dealers operating on the coast (Abraham 1933:19; Curtin 1965:255, 298; Latham 1973:29; Tambo 1976: 201â3.) Itâs doubtless significant here that many Tiv insisted in the 1930s that the Jukun were themselves cannibals, and that the origins of the **mbatsav** âorganizationâ lay in certain chiefly titles that Tiv acquired from them when they finally came to a political rapprochement (Abraham 1933:33â35).
[266] Jones 1958; Latham 1971; Northrup 1978:157â64; Herbert 2003:196. The famous Medieval Arab traveler Ibn Battuta, who weâve already met at the court of the King of Singh in chapter 2, saw people using them as money in the Niger region, not far away, in the 1340s.
[267] Herbert (2003:181) estimates that Europeans imported about 20,000 tons of English brass and copper into Africa between 1699 and 1865. It was manufactured in Bristol, Cheadle, and Birmingham. The vast majority was exchanged for slaves
[268] I base this number on the fact that 152,076 slaves are known to have been exported from the Bight of Biafra as a whole in those years (Eltis, Behrent, Richardson & Klein 2000). The slave trade at Old Calabar lasted roughly from 1650 to 1841, during which time the port was by far the largest in the Bight, and the exports from the Bight itself during its height represent about 20 percent of all Africa (Lovejoy & Richardson 1999:337).
[269] Sheridan 1958, Price 1980, 1989, 1991.
[270] A larger variety of beads.
[271] Barbot in Talbot 1926 I: 185â186.
[272] Inkori (1982) demonstrates that in the late eighteenth century, British ships docking in Old Calabar brought on average 400 muskets each, and that between 1757 and 1806, the total number imported into the Calabar-Cameroons region was 22,986. Rum and other liquor was, however, a very minor import.
[273] One common expedient, especially in the early years, was for merchants to arrive at village markets with canoes full of wares, exchange them for slaves, and then, if they didnât come up to quota, wait until nightfall and simply attack homesteads along the river, carrying off anyone they could find (Clarkson in Northrup 1978:66, also cited in Noah 1990:94.)
[274] The existing scholarly literature is of little help in reconstructing the history of how one form was transformed into the other, since there are only works treating pawnship **either** as a matter of kinship (e.g., Douglas 1964, Fardon 1985, 1986), or of commerce (e.g., Falola & Lovejoy 1994), but never comparing the two. As a result, many basic questions remain unasked. Falola and Lovejoy, for instance, suggest that pawnsâ labor functions as interest, but the book contains no information on whether interest-bearing loans even existed in the parts of Africa where pawnship was practiced.
[275] Itâs also clear that this sort of pawnship must have developed from something like the Lele institution. Many of the rules are the same: for instance, much as among the Lele, if a girl was pledged, the creditor often had the option of marrying her when she reached maturity, thus cancelling the debt.
[276] Lovejoy & Richardson 1999:349â51; 2001.
[277] Equiano 1789:6â13.
[278] Others included the Akunakuna, and the Efik, who were based in Calabar itself. The Aro were Igbo-speakers, and the region a patchwork of speakers of Igbo and Ibibio languages.
[279] On the Aro in general, see Jones 1939; Ottenberg 1958; Afigbo 1971; Ekejiuba 1972; Isichei 1976; Northrup 1978; Dike & Ekejiuba 1990; Nwauwa 1991.
[280] Dike and Ekejiuba (1990:150) estimate that 70 percent of the slaves sold to Europeans in the Bight of Biafra came from the Aro. Most of the rest came from the other merchant societies.
[281] One twentieth-century elder recalled, âa woman who commited adultery would be sold by her husband and the husband kept the money. Thieves were sold, and the money went to the elders whose responsibility it was to make the decision.â (Northrup 1978: 69)
[282] Northrup 1978:73
[283] On Ekpe as debt enforcement in Calabar itself: Jones 1968, Latham 1973:35â41, Lovejoy & Richardson 1999:347â49. On the spread of Ekpe to Arochukwe and throughout the region: Ruel 1969:250â258, Northrup 1978:109â110, Nwaka 1978, Ottenberg & Knudson 1985. Nwaka (1978:188) writes: âThe Ekpe society, the most widespread in the Cross River area, formed the basis of local government. It performed executive and judicial functions in areas where it operated. Through the agency of its members, punishments were administered to public offenders, customs enforced and the authority of the elders upheld. Ekpe laws to some extent regulated the lives of most members of the community in such matters as the cleaning of towns and streets, collection of debts and other measures of public benefit.â
[284] Latham 1963:38.
[285] Taken from Walker 1875:120
[286] Ottenberg & Ottenberg 1962:124.
[287] Partridge 1905:72.
[288] If one were seeking a pawn, one couldnât simply take a random child from a neighboring village, as his or her parents would quickly track the child down.
[289] In Lovejoy & Richardson 2001:74. For a parallel case in Ghana, see Getz 2003:85.
[290] Remarkably, Akiga Sai (1939:379â80) insists that, among the Tiv, this was the origin of slavery: the seizing of hostages from the same lineage as someone who refused to pay a debt. Say, he says, the debtor still refuses to pay. They will keep their hostage fettered for a while, then, finally, sell them in another country. âThis is the origin of slavery.â
[291] So Harris 1972:128 writing of another Cross River district, Ikom: one of the major suppliers of slaves for Calabar. There, she notes, debtors were often obliged to pawn themselves when maternal and paternal kin intervened to prevent them from selling off any more of their relatives, with the result that they were finally enslaved and sent to Calabar.
[292] We do not know what proportion. King Eyo II told a British missionary that slaves âwere sold for different reasonsâsome as prisoners of war, some for debt, some for breaking their countryâs laws and some by great men who hated themâ (in Noah 1990:95). This suggests that debt was not insignificant, especially since as Pier Larson (2000:18) notes, all sources at the time would list âwar,â since it was considered the most legitimate. Compare Northrup (1978:76â80).
[293] Reid 1983:8
[294] op cit.
[295] Reid 1983:10
[296] Vickers (1996) provides an excellent history of Baliâs image in the North Atlantic imagination, from âsavage Baliâ to terrestrial paradise.
[297] Geertz & Geertz 1975; Boon 1977:121â24. Belo (1936:26) cites informants in the 1920s that insisted that marriage by capture was a fairly recent innovation, which emerged from gangs of young men stealing women from enemy villages and, often, demanding that their fathers pay money to get them back.
[298] Boon 1977:74
[299] Covarrubias (1937:12) notes that as early as 1619, Balinese women were in great demand in slave markets in Reunion.
[300] Boon 1977:28, van der Kraan 1983, Wiener 1995:27
[301] Vickers 1996:61. I need only remark that the anthropological literature on Bali, most notably Clifford Geertzâs famous essay on the Balinese cockfight as âdeep playâ (1973), a space where Balinese people can express their inner demons and tell stories about themselves, or his conception of pre-colonial governments as âtheater statesâ (1980) whose politics centered around gathering the resources to create magnificent rituals, might well be rethought in the light of all of this. There is a peculiar blindness in this literature. Even Boon, after the above quote about men hiding their daughters, proceeds on the very next page (1977:75) to refer to that governmentâs âsubjectsâ as really just a âslightly taxed audience for its rituals,â as if the likely prospect of the rape, murder and enslavement of oneâs children didnât really matter, or, anyway, was not of explicitly political import.
[302] All this is meant in part as a critique of Louis Dumontâs arguments (1992) that the only truly egalitarian societies are modern ones, and even those only by default: since their ultimate value is individualism, and since each individual is valuable above all for the degree to which he or she is unique, there can be no basis for saying that anyone is intrinsically superior to anybody else. One can have the same effect without any doctrine of âWestern individualismâ at all. The entire concept of âindividualismâ needs to be seriously rethought.
[303] Beattie 1960: 61.
[304] True, in many traditional societies, penalties are given to men who beat their wives excessively. But again, the assumption is that **some** such behavior is at least par for the course.
[305] On charivari, see for instance Davis 1975, Darnton 1984. Keith Thomas (1972:630), who cites this very Nyoro story in an account of English villages of that time, recounts a whole series of social sanctions, such as dunking the âvillage scold,â that seem almost entirely aimed at the violent control of women, but oddly, he claims that charivari were directed at **men** who beat their wives, despite the fact that all other sources say the opposite.
[306] Not quite all. Again, one might cite Iroquois society of the same period as an example: it was in many senses a matriarchy, particularly on the everyday household level, and women were not exchanged.
[307] Taken from Trawick 2000:185, figure 11.
[308] The diagram is reproduced from P. Bohannan 1957:87.
[309] Akiga Sai 1939:161.
[310] So too among the Lele, where Mary Douglas (1963:131) remarks that it was considered acceptable to whip a village wife for refusing work or sex, but this was no reflection on her status, since the same was true of Lele wives married to just one man, too.
[311] [[http://www.http.sumerianorg/prot-sum.htm][http.sumerianorg/prot-sum.htm]], from a âProto-Sumerian dictionaryâ
[312] Florentius in Justinianâs Institutes (1.5.4.1). It is interesting to note that when attempts are made to justify slavery, starting with Aristotle, they generally focus not on the institution, which is not in itself justifiable, but on the inferior qualities of some ethnic group being enslaved.
[313] Elwahid 1931. Clarence-Smith (2008:17n56) notes that al-Wahidâs book itself emerged from within lively debates in the Middle East about the role of slavery in Islam that had been going on at least since the mid-nineteenth century.
[314] Elwahid 1931: 101â10, and passim. An analogous list appears in Patterson 1982:105.
[315] The sale of children was always felt to be a sign of economic and moral breakdown; even later Roman emperors like Diocletian, notes al-Wahid, supported charities aimed to provide relief for poor families explicitly so they would not have to resort to things like this (Elwahed 1931: 89â91).
[316] Mitamura 1970.
[317] Debt slavery, he notes, was practiced in early Roman history, but this is because according to the laws of the twelve tablets, insolvent debtors could actually be killed. In most places, where this was not possible, debtors were not fully enslaved by reduced to pawns or peons (see Testart 2000, 2002, for a full explanation of the different possibilities).
[318] Al-Wahid cites examples from Athenaeus of Greek patients who offered themselves as slaves to doctors who had saved their lives (op cit:234)
[319] Ulpian is precise: âIn every branch of the law, a person who fails to return from enemy hands is regarded as having died at the moment when he was captured.â (Digest 49.15.18) The Lex Cornelia of 84â81 bc specifies the need for remarriage.
[320] Meillassoux 1996:106
[321] Patterson 1982. âSlavery,â as he defines it, âis the permanent, violent domination of natally alienated and generally dishonored persons.â (1982:13)
[322] He quotes Frederick Douglass here to great effect: âA man without force is without the essential dignity of humanity. Human nature is so constituted that it cannot honor a helpless man, although it can pity him; and even that it cannot do long, if the signs of power do not arise.â (in Patterson 1982:13)
[323] Presumably an honorable woman as well, though in the case of women, as we shall see, the question became inextricably caught up in questions of fidelity and chastity.
[324] Paul Houlm (in Duffy, MacShamhrĂĄin and Moynes 2005:431.) True, the balance of trade seems to have shifted back and forth; at some periods Irish ships were raiding English shores, and after 800 ad the Vikings carried off thousands, briefly making Dublin the largest slave market in Europe. Still, by this time, cumals do not appear to any longer have been used as actual currency. There are some parallels here with Africa, where in certain times and places affected by the trade, debts were tallied up in slaves as well (Einzig 1949:153).
[325] St. Patrick, one of the founders of the Irish church, was one of the few of the early Church Fathers who was overtly and unconditionally opposed to slavery.
[326] Doherty 1980:78â83.
[327] Gerriets 1978:128, 1981:171â72, 1985:338. This was in dramatic contrast, incidentally, to Welsh laws from only two or three centuries later, where the prices of all such objects are fastidiously specified (Ellis 1926:379â81). The list of items incidentally is a random selection from the Welsh codes.
[328] Doherty 1980:73â74
[329] This was true in Irish and in Welsh, and apparently, other Celtic languages as well. Charles-Edwards (1978:130, 1993:555) actually translates âhonor priceâ as âface value.â
[330] The one exception being an early ecclesiastical text: Einzig 1949:247â48, Gerriets 1978:71.
[331] The main source on the monetary system is Gerriets (1978), a dissertation that unfortunately was never published as a book. A table of standard rates of exchange between cumal, cows, silver, etc, are also to be found in Charles-Edwards 1993:478â85.
[332] Gerriets 1978:53.
[333] If you had lent a man your horse or sword and he didnât return it in time for a battle, causing loss of face, or even if a monk lent his cowl to another monk who didnât return it in time, causing him not to have proper attire for an important synod, he could demand his honor price (Fergus 1988:118).
[334] The honor price of Welsh kings was far higher (Ellis 1926:144).
[335] Provincial kings, who ranked higher, had an honor price of 14 cumals, and in theory there was a high king at Tara who ruled all Ireland, but the position was often vacant or contested (Byrne 1973).
[336] All of this is a simplification of whatâs in fact an endlessly complicated system, and some points, especially concerning marriage, of which there are several varieties, with different integrations of brideprice and dowry, remain obscure. In the case of clients, for example, there were two initial payments by the lord, the honor price being one of them; with âfree clients,â however, the honor price was not paid and the client was not reduced to servile status, (See Kelly 1988 for the best general summary.)
[337] Dimetian Code II.24.12 (Howel 2006:559). A similar penalty is specified for the killing of public officials from certain districts (Ellis 1926:362).
[338] âThere is no evidence that goods themselves could be assigned prices. That is, while Irish moneys could quantify the status of an individual, they were not used to quantify the value of goods.â (Gerriets 1985:338).
[339] Sutton 2004:374.
[340] Gallant 2000. One might also consider here the phrase âaffair of honor,â or for that matter, âhonor killingââwhich also make clear that such sentiments are hardly confined to rural Greece.
[341] In fact, one could just as easily turn the question around, and ask: Why is it so insulting to suggest that a manâs sister is trading sex for money in the first place? This one reason I say that concepts of honor still shape our perceptions in ways weâre not aware ofâthere are plenty of places in the world where the suggestion that a manâs wife is trading sex for profit, or that his sister is engaged with multiple partners, is more likely to be greeted with bemused good humor than with murderous rage. Weâve already seen examples in the Gunwinggu and the Lele.
[342] Obviously I am distinguishing the term here from the broader sense of patriarchy used in much feminist literature, of any social system based on male subordination of women. Clearly the origins of patriarchy in this broader sense must be sought in a much earlier period of history in both the Mediterranean and Near East.
[343] The âSemitic infiltrationâ model is already to be found in such classic sources as Saggs (1962). Generally speaking, the pattern seems to be one of periodic urban crisis, the near-breakdown of riverine society being followed by revival, apparently after the advent of a new wave of Semitic pastoralists (Adams et al. 1974).
[344] Rohrlich 1980 is a compelling example.
[345] This is of course a vast simplification of a thesis mainly identified with the anthropologist Jack Goody (1976, 1983, 1990). The basic principle is that dowry is not so much a payment by the brideâs father (it might come equally from both sides) but a kind of premature inheritance. Goody has had very little to say about Mesopotamia, though, and that little (1990:315â17) focuses almost exclusively on upper-class practice.
[346] Wilcke 1985, Westbrook 1988, Greengus 1990, Stol 1995:125â27. For Mari: Lafont 1987; for Old Babylonian practice: Greengus 1966, 1969; for Nuzi, Grosz 1983, 1989.
[347] Our best sources are from the city of Nuzi c1500 bc, though Nuzi was atypical in certain ways, mainly due to Hurrian influence. There, marriage payments appear to have been made in stages, for instance, at the birth of a first child (Grosz 1981:176)âa pattern familiar to anthropologists from Melanesia, Africa, and numerous other parts of the world.
[348] Finkelstein 1966, VerSteeg 2000:121, 153n91. A father could claim monetary damages against someone who falsely claimed that his daughter was not a virgin, presumably because it would lower the bride-price (Cooper 2002:101).
[349] Bottéro 1992:113.
[350] Stol 1995:126.
[351] Cardascia 1959 on âmatrimonial adoptionâ (also Mendelsohn 1949:8â12, Greengus 1975). During times of famine, sometimes even the brideprice was dispensed with, and a starving family might turn over their daughter to a rich household in exchange for a promise to keep her alive.
[352] Evans-Prichard 1931, Raglan 1931. Itâs a little ironic that the debate was occurring in England, since this was one of the few places where it was, technically, legal to sell or even auction off oneâs wife (Menefee 1981; Stone 1990:143â48; see Pateman 1988). Stone notes that while public âwife-salesâ in English villages were apparently really prearranged divorces, âthe details of the ritual were designed to emphasize the final nature of the transfer of property, by imitating as closely as possible the sale of a cow or a sheep. A halter was used to lead the wife from her home to the market, and from the market to the house of her purchaser.â (1990:145) The practice, confined to the popular classes, caused a scandal when documented in Hardyâs **Mayor of Casterbridge**, but it was only completely abandoned in 1919.
[353] Finley 1981:153â55; Stienkeller 2003; Mieroop 2005:27â28. Mieroop notes that the earliest such contract is documented from twenty-first-century Babylonia. This is an interesting example for the early history of wage labor. As Iâve written elsewhere (Graeber 2006:66â69; 2007:91â94), wage-labor contracts in the ancient world were primarily a matter of the rental of slavesâa practice that in Mesopotamia is first documented only in neo-Babylonian times (Oppenheim 1964:78, VerSteeg 2000:70â71; for an Egyptian parallel VerSteeg 2002:197).
[354] The entire issue has been complicated by Herodotusâ claim (1.199) that all Babylonian women other than daughters of the elite were expected to prostitute themselves at temples, once, to earn the money for their dowries. This was certainly false, but it has caused the terms of debate to become rather confused between people insisting on the importance of âhierodulesâ or even claiming that all prostitution was effectively sacred (e.g., Kramer 1969, Lambert 1992) and those rejecting the entire notion as Orientalist fantasy (Arnaud 1973, Westenholz 1989, Beard & Henderson 1997, Assante 2003). However, recently published texts from Kish and Sippar make clear that sexual rituals involving temple women, at least some of whom were paid for their services, definitely did take place (Gallery 1980; Yoffee 1998; Stol 1995:138â39) The devadasi analogy incidentally was first to my knowledge proposed in Yoffee 1998:336. On devadasis in general: Orr 2000, Jordan 2003, Vijaisri 2004.
[355] Kramer 1963:116, Bahrani 2001: 59â60.
[356] A similar reading can be found in Bottéro 1992:96, but without the ambivalence, which Lerner (1980:247) emphasizes.
[357] See Lerner 1980, Van Der Toorn 1989, Lambert 1992.
[358] Also, in many places, small-scale female traders are likened to or confused with prostitutes, simply because they have multiple ongoing relationships with unrelated men (for a contemporary Kazakh example: Nazpary 2001)âand the roles can sometimes overlap.
[359] Diakonoff (1982). Loose bands of pastoral nomads or refugees, who also sometimes doubled as soldiers, were often referred to generically as **hapiru** or **habiru**, both in Mesopotamia and to the West. This might be the origin of the term âHebrew,â another group that according to their own histories had fled from bondage, wandered with their flocks in the desert, and eventually descended as conquerors on urban society.
[360] Herodotus 1.199, also Strabo 16.1.20.
[361] Revelations 17.4â5. Revelations seems to follow the perspective of the followers of Peter more than those of Paul. I observe in passing that Rastafarianism, the main prophetic voice today that makes use of the image of Babylon as corruption and oppressionâthough it does tend to play down the imagery of sexual corruptionâhas in practice been very much about the reassertion of patriarchal authority among the poor.
[362] 1980:249â54; 1989:123â40. The main textual source is Driver & Miles 1935; also Cardascia 1969.
[363] In Sumerian weddings, a brideâs father would cover her with a veil, and the groom would remove itâit was by this act that he made her his wife (Stol 1995:128). Not only does this demonstrate the degree to which the veil was a symbol of encompassment in some manâs domestic authority; it might also have been the source from which the later Assyrian practice was eventually adopted.
[364] My take on Confucianism follows Dengâs (1999) somewhat unconventional approach. See Watson 1980 on the commoditization of women; Gates 1989 on its relation to general decline of womenâs freedoms during the Song; there seems to have been another major setback during the Ming dynastyâfor a recent overview, Ko, Haboush, and Piggott (2003). Testart (2000, 2001:148â49, 190) emphasizes that the case of China confirms his âgeneral sociological law,â that societies that practice brideprice will also allow debt slavery (Testart, LĂ©crivain, Karadimas & Govoroff 2001), since this was a place where the government vainly tried to stop both. Another aspect of Confucianism was that male slavery was seen as much more dubious than female slavery; though it never went as far as in Korea, where after the invasion of Hideyoshi, a law was passed decreeing that **only** women could be enslaved.
[365] Tambiah (1973, 1989) was the first to make what is now the standard critique of Goodyâs argument. Goody prefers to see these as indirect dowry payments since they were normally passed to the family (1990:178â97).
[366] On Homeric honor: Finley 1954:118â19, Adkins 1972:14â16 Seaford 1994:6â7. Cattle are again the main unit of account, and silver. Is also apparently used As Classicists have noted, the only actual acts of buying and selling in the Homeric epics are with foreigners (Von Reden 1995:58â76, Seaford 2004:26â30, Finley 1954:67â70). Needless to say, Homeric society lacked the legalistic precision of the Irish notion of âhonor priceâ but the principles were broadly the same, since **tÄ«me** could mean not only âhonorâ but âpenaltyâ and âcompensation.â
[367] **TÄ«me** is not used for the âpriceâ of commodities in the **Iliad** or the **Odyssey**, but then prices of commodities are barely mentioned. It is, however, used for âcompensation,â in the sense of wergeld or honor-price (Seaford 2004:198n46). The first attested use of **time** as purchase price is in the slightly later Homeric Hymn to Demeter (132) where, as Seaford notes, it seems significant that in fact it refers to a slave.
[368] Aristotle, **Constitution of the Athenians** 2.2. He is referring to the great crisis leading to Solonâs reforms, the famous âshaking off of burdensâ of c. 594 bc.
[369] Greek chattel slavery was in fact much more extreme than anything that appears to have existed in the ancient Near East at the time (see e.g., Westermann 1955; Finley 1974, 1981; Wiedemann 1981; Dandamaev 1984; Westbrook 1995), not only because most Near Eastern âslavesâ were not technically slaves at all but redeemable debt pawns, who therefore at least in theory could not be arbitrarily abused, but because even those who were absolute private property had greater rights.
[370] âSelf-sufficiency is an end and what is bestâ (Aristotle **Politics 12**56â58; see Finley 1974:109â11, Veyne 1979, for classic discussions of what this meant in practice.)
[371] The argument here follows Kurke 2002. On the public brothels, see Halperin 1990, Kurke 1996. There actually were Temple prostitutes in Greece too, mostly famously in Corinth, where Strabo (8.6.20) claimed that the Temple of Aphrodite owned a thousand of them, apparently, slaves who had been dedicated to the temple by pious worshippers.
[372] As noted in the quote from David Sutton (2004) above. For a sampling of the anthropological literature on honor in contemporary Greek society, see: Campbell 1964, Peristiany 1965, Schneider 1971, Herzfeld 1980, 1985, Just 2001.
[373] On the impropriety of womenâs work outside the household, see Brock 1994. On segregation of women in general: Keuls 1985, Cohen 1987, Just 1989, Loraux 1993.
[374] The evidence is overwhelming, but until recently has been largely ignored. Llewellyn-Jones (2003) notes that the practice began as an aristocratic affectation, but that by the fifth century, all respectable women âwere veiled daily and routinely, at least in public or in front of non-related menâ (ibid:14).
[375] van Reden 1997:174, referencing Herodotus 7.233, Plutarchâs Pericles, 26.4.
[376] A woman who one of them, Achilles, had personally reduced to slavery. Briseis was from the Trojan town of Lyrnessus, and after Achilles killed her husband and three brothers in the Greek attack on the town, she was awarded to him as a prize. (On learning of this, her father later hanged himself.) In the Iliad, Achilles insists he loves her. Briseisâ opinions were not considered worth recording, though later poets, uncomfortable with the idea that the greatest epic of antiquity was a celebration of simple rape, concocted a story whereby Briseis had actually long been in love with Achilles from afar, and somehow manipulated the course of events so as to cause the battle to begin with.
[377] Homeric warriors werenât really aristocrats at all, or if they were, as Calhoun puts it (1934:308) they were aristocrats âonly in the loosest sense of the word.â Mostly they were just a collection of local chieftains and ambitious warriors.
[378] See Kurke 1997:112â13, 1999:197â98 for Greek elaborations on the theme. So too Seaford: âWhereas the Homeric **gift** is invested with the personality of its heroic donor, the only kind of person that **money** resembles is the prostitute. For Shakespeare it is âthe common whore of all mankindâ â (2002:156, emphasis in the original. For what itâs worth, Seaford is slightly off here: Shakespeare described the **earth** as the âcommon whore of all mankind,â whose womb produces gold, which is money **[Timon of Athens** 4.3.42â45].)
[379] Seaford 2002 in his review of Kurke notes that Greek sources regularly go back and forth on this.
[380] In the **Odyssey** (11.488â91), famously, Achilles, when trying to invoke the lowest and most miserable person he can possibly imagine, invokes not a slave but a **thete**, a mere laborer unattached to any household.
[381] Free **porne** were always the daughters of foreigners or resident aliens. So, incidentally, were the aristocratsâ courtesans.
[382] The reader will observe that even in the anecdotes that follow, women simply donât appear. We have no idea who Polemarchusâ wife was.
[383] Recall here that pederasty was technically against the law. Or, to be more exact, for a man to submit to the passive role in sodomy was illegal; one could be stripped of oneâs citizenship for having done so. While most adult men were involved in love affairs with boys, and most boys with men, all did so under the pretense that no intercourse was actually taking place; as a result, almost anyone could be accused of former impropriety. The most famous case here is Aeschinesâ **Against Timarchus** (see van Reden 2003:120â23, also Dillon 2003:117â28.) Exactly the same dilemmas resurface in Rome, where Cicero, for instance, accused his rival Marc Antony of having once made his living as a male prostitute (Philippics 2.44â45), and Octavian, the later Augustus, was widely reputed to have âprostitutedâ himself, as a youth, to Julius Caesar, among other powerful patrons (Suetonius **Augustus** 68).
[384] The most famous cases were Athens, Corinth, and Megara (Asheri 1969; St. Croix 1981; Finley 1981:156â57.)
[385] The law was called the **palintokia** and is known mainly from Plutarch **(Moralia** 295D, apparently drawing on a lost Aristotelian **Constitution of the Megarians.)** Almost everything about it is at issue in current scholarship (Asheri 1969:14â16; Figueria 1985:149â56, Millettt 1989: 21â22; Hudson 1992:31; Bryant 1994:100â044). Hudson for instance argues that since the event is said to have happened around 540 bc, at a time when interest-bearing loans might not even have existed, the whole story is likely to be later propaganda. Others suggest that it really happened much later. Itâs interesting that all Greek sources treat this as a most radical and outrageous populist measureâdespite the fact that similar measures became standard Catholic policy during most of the European Middle Ages.
[386] It is entirely unclear whether loans at interest even existed in this early period, since the first apparent reference to interest is from roughly 475 bc, and the first utterly clear ones from the later part of that same century (Bogaert 1966, 1968; Finley 1981; Millett 1991a: 44â45; Hudson 1992).
[387] Compare for example Leviticus 25:35â37, which stipulates that it is permissible to make an impoverished âfellow countrymanâ a client or tenant, but **not** to give him an interest-bearing loan.
[388] As Hesiod emphasizes in **Works and Days** (II 344â63); heâs our main source on such matters. Paul Millett (1991a:30â35) provides a close reading of this passage, to illustrate the ambiguities between gifts and loans. Millettâs book **Lending and Borrowing in Ancient Athens** (op cit) is the basic work on that topic. Scholarship on the Greek economy has long been preoccupied by whatâs still (rather anachronistically) called the Primitivist-Modernist debate; Millett takes a strong Primitivist position and has taken predictable heat from the other side (e.g., Cohen 1995, Shipley 1997, 2001). Most of the debate, though, turns on the prevalence of commercial lending, which is tangential to my present concerns.
[389] The story is so striking because Nasruddin almost never elsewhere behaves in a way that a contemporary audience would consider unfair or exploitative. Those stories that do always focus on his relations with his neighbor the miserâthe listener is presumed to know that being a miser, he must, necessarily, be up to no good.
[390] âAgainst Nicostratusâ (Demosthenes 53). My version largely follows Millet (1991a:53â59) but also draws on Trevett 1992, Dillon 2002:94â100, Harris 2006:261â63). The interpretation of Nicostratusâ motives is my own; Dillon, for example, suspects that the entire story of his kidnapping and ransom at Aegina was made upâthough if that were the case, one would imagine Apollodorus would have eventually found out and told the jurors. The text doesnât explicitly say that Nicostratus was an aristocrat, but this seems the most plausible explanation of why someone might have a comfortable country estate but no money. Apollodorus, though, was known, from other contexts, to have feared that his fellow citizens would have contempt for his lowly background, and tried to compensate by lavishâand some felt, over-lavishâgenerosity (see Ballin 1978; Trevett 1992).
[391] Athenians when trying to be high-minded at least spoke as if fellow citizens should behave this way to one another; to loan money at interest to a citizen in dire need was treated as obviously reprehensible behavior (Millett 1991a:26). All philosophers who touched on the subject, starting with Plato **(Laws** 742c, 921c) and Aristotle **(Politics** 1258c) denounced interest as immoral. Obviously not everyone felt that way. Here as in the Middle East, from whence the custom had spread (Hudson 1992), the dilemma was that charging interest made obvious sense in the case of commercial loans, but easily became abusive in the case of consumer loans.
[392] Itâs not clear whether debt slavery, or at least debt peonage, was anywhere entirely eliminated, and debt crises continued to occur at regular intervals in cities other than Athens (Asheri 1969; St. Croix 1981). Some (Rhodes 1981:118â27; Cairns 1991; Harris 2006:249â80) believe that debt bondage was not even entirely eliminated in Athens. Millett (1991a:76) is probably right to say that imperial capitals like Athens, and later Rome, fended off the dangers of debt crises and resulting unrest less by forbidding the practice than by funneling tribute money into social programs that provided a constant source of funds for the poor, making usury largely unnecessary.
[393] Millett 1991b:189â92. The same was true in Roman Galilee (Goodman 1983:55), and presumably in Rome as well (Howgego 1992:13).
[394] the Furies, who pursue Orestes to avenge his killing of his mother, insist that they are collecting a debt due in blood (Aeschylus, Eumenides 260, 319.) Millett (1991a:6â7) compiles a number of examples. Korver (1934, cf. Millet 1991:29â32) demonstrates that there was never any formal distinction between âgiftâ and âloanâ; the two continually shaded into each other.
[395] The two were seen to be connected: Herodotus, famously, argued that for the Persians, the greatest crime was to lie, and that they therefore forbade the loaning of money at interest since it would necessarily give rise to untruthful behavior (1.138).
[396] Plato **Republic** 331c.
[397] Plato Republic 345d. My reading is strongly influenced here by that of Marc Shell (1978). Shellâs essay is important, but sadly neglected, as Classicists only seem to cite each other (at least, on the subject of the Classics).
[398] What Polemarchus is invoking of course is the logic of the heroic gift, and of the feud. If someone helps or harms you, you pay them back the same or better. Polemarchus actually says that there are two circumstances when itâs easiest to do this: in war, and in banking.
[399] The Republic was written in 380 bc, and these events took place in 388/7. See Thesleff 1989:5, DuBois 2003:153â54, for the dates and references to ancient and contemporary scholarship on the issue, which concur that these events did take place. Itâs not entirely clear if Plato was taken in an act of piracy, sold on the orders of an angry ex-patron, or seized as a prisoner of war (AeginaâPlatoâs birthplace, incidentallyâwas then at war with Athens.) But the lines blurred. Curiously, Diogenes the Cynic, a younger contemporary of Plato, was also captured by pirates on a trip to Aegina around the same time. In his case no one came to his aid (unsurprising considering that he rejected all worldly attachments and tended to insult everyone he met). He ended up spending the rest of his life as a slave in Corinth (Diogenes Laertius, 4.9). Plato, Aristotle, and Diogenes were the three most famous philosophers of the fourth century; the fact that two of the three had the experience of standing on an auction block demonstrates that such things really could happen to anyone.
[400] Plato recounts the events in his **Seventh Letter to Dion**, but Annikeris only appears in Diogenes Laertius 3.19â20.
[401] Ihering 1877.
[402] Rights **âin rem,â** or âin the thing,â are considered to be held âagainst all the world,â since âa duty is incumbent on all persons whatsoever to abstain from acts injurious to the rightââthis is opposed to rights â**in personem,â** which are held against a specific individual or group of individuals (Digby & Harrison 1897:301). Garnsey (2007:177â178) notes that Proudhon (1840) was correct in insisting that the âabsoluteâ nature of property rights in the French Civil Code and other paradigmatic modern legal documents goes back directly to Roman law, **both** to the notion of absolute private property, and to that of the emperorâs absolute sovereignty.
[403] The idea that Roman property was not a right goes back to Villey (1946), and became mainstream in English scholarship with Tuck (1979:7â13) and Tierney (1997), though Garnsey (2007:177â95) has recently made a convincing case that Roman jurists did see property as a right **(ius)** in the sense that one had a right of alienation, and to defend oneâs claims in court. Itâs an interesting debate, largely turning on oneâs definition of âright,â but somewhat tangential to my own argument.
[404] âThe paradigmatic relation between a person and a thing is that of ownership, yet the omans themselves seemed never to have defined it. To them, it was a power relationâa form of **potestasâ**directly exercised over the physical thing itselfâ (Samuel 2003:302).
[405] In earliest Roman law (the Twelve Tablets of c450 bc) slaves were still people, but of diminished worth, since injuries against them counted as 50 percent those of a free person (Twelve Tablets VIII.10). By the late Republic, around the time of the emergence of the concept of dominium, slaves had been redefined as **res**, things, and injuries to them had the same legal status as injuries to farm animals (Watson 1987:46)
[406] Patterson: âit is difficult to understand why the Romans would want to invent the idea of a relation between a person and a thing (an almost metaphysical notion, quite at variance with the Roman way of thinking in other areas) ⊠unless we understand that, for most purposes, the âthingâ on their minds was a slaveâ (1982:31).
[407] It does not appear in the Twelve Tablets or early legal documents.
[408] **Dominus** first appears in 111 bc, **dominium**, sometime later (Birks 1985:26). Keith Hopkins (1978) estimates that by the end of the Republic, slaves made up between 30 and 40 percent of the Italian population, perhaps the highest proportion of any known society.
[409] **Digest** 9.2.11 pr., Ulpian in the 18thbook on the Edict.
[410] The examples are from **Digest** 47.2.36 pr., Ulpian in the 41st book on Sabinus, and **Digest** 9.2.33 pr, Paulusâ second book to Plautius, respectively.
[411] See Saller (1984) on **domus** versus **familia**. The word **familia**, and its various later European cognates, **famille** in French, **family** in English, and so on, continued to refer primarily to a unit of authority and not necessarily of kinship until at least the 18th century (Stone 1968, Flandrin 1979, Duby 1982:220â23, Ozment 1983; Herlihy 1985)
[412] Westbrook 1999:207 goes through the three known cases of this really happening. It would seem that the fatherâs authority here was considered identical to that of the state. If a father was found to have executed his child illegitimately, he could be punished.
[413] Or to enslave them. In fact the Law of the Twelve Tablets (III.1) itself seems to be an attempt to reform or moderate even harsher practices, as al-Wahid (Elwahed 1931:81â82) was perhaps the first to point out.
[414] Finley notes that the sexual availability of slaves âis treated as a commonplace in the Graeco-Roman literatureâ (1980:143; see Saller 1987:98â99, Glancey 2006:50â57).
[415] There is a lively debate about whether breeding slaves was ever extensively practiced in Rome: one common theory of slavery (e.g., Meillassoux 1996, Anderson 1974) arguing that it is never profitable to do so, and when a supply of new slaves is cut off, slaves will ordinarily be converted into serfs. There seems no reason to weigh in on this here, but for a summary, see Bradley 1987.
[416] True, Roman citizens could not legally enslave one another; but they could be enslaved by foreigners, and pirates and kidnappers rarely put too fine a point on such things.
[417] The Chinese emperor Wang Mang was so fastidious on this point, for instance, that he once ordered one of his own sons put to death for the arbitrary murder of a slave (Testart 1998:23.)
[418] The **lex Petronia**. Technically it bans owners from ordering slaves to âfight the wild beasts,â a popular public entertainment: âfight,â though, is usually a euphemism, since those fighting hungry lions were not provided with weapons, or obviously inadequate ones. It was only a century later, under Hadrian (117â138 ad), that owners were forbidden to kill their slaves, maintain private dungeons for them or practice other cruel and excessive punishments. Interestingly, the gradual limitation of the power of slave-owners was accompanied by increasing state power, expansion of citizenship, but also the return of various forms of debt-bondage and the creation of dependent peasantry (Finley 1972:92â93; 1981:164â65).
[419] Thus Livy (41.9.11) notes in 177 bc the senate actually passed a law to prevent Italians who were not Roman citizens from selling relatives into slavery in this way in order to become citizens.
[420] The phrase is preserved in the work of the elder Seneca **(Controversias** 4.7) and noted by Finley (1980:96), among others. There is a detailed discussion in Butrica 2006:210â23.
[421] Wirszubski 1950. On the etymology, see Benveniste 1963:262â72. Similarly Kopytoff and Miers (1977) emphasize that in Africa, âfreedomâ always meant incorporation into some kin groupâonly slaves were âfreeâ (in our sense) of all social relations.
[422] Florentius in Justinianâs Institutes (1.5.4.1). Some suggest that the word ânaturalâ in the first sentence was only inserted in later editions, perhaps in the fourth century. The position that slavery is a product of force enshrined in law, contrary to nature, however, goes back at least to the fourth century bc, when Aristotle (Politics 1253b20â23) explicitly takes issue with it (see Cambiano 1987).
[423] Already in the that century, lawyers like Azo and Bracton began asking: If this is true, wouldnât that mean a serf is a free man too? (Harding 1980:424 note 6; see also Buckland 1908:1, Watson 1987).
[424] Ulpian wrote that âeveryone was born free under the law of natureâ and that slavery was a result of the **ius gentium** (âlaw of nationsâ), the common legal usages of mankind. Some later jurists added that property was originally common and the **ius gentium** was responsible for kingdoms, property, and so on (Digest 1.1.5). As Tuck notes (1979:19), these were really scattered ideas, only systematized by Church thinkers like Gratian much later, during the twelfth-century revival of Roman law.
[425] **Princeps legibus solutus est** (âthe sovereign is not bound by the lawsâ), a phrase initially coined by Ulpian and repeated by Justinian (1.3 pr.) This was a very new notion in the ancient world; the Greeks, for instance, had insisted that while men could do as they liked with their women, children, and slaves, any ruler who exploited their own subjects in the same way was the definition of a tyrant. Even the basic principle of modern sovereignty, that rulers hold the ultimate power of life and death over their subjects (which modern heads of state still hold in their power to grant pardons), was looked on with suspicion. Similarly, under the Republic, Cicero argued that rulers who insisted on holding the power of life and death were by definition tyrants, âeven if they prefer to be called kingsâ (De **Re Publica** 3.23, Westbrook 1999:204.)
[426] In the Chronicle of Walter of Guisborough (1957:216); see Clanchy 1993:2â5.
[427] Aylmer 1980.
[428] To be fair, a classical liberal would insist that this is the logical conclusion with starting out from the notion of freedom as active instead of passive (or as philosophers put it, that there are âsubjective rightsâ)âthat is, seeing freedom not just as othersâ obligations to allow us to do whatever the law or custom says we can do, but to do anything that is not specifically forbidden, and that this has had tremendous liberating effects. There is certainly truth in this. But historically, it has been something of a side effect, and there are many other ways to come to the same conclusion that do not require us to accept the underlying assumptions about property.
[429] Tuck 1979:49, cf. Tully 1993:252, Blackburn 1997:63â64.
[430] Note here that in this period, the justification was not based on any assumption of racial inferiorityâracial ideologies came laterâbut rather on the assumption that African laws were legitimate and should be considered binding, at least on Africans.
[431] Iâve made the argument that wage labor is rooted in slavery extensively in the pastâsee e.g., Graeber 2006.
[432] This is the reason, as C.B. MacPherson (1962) explained, that when âhuman rights abusesâ are evoked in the newspapers, it is only when governments can be seen as trespassing on some victimâs person or possessionsâsay, by raping, torturing, or killing them. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, like just about all similar documents, also speaks of universal rights to food and shelter, but one never reads about governments committing âhuman rights abusesâ when they eliminate price supports on basic foodstuffs, even if it leads to widespread malnutrition, or for razing shantytowns or kicking the homeless out of shelters.
[433] One can trace the notion back as least as far back as Seneca, who in the first century ad, argued that slaves could be free in their minds, since force only applied to the âprison of the bodyâ **(De ben-eficiis** 3.20)âthis appears to have been a key point of transition between the notion of freedom as the ability to form moral relations with others, and freedom as an internalization of the masterâs power.
[434] See Roitman 2003:224 for one author who explicitly relates this to debt. For objects as unique points in a human history, there is a vast literature, but see Hoskins 1999, Graeber 2001.
[435] One can tell how unusual slavery was by informantsâ assumptions that slaves would have no idea that this was to be their fate.
[436] Significantly, at the very moment when his social existence was the only existence he had left. The mass killing of slaves at the funerals of kings, or grandees, has been documented from ancient Gaul, to Sumer, China, and the Americas.
[437] **Iliad** 9:342â44.
[438] Evans-Pritchard 1948:36; cf., Sahlins 1981. For a good example of identification of kings and slaves, Feeley-Harnik 1982. Obviously, everyone is well aware that kings do have families, friends, lovers, etcâthe point is that this is always seen as something of a problem, since he should be king to all his subjects equally.
[439] Regarding the influence of Roman law on the liberal tradition, it is fascinating to note that the very earliest author we have on record who laid out something like Smithâs model, where money, and ultimately coinage, is invented as an aid to commerce, was another Roman jurist, Paulus: **Digest** 18.1.1.
[440] But it has by no means been eliminated. (If anyone is inclined to doubt this, I recommend they take a stroll through their neighborhood ignoring all property rights, and see just how long it takes for the weapons to come out.)
[441] âDebt, n. An ingenious substitute for the chain and whip of the slavedriver,â wrote the notorious cynic Ambrose Bierce (The **Devilâs Dictionary**, 1911:49). Certainly for those Thai women who appeared at Neil Bushâs door, the difference between having been sold by oneâs parents, and working off oneâs parentsâ debt contract, was as much a technicality as it would have been two thousand years ago.
[442] One of the few authors I know whoâs confronted the question head-on is Pierre DockĂ©s (1979), who makes a convincing statement that it has to do with the power of the state: at least, slavery as an institution was briefly revived under the Carolingian empire and then vanished again afterward. It is certainly interesting that since the nineteenth century at least, the âtransition from feudalism to capitalismâ has become our historical paradigm for epochal social change, and no one much addresses the transition from ancient slavery to feudalism, even though there is reason to believe that whatever is happening now may much more closely resemble it.
[443] Robin Blackburn makes this argument quite convincingly in **The Making of New World Slavery** (1997). There were some exceptions, notably the Italian city-states. The story is of course more complicated than Iâm representing it: one reason for the hostility was that during much of the Middle Ages, Europeans were largely victims of slave-raiders rather than their beneficiaries, with many captives marketed in North Africa and the Middle East.
[444] The Aegean coins were stamped; the Indian, punched; and the Chinese, cast. This suggests that we are not talking about diffusion here. Speaking of Indian coins, for instance, one historian remarks: âIf there is one thing that seems clear from a punch-marked coin, it is that the person who thought it up had never seen a Greek coinâor if he had seen one, it had not impressed him. The punch-marked coin is made by an entirely different metallurgical processâ (Schaps 2006:9).
[445] Pruessner (1928) was perhaps the first to point this out.
[446] They appear to have been widely used by Old Assyrian merchants operating in Anatolia (Veenhof 1997).
[447] Powell (1978, 1979, 1999:14â18) provides an excellent assessment of the evidence, emphasizing that Babylonians did not produce scales accurate enough to measure the tiny amounts of silver they would have had to use to make ordinary household purchases like fried fish or cords of firewood in cash. He concludes that silver was largely used in transactions between merchants. Market vendors therefore presumably acted as they do in small-scale markets in Africa and Central Asia, today, building up lists of trustworthy clients to whom they could extend credit over time (e.g., Hart 1999:201, Nazpary 2001).
[448] Hudson 2002:21â23, who hypothesizes that the time element was important as merchants would presumably otherwise delay to employ the funds as long as possible. See Renger 1984, 1994; Meiroop 2005.
[449] Iâm referring here to **Qirad** and **Mudaraba** arrangements, similar to the ancient and Medieval Mediterranean **Commenda** (Udovitch 1970, Ray 1997).
[450] Herodotus 1.138.
[451] Herodotus 3.102â5.
[452] Mieroop 2002:63, 2005:29. He notes that Enmetenaâs total grain income in any one year was roughly 37 million liters, making the sum he claims to be owed more than one thousand times his own palaceâs annual revenue.
[453] Lambert 1971; Lemche 1979:16.
[454] Hudson 1993 provides the most detailed overview of this literature.
[455] Hudson 1993:20.
[456] Grierson 1977:17, citing Cerny 1954:907.
[457] Bleiberg 2002
[458] One authority states categorically: âI do not know of debt-annulment decrees issued by any Pharaohâ (Jasnow 2001:42), and adds that there is no evidence for debt-bondage until the very late Demotic period. This is the same period when Greek sources begin to speak of both.
[459] VerSteeg 2002:199; see Lorton 1977:42â44.
[460] This in certain ways resembles the legal loopholes created in both the Medieval Christian and Islamic worlds, where interest was formally banned: see chapter 10 below.
[461] Diodorus Siculus 1.79. See Westermann 1955:50â51 for a comparison of Greek and Egyptian sources on the subject.
[462] The history of the dissemination of interest-bearing debt is only beginning to be reconstructed. It does not yet appear in Ebla (c. 2500 bc), in Old or Middle Kingdom Egypt, or in Mycenaean Greece, but it eventually becomes common in the Levant in the late Bronze Age, and also in Hittite Anatolia. As weâll see, it came quite late to Classical Greece, and even later to places like Germany.
[463] In Chinese historiography, in fact, this whole epoch is known as âthe feudal period.â)
[464] The **Guanzi**, cited in Schaps 2006:20.
[465] Yung-Ti (2006) has recently argued that they werenât, though we wouldnât really know. Thierry (1992:39â41) simply assumes they were, providing much evidence of their use both as units of account and means of payment, but none of their use for buying and selling.
[466] At any rate, cowries were definitely being used as the equivalent of coins in later periods, and the government periodically either suppressed their use or reintroduced them (Quiggin 1949, Swann 1950, Thierry 1992:39â41, Peng 1994.) Cowrie money survived, alongside tally sticks, as a common form of currency in Yunnan province in the far south until relatively recent times (B. Yang 2002), and detailed studies exist, butâas far as I can tellâonly in Chinese.
[467] Scheidel 2004:5.
[468] Kan 1978:92, Martzloff 2002:178. I note in passing that a study of the Inca **khipu** system itself would itself be quite fascinating in this regard; the strings were used to record both obligations we would consider financial, and others we would consider ritual, since as in so many Eurasian languages, the words âdebtâ and âsinâ were the same in Quechua as well (Quitter & Urton 2002:270).
[469] L. Yang (1971:5) finds the first reliable literary reference to loans at interest in the fourth century bc. Peng (1994:98â101) notes that the earliest surviving records (the oracle bones and inscriptions) do not mention loans, but thereâs no reason they would; he also assembles most of the available literary references, finds many references to loans in early periods, and concludes that thereâs no way to know whether to take them seriously. By the Warring States period, however, there is abundant evidence for local usurers, and all the usual abuses.
[470] **Yan tie lun I** 2/4b2â6, in Gale (1967):12.
[471] Guanzi (73 12), Rickett (1998:397)
[472] So around 100 bc, âwhen flood and drought come upon them ⊠those who have grain sell at half value, while those who have not borrow at exorbitant usury. Then paternal acres change hands; sons and grandsons are sold to pay debts; merchants make vast profits, and even petty tradesmen set up business and realize unheard of gainsâ (in Duyvendak 1928:32). Loans at interest are first documented in the fourth century bc in China but may have existed before that (Yang 1971:5). For a parallel case of child-selling for debt in early India, Rhys Davids 1922:218.
[473] Jaspers 1949.
[474] Parkes 1959:71.
[475] Or, if one must be even more precise, we should probably end it in 632 ad, with the death of the Prophet.
[476] Obviously Vedic Hinduism is earlier; I am referring to Hinduism as a self-conscious religion, which is generally seen as having taken shape in reaction to Buddhism and Jainism around this time.
[477] The date used to be set much earlier, at 650 or even 700 bc, but recent archaeology has called this into question. Lydian coins still seem to be the earliest, though, as most of the others have been seem to be the earliest though.
[478] Prakash & Singh 1968, Dhavalikar 1974, Kosambi 1981, Gupta & Hardaker 1995. The latest accepted dates for the appearance of coinage in India, based on radiocarbon analysis, is circa 400 bc (Erdosy 1988:115, 1995:113).
[479] Kosambi (1981) notes that there seems to be a direct connection between the first of these and Bronze Age Harappan cities: âeven after the destruction of Mohenjo Daro, which is entirely a trade city as shown by its fine weights and poor weapons, the traders persisted, and continued to use the very accurate weights of that period.â (ibid:91). Given what we know of Mesopotamia, with which the Harappan civilization was in close contact, it also seems reasonable to assume that they continued to employ older commercial techniques, and, indeed, âpromissory notesâ do appear as familiar practices in our earliest literary sources, such as the Jakatas (Rhys Davids 1901:16, Thapar 1995:125, Fiser 2004:194), even if these are many centuries later. Of course, in this case, the marks were presumably meant to confirm the accuracy of the weight, to show that it hadnât been further trimmed, but the inspiration of earlier credit practices seems likely. Kosambi later confirms this: âThe marks would correspond to modern countersignatures on bills or cheques cleared through business houses.â (1996:178â79)
[480] Our first literary record of coinage in China is of a kingdom that reformed its currency system in 524 bcâwhich means that it already had a currency system, and presumably had for some time (Li 1985:372).
[481] Schaps 2006:34. For a similar recent argument, Schoenberger 2008.
[482] Of course the very first coins were of fairly high denominations and quite possibly used for paying taxes and fees, and for buying houses and cattle more than for everyday purchases (Kraay 1964, Price 1983, Schaps 2004, Vickers 1985). A real market society in Greece, for instance, could only be said to exist when, as in the fifth century, ordinary citizens went to the market carrying minuscule coins of stamped silver or copper in their cheeks.
[483] First proposed by Cook (1958), the explanation has since lost favor (Price 1983, Kraay 1964, Wallace 1987, Schaps 2004:96â101; though cf. Ingham 2004:100)âlargely, on the argument that one cannot pay soldiers with coins unless there are already markets with people willing to accept the coins. This strikes me as a weak objection, since the absence of coinage does not imply the absence of either money or markets; almost all parties to the debate (e.g., Balmuth [1967, 1971, 1975, 2001) who argues that irregular pieces of silver were already in wide use as currency, and Le Rider (2001), Seaford (2004:318â37) or for that matter Schaps (2004:222â35), who argue that they were not numerous enough to be a viable everyday currency, seem to give much consideration to the possibility that most market trade took place on credit. Anyway, as Iâve noted earlier, it would be easy enough for the state to ensure that the coins became acceptable currency simply by insisting that they were the only acceptable means of payment for obligations to the state itself.
[484] Most of the earliest known Greek bankers were of Phoenician descent, and itâs quite possible that they first introduced the concept of interest there (Hudson 1992).
[485] Elayi & Elayi 1992.
[486] Starr 1977:113; see Lee 2000.
[487] Itâs interesting to note that, to our knowledge, the great trading nations did not produce much in the way of great art or philosophy.
[488] The great exception was of course Sparta, which refused to issue its own coinage but developed a system whereby aristocrats adopted a strict military lifestyle and trained permanently for war.
[489] Aristotle himself noted the connection when he emphasized that the constitution of a Greek state could be predicted by the main army of its military: aristocracies if they relied on cavalry (since horses were very expensive), oligarchies in the case of heavy infantry (since armor was not cheap), democracy in the case of light infantry or navies (since anyone could wield a sling or row a boat) **(Politics** 4.3.1289b33â44, 13.1297b16â24, 6.7.1321a6â14).
[490] Keyt (1997:103) summarizing **Politics** 1304b27â31.
[491] Thucydides (6.97.7) claimed that 20,000 escaped from the mines in 421 bc, which is probably exaggerated, but most sources estimate at least 10,000 for most of that century, generally working shackled and under atrocious conditions (Robinson 1973).
[492] Ingham 2004:99â100.
[493] MacDonald 2006:43.
[494] On Alexanderâs armies monetary needs, Davies 1996:80 in turn, 83; on his logistics more generally, Engels 1978. The figure 120,000 includes not only actual troops but servants, camp-followers, and so forth.
[495] Green 1993:366.
[496] The Roman institution was called **nexum**, and we donât know entirely how it worked: i.e., whether it was a form of labor contract, whereby one worked off the debt for a fixed term, or something more like African pawn systems, where the debtorâand his or her childrenâserved in conditions roughly like those of a slave until redemption (see Testart 2002 for the possibilities). See Buckler 1895, Brunt 1974, Cornell 1994:266â67, 330â32.
[497] Hence, most of the scandalous stories that sparked uprisings against debt bondage centered on dramatic cases of physical or sexual abuse; of course, once debt bondage was abolished and household labor was instead supplied by slaves, such abuse was considered normal and acceptable.
[498] The first bronze coins paid to soldiers seem to have been coined around 400 bc (Scheidel 2006), but this was the traditional date according to Roman historians.
[499] What I am arguing flies in the face of much of the conventional scholarly wisdom, summed up best perhaps by Moses Finley when he wrote âin Greece and Rome the debtor class rebelled; whereas in the Near East they did notââand therefore reforms like those of Nehemiah were at least minor, temporary palliatives. Near Eastern rebellion took a different form; moreover, Greek and Roman solutions were both more limited and more temporary than he supposed.
[500] Ioannatou 2006 for a good example. Catalineâs conspiracy of 63 bc was an alliance of indebted aristocrats and desperate peasants. On continued Republican debt and land redistribution campaigns: Mitchell 1993.
[501] Howgego makes this point: âIf less is heard of debt under the Principate it may well be because political stability removed the opportunity for the expression of discontent. This argument is supported by the way in which debt re-emerges as an issue at times of open revoltâ (1992:13).
[502] Plutarch, **Moralia**, 828fâ831a.
[503] There is, needless to say, a vast and conflicting literature, but probably the best source is Banaji (2001). He emphasizes in the late empire, âdebt was the essential means by which employers enforced control over the supply of labour, fragmenting the solidarity of workers and âpersonalizingâ relations between owners and employeesâ (ibid:205), a situation he compares interestingly to India.
[504] Kosambi 1966, Sharma 1968, Misra 1976, Altekar 1977:109â38. Contemporary Indian historians, who refer to them as gana-sanghas (âtribal assembliesâ), tend to dismiss them as warrior aristocracies supported by populations of helots or slaves, though of course, Greek city-states could be described the same way.
[505] In other words, they looked more like Sparta than like Athens. The slaves were also collectively owned (Chakravarti 1985:48â49.) Again, one has to wonder how much this was really the general rule, but I yield to the predominant scholarly opinion on such matters.
[506] **Arthasastra** 2.12.27. See Schaps 2006:18 for a nice comparative commentary.
[507] Thapar 2002:34, Dikshitar 1948.
[508] There were also taxes, of course, usually ranging from 1/6 to 1/4 of total yield (Kosambi 1996:316; Sihag 2005), but taxes also served as a way to bring goods to the market.
[509] So Kosambi 1966:152â57.
[510] And wage labor, two phenomena that, as so often in the ancient world, largely overlapped: the common phrase for workers used in texts from the period was **dasa-karmakara**, âslave-hirelingâ with the assumption that slaves and laborers worked together and were barely distinguishable (Chakravarti 1985). On the predominance of slavery, see Sharma 1958, Rai 1981. The extent is contested, but early Buddhist texts do seem to assume that any wealthy family would normally have domestic slavesâwhich certainly wasnât true in other periods.
[511] Punch-marked coins were also eventually replaced, after Alexanderâs brief conquest of the Indus Valley and his establishment of Greek colonists in Afghanistan, by Aegean-style coins, ultimately causing the entire Indian tradition to disappear (Kosambi 1981, Gupta & Hardaker 1985.)
[512] Itâs referred to as the âPillar Edictâ (Norman 1975:16).
[513] Thereâs a good deal of debate as to when: Schopen (1994) emphasizes there is little evidence for substantial Buddhist monasteries until the first century ad, perhaps three centuries later. This has a great deal of bearing on monetarization too, as weâll see.
[514] âThe private trader was regarded as a thorn **(kantaka)**, a public enemy just short of a national calamity, by Arth. 4.2, taxed and fined for malpractices of which many are taken for grantedâ (Kosambi 1996:243).
[515] Those wishing to become monks had to first affirm that they were not themselves debtors (just as they also had to promise they werenât runaway slaves); but there was no rule saying the monastery itself could not lend money. In China, as weâll see, providing easy credit terms for peasants came to be seen as a form of charity.
[516] Similarly, Buddhist monks are not allowed to see an army, if they can possibly avoid it (Pacittiya, 48â51).
[517] Lewis 1990.
[518] Wilbur 1943, Yates 2002. The state of Qin, during the Warring States period, not only allowed for army officers to be allocated slaves by rank, but for merchants, craftsmen, and the âpoor and idleâ to themselves be âconfiscated as slavesâ (Lewis 1990:61â62).
[519] Scheidel (2006, 2007, 2009) has considered the matter at length and concluded that Chinese currency took the unusual form that it did for two maibn reasons: (1) the historical coincidence that Qin (which used bronze coins) defeated Chu (which used gold) in the civil wars, and subsequent conservatism, and (2) the lack of a highly paid professional army, which allowed the Chinese state to act like the early Roman republic, which also limited itself to bronze coins for peasant conscriptsâbut unlike the Roman republic, was not surrounded by states accustomed to other forms of currency.
[520] Pythagoras was, as far as we know, the first to take the latter course, founding a secret political society that for a while had control over the levers of political power in the Greek cities of southern Italy.
[521] Hadot 1995, 2002. In the ancient world, Christianity was recognized as a philosophy largely because it had its own forms of ascetic practice.
[522] On the Tillers: Graham 1979, 1994:67â110. They seem to have flourished around the same time as Mo Di, the founder of Mohism (roughly 470â391 bc). The Tillers ultimately vanished, leaving behind mainly a series of treatises on agricultural technology, but they had a tremendous influence on early Taoismâwhich, in turn, became the favorite philosophy for peasant rebels for many centuries to come, starting with the Yellow Turbans of 184 ad. Eventually, Taoism was displaced by messianic forms of Buddhism as the favorite ideology of rebellious peasants.
[523] Wei-Ming 1986, Graham 1989, Schwartz 1986.
[524] Legend has it that after one Pythagorean mathematician discovered the existence of irrational numbers, other members of the sect took him on a cruise and dropped him overboard. For an extended discussion of the relation of early Pythagoreanism (530â400 bc) to the rise of a cash economy, see Seaford 2004:266â75).
[525] At least if my own experience in Madagascar is anything to go on.
[526] War is quite similar: itâs also an area in which itâs possible to imagine everyone as playing a game where the rules and stakes are unusually transparent. The main difference is that in war one does care about oneâs fellow soldiers. On the origins of our own notion of âself-interest,â see chapter 11 below.
[527] Not to be confused with the unrelated Confucian term **li**, meaning âritualâ or âetiquette.â Later, **li** became the word for âinterestââthat is, not only âself-interest,â but also âinterest paymentâ (e.g., Cartier 1988:26â27). I should note that my argument here is slightly unconventional. Schwartz (1985:145â51) notes that in Confucius, âprofitâ has a purely pejorative meaning, and he argues that it was subversively reinterpreted by Mo Di. I find it unlikely that Confucius represents conventional wisdom at this time; while his writings are the earliest we have on the subject, his position was clearly marginal for centuries after his death. I am assuming instead that the Legalist tradition reflected the common wisdom even before Confuciusâor certainly, Mencius.
[528] **Zhan Guo Ce** (âStrategies of the Warring Statesâ) no. 109, 7.175
[529] **Annuals of LĂŒ Buwei**, 8/5.4.
[530] See Ames (1994) for a discussion of key terms: **si li** (self-interest), **shi** (strategic advantage), and **li min** (public profit).
[531] Book of Lord Shang 947â48, Duyvendak 1928:65.
[532] Kosambiâs translation (1965:142); the Encyclopedia Britannica prefers âhandbook on profitâ (entry for âCÄrvÄkaâ); Altekar (1977:3), âthe science of wealth.â
[533] Nag & Dikshitar 1927:15. Kosambi argues that the Mauryan polity was thus based on a fundamental contradiction: âa moral law-abiding population ruled by a completely amoral kingâ (1996:237). Yet such a situation is hardly unusual, before or since.
[534] Thucydides 5.85-113 (cf. 3.36â49). The event took place in 416 bc, around the same time that Lord Shang and Kautilya were writing. Significantly, Thucydidesâ own objections to such behavior are not explicitly moral but center on showing that it was not to the âlong-term profitâ of the empire (Kallet 2001:19). On Thucydidesâ own utilitarian materialism more generally, see Sahlins 2004.
[535] Mozi 6:7B, in Hansen 2000:137
[536] Mencius 4.1, in Duyvendak 1928:76â77. He appears to be referring to a distinction originally made by Confucius himself: âthe superior person understands what is right while the inferior person only understands what is personally profitableâ **(Analects** 7.4.16).
[537] The Mohist pathâovertly embrace financial logicâwas the less well trodden. Weâve already seen how in India and Greece, attempts to frame morality as debt went nowhere: even the Vedic principles are ostensibly about liberation from debt, which was also, as weâve seen, a central theme in Israel.
[538] Leenhardt 1979:164.
[539] This interpretation does fly fairly directly in the face of the main thrust of scholarship on the issue, which tends instead to emphasize the âtranscendentalâ nature of Axial Age ideas (e.g., Schwartz 1975, Eisenstadt 1982, 1984, 1986, Roetz 1993, Bellah 2005).
[540] The Greek system actually began with Fire, Air, and Water, and the Indian with Fire, Water, and Earth, though in each case there were numerous elaborations. The Chinese elemental system was fivefold: Wood, Fire, Earth, Metal, Water.
[541] In Christianity, at least in the Augustinian tradition, this is quite explicit: the material world does not in any sense partake of God; God is not in it; it was simply made by Him **(De civitate dei** 4. 12)âthis radical separation of spirit and nature beingâaccording to Henri Frankfort (1948:342â44)âa peculiarity of the Judaeo-Christian tradition. That same Augustinian tradition, though, also drew on Plato to insist that reason, on the other handâthe abstract principle which allows us to understand such things, and which is entirely separate from matter**âdoes** partake of the divine (see Hoitenga 1991:112â14, for the conflict in Augustineâs own ideas here).
[542] Shellâs essay âThe Ring of Gygesâ (1978) has already been cited in the last chapter, in my discussion of Plato; Seaford 1998, 2004.
[543] This is based on the fact that Miletus was one of the cities, if not the first city, to produce coins of small enough denominations that they could be used for everyday transactions (Kraay 1964:67).
[544] Heraclitus was from the nearby Ionian city of Ephesus and Pythagoras originally from the Ionian island of Samos. After Ionia was incorporated into the Persian empire, large numbers of Ionians fled to southern Italy, which then became the center of Greek philosophy, again, at just the period when the Greek cities there became thoroughly monetarized. Athens became the center of Greek philosophy only in the fifth century, which is also when Athens was militarily dominant and the Athenian âowlâ coinage became the main international currency of the Eastern Mediterranean.
[545] Or as Seaford (2004:208) puts it, echoing Anaximanderâs description of his primal substance, âa distinct, eternal, impersonal, all-embracing, unlimited, homogeneous, eternally moving, abstract, regulating substance, destination for all things as well as their originâ (or, at least, âall thingsâ that were available for purchase.)
[546] Seaford 2004:136â46; see Picard 1975; Wallace 1987; Harris 2008a:10. Purely âfiduciaryâ money is of course what a metallist would call âfiatâ or âtokenâ money, or a Keynesian, âchartal money.â Despite Finleyâs arguments to the contrary (1980:141, 196), just about all ancient money was fiduciary to some extent. Itâs easy to see why coins would ordinarily circulate at a higher face value than their weight in gold or silver, since the price of the latter would tend to fluctuate, but the moment the coinâs face value was lower than that of its metal content, there would be no reason not to melt it down.
[547] In the case of truly large states like the Roman or Mauryan empires, inflation did eventually result, but the full effects were not felt for at least a century (see Ingham 2002:101â4, Kessler & Temin 2008, Harris 2008b for some good discussions of the Roman situation.)
[548] Seaford 2004:138â39.
[549] I am partly inspired here by Marcel Maussâs arguments about of the concept of substance (Allen 1998).
[550] Hence, as weâll see Aristotleâs position that a coin was only a social convention **(Nicomachean Ethics** 1133a29â31) remained very much a minority view in the ancient world. It did become the predominant view later, in the Middle Ages.
[551] He is known as PÄyÄsi in the Buddhist scriptures, Paesi in the Jaina (see Bronkhorst 2007:143â159 for a good discussion of these earliest Indian materialists; for the later materialist school, to which Kautilya is said to belong, see Chattopadhyaya 1994. Jaspers (1951:135), writing of India, notes the appearance of âall philosophical trends, including skepticism and materialism, sophistry and nihilismââa significant list, since itâs obviously not a list of âallâ philosophical trends at all, but only the most materialist.
[552] In **The Republic** it is rejected out of hand. In India, as Iâve argued, the Hindu tradition only appears to embrace it. Buddhists, Jains, and other oppositional philosophies didnât use the term at all.
[553] Philo of Alexandria, writing around the time of Christ, says of the Essenes: ânot a single slave is to be found among them, but all are free, exchanging services with each other, and they denounce the owners of slaves, not merely for their injustice in outraging the law of equality, but also for their impiety in annulling the statute of natureâ **(Quod omnis probus liber sit** 79). The Therapeutae, another Jewish group, group rejected all forms of property, but looked on slavery âto be a thing absolutely and wholly contrary to nature, for nature has created all men freeâ (De **Vita Contemplativa** 70). The similarity to Roman law ideas is notable. Jewish groups are unusually well documented; if similar sects existed in, say, Thrace, or Numidia, we probably wouldnât know.
[554] Later legend had it that his father was a king and he grew up in a palace, but the Sakya âkingâ of the time was in fact a elected and rotating position (Kosambi 1965:96).
[555] Coins produced by the barbarian successor states generally did not have a great deal of gold or silver in them; as a result they tended to circulate only within the principality of the king or baron who issued them and were largely useless for trade.
[556] DockĂ©s (1979:62â70) provides a good overview of the situationâliterally, since current understandings of the extent of Roman slave estates in France are based largely on aerial photography. Over time even the free communities largely ended up in debt peonage of one sort or another, or bound to the land as serfs (in Latin, **coloni)**.
[557] As weâve seen, Kosambi saw Magadha as a peak of monetarization. R.S. Sharma (2001:119â62) argues that coinage remained commonplace under the Guptas (280 to 550 ad) but then abruptly disappeared almost everywhere thereafter. However, even if he is right that the total number of coins in circulation did not diminish until then, he himself points out (ibid:143) that the total population of the Ganges Plain almost tripled over this period, so even this would mark a steady decline.
[558] For an overview: R.S. Sharma 1965, Kane 1968 III:411â61, Chatterjee 1971. Schopen (1994) especially emphasizes that the techniques grow more sophisticated over the course of the Middle Ages, for instance, developing bookkeeping techniques for combining compound interest with partial repayments.
[559] Documents on the regulation of monastic affairs pay a great deal of attention to the details: how when the money was lent out, contracts would be signed, sealed, and deposited in the temple before witnesses; how a surety or pledge worth twice the amount of the loan should be turned over, how âdevout lay brothersâ should be assigned to manage the investment, and so forth (Schopen 1994).
[560] From the Arab **dinar**, which in turn derives from the Roman **denarius**. It is unclear whether such sums were actually paid in coins at this point: one early monastic manual, for example, speaking of objects that might be relegated to the Inexhaustible Treasuries and thus put out at interest, mentions âgold and silver, whether in the form of coins, finished or raw, in large or small quantities, pure or alloyed, or whether in the form of utensils, finished or unfinishedâ (MahÄsÄmghika Vinaya, in Gernet 1956 [1995:165]).
[561] Fleet 1888: 260â62, as translated in Schopen 1994:532â33. One need hardly remark on the irony of this emphasis on eternity emerging within Buddhism, a religion founded on the recognition of the impermanence of all worldly attachments.
[562] The commercial loans are documented from an inscription at the West Indian monastery at Karle (Levi 1938: 145; Gernet 1956 [1995:164]; Barreau 1961:444â47), the assemblies from later Tamil temples (Ayyar 1982:40â68, R.S. Sharma 1965.) It is not clear whether some of these were commercial loans, or more like the later Buddhist custom of **jisa** still current in Tibet, Bhutan, and Mongolia, where an individual, or collective, or group of families wishing to support a specific ceremony or, say, an educational project might receive a 500-rupee loan âin perpetuityâ and then be expected to provide 800 rupees a year to organize the ceremony. The responsibilities are then inherited, though the âloanâ can be transferred (Miller 1961, Murphy 1961).
[563] Kalhana, **Rajatarangini** 7.1091â98; see Basham 1948, Riepe 1961:44n49.) The monks were apparently Ajivkas, who still existed at this time.
[564] Naskar 1996, R.S. Sharma 2001:45â66, on the Puranic description of the âKali age,â which seems to be the way later Brahmins referred to the period from roughly Alexanderâs reign to the early Middle Ages, a period of insecurity and unrest when foreign dynasties ruled much of India, and caste hierarchies were widely challenged or rejected.
[565] Manusmrti 8.5.257. Significantly, the debt to other humans vanishes entirely in these texts.
[566] Manusmrti 8.5.270â72. A Sudraâs tongue would also be cut off for insulting a member of the twice-born castes (8.270).
[567] R.S. Sharma 1958, 1987, Chauhan 2003.
[568] âA Sudra, though emancipated by his master, is not released from a state of servitude, for a state which is natural to him, by whom can he be divested?â (Manusmrti, YÄjñavalkya Smrti 8.5.419), or even âSudras must be reduced to slavery, either by purchase or without purchase, because they were created by God for the sake or serving others (8.5.413).
[569] Kautilya allowed 60 percent for commercial loans, 120 percent âfor enterprises that involve journeys through forests,â and twice that for those that involve shipping goods by sea **(Arthasastra** 3.11; one later code, YÄjñavalkya Smrti 2.38 follows this.)
[570] YÄjñavalkya Smrti 2.37, Manusmrti 8.143, Visnusmrti 5.6.2, see Kane 1968 III:421.
[571] R.S. Sharma 1965:68. Similarly, early law-codes specified that anyone who defaulted on a debt should be reborn as a slave or even a domestic animal in their creditorâs household: one later Chinese Buddhist text was even more exact, specifying that for each eight wen defaulted, one must spend one day as an ox, or for each seven, one day as a horse (Zhuang Chun in Peng 1994:244n17)
[572] Dumont (1966).
[573] Gyan Prakash (2003:184) makes this point for the colonial period: when one-time caste hierarchies began to be treated instead as matters of debt bondage, subordinates turned into persons who had equal rights, but whose rights were temporarily âsuspended.â
[574] To be fair, one could also argue that indebted peasants are also likely to be in command of more resources, and thus be more capable of organizing a rebellion. We know very little about popular insurrections in Medieval India (though see Guha (1999). Palat (1986, 1988:205â15; Kosambi 1996:392â93), but the total number of such revolts seems to have been relatively low in comparison to Europe and certainly in comparison to China, where rebellion was almost ceaseless.
[575] âNo one knows just how many rebellions have taken place in Chinese history. From the official record there were several thousand incidents within just three years from 613 to 615 ad, probably one thousand events a year (Wei Z. ad 656: ch. âReport of the Imperial Historiansâ). According to Parsons, during the period 1629â44, there were as many as 234,185 insurrections in China, averaging 43 events per day, or 1.8 outbreaks per hourâ (Deng 1999:220).
[576] Following Deng (1999).
[577] Huang 1999:231.
[578] These loans appear to have been an extension of the logic of the state granaries, which stockpiled food; some to sell at strategic moments to keep prices low, some to distribute free in times of famine; some to loan at low interest to provide an alternative to usurers.
[579] Huang op cit; cf. Zhuoyun & Dull 1980:22â24. For his complex currency reforms: Peng 1994:111â14.
[580] Generally, interest rates were set at a maximum of 20 percent and compound interest was banned. Chinese authorities eventually also adopted the Indian principle that interest should not be allowed to exceed the principal (Cartier 1988:28; Yang 1971:92â103).
[581] Braudel 1979; Wallerstein 1991, 2001.
[582] I am here especially following the work of Boy Bin Wong (1997, 2002; also Mielants 2001, 2007.) Granted, most Braudelans only see later dynasties like the Ming as fully embodying this principle, but I think it can be projected backwards.
[583] So, for instance, while markets themselves were considered beneficial, the government also systematically intervened to prevent price fluctuations, stockpiling commodities when they were cheap and releasing them if prices rose. There were periods of Chinese history when rulers made common cause with merchants, but the result was usually a major popular backlash (Deng 1999:146).
[584] Pommeranz 1998, Goldstone 2002 for an introduction to the vast literature on comparative standards of living. India was actually doing rather well also for most of its history.
[585] ZĂŒrcher 1958:282.
[586] Gernet 1956 (1999: 241â42); for the following discussion see Gernet 1960, Jan 1965, Kieschnick 1997, Benn 1998, 2007.
[587] Tsan-ning (919-1001 ad) quoted in Jan 1965:263. Others appealed to the history of bodhisattvas and pious kings who had made gifts of their own bodies, such as the king who, in time of famine, leapt to his death to be transformed into a mountain of flesh, replete with thousands of heads, eyes, lips, teeth, and tongues, which for ten thousand years only grew larger no matter how much of it humans and animals ingested (Benn 2007:95, 108; cf. Ohnuma 2007).
[588] Tu Mu, cited in Gernet 1956 (1995:245).
[589] This might come as something of a surprise, since the phrase is used so often in contemporary Western popular usage, âkarmic debtâ becoming something of a New Age clichĂ©. But it seems to strike a much more intuitive chord with Euro-Americans than it ever did in India. Despite the close association of debt and sin in the Indian tradition, most early Buddhist schools avoided the conceptâlargely because it implied a continuity of the self, which they saw as ephemeral and ultimately illusory. The exception were the Sammitiya, called âpersonalistsâ as they did believe in an enduring self, who developed the notion of aviprÄÄĆa, whereby the results of good or bad actionsâkarmaââendure like a sheet of paper on which a debt is inscribedâ as an unconscious element of the self that passes from one life to another (Lamotte 1997:22â24, 86â90; Lusthaus 2002:209â10). The idea might have died with that sect had it not been taken up by the famous Mahayana philosopher NÄgÄrjuna, who compared it to an âimperishable promissory noteâ (Kalupahana 1991:54â55, 249; Pasadika 1997). His MÄdhyamaka school in turn became the Sanlun or âThree Treatiseâ school in China; the notion of karmic debt was taken up in particular by the âThree Stagesâ or âThree Levelsâ school created the monk Hsin-Hsing (540â94 ad) (Hubbard 2001).
[590] **Commentary on the Dharma of the Inexhaustible Storehouse of the Mahayana Universe**, as translated by Hubbard (2001:265), with a few changes based on Gernet (1956 [1995:246]).
[591] In Hubbord 2001:266.
[592] Dao Shi, in Cole 1998:117. Coleâs book provides an excellent summary of this literature (see also Ahern 1973, Teiser 1988, Knapp 2004, Oxfeld 2005). Some Medieval texts focus exclusively on the mother, others on parents generally. Interestingly, the same notion of an infinite and unpayable âmilk-debtâ to oneâs mother also appears in Turkey (White 2004:75â76).
[593] **Sutra for the Recompense of Gratitude** cited in Baskind 2007:166. My âfour billion yearsâ translates âkalpa,â which is technically 4.32 billion years. I also changed âthemâ for parents to âherâ for mother since the context refers to a man who cut his own flesh specifically for his motherâs sake.
[594] Chinese Buddhists did not invent the pawnshop, but they appear to have been the first to sponsor them on a large scale. On the origins of pawnbroking in general, see Hardaker 1892, Kuznets 1933. On China specifically: Gernet 1956 [1995:170â73], Yang 1971:71â73, Whelan 1979. In a remarkable parallel, the first âformalâ pawnshops in Europe also emerged from monasteries for similar purposes: the **monti di pieta** or âbanks that take pityâ created by the Franciscans in Italy in the fifteenth century. (Peng 1994:245, also makes note of the parallel.)
[595] Gernet 1956 [1995:142â86], Châen 1964:262â65; Collins 1986:66â71; Peng 1994:243â45. It would seem that Taoist monasteries, which also multiplied in this period, banned making loans (Kohn 2002:76), perhaps in part to mark a distinction.
[596] Gernet 1956 [1995:228], where he famously wrote, âthe donors to the Inexhaustible Treasuries were shareholders, not in the economic domain but that of religion.â As far as I know, the only contemporary scholar who has fully embraced the premise that this was indeed an early form of capitalism is Randall Collins (1986) who sees similar monastic capitalism in later Medieval Europe as well. The accepted Chinese historiography has tended to see the first âshoots of capitalismâ developing later, in the Song, which was much less hostile to merchants than other dynasties, followed by a full embrace of the marketâbut firm rejection of capitalismâin the Ming and Qing. The key question is the organization of labor, and in Tang times this remains somewhat opaque, since even if statistics were available, which theyâre not, itâs difficult to know what terms like âserf,â âslave,â and âwage-laborerâ actually meant in practice.
[597] Gernet 1956 [1995:116â39], Châen 1964:269â71, on land reclamation and monastic slaves.
[598] âIt is claimed that the purpose of this generosity is to relieve the poor and orphans. But in fact there is nothing to it but excess and fraud. This is not a legitimate businessâ Gernet 1956 (1995:104â5, 211).
[599] Gernet 1956 [1995:22].
[600] See Adamek 2005, Walsh 2007.
[601] This is probably why abstractions like Truth, Justice, and Freedom are so often represented as women.
[602] Marco Polo observed the practice in the southern province of Yunnan in the thirteenth century: âBut when they have any business with one another, they take a round or square piece of stick, and split it in two; and one takes one half and the other takes the other half. But before they split it, they make two or three notches in it, or as many as they wish. So, when one of them comes to pay another, he gives him the money or whatever it is, and gets back the piece of stick the other hadâ (Benedetto 1931:193). See also Yang 1971:92, Kan 1978, Peng 1994:320, 330, 508, Trombert 1995:12â15. Tallies of this sort seem, according to Kan, to have preceded writing; and one legend claims that the same man, a minister to the Yellow Emperor, invented both writing and tally contracts simultaneously (Trombert 1995:13).
[603] Graham 1960:179.
[604] Actually the similarity was noticed in antiquity as well: Laozi **(Daodejing** 27) speaks of those who can âcount without a tally, secure a door without a lock.â Most famously, he also insisted âwhen wise men hold the left tally pledge, they do not press their debtors for their debts. Men of virtue hold on to the tally; men lacking virtue pursue their claimsâ (stanza 79).
[605] Or one might better say, turning them at one snap from monetary debts to moral ones, since the very fact that we know the story implies he was eventually rewarded (Peng 1994:100). It is probably significant that the word **fu**, meaning âtally,â also could mean âan auspicious omen granted to a prince as a token of his appointment by Heavenâ (Mathews 1931:283). Similarly, Peng notes a passage from **Strategems of the Warring States**, about a lord attempting to win popular support: âFeng hurried to Bi, where he had the clerks assemble all those people who owed debts, so that his tallies might be matched against theirs. When the tallies had been matched, Feng brought forth a false order to forgive these debts, and he burned the tallies. The people all cheeredâ (ibid:100n9). For Tibetan parallels, see Uebach 2008.
[606] Similar things happened in England, where early contracts were also broken in half in imitation of tally sticks: the phrase âindentured servantâ derives from this practice, since these were contract laborers; the word actually derives from the âindentationsâ or notches on the tally stick used as a contract (Blackstone 1827 I:218).
[607] L. Yang 1971:52; Peng 1994:329â31. Peng perceptively notes âthis method of matching tallies to withdraw cash was actually an outgrowth of the process used in borrowing money, except that the movement over time of loans was transformed into a movement over spaceâ (1994:330).
[608] They were called âdeposit shopsââand L. Yang (1971:78â80) calls them âproto-banks.â Peng (1994:323â27) notes something along these lines was already operating, at least for merchants and travelers, under the Tang, but the government had strict controls preventing bankers from reinvesting the money.
[609] The practice began in Sichuan, which had its own peculiar form of cash, in iron, not bronze, and therefore much more unwieldy.
[610] Peng 1994:508, also 515, 833. All this is very much like the token money that circulated in much of Europe in the Middle Ages.
[611] The most important scholarly exponent of this view is von Glahn (1994, though Peng \[1994\] holds to something close), and it seems the prevailing one among economists, popular and otherwise.
[612] Diagram from MacDonald 2003:65.
[613] One of the favorite images employed when remembering the rule of the Legalists, under the much-hated First Dynasty, was that they constructed great brass cauldrons, in which each law was openly and explicitly spelled outâthen used them to boil criminals alive.
[614] See Bulliet 1979 (also Lapidus 2003:141â46) on the process of conversion. Bulliet also emphasizes (ibid:129) that the main effect of mass conversion was to make the ostensible justification of government, as protector and expander of the faith, seem increasingly hollow. Mass popular support for caliphs and political leaders only reemerged in periods, like the Crusades or during the **reconquista** in Spain, when Islam itself seemed under attack; as of course, for similar reasons, it has in much of the Islamic world today.
[615] âMost of the time the lower circles paid their taxes through their heads, and looked after themselves. Similarly the government received the taxes and provided some sort of security, and apart from this, occupied itself with matters of concern to itself: external war, patronage of learning and the arts, a life of luxurious ostentationâ (Pearson 1982:54).
[616] The proverb appears, attributed to the Prophet himself, in al-Ghazaliâs **Ihyaâ, kitab al-âIlm**, 284, followed by a long list of similar statements: âSaâid Bin Musaiyab said, âWhen you see a religious scholar visiting a prince, avoid him, for he is a thief.â Al-Auzaâi said, âThere is nothing more detestable to Allah than a religious scholar who visits an officialâ âŠâ etc. This attitude has by no means disappeared. A strong majority of Iranian ayatollahs, for example, oppose the idea of an Islamic state, on the grounds that it would necessarily corrupt religion.
[617] Lombard 1947, Grierson 1960. This is often represented as a wise policy of refusal to âdebaseâ the coinage, but it might equally be read as meaning that the caliphâs signature added no additional value. An experiment with Chinese-style paper money in Basra in 1294 failed, as no one was willing to accept money backed only by state trust (Ashtor 1976:257).
[618] MacDonald 2003:64. Gradually this became unsupportable and Muslim empires adopted the more typically Medieval **iqtaâ** system, whereby soldiers were granted the tax revenues from specific territories.
[619] Neither have slaves been employed as soldiers since, except in temporary and anomalous circumstance (e.g., by the Manchus, or in Barbados).
[620] It seems significant that (1) the âinquisitionâ of 832, the failed Abbasid attempt to take control of the ulema; (2) the most important mass conversion of the Caliphateâs subjects to Islam, peaking around 825â850; and (3) the definitive ascent of Turkish slave soldiers in Abbasid armies, often dated to 838, all roughly corresponded in time.
[621] Elwahed 1931:111â35. As he puts it (ibid:127), âthe **inalienability of liberty** is one of the fundamental and uncontested principles of Islam.â Fathers do not have the right to sell their children, and individuals do not have the right to sell themselvesâor at least, if they do, no courts will recognize any resultant ownership claims. I note that this is the diametrical opposite of the ânatural lawâ approach that later developed in Europe.
[622] There is a certain controversy here: some scholars, including some contemporary Muslim scholars opposed to the Islamic economics movement, insist that **riba**, which is unequivocally condemned in the Koran, did not originally refer to âinterestâ in general, but to a pre-Islamic Arabian practice of fining late payment by doubling the money owed, and that the blanket condemnation of interest is a misinterpretation (e.g., Rahman 1964, Kuran 1995). I am in no position to weigh in but, if true, this would suggest that the ban on usury really emerged in Iraq itself as part of the process of the creation of grassroots Islam, which would actually reinforce my general argument.
[623] The best records we have are actually from a community of Jewish merchants in Geniza, in twelfth-century Egypt, who observed the ban on interest even in dealings with one another. The one area where we regularly hear of interest being charged is the one area where coercion was also regularly employed: that is, in dealings with kings, viziers, and officials, who often borrowed large sums of money at interestâespecially, but not exclusively, from Jewish or Christian bankersâto pay their troops. Obliging a request for such an illegal loan was a dangerous business, but refusing even more so (for Abbasid examples, see Ray 1997:68â70, mainly drawing from Fischel 1937).
[624] There were also a whole host of legal subterfuges (called **hiyal)** that one might undertake if one were absolutely determined to charge interest: for instance, buying oneâs debtorâs house for the amount of the loan, charging them rent for it, and then allowing them to buy it back for the same sum; having oneâs debtor agree to buy a certain product monthly and sell it to one at a discount, and so forth. Some schools of Islamic law banned these outright; others merely disapproved. It used to be assumed that these methods were widely employed, since most economic historians assumed interest to be a necessary element of credit, but recent research provides no evidence that they were especially common (for the older view: Khan 1929, for the new: Ray 1997:58â59).
[625] Mez 1922:448, quoted in Labib 1969:89. Note that Basra, the city where everyone in the market paid by check, was also the city where, a century later, Mongol attempts to introduce government-issue paper money were so doggedly resisted. The word **sakk** is incidentally the origin of the English âcheck.â The ultimate origins of **sakk** are contested: Ashtor (1972:555) suggests they were Byzantine; Chosky (1988), Persian.
[626] Goitein (1966, 1967, 1973) provides a detailed summary of financial practices among Jewish merchants in twelfth-century Egypt. Almost every transaction involved credit to some degree. Checks, remarkably similar even in appearance to the kind used today, were in common usageâthough sealed bags of metal coins were even more common in everyday transactions.
[627] Though apparently governments sometimes paid wages by check (Tag El-Din 2007:69.) I am no doubt underplaying the government role in all this: there were, for instance, attempts to set up central government banks, and certainly usually a commitment in principle that the government should enforce commercial standards and regulations. It seems, however, that this rarely came to much in practice.
[628] Udovitch 1970:71â74.
[629] Sarakhsi in Udovitch 1975:11, who has a good discussion of the issues involved. Likewise Ray 1997:59â60.
[630] This should surely also be of interest to students of Pierre Bourdieu, who made a famous argument, based on his study of Kabyle society in Algeria, that a manâs honor in such a society is a form of âsymbolic capital,â analogous to but more important than economic capital, since it is possible to turn honor into money but not the other way around (Bourdieu 1977, 1990). True, the text above does not quite say this, but one does wonder how much this is Bourdieuâs own insight, and how much simply reflects the common sense of his informants.
[631] Following K.N. Chaudhuri (1985:197). The expansion of Islam was spearheaded by both Sufi brotherhoods and legal scholars; many merchants doubled as either or both. The scholarly literature here is unusually rich. See, for instance: Chaudhuri 1985, 1990; Risso 1995; Subrahmanyam 1996; Barendtse 2002; Beaujard 2005.
[632] In Goody 1996:91.
[633] M. Lombard 2003:177â79.
[634] Burtonâs translation; 1934 IV:2013.
[635] And whatâs more, officials employed their own person bankers, and themselves made extensive use of credit instruments such as **suftaja** both for transfer of tax payments, and the secreting away of ill-gotten gains (Hodgson 1974 I:301, Udovitch 1975:8, Ray 1994:69â71.)
[636] âFor Mohammed this natural regulation of the market corresponds to a cosmic regulation. Prices rise and fall as night follows day, as low tides follow high, and price imposition is not only an injustice to the merchant, but a disordering of the natural order of thingsâ (Essid 1995:153).
[637] Only very limited exceptions were made, for instance in times of disaster, and then most scholars insisted it was always better to provide direct relief to the needy than to interfere with market forces. See Ghazanfar & Islahi 2003, Islahi 2004:31â32; for a fuller discussion of Mohammedâs views on price formation, see Tuma 1965, Essid 1988, 1995.
[638] Hosseini 1998:672, 2003:37: âBoth indicate that animals, such as dogs, do not exchange one bone for another.â
[639] Hosseini 1998, 2003. Smith says he visited such a factory himself, which may well be true, but the example of the eighteen steps originally appears in the entry âĂpingleâ in Volume 5 of the French **Encyclopedie**, published in 1755, twenty years earlier. Hosseini also notes that âSmithâs personal library contained the Latin translations of some of the works of Persian (and Arab) scholars of the medieval periodâ (Hosseini 1998:679), suggesting that he might have lifted them from the originals directly. Other important sources for Islamic precedents for later economic theory include: Rodison 1978, Islahi 1985, Essid 1988, Hosseini 1995, Ghazanfar 1991, 2000, 2003, Ghazanfar & Islahi 1997, 2003. It is becoming more and more clear that a great deal of Enlightenment thought traces back to Islamic philosophy: Decartesâ **cogito**, for example, seems to derive from Ibn Sina (a.k.a. Avicenna), Humeâs famous point that the observance of constant conjunctions does not itself prove causality appears in Ghazali, and I have myself noticed Immanuel Kantâs definition of enlightenment in the mouth of a magic bird in the fourteenth-century Persian poet Rumi.
[640] Tusiâs **Nasirean Ethics**, in Sun 2008:409.
[641] Ghazanfar & Islahi 2003:58; Ghazanfar 2003:32â33.
[642] So for example among Ghazaliâs ethical principles, we find âthe buyer should be lenient when bargaining with a poor seller and strict when transacting with a rich seller,â and âa person should be willing to sell to the poor who do not have the means and should extend credit to them without the expectation of repaymentâ (Ghazali **Ihya Ulum al Din II**:79â82, cited in Ghazanfar & Islahi 1997:22)âthe latter of course recalling Luke 6:35.
[643] Ghazali in Ghazanfar & Islahi 1997:27.
[644] Ibid:32.
[645] Ibid:32.
[646] Ibid:35. On postmen in Medieval Islam: Goitein 1964. Ghazaliâs position here recalls and is no doubt influenced by Aristotleâs **Nicomachean Ethics** (1121b): that since money is a social convention meant to facilitate exchange, diverting it into usury defies its purpose; but its ultimate thrust is quite different, closer to Thomas Aquinasâ argument that money is basically a measure and that usury distorts it, and Henry of Ghentâs argument that âmoney is a medium in exchange and not a terminusââunsurprisingly, since Aquinas was likely directly influenced by him (Ghazanfar 2000).
[647] Itâs hard to overstate this. Even the famous âLaffer Curve,â by which the Reagan Administration in the 1980s tried to argue that cutting taxes would increase government revenue by stimulating economic activity, is often called the Khaldun-Laffer curve because it was first proposed, as a general principle, in Ibn Khaldunâs 1377 **Muqaddimah**.
[648] Goitein 1957 for the rise of the âMiddle Eastern bourgeoisie.â
[649] âCrying downâ acted as a de facto tax increase, since one would now need to pay more ecus to make up a tax rate fixed in shillings. Since wages were fixed in pounds, shillings, and pence, this also had the effect of raising their value, and hence it was usually popular. âCrying upâ by contrast had the effect of lowering the effective value of the units of account. This could be useful to reduce a kingâsâor his alliesââpersonal debt measured in such units, but it also undercut the income of wage-earners and those on any sort of fixed income and so was often protested.
[650] Langholm 1979, Wood 2002:73â76.
[651] On the patristic literature on usury: Maloney 1983; Gordon 1989; Moser 2000; Holman 2002:112â26; Jones 2004:25â30.
[652] Matthew 5:42
[653] St Basil of Caesarea, **Homilia II in Psalmum XIV** (PG 29, 268â69).
[654] op cit.
[655] op cit.
[656] Ambrose **De Officiis** 2.25.89.
[657] Ambrose **De Tobia** 15:51. See Nelson 1949:3â5, Gordon 1989:114â118.
[658] Though not entirely. Itâs worthy to note that the main supply of slaves to the empire at this time came from Germanic barbarians outside the empire, who were acquired **either** through war or debt.
[659] âIf each one,â he wrote, âafter having taken from his personal wealth whatever would satisfy his personal needs, would leave what was superfluous to those who lack every necessity, there would be no rich or poorâ **(In Illiud Lucae** 49D)âBasil himself had been born an aristocrat, but he had sold off his landed estates and distributed the proceeds to the poor.
[660] **Homilia II in Psalmum XIV** (PG 29, 277C). The reference is to Proverbs 19.17.
[661] **Summa** 8.3.1.3: âsince grace is freely given, it excludes the idea of debt ⊠In [no] sense does debt imply that God owes anything to another creature.â
[662] Clavero (1986) sees this as a basic conflict over the nature of the contract, and hence the legal basis of human relations in European history: usury, and by extension profit, was denounced, but rent, the basis of feudal relations, was never challenged.
[663] Gordon 1989:115. âWhat is commerce,â wrote Cassiodorus (485â585), âexcept to want to sell dear that which can be bought cheap? Therefore those merchants are detestable who, with no consideration of Godâs justice, burden their wares more with perjury than value. Them the Lord evicted them from the Temple saying, âDo not make my Fatherâs house into a den of thievesâ (in Langholm 1996:454).
[664] On the Jewish legal tradition concerning usury, see Stein 1953, 1955; Kirschenbaum 1985.
[665] Poliakov 1977:21.
[666] Nelson (1949) assumed that the âExceptionâ was often held to apply to relations between Christians and Jews, but Noonan (1957:101â2) insists that it was mainly held to apply only to âheretics and infidels, particularly the Saracens,â and by some, not even to them.
[667] Up to 52 percent with security, up to 120 percent without (Homer 1987:91).
[668] Debtorâs prisons, in the sense of prisons exclusively for debtors, existed in England only after 1263, but the imprisonment of debtors has a much longer history. Above all, Jewish lenders seem to have been employed as the means of transforming virtual, credit money into coinage, collecting the family silver from insolvent debtors, and turning it over to royal mints. They also won title to a great deal of land from defaulting debtors, most of which ended up in the hands of barons or monasteries (Singer 1964; Bowers 1983; Schofield & Mayhew 2002).
[669] Roger of Wendower, **Flowers of History** 252â53. Roger doesnât name the victim; in some later versions his name is Abraham, in others, Isaac.
[670] Matthew Prior, in Bolles 1837:13.
[671] Or even, for that matter, Nietzscheâs fantasies of the origins of justice in mutilation. Where one was a projection onto Jews of atrocities actually committed against Jews, Nietzsche was writing in an age where actual âsavagesâ were often punished by similar tortures and mutilations for failure to pay their debts to the colonial tax authorities, as later became a most notorious scandal in Leopoldâs Belgian Congo.
[672] Mundill (2002), Brand (2003).
[673] Cohn 1972:80.
[674] Peter Cantor, in Nelson 1949:10â11.
[675] It was a firm from Cahors, for instance, who received the property of the English Jews when the latter were finally expelled in 1290. Though for a long time, Lombards and Cahorsins were themselves dependent on royal favor and hardly in much better position than the Jews. In France, the kings seemed to expropriate and expel Jews and Lombards alternately (Poliakov 1977:42).
[676] Noonan 1957:18â19; Le Goff 1990:23â27.
[677] There are two sorts of wealth-getting, as I have said; one is a part of household management, the other is retail trade: the former necessary and honorable, while that which consists in exchange is justly censured; for it is unnatural, and a mode by which men profit from one another. The most hated sort, and with the greatest reason, is usury, which makes a profit out of money itself, and not from the natural object of it. For money was intended to be used in exchange, but not to increase at interest. And this term âinterestâ **(tokos)**, which means the birth of money from money, is applied to the breeding of money because the offspring resembles the parent. âWherefore of all modes of getting wealth this is the most unnaturalâ (Aristotle, **Politics** 1258b). The Nicomachean Ethics (1121b) is equally damning. For the best general analysis of the Aristotelean tradition on usury: Langholm 1984.
[678] Noonan 1957:105â12; Langholm 1984:50.
[679] The technical term for the lost income is **lucrum cessans:** see OâBrien 1920: 107â10, Noonan 1957:114â28, Langholm 1992:60â61; 1998:75; Spufford 1989:260.
[680] As German merchants also did in the Baltic cities of the Hanseatic alliance. On the Medici bank as a case in point, see de Roover 1946, 1963, Parks 2005.
[681] The situation in Venice, a pioneer in these matters, is telling: there was no merchant guild, but only craft guilds, since guilds were essentially created as protection against the government, and in Venice, the merchants **were** the government (MacKenney 1987; Mauro 1993:259â60).
[682] They were accused of both heresy and sodomy: see Barber 1978.
[683] One cannot âproveâ the Islamic inspiration of European bills of exchange, but considering the amount of trade between the two sides of the Mediterranean, denying it seems bizarre. Braudel (1995:816â17) proposes that the idea must have reached Europe through Jewish merchants, who we know to have long been using them in Egypt.
[684] On bills of exchange: Usher 1914; de Roover 1967; Boyer-Xambeu, Deleplace, and Gillard 1994; Munro 2003b:542â46; Denzel 2006. There were innumerable currencies, any of which might at any time be âcried up,â âcried down,â or otherwise fluctuate in value. Bills of exchange also allowed merchants to effectively engage in currency speculation, and even get around usury laws, once it became possible to pay for one bill of exchange by writing a different bill of exchange, due in several monthsâ time, for a slightly higher sum. This was called âdry exchangeâ (de Roover 1944), and over time the Church became increasingly skeptical, causing yet another round of financial creativity to get around the laws. Itâs worthy of note that the rates of interest on such commercial loans were generally quite low: twelve percent at the highest, in dramatic contrast to consumer loans. This is a sign of the increasingly lower risk of such transactions (see Homer 1987 for a history of interest rates).
[685] Lane 1934.
[686] âIn very many respects, such as the organization of slave labor, management of colonies, imperial administration, commercial institutions, maritime technology and navigation, and naval gunnery, the Italian city-states were the direct forerunners of the Portuguese and Spanish empires, to the shaping of which the Italians contributed so heavily, and in the profits of which they so largely sharedâ (Brady 1997:150).
[687] They appear to have used Greek serfs at first, and sometimes Arabs captured in the Crusades, and only later, Africans. Still, this was the economic model that was eventually transported by Portuguese merchants to Atlantic islands like the Canaries, then eventually to the Caribbean (Verlinden 1970, Phillips 1985:93â97, Solow 1987, Wartburg 1995).
[688] Scammell 1981:173â75.
[689] Spufford 1988:142
[690] On the notion of adventure: Auerbach 1946, Nerlich 1977.
[691] Duby (1973) makes this point. The âround tableâ was originally a type of tournament, and especially in the 1300s, it became common to make such tournaments explicit imitations of King Arthurâs court, with knights entering the contests taking on roles from them: Galahad, Gawain, Bors, etc.
[692] Also at a time when technological changes, especially the invention of the crossbow and the rise of professional armies, were beginning to render knightsâ role in combat increasingly irrelevant (Vance 1973).
[693] Kelly 1937:10.
[694] See Schoenberger 2008 for a recent and compelling take: comparing the role of war mobilization in creating markets in Greece and Rome to Western Europe in the High Middle Ages.
[695] Wolf 1954.
[696] A point originally made by Vance (1986:48). The similarity is more obvious in the German poet Wolfram von Eschenbachâs **Parzifal**, written perhaps twenty years later, in which knights âroam freely over Spain, North Africa, Egypt, Syria, to Baghdad, Armenia, India, Ceylonâ (Adolf 1957:113)âand Islamic references are legion (Adolf 1947, 1957)âthat is, areas known to Europeans of the time only through trade. The fact that actual merchants, on those rare occasions when they appear, are never sympathetic characters has little bearing.
[697] Wagner, **Die Wibelungen: Weltgeschichte aus der Sage** (1848)âwhich in English is âWorld History as Told in Saga.â I am taking my account of Wagnerâs argument from another wonderful, if sometimes extravagant, essay by Marc Shell called âAccounting for the Grailâ (1992:37â38). Wagnerâs argument is really more complicated: it centers on the failed attempt by the Holy Roman Emperor Frederick Barbarossa to subdue the Italian city-states and the abandonment of his principle that property can only flow from the king; instead, we have the rise of mercantile private property, which is echoed by financial abstraction.
[698] Shell sees the Grail as a transformation of the older notion of the cornucopia or inexhaustible purse in an age âjust beginning to be acquainted with checks and creditâânoting the connection of the legend with the Templars, and fact that Chretienâwhose name means âChristianââwas likely, for that reason, to have been a converted Jew. Wolfram also claimed that he got the legend from a Jewish source (Shell 1992:44â45).
[699] Even China was often split and fractured. Just about all the great empire-building projects of the Middle Ages were the work not of professional armies, but of nomadic peoples: the Arabs, Mongols, Tatars, and Turks.
[700] **Nicomachean Ethics** 1133a29â31.
[701] He compares money not only to a postman, but also, to a âruler,â who also stands outside society to govern and regulate our interactions. Itâs interesting to note that Thomas Aquinas, who might have been directly influenced by Ghazali (Ghazanfar 2000), did accept Aristotleâs argument that money was a social convention that humans could just as easily change. For a while, in the late Middle Ages, this became the predominant Catholic view.
[702] As far as I know, the only scholar to have pointed out the connection is Bernard Faure, a French student of Japanese Buddhism: Faure 1998:798, 2000:225.
[703] Later still, as cash transactions became more common, the term was applied to small sums of cash offered as down-payment, rather in the sense of English âearnest money.â On **symbola** in general: Beauchet 1897; Jones 1956:217; Shell 1978:32â35.
[704] Descat 1995:986.
[705] Aristotle **On Interepretation** 1.16â17. Whitaker (2002:10) thus observes that for Aristotle, âthe meaning of a word is fixed by convention, just as the importance attached to a tally, token, or ticket depends on agreement between the parties concerned.â
[706] **Nicomachean Ethics** 1133a29â31.
[707] But they believed that these formulae summed up or âdrew togetherâ the essence of those secret truths that the Mysteries revealedââsymbolon,â being derived the verb **symballein**, meaning âto gather, bring together, or compare.â
[708] MĂŒri 1931, Meyer 1999. The only knowledge we have of such **symbola** comes from Christian sources; Christians later adopted their own symbolon, the Creed, and this remained the primary referent of the term âsymbolâ throughout the Middle Ages (Ladner 1979).
[709] Or pseudo-Dionysius, since the real Dionysius the Areopagite was a first-century Athenian converted to Christianity by St. Paul. Pseudo-Dionysiusâ works are an attempt to reconcile neo-Platonism, with its notion of philosophy as the process of the liberation of the soul from material creation and its reunification with the divine, with Christian orthodoxy. Unfortunately, his most relevant work, **Symbolic Theology**, has been lost, but his surviving works all bear on the issue to some degree.
[710] In Barasch 1993:161.
[711] Pseudo-Dionysius, **On the Celestial Hierarchy** 141AâC. On Dionysiusâ theory of symbolism in general, and its influence, see Barasch 1993:158â80, also Goux 1990:67, Gadamer 2004:63â64.
[712] He calls them, like communion, âgifts that are granted to us in symbolic mode.â **On the Celestial Hierarchy** 124A.
[713] Mathews 1934:283. Compare the definition of symbolon:
[714] Rotours 1952:6. On **fu** (or **qi**, another name for debt tallies that could be used more generally for âtokensâ) more generally: Rotours 1952, Kaltenmark 1960, Kan 1978, Faure 2000:221â29: Falkenhausen 2005.
[715] There is a curious tension here: the will of heaven is also in a certain sense the will of the people, and Chinese thinkers varied on where they placed the emphasis. Xunzi, for instance, assumed that the authority of the king is based on the confidence of the people. He also argued that while confidence among the people is maintained by contracts ensured by the matching of tally sticks, under a truly just king, social trust will be such that such objects will become unnecessary (Roetz 1993:73â74).
[716] Kohn 2000:330. Similarly in Japan: Faure 2000:227.
[717] In the **Encyclopedia of Taoism** they are described as âdiagrams, conceived as a form of celestial writing, that derive their power from the matching celestial counterpart kept by the deities who bestowed themâ (Bokenkamp 2008:35). On Taoist **fu:** Kaltenmark 1960; Seidel 1983; Strickmann 2002:190â91; Verellen 2006; on Buddhist parallels, see Faure 1998; Robson 2008.
[718] Sasso 1978; the origins of the yin-yang symbol remain obscure and contested but those Sinologists Iâve consulted find this plausible. The generic word for âsymbolâ in contemporary Chinese is **fĂșhĂ o**, which is directly derived from fu.
[719] Insofar as Iâm weighing in on the âWhy didnât the Islamic world develop modern capitalism?â debate, then, it seems to me that both Udovitchâs argument (1975:19â21) that the Islamic world never developed impersonal credit mechanisms, and Rayâs objection (1997:39â40) that the ban on interest and insurance was more important, carry weight. Rayâs suggestion that differences in inheritance laws might play a role also deserves investigation.
[720] Maitland 1908:54.
[721] Davis 1904.
[722] In the Platonic sense: just as any particular, physical bird we might happen to see on a nearby fruit tree is merely a token of the general idea of âbirdâ (which is immaterial, abstract, angelic), so do the various physical, mortal individuals who join together to make up a corporation become an abstract, angelic Idea. Kantorowicz argues that it took a number of intellectual innovations to make the notion of the corporation possible: notably, the idea of the aeon or aevum, eternal time, that is, time that lasts forever, as opposed to the Augustinian eternity which is outside of time entirely and was considered the habitation of the angels, to the revival of the works of Dionysius the Areopagite (1957:280â81).
[723] Kantorowicz 1957:282â83.
[724] Islamic law, for instance, not only did not develop the notion of fictive persons, but steadfastly resisted recognizing corporations until quite recently (Kuran 2005).
[725] Mainly Randall Collins (1986:52â58), who also makes the comparison with China; cf. Coleman 1988.
[726] See Nerlich 1987:121â24.
[727] On English wages, see Dyer 1989; on English festive life, there is a vast literature, but a good recent source is Humphrey 2001. Silvia Federici (2004) provides a compelling recent synthesis.
[728] For a very small sampling of more recent debates over the âprice revolution,â see Hamilton 1934, Cipolla 1967, Flynn 1982, Goldstone 1984, 1991, Fisher 1989, Munro 2003a, 2007. The main argument is between monetarists who continue to argue that increase in the amount of specie is ultimately responsible for the inflation, and those who emphasize the role of rapid population increase, though most specific arguments are considerably more nuanced.
[729] Historians speak of âbullion faminesââas most active mines dried up, such gold and silver that wasnât sucked out of Europe to pay for eastern luxuries was increasingly hidden away, causing all sorts of difficulties for commerce. In the 1460s, the shortage of specie in cities like Lisbon had been so acute that merchant ships visiting with cargoes full of wares often had to return home without selling anything (Spufford 1988:339â62).
[730] Brook 1998. Needless to say, Iâm simplifying enormously: another problem was the growth of landlordism, with many smallholders falling in debt to landlords for inability to pay. As members of the ever-increasing royal family and other favored families gained tax exemptions from the state, the tax burden on smallholders became so heavy that many felt forced to sell their lands to the powerful families in exchange for tenancy agreements to free those lands from taxes.
[731] Chinese historians count 77 different âminersâ revoltsâ during the 1430s and â40s (Harrison 1965:103â4; cf. Tong 1992:60â64; Gernet 1982:414). Between 1445 and 1449 these became a serious threat as silver miners under a rebel leader named Ye Zongliu made common cause with tenant farmers and the urban poor in overpopulated Fujian and Shaxian, sparking an uprising that spread to a number of different provinces, seizing a number of cities and expelling much of the landed gentry.
[732] Von Glahn (1996:70â82) documents the process. Gernet (1982:415â16) documents how between 1450 and 1500, most taxes became payable in silver. The process culminated in the âsingle lash of the whipâ method: tax reforms put into place between 1530 and 1581 (Huang 1974, see Arrighi, Hui, Hung and Seldon 2003:272â73).
[733] Wong 1997, Pomeranz 2000, Arrighi 2007, among many others who make this point.
[734] Pomeranz 2000:273.
[735] The value of silver in China (as measured in gold) remained, through the sixteenth century, roughly twice what it was in Lisbon or Antwerp (Flynn & GirĂĄldez 1995, 2002).
[736] von Glahn 1996b:440; Atwell 1998.
[737] Chalis 1978:157.
[738] China had its own âage of explorationâ in the early fifteenth century, but it was not followed by mass conquest and enslavement.
[739] Itâs possible that they were wrong. Generally populations did decline by 90 percent even in areas where no direct genocide was taking place. But in most places, after a generation or so, populations started recovering; in Hispaniola and many parts of Mexico and Peru, around the mines, the ultimate death rate was more like 100 percent.
[740] Todorov 1984:137â38; for the original, Icazbalceta 2008:23â26.
[741] One historian remarks: âBy the close of the sixteenth century bullion, primarily silver, made up over 95 percent of all exports leaving Spanish America for Europe. Nearly that same percentage of the indigenous population had been destroyed in the process of seizing those richesâ (Stannard 1993:221).
[742] Bernal DĂaz 1963:43.
[743] Bernal DĂaz: the quote is a synthesis of the Lockhart translation (1844 II:120) and Cohen translation (1963:412), though these appear to be based on slightly different originals.
[744] Bernal DĂaz op cit.
[745] Cortés 1868:141.
[746] Most of the conquistadors had similar stories. Balboa came to the Americas to flee his creditors; Pizarro borrowed so heavily to outfit his expedition to Peru that after early reverses, it was only the fear of debtorâs prison that prevented his return to Panama; Francisco de Montejo had to pawn his entire Mexican possessions for an eight-thousand-peso loan to launch his expedition to Honduras; Pedro de Alvarado too ended up deeply in debt, finally throwing everything into a scheme to conquer the Spice Islands and Chinaâon his death, creditors immediately tried to put his remaining estates to auction.
[747] e.g., Pagden 1986.
[748] Gibson 1964:253. All this is disturbingly reminiscent of global politics nowadays, in which the United Nations, for example, will urge poor countries to make education free and available to everyone, and then the International Monetary Fund (which is, legally, actually a part of the United Nations) will insist that those same countries do exactly the opposite, imposing school fees as part of broader âeconomic reformsâ as a condition of refinancing the countryâs loans.
[749] Following William Pietz (1985:8), who studied early merchant adventurerâs accounts of West Africa; though Todorov (1984:129â31) on the very similar perspective of the conquistadors.
[750] Some did go bankruptâfor instance, one branch of the Fuggers. But this was surprisingly rare.
[751] Martin Luther, **Von Kaufshandlung und Wucher**, 1524, cited in Nelson 1949:50.
[752] In Lutherâs time the main issue was a practice called **Zinskauf**, technically rent on leased property, which was basically a disguised form of interest-bearing loan.
[753] In Baker 1974:53â54. The reference to Paul is in Romans 13:7.
[754] He argued that the fact that Deuteronomy allows usury under any circumstances demonstrates that this could not have been a universal âspiritual law,â but was a political law created for the specific ancient Israeli situation, and therefore, that it could be considered irrelevant in different ones.
[755] And in fact, this is what âcapitalâ originally meant. The term itself goes back to Latin **capitale**, which meant âfunds, stock of merchandise, sum of money, or money carrying interestâ (Braudel 1992:232). It appears in English in the midâsixteenth century largely as a term borrowed from Italian bookkeeping techniques (Cannan 1921, Richard 1926) for what remained when one squared property, credits, and debts; though until the nineteenth century, English sources generally preferred the word âstockââin part, one suspects, because âcapitalâ was so closely associated with usury.
[756] Nations that, after all, also practiced usury on one another: Nelson 1949:76.
[757] Ben Nelson emphasized this in an important book, **The Idea of Usury: From Tribal Brotherhood to Universal Otherhood**.
[758] Midelfort 1996:39.
[759] Zmora 2006:6â8. Public financing at this period largely meant disguised interest-bearing loans from the minor nobility, who were also the stratum from which local administrators were drawn.
[760] On church lands: Dixon 2002:91. On Casimirâs gambling debts: Janssen 1910 IV:147. His overall debt rose to half a million guilders in 1528, and over three quarters of a million by 1541 (Zmora 2006:13n55.)
[761] He was later accused of conspiring with Count Wilhelm von Henneburg, who had gone over to the rebels, to become secular Duke of the territories then held by the Bishop of Wurzburg.
[762] From âReport of the Margraveâs Commander, Michel Gross from Trock-au,â in Scott & Scribner 1991:301. The sums are based on a promise of 1 florin per execution, Âœ per mutilation. We do not know if Casimir ever paid this particular debt.
[763] For some relevant accounts of the revolt and repression: Seebohm 1877:141â45; Janssen 1910 IV:323â26; Blickle 1977; Endres 1979; Vice 1988; Robisheaux 1989:48â67, Sea 2007. Casimir is said to have ultimately settled into exacting fines, eventually demanding some 104,000 guldens in compensation from his subjects.
[764] Linebaugh (2008) makes a beautiful analysis of this sort of phenomenon in his essay on the social origins of the Magna Carta.
[765] It is telling that despite the endless reprisals against commoners, none of the German princes or nobility, even those who openly collaborated with the rebels, was held accountable in any way.
[766] Muldrew 1993a, 1993b, 1996, 1998, 2001; cf. MacIntosh 1988; Zell 1996, Waswo 2004, Ingram 2006, Valenze 2006, Kitch 2007. I find myself strongly agreeing with most of Muldrewâs conclusions, only qualifying some: for instance, his rejection of MacPhersonâs possessive individualism argument (1962) strikes me as unnecessary, since I suspect that the latter does identify changes that are happening on a deeper structural level less accessible to explicit discourse (see Graeber 1997).
[767] Muldrew (2001:92) estimates that in c. 1600, eight thousand London merchants might have possessed as much as one-third of all the cash in England.
[768] Williamson 1889; Whiting 1971; Mathias 1979b; Valenze 2006:34â40.
[769] Gold and silver were a very small part of household wealth: inventories reveal on average fifteen shillings of credit for every one in coin (Muldrew 1998).
[770] This principle of a right to livelihood is key to what E.P. Thompson famously called âmoral economy of the crowdâ (1971) in eighteenth-century England, a notion that Muldrew (1993a) thinks can be applied to these credit systems as a whole.
[771] Stout 1742:74â75, parts of the same passage are cited in Muldrew 1993a:178, and 1998:152.
[772] To be more precise, either piety (in the Calvinist case) or good natured sociality (in the case of those that opposed them in the name of older festive values)âin the years before the civil war, many parish governments were divided between the âgodlyâ and âgood honest menâ (Hunt 1983:146)
[773] Shepherd 2000, Walker 1996; for my own take on âlife-cycle serviceâ and wage labor, see, again, Graeber 1997.
[774] Hill 1972:39â56, Wrightson & Levine 1979, Beier 1985.
[775] Muldrew 2001:84.
[776] For a classic statement on the connection of Tudor markets, festivals, and morality, see Agnew (1986).
[777] Johnson 2004:56â58. On the two conceptions of justice: Wrightson 1980. Bodinâs essay was widely read. It drew on Aquinasâ view of love and friendship as prior to the legal order, which, in turn, harkens back to Aristotleâs **Nicomachean Ethics**, which reached Europe through Arab sources. Whether there was also a direct influence from the Islamic sources themselves we do not know, but considering the degree of general mutual engagement (Ghazanfar 2003) it seems likely.
[778] Gerard de Malynesâs **Maintenance of Free Trade** (1622), cited in Muldrew 1998:98, also Muldrew 2001:83.
[779] Chaucer is full of this sort of thing: the Wife of Bath has much to say about conjugal debts (e.g., Cotter 1969). It was really in the period of about 1400â1600 that everything came to be so framed as debt, presumably reflecting the first stirrings of possessive individualism, and attempts to reconcile it to older moral paradigms. Guth (2008), a legal historian, thus calls these centuries âthe age of debt,â one which was then replaced after 1600 by an âage of contract.â
[780] Davenant 1771:152.
[781] Marshall Sahlins (1996, 2008) has been emphasizing the theological roots of Hobbes for some time. Much of the following analysis draws on his influence.
[782] Hobbes himself doesnât use the term âself-interestâ but does speak of âparticular,â âprivate,â and âcommonâ interests.
[783] **De LâEsprit** 53, cited in Hirschman 1986:45. Exploring the contrast between Shangâs âprofitâ and HelvĂ©tiusâ âinterestâ would be a telling history in itself. They are not the same concept.
[784] âInterestâ (from **interesse)** comes into common usage as a euphemism for usury in the fourteenth century, but it only comes to be used in its more familiar, general sense in the sixteenth. Hobbes doesnât use âself-interest,â though he speaks of âprivateâ and âcommonâ interests; but that term was already current, having appeared in the work of Machiavelliâs friend Francesco Guicciadini in 1512. It becomes commonplace in the eighteenth century (see Hirschman 1977, 1992, especially chapter 2, âon the concept of interestâ; Dumont 1981; Myers 1983, Heilbron 1998).
[785] SĂ©e (1928:187) notes that until around 1800, âinteresseâ was the common word for âcapitalâ in French; in English the preferred word was âstock.â It is curious to note that Adam Smith, for one, actually returns to the Augustinian usage, âself-love,â in his famous passage about the butcher and the baker **(Wealth of Nations** 1.2.2).
[786] Beier 1985:159â63; cf. Dobb 1946:234. Consorting with gypsies was also a capital crime. In the case of vagrancy, justices found it so difficult to find anyone willing to press charges against vagrants that they were eventually forced to reduce the penalty to public whipping.
[787] In Walker 1996:244.
[788] Helmholtz 1986, Brand 2002, Guth 2008.
[789] Helmholz 1986, Muldrew 1998:255, Schofield & Mayhew 2002, Guth 2008).
[790] Stout 1742:121.
[791] âThe horrors of the Fleet and Marshalsea were laid bare in 1729. The poor debtors were found crowded together on the âcommon side,ââcovered with filth and vermin, and suffered to die, without pity, of hunger and jail fever ⊠No attempt was made to distinguish the fraudulent from the unfortunate debtor. The rich rogueâable, but unwilling to pay his debtsâmight riot in luxury and debauchery, while his poor unlucky fellow-prisoner was left to starve and rot on the âcommon sideâ â (Hallam 1866 V:269â70.)
[792] I do not want to argue that the more familiar narrative of âprimitive accumulation,â of the enclosure of common lands and rise of private property, the dislocation of thousands of one-time cottagers who became landless laborers, is false. I simply highlight a less familiar side of the story. Itâs especially helpful to highlight it because the degree to which the Tudor and Stuart periods were actually marked by a rise of enclosures is a heated matter of debate (e.g., Wordie 1983). The use of debt to split communities against themselves is meant in the same vein as Silvia Federiciâs (2004) brilliant argument about the role of witchcraft accusations in reversing popular gains of the late Middle Ages and opening the way to capitalism.
[793] âPersonal credit received a bad press in the eighteenth century. It was frequently said that it was wrong to go into debt simply to pay for everyday consumption goods. A cash economy was celebrated and the virtues of prudent housekeeping and parsimony extolled. Consequently retail credit, pawnbroking, and moneylending were all attacked, with both borrowers and lenders the targetsâ (Hoppit 1990:312â13.)
[794] **Wealth of Nations** 1.2.2.
[795] Muldrew makes this point: 1993:163.
[796] **Theory of Moral Sentiments** 4.1.10.
[797] âThe man who borrows in order to spend will soon be ruined, and he who lends to him will generally have occasion to repent of his folly. To borrow or to lend for such a purpose, therefore, is in all cases, where gross usury is out of the question, contrary to the interest of both parties; and though it no doubt happens sometimes that people do both the one and the other; yet, from the regard that all men have for their own interest, we may be assured that it cannot happen so very frequently as we are sometimes apt to imagineâ **(Wealth of Nations** 2.4.2). He does occasionally acknowledge the existence of retail credit, but he grants it no significance.
[798] Reeves 1999. Reeves, like Servet (1994, 2001) shows that many were aware of the variability of money-stuffs: Puffendorf, for example, made a long list of them.
[799] When we attribute value to gold, then, we simply recognize this. The same argument was usually invoked to solve the old Medieval puzzle about diamonds and water: Why is it that diamonds are so expensive, though useless, and water, which is useful in all sorts of ways, hardly worth anything at all? The usual solution was: diamonds are the eternal form of water. (Galileo, who objected to the entire premise, at one point suggested that those who make such claims should really be turned into statues. That way, he suggested, in inimitable Renaissance style, everyone would be happy, since (1) they would be eternal, and (2) the rest of us would no longer have to listen to their stupid arguments.) See Wennerlind 2003, who notes, interestingly, that most European governments employed alchemists in the seventeenth century in order to manufacture gold and silver for coins; itâs only when these schemes definitively failed that the governments moved to paper currency.
[800] Kindleberger 1984; Boyer-Xambeu, Deleplace, & Gillard 1994; Ingham 2004:171. Rather, this path eventually led to the creation of stock markets: the first public bourses, in fifteenth-century Bruges and Antwerp, began not by trading shares in joint-stock ventures, which barely existed at the time, but by âdiscountingâ bills of exchange.
[801] Usher (1934, 1944) originally introduced the distinction between âprimitive banking,â where one simply lends out what one has, and âmodern banking,â based on some sort of fractional reserve systemâthat is, one lends more than one has, thus effectively creating money. This would be another reason why we have now moved to something other than âmodern bankingââsee below.
[802] Spufford 1988:258, drawing on Usher 1943:239â42. While deposit notes were used, private bank notes, based on credit, only appear quite lateâfrom London goldsmiths, who also acted as bankers, in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.
[803] See Munro 2003b for a useful summary.
[804] MacDonald 2006:156.
[805] Tomas de Mercado in Flynn 1978:400.
[806] See Flynn 1979; Braudel 1992:522â23; Stein & Stein 2000: 501â05, 960â62; Tortella & ComĂn 2002. The number of **juros** in circulation went from 3.6 million ducats in 1516 to 80.4 million in 1598.
[807] The most famous exponent of this position was Nicholas Barbon (1690), who argued that âmoney is a value made by lawâ and a measure in just the same manner as inches or hours or fluid ounces. He also emphasized that most money was credit anyway.
[808] Locke (1691:144) also cited in Caffentzis 1989:46â47, which remains the most insightful summary of the debate and its implications. Compare Perlman & McCann 1998:117â20; Letwin 2003:71â78; Valenze 2006:40â43.
[809] We tend to forget that the materialism of the Marxist tradition is not some radical departureâMarx was, like Nietzsche, taking bourgeois assumptions (though in his case, different ones) and pushing them in directions that would outrage their original proponents. Anyway, there is good reason to believe that what we now call âhistorical materialismâ is really Engelsâ addition to the projectâEngels being himself nothing if not bourgeois in background and sensibilities (he was a stalwart of the Cologne stock exchange).
[810] Macaulay 1886:485âthe original essay was published in the Spectator, March 1, 1711.
[811] **Faust** II, Act 1âsee Shell 1992, Binswanger 1994 for a detailed analysis. The connection with alchemy is revealing. When in 1300 Marco Polo had remarked that the Chinese emperor âseemed to have mastered the art of alchemyâ in his ability to turn mere paper into something as good as gold, this was clearly meant as a joke; by the seventeenth century most European monarchs actually did employ alchemists to try to produce gold from base metals; it was only their failure that led to the adoption of paper money (Wennerlend 2003).
[812] Itâs not as if suspicions about money didnât existâbut they tended to focus, instead, on moral and metaphysical issues (e.g., âthe theft of timeâ).
[813] Said to have been given at a talk at the University of Texas in 1927, but in fact, while the passage is endlessly cited in recent books and especially on the internet, it cannot be attested to before roughly 1975. The first two lines appear to actually derive from a British investment advisor named L.L.B. Angas in 1937: âThe modern Banking system manufactures money out of nothing. The process is perhaps the most astounding piece of sleight of hand that was ever invented. Banks can in fact inflate, mint and unmint the modern ledger-entry currencyâ (Angas 1937:20â21). The other parts of the quote are probably later inventionsâand Lord Stamp never suggested anything like this in his published writings. A similar line, âthe bank hath benefit of all interest which it creates out of nothingâ attributed to William Patterson, the first director of the Bank of England, is likewise first attested to only in the 1930s, and is also almost certainly apocryphal.
[814] Joint-stock corporations were created in the beginning of the colonial period, with the famous East India Company and related colonial enterprises, but they largely vanished during the period of the industrial revolution and were mainly revived only at the end of the nineteenth century, and then principally, at first, in America and Germany. As Giovanni Arrighi (1994) has pointed out, the heyday of British capitalism was marked by small family firms and high finance; it was America and Germany, who spent the first half of the twentieth century battling over who would replace Great Britain as hegemon, that introduced modern bureaucratic corporate capitalism.
[815] MacKay 1854:52.
[816] MacKay 1854:53â54.
[817] Spyer 1997.
[818] Prakash 2003:209â16.
[819] Hardenburg & Casement 1913; the story has been analyzed most famously, and insightfully, by Mick Taussig (1984, 1987).
[820] Encyclopedia Britannica, 11th edition (1911): entry for âPutumayo.â
[821] As Taussig notes (1984:482), when the head of the company was later asked what he actually meant by âcannibalâ he said, simply, that it meant the Indians refused to trade with anybody else.
[822] This is a point demonstrated in great detail in an important book by Yann Moulier-Boutang (1997), which unfortunately has never been translated into English.
[823] Davies 1975:59. âIndenturedâ comes from the âindentationsâ or notches on a tally again, since these were widely used as contracts for those who, like most indentured servants, couldnât read (Blackstone 1827 I:218).
[824] Immanuel Wallerstein (1974) provides the classic analysis of this âsecond serfdom.
[825] This was true, incidentally, across the class spectrum: everyone was expected to do this, from lowly milkmaids and apprentices to âladies in waitingâ and knightâs pages. This was one reason, incidentally, why indentured-service contracts did not seem like much of a jump in the seventeenth century: they were simply lengthening the term of contracted employment from one to five or seven years. Even in Medieval times there were also adult day-laborers, but these were often considered indistinguishable from simple criminals.
[826] The very word âproletariatâ in a way alludes to this, as itâs taken from a Roman term for âthose who have children.â
[827] C.L.R. James 1938; Eric Williams 1944.
[828] âMany devices were available by which businessmen economized in the use of cash in wage paymentsâpayment could be made only at long intervals; payment might consist in giving claims on others (truck payment, tickets or vouchers to authorize purchasing from shops, etc., the provision of private notes and tokens)ââMathias 1979a:95.
[829] Actually the full list is: âcabbage, chips, waxers, sweepings, sockings, wastages, blessing, lays, dead men, onces, primage, furthing, dunnage, portage, wines, vails, tinge, buggings, colting, rumps, birrs, fents, thrums, potching, scrapings, poake, coltage, extra, tret, tare, largess, the con, nobbings, knockdown, boot, tommy, trimmings, poll, gleanings, lops, tops, bontages, keepy back, pin moneyâ (Linebaugh 1993:449; see also Linebaugh 1982, Rule 1986:115â17).
[830] Tebbutt 1983:49. On pawnbroking in general: Hardaker 1892, Hudson 1982, Caskey 1994, Fitzpatrick 2001.
[831] Linebaugh 1993: 371â404.
[832] Usually in order to conclude that today, of course, we are living in an entirely different world, because clearly thatâs not true any more. It might help here to remind the reader that Marx saw himself as writing a âcritique of political economyââthat is, of theory and practice of economics of his day.
[833] See the Lockhart translation of Bernal DĂaz (DĂaz 1844 II:396), which gives several versions of the story, drawn from different sources.
[834] Clenninden 1991:144.
[835] It is on these grounds that Testart distinguishes slavery owing to gambling, where the gambler stakes his own person, and debt slavery, even if these are ultimately gambling debts. âThe mentality of the gambler who directly stakes his person in the game is closer to that of the warrior, who risks losing his life in war or being taken into slavery, than to that of the poor person willing to sell himself to surviveâ (Testart 2002:180).
[836] This is incidentally why complaints about the immorality of deficits are so profoundly disingenuous: since modern money effectively **is** government debt, if there was no deficit, the results would be disastrous. True, money can also be generated privately, by banks, but there would appear to be limits to this. This is why U.S. financial elites, led by Alan Greenspan, panicked in the late 1990s when the Clinton administration began to run budget surpluses; the Bush tax cuts appear to have been designed specifically to ensure that the deficit was maintained.
[837] Wallerstein 1989.
[838] 1988:600.
[839] Britain passed its first bankruptcy law in 1542.
[840] This is no doubt what Goethe was getting at when he had Faust, specifically, tell the emperor to pay his debts with IOUs. After all, we all know what happened to him when his time came due.
[841] Sonenscher (2007) gives a long and detailed history of these debates.
[842] One might trace a religious element here: in the time of Augustus, a group of religious cultists in the Middle East conceived the idea that fire was about to come from the sky and consume the planet. Nothing seemed less likely at the time. Leave them in charge of a corner of the world for two thousand years, they figure out a way to do it. But still, this is clearly part of a larger pattern.
[843] I was first put on to the significance of the date by fellow anthropologist Chris Gregory (1998: 265â96; also Hudson 2003a). U.S. citizens had not been able to cash in dollars for gold since 1934. The analysis that follows is inspired by both Gregory and Hudson.
[844] One plausible-sounding version, which cites rather small amounts of bullion, can be found at: [[http://www.rediff.com/money/2001/nov/17wtc.htm][www.rediff.com/money/2001/nov/17wtc.htm]]. For a more entertaining, fictional version: [[http://www.rense.com/general73/confess.htm][www.rense.com/general73/confess.htm]].
[845] âThe Federal Reserve Bank of New York: the Key to the Gold Vaultâ ([[http://www.newyorkfed.org/education/addpub/goldvaul.pdf][newyorkfed.org/education/addpub/goldvaul.pdf]]).
[846] As a minor aside, I remember from the time also reading news reports noting that there were, in fact, a number of expensive jewelry shops in the arcades directly beneath the Towers, and that all the gold in them did in fact disappear. Presumably they were pocketed by rescue workers, but considering the circumstances, it would seem there were no serious objectionsâat least, Iâve never heard anything about the matter being further investigated, let alone prosecuted.
[847] Itâs no coincidence, certainly, that William Greider decided to name his great history of the Federal Reserve (1989) **The Secrets of the Temple**. This is actually how many of its own officials privately describe it. He quotes one: âThe System is just like the Church ⊠Itâs got a pope, the chairman; and a college of cardinals, the governors and bank presidents; and a curia, the senior staff. The equivalent of the laity is the commercial banks ⊠We even have different orders of religious thought like Jesuits and Franciscans and Dominicans only we call them pragmatists and monetarists and neo-Keynesiansâ (ibid:54).
[848] This is hardly a new claim, and it rests in part on the Braudelian (world-systems) school, for instance, the recent work of Mielants (2007). For a more classically Marxist version developing the connection since Nixonâs time, see Custers 2007. For a more mainstream neoclassical treatments of the connection, see MacDonald & Gastman 2001, MacDonald 2006.
[849] Senator Fullbright, in McDermott 2008:190.
[850] I note that this flies directly in the face of the intent of the United States Constitution (1.8.5), which specifies that only Congress was relegated the power âto coin money, [and] regulate the value thereofââno doubt at the behest of the Jeffersonians, who were opposed to creating a central bank. The United States still observes the letter of the law: United States coins are issued directly by the Treasury. United States paper money, while signed by the head of the Treasury, is not issued by the Treasury but by the Federal Reserve. They are technically banknotes, though as with the Bank of England, one bank is granted a monopoly in issuing them.
[851] For those who donât know how the Fed works: technically, there are a series of stages. Generally the Treasury puts out bonds to the public, and the Fed buys them back. The Fed then loans the money thus created to other banks at a special low rate of interest (âthe prime rateâ), so that those banks can then lend at higher ones. In its capacity as regulator of the banking system, the Fed also establishes the fractional reserve rate: just how many dollars these banks can âlendââeffectively, createâfor every dollar they borrow from the Fed, or have on deposit, or can otherwise count as assets. Technically this is 10 to 1, but a variety of legal loopholes allow banks to go considerably higher.
[852] Which does raise the rather interesting question of what its gold reserves are actually for.
[853] Indeed, perhaps the greatest compromise to United States global power in recent years is the fact that there is now one placeâthe region of China facing Taiwanâwhere air defenses are now so dense and sophisticated that the United States Air Force is no longer certain that it can penetrate at will. The inability to blow up Osama bin Laden is, of course, the most dramatic limit to this power.
[854] Or, to put the money in the United States stock market, which ultimately has a similar effect. As Hudson notes, âAmerican diplomats have made it clear that to buy control of U.S. companies or even to return to gold would be viewed as an unfriendly actâ (2002a:7), so, unless they want to move out of dollars entirely, which would be considered an even more unfriendly act, there is little alternative. As to how âunfriendlyâ acts might be received: see below.
[855] Hudson 2002a:12.
[856] As many have remarked, the three countries that switched to the euro around this timeâIraq, Iran, and North Koreaâwere precisely those singled out by Bush as his âAxis of Evil.â Of course we can argue about cause and effect here. Itâs also significant that the core euro-using states such as France and Germany uniformly opposed the war, while U.S. allies were drawn from euro-skeptics like the UK.
[857] For a few representative takes on the relation of the dollar and empire: from a neoclassical economic perspective, Ferguson (2001, 2004), from a radical Keynesian perspective, Hudson (2003a), from a Marxist one, Brenner (2002).
[858] Even the CIA now ordinarily refers to such arrangements as âslavery,â though technically debt peonage is different.
[859] Compare this to the deficit/military chart above, on page 366âthe curve is effectively identical.
[860] See [[http://www.dailybail.com/home/china-warns-us-about-debt-monetization.html][dailybail.com/home/china-warns-us-about-debt-monetization.html]], accessed December 22, 2009. The story is based on a piece from the **Wall Street Journal**, âDonât Monetize the Debt: The president of the Dallas Fed on inflation risk and central bank independenceâ (Mary Anastasia OâGrady, **WSJ**, May 23, 2009.) I should add that in popular usage nowadays, âto monetize the debtâ is generally used as a synonym for âprinting moneyâ to pay debt. This usage has become almost universal, but itâs not the original sense of the term, which is to turn the debt itself into money. The Bank of England did not print money to pay the national debt; it turned the national debt itself into money. Here too there is a profound argument going on about the nature of money itself.
[861] The arrangement is sometimes referred to as Bretton Woods II (Dooley, Folkerts-Landau & Garber 2004, 2009): effectively, an agreement since the 1990s at least to use various unofficial means to keep the dollarâs value artificially high, and East Asian currenciesâparticularly the Chineseâartificially low, in order to expedite cheap Asian exports to the United States. Since real wages in the United States have either stagnated or retreated continually since the 1970s, this, and the accumulation of consumer debt, is the only reason living standards in the United States have not precipitously declined.
[862] On Zheng He, see Dreyer 2006, Wade 2004, Wake 1997. On the tribute trade in general: Moses 1967, YĂŒ 1967, Hamashita 1994, 2003; Di Cosmo & Wyatt 2005.
[863] The argument here follows Arrighi, Hui, Hung and Selden 2003, some elements of which were echoed in Arrighiâs last work, **Adam Smith in Beijing** (2007).
[864] Japan of course was something of an exception, since it had arguably achieved something like First World status even before this.
[865] Keynes 1936:345.
[866] See [[http://www.irle.berkeley.edu/events/spring08/feller/][www.irle.berkeley.edu/events/spring08/feller/]]
[867] The key legislation was the âDepository Institutions Deregulation and Monetary Control Actâ of 1980, which struck down all federal usury laws: ostensibly, in reaction to the rampant inflation of the late 1970s, though of course they were never restored when inflation was brought back under control, as it has in the last quarter-century. It left state interest ceilings in place, but institutions like credit-card companies were allowed to observe the laws of the state in which they are registered, no matter where they operated. This is why most are registered in South Dakota, which has no maximum interest rate.
[868] The first is from Thomas Friedman (1999) in a cocky and vacuous book called **The Lexus and the OIive Tree**, the second from Randy Martin (2002) in a book of the same name.
[869] In America this âuniversal othernessâ is accomplished above all through racism. This is why most small retailing in the United States is conducted on ethnic lines: say, Korean grocers or dry-cleaners, who pool credit with one another, whose clients, however, are sufficiently socially distant that there is no question of extending credit outside, or even expecting basic relations of trustâsince they themselves ordinarily expect electricians, locksmiths, contractors of various sorts who provide services to at least attempt to shaft them. Essentially the market across racial or ethnic lines becomes one where everyone is assumed to be Amalek.
[870] Gilder 1981:266, cited in Cooper 2008:7. Cooperâs essay is a brilliant exploration of the relation between debt imperialismâa phrase she seems to have coined, inspired by Hudsonâand evangelical Christianity, and it is heartily recommended. See also Naylor 1985.
[871] Robertson 1992:153. In Cooper again: op cit.
[872] Atwood 2008:42.
[873] This is, incidentally, also the best response to conventional critiques of the poor as falling into debt because they are unable to delay gratificationâanother way in which economic logic, with all its human blind spots, skews any possible understanding of âconsumersâ â actual motivations. Rationally, since CDs yield around 4 percent annually, and credit cards charge 20 percent, consumers should save as a cushion and only go into debt when they absolutely have to, postponing unnecessary purchases until thereâs a surplus. Very few act this way, but this is rarely because of improvidence (canât wait to get that flashy new dress) but because human relations canât actually be put off in the same way as imaginary âconsumer purchasesâ: oneâs daughter will only be five once, and oneâs grandfather has only so many years left.
[874] There are so many books on the subject that one hesitates to cite, but a couple of outstanding examples are Anya Kamentzâs **Generation Debt** (2006), and Brett Williamâs **Social History of the Credit Trap** (2004). The larger point about demands for debt as a form of class struggle is in large part inspired by the Midnight Notes collective, who argue that, however paradoxically, âneoliberalism has thrown open a new dimension of struggle between capital and the working class within the domain of creditâ (2009:7). I have followed this analysis to a degree, but tried to move away from the economistic framing of human life as âreproduction of laborâ that hobbles so much Marxist literatureâthe emphasis on life beyond survival might be distantly Vaneigem-influenced (1967), but largely falls back on my own work on value theory (Graeber 2001).
[875] Elyachar 2002:510.
[876] See for instance, âIndiaâs micro-finance suicide epidemic,â Soutik Biswas, BBC News South Asia, 16 December 2010, [[http://www.http.bbc.co.uk/news/world-south-asia-11997571][http.bbc.co.uk/news/world-south-asia-11997571]]
[877] I have observed this first hand on any number of occasions in my work as an activist: police are happy to effectively shut down trade summits, for example, just to ensure that thereâs no possible chance that protestors can feel they have succeeded in doing so themselves.
[878] In practice, it mainly consists of âinterest-freeâ banking arrangements that pay lip service to the notion of profit-sharing but in reality operate in much the same way as any other bank. The problem is that if profit-sharing banks are competing with more conventional ones in the same marketplace, those who anticipate that their enterprises will yield high profits will gravitate toward the ones offering fixed-interest loans, and only those who anticipate lower profits will turn to the profit-sharing option (Kuran 1995:162). For a transition to no-interest banking to work, it would have to be total.
[879] Under the Caliphate, to guarantee the money supply; in China, through systematic intervention to stabilize markets and prevent capitalistic monopolies; later, in the United States and other North Atlantic republics, through allowing the monetization of its own debt.
[880] True, as I showed in chapter 5, economic life will always be a matter of clashing principles, and thus might be said to be incoherent to a certain extent. Actually I donât think this is in any way a bad thingâat the very least, itâs endlessly productive. The distortions born of violence strike me as uniquely insidious.
[881] von Mises 1949:540â41. The original German text was published in 1940 and presumably composed a year or two previous.
[882] Ferguson 2007:iv.
[883] I can speak with some authority here since I was myself born of humble origins and have advanced myself in life almost exclusively through my own incessant labors. I am well known by my friends to be a workaholicâto their often justifiable annoyance. I am therefore keenly aware that such behavior is at best slightly pathological, and certainly in no sense makes one a better person.
<biblio>
Abraham, Roy Clive. 1933. **The Tiv People**. Lagos: Government Printer.
Abu Lughod, Janet. 1989. **Before European Hegemony** Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Adamek, Wendi L. 2005. âThe Impossibility of the Given: Representations of Merit and Emptiness in Medieval Chinese Buddhism.â **History of Religions** 45 (2): 135-180.
Adams, Robert McC,. C. Lamberg-Karlovsky, William L. Moran. 1974. âThe Mesopotamian Social Landscape: The View from the Frontier.â **Bulletin of the American Schools of Oriental Research. Supplementary Studies** No. 20, Reconstructing Complex Societies: An Archaeological Colloquium, pp. 1-20.
Adkins, Arthur W. H. 1972. **Moral Values and Political Behaviour in Ancient Greece: From Homer to the End of the Fifth Century**. New York: Norton.
Adolf, Helen. 1947. âNew Light on Oriental Sources for Wolframâs Parzival and Other Grail Romances.â PMLA 62 (2): 306-324.
_____. 1957. âChristendom and Islam in the Middle Ages: New Light on âGrail Stoneâ and âHidden Host.â â **Speculum** 32 (1): 103-115.
Afigbo, Adiele Eberechukwu. 1971. âThe Aro of southeastern Nigeria: a socio-historical analysis of legends of their origins.â **African Notes** 6: 31-46.
Aglietta, M. and Orlean, A. 1992. **La Violence de la monnaie**. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
_____. 1995. **SouverainetĂ©, lĂ©gitimitĂ© de la monnaie**. Paris: Association dâĂconomie FinanciĂšre (Cahiers finance, Ă©thique, confiance).
_____. 1998. **La Monnaie souveraine**. Paris: Odile Jacob.
Aglietta, M., et al. 1998. âIntroduction.â In: **La monnaie souveraine (M**. Aglietta & A. OrlĂ©an, eds.), pp. 9â31. Paris: Odile Jacob.
Aglietta, M., & OrlĂ©an, A. (Eds.). 1995. **SouverainetĂ©, lĂ©gitimitĂ© de la monnaie**. Paris: Association dâĂconomie FinanciĂšre (Cahiers finance, Ă©thique, confiance).
Agnew, Jean-Christophe. 1986. **Worlds Apart: The Market and the Theater in Anglo-American Thought**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ahern, Emily. 1973. **The Cult of the Dead in a Chinese Village**. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Akiga Sai, B. 1939. **Akigaâs story; the Tiv tribe as seen by one of its members. Translated and annotated by Rupert East**. London, New York, Published for the International African Institute by the Oxford University Press.
_____. 1954. âThe âDescentâ of the Tiv from Ibenda Hillâ (translated by Paul Bohannan.) **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 24 (4): 295-310.
Akin, David and Joel Robbins,. 1998. âAn Introduction to Melanesian Currencies: Agencies, Identity, and Social Reproductionâ. In **Money and Modernity: State and Local Currencies in Melanesia** (David Akin and Joel Robbins, editor), pp. 1-40. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Alexander, John B. 1938. âA Babylonian Year of Jubilee?â **Journal of Biblical Literature** 57: 55-79.
Allen, N. J. 1998. âThe category of substance: a Maussian theme revisited.â In Marcel Mauss: A Centenary Tribute (Wendy James, N. J. Allen, editors), pp. 175-191. London: Berghahn Books.
Altekar, Anant Sadashiv. 1977. **State and Government in Ancient India**. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
_____. 1983. **The Position of Women in Hindu Civilization**. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Althabe, GĂ©rard. 1968. âLa circulation monĂ©taire dans un village Betsimisaraka.â **Tany Gasy** 8: 35-46.
Ames, Roger. 1994. **The Art of Rulership: A Study of Ancient Chinese Political Thought**. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Anderson, Perry. 1974. **Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism**. London: Verso Press.
Angas, Lawrence Lee Bazley. 1937. **Slump Ahead in Bonds**. New York: Somerset Pub. Co
Arnaud, Daniel. 1973. âLa prostitution sacrĂ©e en MĂ©sopotamie, un mythe historique?â **Revue de lâhistoire des religions** 183: 111-115.
Arrighi, Giovanni. 1994. **The Long Twentieth Century: Money, Power, and the Origins of Our Times**. London: Verso.
_____. 2007. **Adam Smith in Beijing: Lineages of the Twenty-First Century**. London: Verso.
Arrighi, Giovanni, Po-Keung Hui, Ho-Fung Hung and Mark Selden,. 2003. âHistorical Capitalism, East and Westâ. In **The Resurgence of East Asia:** 500, 150, **and** 50 **year perspectives**. (Giovanni Arrighi, Takeshi Hamashita and Mark Selden, eds.) London: Routledge, pp. 259-333.
Asheri, David. 1969. âLeggi greche sul problema dei debiti.â **Studii classici e orientali** 18: 5-122.
Ashtor, Eliahu. 1972. âBanking instruments between the Muslim East and the Christian West.â **Journal of European Economic History 1**: 559-573.
_____. 1976. **A Social and Economic History of the Middle East**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Assante, Julia. 2003. âFrom Whores to Hierodules: The Historiographic Invention of Mesopotamian Female Sex Professionals.â In **Ancient Art and Its Historiography** (edited A.A. Donahue and Mark D. Fullerton), 13-47. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Atwood, Margaret. 2008. **Payback: Debt and the Shadow Side of Wealth**. London: Blooms-bury.
Auerbach, Erich. 1946 \[2003\]. **Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Aydan, Ertan. 2003. **The Peculiarities of Turkish Revolutionary Ideology in the** 1930**s: the ĂŒlĂŒku version of Kemalism**, 1933-1936. Ph.D. dissertation, Bilkent University, Ankara ([[http://www.thesis.bilkent.edu.tr/0002416.pdf][http://www.thesis.bilkent.edu.tr/0002416.pdf]]).
Aylmer, G. E. 1980. âThe Meaning of Property in Seventeenth-Century England.â **Past and Present** 86: 87-97.
Ayyar, P. V. Jagadisa. 1982. **South Indian Shrines: Ilustrated**. New Delhi: Apex.
Bahrani, Zainab. 2001. **Women of Babylon: Gender and Representation in Mesopotamia**. London: Routledge.
Baker, J. Wayne. 1974. âHeinrich Bullinger and the Idea of Usury.â **The Sixteenth Century Journal** 5 (1): 49-70.
Baker, Jennifer. 2005. **Securing the commonwealth: debt, speculation, and writing in the making of early America**. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Ballin, Theodore N. 1978. âA Commentary on [Demosthenes] 50.â Doctoral Dissertation: University of Washington, Seattle.
Balmuth, Miriam S. 1967. âThe Monetary Forerunners of Coinage in Phoenicia and Palestineâ, in Aryeh Kindler, ed., **International Numismatic Convention, Jerusalem**, 27-31 **December** 1963: **The Patterns of Monetary Development in Phoenicia and Palestine in Antiquity, Proceedings** (Shocken, Tel Aviv, pp. 25-32.
_____. 1971. âRemarks on the Appearance of the Earliest Coinsâ, in David G. Mitten, John Griffiths Pedley, and Jane Ayer Scott, eds., **Studies Presented to George M. A. Hanfmann** (Philipp von Zabern, Mainz), pp. 1-7.
_____. 1975. âThe Critical Moment: the Transition from Currency to Coinage in the Eastern Mediterranean.â **World Archeology** 6: 293-9.
_____. 2001. Hacksilber to Coinage: New Insights into the Monetary History of the Near East and Greece. **Numismatic Studies** No. 24. New York: American Numismatic Society,
Banaji, Jairus. 2001. **Agrarian change in late antiquity: gold, labour, and aristocratic dominance**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Barasch, Moshe. 1993. **Icon: studies in the history of an idea**. New York: NYU Press.
Barber, Malcolm. 1978. **The Trial of the Templars**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Barendse, Rene J. 2002. **The Arabian Seas: The Indian Ocean World of the Seventeenth Century**. Armonk: M. E. Sharpe.
Barnes, Robert Harrison and Ruth Barnes. 1989. âBarter and Money in an Indonesian Village Economy.â **Man (New Series)** 24 (3): 399-418
Barreau, Andre. 1961. âIndian and Ancient Chinese Buddhism: Institutions Analogous to the Jisa.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 3 (4): 443-451.
Barth, Frederick. 1969. âEconomic Spheres in Darfur.â Themes in Economic Anthropology, ASA Monographs no. 6, pp. 149-174. London: Tavistock.
Basham, Arthur Llewellyn. 1948. âHarsa of Kashmir and the Iconoclast Ascetics.â **Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London** 12 (3/4): 668-99.
Baskind, James. 2007. âMortification Practices in the Obaku School.â In **Essays on East Asian Religion and Culture, Festschrift in honour of Nishiwaki Tsuneki on the occasion of his** 65**th birthday** (edited by Christian Wittern and Shi Lishan). Kyoto: Kyoto University.
Bataille, George. 1993. âThe Accursed Share Volume III, Sovereignty, Part One: âWhat I Understand by Sovereignty;â, pp. 197-257. In **The Accursed Share Volumes II & III**, New York: Zone Books.
Baxter, W. T. 1989. âEarly accounting: The tally and checkerboard.â **Accounting Historians Journal** 16 (2): 43-83
Beard, Mary and John Henderson. 1997. âWith This Body I Thee Worship: Sacred Prostitution in Antiquity.â **Gender & History** 9: 480-503.
Beattie, John. 1960. **Bunyoro: an African Kingdom**. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Beauchet, Ludovic. 1897. **Histoire du droit privé de la République athénienne**. Paris: Chevalier-Maresoq.
Beaujard, Philippe. 2005. âThe Indian Ocean in Eurasian and African World-Systems before the Sixteenth Century.â **Journal of World History** 16 (4): 411-465.
Begg, David, Stanley Fischer, and Rudiger Dornbusch. 2005. **Economics** (Eighth Edition). Maidenhead, Berkshire: McGraw-Hill
Beier, A. Lee. 1985. **Masterless men: the vagrancy problem in England** 1560-1640. London: Routledge.
Bell, Stephanie. 1999. âDo taxes and bonds finance government spending?â **Journal of Economic Issues** 34: 603-20.
_____. 2000. âThe role of the state and the hierarchy of money.â **Cambridge Journal of Economics** 25: 149-63.
Bell, Stephanie and John F. Henry. 2001. âHospitality versus Exchange: the Limits of Monetary Economics.â **Review of Social Economics** 54 (2): 203-226.
Bellah, Robert N. 2005. âWhat is Axial About the Axial Age?â **Archives of European Sociology** 46 (1): 69-87.
Belo, Jane. 1936. âA Study of the Balinese Family.â **American Anthropologist** 38 (1):12-31.
Benedetto, Luigi Foscolo. 1994. **The Travels of Marco Polo the Venetian** (Aldo Ricciâs translation). London: Routledge.
Benn, James A. 1998. âWhere Text Meets Flesh: Burning the Body as an Apocryphal Practice in Chinese Buddhism.â **History of Religions** 37 (4): 295-322.
_____. 2007. **Burning for the Buddha: Self-Immolation in Chinese Buddhism**. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Benveniste, Emile. 1963. **Indo-European Language and Society** (2 volumes). London: Faber & Faber.
_____. 1972. âDon et Ă©change dans le vocabulaire indo-europĂ©en.â In **ProblĂšmes de linguistique gĂ©nĂ©rale** (Paris: Galimard).
Berndt, Ronald M. 1951. âCeremonial Exchange in Western Arnhem Land.â **Southwestern Journal of Anthropology** 7 (2): 156-176.
Binswanger, Hans Christoph. 1994. **Money and Magic: A Critique of the Modern Economy in the Light of Goetheâs Faust**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Birks, Peter. 1985. âThe Roman Law Concept of Dominium and the Idea of Absolute Ownership.â **Acta Juridica** 7: 1-37.
Bishop, Ryan and Lilian S. Robinson. 1998. **Night Market: Sexual Cultures and the Thai Economic Miracle**. New York: Routledge.
Blackburn, Robin. 1997. **The Making of New World Slavery: From the Baroque to the Modern**, 1492-1800. London: Verso.
Blackstone, Sir William. 1827. **Commentaries on the laws of England**. London: E. Duyckinck.
Blanc, Louis. 1839. **Lâorganisation du travail**. Paris: Au Bureau de Nouveau Monde.
Blau, Peter. 1964. **Exchange and Power in Social Life**. New York: Wiley.
Blaxter, Lorraine. 1971. **âRendre service** and **Jalouisie.â** In **Gifts and Poison** (F. G. Bailey, editor). London: Basil Blackwell, pp. 119-130.
Bleiberg, Edward. 2002. âLoans, Credit and Interest in Ancient Egypt.â In **Debt and Economic Renewal in the Ancient Near East** (Hudson, Michael and Marc Van de Mieroop, editors), pp. 257-276. Bethesda: CDL Press.
Blickle, Peter. 1977. **The Revolution of 1**525: **The German Peasantâs War from a New Perspective**. (Thomas Brady and Erik Midelfort, translators.) Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
Bloch, Marc. 1961. **Feudal Society**. (2 volumes). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bogaert, Raymond. 1966. **Les Origines antiques de la banque de dépÎt**. Leiden: Sijthoff.
_____. 1968. **Banques et banquiers dans les cités grecques**. Leiden: Sijthoff
Bohannan, Laura. 1952. âA Genealogical Charter.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 22:301-15.
_____. 1958. âPolitical Aspects of Tiv Social Organization.â In **Tribes Without Rulers** (John Middleton and David Tait, editors), pp. 33-66. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
_____. 1964. **Return to Laughter, An Anthropological Novel**. (As âElenore Bowen Smithâ). New York: Praeger.
Bohannan, Paul. 1954. âThe Migration and Expansion of the Tiv.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 24 (1): 2-16.
_____. 1955. âSome Principles of Exchange and Investment among the Tiv.â **American Anthropologist** 57:60-67.
_____. 1957. **Justice and Judgment among the Tiv**. London: Oxford University Press.
_____. 1958. âExtra-processual events in Tiv Political Institutions.â **American Anthropologist** 60:1-12
_____. 1959. âThe Impact of Money on an African Subsistence Economy.â **Journal of Economic History** 19:491-503.
Bohannan, Paul and Laura Bohannan. 1953. **The Tiv of Central Nigeria**. London: International African Institute.
_____. 1968. **Tiv Economy**. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
_____. 1969. **A Source Notebook on Tiv Religion**. 5 volumes. New Haven: Human Relations Area Files.
Boianovsky, Mauro. 1993. âBöhm-Baewerk, Irving Fisher, and the Term âVeil of Money.â â **History of Political Economy** 25 (4):725-738
Bokenkamp, Stephen R. 2008. **âFu:** Talisman, Tally, Charm.â In **The Encyclopedia of Taoism** (Fabrizio Pregadio, editor), pp. 35-38. London: Routledge.
Bolles, John Augustus. 1837. **A treatise on usury and usury laws**. Boston: James Munroe.
Boon, James. 1975. **The anthropological romance of Bali**, 1597-1972: **dynamic perspectives in marriage and caste, politics, and religion**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
BottĂ©ro, Jean. 1961. âDesordre Ă©conomique et annulation des dettes en Mesopotamie Ă lâepoque paleo-babylonienne.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 4:113-164.
_____. 1992. **Everyday Life in Ancient Mesopotamia**. (Translated by Antonia Nevill.) Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1965. âThe Sentiment of Honor in Kabyle Society.â In J. G. Peristiany, editor, **Honour and Shame: the Values of Mediterranean Society**. London: Trinity Press, pp. 191-242.
_____. 1977. **Outline of a Theory of Practice**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1990. **The Logic of Practice** (Translated by Richard Nice.) Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bowers, Richard H. 1983. âFrom Rolls to Riches: Kingâs Clerks and Moneylending in Thirteenth-Century England.â **Speculum** 58 (1): 60-71.
Boyer-Xambeu, Marie-ThérÚse, Ghislain Deleplace, and Lucien Gillard. 1994. **Private Money & Public Currencies: the** 16**th Century Challenge**. (Azizeh Azodi, translator). Armonk: M. E. Sharpe.
Bradley, Keith R. 1987. âOn the Roman Slave Supply and Slavebreeding.â In **Classical Slavery** (M. I. Finley, editor), pp. 42-64. London: Routledge.
Brady, Thomas A., Jr. 1997. âThe Rise of Merchant Empires, 1400-1700. A European Counterpoint.â In **The political economy of merchant empires** (James D. Tracy, editor), pp. 117-160. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brand, Paul. 2002. âAspects of the Law of Debt, 1189-1307.â In **Credit and debt in medieval England, c.11**80-c.1350 (Schofield, Phillipp R. and N. J. Mayhew, editors), pp. 19-41. London: Oxbow.
_____. 2003. âThe Jewish Community of England in the Records of the English Royal Government.â In **The Jews in medieval Britain: historical, literary, and archaeological perspectives** (Patricia Skinner, editor), pp. 73-96. Woodbridge: Boyden and Brewer.
Braudel, Fernand. 1979. **Civilisation matérielle, économie et capitalisme, XVe-XVIIIe siÚcle, 3: Le temps du monde**. Paris: A. Colin.
_____. 1992. **Civilization and Capitalism, 15th-18th Century: The wheels of commerce**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
_____. 1995. **The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean world in the age of Philip II** (two volumes). Berkeley: University of California Press.
Brenner, Robert. 2002. **The Boom and the Bubble: The US in the World Economy**. London and New York: Verso.
Briant, Paul. 2006. **From Cyrus to Alexander: A History of the Persian Empire**. New York: Eisenbrauns.
Brock, Roger. 1994. âThe Labour of Women in Classical Athens.â **The Classical Quarterly** (new series) 44 (2): 336-346.
Bronkhorst, Johannes. 2007. **Greater Magadha: Studies in the Culture of Early India**. Leiden: Brill.
Brook, Timothy. 1998. **The Confusions of Pleasure: Commerce and Culture in Ming China**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Brunt, P. A. 1974. **Social Conflicts in the Roman Republic**. New York: Norton.
Bryant, Joseph M. 1996. **Moral Codes and Social Structure in Ancient Greece: A Sociology of Greek Ethics from Homer to the Epicureans and Stoics**. Albany: SUNY.
BĂŒcher, Karl. 1907. **Industrial Evolution**. (S. Morley Wickett, trans.) New York: Holt.
Buckland, William Warwick. 1908. **The Roman Law of Slavery**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Buckler, W. H. 1896. **The Origin and History of Contract in Roman Law down to the End of the Republican Period**. London: C. J. Clay & Sons.
Bulliet, Richard W. 1979. **Conversion to Islam in the Medieval Period: An Essay in Quantitative History**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Burton, Sir Richard F. 1934. **The Book of a Thousand Nights and a Night** (6 volumes). New York: Heritage Press.
Butrica, James L. 2006. âSome Myths and Anomalies in the Study of Roman Sexuality.â In **Same-Sex Desire and Love in Greco-Roman Antiquity and in the Classical Tradition of the West** (Beert C. Verstraete and Vernon Provencal, editors), pp. 209-270. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Byrne, Frances. 1971. âTribes and Tribalism in early Ireland.â **Ăriu** 22: 128-166.
_____. 1973. **Irish Kings and High Kings**. London: Batsford.
Caffentzis, Constantine George. 1989. **Clipped Coins, Abused Words, and Civil Government: John Lockeâs Philosophy of Money**. New York: Autonomedia.
Cairns, Francis. 1991. âThe âLaws of Eretriaâ (âIGâ XII. 9 1273 and 1274): Epigraphic, Legal, Historical, and Political Aspects.â **Phoenix** 45 (4): 296-313
Calhoun, George W. 1934. âClasses and Masters in Homer.â **Classical Philology** 29:192-206, 301-316.
Cambiano, Guiseppe. 1987. âAristotle and the Anonymous Opponents of Slavery.â In **Classical Slavery** (M. I. Finley, editor), pp. 28-53. London: Frank Cass.
Campbell, John Kennedy. 1964. **Honour, family and Patronage: A Study of Institutions and Moral Values in a Greek Mountain Community**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cannan, Edwin. 1921. âEarly History of the Term Capital.â **Quarterly Journal of Economics** 35 (3): 469-81.
Cardascia, Guillaume. 1959. âLâadoption matrimonlale Ă Babylone et Ă Nuzi.â **Revue historique de droit français et Ă©tranger** 37: 1-16.
_____. 1969. **Les lois assyriennes**. Littératures Anciennes du Proche-Orient 2. Paris: Cerf.
Cartier, Michel. 1988. âDette et propriĂ©tĂ© en Chine.â In **Lien de Vie: Noued Mortel: les representations de la dette en Chine, au Japan, et dans le monde Indien** (Charles Malamoud, editor), pp. 17-29. Paris: Editions de lâEcole des Hautes Ătudes en Science Sociales.
Case, Karl E., Ray C. Fair, Manfred GĂ€rtner, and Ken Heather. 1996. **Economics**. London: Prentice Hall.
Caskey, John P. 1994. **Fringe Banking: Check-Cashing Outlets, Pawnshops, and the Poor**. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Cerny, Jaroslav. 1954. âPrices and wages in Egypt in the Ramesside period.â **Cahiers dâhistoire mondiale** 4: 903-921.
Chakravarti, Uma. 1985. âOf dasas and karmakaras: servile labor in ancient India.â In **Chains of Servitude: Bondage and Slavery in India** (Utsa Patnaik, Manjari Dingwaney, editors), pp. 35-75. Reno: University of Nevada Press.
Chapman, Anne. 1980. âBarter as a Universal Mode of Exchange.â **LâHomme** 22 (3): 33-83.
Charles-Edwards, T. M. 1978. âHonour and Status in Some Irish and Welsh Prose Tales.â **Eriu** 29: 123-141.
_____. 1993. **Early Irish and Welsh kinship**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chatterjee, Heramba. 1971. **The Law of Debt in Ancient India**. Calcutta: Sanskrit College.
Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad. 1994. **Carvaka/Lokayata: An Anthology of Source Materials and Some Recent Studies**. New Delhi: Mrinal Kanti Gangopadhyaya.
Chaudhuri, Kirti N. 1985. **Trade and Civilisation in the Indian Ocean: An Economic History from the Rise of Islam to** 1750. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1990. **Asia Before Europe: Economy and Civilization of the Indian Ocean from the Rise of Islam to** 1750. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chauhan, Gian Ghand. 2003. **An Economic history of early medieval northern India**. New Delhi: Atlantic Publishers.
Châen, Kenneth K.S. 1964. **Buddhism in China: A Historical Survey**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Choksy, Jamsheed K. 1988. âLoan and sales contracts in ancient and early medieval Iran.â **Indo-Iranian Journal** 31(3: 191-218.
Cipolla, Carlo M. 1967. **Money, Prices and Civilisation in the Mediterranean World: Fifth to Seventeenth Centuries**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Clanchy, M. T. 1993. **From memory to written record, England** 1066-1307. Oxford: Blackwell.
Clarence-Smith, William G. 2008. âIslamic Abolitionism in the Western Indian Ocean from c. 1800.â Presented at the conference, **Slavery and the Slave Trades in the Indian Ocean and Arab Worlds: Global Connections and Disconnections**, Yale University, November 7-8, 2008. [[http://www.yale.edu/glc/indian?ocean/clarence?smith.pdf][http://www.yale.edu/glc/indian?ocean/clarence?smith.pdf]].
Clavero, BartolomĂ©. 1986. âThe jurisprudence on usury as a social paradigm in the history of Europe.â In **Historische Soziologie der Rechtswissenschaft** (Erik Volkmar Heyen, editor), pp. 23-36. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.
Codere, Helen. 1950. **Fighting with Property: A Study of Kwakiutl Potlatching and Warfare** 1792-1930. Monograph 18. New York: American Ethnological Society.
Cohen, David. 1987. âSeclusion, separation and the status of women in classical Athens.â **Greece and Rome** 36.(1): 1-15
Cohen, Edward E. 1995. Review of âLending and Borrowing in Ancient Athensâ, Bryn Mawr Classical Review 3 (4):
([[http://hegel.lib.ncsu.edu/stacks/serials/bmcr/bmcr-v3n04-cohen-lending][http://hegel.lib.ncsu.edu/stacks/serials/bmcr/bmcr-v3n04-cohen-lending]])
Cohn, Norman. 1972. **The pursuit of the millennium: revolutionary millenarians and mystical anarchists of the Middle Ages**. New York: Oxford University Press.
Cole, Alan. 1998. **Mothers and Sons in Chinese Buddhism**. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.
Coleman, Janet. 1985. âDominium in 13th and 14th Century Political Thought and its 17th Century Heirs: John of Paris and Locke.â **Political Studies** 33: 73-100.
_____. 1988. âProperty and Poverty.â In **The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c**1350-1450 (J. H. Barnes, editor), pp. 607-648. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Collins, Randall. 1986. **Weberian Social Theory**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1989. **The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Cook, Robert Manuel. 1958. âSpeculations on the Origins of Coinage.â **Historia** 7: 257-267.
Cooper, Frederick. 1979. âThe Problem of Slavery in African studies.â **Journal of African History** 20:103-125.
Cooper, Jerrold S. 1986. **Sumerian and Akkadian Royal Inscriptions, Volume** 1: **Presargonic Inscriptions**. New Haven: American Oriental Society.
_____. 2002. âVirginity in Ancient Mesopotamia.â **Compte rendu, Rencontre Assyriologique Internationale** 47: 91-112.
Cooper, Melinda. 2006. âThe Unborn Born Again: Neo-Imperialism, the Evangelical Right and the Culture of Life.â **Postmodern Culture** (PMC) 17.1: #3.
_____. 2008. **Life as surplus: biotechnology and capitalism in the neoliberal era**. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Cornell, Tim. 1995. **The beginnings of Rome: Italy and Rome from the Bronze Age to the Punic Wars (c**. 1000-264 **BC)**. London: Routledge.
Cortés, Hernan. 1868. **The fifth letter of Hernan Cortes to the Emperor Charles V: containing an account of his expedition to Honduras**. London: Hakluyt Society.
Cotter, James Finn. 1969. âThe Wife of Bath and the Conjugal Debt.â **English Language Notes** 6: 169-72
Covarrubias, Miguel. 1937. **Island of Bali**. London: Kegan Paul.
Curtin, Phillip D. 1969. **The Atlantic Slave Trade: A Census**. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Curtin, Phillip D., and Jan Vansina,. 1964. âSources of the Nineteenth Century Atlantic Slave Trade.â **Journal of African History** 5 (2): 185-208.
Custers, Peter. 2006. **Questioning Globalized Militarism: Nuclear and Military Production and Critical Economic Theory**. Monmouth: Merlin Press.
Dandamaev, Muhammed. 1984. **Slavery in Babylonia, from Nabopolasser to Alexander the Great** (626-331 **BC)**. De Kalb: Northern Illinois University Press.
Darnton, Robert. 1984. **The Great Cat Massacre**. New York: Vintage Books.
Davenant, Charles. 1771. âDiscourses on the Public Revenues and on Trade. Discourse II: Concerning Credit, and the Means and Methods by which it may be restored.â In **The political and commercial works of that celebrated writer Charles DâAvenant: relating to the trade and revenue of England, the Plantation trade, the East-India trade and African trade** (Sir Charles Whitworth, editor), pp. 150-206. London: R. Horsefeld.
Davidson, Paul. 2006. âKeynes and Money.â In **A Handbook of Alternative Monetary Economics** (Philip Arestis and Malcolm Sawyer, editors), pp. 139-153. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Davies, Glynn. 1996. **A History of Money**. Cardiff: University of Wales Press.
Davies, Kenneth Gordon. 1975. **The North Atlantic world in the seventeenth century**. St. Paul: University of Minnesota Press.
Davis, John. 1904. **Corporations**. New York: Capricorn.
DelĂąge, Denys. 1993. **Bitter Feast: Amerindians and Europeans in Northeastern North America**, 1600-64. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.
Deleuze, Giles and Felix Guattari. 1972. **Anti-Oedipe**. Translated into English as **Anti-Ćdipus**. (Robert Hurley, Mark Seem and Helen R. Lane, translators.) New York: Continuum, 2004
Deng, Gang. 1999. **The Premodern Chinese Economy: Structural Equilibrium and Capitalist Stagnation**. London: Routledge.
Denzel, Markus A. 2006. âThe European bill of exchange.â Paper presented at the XIV International Economic History Congress, Helsinki, Finland, 21 to 25 August 2006. [[http://www.helsinki.fi/iehc2006/papers1/Denzel2.pdf][http://www.helsinki.fi/iehc2006/papers1/Denzel2.pdf]]
Derrida, Jacques. 2000. **Of Hospitality: Anne Dufourmantelle Invites Jacques Derrida to Respond**. (Trans. Rachel Bowlby), Stanford: Stanford University Press.
_____. 2001. **Acts of Religion**. London: Routledge.
Descat, Raymond. 1995. âLâĂ©conomie antique et la citĂ© grecque: Un modĂšle en question.â Annales. Histoire, Sciences Sociales, 50e AnnĂ©e, No. 5: 961-989.
Dhavalikar, Madhukar Keshav. 1975. âThe Beginning of Coinage in India.â **World Archaeology** 6 (3):330-338.
Di Cosmo, Nicola & Don J. Wyatt, editors. 2005. **Political frontiers, ethnic boundaries, and human geographies in Chinese history**. London: Routledge Curzon.
Diakonoff, Igor. 1982. âThe Structure of Near Eastern Society before the Middle of the 2nd Millennium BC.â **Oikumene** 3: 7-100.
Diaz, Bernal. 1844. **The memoirs of the conquistador Bernal Diaz del Castillo, Written by Himself, Containing a True and Full Account of the Discovery and Conquest of Mexico and New Spain**. (John Ingram Lockhart, translator.) Boston: J. Hatchard and Son.
_____. 1963. **The Conquest of New Spain**. (J. M. Cohen, translator.) New York: Penguin Books.
Digby, Kenelm Edward, and William Montagu Harrison. 1897. **An Introduction to the History of the Law of Real Property with Original Authorities**. Fifth Edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Dighe, Ranjit, editor. 2002. **The historianâs Wizard of Oz: reading L. Frank Baumâs classic as a political and monetary allegory**. Westport: Greenwood Publishing Group.
Dike, K. Onwuka and Felicia Ekejiuba. 1990. **The Aro of south-eastern Nigeria**, 1650-1980: **a study of socio-economic formation and transformation in Nigeria**. Ibadan: University Press.
Dikshitar, V. R. Ramachandra. 1948. **War in Ancient India**. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Dillon, John M. 2004. **Morality and Custom in Ancient Greece**. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Dixon, C. Scott. 2002. **The Reformation and Rural Society: The Parishes of Brandenburg-Ansbach-Kulmbach**, 1528-1603. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dockés, Pierre. 1979. **Medieval Slavery and Liberation** (Arthur Goldhammer, translator). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Doherty, Charles. 1980. âExchange and Trade in Early Medieval Ireland.â **Journal of the Royal Society of Antiquaries of Ireland** 110: 67-89.
Donzelot, Jacques. 1994. **Lâinvention du social: essai sur le dĂ©clin des passions politiques**. Paris: Seuil
Dorward, David C. 1976. âPrecolonial Tiv Trade and Cloth Currency.â **International Journal of African Historical Studies** 9 (4):576-591.
Douglas, Mary. 1951. âA form of polyandry among the Lele of the Kasai.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 21 (1):1-12. (As Mary Tew.)
_____. 1958. âRaffia Cloth Distribution in the Lele Economy.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 28 (2): 109-122.
_____. 1960. âBlood-Debts and Clientship Among the Lele.â **Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland** 90 (1): 1-28.
_____. 1962. âThe Lele Compared with the Bushong: A Study in Economic Backwardness.â In **Markets in Africa** (Paul Bohannan and George Dalton, editors), pp. 211-223. Chicago: Northwestern University Press.
_____. 1963. **The Lele of the Kasai**. London: Oxford University Press.
_____. 1964. âMatriliny and Pawnship in Central Africa.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 34 (4): 301-313.
_____. 1966. **Purity and Danger: An Analysis of Concepts of Pollution and Taboo**. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
_____. 1982. **In the Active Voice**. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
_____. 1999. âSorcery Accusations Unleashed: the Lele Revisited, 1987.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 69 (2): 177-193.
Downes, Rupert Major. 1933. **The Tiv Tribe**. Kaduna: Government Printer.
_____. 1977. **Tiv Religion**. Ibadan: Ibadan University Press.
Dreyer, Edward L. _. 2006. **Zheng He: China and the Oceans in the Early Ming Dynasty**, 1405-1433. Library of World Biography (editor, Peter N. Stearns). New York: Pearson Longman, 2006.
Driver, Godfrey Rolles. and John C. Miles. 1935. **The Assyrian Laws**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Dubois, Page. 2003. **Slaves and Other Objects**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Duby, Georges. 1973. **Guerriers et paysans, VIIeâXIIe sĂšcle: Premier essor de lâĂ©conomie europĂ©enne**. Paris: Gallimard.
_____. 1980. **The Three Orders: Feudal Society Imagined** (translated by Arthur Goldhammer). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
_____. 1982. **Rural Economy and the Country Life in the Medieval West**. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Duffy, SeĂĄn, Ailbhe MacShamhrĂĄin, and James Moynes, editors. 2005. **Medieval Ireland: an encyclopedia**. Dublin: CRC Press.
Duggan, E. de C. 1932. âNotes on the Munshi Tribe.â **Journal of the African Society** 31: 173-82.
Dumont, Louis. 1966. **Homo Hierarchicus: Essai sur le systĂšme des castes**. Paris: Gallimard.
_____. 1981. **From Mandeville to Marx: the Genesis and Triumph of Economic Ideology**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
_____. 1992. **Essays on Individualism: Modern Ideology in Anthropological Perspective**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Duyvendak, Jan Julius Lodewijk. 1928. **The Book of Lord Shang**. London: Arthur Probsthain.
Dyer, Christopher. 1989. **Standards of living in the later Middle Ages: social change in England, c**. 1200-1520. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Einaudi, Luigi. 1936. âThe Theory of Imaginary Money from Charlemagne to the French Revolutionâ, in F. C. Lane and J. C. Riemersma (eds.), **Enterprise and Secular Change**, London: Allen & Unwin, 1956.
Einzig, Paul. 1949. **Primitive Money in its Ethnological, Historical, and Ethnographic Aspects**. New York: Pergamon Press.
Eisenstadt, Shmuel N. 1982. âThe Axial Age: The Emergence of Transcendental Visions and the Rise of Clerics.â **European Journal of Sociology** 23(2):294â314.
_____. 1984. âHeterodoxies and Dynamics of Civilizations.â **Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society** 128 (2): 104-113.
_____. 1986. **The Origins and Diversity of Axial Age Civilizations**. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Ekejiuba, Felicia Ifeoma. 1972. âThe Aro trade system in the nineteenth century.â **Ikenga 1** (1):11-26, 1 (2):10-21.
Elayi, Josette and A. G. Elayi. 1993. **Trésors de monnaies phéniciennes et circulation monétaire (Ve-IVe siÚcle avant J.-C.)**. Paris: Gabalda.
Ellis, Thomas Peter. 1926. **Welsh Tribal Law and Custom in the Middle Ages**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Eltis, David, Stephen D. Behrent, David Richardson, Herbert S. Klein. 2000. **The Transatlantic Slave Trade: A Database**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Elwahed, Ali Abd. 1931. **Contribution Ă une thĂ©orie sociologique de lâesclavage. Ătude des situations gĂ©nĂ©ratrices de lâesclavage. Avec appendice sur lâesclavage de la femme et bibliographie critique**. Paris: Ăditions Albert Mechelinck.
Elyachar, Julia. 2002. âEmpowerment Money: The World Bank, Non-Governmental Organizations, and the Value of Culture in Egypt.â **?Public Culture** 14 (3): 493-513
_____. 2005. **Markets of Dispossession: NGOs, Economic Development, and the State in Cairo**. Durham: Duke University Press.
Endres, Rudolf. 1979. âThe Peasant War in Franconia.â In **The German Peasant War of** 1525â**New Viewpoints** (Bob Scribner & Gerhard Benecke, editors), pp. 63-83. London: Allen & Unwin.
Engels, Donald W. 1978. **Alexander the Great and the Logistics of the Macedonian Army**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Equiano, Olaudah. 1789. **The Interesting Narrative of the Life of Olaudah Equiano: or, Gustavus Vassa, the African**. Modern Library Edition, New York, 2004.
Erdosy, George. 1988. **Urbanisation in Early Historic India**. Oxford: British Archaeological Reports.
_____. 1995. âCity states in North India and Pakistan at the time of the Buddha.â In **The archaeology of early historic South Asia: the emergence of cities and states** (Frank Allichin and George Erdosy, editors), pp. 99-122. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Essid, Yassine. 1988. âIslamic Economic Thought.â In **Preclassical Economic Thought: From the Greeks to the Scottish Enlightenment** (edited by Todd Lowry), pp. 77-102. Boston: Kluwer.
_____. 1995. **A critique of the origins of Islamic economic thought**. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. 1931. âAn Alternative Term for âBride-Priceâ.â **Man** 31: 36-39.
_____. 1940. **The Nuer: a Description of the Modes of Livelihood and Political Institutions of a Nilotic People**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
_____. 1948. **The Divine Kingship of the Shilluk of the Nilotic Sudan. The Frazer Lecture for** 1948. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1951. **Kinship and Marriage among the Nuer**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Falkenhausen, Lothar von. 2005. âThe E Jun Qi Metal Tallies: Inscribed Texts and Ritual Contexts.â In **Text and Ritual in Early China** (edited by Martin Kern), pp.79-123. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Falkenstein, Adam. 1954. âLa citĂ©-temple sumĂ©rienne.â **Cahiers dâhistoire mondiale** 1: 784-814.
Falola, Toyin and Paul E. Lovejoy, editors. 1994. **Pawnship in Africa: Debt Bondage in Historical Perspective**. Boulder: University of Colorado Press.
Fardon, Richard. 1985. âSisters, Wives, Wards and Daughters: A Transformational Analysis of the Political Organization of the Tiv and their Neighbors. Part I: The Tiv. **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 54 (4): 2-21.
_____. 1986. âSisters, Wives, Wards and Daughters: A Transformational Analysis of the Political Organization of the Tiv and their Neighbors. Part II: The Transformations.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 55 (1): 77-91.
Faure, Bernard. 1998. âThe Buddhist Icon and the Modern Gaze.â **Critical Inquiry** 24 (3): 768-813.
_____. 2000. **Visions of Power: Imagining Medieval Japanese Buddhism**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Fayazmanesh, Sasan. 2006. **Money and Exchange: Folktales and Reality**. New York: Routledge.
Federal Reserve Bank of New York. 2008. âThe Key to the Gold Vault.â [[http://www.newyorkfed.org/education/addpub/goldvaul.pdf][www.newyorkfed.org/education/addpub/goldvaul.pdf]].
Federici, Silvia. 2004. **Caliban and the Witch: Women, the Body and Primitive Accumulation**. New York: Autonomedia.
Feeley-Harnik, Gillian. 1982. âThe Kingâs Men in Madagascar: Slavery, Citizenship and Sakalava Monarchy.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 52 (2): 31-50.
Fenton, William N. 1978 âNorthern Iroquois Culture Patterns.â In **Handbook of the North American Indians, volume** 15, **Northeast** (W. Sturtevant and B. Trigger, editors), pp. 296-321. Washington D.C.: Smithsonian Institute Press.
Ferguson, Niall. 2001. **The Cash Nexus: Money and Power in the Modern World**, 1700-2000. London: Allen Lane.
_____. 2004. **Colossus: the price of Americaâs empire**. London: Penguin.
_____. 2007. **The Ascent of Money: A Financial History of the World**. London: Penguin.
Finkelstein, Jacob J. 1961. âAmmisaduqaâs Edict and the Babylonian âLaw Codes.â â **Journal of Cuneiform Studies** 15: 91-104.
_____. 1965. âSome New Misharum Material and Its Implications.â **Assyriological Studies** 16: 233-46.
_____. 1966. âSex Offenses in Sumerian Laws.â **Journal of the American Oriental Society** 86:355-372.
Finley, Moses I. 1954. **The World of Odysseus**. New York: Viking Press.
_____. 1960. **Slavery in classical antiquity: views and controversies**. Cambridge: W. Heffer & Sons.
_____. 1963. **The ancient Greeks: an introduction to their life and thought**. New York: Viking Press.
_____. 1964. âBetween Slavery and Freedomâ **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 6 (3): 233-249.
_____. 1974. **The Ancient Economy**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
_____. 1980. **Ancient Slavery and Modern Ideology**. London: Penguin
_____. 1981. **Economy and Society in Ancient Greece**. New York: Penguin.
_____. 1983. **Politics in the Ancient World**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1985. **Studies in land and credit in ancient Athens**, 500-200 **B.C.: the horos inscriptions**. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
Firth, Raymond. 1959. **Economics of the New Zealand Maori**. Wellington, New Zealand: R. E. Owen.
Fischel, Walter J. 1937. **Jews in the Economic and Political Life of Medieval Islam**. London: Royal Asiatic Society.
Fiser, Ivo. 2004. âThe Problem of the Setthi in Buddhist Jatakas.â In **Trade in Early India** (Ranabir Chakravarti, editor), pp. 166-198. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fisher, Douglas. 1989. âThe Price Revolution: A Monetary Interpretation.â **Journal of Economic History** 49 (1):884-902.
Fitzpatrick, Jim. 2001. **Three Brass Balls: the Story of the Irish Pawnshop**. Dublin: Collins Press.
Flandrin, Jean-Louis. 1979. **Families in Former Times**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fleet, John Faithful. 1888. **Inscriptions of the Early Gupta Kings and Their Successors, Corpus Inscriptionium Indicarum, vol. III**. Calcutta: Government Printer.
Flynn, Dennis. 1978. âA New Perspective on the Spanish Price Revolution: The Monetary Approach to the Balance of Payments.â **Explorations in Economic History** 15:388-406.
_____. 1979. âSpanish-American Silver and World Markets in the Sixteenth Century.â **Economic Forum** 10: 46-71.
_____. 1982. âThe Population Thesis View of Sixteenth-Century Inflation Versus Economics and History.â In **Munzpragung, Geldumlauf und Wechselkurse/Mintage, Monetary Circulation and Exchange Rates. Akten der C**7**-Section des** 8**th International Economic History Congress Budapest** 1982. (F. Irsigler and E. H.G. Van Cauwenberghe, editors.), pp. 361-382. Trier: THF-Verlag.
Flynn, Dennis and Arturo GirĂĄldez. 1995. âBorn with a âSilver Spoonâ: the Origin of World Trade in 1571.â **Journal of World History** VI (2): 201-11.
_____. 2002. âCycles of Silver: Global Economic Unity through the Mid-Eighteenth Century.â **Journal of World History**, vol.13, no 2, pp.391-427.
Forstater, Mathew. 2005. âTaxation and Primitive Accumulation: The Case of Colonial Africa,â **Research in Political Economy**, 22, 51-64.
_____. 2006. âTaxation: Additional Evidence from the History of Thought, Economic History, and Economic Policy,â in M. Setterfield (ed.), **Complexity, Endogenous Money, and Exogenous Interest Rates**, Chetlenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
Frankfort, Henri. 1948. **Kingship and the Gods: A Study of Ancient Near Eastern Religion as the Integration of Society and Nature**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Freuchen, Peter. 1961. **Book of the Eskimo**. Cleveland, Ohio: World Publishing Co.
Friedman, Thomas L. 1999. **The Lexus and the Olive Tree**. New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 2004. **Truth and Method** (Joel Weinsheimer; Donald G Marshall, translators). London: Continuum.
Gale, Esson McDowell. 1967. **Discourse on Salt and Iron: a debate on state control of commerce and industry in ancient China** (by Huan Kâuan). Taipei: Châeng-Wen.
Galey, Jean-Claude. 1983. âCreditors, Kings and Death: determinations and implications of bondage in Tehri-Gathwal (Indian Himalayas).â In **Debts and Debtors** (Charles Malamoud, editor), pp. 67-124. London: Vikas.
Gallant, Thomas W. 2000. âHonor, Masculinity, and Ritual Knife Fighting in Nineteenth-Century Greece.â **American Historical Review** 105 (2): 359-82.
Gardiner, Geoffrey. 2004. âThe Primacy of Trade Debts in the Development of Money.â In **Credit and State Theories of Money: The Contributions of A. Mitchell Innes** (L. Randall Wray, editor). Cheltingham, Edward Elgar.
Garnsey, Peter. 1996. **Ideas of Slavery from Aristotle to Augustine**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 2008. **Thinking about Property: From Antiquity to the Age of Revolution**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gates, Hill. 1989. âThe Commoditization of Women in China.â **Signs** 14 (4): 799-832.
Geertz, Clifford. 1973. âDeep play: notes on the Balinese cockfight.â In **The Interpretation of Culture**. New York: Basic Books.
Geertz, Hildred, and Clifford Geertz. 1975. **Kinship in Bali**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gernet, Jacques. 1956. **Les aspects economiques du bouddhisme dans la societe chinoise du Ve au Xe siĂšcle**. Paris: Ecole francaise dâExtreme-Orient. English version: **Centuries** (Franciscus Verellen, translator). New York: Columbia University Press, 1995.
_____. 1960. âLes suicides par le feu chez les bouddhiques chinoises de Ve au Xe siecle,â **Melange publies par lâInstitut des Hautes Ătudes** II: 527-558.
_____. 1982. **A History of Chinese Civilization**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gerriets, Marilyn. 1978. **Money and Clientship in the Ancient Irish Laws**. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Toronto.
_____. 1981. âThe Organization of Exchange in Early Christian Ireland.â **Journal of Economic History** 41 (1): 171-176.
_____. 1985. âMoney in Early Christian Ireland according to the Irish Laws.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 27 (2): 323-339.
_____. 1987. âKinship and Exchange in Pre-Viking Ireland.â **Cambridge Medieval Celtic Studies** 13: 39-72.
Getz, Trevor R. 2003. âMechanisms of Slave Acquisition and Exchange in Late Eighteenth Century Anomabu: Reconsidering a Cross-Section of the Atlantic Slave Trade.â **African Economic History** 31: 75-89
Ghazanfar, Shaikh M.,. 1991. âScholastic Economics and Arab Scholars: The âGreat Gapâ Thesis Reconsidered.â **Diogenes: International Review of Humane Sciences;** No.154: 117-33.
_____. 2000. âThe Economic Thought of Abu Hamid Al-Ghazali and St. Thomas Aquinas: Some Comparative Parallels and Links.â **History of Political Economy**, 32 (4): 857-888.
_____. 2003. **âMedieval Islamic economic thought: filling the âgreat gapâ in European economics**. New York: Routledge.
Ghazanfar, Shaikh M., and Abdul Azim Islahi,. 1997. **The Economic Thought of al-Ghazali** (450-505 **A.H.** / 1058-1111 **A.D.)** Jeddah: Scientific Publishing Centre King Abdulaziz University.
_____. 2003. âExplorations in Medieval Arab-Islamic Thought: Some Aspects of Ibn Taimiyahâs Economics.â In **Medieval Islamic economic thought: filling the âgreat gapâ in European economics** (S. Ghazanfar, editor), pp. 53-71. New York: Routledge.
Gibson, Charles. 1964. **The Aztecs under Spanish rule: a history of the Indians of the Valley of Mexico**, 1519-1810. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Gilder, George. 1981. **Wealth and Poverty**. New York: Basic Books.
_____. 1990. **Microcosm: the quantum revolution in economics and technology**. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Glahn, Richard Von. 1996a. **Fountain of Fortune: Money and Monetary Policy in China**, 1000-1700. Berkeley: University of California Press.
_____. 1996b. âMyth and Reality of Chinaâs Seventeenth Century Monetary Crisis.â **Journal of Economic History** 56, no 2, pp. 429-54.
Glancey, Jennifer A. 2006. **Slavery in Early Christianity**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gluckman, Max. 1971. **Politics, Law and Ritual in Tribal Society**. London: Basil Blackwell.
Goldstone, Jack A. 1984. âUrbanization and Inflation: Lessons from the English Price Revolution of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries.â **American Journal of Sociology** 89 (5): 1122-60.
_____. 1991. âMonetary Versus Velocity Interpretations of the âPrice Revolutionâ: A Comment.â **Journal of Economic History** 51 (1): 176-181
_____. 2002. âEfflorescences and Economic Growth in World History: Rethinking the âRise of the Westâ and the Industrial Revolution.â **Journal of World History** 13 (2): 323-89.
Goodman, Martin. 1983. **State and Society in Roman Galilee, A.D**. 132-212. London: Valentine Mitchell.
Goody, Jack. 1976. **Production and reproduction: a comparative study of the domestic domain**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1983. **Development of Marriage and the Family in Europe**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1990. **The Oriental, the Ancient, and the Primitive: Systems of Marriage and the Family in the pre-Industrial Societies of Eurasia**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1996. **The East in the West**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goody, Jack and Stanley J. Tambiah. 1973. **Bridewealth and Dowry**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goitein, Shelomo Dov. 1954. âFrom the Mediterranean to India: Documents on the Trade to India, South Arabia, and East Africa from the Eleventh to Twelfth Centuries.â **Speculum** 29: 181-97.
_____. 1957. âThe Rise and Fall of the Middle Eastern bourgeoisie in early Islamic times.â **Journal of World History** 3: 583-603.
_____. 1964. âThe commercial mail service in medieval Islam.â **Journal of the American Oriental Society** 84: 118-23.
_____. 1966. âBankerâs Accounts from the Eleventh Century A.D.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 9: 28-66.
_____. 1967. **A Mediterranean Society, The Jewish Communities of the Arab World as Portrayed in the Documents of the Cairo Geniza**. Berkeley: University of California. Press.
_____. 1973. **Letters of Medieval Jewish Traders**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gordon, Barry. 1982. âLending at interest: some Jewish, Greek, and Christian approaches, 800 BC-AD 100.â **History of Political Economy** 14 (3):406-426.
_____. 1989. **The economic problem in biblical and patristic thought**. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Gough, Kathleen. 1971. âNuer Kinship: a Reexamination.â In **The Translation of Culture: Essays to E. E. Evans-Pritchard** (T. Beidelman, editor), pp. 79-123. London: Tavistock Publications.
Goux, Jean-Joseph. 1990. **Symbolic Economies: After Marx and Freud** (Jennifer Curtiss Gage, translator.) Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Graeber, David. 1997. âManners, Deference and Private Property: the Generalization of Avoidance in Early Modern Europe.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 39 (4): 694-728.
_____. 2001. **Toward an Anthropological Theory of Value: The False Coin of Our Own Dreams**. New York: Palgrave.
_____. 2005. âFetishism and Social Creativity, or Fetishes are Gods in Process of Construction.â **Anthropological Theory** 5 (4): 407-438.
_____. 2006. âTurning Modes of Production Inside Out: Or, Why Capitalism is a Transformation of Slavery (short version).â **Critique of Anthropology** 26 (1): 61-81.
_____. 2007. **Possibilities: Essays on Hierarchy, Rebellion and Desire**. Oakland: AK Press.
_____. 2009. âDebt, Violence, and Impersonal Markets: Polanyian Meditations.â In **Market and Society: The Great Transformation today** (Chris Hann and Keith Hart, editors), pp. 106-132. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Graham, Angus Charles. 1960. **The Book of Lieh-Tzu**. London: John Murray.
_____. 1979. âThe Nung-Chia âSchool of the Tillersâ and the Origin of Peasant Utopianism in China.â **Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London**, Vol. 42 no.1, pp. 66-100.
_____. 1989. **Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China**. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court Press.
_____. 1994. Studies in Chinese philosophy and philosophical literature. **SUNY series in Chinese philosophy and culture. Albany: SUNY**.
Grahl, John. 2000. âMoney as Sovereignty: the Economics of Michel Aglietta.â **New Political Economy** 5 (2): 291-316.
Grandell, Axel. 1977. âThe reckoning board and tally stick.â **Accounting Historians Journal** 4 (1): 101-105.
Gray, Robert F. 1968. âSonjo Bride-Price and the Question of African âWife Purchase.â â **American Anthropologist** 62: 34-47.
Greengus. Samuel. 1966. âOld Babylonian Marriage Ceremonies and Rites.â **Journal of Cuneiform Studies** 20: 57-72.
_____. 1969. âThe Old Babylonian marriage contract.â **Journal** of **the American Oriental Society** 89: 505-532.
_____. 1975. âSisterhood Adoption at Nuzi and the âWife-Sisterâ in Genesis.â **Hebrew Union College Annual** 46: 5-31.
_____. 1990. âBridewealth in Sumerian sources.â **Hebrew Union College Annual** 61: 25-88.
Gregory, Christopher A. 1982. **Gifts and Commodities**. New York: Academic Press.
_____. 1998. **Savage Money: The Anthropology and Politics of Commodity Exchange**. Amsterdam: Harwood Academic Publishers.
Green, Peter. 1993. **Alexander to Actium: the historical evolution of the Hellenistic age**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Greider, William. 1989. **Secrets of the Temple: How the Federal Reserve Runs the Country**. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Grierson, Phillip. 1959. âCommerce in the Dark Ages: a critique of the evidence.â **Transactions of the Royal Historical Society**, 5th series 9: 123-40.
_____. 1960. âThe monetary reforms of âAbd al-Malik: their metrological basis and their financial repercussions.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 3: 241-264.
_____. 1977. **The Origins of Money**. London: Athlone Press.
_____. 1978. âThe Origins of Money.â In **Research in Economic Anthropology Vol. I**. Greenwich: Journal of the Anthropological Institute Press.
_____. 1979. **Dark Age Numismatics**. London: Variorium Reprints.
Grosz, Katarzyna. 1983. âBridewealth and Dowry in Nuzi.â In **Images of Women in Antiquity** (A. Cameron and A. Kuhrt, editors), pp. 193-206. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.
_____. 1989. âSome aspects of the position of women in Nuzi.â In **Womenâs Earliest Records From Ancient Egypt and Western Asia** (Barbara S. Lesko editor), pp. 167-180. Atlanta: Scholarâs Press.
Gudeman, Stephen. 2002. **The Anthropology of Economy**. London: Blackwell.
Guha, Ranjanit. 1999. **Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India**. Durham: Duke University Press.
Guisborough, William of. 1954. **The Chronicle of William of Guisborough**. (H. Rothwell, editor.) London: Camden.
Gupta, Parameshwari Lal and T. R. Hardaker,. 1985. **Indian Silver Punchmarked Coins: Magadha-Maurya Karshapana Series**. Nashik: Indian Institute of Research in Numismatic Studies.
Guth, Delloyd J. 2008. âThe Age of Debt: the Reformation and English Law.â In **Tudor Rule and Revolution: Essays for G. R. Elton from His American Friends** (Delloyd J. Guth and John W. McKenna, editors), pp. 69-86. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Guyer, Jane I. 1994. âBrideprice.â In The Encyclopedia of Social History (Peter N. Stearns, editor.), page 84. London: Taylor & Francis.
_____. 2004. **Marginal Gains: Monetary Transactions in Atlantic Africa**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hadot, Pierre. 1995. **Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault**. (Michael Chase, translator). Oxford: Blackwell.
_____. 2002. **What Is Ancient Philosophy?** Cambridge: Belknap Press.
Hallam, Henry. 1866. **The constitutional history of England, from the accession of Henry VII to the death of George II**. London: Widdelton.
Halperin, David. 1990. âThe Democratic Body: Prostitution and Citizenship in Classical Athens.â In **One Hundred Years of Homosexuality and Other Essays on Greek Love** (David Halperin, editor), pp. 88-112. New York: Routledge.
Hamashita, Takeshi. 1994. Tribute Trade System and Modern Asia.â In **Japanese Industrialization and the Asian Economy** (A. J. H. Latham and H. Kawakatsu, editors), pp. 91-107. London and New York: Routledge.
_____. 2003 âTribute and treaties: maritime Asia and treaty port networks in the era of negotiations, 1800-1900. In **The resurgence of East Asia:** 500, 150 **and** 50 **year perspectives** (Giovanni Arrighi, et al, editors), pp. 15-70. London; New York: Routledge.
Hamilton, Earl J. 1934. **American Treasure and the Price Revolution in Spain**, 1501-1650. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Hardaker, Alfred. 1892. **A Brief History of Pawnbroking**. London: Jackson, Ruston and Keeson.
Hardenburg, Walter Ernest, and Sir Roger Casement. 1913. **The Putumayo: the devilâs paradise; travels in the Peruvian Amazon region and an account of the atrocities committed upon the Indians therein**. London: T. F. Unwin.
Harding, Alan. 1980. âPolitical Liberty in the Middle Ages.â **Speculum** 55 (3): 423-443.
Harrill, J. Albert. 1998. **The manumission of slaves in early Christianity**. TĂŒbingen: Mohr Siebek.
Harris, Edward M. 2006. **Democracy and the Rule of Law in Classical Athens: Essays on Law, Society, and Politics**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Harris, William Vernon, editor. 2006. âA Revisionist View of Roman Money.â **Journal of Roman Studies** 96: 1-24.
_____. 2008a. âIntroduction.â In **The monetary systems of the Greeks and Romans** (W. V. Harris, editor), pp. 1-12. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
_____. 2008b. âThe Nature of Roman Money.â In **The monetary systems of the Greeks and Romans** (W. V. Harris, editor), pp. 174-207. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harris, Rosemary. 1972. âThe History of Trade at Ikom, Eastern Nigeria.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** Vol. 42 (2): 122-139.
Harrison, James P. 1965. . âCommunist Interpretations of the Chinese Peasant Wars.â **The China Quarterly**, no. 24. pp. 92-118.
Hart, Keith. 1986. âHeads or Tails? Two Sides of the Coin.â **Man** (N.S.) 21: 637-56.
_____. 1999. **The Memory Bank: Money in an Unequal World**. London: Perpetua Books.
Huang, Ray. 1974. **Taxation and Governmental Finance in Sixteenth-Century China**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1999. **Broadening the horizons of Chinese history: discourses, syntheses, and comparisons**. Amonk: M. E. Sharpe.
Hawtrey, Ralph G. 1928. **Currency and Credit**. 3rd edition. London: Longmans, Green and Co.
Hayward, Jack. 1959. âSolidarity: The Social History of an Idea in Nineteenth Century France.â **International Review of Social History** 4: 261-284.
Heady, Patrick. 2005. âBarter.â In **Handbook of Economic Anthropology** (James Carrier, editor), pp. 262-274. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
HĂ©bert, Jean-Claude. 1958. âLa ParentĂ© Ă Plaisanterie Ă Madagascar: Ătude dâEthnologie Juridique.â **Bulletin de Madagascar** No. 142-143 (April-May 1958): 122-258.
Heilbron, Johan. 1998. âFrench Moralists and the Anthropology of the Modern Era: On the Genesis of the Notions of âInterestâ and âCommercial Society.â â In **The rise of the social sciences and the formation of modernity: conceptual change in context**, 1750-1850 (Björn Wiitrock, Johan Heilbron, & Lars Magnusson, editors), pp. 77-106. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Heinsohn, Gunnar and Otto Steiger. 1989. âThe Veil of Barter: The Solution to âThe Task of Obtaining Representations of an Economy in which Money is Essential.â In **Inflation and Income Distribution in Capitalist Crisis: Essays in Memory of Sidney Weintraub**. Edited by J. A. Kregel. New York: NYU Press, pp. 175-202.
Helmholz, Richard H. 1986. âUsury and the Medieval English Church Courts.â **Speculum** 56: 364-80
Herbert, Eugenia W. 2003. **Red Gold of Africa: Copper in Precolonial History and Culture**. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Herlihy, David. 1985. **Medieval Households**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Herzfeld, Michael. 1980. âHonour and Shame: Problems in the Comparative Analysis of Moral Systems.â **Man** 15:339-351.
_____. 1985. **The Poetics of Manhood**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Hezser, Catherine. 2003. âThe Impact of Household Slaves on the Jewish Family in Roman Palestine.â **Journal for the Study of Judaism** 34 (4): 375-424.
Hildebrand, Bruno. 1864. âNatural-, Geld- und Creditwirtschaft.â **Jahrbuch Nationalökonomie** 1864.
Hill, Christopher. 1972. **The World Turned Upside Down**. New York: Penguin.
Hirschman, Albert 0. 1977. **The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before its Triumph**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
_____. 1992. **Rival views of market society and other recent essays**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Hocart, Alfred M. 1936. **Kings and Councillors: an essay in the comparative anatomy of human society**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hodgson, Marshall G. S. 1974. **The Venture of Islam: Conscience and History in a World Civilization**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hoitenga, Dewey J. 1991. **Faith and reason from Plato to Plantinga: an introduction to Reformed epistemology**. Albany: SUNY Press.
Holman, Susan R. 2002. **The hungry are dying: beggars and bishops in Roman Cappadocia**. New York: Oxford University Press.
Homans, George. 1958. âSocial Behavior as Exchange.â **American Journal of Sociology** 63 (6): 597-606.
Homer, Sydney. 1987. **A History of Interest Rates** (2nd edition). New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.
Hopkins, Keith. 1978. **Conquerors and Slaves: Sociological Studies in Roman History**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hoppit, Julian. 1990. âAttitudes to Credit in Britain, 1680-1790.â **The Historical Journal** 33 (2): 305-322.
Hoskins, Janet. 1999. **Biographical Objects: How Things Tell the Stories of Peopleâs Lives**. New York: Routledge.
Hosseini, Hamid S. 1995. âUnderstanding the market mechanism before Adam Smith: economic thought in Medieval Islam.â **History of Political Economy** 27 (3): 539-61.
_____. 1998. âSeeking the roots of Adam Smithâs division of labor in medieval Persia.â **History of Political Economy** 30 (4): 653-81.
_____. 2003. âContributions of Medieval Muslim Scholars to the History of Economics and their Impact: A Refutation of the Schumpeterian Great Gap.â In **The Blackwell Companion to Contemporary Economics, III: A Companion to the History of Economic Thought** (Warren J. Samuels, Jeff Biddle, and John Bryan Davis, editors), pp. 28-45. London: Wiley-Blackwell.
Houston, Walter J. 2006. **Contending for Justice: Ideologies and Theologies of Social Justice in the Old Testament**. London: T & T Clark.
Howel, King. 2006. **Ancient laws and institutes of Wales: Laws Supposed to Be Enacted by Howel the Good**. Clark, New Jersey: The Lawbook Exchange, Ltd.
Howell, Paul P. 1954. **A Manual of Nuer Law**. International Africa Institute. London: Oxford University Press.
Howgego, Christopher. 1992. âThe Supply and Use of Money in the Roman World 200 B.C. to A.D. 300.â **Journal of Roman Studies** 82: 1-31
Hubbard, Jamie. 2001. **Absolute Delusion, Perfect Buddhahood: The Rise and Fall of a Chinese Heresy**. Honolulu: University of Hawaii.
Hubert, Henri and Marcel Mauss. 1964. **Sacrifice: Its Nature and Function**. Translated by W.D. Halls. London: Cohen and West.
Hudson, Kenneth. 1982. **Pawnbroking: An Aspect of British Social History**. London: The Bodley Head.
Hudson, Michael. 1992. âDid the Phoenicians Introduce the Idea of Interest to Greece and Italy â And if So, When?â In **Greece Between East and West: 10th?8th Centuries BC** (GĂŒnter Kopcke and Isabelle Tokumaru, editors), pp. 128-143. Mainz: Verlag Philipp von Zabern.
_____. 1993. âThe Lost Tradition of Biblical Debt Cancellations.â Research paper presented at the Hentry George School of Social Science, 1992 ([[http://www.michael-hudson.com/articles/debt/Hudson,LostTradition.pdf][http://www.michael-hudson.com/articles/debt/Hudson,LostTradition.pdf]].)
_____. 2002. âReconstructuring the Origins of Interest-Bearing Debt and the Logic of Clean Slates.â In **Debt and Economic Renewal in the Ancient Near East** (Hudson, Michael and Marc Van de Mieroop, editors), pp. 7-58. Bethesda: CDL Press.
_____. 2003a. **Super Imperialism: The Origins and Fundamentals of U.S World Dominance**. London: Pluto Press.
_____. 2003b. âThe creditary/monetarist debate in historical perspective.â **The State, the Market, and Euro: chartalism versus metallism in the theory of money**. (edited by Stephanie Bell and Edward Nell), pp. 39-76. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Press.
_____. 2004a. âThe archeology of money: debt vs. barter theories of money.â In **Credit and State Theories of Mone**y (Randall Wray, editor), pp. 99-127. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Press.
_____. 2004b. âThe Development of Money-of-Account in Sumerâs Temples.â In **Creating Economic Order: Record-Keeping, Standardization and the Development of Accounting in the Ancient Near East** (Michael Hudson and Cornelia Wunsch, editors), pp. 303-329. Baltimore: CDL Press.
Hudson, Michael and Marc Van de Mieroop, editors. 2002. **Debt and Economic Renewal in the ancient Near East**. Bethesda, MD: CDL Press.
Humphrey, Caroline. 1985. âBarter and Economic Disintegration.â **Man** 20: 48-72.
_____. 1994. âFair Dealing, Just Rewards: the Ethics of Barter in North-East Nepal.â In **Barter, Exchange, and Value: An Anthropological Approach** (Caroline Humphrey and Stephen Hugh-Jones, editors), pp. 107-141. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Humphrey, Chris. 2001. **The politics of carnival: festive misrule in medieval England**. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Hunt, William. 1983. **The Puritan moment: the coming of revolution in an English county**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Hutchinson, Sharon. 1996. **Nuer Dilemmas: Coping with Money, War, and the State**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Ibn Battuta. 1354 \[1929\]. **Travels in Asia and Africa**, 1325-1354 (translated by H. A. R. Gibb). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Icazbalceta, Joaquin Garcia. 2008. Memoriales de Fray Toribio de Motolinia. Charleston: BiblioBazaar.
Ihering, Rudolf von. 1877. **Geist des Romischen Rechts auf den verschieden en Stufen seiner Entwicklung**. (Republished 2003 by Adamant Media Corporation, Berlin.)
Ilwof, Franz. 1882. **Tauschhandel und Geldsurrogate in alter und neuer Zeit**. Graz.
Ingham, Geoffrey. 1996. âMoney as a Social Relation.â **Review of Social Economy** 54 (4): 507-29.
_____. 1999. âCapitalism, Money, and Banking: a critique of recent historical sociology.â **British Journal of Sociology** 5 (1): 76-96.
_____. 2000. â âBabylonian Madnessâ: on the historical and sociological origins of money.â in **What is Money?** (edited by John Smithin), New York: Routledge, pp. 16-41.
_____. 2004. **The Nature of Money**. Cambridge: Polity Press. Ingram, Jill Phillips. 2006. **Idioms of Self-Interest: Credit, Identity and Property in English Renaissance Literature**. New York: Routledge.
Inkori, Joseph E. 1982. âThe Import of Firearms into West Africa, 1750 to 1807: a quantative analysis.â In **Forced Migration: The Impact of the Export Slave Trade on African Societies** (J. E. Inkori, editor), pp 126-153. London: Hutchinson University Library.
Innes, A. Mitchell. 1913. âWhat is Money?â **Banking Law Journal** (May1913): 377-408.
_____. 1914. âThe Credit Theory of Money.â **Banking Law Journal** (January 1914): 151-168.
Ioannatou, Marina. 2006. **Affaires dâargent dans la correspondance de CicĂ©ron: lâaristocratie sĂ©natoriale face Ă ses dettes**. Paris: De Boccard.
Isichei, Elizabeth. 1976. **A History of the Igbo People**. London: Basingstoke.
Islahi, Abdul Azim. 1985. âIbn Taimiyahâs Concept of Market Mechanism.â **Journal of Research in Islamic Economics**2 (2): 55-65.
_____. 2003. **Contributions of Muslim Scholars to Economic Thought and Analysis** (11-905 **A. H**./632-1500 **A.D.)** Jeddah: Islamic Research Center.
Jacob, Guy. 1987. âGallieni et âlâimpot moralisateurâ a Madagascar: thĂ©orie, pratiques et consĂ©quences (1901-1905).â **Revue Francaise dâHistoire dâOutre-mer** 74 (277): 431-473.
James, C. L. R. 1938. **The Black Jacobins: Toussaint LâOuverture and the San Domingo Revolution**. London: Secker and Warburg.
Jan, Yun-hua,. 1964. âBuddhist Self-Immolation in Medieval China.â **History of Religions** (4) 2: 243-268.
Janssen, Johannes. 1910. **A History of the German People at the Close of the Middle Ages**. (A. M. Christie, translator.) London: Kegan Paul.
Jasnow, Richard Lewis. 2001. âPre-demotic Pharaonic sources.â In **Security for debt in Ancient Near Eastern law** (Westbrook, R. & Jasnow, R, editors), pp. 35-45. Leiden, Boston & Köln: Brill.
Jaspers, Karl. 1949. **Vom Ursprung und Ziel der Geschichte**. MĂŒnchen: Piper Verlag.
_____. 1951. **Way to Wisdom: An Introduction to Philosophy**. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Jefferson, Thomas. 1988. **Political Writings**. (Joyce Oldham Appleby, Terence Ball, editors). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jenkinson, C. Hilary. 1911. âExchequer Tallies.â **Archaeologia** 62: 367-380.
_____. 1924. âMedieval Tallies, Public and Private.â **Archaeologia** 74: 289-324.
Jevons, W. Stanley. 1871. **Theory of Political Economy**. New York: Macmillan & Co.
_____. 1875. **Money and the Mechanism of Exchange**. New York: Appleton and Company.
Jobert, Bruno. 2003. âDe la solidaritĂ© aux solidaritĂ©s dans la rhĂ©torique politique française.â In C. Becc and G. Procacci, ed., **De la responsabilitĂ© solidaire**, pp. 69-83. Paris: Syllepses.
Johnson, Lynn. 2004. âFriendship, Coercion, and Interest: Debating the Foundations of Justice in Early Modern England.â **Journal of Early Modern History** 8 (1): 46-64.
Johnson, Simon. 2009. âThe Quiet Coup.â Atlantic Monthly, May 2009, [[http://www.the-atlantic.com/doc/200905/imf-advice][http://www.the-atlantic.com/doc/200905/imf-advice]].
Jones, David. 2004. **Reforming the morality of usury: a study of differences that separated the Protestant reformers**. Lanham: University Press of America.
Jones, G. I. 1939. âWho are the Aro?â **Nigerian Field** 8: 100-103.
_____. 1958. âNative and Trade Currencies in Southern Nigeria during the Eighteenth and Nineteenth Centuries.â **Africa: Journal of the International African Institute** 28 (1): 43-56.
_____. 1968. âThe Political Organization of Old Calabar.â In **Efik Traders of Old Calabar** (D. Forde, editor). London: International African Institute.
Jones, J. Walter. 1956. **The Law and Legal Theory of the Greeks**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Jordan, Kay E. 2003. **From Sacred Servant to Profane Prostitute: A History of the Changing Legal Status of Devadasis in India**, 1857-1947. New Delhi: Manohar.
Just, Roger. 1989. **Women in Athenian Law and Life**. London: Routledge
_____. 2001. âOn the Ontological Status of Honour.â In **An anthropology of indirect communication** (Joy Hendry, C. W. Watson, editors), pp. 34-50. ASA Monographs 37. London: Routledge.
Kahneman, Daniel. 2003. âA Psychological Perspective on Economics.â **American Economic Review** 93 (2): 162-168
Kallet, Lisa. 2001. **Money and the corrosion of power in Thucydides: the Sicilian expedition and its aftermath**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Kaltenmark, Max. 1960. âLing pao: Notes sur un terme du taoĂźsme religieux.â **MĂ©langes publiĂ©s par lâInstitut des Hautes Ătudes Chinoises** 2: 559-88.
Kalupahana, David. 1991. **Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna: the Philosophy of the Middle Way**. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidas.
Kamentz, Anya. 2006. **Generation Debt: Why Now is A Terrible Time to Be Young**. New York: Riverhead Books.
Kan, Lao. 1978. âThe Early Use of the Tally in China.â In **Ancient China: Studies in Early Civilization** (edited by David T. Roy and Tsuen-hsuin Tsien), pp. 91-98. Hong Kong: Chinese University Press.s
Kane, Pandurang Vaman,. 1968. **History of Dharmasastra Volume III**. Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute.
Kantorowicz, Ernst H. 1957. **The Kingâs Two Bodies: a Study in Medieval Political Theology**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Karatani, Kojin. 2003. **Transcritique: On Kant and Marx**. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Keil, Charles. 1979. **Tiv Song**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Keith, Arthur Berriedale. 1925. **The Religion and Philosophy of the Veda and Upanishads**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Kelly, Amy. 1937. âEleanor of Aquitaine and Her Courts of Love.â **Speculum** 12 (1): 3-19
Kelly, Fergus. 1988. **A Guide to Early Irish Law**. Dublin: Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies.
Kessler, David & Peter Temin. 2008. âMoney and Prices in the Early Roman Empire.â In **The monetary systems of the Greeks and Romans** (W. V. Harris, editor), pp. 137-160. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Keuls, Eva. 1985. **The Reign of the Phallus: Sexual Politics in Ancient Athens**. Cambridge: Harper & Row.
Keynes, John Maynard. 1930. **A Treatise on Money**. London: MacMillan.
_____. 1936. The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money.
Keyt, David. 1997. **Aristotle: Politics Books VII and VIII**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Khan, Mir Siadat Ali. 1929. âThe Mohammedan Laws against Usury and How They Are Evaded.â **Journal of Comparative Legislation and International Law**, Third Series 11 (4): 233-24
Kieschnick, John. 1997. **The eminent monk: Buddhist ideals in medieval Chinese hagiography**. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Kim, Henry S. 2001. âArchaic Coinage as Evidence for the Use of Money,â in, A. Meadows and K. Shipton, eds., Money and Its Uses in the Ancient Greek World (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 7â21.
_____. 2002. âSmall Change and the Moneyed Economy.â In **Money, Labour and Land: Approaches to the economies of ancient Greece** (Paul Cartledge, Edward E. Cohen and Lin Foxhall, editors). New York: Routledge.
Kindleberger, Charles P. 1984. **A Financial History of Western Europe**. London: MacMillan.
_____. 1986. **Manias, Panics, and Crashes: A History of Financial Crises**. London: MacMillan.
Kirschenbaum, Aaron. 1985. âJewish and Christian Theories of Usury in the Middle Ages.â **The Jewish Quarterly Review** 75 (1): 270-89.
Kitch, Aaron. 2007. âThe Character of Credit and the Problem of Belief in Middletonâs City Comedies.â **Studies in English Literature** 47 (2): 403â426.
Klein, Martin A. 2000. âThe Slave Trade and Decentralized Societies.â **Journal of African History** 41 (1): 49-65.
Knapp, Georg Friedrich. 1905. **Staatliche Theorie des Gelde**. Leipzing: Dunker and Humblot. [English edition, **The State Theory of Money**. London: MacMillan, 1925.]
Knapp, Keith N. 2004. âReverent Caring: the parent-son relation in early medieval tales of filial offspring.â In **Filial Piety in Chinese Thought and History** (Alan Kam-leung Chan, and Sur-hoon Tan, editors), pp. 44-70. London: Routledge.
Ko, Dorothy, JaHyun Kim Haboush, and Joan R. Piggott, editors. 2003. **Women and Confucian cultures in premodern China, Korea, and Japan**. Berkeley: University of California Press
Kohn, Livia. 2000. **Daoism handbook**. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
_____. 2002. **Monastic life in medieval Daoism: a cross-cultural perspective**. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Kopytoff, Igor and Suzanne Miers. 1977. âAfrican âSlaveryâ as an Institution of Marginality.â In **Slavery in Africa: Historical and Anthropological Perspectives** (edited by Suzanne Miers and Igor Kopytoff), pp. 1-84. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Korver, Jan. 1934. **Die terminologie van het crediet-wezen en het Grieksch**. Amsterdam: H. J. Paris.
Kosambi, Damodar Dharmanand. 1965. **The Culture and Civilisation of Ancient India in Historical Outline**. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
_____. 1966. **Ancient India: A History Of Its Culture And Civilization**. New York: Pantheon Books.
_____. 1981. **Indian Numismatics**. Hyderabad: Orient Longman.
_____. 1996. **An introduction to the study of Indian history**. Bombay: Popular Prakashan.
Kraan, Alfons van der. 1983. âBali: Slavery and Slave Trade.â In **Slavery, Bondage and Dependence in Southeast Asia** (Anthony Reid, editor), pp. 315-340. New York: St. Martinâs Press
Kraay, Colin M. 1964. âHoards, Small Change and the Origin of Coinage,â **Journal of Hellenic Studies**, 84, pp. 76-91.
Kramer, Samuel Noah. 1963. **The Sumerians: Their History, Culture, and Character**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
_____. 1969. **The Sacred Marriage: Aspects of Faith, Myth and Ritual in Ancient Sumer**. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Kropotkin, Peter. 1902. **Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution**. London: William Heinemann.
Kulischer, Joseph. 1926. **Allgemeine Wirtschaftsgeschichte des Mittelalters und der Neuzeit**. Munich.
Kuran, Timur. 1995. âIslamic Economics and the Islamic Subeconomy.â **Journal of Economic Perspectives** 9 (4): 155-173.
_____. 2005. âThe Absence of the Corporation in Islamic Law: Origins and Persistence.â **American Journal of Comparative Law** 53 (4): 785-834.
Kurke, Leslie. . 1995. âPindar and the Prostitutes, or Reading Ancient âPornography.â â **Arion**, Third Series 4 (2): 49-7.
_____. 1997. âInventing the âHetairaâ: Sex, Politics, and Discursive Conflict in Archaic Greece.â **Classical Antiquity** 16 (1):106-150
_____. 2002. **Coins, bodies, games, and gold: the politics of meaning in archaic Greece**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kuznets, Solomon. 1933. âPawnbroking.â In **Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences** (Edwin R. A. Seligman, editor), VII:38. New York: MacMillan.
Labib, Subhi Y. 1969. âCapitalism in Medieval Islam.â **The Journal of Economic History** 29 (1): 79-96.
Ladner, Gerhardt B. 1979. âMedieval and Modern Understanding of Symbolism: A Comparison.â **Speculum** 54 (2): 223-256.
Lafitau, Joseph François. 1974. **Customs of the American Indians Compared with the Customs of Primitive Times** (edited and translated by William N. Fenton and Elizabeth L. Moore). Toronto: Champlain Society.
LaFleur, William R,. 1986. **The karma of words: Buddhism and the literary arts in medieval Japan**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Lafont, Bertrand. 1987. âLes filles du roi de Mari.â In **La femme dans le Proche-orient antique** (J -M. Durand, editor), pp. 113-123. Paris: ERC.
Lambert, Maurice. 1971. âUne Inscription nouvelle dâEntemena prince de Lagash.â **Revue du Louvre** 21:231-236.
Lambert, Wilfried G. 1992. âProstitution.â In **Aussenseiter und Randgruppen: Beitrage zu einer Sozialgeschichte des Alten Orients** (edited V. Haas), 127-157. Konstanz: Universitatsverlag
Lamotte, Etienne. 1997. **Karmasiddhi Prakarana: The Treatise on Action by Vasubandhu**. Freemont: Asian Humanities Press.
Lane, Frederic Chapin. 1934. **Venetian ships and shipbuilders of the Renaissance**. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
Langholm, Odd. 1979. **Price and Value in the Aristotelian Tradition**. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.
_____. 1984. **The Aristotelian Analysis of Usury**. Bergen: Universitetsforlaget.
_____. 1992. **Economics in the Medieval Schools: Wealth, Exchange, Value, Money and Usury According to the Paris Theological Tradition**, 1200-1350: 29 (Studien Und Texte Zur Geistesgeschichte Des Mittelalters). Leiden: E. J. Brill.
_____. 1996. âThe Medieval Schoolmen, 1200-1400.â In **Ancient and Medieval Economic Ideas and Concepts of Social Justice** (edited by S. Todd Lowry and Barry Gordon), pp. 439-502. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
_____. 1998. **The Legacy of Scholasticism in Economic Thought: Antecedents of Choice and Power**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 2002. **The Merchant in the Confessional: Trade and Price in the Pre-Reformation Penitential Handbooks**. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Lapidus, Ira. 1995. âState and Religion in Islamic Societies.â **Past and Present 151**: 3-27.
_____. 2002. **A History of Islamic Societies** (2nd edition.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Larson, Pier. 2000. **History and Memory in the Age of Enslavement: Becoming Merina in Highland Madagascar**, 1770-1822. Portsmouth: Heinemann.
Latham, A. J. H. 1971. âCurrency, Credit and Capitalism on the Cross River in the Pre-colonial Era.â **Journal of African History** 12 (4): 599-605.
_____. 1973. **Old Calabar** 1600-1891: **The Impact of the International Economy Upon a Traditional Society**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
_____. 1990. âThe Pre-Colonial Economy; The Lower Cross Region.â In **A History of the Cross River Region of Nigeria**. (Monday B. Abasiattai, editor), pp. 70-89. Calabar: University of Calabar Press.
Laum, Bernard. 1924. **Heiliges Geld: Eine historische Untersuchung ueber den sakralen Ursprung des Geldes**. TĂŒbingen: J. C. B. Mohr.
Law, Robin. 1994. âOn Pawning and Enslavement for Debt in the Pre-colonial Slave Coaast.â **Pawnship in Africa: Debt Bondage in Historical Perspective** (Falola, Toyin and Paul E. Lovejoy, editors), pp. 61-82. Boulder: University of Colorado Press.
Le Guin, Ursula. 1974. **The Disposessed**. New York: Avon.
Leach, Edmund R. 1961. **Rethinking Anthropology**. London: Athlone Press.
_____. 1983. âThe kula: an alternative view.â In **The Kula: New Perspectives on Massim Exchange** (Jerry Leach, editor), pp. 529-538. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Le Goff, Jacques. 1990. **Your Money or Your Life: Economy and Religion in the Middle Ages**. (Translated by Patricia Ranum.) New York: Zone Books.
Le Rider, George,. 2001. **La naissance de la monnaie: pratiques monĂ©taires de lâOrient ancient**. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Lee, Ian. 2000. âEntella: the silver coinage of the Campanian mercenaries and the site of the first Carthaginian mint, 410-409 BC.â **Numismatic Chronicle** 160: 1-66.
Leenhardt, Maurice. 1967. **Do Kamo: Person and Myth in the Melanesian World**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lemche, Niels Peter. 1975. âThe âHebrew Slaveâ: Comments on the Slave Law, Ex. Xxi 2-11.â **Vetus Testamentum** 25: 129-44.
_____. 1976. âThe Manumission of Slaves: The Fallow Year, The Sabbatical Year, The Jobel Year.â **Vetus Testamentum** 26: 38-59.
_____. 1979. **Andurarum** and **Misharum:** Comments on the Problems of Social Edicts and their Application in the Ancient Near East,â **Journal of Near Eastern Studies** 38:11-18.
_____. 1985. **Ancient Israel: A New History of Israelite Society**. Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press.
Lerner, Abba P. 1947. âMoney as a Creature of the State.â **American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings** 37 (2): 312-17.
Lerner, Gerda. 1983. âWomen and Slavery.â **Slavery and Abolition: A Journal of Comparative Studies** 4 (3):173-98.
_____. 1980. âThe Origin of Prostitution in Ancient Mesopotamia.â **Signs 11** (2): 236-254.
_____. 1989. **The Creation of Patriarchy**. New York: Oxford University Press.
Letwin, William. 2003. **Origins of Scientific Economics: English Economic Thought**, 1660-1776. London: Routledge.
LĂ©vi, Sylvain. 1898. **La Doctrine du Sacrifice dans les BrĂąhmanas**. Paris: Ernest Leroux.
_____. 1938. **LâInde civilisatrice**. Paris: Institut de Civilisation Indienne.
Levi-Strauss, Claude. 1943. âGuerre et commerce chez les Indiens dâAmĂ©rique du Sud.â **Renaissance**. Paris: Ecole Libre des Hautes Ătudes, vol, 1, fascicule 1 et 2.
_____. 1963. **Structural Anthropology**. (C. Jacobson and B. G. Schoepf, translators.) New York: Basic Books.
LĂ©vy-Bruhl, Lucien. 1923. **Primitive Mentality**. London: Allen & Unwin.
Lewis, Mark Edward. 1990. **Sanctioned Violence in Early China**. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Li, Xueqin. 1985. **Eastern Zhou and Qin Civilizations**. (translated by K. C. Chang). New Haven: Yale University Press
Liddell. Henry George and Robert Scott. 1940. **A Greek-English Lexicon, revised and augmented throughout by Sir Henry Stuart Jones with the assistance of Roderick McKenzie**. Oxford. Clarendon Press.
Lindholm, Charles. 1982. **Generosity and Jealousy: the Swat Pukhtun of Northern Pakistan**. New York: Columbia University Press.
Linebaugh, Peter. 1982. âLabour History without the Labour Process: A Note on John Gast and His Times.â **Social History** 7 (3): 319-28.
_____. 1993. **The London Hanged: Crime and Civil Society in the Eighteenth Century**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 2008. **The Magna Carta Manifesto: Liberties and Commons for All**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Littlefield, Henry. 1963. âThe Wizard of Oz: Parable on Populism.â **American Quarterly** 16 (1): 47-98.
Llewellyn-Jones, Lloyd. 2003. **Aphroditeâs Tortoise: the veiled woman of ancient Greece**. Swansea: Classical Press of Wales
Locke, John. 1680-1690. **Two Treatises on Government**. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press edition, 1988).
_____. 1691. âFurther Considerations Concerning Raising the Value of Money.â In The Works of John Locke Volume 5, pp. 131-206. London: W. Otridge & Son, 1812.
Loizos, Peter. 1977. âPolitics and patronage in a Cypriot village, 1920-1970.â In Ernest Gellner and John Waterbury, editors, **Patrons and Clients** (London: Duckworth), pp. 115-135.
Lombard, Maurice. 1947. âLes bases monĂ©taires dâune suprĂ©matie Ă©conomique: lâor musulman du VIIe au XIe siĂšcleâ, **Annales** 2:143-60.
_____. 2003. **The Golden Age of Islam**. Princeton: Markus Wiener Publishers.
Loraux, Nicole. 1993. **The Children of Athena: Athenian Ideas About Citizenship and the Division Between the Sexes**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Lorton, David. 1977. âThe Treatment of Criminals in Ancient Egypt: Through the New Kingdom.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 20 (1): 2-64.
Lovejoy, Paul F. and David Richardson. 1999. âTrust, Pawnship, and Atlantic History: The institutional foundations of the Old Calabar slave trade.â **American Historical Review** 104: 333-355.
_____. 2001. âThe Business of Slaving: Pawnship in Western Africa, c. 1600-1810.â **Journal of African History** 42 (1) 67-84.
_____. 2004. â âThis Horrid Holeâ: Royal Authority, Commerce and Credit at Bonny, 1690-1840.â **Journal of African History** 45 (3): 363-392.
Lusthaus, Dan. 2002. **Buddhist phenomenology: a philosophical investigation of YogÄcÄra Buddhism and the Ch?eng Wei-shih lun**. Volume 13 of Curzon critical studies in Buddhism. New York: Routledge.
Macaulay, Baron Thomas Babington. 1886. **The history of England, from the accession of James the Second**. London: Longmans, Green and co.
MacDonald, James. 2006. **A free nation deep in debt: the financial roots of democracy**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
MacDonald, Scott B. and Albert L. Gastmann. 2001. **A History of Credit & Power in the Western World**. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
MacIntosh, Marjorie K. 1988. âMoney Lending on the Periphery of London, 1300-1600.â **Albion** 20 (4): 557-571
Mackay, Charles. 1854. **Memoirs of extraordinary popular delusions: and the madness of crowds, Volumes** 1-2. London: G. Routledge and sons.
MacKenney, Richard. 1987. **Tradesmen and Traders: The World of the Guilds in Venice and Europe (c**. 1250**-c**. 1650). Totowa: Barnes & Noble.
MacPherson, Crawford Brough. 1962. **The political theory of possessive individualism; Hobbes to Locke**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Maekawa, Kazuya. 1974. âThe development of the Ă-MĂ in Lagash during Early Dynastic III.â **Mesopotamia** 8â9: 77-144.
Maitland, Frederick William. 1908. **The Constitutional History of England: A Course of Lectures Delivered**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Malamoud, Charles. 1983. âThe Theology of Debt in Brahmanism.â In **Debts and Debtors** (Charles Malamoud, editor), pp. 21-40. London: Vices.
_____. 1988. âPrĂ©sentation.â **In Lien de vie, noeud mortel. Les reprĂ©sentations de la dette en Chine, au Japon et dans le monde indien** (Charles Malamoud, editor), pp. 7-15. Paris: EHESS.
_____. 1998. âLe paiement des actes rituals dans lâInde vĂ©dique.â In **La Monnaie Suzerain** (Michael Aglietta and AndrĂ© Orlean, editors), pp. 35-54. Paris: Editions Odile Jacob.
Malinowski, Bronislaw. 1922. **Argonauts of the Western Pacific: An Account of Native Enterprise and Adventure in the Archipelagoes of Melanesian New Guinea**. London: Routledge.
Maloney, Robert P. 1983. âThe Teaching of the Fathers on Usury: An Historical Study on the Development of Christian Thinking.â **Vigiliae Christianae** 27 (4):241-65.
Mann, Bruce H. 2002. **Republic of Debtors: Bankruptcy in the Age of American Independence**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Martin, Randy. 2002. **The Financialization of Everyday Life**. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Martzloff, Jean-Claude. 2006. **A history of chinese mathematics**. Berlin: Springer Verlag.
Marx, Karl. 1853. âThe British Rule in India.â **New-York Daily Tribune**, June 25, 1853.
_____. 1857 \[1973\]. **The Grundrisse**. New York: Harper and Row.
_____. 1858 \[1965\]. **Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations**. (Jack Cohen, trans.) New York: International Publishers.
_____. 1867 \[1967\]. **Capital**. New York: New World Paperbacks. 3 volumes.
Mathews, Robert Henry. 1931. **Mathewsâ Chinese-English dictionary**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Mathias, Peter. 1979a. âCapital, Credit, and Enterprise in the Industrial Revolution.â In **The transformation of England: essays in the economic and social history of England in the eighteenth century** (Peter Mathias, editor), pp. 88-115. London: Taylor & Francis.
_____. 1979b. âThe Peopleâs Money in the Eighteenth Century: The Royal Mint, Trade Tokens and the Economy.â In **The transformation of England: essays in the economic and social history of England in the eighteenth century** (Peter Mathias, editor), pp. 190-208. London: Taylor & Francis.
Maunder, Peter, Danny Myers, Nancy Wall, Roger LeRoy Miller,. 1991. **Economics Explained (Third Edition)**. London: Harper Collins.
Mauro, FrĂ©dĂ©ric. 1993. âMerchant Communities, 1350-1750.â In **The Rise of merchant empires: long-distance trade in the early modern world**, 1350-1750 (James D. Tracy, editor), pp. 255-286. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mauss, Marcel. 1924. Essai sur le don. Forme et raison de lâĂ©change dans les sociĂ©tĂ©s archaĂŻques.â **Annee sociologique**, 1 (series 2):30-186.
_____. 1925. âCommentaires sur un texte de Posidonius. Le suicide, contre-prestation supreme.â **Revue celtique** 42: 324-9.
_____. 1947. **Manuel dâethnographie**. Paris: Payot.
Meillassoux, Claude. 1996. **The Anthropology of Slavery: The Womb of Iron and Gold** (Alide Dasnois, translator). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Menefee, Samuel Pyeatt. 1981. **Wives for Sale: an Ethnographic Study of British Popular Divorce**. Oxford: Blackwell.
Mendelsohn, Isaac. 1949. **Slavery in the Ancient Near East: A Comparative Study of Slavery in Babylonia, Assyria, Syria and Palestine from the Middle of the Third Millennium to the End of the First Millennium**. Westport: Greenwood Press.
Menger, Karl. 1892. âOn the origins of money.â **Economic Journal** 2 no 6, pp. 239-55.
Meyer, Marvin W. 1999. **The ancient mysteries: a sourcebook: sacred texts of the mystery religions of the ancient Mediterranean world**. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Midelfort, H. C. Erik. 1996. **Mad princes of renaissance Germany**. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press.
Midnight Notes Collective. 2009. âPromissory Notes: From Crises to Commons.â ([[http://www.midnightnotes.org/Promissory_Notes.pdf][http://www.midnightnotes.org/Promissory_Notes.pdf]])
Mielants, Eric. 2001. âEurope and China Compared.â **Review** XXV, no. 4, pp. 401-49.
_____. 2007. **The Origins of Capitalism and the âRise of the West.â** Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Mieroop, Marc Van De. 2002. âA History of Near Eastern Debt?â In **Debt and Economic Renewal in the Ancient Near East** (Hudson, Michael and Marc Van de Mieroop, editors), pp. 59-95. Bethesda: CDL.
_____. 2005. âThe Invention of Interest: Sumerian Loans.â In **The Origins of Value: The Financial Innovations That Created Modern Capital Markets** (William N. Goetzmann and K. Geert Rouwenhorst, editors), pp. 17-30. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mez, Adam. 1932. **Die Renaissance des Islams**. Heidelberg: C. Winter.
Miller, Joseph. 1988. **Way of Death: Merchant Capitalism and the Angolan Slave Trade** 1730-1830. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Miller, Robert J. 1961. âMonastic Economy: The Jisa Mechanism.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 3 (4): 427-438.
Miller, William. 1993. **Humiliation : and other essays on honor, social discomfort, and violence**. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
_____. 2006. **An Eye for an Eye**. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Millett, Paul. 1989. âPatronage and its Avoidance.â In **Patronage in Ancient Society** (A. Wallace-Hadrill, editor), pp. 15-47. London: Routledge.
_____. 1991a. **Lending and Borrowing in Classical Athens**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1991b. âSale, Credit and Exchange in Athenian Law and Society.â In **Nomos** (P. Cartiledge, P. C. Millett and S. C. Todd, editors), pp. 167-194. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Millon, Frances. 1955. **When money grew on trees: a study of cacao in ancient Mesoamerica**. Ph.D dissertation, Columbia University.
Mises, Ludwig von. 1949. **Human Action: A Treatise on Economics**. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Misra, Shive Nandan. 1976. **Ancient Indian Republics: from the Earliest Times to the** 6**th Century A.D**. Delhi: Upper India Publishing House.
Mitamura, Taisuke. 1970. **Chinese eunuchs: the structure of an intimate politics**. Rutland: Charles E. Tuttle Company.
Mitchell, Richard E. 1993. âDemands for Land Redistribution and Debt Reduction in the Roman Republic.â In **Social Justice in the Ancient World** (K. D. Irani and Morris Silver, editors), pp. 199-214. Westport: Greenwood Press.
Morgan, Lewis Henry. 1851. **League of the Ho-de-no-sau-nee, or Iroquois**. Secaucus: Citadel Press.
_____. 1877. **Ancient Society**. New York: Henry Holt.
_____. 1881. **Houses and House-Life of the American Aborigines**. [1965 edition] Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Moser, Thomas. 2000. âThe Idea of Usury in Patristic Literature.â In **The canon in the history of economics: critical essays** (edited by MichalÄs Psalidopoulos), pp. 24-44. London: Routledge.
Moses, Larry W. 1976. âTâang tribute relations with the Inner Asian barbarian.â In **Essays on Tâang society: the interplay of social, political and economic forces** (Perry, John C. and Bardwell L. Smith, editors), pp. 61-89. Leiden: Brill.
Moulier-Boutang, Yann. 1997. **De lâesclavage au salariat: Ă©conomie historique du salariat bridĂ©**. Paris : Presses universitaires de France.
Muhlenberger, Steven, and Phil Paine. 1997. âDemocracy in Ancient India.â World History of Democracy site, [[[http://www.nipissingu.ca/department/history/histdem][http://www.nipissingu.ca/department/history/histdem]]].
Muldrew, Craig. 1993a. âInterpreting the Market: The Ethics of Credit and Community Relations in Early Modern England.â **Social History** 18 (2): 163-183.
_____. 1993b. âCredit and the Courts: Debt Litigation in a Seventeenth-Century Urban Community.â **The Economic History Review**, New Series, 46 (1): 23-38.
_____. 1996. âThe Culture of Reconciliation: Community and the Settlement of Economic Disputes in Early Modern England.â **The Historical Journal** 39 (4): 915-942.
_____. 1998. **The Economy of Obligation: The Culture of Credit and Social Relations in Early Modern England**. New York: Palgrave.
_____. 2001. â âHard Food for Midasâ: Cash and its Social Value in Early Modern England.â **Past and Present** 170: 78-120.
Mundill, Robin R. 2002. **Englandâs Jewish Solution: Experiment and Expulsion**, 1262-1290. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Munn, Nancy. 1986. **The Fame of Gawa: A Symbolic Study of Value Transformation in a Massim (Papua New Guinea) Society**. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Munro, John H. 2003a. âThe Monetary Origins of the âPrice Revolutionâ: South German Silver Mining, Merchant Banking, and Venetian Commerce, 1470-1540.â In **Global Connections and Monetary History**, 1470-1800 (D. Flynn, A. GirĂĄldez, and R. Von Glahn editors), pp. 1-34. Burlington: Ashgate.
_____. 2003b. âThe Medieval Origins of the Financial Revolution: Usury, Rents, and Negotiability.â **International History Review** 25 (3): 505-562.
_____. 2007. âReview of Earl J. Hamilton, **American Treasure and the Price Revolution in Spain**, 1501-1650.â EH.Net Economic History Services, Jan 15 2007. URL: [[http://eh.net/bookreviews/library/munro][http://eh.net/bookreviews/library/munro]]
MĂŒri, Walter. 1931. **Symbolon: Wort- und sachgeschichtliche Studie**. Bern: Beilage zum Jahresbericht ĂŒber das stĂ€dtische Gymnasium Bern.
Murphy, George. 1961. â[Buddhist Monastic Economy: The Jisa Mechanism]: Comment.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 3 (4): 439-42.
Myers, Milton L. 1983. **The Soul of Modern Economic Man: Ideas of Self-Interest, Thomas Hobbes to Adam Smith**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Nag, Kalidas and V. R. Ramachandra Dikshitar. 1927. âThe Diplomatic Theories of Ancient India and the **Arthashastra.â Journal of Indian History** 6 (1): 15-35.
Nakamura, KyĆko Motomochi. 1996. **Miraculous stories from the Japanese Buddhist tradition: the Nihon ry**Ć**iki of the monk Ky**Ć**kai**. London: Routledge.
Naskar, Satyendra Nath. 1996. **Foreign impact on Indian life and culture (c**. 326 **B.C. to c**. 300 **A.D.)** New Delhi: Abhinav Publications.
Naylor, Robin Thomas. 1985. **Dominion of debt: centre, periphery and the international economic order**. London: Black Rose Books.
Nazpary, Jomo. 2001. **Post-Soviet Chaos: Violence and Dispossession in Kazakhstan**. London: Pluto.
Nelson, Benjamin. 1949. **The Idea of Usury: From Tribal Brotherhood to Universal Otherhood**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nerlich, Michael. 1987. **Ideology of adventure: studies in modern consciousness**, 1100-1750. (translation by Ruth Crowley). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Nicholls, David. 2003. **God and Government in an âAge of Reason.â** New York: Routledge.
Noah, Monday Efiong. 1990. âSocial and Political Developments: The Lower Cross Region, 1600-1900.â In **A History of the Cross River Region of Nigeria**. (Abasiattai, Monday B., editor), pp. 90-108. Calabar: University of Calabar Press.
Nolan, Patrick. 1926. **A Monetary History of Ireland**. London: King.
Noonan, John T. 1957. **The Scholastic Analysis of Usury**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Norman, K. R. 1975. âAĆoka and Capital Punishment: Notes on a Portion of AĆokaâs Fourth Pillar Edict, with an Appendix on the Accusative Absolute Construction.â **The Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland** 1: 16-24.
North, Robert. 1954. **Sociology of the Biblical Jubilee**. Rome: Pontifical Biblical Institute.
Northrup, David. 1978. **Trade Without Rulers: Pre-Colonial Economic Development in South-Eastern Nigeria**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
_____. 1995. **Indentured labor in the age of imperialism**, 1834-1922. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nwaka, Geoffrey I. 1978. âSecret Societies and Colonial Change: A Nigerian Example (SociĂ©tĂ©s secrĂštes et politique coloniale: un exemple nigerian).â Cahiers dâĂtudes Africaines, Vol. 18(69/70): 187-200.
Nwauwa, Apollos Okwuchi. 1991. âIntegrating Arochukwu into the Regional Chronological Structure.â **History in Africa** 18: 297-310.
OâBrien, George. 1920. **An Essay on Medieval Economic Teaching**. London: Longmans, Green & Co.
Ohnuma, Reiko. 2007. **Head, eyes, flesh, and blood: giving away the body in Indian Buddhist literature**. New York: Columbia University Press.
Olivelle, Patrick. 1992. **The Asrama System: The History and Hermeneutics of a Religious Institution**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
_____. 2005. **Manuâs Code of Law: A Critical Edition and Translation of the MÄnava-Dharma**Ć**Ästra**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
_____. 2006. âExplorations in the Early History of DharmaĆÄstra.â In **Between the Empires: Society in India** 300 **BC to** 400 **CE** (Patrick Olivelle, editor), pp. 169-190. New York: Oxford University Press.
_____. 2009. âDharmaĆÄstra: A Literary History.â In **The Cambridge Handbook of Law and Hinduism** (T. Lubin and D. Davis, editors), pp. 112-143. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Oliver, Douglas. 1955. **A Solomon Island Society**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Onvlee, Louis. 1980. âThe Significance of Livestock on Sumba.â In **The Flow of Life: Essays on Eastern Indonesia** (James J. Fox, editor), pp. 195-207. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Oppenheim, Leo. 1964. **Ancient Mesopotamia: Portrait of a Dead Civilization**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
OrlĂ©an, AndrĂ©. 1998. âLa monnaie autorĂ©fĂ©rentielle.â In: M. Aglietta & A. OrlĂ©an (editors), **La monnaie souveraine**, pp. 359â386. Paris: Odile Jacob.
Orlove, Benjamin. 1986. âBarter and Cash Sale on Lake Titicaca: A Test of Competing Approaches.â **Current Anthropology** 27 (2): 85-106.
Orr, Leslie C. 2000. **Donors, Devotees, and Daughters of God: Temple Women in Medieval Tamilnadu**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ottenberg, Simon. 1958. âIbo Oracles and Intergroup Relations.â **Southwestern Journal of Anthropology** 14 (3): 295-317.
Ottenberg, Simon and Phoebe Ottenberg. 1962. âAfikpo Markets: 1900-1960.â In **Markets in Africa** (Paul Bohannan and George Dalton, editors), pp. 118-169. Chicago: Northwestern University Press.
Ottenberg, Simon and Linda Knudsen. 1985. âLeopard Society Masquerades: Symbolism and Diffusion.â **African Arts** 18 (2): 37-44.
Oxfeld, Ellen. 2004. â âWhen You Drink Water, Think of its Sourceâ: Morality, Status, and Reinvention in Chinese Funerals.â **Journal of Asian Studies** 63 (4): 961-990.
Ozment, Steven. 1983. **When Fathers Ruled**. Harvard University Press, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pagden, Anthony. 1986. **The Fall of Natural Man: the American Indian and the origins of comparative ethnology**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Palat, Ravi Arvind. 1986. âPopular Revolts and the State in Medieval South India: A Study of the Vijayanagara Empire (1360-1565),â **Bijdragen tot de taal-, Land-, en Volkenkunde**, CXII, pp. 128-44.
_____. 1988. **From World-Empire to World-Economy: Southeastern India and the Emergence of the Indian Ocean World-Economy** (1350-1650). Ph. D. Dissertation, State University of New York at Binghamton.
Parker, Arthur. 1926. **An Analytical History of the Seneca Indians**. Researches and Transactions of the New York State Archaeological Association. Rochester, NY.
Parker, David B. 1994. âThe Rise and Fall of The Wonderful Wizard of Oz as a âParable on Populism.â â **Journal of the Georgia Association of Historians** 15: 49-63.
Parkes, Henry Bamford. 1959. **Gods and Men: The Origins of Western Culture**. New York: Vintage Books.
Parkin, Michael and David King. 1995. **Economics (Second Edition)**. London: Addison-Wesley Publishers.
Parks, Time. 2005. **Medici Money: Banking, Metaphysics, and Art in Fifteenth-Century Florence**. New York: Norton.
Partridge, Charles. 1905. **Cross River Natives: Being Some Notes on the Primitive Pagans of Obubura Hill District, Southern Nigeria**. London: Hutchinson & Co.
Pasadika, Bhikkhu. 1997. âThe concept of avipranÄĆa in NÄgÄrjuna.â In **Recent Researches in Buddhist Studies: Essays in Honour of Y. Karunadasa**, pp. 516-523. Kuala Lumpur: Y. Karunadasa Felicitation Committee. & Chi Ying Foundation.
Pateman, Carole. 1988. **The Sexual Contract**. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Patterson, Orlando. 1982. **Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Pearson, Michael N. 1982. âPremodern Muslim Political Systems.â **Journal of the American Oriental Societ**y vol. 102 (no. 1):47-58.
Peng, Xinwei. 1994. **A monetary history of China (Zhongguo Huobi Shi)**. Two Volumes. (Edward H. Kaplan, translator). Bellingham: Western Washington University.
Perlman, Mark and Charles Robert McCann. 1998. **The pillars of economic understanding: ideas and traditions**. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Peters, E. L. 1967. âSome Structural Aspects of the Feud Among the Camel-Herding Bedouins of Cyrenaica.â **Africa** 37: 261-282.
Phillips, William D. 1985. **Slavery From Roman Times to the Early Transatlantic Trade**. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Picard, Olivier. 1975. âLa âfiduciaritĂ©â des monnaies mĂ©talliques en GrĂšce.â **Bulletin de la SociĂ©tĂ© Française de Numismatique** 34 (10: 604-609.
Pietz, William. 1985. . âThe Problem of the Fetish I.â **RES: Journal of Anthropology and Aesthetics** 9:5-17.
Pigou, Arthur Cecil. 1949. **The Veil of Money**. London: Macmillan.
Polanyi, Karl. 1949. The Great Transformation. New York: Rinehart.
_____. 1957a. âAristotle Discovers the Economy.â In K. Polanyi, C. Arensberg and H. Pearson (eds.), **Trade and Market in the Early Empires**, pp. 64-94. Glencoe: The Free Press.
_____. 1957b. âThe economy as an instituted process.â In K. Polanyi, C. Arensberg and H. Pearson (eds.), **Trade and Market in the Early Empires**, pp. 243-269 Glencoe: The Free Press.
_____. 1968. âThe Semantics of Money Uses.â In **Primitive, Archaic, and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi**. (George Dalton, ed.) New York: Anchor.
Poliakov, LĂ©on. 1977. **Jewish bankers and the Holy See from the thirteenth to the seventeenth century**. London: Routledge.
Pomeranz, Kenneth. 1998. **The Great Divergence: China, Europe, and the Making of the Modern World Economy**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Powell, Marvin A. 1978. âA Contribution to the History of Money in Mesopotamia prior to the Invention of Coinage.â In **Festschrift Lubor Matous** (B. Hruska and G. Comoroczy, eds.) Budapest) II, pp. 211-43.
_____. 1979. âAncient Mesopotamian Weight Metrology: Methods, Problems and Perspectives.â In **Studies in Honor of Tom B. Jones** (M. A. Powell and R. H. Sack, editors), pp. 71-109. Amsterdam: Kevelaer/Neukirchen-Vluyn.
_____. 1999. âWir **mussen unsere nisch Nutzen:** Monies, Motives and Methods in Babylonian economics.â In **Trade and Finance in Ancient Mesopotamia, Proceedings of the First Mos Symposium (Ledien** 1997), (J. G. Derksen, editior), pp. 5-24. Istanbul: Nederlands Historich-Archeologisch Instiuut.
Prakash, Gyan. 2003. **Bonded Histories: Genealogies of Labor Servitude in Colonial India**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Prakash, Satya and Rajendra Singh,. 1968. **Coinage in Ancient India** New Delhi: Research Institute of Ancient Scientific Studies.
Price, Jacob M. 1980. **Capital and Credit in British Overseas Trade: the View from the Chesapeake**, 1700-1776. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
_____. 1989. âWhat Did Merchants Do? Reflections on British Overseas Trade, 1660-1790.â **The Journal of Economic History** 49 (2): 267-284.
_____. 1991. âCredit in the Slave Trade and Plantation Economies.â In Barbara L. Solow, editor, **Slavery and the Rise of the Atlantic System**, pp. 313-17. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Price, Martin Jessop,. 1983. âThoughts on the beginnings of coinage.â In **Studies in Numismatic Method Presented to Philip Grierson** (C.N.L. Brooke et al., editors,), pp. 1-10. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph. 1840. **Quâest-ce que la propriĂ©tĂ©? Recherche sur le principe du droit et du gouvernement. Premier mĂ©moire**. Paris : J.-F. Brocard.
Puett, Michael J. 2002. **To Become a God: Cosmology, Sacrifice, and Self-Divinization in Early China**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Quiggin, A. Hingston. 1949. **A Survey of primitive money; the beginning of currency** London: Methuen.
Quilter, Jeffrey and Gary Urton. 2002. **Narrative threads: accounting and recounting in Andean Khipu**. Austin: University of Texas.
Radford, R. A. 1945. âThe Economic Organization of a POW Camp.â **Economica** 12 (48): 189-201
Raglan, FitzRoy Richard Somerset, Baron. 1931. âBride Price.â **Man** 31: 75.
Rahman, Fashur. 1964. âRiba and Interest.â **Islamic Studies** 3:1-43.
Rai, G. K. 1981. **Involuntary Labour in Ancient India**. Allahabad: Chaitanya Press.
Ray, Nicholas Dylan. 1997. âThe Medieval Islamic System of Credit and Banking: Legal and Historical Considerations.â **Arab Law Quarterly** 12 (1): 43-90.
Reden, Sitta von. 1997. âMoney, Law and Exchange: Coinage in the Greek Polis.â **Journal of Hellenic Studies** 117: 154-176.
_____. 2003. **Exchange in Ancient Greece**. London: Duckworth.
Reeves, Eileen. 1999. âAs Good as Gold: The Mobile Earth and Early Modern Economics.â **Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes** 62: 126-166.
Reid, Anthony. 1983. **Slavery, Bondage and Dependence in Southeast Asia**. New York: St. Martinâs Press.
Renger, Johannes. 1983. âPatterns of Non-Institutional Trade and Non-Commercial. Exchange in Ancient Mesopotamia at the Beginning of the Second Millennium B.C.â In **Circulation of Goods in Non-palatial Contexts in the Ancient Near East** (A. Archi, editor), pp. 31-123. Rome: Edizioni dellâAteneo
_____. 1994. âOn Economic Structures in Ancient Mesopotamia.â **Orientalia** 18:157-208.
Retours, Robert de. 1952. âLes insignes en deux parties (fou) sous la dynastie des Tâang (618-907).â **Tâoung Pao** 41 (1/3): 1-148.
Rhys Davids, Caroline A. F. 1901. âEconomic Conditions in Ancient India.â **The Economic Journal** 11 (43): 305-320
_____. 1922. âEconomic Conditions According to Early Buddhist Literature.â In **The Cambridge History of India Volume I: Ancient India** (E. J. Rapson, editor), pp. 198-219. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Richard, R. D. 1926. âEarly History of the Term Capital.â **Quarterly Journal of Economics** 40 (2): 329-38.
Richards, Audrey. 1939. **Land, Labour and Diet in Northern Rhodesia**. London: Oxford University Press.
Richter, Daniel K. 1983. âWar and Culture: the Iroquois Experience.â **William and Mary Quarterly**, 3d Series, 40:528-559.
Rickett, W. Allyn. 1998. **Guanzi: Political, Economic, and Philosophical Essays from Early China** (2 volumes). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Riepe, Dale Maurice. 1961. **The Naturalistic Tradition in Indian Thought**. Seattle: University of Washington Press
Risso, Patricia. 1995. **Merchants and Faith: Muslim Commerce and Culture in the Indian Ocean**. Boulder: Westview Press.
Robertson, Pat. 1992. **The Secret Kingdom**. Dallas and London: Word Publishing.
Robinson, Rachel Sargent. 1973. **The size of the slave population at Athens during the fifth and fourth centuries before Christ**. Westport: Greenwood Press.
Robisheaux, Thomas. 1989. **Rural society and the search for order in early modern Germany**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rockoff, Hugh. 1990. âThe âWizard of Ozâ as a Monetary Allegory.â **Journal of Political Economy** 98 (4): 739-760.
Rodinson, Maxine. 1978. **Islam and Capitalism**. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Roetz, Heiner. 1993. **Confucian ethics of the axial age: a reconstruction under the aspect of the breakthrough toward postconventional thinking**. Albany: SUNY.
Rohrlich, Ruby. 1980. âState Formation in Sumer and the Subjugation of Women.â **Feminist Studies** 6 (1): 76-102.
Roitman, Janet. 2003. âUnsanctioned Wealth; or, the Productivity of Debt in Northern Cameroon.â **Public Culture** 15 (2): 211-237.
Roover, Raymond de. 1944. âWhat is Dry Exchange? A Contribution to the Study of English Mercantilism.â **Journal of Political Economy** 52: 250-66
_____. 1946. âThe Medici Bank.â **Journal of Economic History** 6: 24-52, 153-72.
_____. 1948. **Money, Banking, and Credit in MediĂŠval Bruges**. Cambridge: Mediaeval Academy of America.
_____. 1963. **The Rise and Decline of the Medici Bank:** 1397-1494. New York: W.W. Norton.
_____. 1967. âThe Scholastics, Usury and Foreign Exchange.â **Business History Review** 41 (3): 257-71.
RospabĂ©, Philippe. 1993. âDon ArchaĂŻque et Monnaie Sauvage.â In **MAUSS: Ce Que Donner Vuet Dire: Don et IntĂ©ret**. Paris: Ăditions la dĂ©couverte, pp. 33-59.
_____. 1995. **La Dette de Vie: aux origines de la monnaie sauvage**. Paris: Editions la DĂ©couverte/MAUSS.
Rotours, Robert de. 1952. âLes insignes en deux parties (fou) sous la dynastie des Tâang (618-907).â **Tâoung Pao** 41: 1-148.
Ruel, Malcolm. 1969. **Leopards and Leaders**. London: Tavistock
Rule, John. 1986. **The Labouring Classes in Early Industrial England**, 1750-1850. London: Longman.
Saggs, Henry William Frederick. 1962. **The Greatness That Was Babylon**. New York: Mentor Books.
Sahlins, Marshall. 1972. **Stone Age Economics**. Chicago: Aldine.
_____. 1981. âThe stranger-king or DumĂ©zil among the Fijians.â **Journal of Pacific History** 16: 107-32.
_____. 1988. âCosmologies of Capitalism.â **Proceedings of the British Academy** 74:1-51.
_____. 1996. âThe Sadness of Sweetness: The Native Anthropology of Western Cosmology.â **Current Anthropology**, Vol. 37 (3): 395-428.
_____. 2004. **Apologies to Thucydides: Understanding History as Culture and Vice Versa**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
_____. 2008. **The Western Illusion of Human Nature**. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press.
Saller, Richard P. 1984. â âFamilia, Domusâ, and the Roman Conception of the Family.â **Phoenix** 38 (4): 336-355.
_____. 1987. âSlavery and the Roman family.â In **Classical Slavery** (Moses Finley, editor), pp. 82-110. London: Frank Cass.
Samuel, Geoffrey. 2003. âProperty, Obligations: Continental and Comparative Perspectives.â In **New Perspectives on Property Law, Human Rights, and the Home** (Alastair Hudson, editor), pp. 295-318. London: Cavendish Publications.
Samuelson, Paul A. 1948. **Economics**. New York: McGraw Hill.
_____. 1958. âAn exact consumption-loan model of interest with or without the social contrivance of money.â In **The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson**, volume 1 (J. Stiglitz, editor), pp. 219-33. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Sarthou-Lajous, Nathalie. 1997. **Lâethique de la dette**. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
Sasso, Michael. 1978. âWhat is the Ho-Tu?â **History of Religions** 17 (314): 399-416.
Scammel, Jeffrey Vaughan. 1981. **The world encompassed: the first European maritime empires c**.800-1650. London: Taylor & Frances.
Schaps, David. 2004. **The Invention of Coinage and the Monetization of Ancient Greece**. Ann Arbor : University of Michigan Press.
_____. 2006. âThe Invention of Coinage in Lydia, in India, and in China.â Helsinki: XIV International Economic History Congress.
Scheidel, Walter. 2006. âThe Divergent Evolution of Coinage in Eastern and Western Eurasia.â Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics (April 2006): [[http://www.princeton.edu/~pswpc/pdfs/scheidel/040603.pdf][www.princeton.edu/~pswpc/pdfs/scheidel/040603.pdf]] _____. 2007. âThe Monetary Systems of the Han and Roman Empires.â (available at [[http://www.princeton.edu/~pswpc/pdfs/scheidel/110505.pdf][http://www.princeton.edu/~pswpc/pdfs/scheidel/110505.pdf]]).
_____. 2009. **Rome and China: Comparative Perspectives on Ancient World Empires**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schlemmer, Bernard. 1983. **Le Menabe: histoire dâune colonization**. Paris: ORSTOM.
Schneider, Jane. 1971. âOf Vigilance and Virgins: Honor, Shame, and Access to Resources in Mediterranean Societies.â **Ethnology** 10:1-24.
Schoenberger, Erica. 2008. âThe Origins of the Market Economy: State Power, Territorial Control, and Modes of War Fighting.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 50 (3): 663-691.
Schofield, Phillipp R. and N. J. Mayhew, editors. 2002. **Credit and debt in medieval England, c**.1180**-c**.1350. London: Oxbow.
Schopen, Gregory. 1994. âDoing Business for the Lord: Lending on Interest and Written Loan Contracts in the MĆ«elasarvÄstivÄda-vinaya.â **Journal of the American Oriental Society** 114 (4): 527-554.
_____. 1995. âMonastic Law Meets the Real World: A Monkâs Continuing Right to Inherit Family Property in Classical India.â **History of Religions** 35 (2): 101-123.
_____. 1997. **Bones, stones, and Buddhist monks: collected papers on the archaeology, epigraphy, and texts of monastic Buddhism in India**. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
_____. 2004. **Buddhist monks and business matters: still more papers on monastic Buddhism in India**. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Schumpeter, Joseph. 1934. **History of Economic Analysis**. New York: Oxford University Press.
Schwartz, Benjamin I. 1975. âThe Age of Transcendence.â **Daedalus** 104:1-7.
_____. 1986. **The World of Thought in Ancient China**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Scott, Tom, and Bob Scribner, editors. 1991. **The German Peasantsâ War: A History in Documents**. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.
Sea, Thomas F. 2007. âThe German Princesâ Responses to the Peasantsâ Revolt of 1525.â **Central European History** 40 (2): 219-240.
Seaford, Richard. 1994. **Reciprocity and Ritual. Homer and Tragedy in the Developing City-State**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
_____. 1998. âTragic Money.â **Journal of Hellenic Studies** 110: 76-90.
_____. 2002. âReview: Reading Money: Leslie Kurke on the Politics of Meaning in Archaic Greece.â **Arion**, Third Series 9 (3):145-165.
_____. 2004. **Money and the Early Greek Mind: Homer, Philosophy, Tragedy**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
SĂ©e, Henri EugĂšne. 1928. **Modern capitalism: its origin and evolution**. New York: Adelphi.
Seebohm, Frederic. 1877. **The Era of the Protestant Revolution**. London: Longmans, Green.
Seidel, Anna. 1983. âImperial Treasures and Taoist Sacraments: Taoist Roots in Apocrypha.â In **Tantric and Taoist Studies in Honor of Rolf A. Stein** (Michel Strickmann, editor), II, pp. 291-371. Bruxelles: Institute Belge des Hautes Ătudes Chinoises.
Servet, Jean-Michel. 1981. âPrimitive Order and Archaic Trade. Part Iâ **Economy and Society** 10 (4): 423-450.
_____. 1982. âPrimitive Order and Archaic Trade. Part II.â **Economy and Society 11** (1): 22-59.
_____. 1994. âLa fable du troc,â numero spĂ©cial de la revue **XVIIIe siĂšcle, Economie et politique** (sous la direction Gerard Klotz, Catherine Larrere et Pierre Retat), n°26: 103-115
_____. 1998. âDemonĂ©tarisation et remonĂ©tarisation en Afrique-Occidentale et Ăquatoriale (XIXe-XXe siĂšcles).â In **La Monnaie souveraine** (Aglietta and Orleans, editors), pp. 289-324. Paris: Odile Jacob.
_____. 2001. âLe troc primitif, un mythe fondateur dâune approche Ă©conomiste de la monnaie.â **Revue numismatique** 2001: 15-32.
Sharma, J. P. 1968. **Republics in Ancient India: c** 1500 â **c**. 500 BC. Leiden: E. J. Brill
Sharma, Ram Sharan. 1958. **Sudras in Ancient India**. Delhi: Mohtial Banarsidas.
_____. 1965. âUsury in Medieval India (A.D. 400-1200).â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 8 (1): 56-77.
_____. 1987. **Urban Decay in India c**. 300- **c**.1000. Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal.
_____. 2001. **Early medieval Indian society: a study in feudalisation**. Hyderbad: Orient Longman.
Shell, Marc. 1978. **The Economy of Literature**. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
_____. 1992. **Money, Language, and Thought**. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Sheridan, R. B. 1958. âThe Commercial and Financial Organization of the British Slave Trade, 1750-1807.â **The Economic History Review**, New Series 11 (2): 249-263.
Silver, Morris. 1985. **Economic structures of the ancient Near East**. London: Taylor & Francis.
Singer, Sholom A. 1964. âThe Expulsion of the Jews from England in 1290.â **The Jewish Quarterly Review**, New Series, 55 (2): 117-136.
Skinner, Quentin. 1998. **Liberty before Liberalism**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Smith, Adam. 1761. **Theory of moral sentiments**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (2002 edition).
_____. 1762. **Lectures on Jurisprudence**. Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith Vol. 5. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund (1982 edition).
_____. 1776. **An Inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations**. Oxford: Clarendon Press (1976 edition).
Smith, Edwin, and Andrew Murray Dale. 1968. **The Ila Speaking Peoples Of Northern Rhodesia**. Two Volumes. London: Kessinger.
Smith, Timothy. 1983. âWampum as Primitive Valuables.â **Research in Economic Anthropology** 5: 225-246.
Snell, F. J. 1919. **The Customs of Old Englan**d. London: Methuen.
Solow, Barbara. 1987. âCapitalism and Slavery in the Exceedingly Long Run.â **Journal of Interdisciplinary History** 17 (4): 711-737.
Sonenscher, Michael. 2007. **Before the Deluge: Public Debt, Inequality, and the Intellectual Origins of the French Revolution**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Spufford, Peter. 1988. **Money and Its Use in Medieval Europe**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Spyer, Patricia. 1997. âThe Eroticism of Debt: Pearl Divers, Traders, and Sea Wives in the Aru Islands of Eastern Indonesia.â **American Ethnologist** 24 (3): 515-538.
Ste. Croix, Geoffrey Ernest Maurice De. 1981. **The Class Struggle in the Ancient Greek World: from the Archaic Age to the Arab Conquests**. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Stannard, David E. 1993. **American holocaust: the conquest of the New World**. New York: Oxford University Press.
Starr, Chester G. 1977. **The Economic and Social Growth of Early Greece**. 800-500 **BC**. New York: Oxford University Press.
Stein, Siegfried. 1953. âLaws of Interest in the Old Testament.â **Journal of Theological Studies** 4: 161-70.
_____. 1955. âThe Development of the Jewish Law of Interest from the Biblical Period to the Expulsion of the Jews from England.â **Historia Judaica** 17:3-40.
Stein, Stanley J., and Barbara H. Stein. 2000. **Silver, trade, and war: Spain and America in the making of early modern Europe**. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
Steinkeller, Piotr. 1980. âThe Renting of Fields in early Mesopotamia and the Development of the Concept of âInterestâ in Sumerian.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 24: 113-145.
_____. 2003. âMoney-Lending Practices in Ur III Babylonia: the question of economic motivation.â In **Debt and Economic Renewal in the Ancient Near East** (Hudson, Michael and Marc Van de Mieroop, editors), pp. 109-137. Bethesda: CDL.
Stiglitz, Joseph, and John Driffill. 2000. **Economics**. New York: W. W. Norton.
Stol, Marten. 1995. âWomen in Mesopotamia.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 38 (2): 123-144.
Stone, Lawrence. 1968. **The Family, Sex and Marriage in England** 1500-1800. London: Unwin.
_____. 1990. **Road to Divorce: England** 1530-1987. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stone, Willard E. 2005. âThe Tally: An Ancient Accounting Instrument.â **Abacus** 11 (1): 49-57.
Stout, William. 1742 \[1967\]. **The Autobiography of William Stout of Lancaster** 1665-1752. (John Duncan Marshall, editor.) Manchester: Manchester University Press
Strickmann, Michel. 2002. **Chinese magical medicine**. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Subrahmanyam, Sanjay. 1996. âOf Imarat and Tijarat: Asian Merchants and State Power in the Western Indian Ocean, 1400 to 1750.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** Vol. 37 no 4, pp. 750-780.
Sun, Guang-Zhen. 2008. âFragment: Nasir ad-Din Tusi on social cooperation and the division of labor: Fragment from The Nasirean Ethics.â **Journal of Institutional Economics** 4 (3): 403-413.
Sutton, David. 2004. âAnthropologyâs value(s).â **Anthropological Theory** 4(3): 373-379.
Swann, Nancy Lee. 1950. **Food and Money in Ancient China: The earliest economic history of China to A. D**. 25. **Han Shu** 24 **with related texts. Han Shu** 91 **and Shih-chi** 129. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Tag El-Din, Saif I. 2007. âCapital and Money Markets of Muslims: The Emerging Experience in Theory and Practice.â Kyoto Bulletin of Islamic Area Studies, 1-2: 54-71.
Tambiah, Stanley J. 1973. âDowry and Bridewealth and the Property Rights of Women in South Asia.â In **Bridewealth and Dowry** (Jack Goody and S. J. Tambiah, editors), pp. 59-169. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
_____. 1989. âBridewealth and Dowry Revisited: The Position of Women in Sub-Saharan Africa and North India.â **Current Anthropology** 30 (4): 413-434.
Tambo, David C. 1976. âThe Sokoto Caliphate Slave Trade in the Nineteenth Century.â **International Journal of African Historical Studies** 9 (2): 187-217.
Taussig, Michael. 1984. âCulture of TerrorâSpace of Death. Roger Casementâs Putumayo Report and the Explanation of Torture.â **Comparative Studies in Society and History** 26 (3): 467-497.
_____. 1987. **Shamanism, Colonialism, and the Wild Man**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Taylor, Quentin P. 2005. âMoney and Politics in the Land of Oz.â **The Independent Review** 9 (3): 413-426.
Tebbutt, Melanie. 1983. **Making Ends Meet: Pawnbroking and Working-Class Credit**. New York: St. Martinâs Press.
Teiser, Stephen F. 1988. **The Ghost Festival in Medieval China**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Testart, Alain. 1997. âLe mise en gage de personnes: sociologie comparative dâune institution.â **Archives EuropĂ©enes de Sociologie** 38: 38-67.
_____. 1998. âPourquoi la condition de lâesclave sâameliore-t-elle en regime despotique?â **Revue française de sociologie** 39 (1): 3-38
_____. 2000. âLâEsclavage pour dettes en Asie Orientale.â **Moussons** 2: 3-29.
_____. 2001. **Esclave, la dette et le pouvoir: Ă©tudes de sociologie comparative**. Paris : Errance
_____. 2002. âThe extent and significance of debt slavery.â **Revue Française de Sociologie** 43: 173-204.
Testart, Alain, Valerie LĂ©crivain, Dimitri Karadimas and Nicolas Govoroff. 2001. âPrix de la fiancĂ©e et esclavage pour dettes: Un exemple de loi sociologique.â **Ătudes rurales** No. 159/160: 9-33.
Thapar, Romila. 1995. âThe First Millennium BC in Northern India.â In **Recent perspectives of early Indian history** (R. Thapar, editor) pp. 87-150. New Delhi: Book Review Trust.
_____. 2002. âThe Role of the Army in the Exercise of Power in Ancient India.â In **Army and power in the ancient world. Volume** 37 **of Heidelberger althistorische BeitrĂ€ge und epigraphische Studien** (Ăngelos ChaniĂłtis, Pierre Ducre, **editors), pp**. 25-39. **Heidelberg:** Franz Steiner Verlag.
Thesleff, Holgar. 1989. âPlatonic Chronology.â **Phronesis** 34 (1): 1-26.
ThĂ©ret, Bruno. 1992. **RĂ©gimes Ă©conomiques de lâordre politique : esquisse dâune thĂ©orie rĂ©gulationniste des limites de lâEtat**. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,.
_____. 1995. **LâĂtat, la finance et le social. SouverainetĂ© nationale et construction europĂ©enne** (direction de publication). Paris: Ăditions la DĂ©couverte.
_____. 1999. âThe Socio-Cultural Dimensions of the Currency: Implications for the Transition to the Euro.â **Journal of Consumer Policy** 22: 51-79.
_____. 2007. **La monnaie dĂ©voilĂ©e par ses crises** (direction de publication). Paris: Editions de lâEHESS, 2 volumes: volume 1, âMonnaies mĂ©talliques, volume 2 âMonnaies autorĂ©fĂ©rentielles. Les autres monnaies en Allemagne et en Russie au XXĂšme siĂšcle
_____. 2008. âLes trios Ă©tats de la monnaie: approche interdisciplinaire du fait monĂ©taire.â Revue Economique 59 (4): 813-842.
Thierry, François. 1992. **Monnaies de Chine.Paris:** BibliothÚque nationale.
_____. 2001. âSur les spĂ©cifitĂ©s fondamentales de la monnaie chinoise.â In **Aux origines de la monnaie** (Alain Testart, editor), pp. 109-44. Paris: Ăditions Errance.
Thomas, Keith. 1972. **Religion and the Decline of Magic: Studies in popular beliefs in sixteenth and seventeenth century England**. New York: Scribners.
Thompson, Edward Palmer. 1971. âThe Moral Economy of the English Crowd in the 18th Century.â **Past & Present** 50: 76-136.
Thurnwald, Richard C. 1916. âBanaro Society: Social Organization and Kinship System of a Tribe in the Interior of New Guinea.â **Memoirs of the American Anthropological Association** 8:251-391.
Tierney, Brian. 1997. **The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law and Church Law 11**50â1625. (Emory University Studies in Law and Religion, number 5). Atlanta: Scholars Press.
Todorov, Tzvetan. 1984. **The conquest of America: the question of the other**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Tong, James W. 1989. **Disorder Under Heaven: Collective Violence in the Ming Dynasty**. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Tortella, Gabriel and Francisco ComĂźn. 2002. âFiscal and Monetary Institutions in Spain, 1600-1900.â In Transferring wealth and power from the old to the new world: monetary and fiscal institutions in the 17th through the 19th century (Michael D. Bordo and Robert CortĂ©s Conde, editors), pp. 140-186. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trawick, Margaret. 1992. **Notes on Love in a Tamil Family**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Trevett, Jeremy. 1992. **Apollodoros he Son of Pasion**. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
_____. 2001. âCoinage and Democracy at Athens,â in A. Meadows and K. Shipton, eds., **Money and Its Uses in the Ancient Greek World** (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 23â34
Trombert, Eric. 1995. **Le crédit à Dunhuang: Vie matérielle et société en Chine médiévale**. Paris: Ihec/Inst.Hautes Etudes.
Tseayo, Justin Iyorbee. 1975. **Conflict and Incorporation in Nigera: the Integration of the Tiv**. Zaria Nigeria: Gaskiya.
Tuck, Richard. 1979. **Natural rights theories: their origin and development**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tull, Herman Wayne. 1989. **The Vedic Origins of Karma: cosmos as man in ancient Indian myth and ritual**. Albany: SUNY.
Tully, James. 1993. **An Approach to Political Philosophy: Locke in Contexts**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tuma, Elias. 1965. âEarly Arab Economic Policies, 1st/7thâ4th/10th Centuries.â **Islamic Studies** 4 (1): 1-23.
Uchendo, Victor. 1967. âSome Principles of Haggling in Peasant Markets.â **Economic Development and Cultural Change** 16 (1): 37-50.
Udovitch, Abraham L. 1970. **Partnership and Profit in Medieval Islam**. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
_____. 1975. âReflections on the Institutions of Credit and Banking in the Medieval Islamic Near East.â **Studia Islamica** 41: 5-21.
Uebach, Helga. 2008. âFrom Red Tally to Yellow Paper: the official introduction of paper in Tibetan administration in 744/745.â **Revue dâEtudes TibĂ©taines 1**4: 57-69.
Usher, Abbot Payson. 1914. âThe Origin of the Bill of Exchange.â **Journal of Political Economy** 22: 566-76.
_____. 1934. âThe Origins of Banking: The Primitive Bank of Deposit, 1200-1600.â **Economic History Review** 4 (4): 399-428.
_____. 1943. **The Early History of Deposit Banking in Mediterranean Europe**. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Valenze, Deborah M. 2006. **The social life of money in the English past**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Valeri, Valerio. 1994. âBuying Women but no Selling Them: Gift and Commodity Exchange in Huaulu Alliance.â **Man** (n.s.) 29:1-26.
_____. 2001. âFeasts.â In **Fragments from Forests and Libraries**, pp. 1-27. Durham: Carolina Academic Press.
Van Der Toorn, Karel. 1989. âFemale Prostitution in Payment of Vows in Ancient Israel.â **Journal of Biblical Literature** 108 (2): 193-205.
Vance, Eugene. 1973. âSigns of the City: Medieval Poetry as Detour.â **New Literary History** 4 (3): 557-574
_____. 1986. âChrĂ©tienâs Yvain and the Ideologies of Change and Exchange.â **Yale French Studies** 70: 42-62.
Vaneigem, Raoul. 1967. **TraitĂ© de savoir-vivre Ă lâusage des jeunes gĂ©nĂ©rations**. Paris, Gallimard.
Veenhof, Karl. 1997. â âModernâ Features in Old Assyrian Trade.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 40: 336-366.
Verellen, Franciscus. 2006. âThe Dynamic Design: Ritual and Contemplative Graphics in Daoist Scriptures.â In **Daoism in History: Essays in Honor of Liu Rsâun-yan** (Quanlen Liu, Benjamin Penny, editors), pp. 159-182. London: Routledge.
Verlinden, Charles. 1970. **The Beginnings of Modern Colonization: Eleven Essays with an Introduction**. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
VerSteeg, Russ. 2000. **Early Mesopotamian Law**. Durham: Carolina Academic Press.
_____. 2002. **Law in Ancient Egypt**. Durham: Carolina Academic Press.
Veyne, Paul-Marie. 1979. âMythe et rĂ©alitĂ© de lâautarcie Ă Rome.â **Revue des Ă©tudes anciennes** 81: 261-280.
Vice, Roy L. 1988. âLeadership and Structure of the Tauber Band during the Peasantsâ War in Franconia.â **Central European History** 24 (2): 175-195.
Vickers, Adrian. 1996. **Bali: a paradise created**. Singapore: Periplus Editions.
Vickers, Michael J. 1985. âEarly Greek Coinage, a Reassessment.â **Numismatic Chronicle** 145:1-44.
Vijaisri, Priyadarshini. 2004. **Recasting the Devadadi: Patterns of Sacred Prostitution in Colonial South India**. New Delhi: Kanishka.
Villey, Michel. 1946. âLâIdee du droit subjectif et les systemes juridiques romains.â Revue historique de droit, series 4: 201-227.
Vondeling, Jan. 1961. **Eranos** (with a summary in English). Amsterdam: Gron.
Wade, Geoffrey. 2004. âThe Zheng He Voyages: A Reassessment.â **Asia Research Institute Working Paper Series** No. 31, Oct 2004
Wake, Christopher. 1997. âThe Great Ocean-going Ships of Southern China in the Age of Chinese Maritime Voyaging to India, Twelfth to Fifteenth Centuries,â **International Journal of Maritime History** 9 (2): 51-81
Walker, Garthene. 1996. âExpanding the Boundaries of Female Honour in Early Modern England.â **Transactions of the Royal Historical Society**, Sixth Series, 8:235-245.
Walker, James Broom. 1875. âNotes on the Politics, Religion, and Commerce of Old Calabar.â **The Journal of the Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland** 6: 119-124.
Wallace, Robert B. 1987. âThe Origin of Electrum Coinage.â **American Journal of Archaeology** 91: 385-97.
Wallace-Hadrill, Andrew, editor. 1989. **Patronage in Ancient Society** (Leicester-Nottingham Studies in Ancient Society, Volume 1). London: Routledge.
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1974. **The Modern World System, volume** I. New York: Academic Press
_____. 1989. âThe French Revolution as a World-Historical Event.â **Social Research** 56 (1): 33-52.
_____. 1991. âBraudel on Capitalism, or Everything Upside Down.â **Journal of Modern History** 63 (2): 354-361.
_____. 2001. **The End of the World as We Know It: Social Science for the Twenty-First Century**. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Walsh, Michael J. 2007. âThe Economics of Salvation: Toward a Theory of Exchange in Chinese Buddhism.â **Journal of the American Academy of Religion** 75 (2): 353â382
Warburton, David. 2000. âBefore the IMF: The Economic Implications of Unintentional Structural Adjustment in Ancient Egypt.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 43 (2): 65-131.
_____. 2001. âState and economy in ancient Egypt.â In **World System History: the social science of long-term change** (Robert Denemark, Jonathan Friedman, Barry Gills, and George Modelski, editors), pp. 169-184. New York: Routledge.
Wartburg, Marie Louise von. 1995. âProduction de sucre de canne Ă Chypre.â In **Coloniser au Moyen Age** (Michel Balard and Alain Ducellier, editors), Paris: A. Colon, pp. 126-31.
Waswo, Richard. 1996. âShakespeare and the Formation of the Modern Economy.â **Surfaces** Vol. 6. 217 (v.1.0A), [[http://www.pum.umontreal.ca/revues/surfaces/vol6/waswo.html][http://www.pum.umontreal.ca/revues/surfaces/
<br>
vol6/waswo.html]].
_____. 2004. âCrises of Credit: Monetary and Erotic Economies in the Jacobean Theater.â In **Plotting early modern London: new essays on Jacobean City comedy** (Dieter Mehl, Angela Stock, Anne-Julia Zwierlein, editors), pp. 55-74. London: Ashgate Publishing.
Watson, Alan. 1987. **Roman Slave Law**. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Watson, James L. 1980. âTransactions in People: The Chinese Market in Slaves, Servants, and Heirs.â In **Asian and African Systems of Slavery** (James L. Watson, editor), pp. 223-250. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Weber, Max. 1924. **Gesammelte AufsÀtze zur Soziale- und Wirtschaftegeschichte**. Tubingen. English version: **The Agrarian Sociology of Ancient Civilizations**. (R. I. Frank, trans.) London: Verso.
_____. 1961. **General Economic History**. New York: Collier Books.
_____. 1978. **Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology**. (Ephrain Fischoff, trans.) Berkeley: University of California Press.
Wennerlind, Carl. 2003. âCredit-money as the Philosopherâs Stone: Alchemy and the Coinage Problem in Seventeenth-century England.â **History of Political Economy** 35:234-61.
Westbrook, Raymond. 1971. âJubilee Laws.â **Israel Law Review** 6: 209-26.
_____. 1984. âThe enforcement of morals in Mesopotamian law.â **Journal of the American Oriental Society** 104: 753-756.
_____. 1988. **Old Babylonian Marriage Law**. Archlv fĂŒr Orientforschung, Beiheft 23. Horn: F. Burger.
_____. 1990. âAdultery in Ancient Near Eastern Law.â **Revue biblique** 97: 542-580
_____. 1991. **Property and the Family in Biblical Law**. Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press.
_____. 1995. âSlave and Master in Ancient Near Eastern Law.â **Chicago-Kent Law Review** 70: 1631-76.
_____. 1999. âVitae Necisque Potestas.â **Historia: Zeitschrift fĂŒr Alte Geschichte** 48 (2): 203-223.
Westenholz, Joan Goodnick. 1989. âTamar, **Qedesa, Qadistu**, and Sacred Prostitution in Mesopotamia.â **Harvard Theological Review** 82: 245â265.
Westermann, William L. 1955. **The Slave Systems of Greek and Roman Antiquity**. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.
Whelan, T. S. 1979. **The Pawnshop in China**. Ann Arbor: Centre for Chinese Studies, University of Michigan Whitaker, C. W. A. 2002. **Aristotleâs De interpretatione: contradiction and dialectic**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
White, Jenny Barbara. 2004. **Money makes us relatives: womenâs labor in urban Turkey**. London: Routledge.
Whiting, John Roger Scott. 1971. **Trade Tokens: A Social and Economic History**. London: Newton Abbot.
Wiedemann, Thomas. 1981. **Greek and Roman Slavery**. New York: Routledge.
Wiener, Margaret J. 1995. **Visible and invisible realms: power, magic, and colonial conquest in Bali**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Wilbur, C. Martin. 1943. **Slavery in China during the Former Han Dynasty**. Anthropological Series, volume 34. Chicago: Chicago Field Museum of Natural History.
Wilcke, Claus. 1985. âFamiliengrĂŒndung im alten Babylonien.â In **Geschlechtsreife und Legitimation zur Zeugung** (E.W MĂŒller, ed.), pp. 213-317. Freiburg and MĂŒnchen: Alber.
Williams, Brett. 2004. **Debt for Sale: A Social History of the Credit Trap**. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Williams, Carl O. 1937. **Thraldom in Ancient Iceland: A Chapter in the History of Class Rule**. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Williams, Eric. 1944. **Capitalism and Slavery**. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
Williamson, George Charles. 1889. **Trade tokens issued in the seventeenth century in England, Wales, and Ireland, by corporations, merchants, tradesmen, etc. Illustrated by numerous plates and woodcuts, and containing notes of family, heraldic, and topographical interest respecting the various issuers of the tokens**. London: E. Stock.
Wilson, Monica Hunter. 1951. âWitch Beliefs and Social Structure.â **The American Journal of Sociology** 56 (4): 307-31
Wink, André. 2002. **Al-Hind: Early medieval India and the expansion of Islam**, 7**th**-11**th centuries**. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Wirszubski, Chaim. 1950. **Libertas as a Political Ideal at Rome During the Late Republic and Early Principate**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wolf, Robert L. 1954. âThe Mortgage and Redemption of an Emperorâs Son: Castile and the Latin Empire of Constantinople.â **Speculum** 29: 45-85.
Wong, Roy Bin. 1997. **China Transformed: Historical Change and the Limits of European Experience**. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
_____. 2002. âBetween Nation and World: Braudelian Regions in Asia.â **Review** 26 (1): 1-45.
Wood, Diana. 2002. **Medieval Economic Thought**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wordie, J. R. 1983. âThe Chronology of English Enclosure, 1500-1914.â Economic History Review, 2nd ser. 26:483-505.
Wray, L. Randall. 1990. **Money and Credit in Capitalist Economies**. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.
_____. 1998. **Understanding Modern Money: the key to full employment and price stability**. Edward Elgar: Cheltenham.
_____. 1999. âAn Irreverent Overview of the History of Money from the Beginning of the Beginning to the Present.â **Journal of Post Keynesian Economics**. 21 (4): 679-687
_____. 2000. **Credit and State Theories of Money**. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Wright, David P. 2009. **Inventing Godâs Law: How the Covenant Code of the Bible Used and Revised the Laws of Hammurabi**. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wrightson, Keith. 1980. âTwo concepts of order: justices, constables and jurymen in seventeenth-century England,â in **An Ungovernable People: The English and their Law in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries** (John Brewer and John Styles, editors), pp. 21-46. London: Hutchinson.
Wrightson, Keith, and David Levine. 1979 **Poverty and Piety in an English Village**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Xu, Zhuoyun, and Jack L. Dull. 1980. **Han agriculture: the formation of early Chinese agrarian economy**, 206 **B.C.-A.D**. 220. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Yang, Bin. 2002. âHorses, Silver, and Cowries: Yunnan in Global Perspective.â **Journal of World History**, vol. 15 no 3:281-322.
Yang, Lien-sheng. 1971. **Money and Credit in China: A Short History**. Harvard-Yenching Institute Monographs 12. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Yates, Robin D. S. 2002. âSlavery in Early China: A Socio-Cultural Approach.â **Journal of East Asian Archaeology** 3 (1/2): 283-331.
Yoffee, Norman. 1998. âThe Economics of Ritual at Late Babylonian Kish.â **Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient** 41 (3): 312-343.
YĂŒ, Ying-shih. 1967. **Trade and Expansion in Han China. A Study in the Structure in Sino-Barbarian Economic Relations**. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Yung-Ti, Li. 2006. âOn the Function of Cowries in Shang and Western Zhou China.â **Journal of East Asian Archaeology** 5: 1-26.
Zell, Michael. 1996. âCredit in the Pre-Industrial English Woollen Industry.â **The Economic History Review**, New Series, 49 (4): 667-691
Zmora, Hillay. 2006. âThe Princely State and the Noble Family: Conflict and Co-operation in the Margraviates Ansbach-Kulmbach in the Early Sixteenth Century.â **The Historical Journal** 49: 1-21.
ZĂŒrcher, Erik. 1958. **The Buddhist conquest of China: the spread and adaptation of Buddhism in early medieval China**. Volume 11 of Sinica Leidensia. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
</biblio>