đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș andrew-culp-dark-deleuze captured on 2024-08-18 at 18:59:29. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Dark Deleuze Date: 2016 Source: Retrieved on 3<sup>rd</sup> May 2021 from [[http://libgen.rs/book/index.php?md5=B6F1D4764C384BA57C646D165DCF1457][libgen.rs]] Authors: Andrew Culp Topics: Deleuze, Deleuzian Published: 2021-05-03 10:39:09Z
<biblio>
C1 **Cinema 1: The Movement-Image** (1986)
C2 **Cinema 2: The Time-Image** (1989)
D **Dialogues 2** (with Claire Parnet; 2007)
DI **Desert Islands** (2004)
DR **Difference and Repetition** (1994)
ECC **Essays Critical and Clinical** (1997)
F **Foucault** (1988)
FB **Francis Bacon** (2005)
H **Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Humeâs Theory of Human Nature** (1991)
L **The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque** (1993)
LS **Logic of Sense** (1990)
N **Negotiations** (1997)
NP **Nietzsche and Philosophy** (1983)
P **Proust and Signs** (2000)
PI **Pure Immanence** (2005)
S **Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza** (1990)
TR **Two Regimes of Madness** (2007)
</biblio>
<biblio>
AO **Anti-Oedipus** (1977)
K **Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature** (1986)
TP **A Thousand Plateaus** (1987)
WP **What Is Philosophy?** (1994)
</biblio>
SUMMARIZING HIS DEEPLY IDIOSYNCRATIC WORK, French philosopher Gilles Deleuze describes writing about others as âa sort of buggeryâ or âimmaculate conceptionâ that is the result of âtaking an author from behind and giving him a childâ (N, 6). Deleuze is still quick to distinguish his project from outright falsification. He strictly limits himself to what an author actually says; he attends to a thinkerâs âshifting, slipping, dislocations, and hidden emissionsâ to give him âa child that would be his own offspring, yet monstrousâ (N, 6). More than thirty years after making these remarks, Deleuze now has plenty of little monsters of his ownârootless rhi-zombies, dizzying metaphysicians, skittish geonaturalists, enchanted transcendentalists, passionate affectivists. My aim is to give him another child that shares his last name: âDark Deleuze.â
Deleuze once told a friend that a âworthwhile bookâ performs at least three functions: polemics, recovery, and creativity. In writing the book, the author must reveal that (1) other scholarship commits an error; (2) an essential insight has been missed; and (3) a new concept can be created. You will find all three is this book. First, I argue against the âcanon of joyâ that celebrates Deleuze as a naively affirmative thinker of connectivity. Second, I rehabilitate the destructive force of negativity by cultivating a âhatred for this world.â Third, I propose a conspiracy of contrary terms that diverge from the joyous task of creation.
Picking out a particular strain of thought: scholars of ânew materialismâ turn to realist ontology by way of Deleuzeâs metaphysics of positivity. The basis for the realist side of Deleuze is perhaps best evinced by his biography. Those who knew Deleuze consistently note his firm commitment to joyful affirmation and his distaste for the **ressentiment** of negativity. Beatifying this sentiment, Deleuze has been used to establishing a whole canon of joy. In the canon of joy, the cosmos is a complex collection of assemblages produced through the ongoing processes of differentiation. The effect of the Joyous Deleuzeâs image of thought is a sense of wonder, accompanied by the enjoyment of creating concepts that express how the world really exists.
A different Deleuze, a darker one, has slowly cast its shadow. Yet this figure only appears when we escape the chapel choir of joy for the dark seclusion of the crypt. Emerging from scholars concerned with the condition of the present, the darkness refashions a revolutionary Deleuze: revolutionary negativity in a world characterized by compulsory happiness, decentralized control, and overexposure. This refashioned Deleuze forms a countercanon out of the perfused negativity of his concepts and affects. On the level of concept, it recognizes that negativity impregnates Deleuzeâs many prefixes of difference, becoming, movement, and transformation, such as **de**-, **a**-, **in**-, and **non**-. On the level of affect, it draws on Deleuzeâs talk of indiscernibility, concealment, the shame of being human, and the monstrous power of the scream. The ultimate task of this approach is not the creation of concepts, and to the extent that it does, Dark Deleuze creates concepts only to write apocalyptic science fiction (DR, xxâxxii).
Michel Foucault half-jokingly suggested in 1970 that âperhaps one day, this century will be known as Deleuzianâ (âTheatrum Philosophicum,â 885). It is easy to see how boosters have used this phrase to raise the profile of Deleuze, who was far less popular than Foucault or Derrida during the initial reception of poststructuralism in America. But what if it is a subtle jab? Foucault makes the remark in the same breath as a reference to Pierre Klossowski, a crucial member of the secret society AcĂ©phale, which helped revive Nietzsche in France when others too easily dismissed the thinker as fascist. âHistorically fittingâ would be an insult to Nietzsche, who proudly proclaims the untimeliness of thought âacting counter to our time and thereby acting on our time and, let us hope, for the benefit of a time to comeâ at the beginning of his essay on the uses and abuses of history for life (**Untimely Meditations,** 60). As a major French interlocutor of Nietzsche, Deleuze uses this exact same phrase on untimeliness in the opening pages of **Difference and Repetition**âthe very book that Foucault was reviewing when he made the comment. Bearing out the implication by mincing another Nietzschean phrase, then perhaps Foucault was accusing him of being âtimely, all too timely.â
What would make Deleuzeâs thought especially timely? Critics such as Slavoj ĆœiĆŸek accuse him of being a poster child for the cultural excesses of postmodern capitalism (âOngoing âSoft Revolutionââ). A recent round of denunciations underwritten by a mix of wonderment and red-baiting exclaim, âThe founder of BuzzFeed wrote his senior thesis on the Marxism of Deleuze and Guattari!,â adding to a long list of guilty associationsââthe Israeli Defense Force reads **A Thousand Plateaus**!,â âDeleuze spouts the fashionable nonsense of pseudoscience!â Deleuzeâs defenders are correct to dismiss such criticisms as either incomplete or outright spurious. Yet there is a kernel of truth that goes back to an old jokeâa communist is someone who reads **Das Kapital**; a capitalist is someone who reads **Das Kapital** and understands it. Saying the same about Deleuze: there is something absolutely essential about his work, but it would not be best to take it at face value. The necessity of âtaking another stepâ beyond Deleuze avant la lettre is especially true when both capitalists and their opponents simultaneously cite him as a major influence. The exact rapport between Deleuzeâs thought and our time thus remains a puzzle for us to solve. Does the problem arise because certain readers act like doctors who participate in death penalty executions, who follow protocol to make a perfectly clinical diagnosis, only to help administer a set of drugs condemned by their field? Or is there something about his prescription that only exacerbates our current condition?
Ours is the age of angels, says French philosopher Michel Serres **(Angels, a Modern Myth)**. Armies of invisible messengers now crisscross the skies, tasked with communication, connection, transmission, and translation. As inspiring as they may seem, they also compel us to embody their messages in word and act. Click, poke, like. We feel the nervous prick of incoming missives that set us in a feverish state until we address the incoming text message, reply to the overdue e-mail, or respond to the pending friend request. These everyday behaviors show that the seemingly modern world of commodities has not stolen our sense of wonderâwe are as divinely moved by media as we once were by angels. Marx, who, in Artaudâs phrase, has âdone away with the judgment of God,â shows that this mystical character of the commodity is capitalism and also its most popular trick. Let us then follow Marxâs old mole in the search of history, moving from the heavens to the underground. Refusing to sing the hymns of the age, Deleuze and Guattari made a crucial declaration in 1991 as the Iron Curtain crumbled and the first commercial Internet service providers came online: âWe do not lack communication. On the contrary, we have too much of it.... **We lack resistance to the present**â (WP, 108).
<em>Dark Deleuze</em>âs immediate target is connectivity, the name given to the growing integration of people and things through digital technology. Acolyte of connection and Google chairman Eric Schmidt recently declared at the World Economic Forum that soon âthe internet will disappearâ as it becomes inseparable from our very being (âit will be part of your presence all the timeâ) <em>(Business Insider)</em>. This should raise suspicion. No one should ever take futurologists at their wordâtechnology progresses with the same combined and uneven gait as all other types development. Yet the numbers behind Schmidtâs claim are hardly a matter of dispute. Five billion new people are slated to join the Internet in the next decade, and the âInternet of thingsâ has motivated individual users to integrate a vast array of online-enabled devices into their everyday lives. Even if they do not fully realize his dreams, they still make up the substance of Googleâs government of things and the living.
Many traditional concerns have been raised about connectivity. Almost all use the conservative voice of moral caution. A band of âNet Criticsâ warn that technology is developing more quickly than our understanding of its effects. Popular media, the great screen of the collective unconscious, materialize fears about runaway technology. There is a whole string of Asian horror films that depict cursed media objects ruining our lives **(Ringu, Pulse, Phone, One Missed Call, White: The Melody of the Curse)**. The usual cottage industry of romanticizing life without technology now suggests that âcell phones make us lazy,â while circulating ideas on how to âget on a social media diet.â Some philosophers, such as Bernard Stiegler, even say that technology is stealing our precious insides. Behind these suggestions lurks a drive to get back to our roots.
The âmad scientistâ criticism of technology misses the mark. The trouble is not that myopic technicians have relentlessly pursued technical breakthroughs without considering the consequences (âforgive them, for they know not what they doâ; ĆœiĆŸek, **The Sublime Object of Ideology,** 28). The antidote for such ignorance would just be a small dose of ideology critique. Alternatively, technology has not exceeded humanityâs capacity to manage itâif anything, Foucaultâs insights (the analytic of finitude, biopower) suggest that humanity influences its own future more than ever before (DI, 90â93). The problem is, **they know perfectly well what they are doing, but they continue doing it anyway**!
Philosophically, connectivity is about world-building. The goal of connectivity is to make everyone and everything part of a single world. The cases made for such a world are virtuous enoughâKantian cosmopolitanism wants perpetual peace, Marxist universalism demands the unity of theory and practice, and Habermas would have us all be part of one great conversation. Yet connectivity today is determined far more by people like Google Ideas director Jared Cohen, who demonstrates the significance of Deleuzeâs argument that âtechnology is social before it is technicalâ (F, 17). Trained as a counterterrorism expert, Google poached Cohen from a position at the Department of State, where he convinced Condoleezza Rice to integrate social media into the Bush administrationâs âdiplomatic tool kitâ (Rice, **No Higher Honor,** 305). In a geopolitical manifesto cowritten with then Google CEO Eric Schmidt, **The New Digital Age,** Cohen reveals Googleâs deep aspiration to extend U.S. government interests at home and abroad. Their central tool? Connectivity.
When connectivity is taken as a mantra, you can see its effects everywhere. Jobseekers are told to hop on to the web (âWhile your resume can help you get the interview for a new job, a fully optimized LinkedIn profile can bring you more business, more connections, and can increase your professional reputation!â). Flat hierarchies are touted as good for business management (âPower is vertical; potential is horizontal!â). And the deluge of digital content is treated as the worldâs greatest resource, held back only by unequal access (âInformation wants to be free!â). As perverse as it sounds, many Deleuzians still promote concepts that equally motivate these slogans: transversal lines, rhizomatic connections, compositionist networks, complex assemblages, affective experiences, and enchanted objects. No wonder Deleuze has been derided as the lava lamp saint of âCalifornia Buddhismââso many have reduced his rigorous philosophy to the mutual appreciation of difference, openness to encounters in an entangled world, or increased capacity through synergy.
Instead of drawing out the romance, **Dark Deleuze** demands that we kill our idols. The first task is negative, as in Deleuze and Guattariâs schizoanalysis, a âcomplete currettageââ**overthrow their altars, and break their pillars, and burn their groves with fire; and ye shall hew down the graven images of their gods, and destroy the names of them out of that place** (AO, 311). Put more modestly, the first step is to acknowledge that the unbridled optimism for connection has failed. Temporary autonomous zones have become special economic zones. The material consequences of connectivism are clear: the terror of exposure, the diffusion of power, and the oversaturation of information. A tempting next move would be to criticize Deleuzian connectivists as falling behind the times, having not recognized their own moment of recuperation. Yet such an accusation would only prepare the ground for a more timely intervention. **Dark Deleuze** does not take up the mantle of prophetic guruism or punctual agitprop. As a project, it instead follows Deleuzeâs advice to create untimely âvacuoles of non-communicationâ that break circuits rather than extend them (D, 175). The point is not to get out of this place but to cannibalize itâwe may be **of** this world, but we are certainly not **for** it. Such out-of-jointedness is a distance. And distance is what begins the dark plunge into the many worlds eclipsed by the old.
âWe need reasons to believe in this world,â Deleuze demands (C2, 172). We are so distracted by the cynicism of ideological critique that we too easily dismiss the real world as an illusion. The problem is exaggerated even more now that we mistake knowledge for belief, a confusion fed by growing databases of readily available information. He asks us to relink with the world as a matter of faith, to believe in something even as transient as the fleeting sensations of cinema (C2, 169â173). Although his suggestion is not wrong, it is incomplete. In his haste, Deleuze forgets to pose the problem with the ambivalence found in all his other accounts of powerâhow affects are ruled by tyrants, molecular revolutions made fascist, and nomad war machines enrolled to fight for the state. Without it, he becomes Nietzscheâs braying ass, which says yes only because it is incapable of saying no (NP, 178â86). We must then make up for Deleuzeâs error and seek the dark underside of belief. The key to identifying what lies beneath begins with the path of belief, but only to pursue a different orientation. So start with a similar becoming-active that links up with the forces that autoproduce the real. But instead of simply appreciating the forces that produce the World, **Dark Deleuze** intervenes in them to destroy it. At one time, such an intervention would have been called the Death of God, or more recently, the Death of Man. What is called for today is the Death of this World, and to do so requires cultivating a hatred for it.
Deleuze refutes the image of Nietzsche as a dour pessimist. Flipping that image on its head, Deleuze argues that Nietzsche is an unparalleled thinker of affirmation. But in doing so, even Deleuzeâs masterful pen cannot erase the many moments of negativity that impregnate Nietzscheâs work. Deleuze thus turns his eye to Nietzscheâs moments of creation, as exemplified in a passage from the fifty-eighth aphorism of **The Gay Science**:
How foolish it would be to suppose that one only needs to point out the origin and this misty shroud of delusion in order to **destroy** the world that counts as real, so-called â**reality**.â We can destroy only as creators.âBut let us not forget: it is enough to create new names and estimations and probabilities in order to create in the long run new âthings.â
Dissatisfied with Nietzscheâs implied goal of destruction, Deleuze inverts the phrase into âdestroy in order to createâ (DI, 130). This formulation appears over and again in his work. To name a few places: in **Anti-Oedipus,** Deleuze and Guattari say that capitalism destroys what came before to create its own earthly existence, a process of three tasks whereby the first is negative (destroy!) and the second two are positive (create! create!). Deleuze later argues that the painter must first destroy prior clichĂ©s before creating a new image (FB, 71â90). And in their final collaboration, Deleuze and Guattari scold âthose who criticize without creatingâ as âthe plague of philosophyâ (WP, 28).
There is something disarming about the sincerity of Deleuze and Guattariâs definition of philosophy as the art of constructing concepts (WP, 2). Yet it feels odd in an era full of trite invitations to being constructive: âif you donât have anything nice to say, donât say anything at all,â âif constructive thoughts are planted, positive outcomes will be the result,â or, simply, âbe constructive, not destructive.â The simple ifâthen structure of these self-help maxims is more than logical; it discloses a transitive theory of justice. Just as the meek will inherit the earth, it promises the just deserts of construction. Good things come to those who are constructive! How far this is from Marxâs âruthless criticism of all that existsâ (âLetter to Arnold Rugeâ). Now that advertisers claim to be the most creative of all creatures on earth, it is time to replace creativity as the central mechanism of liberation.
Deleuze would have hated todayâs images of creativityâthere is a great violence in comparing the fabrication of concepts to any happy means of construction; concepts are friends only to thought, as they break consensus (WP, 4â6, 99). Concepts are not discovered but the result of a catastrophe, Deleuze and Guattari say, from turning away, tiredness, distress, and distrust (6â7). True thought is rare, painful, and usually forced on us by the brutality of an event so terrible that it cannot be resolved without the difficulty of thought. As such, we must quit treating concepts as some âwonderful dowry from some wonderlandâ to understand the hard, rigorous work that goes into their creation (5).
Productivism is **Dark Deleuze**âs second object of criticism (connectivism being the first). It may be possible to distinguish concept creation from productivism, for the latter is âcommercial professional trainingâ that aspires for thought only beneficial âfrom the viewpoint of universal capitalismâ (WP, 14). Maintaining such a distinction is difficultâin an age of compulsory happiness, it is easy for construction to be conflated with capitalist value, the empty promises of democracy, or just plain helpfulness (106â8). To that end, productivism distinguishes itself with two formal principles: accumulation and reproduction. First, productivism manages political conflicts through a logic of accumulation, as seen in the âfull mobilizationsâ of World War II as well as in Stalinâs and Maoâs dreary attempts to outproduce the capitalist world system. Second, productivism limits production to reproduction, as capitalism attempts to do, by initiating only those circuits of production that operate on an expanding basis (what Lenin called âimperialismâ). The significance of the critique of productivism is that it expands the grammar of power beyond what is beholden to accumulation or reproduction.
Dark Deleuze does not philosophically quibble with creation. But it is easy to get drowned out by those who praise Deleuze for his âjoy.â The difficulty with joy is that it lies in the slippage between metaphysics and normativity. Michel Serres, for instance, remains steadfast that Deleuzeâs death must have been an accident because he felt that suicide was not in Deleuzeâs character or philosophy (Flint, âMichel Serresâ Angelsâ). Such liberties may be authorized by the term itself, as it comes from Spinozaâs **Ethics,** in which the line between the two is blurred. Joy surfaces as the feeling of pleasure that comes when a body encounters something that expands its capacities, which are affects said to âagree with my nature,â to be âgoodâ or simply âusefulâ (S, 239). To end the story here (though some do) would reproduce a naive hedonism based on inquiries into subjects and their self-reported affective states. Spinozaâs theory of affects is not an affirmation of a subjectâs feelings but a proof of the inadequacy of critique. Affects are by-products emitted during the encounter that hint at a replacement for recognition or understanding as the feedback loop to indicate if knowledge was sufficient. But there are innumerable forms of knowledge, many of which invite stupidity or illusion. What characterizes Spinozaâs âadequate knowledgeâ is its ability to create something newâit is that knowledge then becomes âidentical to the construction of realityâ (138). This is why Spinoza says that God = nature; knowledge-as-God is defined as that thought which increases the capacity to make actions flourish in the natural world (âI think, therefore I am activeâ) (WP, 31). The implication is that critique is not effective in its own right, no matter how loudly it proclaims its truth. The only adequate knowledge is activity.
Deleuze corrupts the holism of an already heretical Spinoza through an old atomist proposition: the relation between two terms produces an independent third term. (âSometimes the relations of two bodies may agree so well that they form a third relation within which the two bodies are preserved and prosperâ; S, 239; H, 101). This is how Deleuze builds his metaphysics of positivityâall elements stand alone without recourse to (Hegelian) opposition, contradiction, or identity. Deleuze and Guattariâs âline of flightâ conceptually embodies the Nietzschean notion that things are not wholly dependent on their context of production. For them, anything that has gained its own internal consistency is free to travel outside its place of origin. They even define art this wayâas impressions that have congealed enough to become their own mobile army of sensations (WP, 163â64). Deleuze and Guattariâs contemporaries share this insight, most notably Foucaultâs strategic reversibility of power relations (**History of Sexuality,** 92â102) and Althusserâs aleatory materialism (**Philosophy of the Encounter**). For Foucault, the reversibility of power is illustrated in homosexuality, which is first created as a medical category of sexual perversion but grows into a whole way of life that âspoke on its own behalf.â For Althusser, the âunderground currentâ of capitalism is made up of various noncontemporaneous elements always in a process of âbecoming-necessaryâ that âgels at certain felicitous moments,â while the singular importance of each haunting contingency simultaneously reveals the systemâs unstable horizon. Atomism thus shows how the world supplies the materials for its destruction.
The powers of the outside, a component of Deleuzeâs thought largely driven underground, offer an additional escape. First, there is this bookâs key pivot point: Deleuze and Guattari establish in **Anti-Oedipus** the autoproduction of the Real, which is a passive process that occurs largely beyond human understanding. Confusing metaphysics for politics, many Deleuzians parrot this production as a positive end unto itself. Yet a return to a politics worthy of the name âcommunismâ demands the opposite, as the greatest system of autoproduction is capitalism, which throws billions into abject poverty, wages horrific wars of devastation, and subjects humanity to a growing matrix of social oppression. Appeals to the frailty of life only obscure the issue even more. To say something rather controversial, though well established by ecologists decades ago: life will survive us. All human concern for the world is ultimately selfish anthropocentrism, for it was never life that was at risk (âthe combined detonation of all the worldâs nuclear weapons would be like a warm summer breeze to Gaia,â I once heard), just the worldâs capacity to sustain humans (Luke, **Ecocritique**; Stengers, **In Catastrophic Times**). Second, the way forward is to invite death, not to avoid it. Deleuze and Guattari suggest this in their reworking of the death drive. Similar sentiments are echoed in the punk ethos of âno future,â which paradoxically realizes that the only future we have comes when we stop reproducing the conditions of the present (Edelman, **No Future**). So let us stop romanticizing life and wish a happy death on calcified political forms, no-good solutions, and bad ways of thinking.
We must correct Deleuzeâs error: failing to cultivate a hatred for this world. It begins with the âambivalent joy of hatredâââWhat my soul loves, I love. What my soul hates, I hateâ (F, 23; ECC, 135). Or to echo Proust, âwe must be harsh, cruel, and deceptive to what we loveâ (P, 92). It is not even that Deleuze never mentioned hatred in a positive light; in fact, he often praises Nietzscheâs âsense of crueltyâ and âtaste for destructionâ (DR, 53). Deleuze was too often overtaken by a naive affirmation of joy, and as such, he was unable to give hatred its necessary form. His image for the future resembles too much of the present, and those who repeat it have come to sound like a parody: ârhizomatic gardens,â âcooperative self-production,â and âaffirming the affirmative of life.â Against those maxims, the Dark Deleuze is reborn as a barbarian depicted in Rimbaudâs season in hell: âIâm of a distant race: my forefathers were Scandinavian; they slashed their sides and drank their own blood. I will make cuts all over; Iâll tattoo myself, I long to be as a hideous Mongol: youâll see, Iâll scream in the streets. I want to be mad with rage.... I dreamt of crusades, of unrecorded voyages of discovery, of republics without history, wars of suppressed religion, moral revolutions, movements of races and continentsâ (**A Season in Hell**). Barbarian hatred is not to be indiscriminate, but it does not follow from a science of judgment. In fact, it is what is left after having done away with judgment (of God, of Man, and even of the World). Hatred is the ambivalent complement to love and, as such, can easily evade a decline into **ressentiment**. For **ressentiment** is just as much a depreciated image of love, as demonstrated by the Christian God who loved this world so much that he introduced the moral judgment of the ascetic ideal. In the end, hatred will prove to be just as important for the Death of this World as it was for the Death of God and the Death of Man.
There are those who have hitherto only enlightened the world in various ways; the point is to darken it. Some speculate that humans first pondered the ways of the world under the brilliant light of the heavens. On that vast celestial stage, the gods played out great dramas of arts and culture. This cosmos also inspired the earliest sciences of mathematics and astronomy, which wove the many constellations into a single tapestry. As the light of the stars became cycles and then detailed calendars, so came the dawn of time.
A more modern story begins in 1609, when, upon hearing news of the Dutch invention of the telescope, Galileo created his own. Almost immediately, Galileo was peering into the dark quadrants of the moon and illustrating its angle of illumination. These discoveries would lead him to loudly endorse heliocentrismâreplacing God with a new light at the center of the universe. Galileo curiously flaunts the rules of astronomy in his lunar record, as he does not date each ink wash according to its time of observation, nor does he make a photorealistic reproduction of the moonâs landscape (Gingrich and van Helden, âFrom **Occhiale** to Printed Page,â 258â62). Centuries of critics have tried to determine the source of Galileoâs inaccuracy. Johannis Hevelii, the father of stenography, wondered if Galileoâs instruments were too crude (**Selenographia sive Lunae Descriptio,** 205). Others suggest that he may have been too overtaken by the excitement of discovery (Kopal, **The Moon,** 225). But what if Galileo chose not to view the moon mathematically but philosophically? He was less concerned about its angles of illumination as an astronomical object than about what his telescopic **perspicillum** revealed about it as a cosmological concept. His styling of the moon reveals a way of seeing far more appropriate to baroque visual argument than to geographic measure. Galileoâs ink washes demonstrate the baroqueâs beautiful convergences. Referring ânot to an essence but rather to an operative function,â Galileoâs moon unfurls in the collision of multiple points of view as darkness and landscape meet in its leaping shadows (L, 3). More importantly, he marks a transition driven by âthe force of divergences, impossibilities, discords, dissonancesâ (81). In a world no longer illuminated by the light of God, Galileo paints âmany possible borders between worldsâ in a chromatic scale so as to be irresolvable from the lens of any one camera set to a single angle (81). How, then, does one continue Galileoâs journey to the far side of the moon? By refusing divine harmony and instead conspiring with divergent underground worlds.
The most immediate instance of lightness, connectivism, is the realization of the techno-affirmationist dream of complete transparency. The fate of such transparency is depicted in Fritz Langâs **Metropolis**. In it, the drive for complete communicability elevates transparency in the false transcendence of a New Tower of Babel. Deep in the shadows of the Lower City labors the working class, enslaved to the machines that automation promised to eliminate. Only in the catacombs does the secret rebellion commence. But instead of ending in Langâs grand Hegelian mediation, it would be better to listen to the Whore of Babylon in **Metropolis,** who says, âLetâs watch the world go to hell.â Such an untimely descent into darkness begins with a protest: lightness has far too long been the dominant model of thought. The road there descends from the chapel to the crypt.
Crypts are by their very nature places of seclusion. Early Christians facing public persecution fled to the underground catacombs below Rome, where they could worship in secret (âEssay upon Crypts,â 73â77). Early basilicas contain crypts as a âsecond churchâ under their choirs, featuring a vaulted ceiling, many columns, several aisles, and an altar (LĂŒbke, **Ecclesiastical Art,** 24â25). Some great churches even included a second crypt dedicated to a particular saint (26). At times, when sacred objects are of special interest, crypts of especially renowned saints have inspired mass pilgrimages (Spence-Jones, **Early Christianity and Paganism,** 269). Deleuze notes that these spaces fold in on themselves, simultaneously expressing the âautonomy of the insideâ and the âindependence of the façadeâ as an inside without an outside or an outside without an inside, depending on how you approach it (L, 28). Looking at El Grecoâs great baroque mannerist painting **The Burial of Count Orgaz,** we are given the choice. Above the great horizontal line, a gathering of saints ascends to the height of Jesus, whose own ascension grants the heavens eternal lightness. Below, a communion of cloaked, pale men crowd together to lay the count to rest under a dark background illuminated only by torchlight. The painting reveals the baroque truth of knowledge: âfor ages there have been places where what is seen is inside: a cell, a sacristy, a crypt, a church, a theater, a study, or a print roomâ (L, 27â28). So beyond the association of crypts with rot and death, it is a projection of subterranean architectural power.
From the crypt, **Dark Deleuze** launches a conspiracy. It is fueled by negativity, but not one of antimonies. Following Freud, negation is not a necessary by-product of consciousness. The lesson to be drawn from him is that negation is finding a way to say ânoâ to those who tell us to take the world as it is. To this end, the path forward is Deleuzeâs nondialectical negation, the âcontrary,â which operates as the distance between two exclusive paths (LS, 172â80). Klossowski identifies the goal of the conspiracy as breaking the collusion between institutionalized morality, capitalism, and the state (âCirculus Vitiosusâ). He then shows how Nietzscheâs laughter can be used as an experimental instrument to dissolve all identities into phantasms. A number of commentators have tried to rehabilitate the conspiracy on the basis of an esoteric/exoteric distinction, whereby exoteric discourses are the mere public face to a deeper paranoia whose desire is concealed in an esoteric code. To the extent that it is true, in his book **Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle,** Klossowski warns that the esoteric tradition must be avoided because it âdemystifies only in order to mystify betterâ (131). The point is not to replace angelic messages with arcane ones. This raises an important question: what is an appropriately cryptic language? Deleuze and Guattari note that âthe man of war brings the secret: he thinks, eats, loves, judges, arrives in secret, while the man of the state proceeds publiclyâ (TP, 543â44). Fortunately, in our conspiratorial world of phantasms, one does not hold a secret but instead becomes a secret. Even if she ends up spilling everything, it turns out to be nothing. Why? The secret first hides within dominant forms to limit exposure, yet what it smuggles inside is not any specific thing that needs to evade discovery. Rather, it is a perception of the secret that spreads under the shroud of secrecy: perception + secret = the secret as secretion. Conspiracies do not remain limited to a few furtive missives; their creeping insinuations are part of a universal project to permeate all of society (TP, 286â89). The best conspiracy is when it has nothing left to hide.
There is an affective dimension to our conspiracy. Pessimism becomes a necessity when writing in an era of generalized precarity, extreme class stratification, and summary executions of people of color. The trouble with the metaphysics of difference is that it does not immediately suggest a positive conception of alienation, exploitation, or social death. To the extent that those who affirm difference and its intensifications do make such violence thinkable, it appears as the consequence of deprivation. As a result, they cannot explain the simultaneous connectionâseparation of a body alienated from their own powers. Such joyousness makes no place for Marxâs theory of exploitation in which one class systematically extracts profit by expanding the capacities of another. The conspiracy offers a way out. On the affective level, it takes the ambivalence of hatred to grasp how oneâs own capacities are the yoke of his oppression. On the level of strategy, it takes deep, labyrinthine paths to develop a cryptography. To do so myself, I reenact Winstonâs trips to the shallow alcove of his apartment in **1984** to keep our own illicit diary of slogans. This is how I learned to find my own way to say âDOWN WITH BIG BROTHERâ and âIf there is hope, it lies with the prolesâ (181). This is because the ultimate task of **Dark Deleuze** is but a modest one: to keep the dream of revolution alive in counterrevolutionary times.
The conspiracy Dark Deleuze is a series of contraries. Contraries are not poles, which are dialectical opposites that ultimately complement each other. To distill a central argument from Deleuzeâs magnum opus **Difference and Repetition,** philosophy has (to its detriment) taken the nature of thinking to be the establishment of equivalence or logical identity between two terms (59). As such, contrasts must avoid relating terms on the basis of âa conceived identity, a judged analogy, an imagined opposition, or a perceived similitudeâ (138). Deleuze summarizes this argument in an interview: âIt was LĂ©vi-Strauss, I think, who showed you had to distinguish the following two propositions: that only similar things can differ [dialecticsâpresupposing a primordial identity behind differences], and only different things can be similar [contrariesâdifference primary to identity]â (N 156). There is a second reason for avoiding opposites: opposites imply a âgolden meanâ whereby the optimal place is found somewhere in between each extreme. Such middling compromise is the greatest tragedy of Deleuze and Guattariâs rhetorical presentation of what appear to be dualisms (smooth/striated, molar/molecular, arborescent/rhizomatic) in **A Thousand Plateaus**. The unfortunate effect is a legion of noncommittal commentators who preach the moderation of the middle. In response, we must contaminate every last one of those conceptual pairs with a third term that arrives from the outside. Deleuze and Guattari set the example in how they reimagine DumĂ©zilâs tripartite state as two opposing poles besieged by a third term that arrives from the outside. Such a reformulation would more closely follow Deleuzeâs atomism of two terms relating through the production of an independent third term. To make the stakes clear: we are told in **A Thousand Plateaus** that the state is made of two opposing poles, one liberal and one authoritarian, that in fact work in a âcomplementarityâ not dissimilar from the dialectical logic of determinate negationâthis is the model of relation that must be avoided at all costs (for more, see the section âDifference: Exclusive Disjunction, Not Inclusive Disjunctionâ) (DumĂ©zil, **Mitra-Varuna**). This is why **Dark Deleuze** contrasts dark to joyous and not dark to light or joyous to sad. Each contrary is a forking path, an alternate route for every instance one is tempted by affirmation.
Listed in what follows are the contrasting terms. In the column on the left, I list a series of tasks. Across each column I have placed two contrary approaches, one joyous and one dark. The association each term has to its contrary is purely incidental. Each termâs contrariness is not given, as if one implied the otherâI propose dark terms simply on their ability to unexpectedly usurp the operations of their contraries. Contrary approaches should be taken as mutually exclusive, as they are independent processes each meant to fulfill the given task without recourse to the other. What makes them dark is the position of exteriority from which the irregular forces of darkness attack the joy of state thought. The foreignness of relation is why each pair of contrasting terms is notably imbalanced.
My ultimate purpose is to convince readers to completely abandon all the joyous paths for their dark alternatives. The best scenario would be that these contraries fade into irrelevance after Dark Deleuze achieves its ostensible goal: the end of this world, the final defeat of the state, and full communism. It is far more likely that various aspects of darkness will be captured along the way. Like any other war machine, a dark term is defeated when it isomorphically takes on relations or forms of its joyous counterpart. So it is worth uttering a cautionary note from **A Thousand Plateaus**: even when contrary, never believe that darkness will suffice to save us.
|+ +|
| | Joyous | Dark |
| The Task | Create Conceptions | Destroy Worlds |
| Subject | Assemblages | Un-becoming |
| Existence | Genesis | Transformation |
| Ontology | Realism | Materialism |
| Difference | Inclusive Disjunction | Exclusive Disjunction |
| Diagram | Complexity | Asymmetry |
| Organization | Rhizome | Unfolding |
| Ethics | Processural Democracy | Conspiratorial Communism |
| Affect | Intensity | Cruelty |
| Speed | Acceleration | Escape |
| Flows | Production | Interruption |
| Substance | Techno-Science | Political Anthropology |
| Nomadism | Pastoral | Barbarian |
| Distribution | Nomos | The Outside |
| Politics | Molecular | Cataclysmic |
| Cinema | The Forces of Bodies | The Powers of the False |
| The Sensible | Experience | Indiscernibility |
The conspiracy against this world will be known through its war machines. A war machine is itself âa pure form of exteriorityâ that âexplains nothing,â but there are plenty of stories to tell about them (TP, 354, 427). They are the heroes of **A Thousand Plateaus**âKleistâs skull-crushing war machine, the migratory war machine that the Vandals used to sack Rome, the gun that Black Panther George Jackson grabs on the run, and the queer war machine that excretes a thousand tiny sexes. âEach time there is an operation against the stateâinsubordination, rioting, guerilla warfare, or revolution as an actâit can be said that a war machine has revivedâ (386). War machines are also the greatest villains of **A Thousand Plateaus,** making all other dangers âpale by comparisonâ (231)âthere is the constant state appropriation of the war machine that subordinates war to its own aims (418), the folly of the commercial war machine (15), the paranoia of the fascist war machine (not the state army of totalitarianism) (230â31), and, worst of them all, the âworldwide war machineâ of capitalism, âwhose organization exceeds the State apparatus and passes into energy, militaryâindustrial, and multinational complexesâ to wage peace on the whole world (387, 419â21, 467).
âMake thought a war machine,â Deleuze and Guattari insist. âPlace thought in an immediate relation with the outside, with the forces of the outsideâ (TP, 376â77). Two important inventions follow: speed and secrecy. These are the affects of the war machine, its weapons of war, which âtranspierce the body like arrowsâ (356, 394). The resulting violence is not so vulgar as to encourage blow-by-blow bloodletting or a once-and-for-all immediate killing but institutes an economy of violence whose hatred is unlimited and therefore durable. The war machine engages in war along two poles: one forms a line of destruction âprolongable to the limits of the universe,â while the other draws a line of flight for the âcomposition of a smooth space and of the movement of people in that spaceâ (422). Deleuze and Guattari would prefer to promote the connectivist line by saying they âmake war only on the condition that they simultaneously create something elseâ (423). But today, that path leads to collusion with capitalismâs drive toward creative destruction (Schumpeter, **Capitalism, Socialism, Democracy,** 87). This is certainly not lost on those in Silicon Valley who spread the mantra of âdisruptive innovation.â We can thus take heed of Deleuze and Guattariâs warning against treating terms as having âan irresistible revolutionary callingâ (387). It is time to accept Nietzscheâs invitation to philosophize with a hammer, rendered here in the voice of Krishna: âI am become Time, the destroyer of worlds.â We must find an appetite for destruction that does not betray Deleuze and Guattariâs âabolitionist dream.â This takes the âprogressive, anxiety-ridden revelationâ that destroying worlds is just another way of âsmashing capitalism, of redefining socialism, of constituting a war machine capable of countering the world war machine by other meansâ (385, 417, 372).
Make the whole world stand still. Indeed, it may be the only way to think the present in any significant sense. To be clear: the suspension of the world is not a hunt for its conditions of reproduction or a meditative ârhapsody of sensationsâ (DR, 56). It is thought that treats the world as if struck by an unspecified disaster, where the best friends you have left are your own ideas. This is not the banal disaster movie, whose ambitions are usually limited to teaching us what are the bare essentials to survive. Writing the disaster is how we break free from the stifling perpetual present, for the present carries with itself a suffocating urgency. The present imposes material limits. To it, the past and the future are the empty form of time, and they must endure the complications of having a body to become part of the present (LS, 146â47, 165). The past and the future exist in their own right only through representationâthe former in history as the present memorialization of things passed and the latter in the yet to come as the projection of an image of the present (147). Such re-presentation is why the future appears with the distinct impression that âwe have seen it all beforeâ (Flaxman, **Fabulation of Philosophy,** 392). The productivist sees the event of thought as an eminently practical reorientation toward the present achieved while generating a new image of the future (WP, 58). In contrast, those learning to hate the world must short-circuit the âhere and nowâ to play out the scene differently. While still being in this world, they turn away from it. This is the life of characters so agitated that they force the world to stand stillâDostoyevskyâs Idiot, the head of Kurosawaâs seven samurai (TR, 317â18). Against bleating urgency that âthere a fire, thereâs fire ... Iâve got to go,â they insist that everything could burn to the ground but nothing happens, because one must seek out a more urgent problem!
There are those who say that we already have one foot in utopia; but would it not be more suitable to say that we have both feet firmly planted in a present slouching toward dystopia? Deleuze and Guattari call on utopia in their search for a new people and a new earth (WP, 99). They look to Samuel Butler, dissecting his **Erewhon** as a simultaneous ânow-hereâ and âno-whereâ (100). Yet a closer examination of his novel reveals utopia to be a farce. While not exactly a dystopia, the utopia Erewhon is a comic satire of the British Empire. The narrator is a crass traveler with settler colonial dreams who catalogs the strange ways of Erewhonâin chapters 10 and 11, he outlines how they punish the sick (âconvicted of aggravated bronchitisâ) and sentence the misfortunate to hard labor (âill luck of any kind ... is considered an offense against societyâ) but nurture financial transgressions with medicine (âtaken to a hospital and most carefully tended at the public expenseâ). Beyond being an object lesson in reading footnotes, Deleuze and Guattariâs reference to **Erewhon** demands an attention to the exact configuration of conceptual devices (**dispositifs**) and how power flows through them. Link thought with its epoch, they suggest, begin with a survey to identify whatever forces are already circulating and then work with themââconnecting up with what is real here and now in the struggle against capitalism, relaunching new struggles whenever the earlier one is betrayedâ (100). They warn of âproud affirmationâ as the guise of restoration that opens the door to transcendence, such as appeals to truth, right, or authority (100). For Butler, **Erewhon** summons neither a new people nor a new earth but is instead a field guide to negate everything he finds intolerable in his present. Utopia becomes the map to transform the now-here into the no-where.
âIt should have been an apocalyptic book,â laments Deleuze, disappointed that the âold styleâ **Difference and Repetition** did not make apparent a key implicationâhe killed God, humankind, and even the world (xxi). The Death of God began long before Deleuze, who sees Feuerbach as completing it long before Nietzsche with the proposition that âsince man has never been anything but the unfold of man, man must fold and refold Godâ (F, 130). Nietzsche identifies a different problem: that God was reborn in the form of Man. For Deleuze, it takes Foucault to establish the finitude of humanityââMan has not always existed, and will not exist foreverââthus sealing its fate (F, 124). But to destroy the world ... that is the truly heretical proposition. A small group of dissident Deleuze scholars have rallied around the slogan that âthere is no âontology of DeleuzeâââGregory Flaxman, Anne Sauvagnargues, Gregg Lambert, and François Zourabichvili, to name a few (Zourabichvili, **A Philosophy of the Event,** 36). The statement does not imply that ontology is an illusion, but criticizing those who build a Deleuzian system around a coherent ontology of the world is ill considered, as it fails draw a line to the outsideââto incalculable forces, to chance and improvisation, to the futureâ (Flaxman, âPolitics and Ontologyâ). Blazing such a path may require âthe extinction of the term âbeingâ and therefore of ontology,â or in so many words, a destruction of this world (37). Deleuze and Guattari suggest as much when they propose to âoverthrow ontologyâ (TP, 25). Summed up, this stance names the âjoyful pessimistâ Deleuze. Too restless to stop there, the Dark Deleuze broadens the **coup de force** into a fierce pessimism that shatters the cosmos.
Subjectivity is shamefulââsubjects are born quite as much from misery as from triumphâ (N, 151). It grows from the seeds of a âcomposite feelingâ made from the compromises with our time: the shame of being alive, the shame of indignity, the shame that it happens to others, the shame that others can do it, and the shame of not being able to prevent it (WP, 108, 225). Existence is the result of a disaster, yet it says very little about us; it does not explain but rather must be explained. This is what makes shame âone of philosophyâs most powerful motifsâ (108). The subject is always something derivative that âcomes into being and vanishes in the fabric of what one says, what one sees,â resembling âspecks dancing in the dust of the visible and permutations in an anonymous babbleâ (N, 108). This does not keep some from clinging to their shame. On this account, Deleuze has nothing but scorn for identity politicsââwe have to counter people who think âIâm this, Iâm thatâ ... arguments from oneâs own privileged experience are bad and reactionary argumentsâ (N, 11â12). Shame is our defense against these people, queer theorists remind us, and it must be put to work on them as a weaponâan affect that acts as a solvent to dissolve whatever binds it to an identity (Halperin and Traub, âBeyond Gay Pride,â 25). There are those who have worked to square identity with Deleuze (Donna Haraway, Tim Dean, Jasbir Puar, Ădouard Glissant). Their theorizations only avoid the problem of shame to the extent that they make identityâs many perforations into points of leverage and transformed differences into a million cutting edges.
For some, the world is made up of assemblages, and all assemblages are subjects. In no time, people, hurricanes, and battles all get addressed in the same register (as all subjects should be afforded proper names)! Although this is, perhaps, technically true, such assemblage-thinking misses the pointâit reduces subjectivity to the name we use to pin down the sum of a bodyâs capacities (AT, 256â57). It sanctifies a bloodless world by cataloging the networks that make up its many attributes. This is why assemblage-modeling is a perfect fit in a world where capitalism produces subjectivity âthe same way it produces Prell shampoo or Ford carsâ (AO, 245). Further proof of its noxious conservativsm is arch-thinkers Manuel DeLandaâs and Bruno Latourâs dismissive rejection of Marxism. Fortunately, Deleuze already warned us by channeling Spinoza on the limits of adequate knowledge, in the often-repeated words that âwe do not know what a body is capable ofâ (NP, 39). The phrase should not be read as an appeal to some evasive essence but simply as applying a principle of Deleuzeâs transcendental empiricism, which holds that the conditions of actual experience are not represented through empirical tracing (DR, 95, 221, 321). This is crucial, because philosophy is too easily thrown back into the transcendental illusions through the personal identitarian experiences built by self-centered habits of mind (DR, 207â8, 73, 119). The pitfall of run-of-the-mill empiricists is that even in the best-case scenario, when they step out of the perspective of the subject, they still reduce existence to conditions of reproduction or chart somethingâs âdegree of freedom.â For us, then, the subject should be spoken about scornfully as simply the sum of a bodyâs habits, most of which are marshaled to evade thought.
The undoing of the subject is un-becoming. Deleuze withholds praise for the subject but does not deny it a place, unlike Althusser, who theorizes âsubjectivity without a subjectâ (Badiou, âAlthusser,â 58â67). But subjects are only interesting when they cast a âline to the outsideââin short, when they stop being subjects (with a double emphasis on âbeingâ and âsubjectsâ) (N, 99). This process is how Deleuze describes Foucaultâs subjectivization, which is not a âcoming backâ to subjectivity to rescue it but the disintegration of the subject as it evaporates into a field of forces where neither persons nor identities survive (N, 93). This is the secret to becoming, for it has nothing to do with âsubjects developing into more of themselves.â Becoming is really a process of un-becoming. In what Elizabeth Grosz calls âundoing the givenness of the givenâ of **Becoming Undone,** un-becoming exercises undoing, a process that works to âundo the stabilities of identity, knowledge, location, and beingâ (210, 3). But in proposing undoing as an alternative to subjectivity, it is necessary to be specific about how to orient the process. While it is easy for an aesthete to indulge in the powers of the outside like a good after-dinner drink, âletting loose, freeing up, and putting into play,â undoing can fulfill the higher purpose of nursing a hatred for this world (55). For it is only when we locate something intolerable outside ourselves that we will âleap beyond shameâ and âtransform [our] paltry undertakings into a war of resistance and liberationâ (ECC, 125).
Philosophy âhas always maintained an essential relation to the law, the institution, and the contractâ (DI, 259). Foundations thus hold a special place in philosophy, with philosophers obsessively writing and rewriting the book of Genesis. It is Kant, the great thinker of the genetic âcondition,â âwho finally turns the philosopher into the Judge at the same time that reason becomes a tribunalâ (WP, 72). Deleuze refuses to disown his own âin the beginning.â But for him, the movement of thought follows an explosive line whose genesis comprises problems manifest from imperceptible forces that disrupt habits of mind. Such thinking does not build a courthouse of reason whereby each advance in thought confirms more about what was already self-evident, as if developing an elaborate mirror of the world (N 38â39; DR 129). In contrast, the âenemyâ Kant does something intolerable by creating a theory of law that diverts the ungrounding called thought, ending its journey to an unrecognized **terra incognita** (DI 58; DR 136). He does this by reversing the Greeks, making it so the law does not depend on the good like a material substrate and instead deriving the good from lawââthe good is that which the law expresses when it expresses itselfâ (K, 43). Expressing their disapproval, Deleuze and Guattari draw a âportraitâ of Kant that depicts him as a vampiric death machine feeding off the world (WP, 56). But even as Kant makes the law rational, he opens up a way out in the third critique through a synthesis that allows a free harmony of the faculties, though he is quick to betray it (WP, 32, 46, 100). Latching on to this furtive insight, Deleuze advances a âmobile war machineâ in its place, to be used against the ârational administrative machineâ of philosophers who âwould be the bureaucrats of pure reasonâ (DI, 259). And in making thought into a siege engine, it gains the nomadic force of transformation. The key is to avoid founding a new order on a new image of world. Fortunately, we can follow the pure idea of Toynbeeâs nomads who shed their habits so they do not have to leave their habitats.
Our appetite produces the real. But do not mistake the real for a simple projectionâit is real through and through. âI take my desires for reality because I believe in the reality of my desire,â says the streets of Paris in 1968 (Anonymous, âGraffitiâ). In response, Deleuze and Guattari say that âthe real is not impossible, on the contrary, within the real everything is possible, everything becomes possibleâ (AO, 27). The only reason that we lack anything, they say, is that our social system deprives us of what we desire. On this account, our taste is not a correlationist yearning, as Quentin Meillassoux calls it in **After Finitude,** which would say that we are reaching for a thing-in-itself always outside the grasp of our perception. Yet this should not lead us to embrace the philosophical realism that connectivists apologize for as an attack on anthropocentrism. âThings exist independently of perception,â the realists assert to bring the Death of Man. But they forget that âthere is no such thing as either man or natureâ when there is âsimply the production of production itselfâ (AO, 2). So while there is no man, nature also must vanish. Without treating the real as truly artificial, thought is regrounded as a theology of this world that plugs all the leaks to the outside.
A superior materialism âconstructs a real that is yet to comeâ (TP, 142). It does not follow so-called new materialism, which is really just a new form of animism, but Marxist materialism as the revolutionary subversion of material necessity. Deleuze and Guattari find their superior materialism by exchanging the theater of representation for the factory of production. It is the materialism of Epicurus and the atomism of the swerve as the necessity of contingency (Althusser, **Philosophy of the Encounter,** 174). This permanent revocation of the fait accompli is at work in politics of destruction, which has too long been mistaken for deliberation but is instead exemplified by the war machines of popular insurrection whose success is registered by the streets themselvesâconsider the words of the Invisible Committee in **To Our Friends**: âLike any specific strike, it is a politics of the accomplished fact. It is the reign of the initiative, of practical complicity, of gesture. As to decision, it accomplishes that in the streets, reminding those whoâve forgotten, that âpopularâ comes from the Latin **populor,** âto ravage, devastate.â It is a fullness of expression ... and a nullity of deliberationâ (54). By showing the nondurability of what is taken as real, so-called reality itself, communist politics is a conspiracy that writes the destruction of the world.
âToo much!â is a potential rallying cryâtoo many products, too many choices, too much of this world! Instead, become contrary! Difference, for Deleuze, is the result of a âdisjunctive synthesisâ that produces a series of âdisjointed and divergentâ differences (LS, 174â76, 177â80). Importantly, these differences can be immediately brought together at a distance through resonance, globally coordinated, or contracted into a divergent multitude (172â76). Following the rule âalways perversify,â Deleuze and Guattari propose including disjunctions in a mad mixture of âworld-historical, political, and racial contentâ as a strategy for scrambling oppressive codes (AO, 15, 88â89).
Global capitalism quickly caught on. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri have shown us how it rules over a virtual Empire of difference that eagerly coordinates a wide arrangement of diverging differences while also producing many more of its own (**Empire,** 44â45, 138â56, 190â201, 339â43). Capital is now indistinguishable from the exemplary subject, the schizo, who is voiced by Nietzsche in his wild claims to be âall the names of historyâ (AO, 86)! Power is now diffuse, and the antagonism of Marxâs class war has been drowned in an overwhelming sea of difference. This development calls for a reorientation that entails learning how to **become contrary**. In the case of Dark Deleuze, the contrarian position is the forced choice of âthis, not that.â Deleuze is perfectly happy to demand âno possible compromise between Hegel and Nietzscheâ (NP, 195). Why not experiment with our own exclusive disjunctive synthesis that is limited, restrictive, and constrained? Hardt and Negri take their cue from those in the Global South who âhomogenize real differencesâ to name âthe potential unity of an international opposition, the confluence of anticapitalist countries and forcesâ (**Empire,** 334). A better response has been the terrifying screams of no that occasionally break apart its grand accords (Holloway, âThe Scream,â 1). Though not demanding the suppression of difference, the problem of Empire reignites the necessity of conspiracy, the power of hatred, and the task of destroying worlds.
âThe ânothingâ (Heidegger), the âtraceâ or âdiffĂ©ranceâ (Derrida), the âsurplus always exterior to the totalityâ (Levinas), the âdifferendâ (Lyotard), âthe invisibleâ (Althusser),â and âthe âpariahâ (Arendt), âthe jewâ (Lyotard), the âmigrantâ (Virilio), the ânomadâ (Deleuze and Guattari), the âhybridâ (Bhabha), the âcatachrestic remainderâ (Spivak), the ânon-beingâ (Dussel), the ârefugeeâ (Agamben), and, most resonantly, the âĂ©migrĂ©â (Said),â are the terms literary theorist William Spanos uses to describe the fleeting figures of the late twentieth century (âQuestion of Philosophy,â 173). Each term names a conflict between differences in kind, mapping lines of flight to the outside and those who dwell there. They speak of effects not equal to their cause. The generic term for this relation is **asymmetry,** which expresses difference as formal inequivalence. Asymmetry works to impede reciprocal relations and prevent reversibility. It diagrammatically starts by constituting two formally distinct terms as contrary asymmetry. It is maintained by concretely establishing a relationship of incommensurability between their sets of forces.
Complexity is snake oil in the age of singularityâeveryone and everything is a unique snowflake, what relations they can establish is not predetermined, and what they can become is limited most by how well they apply themselves! Any criticism of complexity must take into account its three levels: complexity as a fact, complexity as a resource, and complexity as deferral. As a fact, it culminates in a âflat ontologyâ that stitches together difference into a strange alliance of philosophy and science (Delanda, **Intensive Science,** 46â47). Though offering some provocative insights, this flattening still often leads to âa uniformization of diversityâ and âequalization of inequalityâ (DR, 223). As a resource, the labyrinthine structure of complex systems can both mobilize and impair forces. Such complexity multiplies paths, which stocks oneâs arsenal with either a range of new options (as in de Certeauâs âtacticsâ) or a trap to bog down their opponents (Kafkaâs **The Trial**). It is this second aspect that contributes to the third dimension of complexity: deferral. A matterâs âcomplexityâ has become a way to defer a sufficient answer (âit is too complex for me to give a complete answer now ...â). The trouble with deferral is its collusion with capitalist time, which delays the arrival of the proletarian revolution (Balibar, **Philosophy of Marx,** 101). Just ask complexity progenitor Stuart Kauffman, who now speaks in a mixture of religious mysticism and computational entrepreneurship (**Reinventing the Sacred**; Kauffman et al., âEconomic Opportunityâ).
Deleuze outlines his case for asymmetry in **Difference and Repetition**. Everything we know is the work of a calculating god whose numbers fail to add up, he says (DR, 222). The effect is a basic injustice, an âirreducible inequality,â that is âthe worldâ (222). âIf the calculations were exact there would be no world,â Deleuze argues, that makes the world itself the âremainderâ that is âthe real in the world understood in terms of fractional or even incommensurable numbersâ (222). This asymmetry is not meant as a refutation of the dubious hypothesis of the computational universe, though he does thoroughly show how the âpartial truthâ of energetics (e.g., the thermodynamics of entropy) is a âtranscendental physical illusionâ that should not be applied to the rest of the world (225, 229). The wider significance of asymmetry is an alternative to dialectics. A dialectical framing of gender, for instance, would establish an intrinsic relation between masculinity and femininity, hopelessly entangling each within each other. Extracted from dialectics, Alexander Galloway and Eugene Thacker note in their media theory of the exploit that âit is not simply that feminism is opposed to patriarchy, but that they are asymmetrically opposed; racism and antiracism are not just opposed but exist in a relationship of asymmetryâ (**The Exploit,** 14). The result is a formal mechanism for political antagonism that draws on the powers of the outside.
Asymmetry is ultimately a question of combat, even if it is formally established diagrammatically. Its best realization was the twentieth-century guerrilla. The guerilla demonstrates two things about asymmetry: first, each side is opposed in terms of its strategic imperatives, but second, as each side varies in orientation, it also varies in type. As Henry Kissinger writes about the American strategy in âThe Vietnam Negotiationsâ for **Foreign Affairs,**
we fought a military war; our opponents fought a political one. We sought physical attrition; our opponents aimed for our psychological exhaustion. In the process we lost sight of one of the cardinal maxims of guerrilla war: the guerrilla wins if he does not lose. The conventional army loses if it does not win. The North Vietnamese used their armed forces the way a bull-fighter uses his capeâto keep us lunging in areas of marginal political importance. (214)
Fact: while the United States was fighting a war, Vietnam was engaged in combat; one for domination, the other for freedom (ECC, 132â35). This is how Marxist struggles for national liberation raised formal asymmetry as a resource for world-historical proportions. Mao defeated the national army of China with guerrillas who âmove amongst the people as a fish swims in the sea.â Che helped Castroâs rebels flood the countryside so that they could spark a revolution that would eventually consume the cities. We must find ways to avoid complexity from deferring our own âfull guerrilla warfareâ (LS, 156â57).
The story of a tyrant: finding his cruelty mollified, God burdens the world with infinite debt. Before him, memories were written on the body in a âterrible alphabetâ so as never to forget them (AO, 145). This system was cruel but finite, which allowed it to form elaborate crisscrossing systems that warded off the centralization of power, such as potlatches (190). A paranoid despot arrives from the outside, as described by Nietzsche in **On the Genealogy of Morality,** installing history âjust like lightning appears, too terrible, sudden,â with the founding of the state to redirect the horizontal lines of alliance up and toward himself. Finite is made infiniteââeverything is owed to the kingâ (AO, 192). Against the infinite torture of unlimited debt, cruelty combats both history and the judgment of God with âa writing of blood and life that is opposed to the writing of the bookâ (ECC, 128). Cruelty returns as language written on fleshââterrible signs that lacerate bodies and stain themâ as âthe incisions and pigmentsâ that reveal âwhat they owe and are owedâ (AO, 128). Only then does the eternal collapse into the finitude of our existence.
Ours is âthe most cruel of all worldsâ (DI, 108). Cruelty has a lighter cousin, intensity, which induces the event of individuation that âaffirms differenceâ without resorting to extensionâs depth (DR, 233). The definition of intensity as âfeltâ has been the source of incredible confusion. Having reduced intensity to a special kind of feeling, practitioners of âaffect studiesâ perform autoethnographies of the ineffable. This is quite peculiar given the antiphenomenology of Deleuzeâs transcendental empiricism, which is explicitly nonhuman, prepersonal, and asubjective. Instead of intensity as âa strong feeling,â cruelty more aptly describes the âbeing of the sensibleâ as âthe demons, the sign-bearers,â who bring thought to us (266). Consider how Deleuzeâs **Difference and Repetition** opens with lightning streaking through the black sky and ends with all the drops of the world swelling into a single ocean of excess (28, 304). Toward the end, he tells us that history presides over every determination since the birth of the world (219). Even though it may not progress âby its bad side,â as Marx would have it through his critique of Proudhon, history is not âany less bloody or cruel as a resultâ (268).
Artaudâs Theater of Cruelty gives shape to the way forward. He would be amused by the cinematic experiment of **A Clockwork Orange**. His theatrical cruelty targets those who see themselves as Alexâthose who complain, âI can no longer think what I want, the moving images-are-substituted for my own thoughtsâ (C2, 166). The resulting theater is not for telling stories but to âempower,â to implant images in the brains of those powerless to stop it (174, 166). The cruel force of these images strikes something in the skull but not the mind (a nerve? brain matter?) (167). But the only thought it allows us to ponder is â**the fact that we are not yet thinking,**â that we are âpowerless to think the whole and to think oneself,â a âthought which is always fossilized, dislocated, collapsedâ (167). Cruelty here is âa dissociative force,â âa figure of nothingness,â and âa hole in appearanceâ good only for unlinking us from ourselves (167).
Enough with rhizomes. Although they were a suggestive image of thought thirty-five years ago, our present is dominated by the Cold War technology of the Internet that was made as a rhizomatic network for surviving nuclear war. The rhizome was a convincing snapshot of things to come, but Deleuze and Guattari left out a few things, most notably the question of movement. How does a rhizome advance, except in the crawl of the blob that slowly takes over everything? This is probably why connectivists have come to revere itâthe alleged open ecology of the network specifies nothing except the bluster of its own inevitability. We know better than to think that a rhizome is enough to save us. Even something as rhizomatic as the Internet is still governed by a set of decentralized protocols that helps it maintain its consistencyâthe drawback being that these forms of control are diffuse, not immediately apparent, and difficult to resist (Galloway, **Protocol,** 61â72).
A contrary path: cast a line to the outside! These lines are found in folds, which are what connects a world where ârelations are external to their termsâ (H, 101). It is through the external bridge of the fold that âa world where terms exist like veritable atomsâ communicates through their irreducible exteriority (DI, 163). More importantly, folding is movement. The inside is not erased from this world; rather, the interior is an operation of the outside (F, 97). Such âin-foldingâ is a structuration, âthe folding back on itself of the fiber to form a compact structureâ that transforms mere sedimentation into hardened strata (TP, 42). It is in this way that we can understand folding as a double-relation of force enveloping itself (and not of some forcesâ relation to others) as found in inorganic life, biological evolution, art, and thought (N, 92). But folding only accounts for one moment in the rhythm of movement; it is complemented by unfoldingââto unfold is to increase to grow; whereas to fold is to diminish, to reduce, âto withdraw into the recesses of a worldââ (L, 8â9).
Although called joyous by some, the great unfolding sparks an experience of terror driven by the question, âhow far can we unfold the line without falling into a breathless void, into death, and how can we fold it, but without losing touch with it, to produce an inside copresent with the outside, corresponding to the outside?â (N, 113). A boring biological example is an animalâs deterritorialization of its milieu by in-folding a function by way of an organ that enables it to escape to form new relations with a new outside, such as a tetrapodâs water retrainment, which enabled it to carry the sea with it on land. The most exciting version of unfolding operates purely in time. As a narrative device, unfolding builds tension until it suddenly âbursts open like a springâ (N, 151). Expectation, anticipation, climax, release. **Modern Times** is a masterful piece of unfolding. At a certain point (âthe moment Charlie Chaplin makes the board fall on his head for a second timeâ), the film unfolds with the âshort-circuits of a disconnected piece of machineryâ (AO, 317). We cease to identify with the main character and instead envelop his events, surprises, premonitions, and habits. There is no more to unfold at dawn as the couple, âseen from the back, all black, whose shadows are not projected by any sun, advance toward nothingâ (317). A line of telegraph poles on the left and pathetic trees on the right, the two fade into an empty road with no horizonâdisappearing as they unfold into the void.
Unfolding operates through conduction, not communicationâat least according to Jean-François Lyotard in **Libidinal Economy** (254â62). As a conductor of affects, unfolding does not build capacities through the accumulative logic of rhizomes, which changes through addition or subtraction. Unfoldingâs disconnection is not the dampening of power but the buildup of charges that jump across the divide. This operation is so vital that Deleuze elevates unfolding to the absolute of unfolding substance itself (S, 310). Yet this process always takes place through a body, which stands at the limit of wild unfolding. The body staves off the âoperation of vertigoâ that comes from chasing after the âtiny and moving folds that waft me along at excessive speedâ (L, 93). Seen from its slower speed, we see that unfolding generates force. Consider Lyotardâs project of an âinvulnerable conspiracy, headless, homeless, with neither programme nor project,â which begins by âdeploying a thousand cancerous tensorsâ (262) across the bodyâs âgreat ephemeral skinâ:
Open the so-called body and spread out all its surfaces: not only the skin with each of its folds, wrinkles, scars, with its great velvety planes, and contiguous to that, the scalp and its mane of hair, the tender pubic fur, nipples, hair, hard transparent skin under the heel, the light frills of the eyelids, set with lashesâbut open and spread, expose the labia majora, so also the labia minora with their blue network bathed in mucus, dilate the diaphragm of the anal sphincter, longitudinally cut and flatten out the black conduit of the rectum, then the colon, then the caecum, now a ribbon with its surface all striated and polluted with shit; as though your dressmakerâs scissors were opening the leg of an old pair of trousers, go on, expose the small intestinesâ alleged interior, the jejunum, the ileum, the duodenum, or else, at the other end, undo the mouth at its comers, pull out the tongue at its most distant roots and split it. Spread out the batsâ wings of the palate and its damp basements, open the trachea and make it the skeleton of a boat under construction; armed with scalpels and tweezers, dismantle and lay out the bundles and bodies of the encephalon; and then the whole network of veins and arteries, intact, on an immense mattress, and then the lymphatic network, and the fine bony pieces of the wrist, the ankle, take them apart and put them end to end with all the layers of nerve tissue which surround the aqueous humours and the cavernous body of the penis, and extract the great muscles, the great dorsal nets, spread them out like smooth sleeping dolphins. (1â2)
Though Lyotardâs account is compelling, we must remain more vigilant. For what is it that fuels capitalism if not the massive energy generated through the unfolding of bodies? This is what inspires the famous line of **The Manifesto of the Communist Party,** whereby the constant revolutionizing of the forces of production leads to an âuninterrupted disturbance of all social conditions, everlasting uncertainty and agitationâ summarized in the phrase âall that is solid melts into airâ (chapter 1). But to be clear: communism is revolutionary because it too believes in the process of dissolution. Capitalism is to be criticized for falling shortâit pairs the conductive power of unfolding with the rhizomatic logic of accumulation. A communism worthy of its name pushes unfolding to its limit.
Democracy should be abolished. Spinozist champions of democracy, such as Antonio Negri, consider Deleuze a fellow traveler. Some Deleuzians have even tried to smuggle democracy back into his metaphysics, some even pervert him into a liberal. Yet Deleuze lumps nothing but hatred upon democracyâsummarized by his mocking of the phrases âEverything is equal!â and âEverything returns!â at the beginning and end of **Difference and Repetition**. Against the principle of equivalence implied in the first, he agrees with Nietzsche, who criticizes contract, consensus, and communication. Against the principle of continuity implied in the second, he agrees with Marx, who rejects the liberal proceduralism that underwrites rights as an obfuscation of power. More than enough ink has been spilled to support both of these positions. But to get the tenor pitch perfect, it is worth mentioning that Deleuze and Guattari viciously criticize democracy in their collaborations, usually by calling it the cousin of totalitarianism. They discuss democracy, fascism, and socialism as all related in **Anti-Oedipus** (261). In **A Thousand Plateaus,** they discuss âmilitary democracyâ (394), âsocial democracyâ as the complementary pole of the State to âtotalitarianismâ (462), âtotalitarian-social democracyâ (463), and a poverty-stricken âThird World social democracyâ (468). In **What Is Philosophy?,** they speak of Athenian âcolonizing democracyâ (97), hegemonic democracy (98), democracy being caught up with dictatorial states (106), a social democracy that âhas given the order to fire when the poor come out of their territory or ghettoâ (107), and a Nazi democracy (108), which all lead them to conclude that their utopian ânew people and a new earth ... will not be found in our democraciesâ (108). Together, they can be neatly summarized: no matter how perfect, democracy always relies on a transcendent sovereign judgment backed by the threat of force. Only twice is Deleuze caught with his pants down in regard to democracy, both in moments of panderingâonce in a letter to Antonio Negriâs jailers that appeals through self-distance to âeveryone committed to democracy,â and again when discussing Americaâs âvirile and popular lovesâ in a brief paean to Walt Whitman (TR, 169; ECC, 60). All other âdemocraticâ Deleuzes are the inventions of his commentators.
Deleuze happily embraces a Marxism so anti-State that it refuses the project of democracy. It is up to us to render his Marxism in darker terms than RanciĂšre, who would rather break down the state through the democratic dissensus of **aesthesis** acting as âthe power of an ontological difference between two orders of realityâ (**Dissensus,** 180). Outright, darkness begins by subverting Negriâs joyous celebration of democracy, which offers a productivist composition of forces as both the conditions of and resolution to capitalism (Ruddick, âPolitics of Affectâ). If Negriism was true, the only thing left for us to do is to âdump the bosses off our backsâ (Hardt, âCommon in Communismâ). But the balance of power is far too ambivalent to make the epochal declaration that a revolutionary subject, such as the multitude, has already been produced and merely needs to be found. Our mad black communism is not a reworking of Marxâs universalism, which is the seamless unity of thought and action that can be found in productivist appeals to immanence as immediate and unmediated, that is to say, automatic (PI, 29; DR, 29). On this account, an a priori communism is too dangerously close to Kant (DI, 60). We have no use for the judgment of a communist **natura,** which comes from the Joyous Deleuziansâ confusion of metaphysics for politics. Neither automatic or automated, our communism is not tempted by the fully automated luxury communism of cybernetics, which is a temptation only from the perspective of control societies. Our communism is nothing but the conspiracy of communism (against ontology). It is the conspiracy to destroy the factory of production. As a conspiracy, communism is a war machine that turns the autoproductive processes of the Real into weapons for destroying any project built on metaphysical consistency. It targets the collusion between the creation of concepts and the reproduction of this world. In this sense, it wages a guerilla struggle against those who joyfully affirm âthe ontology of Deleuze.â It is a conspiracy for at least two reasons: first, it has a penchant for negativity that makes its revolutionary force appear as a conspiracy against everything that the joyful take as a given; second, its inclination toward collective forms of asymmetric struggle sets it wholly at odds with scholarly common sense. It dares any communism worth its name to wage a war of annihilation against God, Man, and the World itself.
Deleuze and Guattariâs âaccelerationismâ has been too tarnished to rehabilitate. The idea was hatched by Nick Land, who held a charismatic influence over the students of the Cybernetic Culture Research Unit at the University of Warwick during the late 1990s. Drawing from Deleuze and Guattariâs insistence on âaccelerating the processâ of capitalist deterritorialization to make a revolutionary breakthrough, Land instead suggests that the commodity system âattains its own âangular momentumââ to become a one-way street impervious to interventions, as it is made up of cosmic-scale processes that are largely blind to human cultural inputs (**Thirst for Annihilation,** 80). For him, the accelerating speed of capital has only one possible conclusion: âa run-away whirlwind of dissolution, whose hub is the virtual zero of impersonal metropolitan accumulationâ that hurls the human animal âinto a new nakedness, as everything stable is progressively liquidated in the stormâ (80). When he initially wrote this position, he left its significance open-ended, only later cashing it out through a neoreactionary project called the âDark Enlightenment.â Land explains that the project is dark because he eagerly adopts a âscaryâ mixture of cognitive elitism, racist social Darwinism, and autocratic Austrian economics. He denounces leftists as theologians of âthe Cathedralâ founded at âGrievance Studies departments of New England universities,â whose appeals to antiracism, democracy, and equality are a type of authoritarian theology.
Commenting later on Williams and Srnicekâs â#Accelerate Manifesto for an Accelerationist Politics,â Land gleefully accuses those leftists who speak favorably about capitalâs destructive forces as âconditional accelerationistsâ (âAnnotated #Accelerate (#3)â). He says that they can only distinguish their position from his own by way of an empty moralism in no position to direct the process. There is perhaps some truth to Landâs criticism of so-called Left Accelerationism as far as they endorse Maoist skepticism for tradition and enthusiasm for productive forces, a social democratic project for a new hegemony, or an intellectual mission of ânew rationalismââall of which seek to mitigate capitalismâs destructive tendencies without outlining real steps to actualize its own future. To substantiate his case, Land argues that âwithin capitalist futures markets, the non-actual has effective currency,â which makes it ânot an âimaginaryâ but an integral part of the virtual body of capitalâ because it is âan operationalized realization of the future,â so âwhile capital has an increasingly densely-realized future, its leftist enemies have only a manifestly pretend oneâ (âAnnotated #Accelerate (#2b)â). The trouble then with either accelerationism is that **neither takes the process far enough,** which is to say, all accelerationism is conditional because it fails to surrender to the outside. As such, Land dresses his fascism up as an athleticism to hide the cowardice of defending the forces of this world, namely, the courthouse of reason, the authority of the market, and a religious faith in technology.
A truly dark path undoes everything that makes up this world. Deleuze and Guattariâs proposal to âaccelerate the processâ follows from R. D. Laingâs clinical prescription for more madness in our âveritable age of Darknessâ (AO, 131). He supports the mad in turning âthe destruction wrecked on themâ into a force of dissolution against the âalienated starting pointâ of normality. This is a method made for breaking with the inside, which âturns in on itselfâ when âpierced by a hole, a lake, a flame, a tornado, an explosion,â so that the outside comes flooding in (132). Such a break can go one of two ways: it can be a breakdown or a breakthrough (239, 132).
The best âbreakthroughâ is âmaking a break for it.â Deleuze is fond of repeating Black Panther George Jackson, who writes from prison that âyes, I can very well escape, but during my escape, Iâm looking for a weaponâ (DI, 277). The phrase applies to far more than Jacksonâs literal imprisonment in San Quentinâwhat he really wanted was liberation from the American capitalist system of racial oppression, which is truly what killed him during his final escape attempt (eleven years into his one-year-to-life indefinite sentence for robbing a gas station for $70). The necessity of weapons should be clear. Even the most terrifying nomadic war machine is overshadowed by the state, which calls its operations âkeeping the peaceâ (as documented by Foucault in his âSociety Must Be Defendedâ lectures and beyond). Such violence has renewed meaning in 2015 as I write in the wake of a white supremacist massacre and as an outcry about racist police violence has finally started to generalize. Jackson stands as a reminder that a revolutionary line of flight must remain active; revolution is not a system-effect, though capitalism as a âsystem leaking all over the placeâ establishes the terrain for ârevolutionary escapeâ (such as a propaganda system that can be infiltrated to attract outside conspirators or a legal system that provides lawyers who can smuggle subversive objects into controlled spaces) (DI, 270). The brilliant guerilla Che wrote the steps for one such dance, the minuet: the guerrillas begin by encircling an advancing column and splitting into a number of âpoints,â each with enough distance to avoid themselves being encircled; a couple pairs off and begins their dance as one of the guerrilla points attacks and draws out the enemy, after which they fall back and a different point attacksâthe goal is not annihilation but to immobilize to the point of fatigue (Guevara, **Guerilla Warfare,** 58â59).
Escapism is the great betrayer of escape. The former is simply âwithdrawing from the social,â whereas the latter learns to âeat away at [the social] and penetrate it,â everywhere setting up âcharges that will explode what will explore, make fall what must fall, make escape what must escapeâ as a ârevolutionary forceâ (AO, 341). The same distinction also holds between two models of autonomy: temporary autonomous zones and zones of offensive opacity. Temporary autonomous zones are momentary bursts of carnivalesque energy that proponent Hakim Bey says âvanish, leaving behind it an empty huskâ when the forces of definition arrive (**Temporary Autonomous Zone,** 100). Deleuze and Guattari suggest, contrary to orthodox Marxists, that societies are defined by how they manage their paths of escape (rather than their modes of production) (TP, 435). As such, âpsychotopologicalâ distance established by temporary autonomous zones does not create a significant enough rupture to open into anything else and thus collapses escape into escape-ism. Tiqqunâs zones of offensive opacity are an improvement, as they oppose a wider web of cybernetic governance without packing maximum intensity into a single moment (Anonymous, âDe lâHypothĂšse CybernĂ©tique,â 334â38). Opacity is its first principle, something they learn from the long tradition of autonomists and anarchists whose most militant factions would refuse all engagement with parliamentary politics, labor and unions, and news media. Offensive orientation is its second principle, though tempered by the famous line from **The Internationale,** âla crosse en lâair,â with the butts of our guns held high in the air: knowing we can take the fight to the trenches, or even take power, but refuse it anyway. Tiqqun is well aware of the difficult history behind the state assassinations of the Black Panther Party and the Red Army Faction, so they know to resist militarization lest they become an army or be liquidated. The advantage of this âstrategic withdrawalâ is autonomy, especially as communism becomes its qualitative guide. Posing communism as oppositional self-determination, it takes the whole social apparatus of capture as its contraryâagainst any temptation to engage the social, for whatever resources offered, arises a demand to be met by a parallel space of communism.
The schizo is dead! Long live the schizo! Schizo culture appealed to a society seized by postwar consumer boredom. âCanât we produce something other than toasters and cars? How about free speech, free school, free love, free verse!â It is no exaggeration to say that the events of May 1968 were sparked by a Situationist intolerance for boredom (âboredom is always counter-revolutionary,â says Guy Debord; âBad Old Days Will End,â 36). In the time since the 1972 publication of **Anti-Oedipus,** capitalism has embraced its schizophrenia through neoliberalism. The schizo has become the paraphilic obsession of Nietzscheâs last man. Its flood of more and more objects has subjects able to muster less and less desire, as seen in the Japanese Lost Decade of stagflation, when a torrent of perversions coincided with a suicide epidemic. The dominant feelings today are probably anxiety or depression (Plan C, âWe Are All Very Anxiousâ). They are expressed as vulnerability in the pervasiveness of trauma, as a constant low-level distress, and through a generalization of contingency. Demonstrating the significance of this shift: âgo play outsideâ is a breath of fresh air to the bored but fails to make the depressive budge. Neoliberalism turns the depressive into the paranoiac through a program of exposure, which unfolds the subject to reveal new surfaces to penetrate. Despite this, the negative project of the process of schizophrenia (âcollapsing a filthy drainage pipeâ) is as necessary as ever (AO, 341). But just as Lenin declared the revolutionary affirmation âAll the power to the Soviets!â counterrevolutionary after a certain time, it is time to retire the slogan âLiberate the flows!â
Militant discussions of infrastructure, blockage, and interruption are refreshingâsince the first âfreeâ laborers threw a shoe in the machine, sabotage has been an important tactic of resistance. But with the elliptical dynamics of capitalism, which poses its own limits only to overcome them for a profit, interruptions cannot be an end unto themselves (230â31). Every economic system is âa system of interruptionsâ that works by breaking down (36â37, 151, 192). One needs to look behind the old social democratic criticism of productivism, âeven pollution, cigarettes, prisons, logging, napalm, and nuclear warheads are counted in the Gross Domestic Production,â to see why (Kennedy, **Remarks at the University of Kansas**). Antiproduction, which prevents specific realizations of value in a systematic way, is âat the heart of production itself, and conditioning this productionâ (235). Potlatch and ritualized warfare are indigenous means of antiproduction that prevent the hoarding that could lead to despotism (Maus, **The Gift**; Clastres, **Society against the State**). Aristocratic glorious expenditure made sure that everything was owed to the king (Bataille, âNotion of Expenditureâ). Marx reminds us that capitalists dip into their own capital stock at the expense of expanded reproduction, but wasting money on the âpoliticalâmilitaryâindustrial complexâ guarantees the smooth advance of the system as a whole (235).
What interruption is revolutionary? The mold was set by Marx, who proposed âexpropriating the expropriatorsâ (**Capital,** chapter 32). âDirect action at the point of productionâ would intervene in the apparatus of capture where the earth, activity, and objects are first coded by the state as territory, work, and money or decoded by capitalism as flows of land, labor, and capital (TP, 437â60). But if âsocieties are determined by their mode of anti-production (and not a mode of production),â then action should be taken at the points of capitalist antiproduction (D, 135). Extending this line of argumentation, the avant-garde taunts the world with a claim: âcapitalism defeated traditional societies because it was more exciting than they were, but now there is something more exciting than capitalism, itself: its destructionâ (Bernadette Corporation, **Get Rid of Yourself**). Though this position is condemned by Leninists as infantile leftism, it is the realization of Deleuze and Guattariâs critique of therapy cultureâclinicians say that one matures out of the depressive position by learning an ambivalent balance of love and hate, which helps delay gratification (Joseph, âProjective Identification,â 99). But is that not the alienation of the worker from the fruits of his labor, Deleuze and Guattari protest, the fundamental separation of a desiring subject from her means of satisfaction (AO, 70â75)? Think of an old German rock song, âMacht Kaputt, Was Euch Kaputt Machtâ by Ton Steine Scherben, an anarchocommunist band connected to the squatter scene and the Red Army Faction (before it went underground). As cheap as it sounds, perhaps the cure for depressive disinterest is the thrill of âdestroying what destroys you.â
âScience does not think,â Heidegger sensationally claims in his 1952 lecture **What Is Called Thinking?** A year later, Gaston Bachelard makes an opposing scandalous assertion in **Le MatĂ©rialisme Rationnel** that âscience does not get the philosophy it deservesâ (20). What science needs, Bachelard says, is a science that produces objects for thought. One such approach is the ânomad scienceâ of **A Thousand Plateaus,** which forms a direct response to Heideggerâs challenge that âwe are still not thinkingâ (**Thinking?,** 6). Nomad science poses problems in clarifying what is really going on in states of affairs (WP, 155â62). In posing better problems, instead of trying to solve them, science invites a range of potential solutions (80â83). âLike a compass, not a blueprint,â the saying goes, which is only useful for those who take the time to learn the terrain. In following some technological lines, humans tend to co-evolve with their technological counterparts, or make an even stronger claim: certain technologies produce new peoples (TP, 404â15). So beyond problems, the science of nomads is more an anthropology (or even a geography). Here it may be helpful to consider Deleuzeâs point about Pascalâs Wager in **Nietzsche and Philosophy,** which he says is not a theological question but an anthropological query about how it would be to live without god. The story about nomad scientists and their cousins, the metallurgical smiths, is mostly a history of their appreciation for the singularities of matter, just as Heidegger says the thinking cabinetmaker does when turning each knot and warp to its advantage.
Deleuze and Guattariâs autopsy of Oedipus demonstrated the need for anthropology. Their method was analytically clear: dissect him with an internal critique of psychoanalysis and then an external of anthropology. From the first, all they could determine was Oedipusâs illegitimate birth, which was already a public secret. It was only through the subsequent historical materialist explanation for Oedipusâs emergence that they could plot his demise. We deserve a new anthropology, especially if we plan to commit an act of sedition against the whole world. It will not be born out of a new Enlightenment. Anthropologyâs Enlightenment father Kant paired anthropology with geography to generate the first scientific classification of race (and white racial superiority) (Bernasconi, âWho Invented the Concept of Race?â). Borrowing from his philosophical work, he lectured on the topic for forty years (1756â97) and published a foundational text, **Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View** (Eze, âColor of Reasonâ). Even anti-Semitic Heidegger knew that reorganizing philosophy along the lines of a succession of psychologies in human history was a grave errorâthough his negative anthropology leaves the door open to the wild phenomenological speculation of Agamben, Stiegler, and Virno (Balibar, âSubjection and Subjectivation,â 2â9). Rather, we need to return to structuralism, if for no other reason than **American anthropology was never (post)structuralist.** Such a provocation is not an attempt to be retro; it is a rejection of the postmodern âreflexive turnâ as thirty years lost to naval gazing (Viveiros de Castro, **Cannibal Metaphysics,** 98â100).
Why not a structuralist political anthropology? Viveiros de Castro says that the opening move would be to shatter anthropology as the âmirror of society,â which is to say, to shift the crosshairs from psychoanalysis to anthropology to write an **Anti-Narcissus** (**Cannibal Metaphysics,** 40â45). There are a few Deleuzian anthropologists who still take seriously the structuralist project of studying the other: Philippe Descola, Eduardo Kohn, Patrice Maniglier, and Eduardo Viveiros de Castro, to name a few. Only with their help can we overturn the mode of production, perhaps learning from the cannibalist ArawetĂ© and TupinambĂĄâs âmetaphysics of predationâ (**Cannibal Metaphysics,** 142â44). Yet even these anthropologists need to get beyond the naturalistâs impulse simply to catalog everything that they see. For even they are struck with their disciplineâs postcolonial guilt and are content to paint their subjectsâ lines of becoming in a connectivist âgeneralized chromaticismâ only a few shades from productivism (45, 161). Like Deleuze and Guattariâs remarks on Freud as the Martin Luther and Adam Smith of psychology, these anthropologists remain imprisoned by their own states of affairsâuntil they produce a body to perform an autopsy, **Anti-Narcissus** pulls its punches. And without a critique, it remains too close to âa bizarre mixture of ontology and anthropology, metaphysics and humanism, theology and atheismâ (NP, 183). Our conspiracy demands more than knowing how the other conditions herself through the enemy, even if it is how they eat each other; it is a communism that wants to consume the flesh and blood of the entire cosmos.
At first blush, nomadism appears pastoral. Deleuzeâs works constitute one great âhorse opera,â as the animals appear in more than half of his published work. One question motivates his obsession: what can a horse do? This is an affective inquiry into their capacities and not their meaning:
take the horse, the apocalyptic beast, as an example: the horse that laughs, in Lawrence; the horse that sticks his head through the window and looks at you, in Kafka; the horse âthat is the sun,â in Artaud; or even the ass that says **YeaYuh,** in Nietzscheâthese are all figures that constitute so many symbols through the building-up of forces, through the constitution of compounds of power. (ECC, 134)
Deleuze chastises Freud for making Little Hansâs fear of horses into an image of the father, when it is really a desire to escape to the street (ECC, 64). Horses appear as the first weapons, whose speed is essential to establishing the asymmetrical relation between nomads and the state (TP, 396). When combined with inventions, such as the stirrup or the photograph, horses generate the peculiar movement of speed through immobilizationâthe voyages in situ of the knight who sleeps on his horse and Muybridgeâs **Sallie Gardner at a Gallop** (D, 74â75; C1, 5â6). They can be the cause of madness, such the public beating of horses that scarred Dostroyevskyâs memory and triggered Nietzscheâs break with reality (TP, 257). Yet there is little of ontological import about the horse itself; it takes âthe earthâ to slow one down through an âartificial reterritorializationâ to give any given horse âa particular substance to the content, a particular code to the utterances, a particular limit to becoming, a particular indicative mood (present, past, future) to timeâ (ECC, 72). As such, the warhorse is far more like a wolf than a workhorse, which is the younger sibling of the ox (TP, 256â57).
The nomads that will dissolve capitalism are not cowboys but barbarians. Not self-attributed but a smear, the term **barbarian** was invented by Hellenistic Greeks as onomatopoeia for the blabber of those who could not speak their language (Padgen, **Fall of Natural Man,** 16). Lacking the capacity for reason, barbarian is used to paint certain foreigners as utterly black and without a single virtue. Not all strangers are vilified by the citizens of empire. Rather, barbarians have two defining characteristics: they refuse to be educated in the language of the **polis** and they act with a savage roughness that exceeds the boundaries of appropriateness (Crisso and Odoteo, **Barbarians,** 40â42). The first jams the usual logocentric means of recognition that would extend them the communal rights of being a human (Padgen, **Fall of Natural Man,** 16); the second banishes them to the uncivilized realm of beasts that lacks decorum, protocol, and restraint (17â18). Nomads are perfectly satisfied with such a one-sided story. What initially appears as an insulting depiction of their limited capacities instead is a definition of how they avoid capture. Barbarians can continue their siege as long as the likes of Hegel, âan honest subject of the Prussian state,â cannot apprehend âa completely autonomous, sovereign, uncompromising oppositionâa multiplicity that does not allow itself to be enrolled in any synthesisâ (Crisso and Odoteo, **Barbarians,** 14). The outside to the new âsocially consciousâ economy, barbarians avoid the liberal trap of tolerance, compassion, and respect. The only risk is that their ferocity will abate and their passion subside.
Cows offer the clearest picture of crowned anarchy, also called ânomadic distributionâ (DR, 41; TP, 158). When set out to pasture, they practice **auto-nomy** by following a self-regulated **nomos,** the customary distribution in open space (âin general an unlimited space; it can be a forest, meadows beside rivers, a mountain slope,â says philologist Emmanuel Laroche on page 116 of his etymological study) that âcrownsâ whatever is unique to each landscape, as in livestock feeding on a particular patch of grass and leaving excrement to fertilize the soil anew. **Nomos** is part of a larger constellation of **nem-** words examined by Laroche, including nomads and distribution **(nomos),** customary law **(nomos),** melody **(nomos),** pasture or sphere of command **(nomos),** roaming (**nomas,** the basis for nomad), pasture **(nemo),** inhabitant **(naetees),** territory **(nemeesis),** governor **(nomarchees),** and law **(nomoi).** Most controversial about Larocheâs argument is his claim that Greek is the only of the Indo-European languages to be pastoral, which casts the Solonic sense of **nomos** as statist distribution as a betrayal of its nomadic roots. Over the generations, **nomos** loses its nomadic heritage to become the administrative appropriation, distribution, and use of land (22â29, 115â24, 178â205). During this time, **nomos** is combined with the household **(oikos)** to name economics; first mentioned by Phocylides in a poem where he compares women to animals: to dogs, bees, free-range pigs, and long-maned horses (Edmonds, **Elegy and Iambus,** 173â74). (Phocylides suggests that his friend marry the bee because she is a good housekeeperâ**oikonomos agathe**; 174.) But Marx shows in chapter 7 of **Capital** that he knows that âwhat distinguishes the worst architect from the best of bees is this, that the architect raises his structure in imagination before he erects it in reality.â Certainly there is a residual speciesism in Marxâs remark, as animalsâ experience of the world **(Umwelt)** is sophisticated enough to produce many things (âart does not wait for human beings to beginâ) (TP, 320). Yet there is a considerable difference in how humans and cows crown the space that they occupy. As such, we should be concerned more by how each constructs the world than by the excrement with which they consecrate it.
Marxâs son-in-law Paul Lafargue demonstrates in his **Social and Philosophical Studies** how **nomos** was turned against the barbarians. Land first âdistributed by lot, with the aid of pebbles,â is set under the watch of Nemesis, the goddess of just distribution (125; Laroche, **Histoire,** 89â106). **Nomos** continues to affirm its groundlessness when it is played like a game of chance at the table of the gods, with the dice affirming aleatory points that fracture the sky and fall back to a broken earth (DR, 284). Lafargue posits that the great betrayal appears when justice, born out of equality, sanctions the inequalities of land distributed by right and not luck (**Social and Philosophical Studies,** 133â34, 129â30). No longer the protector of nomads, Nemesis inflicts the death penalty âagainst those who menace propertyâ for the purpose of âteaching the barbarians to trample under foot their noble sentiments of equality and brotherhoodâ (130â31). Lafargue thus demands a communist revolution that suppresses private property to banish âthe most frightful nightmare which ever tortured sad civilized humanity,â the idea of nomic justice (134).
There are two outsides to the state: one a worldwide union, the other a fragmented resistance (TP, 381). To Deleuze and Guattari, this exteriority demonstrates the irreducibility of the **nomos** to the law. If there is anything to this notion, it is not found in a form of exteriority but in the fact of the outsideâthat there will always be nondenumerable groups (469â73), that there are flows that even the best axiomatic can never master (468â69), and that power now produces more than it can repress (F, 28â29). This is the true meaning of âdeterritorializationâ and âthe infinite speed of thoughtââeach concept confirms the extraordinary powers of the outside (AO, 105; WP, 21, 35â38, 42). The difficulty is that âone cannot write sufficiently in the name of an outsideâ because it âhas no image, no signification, no subjectivityâ (TP, 23). How then to link with the outside? The simplest way is to fashion a war machine as a relation to the outside (TP, 376â77). Another path to âa new relation to the outsideâ may be found in a fissured planet that spews fires that consume the world (DI, 156, 158â59). Such deterritorializations unleash movements that âcease to be terrestrialâ when âthe religious Nome blooms and dissolvesâ and âthe singing of the birds is replaced by combinations of water, wind, clouds, and fogâ (TP, 327).
The outside appears like Frankensteinâs monster, with a crack of lightning late into the dreary night while the atomistâs rain patters away from the outside. Its darkness does not come from void worship or an existentialist reckoning with nothingness. Flashing brilliantly as a shock to thought, it appears as the âbearer of a problemâ that paints the world black with dread (DR, 140). This movement grounds thought as âthe relationship with the outsideâ (DI, 255). Exteriority here is not some transcendent light or yawning void. Rather, the outside opens out to a new milieu, like cracking the window in a house. The outside is seldom as pleasant as a breeze, however, as it invades in all its alien force. Thought here has a choice, to represent or intensify; the latter follows Paul Kleeâs famous formula: ânot to render the visible, but to render visibleâ (FB, 144). It amplifies the impinging power of the outside to cause a horrible discord that splits apart the harmonies of reason sung in the halls of state thought (DI, 259â60). Such philosophy does not sing, it screams in the analogical language of âexpressive movements, paralinguistic signs, breathsâ (FB, 93). The outside howls with an âopen mouth as a shadowy abyssâ (51).
âThe revolutionary was molecular, and so was the counter-revolution,â Tiqqun prophetically declares (**Introduction to Civil War,** 200). Yet the âmolecular revolutionâ actually begins with Proust, who writes in **Sodom and Gomorrah** of three levels of sexuality: straights, gays, and queers. The first two types connect âmolarâ lines between fixed objects, each category simply being an inversion of the other (AO, 68â71). The third draws a âtransversalâ molecular line between the unspecified, partial, and flux of flows âunaware of persons, aggregates, and laws, and of images, structures, and symbolsâ (70â71, 311). For a long time, the love that dare not speak its name hid with other queer things made up of âvery different mechanisms, thresholds, sites, and observersâ (WP, 78). But counterculture exposed the secret, which is to say, disclosed a molecular line of previously clandestine passions while blossoming into the flower power of the Summer of Love publicly consecrated at Woodstockâs Three Days of Peace, Music, and Love. This new world bore what Paolo Virno calls in **Grammar of the Multitude** the liberatory âanti-socialist demandsâ of âradical criticism of labor,â âan accentuated taste for differencesâ and âthe aptitude (at times violent, certainly) for defending oneself from the State, for dissolving the bondage to the State as suchâ (111). But the life of this molecular line was short. It was put back to work by disco, flexible production, and the Reagan revolution in an odd âcommunism of capitalâ (111).
The cataclysm is not an end but a new beginning, the cataclysm of a temporary hell, âitself the effect of an elementary injusticeâ that sweeps in and out, rather than being an abysmal lake of sulfur where souls burn forever (ECC, 46). It is the apocalypse before its decadent transformation into the system of Judgment (39). Only a revival of this cataclysmic event can end the apocalypse of an âalready industrialized organizationâ that appeared âa Metropolisâ by way of âthe great military, police, and civil security of a new Stateâ with a âprogrammed self-glorificationâ complemented by a âdemented installation of an ultimate judiciary and moral powerâ (44, 46). We know from Nietzscheâs **Gay Science** that the impending cataclysm of âbreakdown, destruction, ruinâ may appear gloomy (279). And it will certainly cover the earth in a blackness darker than the world has ever seen (279). Yet we should greet it with cheer. For the cataclysm brings with it a new dawn worthy of our highest expectations. Though the daybreak may not be bright, we will have escaped the judgment of God, Man, and the World. âAt long last our ships may venture out again, venture out to face any danger,â because âthe sea, **our** sea, lie open againâ ... âperhaps there has never yet been such an âopen seaââ (280).
Bodies are a well-composed image of power. The body of God (the Sacrament of Jesus). The body of a saint (the pierced corpse of the martyr). The body of the sovereign (the Kingâs two bodies). The body of the tyrant (Big Brotherâs face). The social body (the body politic). A body of evidence (the stateâs case). The idea of society or the world functioning as an organism is well sedimented. In its stupidest form, it posits a resemblance between the human body and society. Just as various organisms interact to form an organism as a functional whole, it states, society is the cooperation of various social organs. The body provides an image for the much-talked-about âbody without organs,â the great inspiration for Deleuze, who says that if we are to believe in the world, âgive me a body thenâ (C2, 189).
The body is not really the enemy, the organism is. Some would have bodies appear through their opposites, locked in eternal combatâas the sinner and their Eternal Savior, the regicide and the King, the criminal and the Law (TP, 108). But as an organism, the body is put to use for extracting âuseful labor,â either as a product of work (where organs are connected to the technical machines of the capitalism) or self-reproduction (where organs are connected to the social machines of the species) (AO, 54). The image of the body as an organism might appear as a step forward, as it invokes a form of ecological thinking of interconnected systems. But we are only interested in the body as a frustrating set of resistances, âobstinate and stubborn,â as it âforces us to think, and forces us to think what is concealed from thought, lifeâ (C2, 189). This is why it is said that âwe do not even know what a body can do.â But with the relative ease in which the body has been confused for an organism, perhaps it is time to abandon the image of the body completely. Stop thinking like lawyers, who try cases only after a body has been found. There is a simple reason: the point is not to construct a body without organs (organization, organism, ...) but organs without a body. We only get outside the productivist logic of accumulation when âat last the disappearance of the visible body is achievedâ (C2, 190).
Against the stateâs body of evidence: âThe âtrue worldâ does not exist,â and even if it did, âit would be inaccessible, impossible to describe, and, if it could be described, would be useless, superfluousâ (C2, 137). The conspiracy against this world begins with time, which âputs truth in crisisâ (130). This is the fundamental problem of the âbody of the lawâ described by Derrida whereby the law must continually rule against what it previously established as the truth (and thus its own authority) (âForce of Lawâ). It is these moments that reveal an in-effectivity of the truthâdenouncing states, nations, or races as fictions does little to dislodge their power, however untrue the historical or scientific justifications for them might be (Seshadri, **Desiring Whiteness**). The state is nothing but these â**not-necessarily true pasts,**â the founding mythologies that fictionalize the origin of states and nations of people (C2, 131). This is the power generated only between the true and the false: what Deleuze calls âthe real.â The importance of the real is central, as trying to use truth to dispute the false does not work: those who denounce the illegal violence used to found legal orders are quickly dismissed or jailed, and the many climate scientists who harangue the public about the truth of global warming fail to spur policy change.
Cinema âtakes up the problem of truth and attempts to resolve it through purely cinematic meansâ (Lambert, **Non-philosophy,** 93). There are films that go beyond metaphor and analogy, operating instead through a realism of the false. This is not the epic cinema of Brecht or Lang, whose dissimulation and relativism ultimately return the morality of judgment through the viewer. It is a realism of what escapes the body, presenting something it cannot perceive on its ownânot different worlds but realities that exist in the present (though not currently lived) that confirm reality by weakening it. Deleuze finds that the elusive truth of postwar cinema does not prevent the existence of a âtruthful manâ but the âforgerâ as the character of new cinema (C2, 132). The forger refuses the moral origins of truth and frustrates the return to judgment (C2, 138â39). The realism of the false shows us love through the eyes of a serial killer (Grandrieuxâs **Sombre**), gives us the real thrill of self-destruction (Gavrasâs **Our Day Will Come**), unleashes the cruelty of nature against the cool logic of liberal patriarchy (von Trierâs **Anti-Christ**), and solicits us in the horrifying conspiracies of a new flesh (Cronenbergâs **Videodrome**).
The senses think when the boundary between the imaginary and the real collapses. This is what happens whenever the suspension of disbelief continues outside the frame (C2, 169). But the suspension carries on only as long as it is not whittled down to a narrow proposition through âinfinite specificationâ (DR, 306). It expands by establishing a âdistinct yet indiscernibleâ proximity (TP, 279â80, 286). In this strange zone of indiscernibility, figuration recedesâit is right before our eyes, but we lose our ability to clarify the difference between a human body, a beast, and meat (FB, 22â27). There is no mystical outside, just the unrelenting intrusion of âthe fact that we are not yet thinkingâ (C2, 167). This is because experience is itself not thought but merely the provocation to thinkâa reminder of the insufferable, the impossibility of continuing the same, and the necessity of change.
âKnowledge is not made for understanding; it is made for cutting,â says Foucault (âNietzsche, Genealogy, History,â 88). Neither is sense. The best sense is a sensation, a provocation, that introduces insufficiency (L, 50â58). So instead of adequate conceptions, we spread insufficient sensations. This insufficiency does not carry the weight of inevitability. It may begin with a petulant indecisiveness, such as Bartlebyâs âI would prefer not to,â but it must not end there. The greatest danger is that indecision consumes us and we become satisfied for one reason or another, withering like Bartleby in jail cells of our own making. Our communism demands that we actively conspire under the cover of the secret; for there is nothing more active than the Death of the World. Our hatred propels us. Just as âan adventure that erupts in sedentary groupsâ through âthe call of the outside,â our sense that the world is intolerable is what compels us to build our own barbarian siege engines to attack the new Metropolis that stands in Judgment like a Heaven on Earth (DI, 259).
AS A PROLEGOMENA to any future negativity in Deleuze, this book risks being too condensed. The moves I make are quick, and many will appear perverse to friends of the Joyous Deleuze. For justification: the force of thought is a matter of style and not the specification of concepts, or to use proper names, Nietzsche contra Kant (DR, 5, 13, 306). I therefore build my case through formulations that are ârigorous yet anexactâ like Deleuzeâs, whose âessentially not accidentally inexactâ concepts modulate enough between books to deserve different names (TP, 367, 555). I promote minor terms through extensive footnotes generated through a deep reading of Deleuze across the breadth of his complete works. So on one hand, I am so indebted to Deleuze that one could say that I merely provide a new nomenclature for old Deleuzian concepts. On the other, this is a book that Deleuze himself could never have written, as his age was not one of obligatory positivity, distributed management, and stifling transparency. My basic argument is that a new untimeliness in a time not Deleuzeâs own requires a negative project that his work introduces but does not sustain: the Death of this World.
The end of this world is the third in a succession of deathsâthe Death of God, the Death of Man, and now the Death of this World. This is not a call to physically destroy the world. The Death of God did not call for the assault of priests or the burning of churches, and the Death of Man did not propose genocide or the extinction of our species. Each death denounces a concept as insufficient, critiques those who still believe in it, and demands its removal as an object of thought. In the Death of Man, we learned that the human sciences were impotent in the face of the systemic injustices of this world. Rather, Foucault shows how expert inquiry makes exploitation, sexism, racism, poverty, violence, and war into the constitutive elements of how humanity defends itself. He shows that attempts to save this humanity created a biopower that âmakes live and lets die,â which paradoxically administers life through âa power to expose a whole population to deathâ that tends toward wars of all-out destruction (Foucault, **History of Sexuality,** 135â37). Elaborating on this condition, subsequent theorists say that we have already been killed but have not yet died, making us an âalready deadâ that makes us already ready to adopt a revolutionary orientation that sacrifices our current time and space for a new, not-yet-realized future (Cazdyn, **Already Dead,** 9). Seen from this perspective, runaway climate change, the Sixth Extinction, and many other impending catastrophes are all essential parts of this world. The Death of this World admits the insufficiency of previous attempts to save it and instead poses a revolutionary gamble: only by destroying this world will we release ourselves of its problems. This does not mean moving to the moon, but that we give up on all the reasons given for saving the world. In my own announcement of the death of this world, I propose critiques of connectivity and positivity, a theory of contraries, the exercise of intolerance, and the conspiracy of communism.
Contemporary Deleuze scholarship tends to be connectivist and productivist. Connectivism is the world-building integration into an expanding web of things. As an organizational logic, it is the promiscuous inclusion of seemingly unrelated elements into a single body to expand its capacities. Academics are not alone in endorsing connectivismâI argue that connectivism drives Googleâs geopolitical strategy of global influence, which proceeds through a techno-affirmationist desire to annex everything. Commentators use different names for their webs of connections, such as rhizomes, assemblages, networks, material systems, or **dispositifs**. I simply call them âthis worldâ and plot for its destruction. Productivism links up with the autonomous, ceaseless autoproduction of the real. The most naive productivists sentimentally cherish creation and novelty for their own sake, whether as dewy-eyed admiration for the complexity of nature or a staunch Voltairine defense of all types of diversity. The productivists worthy of criticism are those who, in the name of âfinding something about this world to believe in,â affirm what is given as if this wretched world already included all materials for a better one. I find that in relinquishing the power of destruction, they can only capitalize on production through the logics of accumulation and reproduction. So in founding a new world on the terms of the old, its horizon expands barely beyond what already exists. The alternative I propose is finding reasons to destroy this world.
The greatest crime of joyousness is tolerance. While mentioning tolerance may have marked one as a radical in Deleuzeâs time, Wendy Brown argues in **Regulating Aversion** that liberal tolerance is now essential to the grammar of empireâs âdomestic discourse of ethnic, racial, and sexual regulation, on the one hand, and as an international discourse of Western supremacy and imperialism on the otherâ (1, 7). Todayâs tolerant are to blame for a âliberal Deleuze,â such as William Connolly, who names Deleuze as an antirevolutionary who inspires his belief that âtransformation is neither needed nor in the cards today; what is needed is creative modes of **intervention** posed at several strategic sites in the service of reducing economic inequality, foster intra- and inter-state pluralism, and promoting ecological sanityâ in his book on pluralism (**Pluralism,** 159). Deleuze criticized a similar position many decades ago when denouncing the media-hungry form of the **Nouveaux Philosophes,** who had âinscribed themselves perfectly well on the electoral grid ... from which everything fades awayâ (âOn the New Philosophers,â 40â41). Liberal Deleuzians can be criticized accordinglyâfor endorsing the usual abstractions of the Law and the State that hide the workings of power; for denouncing Marxism ânot so much because real struggles would have made new enemies, new problems and new means arise, but because THE revolution must be declared impossibleâ; and for reviving the subject as part of a general martyrology. What stands between liberalism and revolution is intolerance, but in a peculiar way. Intolerance arises out of this world as âsomething intolerable in the worldâ to prove that there is âsomething unthinkable in thoughtâ (C2, 169). Which is to say, it is when we find it all unbearable that we realize âit can no longer think a world or think itselfâ (170). This is where the Dark Deleuze parts ways with the joyful by inviting the death of this world. There are many fellow travelers of revolutionary intolerance, including Wendy Brown and Herbert Marcuse. Newton argues in his autobiography **Revolutionary Suicide** that the revolutionary task is to risk oneâs life for the chance of âchanging intolerable conditionsâ (5). In his essay on ârepressive tolerance,â Marcuse extends tolerance only to the left, subversion, and revolutionary violence and proposes a militant intolerance of the right, this world, and âbenevolent neutrality.â Together, they express the dark truth of the intolerable as the lived present of being trapped by something so unbearable, so impossible, that it must be destroyed. To be completely clear: the point is not to grow obstinate but to find new ways to end our suffocating perpetual present.
Darkness advances the secret as an alternative to the liberal obsession with transparency. Foucault smartly identifies transparencyâs role in the âscience of the police,â which is used in the task of maintaining order through the collusion between the state and capital from liberalismâs beginnings in the German notion of the police state through to contemporary biopolitics (**Security, Territory, Population**). The conspiracy is against the consistency of everything being in its proper place, and the secret is the fact that nothing is as it seems. Such a conspiracy is not the pursuit of the ineffable or sublime, as it is neither esoteric nor mystical. It circulates as an open secret that retains its secrecy only by operating against connectivism through the principle of selective engagement. The lesson to be taken is that âwe all must live double livesâ: one full of the compromises we make with the present, and the other in which we plot to undo them. The struggle is to keep oneâs cover identity from taking over. There are those whose daily drudgery makes it difficult to contribute to the conspiracy, though people in this position are far more likely to have secret dealings on the side. Others are given ample opportunities but still fail to grow the secret, the most extreme example being those who live their lives âwith nothing to hide,â often declaring that they are âan open book.â Some treat the conspiracy as a form of hobbyism, working to end the world only after everything else has been taken care ofâthe worst being liberal communists, who exploit so much in the morning that they can give half of it back as charity in the afternoon. And then there are those who escape. Crafting new weapons while withdrawing from the demands of the social, they know that cataclysm knows nothing of the productivist logic of accumulation or reproduction. Escape need not be dreary, even if they are negative. Escape is never more exciting than when it spills out into the streets, where trust in appearances, trust in words, trust in each other, and trust in this world all disintegrate in a mobile zone of indiscernibility (Fontaine, âBlack Blocâ). It is in these moments of opacity, insufficiency, and breakdown that darkness most threatens the ties that bind us to this world.
Thanks to Mark Purcell, Keith Harris, Cheryl Gilge, and everyone at the University of Washington for the opportunity to write this book. I am grateful for critical feedback from Alex Galloway, Geert Lovink, Jose Rosales, Matt Applegate, Alejandro de Acosta, and an anonymous reviewer. Finally, I am indebted to the numerous people who stood beside me at the intellectual and political barricades throughout the project, perhaps too numerous to name, except for one: Eva Della Lana.
<biblio>
Althusser, Louis. **Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings, 1978â1987**. 1993/1994. Translated by G. M. Goshgarian. Edited by Oliver Corpet and François Matheron. New York: Verso, 2006.
Anonymous. âDe lâHypothĂšse CybernĂ©tique.â **Tiqqun** 2 (2001): 223â339.
Anonymous. âMay 1968 Graffiti.â In **Bureau of Public Secrets,** translated by Ken Knabb. 2006. [[http://www.bopsecrets.org/CF/graffiti.htm][http://www.bopsecrets.org/CF/graffiti.htm]].
Bachelard, Gaston. **Le Matérialisme Rationnel**. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1953.
Badiou, Alain. âAlthusser: Subjectivity without a Subject.â 1998. In **Metapolitics,** translated by Jason Barker, 58â67. New York: Verso, 2005.
Balibar, Ătienne. âSubjection and Subjectivation.â In **Supposing the Subject,** edited by Joan Copjec, 1â15. New York: Verso, 1994.
â. **The Philosophy of Marx**. 1993. Translated by Chris Turner. New York: Verso, 1995.
Bataille, Georges. âThe Notion of Expenditure.â 1933. In **Visions of Excess: Selected Writings, 1927â1939,** translated by Allan Stoekl, Carl R. Lovin, and Donald M. Leslie Jr., 167â81. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985.
Bernadette Corporation, dir. **Get Rid of Yourself**. New York: Electronic Arts Intermix, 2003.
Bernasconi, Robert. âWho Invented the Concept of Race? Kantâs Role in the Enlightenment Construction of Race.â In **Race,** edited by Robert Bernasconi, 11â36. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2001.
Bey, Hakim. **The Temporary Autonomous Zone, Ontological Anarchy, Poetic Terrorism**. 2nd ed. Brooklyn, N.Y.: Autonomedia, 2003.
Brown, Wendy. **Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire**. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
<em>Buiness Insider</em>. âGoogle Chairman: âThe Internet Will Disappear.ââ 2015. [[http://www.businessinsider.com/google-chief-eric-schmidt-the-internet-will-disappear-2015-1][http://www.businessinsider.com/google-chief-eric-schmidt-the-internet-will-disappear-2015-1]].
Butler, Samuel. **Erewhon: or, Over the Range**. 1872. London: AC Fifield, 1910. [[http://www.gutenberg.org/files/1906/1906-h/1906-h.htm][http://www.gutenberg.org/files/1906/1906-h/1906-h.htm]].
Cazdyn, Eric. **The Already Dead: The New Time of Politics, Culture, and Illness**. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2012.
Chaplin, Charlie, dir. **Modern Times**. New York: Criterion Collection, 1936.
Clastres, Pierre. **Society against the State**. 1974. Translated by Robert Hurley and Abe Stein. New York: Zone Books, 1987.
Cohen, Jared, and Eric Schmidt. **The New Digital Age: Reshaping the Future of People, Nations, and Business**. New York: Doubleday, 2013.
Connolly, William E. **Pluralism**. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2005.
Crisso and Odoteo. **Barbarians: The Disordered Insurgence**. Anonymous translation. 2003. [[http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/crisso-and-odoteo-barbarians-the-disordered-insurgence.pdf][http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/crisso-and-odoteo-barbarians-the-disordered-insurgence.pdf]].
Debord, Guy. âThe Bad Old Days Will End.â 1963. In **Leaving the 20<sup>th</sup> Century: The Incomplete Work of the Situationist International,** translated by Christopher Gray, 33â37. London: Rebel Press, 1998.
DeLanda, Manuel. **Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy**. London: Continuum, 2002.
Deleuze, Gilles. **Cinema 1: The Movement-Image**. 1983. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986.
â. **Cinema 2: The Time-Image**. 1985. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989.
â. **Desert Islands and Other Texts, 1953â1974**. 2002. New York: Semiotext(e), 2004.
â. **Difference and Repetition**. 1968. Translated by Paul Patton. New York: Columbia University Press, 1994.
â. **Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Humeâs Theory of Human Nature**. 1953. Translated by Constantin V. Boundas. New York: Columbia University Press, 1995.
â. **Essays Critical and Clinical**. 1993. Translated by Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Greco. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997.
â. **Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza**. 1968. Translated by Martin Joughin. New York: Zone Books, 1990.
â. **The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque**. 1988. Translated by Tom Conley. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993.
â. **Foucault**. 1986. Translated by SeĂĄn Hand. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988.
â. **Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation**. 1981. Translated by Daniel W. Smith. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2005.
â. **Logic of Sense**. 1969. Translated by Mark Lester, with Charles Stivale. Edited by Constantin V. Boundas. New York: Columbia University Press, 1990.
â. **Negotiations: 1972â1990**. 1990. Translated by Martin Joughin. New York: Columbia University Press, 1995.
â. **Nietzsche and Philosophy**. 1962. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson. New York: Columbia University Press, 2006.
â. âOn the New Philosophers and a More General Problem.â Interview with Bertrand Augst. Translated by Bertrand Augst. **Discourse** 20, no. 3 (1998): 34â43.
â. **Proust and Signs**. 1964. Translated by Richard Howard. London: Continuum, 2000.
â. **Pure Immanence: A Life**. 1995. Translated by Anne Boyman. New York: Zone Books, 2001.
â. **Spinoza: Practical Philosophy**. 1970. Translated by Robert Hurley. San Francisco: City Lights Books, 1988.
â. **Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975â1995**. 2001. Translated by Amed Hodges and Mike Taormina. Edited by David Lapoujade. Los Angeles, Calif.: Semiotext(e), 2007.
Deleuze, Gilles, and FĂ©lix Guattari. **Anti-Oedipus**. 1972. Translated by Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1977.
â. **Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature**. 1975. Translated by Dana Polan. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986.
â. **A Thousand Plateaus**. 1980. Translated by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987.
â. **What Is Philosophy?** 1991. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell. New York: Columbia University Press, 1994.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Claire Parnet. 1977. **Dialogues 2,** rev. ed., translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. New York: Columbia University Press, 2007.
Derrida, Jacques. âForce of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority.â 1989. In **Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice,** edited by Drucilla Cornell et al., 3â66. New York: Routledge, 1992.
Dumézil, Georges. **Mitra-Varuna: An Essay on Two Indo-European Representations of Sovereignty**. 1984. Translated by Derek Coltman. New York: Zone Books, 1988.
Edelman, Lee. **No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive**. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2004.
Edmonds, John Maxwell. **Elegy and Iambus, Being the Remains of All the Greek Elegiac and Iambic Poets from Callinus to Crates, Excepting the Choliambic Writers, with the Anacreontea**. Vol. 1. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1931.
Eze, Emmanuel Chudwuki. âThe Color of Reason: The Idea of âRaceâ in Kantâs Anthropology.â In **Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader,** edited by Emmanuel Chudwuki Eze, 103â31. Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell, 1997.
Flaxman, Gregory. **Gilles Deleuze and the Fabulation of Philosophy**. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2011.
â. âPolitics and Ontology: A Review of Nathan Widder: **Political Theory after Deleuze**.â **Postmodern Culture** 24, no. 2 (2014), [[https://muse.jhu.edu/article/580775][https://muse.jhu.edu/article/580775]].
Flint, Jim. âMichel Serresâ Angels: A Modern Myth.â **Mute** 1, no. 4 (1996). [[http://www.metamute.org/editorial/articles/michel-serres-angels-modern-myth][http://www.metamute.org/editorial/articles/michel-serres-angels-modern-myth]].
Fontaine, Claire. âThis Is Not the Black Bloc.â 2007. [[http://www.clairefontaine.ws/pdf/black_bloc_eng.pdf][http://www.clairefontaine.ws/pdf/black_bloc_eng.pdf]].
Foucault, Michel. **History of Sexuality, Volume 1: An Introduction**. Translated by Robert Hurley. New York: Pantheon Books, 1978.
â. âNietzsche, Genealogy, History.â 1971. In **Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews,** translated by Donald F. Bouchard and Sherry Simon, 113â38. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1977.
â. **Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the CollĂšge de France 1977â1978**. 2004. Translated by Graham Burchell. Edited by Michel Senellart. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007.
â. **âSociety Must Be Defendedâ: Lectures at the CollĂšge de France, 1975â1976**. 1997. Translated by David Macey. New York: Picador, 2003.
â. âTheatrum Philosophicum.â **Critique** 282 (1970): 885â908.
Galloway, Alexander R. **Protocol: How Control Exists after Decentralization**. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2004.
Galloway, Alexander R., and Eugene Thacker. **The Exploit: A Theory of Networks**. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2007.
Gingrich, Owen, and Albert van Helden, âFrom **Occhiale** to Printed Page: The Making of Galileoâs **Sidereus Nuncius**.â **Journal for the History of Astronomy** 34, no. 116 (2003): 251â67.
Grosz, Elizabeth. **Becoming Undone: Darwinian Reflections on Life, Politics, and Art**. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2011.
Guevara, Ernesto âChe.â **Guerilla Warfare**. 1960. Translated by J. P. Morray. Oxford: SR Books, 1997.
Halperin, David, and Valerie Traub. âBeyond Gay Pride.â In **Gay Shame,** 3â40. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009.
Hardt, Michael. âThe Common in Communism.â 2010. [[http://seminaire.samizdat.net/IMG/pdf/Microsoft_Word_-_Michael_Hardt.pdf][http://seminaire.samizdat.net/IMG/pdf/Microsoft_Word_-_Michael_Hardt.pdf]].
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. **Empire**. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000.
Heidegger, Martin. **What Is Called Thinking?** 1952. Translated by J. Glenn Gray. New York: Perennial, 1976.
Hevelii, Johannis. **Selenographia sive Lunae Descriptio**. Gdansk, 1647.
Holloway, John. âThe Scream.â In **Change the World without Taking Power: The Meaning of Revolution Today,** 1â10. London: Pluto Press, 2002.
Invisible Committee. **To Our Friends**. 2014. Translated by Robert Hurley. Los Angeles, Calif.: Semiotext(e), 2015.
Joseph, Betty. âProjective Identification: Some Clinical Aspects.â In **Projective Identification: The Fate of a Concept,** edited by Elizabeth Spillius and Edna OâShaughnessy, 98â111. New York: Routledge, 2012.
Kafka, Franz. **The Trial**. 1925. Translated by Willa and Edwin Muir. New York: Schocken, 1956.
Kant, Immanuel. **Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View**. 1798. Translated by Robert B. Louden. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Kauffman, Stuart. **Reinventing the Sacred: A New View of Science, Reason, and Religion**. New York: Basic Books, 2008.
Kauffman, Stuart, Teppo Felin, Roger Koppl, and Giuseppe Longo. âEconomic Opportunity and Evolution: Beyond Landscapes and Bounded Rationality.â **Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal** 8, no. 4 (2014): 269â82.
Kennedy, Robert F. **Remarks at the University of Kansas**. March 18, 1968.
Kissinger, Henry. âThe Vietnam Negotiations.â **Foreign Affairs** 48, no. 2 (1969): 211â34.
Klossowski, Pierre. âCirculus Vitiosus.â Translated by Joseph Kuzma. **The Agonist: A Nietzsche Circle Journal** 2, no. 1 (2009): 31â47.
â. **Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle**. 1969. Translated by Daniel W. Smith. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997.
Kopal, ZdenÄk. **The Moon**. Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel, 1969.
Kubrick, Stanley, dir. **Clockwork Orange**. Burbank, Calif.: Warner Bros. Pictures, 1971.
Lafargue, Paul. **Social and Philosophical Studies**. Translated by Charles H. Kerr. Chicago: Charles H. Kerr, 1910.
Lambert, Gregg. **The Non-philosophy of Gilles Deleuze**. London: Continuum, 2002.
Land, Nick. âAnnotated #Accelerate (#2b).â **Urban Future** 2, no. 1 (2014). [[http://www.ufblog.net/on-accelerate-2b][http://www.ufblog.net/on-accelerate-2b]].
â. âAnnotated #Accelerate (#3).â **Urban Future** 2, no. 1 (2014). [[http://www.ufblog.net/annotated-accelerate-3/][http://www.ufblog.net/annotated-accelerate-3/]].
â. âThe Dark Enlightenment.â In **The Dark Enlightenment**. 2013. [[http://www.thedarkenlightenment.com/the-dark-enlightenment-by-nick-land/][http://www.thedarkenlightenment.com/the-dark-enlightenment-by-nick-land/]].
â. **Thirst for Annihilation: George Bataille and Virulent Nihilism**. London: Routledge, 1992.
Lang, Fritz, dir. **Metropolis**. 1927. New York: Kino Video, 2004.
Laroche, Emmanuel. **Histoire de la Racine âNem-â en Grec Ancien**. Paris: Librairie C. Klincksieck, 1949.
LĂŒbke, Wilhelm. **Ecclesiastical Art in Germany during the Middle Ages**. 1852. Translated by I. A. Wheatley. London: Cassell, Petter, and Galpin, 1871.
Luke, Timothy W. **Ecocritique: Contesting the Politics of Nature, Economy, and Culture**. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997.
Lyotard, Jean-François. **Libidinal Economy**. 1974. Translated by Iain Hamilton Grant. London: Athlone, 2004.
Marcuse, Herbert. âRepressive Tolerance.â In **A Critique of Pure Tolerance,** 81â117. Boston: Beacon Press, 1965.
Marx, Karl. **Capital: A Critique of Political Economy**. Vol. 1. Translated by Ben Fowkes. Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin, 1976.
â. âRuthless Criticism.â Letter to Arnold Ruge, September 1843. In **Marx Engelâs Collected Works,** 3. [[https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/letters/43_09.htm][https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/letters/43_09.htm]].
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. **Manifesto of the Community Party**. 1848. Translated by Samuel Moore and Friedrich Engels. 2000. [[https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1848/communist-manifesto/ch01.htm][https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1848/communist-manifesto/ch01.htm]].
Maus, Marcel. **The Gift: The Form and Reason for Exchange in Archaic Societies**. 1950. Translated by W. D. Hallis. New York: Routledge, 1990.
Meillassoux, Quentin. **After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency**. 2006. Translated by Ray Brassier. London: Continuum, 2008.
Muybridge, Eadweard, dir. **Sallie Gardner at a Gallop**. 1878.
Newton, Huey. **Revolutionary Suicide**. New York: Writers and Readers, 1973.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. **The Gay Science**. 1887. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books, 1974.
â. **On the Genealogy of Morality**. 1887. Translated by Carol Diethe. Edited by Keith Ansell-Pearson. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
â. **Untimely Meditations**. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. Edited by Daniel Breazeale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Orwell, George. **1984.** New York: Penguin, 1949.
Padgen, Anthony. **The Fall of Natural Man: The American Indian and the Origins of Comparative Ethnology**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Plan C. âWe Are All Very Anxious.â April 4, 2014. [[http://www.weareplanc.org/blog/we-are-all-very-anxious/][http://www.weareplanc.org/blog/we-are-all-very-anxious/]].
Proust, Marcel. âCities of the Plainâ [alternative title to âSodom and Gomorrahâ]. 1921. In **Remembrance of Things Past** [alternative title to **In Search of Lost Time**], translated by C. K. Scott Moncrieff, 3â378. New York: Random House, 1932.
RanciĂšre, Jacques. **Dissensus: On Politics and Aesthetics**. Edited and translated by Steven Corcoran. London: Continuum, 2010.
Rice, Condoleezza. **No Higher Honor**. New York: Broadway, 2011.
Rimbaud, Arthur. âA Season in Hell.â 1873. Translated by A. S. Kline. [[http://www.poetryintranslation.com/PITBR/French/Rimbaud3.htm#anchor_Toc202003798][http://www.poetryintranslation.com/PITBR/French/Rimbaud3.htm#anchor_Toc202003798]].
Ruddick, Susan. âThe Politics of Affect: Spinoza in the Work of Negri and Deleuze.â **Theory, Culture, Society** 27, no. 4 (2010): 21â45.
Schumpeter, Joseph Alois. 1942. **Capitalism, Socialism, Democracy**. New York: Harper and Row, 1950.
Serres, Michel. **Angels, a Modern Myth**. Paris: Flammarion, 1995.
Seshadri, Kalpana Rahita (formerly Seshadri-Crooks). **Desiring Whiteness: A Lacanian Analysis of Race**. London: Routledge, 2000.
Spanos, William V. âThe Question of Philosophy and **Poiesis** in the Posthistorical Age: Thinking/Imagining the Shadow of Metaphysics.â **Boundary 2** 27, no. 1 (2000): 151â74.
Spence-Jones, Henry Donald Maurice. **Early Christianity and Paganism, a.d. 64 to the Peace of the Church in the Fourth Century**. London: Cassell, 1902.
Spinoza, Benedict de. **Ethics**. 1677. Translated by Edwin Curley. New York: Penguin, 2005.
Stengers, Isabelle. **In Catastrophic Times: Resisting the Coming Barbarism**. Translated by Andrew Goffey. London: Open Humanities Press.
Tiqqun. **Introduction to Civil War**. 2001. Translated by Alexander R. Galloway and Jason E. Smith. Los Angeles, Calif.: Semiotext(e), 2010.
Unknown. âEssay upon Crypts.â **The Crypt: or, Receptacle for Things Past** 6 (September 1829): 73â77.
Virno, Paolo. **Grammar of the Multitude: For an Analysis of Contemporary Forms of Life**. 2003. Translated by Isabella Bertoletti, James Cascaito, and Andrea Casson. New York: Semiotext(e), 2004.
Viveiros de Castro, Eduardo. **Cannibal Metaphysics: For a Post-structural Anthropology**. 2009. Translated by Peter Skafish. Minneapolis, Minn.: Univocal, 2014.
Williams, Alex, and Nick Srincek. â#Accelerate Manifesto for an Accelerationist Politics.â **Critical Legal Thinking**. 2013, [[http://criticallegalthinking.com/2013/05/14/accelerate-manifesto-for-an-accelerationist-politics/][http://criticallegalthinking.com/2013/05/14/accelerate-manifesto-for-an-accelerationist-politics/]].
ĆœiĆŸek, Slavoj. âThe Ongoing âSoft Revolution.ââ **Critical Inquiry** 30, no. 2 (2004): 292â323.
â. **The Sublime Object of Ideology**. New York: Verso, 1989.
Zourabichvili, François. **Gilles Deleuze: A Philosophy of the Event**. 1994. Translated by Kieran Aarons. Edited by Gregg Lambert and Daniel W. Smith. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2012.
</biblio>>