đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș murray-bookchin-what-is-social-ecology captured on 2024-08-18 at 20:34:14. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-03-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: What is Social Ecology? Date: 1993 Source: *Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology*, edited by M.E. Zimmerman, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1993. Partial transcription retrieved on 2019-08-26 from [[http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/Anarchist_Archives/bookchin/socecol.html][dwardmac.pitzer.edu/Anarchist_Archives/bookchin/socecol.html]] Notes: This text was substantially revised for [[http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/murray-bookchin-social-ecology-and-communalism#toc2][*Social Ecology and Communalism* (2006)]]. First time readers are encouraged to read the 2006 version. Authors: Murray Bookchin Topics: Green anarchism, Social ecology, Ecology Published: 2021-11-26 06:56:28Z
<right>
Murray Bookchin has long been a major figure in anarchlst
and utopian political theory, theory of technology,
urbanism, and the philosophy of nature. He is the
cofounder and director emeritus of the Institute for
Social Ecology. His many books include *Toward an
Ecological Society*, *The Ecology of Freedom*, *The Rise of
Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship*, *Remaking
Society*, and *The Philosophy of Social Ecology*.
</right>
----
What literally defines social ecology as âsocialâ is its recognition of the often overlooked fact that nearly all our present ecological problems arise from deep-seated social problems. Conversely, present ecological problems cannot be clearly understood, much less resolved, without resolutely dealing with problems within society. To make this point more concrete: economic, ethnic, cultural, and gender conflicts, among many others, lie at the core of the most serious ecological dislocations we face todayâapart, to be sure, from those that are produced by natural catastrophes.
If this approach seems a bit too âsociologicalâ for those environmentalists who identify ecological problems with the preservation of wildlife, wilderness, or more broadly, with âGaiaâ and planetary âOneness,â it might be sobering to consider certain recent facts. The massive oil spill by an Exxon tanker at Prince William Sound, the extensive deforestation of redwood trees by the Maxxam Corporation, and the proposed James Bay hydroelectric project that would flood vast areas of northern Quebecâs forests, to cite only a few problems, should remind us that the real battleground on which the ecological future of the planet will be decided is clearly a social one.
Indeed, to separate ecological problems from social problemsâor even to play down or give token recognition to this crucial relationship â would be to grossly misconstrue the sources of the growing environmental crisis. The way human beings deal with each other as social beings is crucial to addressing the ecological crisis. Unless we clearly recognize this, we will surely fail to see that the hierarchical mentality and class relationships that so thoroughly permeate society give rise to the very idea of dominating the natural world.
Unless we realize that the present market society, structured around the brutally competitive imperative of âgrow or die,â is a thoroughly impersonal, self-operating mechanism, we will falsely tend to blame technology as such or population growth as such for environmental problems. We will ignore their root causes, such as trade for profit, industrial expansion, and the identification of âprogressâ with corporate self-interest. In short, we will tend to focus on the symptoms of a grim social pathology rather than on the pathology itself, and our efforts will be directed toward limited goals whose attainment is more cosmetic than curative.
While some have questioned whether social ecology has dealt adequately with issues of spirituality, it was, in fact, among the earliest of contemporary ecologies to call for a sweeping change in existing spiritual values. Such a change would mean a far-reaching transformation of our prevailing mentality of domination into one of complementarity, in which we would see our role in the natural world as creative, supportive, and deeply appreciative of the needs of nonhuman life. In social ecology, a truly **natural** spirituality centers on the ability of an awakened humanity to function as moral agents in diminishing needless suffering, engaging in ecological restoration, and fostering an esthetic appreciation of natural evolution in all its fecundity and diversity.
Thus social ecology has never eschewed the need for a radically new spirituality or mentality in its call for a collective effort to change society. Indeed, as early as 1965, the first public statement to advance the ideas of social ecology concluded with the injunction: âThe cast of mind that today organizes differences among human and other life-forms along hierarchical lines of âsupremacyâ or âinferiorityâ will give way to an outlook that deals with diversity in an ecological manner--that is, according to an ethics of complementarity.â[1] In such an ethics, human beings would complement nonhuman beings with their own capacities to produce a richer, creative, and developmental wholeânot as a âdominantâ species but as a supportive one. Although this idea, expressed at times as an appeal for the ârespiritization of the natural world,â recurs throughout the literature of social ecology, it should not be mistaken for a theology that raises a deity above the natural world or that seeks to discover one within it. The spirituality advanced by social ecology is definitively naturalistic (as one would expect, given its relation to ecology itself, which stems from the biological sciences), rather than supernaturalistic or pantheistic.
To prioritize any form of spirituality over the social factors that actually erode all forms of spirituality, raises serious questions about oneâs ability to come to grips with reality. At a time when a blind social mechanism, the market, is turning soil into sand, covering fertile land with concrete, poisoning air and water, and producing sweeping climatic and atmospheric changes, we cannot ignore the impact that a hierarchical and class society has on the natural world. We must earnestly deal with the fact that economic growth, gender oppressions, and ethnic dominationânot to speak of corporate, state, and bureaucratic interestsâare much more capable of shaping the future of the natural world than are privatistic forms of spiritual self-regeneration. These forms of domination must be confronted by collective action and major social movements that challenge the social sources of the ecological crisis, not simply by personalistic forms of consumption and investment that often go under the rubric of âgreen capitalism.â We live in a highly cooptative society that is only too eager to find new areas of commercial aggrandizement and to add ecological verbiage to its advertising and customer relations.
Let us begin, then, with basicsânamely, by asking what we mean by nature and society. Among the many definitions of nature that have been formulated over time, one is rather elusive and often difficult to grasp because it requires a certain way of thinkingâone that stands at odds with what we popularly call âlinear thinking.â This form of ânonlinearâ or organic thinking is developmental rather than analytical, or, in more technical terms, dialectical rather than instrumental. Nature, conceived in terms of developmental thinking, is more than the beautiful vistas we see from a mountaintop or in the images that are fixed on the backs of picture postcards. Such vistas and images of nonhuman nature are basically static and immobile. Our attention, to be sure, may be arrested by the soaring flight of a hawk, or the bolting leap of a deer, or the low-slung shadowy loping of a coyote. But what we are really witnessing in such cases are the mere kinetics of physical motion, caught in the frame of an essentially static image of the scene before our eyes. It deceives us into believing in the âeternalityâ of a single moment in nature.
If we look with some care into nonhuman nature as more than a scenic view, we begin to sense that it is basically an evolving phenomenon, a richly fecund, even dramatic development that is forever changing. I mean to define nonhuman nature precisely as an evolving process, as the **totality**, in fact of its evolution. This encompasses the development from the inorganic into the organic, from the less differentiated and relatively limited world of unicellular organisms into that of multicellular ones equipped with simple, later complex, and presently fairly intelligent neural apparatuses that allow them to make innovative choices. Finally, the acquisition of warm-bloodedness gives to organisms the astonishing flexibility to exist in the most demanding climatic environments.
This vast drama of nonhuman nature is in every respect stunningly wondrous. It is marked by increasing subjectivity and flexibility and by increasing differentiation that makes an organism more adaptable to new environmental challenges and opportunities and renders a living being more equipped to alter its environment to meet its own needs. One may speculate that the potentiality of matter itselfâthe ceaseless interactivity of atoms in forming new chemical combinations to produce ever more complex molecules, amino acids, proteins, and, under suitable conditions, elementary life-formsâis inherent in inorganic nature. Or one may decide, quite matter-of-factly, that the âstruggle for existenceâ or the âsurvival of the fittestâ (to use popular Darwinian terms) explains why increasingly subjective and more flexible beings are capable of dealing with environmental changes more effectively than are less subjective and flexible beings. But the fact remains that the kind of evolutionary drama I have described did occur, and is carved in stone in the fossil record. That nature is this record, this history, this developmental or evolutionary process, is a very sobering fact.
Conceiving nonhuman nature as its own evolution rather than as a mere vista has profound implicationsâethical as well as biologicalâfor ecologically minded people. Human beings embody, at least potentially, attributes of nonhuman development that place them squarely within organic evolution. They are not ânatural aliens,â to use Neil Everndenâs phrase, strange âexotics,â phylogenetic âdeformitiesâ that, owing to their tool-making capacities, âcannot evolve with an ecosystem anywhere.â[2] Nor are they âintelligent fleas,â to use the language of Gaian theorists who believe that the earth (âGaiaâ) is one living organism.[3] These untenable disjunctions between humanity and the evolutionary process are as superficial as they are potentially misanthropic. Humans are highly intelligent, indeed, very self-conscious primates, which is to say that they have emergedânot divergedâfrom a long evolution of vertebrate life-forms into mammalian, and finally, primate life-forms. They are a product of a significant evolutionary trend toward intellectuality, self-awareness, will, intentionality, and expressiveness, be it in oral or body language.
Human beings belong to a natural continuum, no less than their primate ancestors and mammals in general. To depict them as âaliensâ that have no place or pedigree in natural evolution, or to see them essentially as an infestation that parasitizes a highly anthropomorphic version of the planet (Gaia) the way fleas parasitize dogs and cats, is bad thinking, not only bad ecology. Lacking any sense of process, this kind of thinkingâregrettably so commonplace among ethicistsâradically bifurcates the nonhuman from the human. Indeed, to the degree that nonhuman nature is romanticized as âwilderness,â and seen presumably as more authentically ânaturalâ than the works of humans, the natural world is frozen into a circumscribed domain in which human innovation, foresight, and creativity have no place and offer no possibilities.
The truth is that human beings not only belong in nature, they are products of a long, natural evolutionary process. Their seemingly âunnaturalâ activitiesâlike the development of technology and science, the formation of mutable social institutions, of highly symbolic forms of communication, of esthetic sensibilities, the creation of towns and citiesâall would be impossible without the large array of physical attributes that have been eons in the making, be they large brains or the bipedal motion that frees their hands for tool making and carrying food. In many respects, human traits are enlargements of nonhuman traits that have been evolving over the ages. Increasing care for the young, cooperation, the substitution of mentally guided behavior for largely instinctive behaviorâall are present more keenly in human behavior. The difference between the development of these traits among nonhuman beings is that among humans they reach a degree of elaboration and integration that yields cultures or, viewed institutionally in terms of families, bands, tribes, hierarchies, economic classes, and the state, highly mutable societies for which there is no precedent in the nonhuman worldâunless the genetically programmed behavior of insects is to be regarded as âsocial.â In fact, the emergence and development of human society is a shedding of instinctive behavioral traits, a continuing process of clearing a new terrain for potentially rational behavior.
Human beings always remain rooted in their biological evolutionary history, which we may call âfirst Nature,â but they produce a characteristically human social nature of their own which we may call âsecond nature.â And far from being âunnatural,â human second nature is eminently a creation of organic evolutionâs first nature. To write the second nature created by human beings out of nature as a whole, or indeed, to minimize it, is to ignore the creativity of natural evolution itself and to view it onesidedly. If âtrueâ evolution embodies itself simply in creatures like grizzly bears, wolves, and whalesâgenerally, animals that **people** find esthetically pleasing or relatively intelligentâthen human beings are literally **de**-natured. In such views, whether seen as âaliensâ or as âfleas,â humans are essentially placed outside the self-organizing thrust of natural evolution toward increasing subjectivity and flexibility. The more enthusiastic proponents of this de-naturing of humanity may see human beings as existing apart from nonhuman evolution, thereby dealing with people as a âfreaking,â as Paul Shepard puts it, of the evolutionary process. Others simply avoid the problem of humanityâs unique place in natural evolution by promiscuously putting human beings on a par with beetles in terms of their âintrinsic worth.â In this âeither/orâ propositional thinking, the social is either separated from the organic, or flippantly reduced to the organic, resulting in an inexplicable dualism at one extreme or a naive reductionism at the other. The dualistic approach, with its quasi-theological premise that the world was âmadeâ for human use is saddled with the name of âanthropocentricity,â while the reductionist approach, with its almost meaningless notion of a âbiocentric democracy,â is saddled with the name of âbiocentricity.â
The bifurcation of the human from the nonhuman reveals a failure to think organically, and to approach evolutionary phenomena with an evolutionary way of thought. Needless to say, if we are content to regard nature as no more than a scenic vista, mere metaphoric and poetic description of it might suffice to replace systematic thinking about it. But if we regard nature as the history of nature, as an evolutionary process that is going on to one degree or another under our very eyes, we dishonor this process by thinking of it in anything but a processual way. That is to say, we require a way of thinking that recognizes that âwhat-isâ as it seems to lie before our eyes is always developing into âwhat-it-is-not,â that it is engaged in a continual self-organizing process in which past and present, seen as a richly differentiated but shared continuum, give rise to a new potentiality for a future, ever-richer degree of **wholeness**. Accordingly, the human and the nonhuman can be seen as aspects of an evolutionary continuum, and the emergence of the human can be located in the evolution of the nonhuman, without advancing naive claims that one is either âsuperior toâ or âmade forâ the other.
By the same token, in a processual, organic, and dialectical way of thinking, we would have little difficulty in locating and explaining the emergence of the social out of the biological, of second nature out of first nature. It seems more fashionable these days to deal with ecologically significant social issues like a bookkeeper. One simply juxtaposes two columnsâlabeled âold paradigmâ and ânew paradigmââas though one were dealing with debits and credits. Obviously distasteful terms like âcentralizationâ are placed under âold paradigm,â while more appealing ones like âdecentralizationâ are regarded as ânew paradigm.â The result is an inventory of bumper-sticker slogans whose âbottom lineâ is patently a form of âabsolute good versus absolute evil.â All of this maybe deliciously synoptic and easy for the eyes, but it is singularly lacking as food for the brain. To truly know and be able to give interpretative **meaning** to the social issues so arranged, we should want to know how each idea derived from others and is part of an overall development. What, in fact, do we mean by the notion of âdecentralization,â and how does it derive from or give rise in the history of human society to âcentralizationâ? Again: processual thinking is needed to deal with processual realities so that we can gain some sense of **direction**âpractical as well as theoreticalâin dealing with our ecological problems.
Social ecology seems to stand alone, at present, in calling for the use of organic, developmental, and derivative ways of thinking out problems that are basically organic and developmental in character. The very definition of the natural world as a development indicates the need for an organic way of thinking, as does the derivation of human from nonhuman natureâa derivation that has the most far-reaching consequences for an ecological ethics that can offer serious guidelines for the solution of our ecological problems.
Social ecology calls upon us to see that nature and society are interlinked by evolution into one nature that consists of two differentiations: first or biotic nature, and second or human nature. Human nature and biotic nature share an evolutionary potential for greater subjectivity and flexibility. Second nature is the way in which human beings as flexible, highly intelligent primates inhabit the natural world. That is to say, people create an environment that is most suitable for their mode of existence. In this respect, second nature is no different from the environment that **every** animal, depending upon its abilities, creates as well as adapts to, the biophysical circumstancesâor ecocommunityâin which it must live. On this very simple level, human beings are, in principle, doing nothing that differs from the survival activities of nonhuman beingsâbe it building beaver dams or gopher holes.
But the environmental changes that human beings produce are significantly different from those produced by nonhuman beings. Humans act upon their environments with considerable technical foresight, however lacking that foresight may be in ecological respects. Their cultures are rich in knowledge, experience, cooperation, and conceptual intellectuality; however, they may be sharply divided against themselves at certain points of their development, through conflicts between groups, classes, nation states, and even city-states. Nonhuman beings generally live in ecological niches, their behavior guided primarily by instinctive drives and conditioned reflexes. Human societies are âbondedâ together by institutions that change radically over centuries. Nonhuman communities are notable for their fixity in general terms or by clearly preset, often genetically imprinted, rhythms. Human communities are guided in part by ideological factors and are subject to changes conditioned by those factors.
Hence human beings, emerging from an organic evolutionary process, initiate, by the sheer force of their blology and survival needs, a social evolutionary development that profoundly involves their organic evolutionary process. Owing to their naturally endowed intelligence, powers of communication, capacity for institutional organization, and relative freedom from instinctive behavior, they refashion their environmentâas do nonhuman beingsâto the full extent of their biological equipment. This equipment now makes it possible for them to engage in social development. It is not so much that human beings, in principle, behave differently from animals or are inherently more problematical in a strictly ecological sense, but that the social development by which they grade out of their biological development often becomes more problematicai for themselves and non human life. How these problems emerge, the ideologies they produce, the extent to which they contribute to biotic evolution or abort it, and the damage they infiict on the planet as a whole lie at the very heart of the modern ecological crisis. Second nature, far from marking the fulfillment of human potentialities, is riddled by contradictions, antagonisms, and conflicting interests that have distorted humanityâs unique capacities for development. It contains both the danger of tearing down the biosphere and, given a further development of humanity toward an ecological society, the capacity to provide an entirely new ecological dispensation.
How, then, did the socialâeventually structured around status groups, class formations, and cultural phenomenaâemerge from the biological? We have reason to speculate that as biological facts such as lineage, gender distribution, and age differences were slowly institutionalized, their uniquely social dimension was initially quite egalitarian. Later it acquired an oppressive hierarchical and then an exploitative class form. The lineage or blood tie in early prehistory obviously formed the organic basis of the family. Indeed, it joined together groups of families into bands, clans, and tribes, through either intermarriage or fictive forms of descent, thereby forming the earliest social horizon of our ancestors. More than in other mammals, the simple biological facts of human reproduction and protracted maternal care of the infant tended to knit siblings together and produced a strong sense of solidarity and group inwardness. Men, women, and their children were brought into a condition of a fairly stable family life, based on mutual obligation and an expressed sense of affinity that was often sanctified by marital vows of one kind or another.
Outside the family and all its elaborations into bands, clans, tribes and the like, other human beings were regarded as âstrangers,â who could alternatively be welcomed hospitably or enslaved or put to death. What mores existed were based on an unreflected body of **customs** that seemed to have been inherited from time immemorial. What we call **morality** began as the commandments of a deity, in that they required some kind of supernatural or mystical reinforcement to be accepted by the community. Only later, beginning with the ancient Greeks, did **ethical** behavior emerge, based on rational discourse and reflection. The shift from blind custom to a commanding morality, and finally, to a rational ethics occurred with the rise of cities and urban cosmopolitanism. Humanity, gradually disengaging itself from the biological facts of blood ties, began to admit the âstrangerâ and increasingly recognize itself as a shared community of human beings rather than an ethnic folkâa community of citizens rather than of kinsmen.
In the primordial and socially formative world that we must still explore, other of humanityâs biological traits were to be reworked from the strictly natural to the social. One of these was the fact of age and its distinctions. In the emerging social groups that developed among early humans, the absence of a written language helped to confer on the elderly a high degree of status, for it was they who possessed the traditional wisdom of the community, the kinship lines that prescribed marital ties in obedience to extensive incest taboos, and techniques for survival that had to be acquired by both the young and the mature members of the group. In addition, the biological fact of gender distinctions were to be slowly reworked along social lines into what were initially complementary sororal and fraternal groups. Women formed their own food-gathering and care taking groups with their own customs, belief systems, and values, while men formed their own hunting and warrior groups with their own behavioral characteristics, mores, and ideologies.
From everything we know about the socialization of the biological facts of kinship, age, and gender groupsâtheir elaboration into early institutionsâthere is no reason to doubt that people existed in a complementary relationship with one another. Each, in effect, was needed by the other to form a relatively stable whole. No one âdominatedâ the others or tried to privilege itself in the normal course of things. Yet with the passing of time, even as the biological facts that underpin every human group were further reworked into social institutions, so the social institutions were slowly reworked at various periods and in various degrees, into hierarchical structures based on command and obedience. I speak here of a historical trend, in no way predetermined by any mystical force or deity, a trend that often did not go beyond a very limited development among many preliterate or aboriginal cultures, and even in certain fairly elaborate civilizations. Nor can we foretell how human history might have developed had certain feminine values associated with care and nurture not been overshadowed by masculine values associated with combative and aggressive behavior.
Hierarchy in its earliest forms was probably not marked by the harsh qualities it has acquired over history. Elders, at the very beginnings of gerontocracy, were not only respected for their wisdom but often beloved of the young, and their affection was often reciprocated in kind. We can probably account for the increasing stridency and harshness of later gerontocracies by supposing that the elderly, burdened by their failing powers and dependent upon the communityâs goodwill, were more vulnerable to abandonment in periods of material want than any other part of the population. In any case, that gerontocracies were the earliest forms of hierarchy is corroborated by their existence in communities as far removed from each other as the Australian Aborigines, tribal societies in East Africa, and Indian communities in the Americas. âEven in simple food-gathering cultures, individuals above fifty, let us say, apparently arrogated to themselves certain powers and privileges which benefitted themselves specifically,â observes anthropologist Paul Radin, âand were not necessarily, if at all, dictated by considerations either of the rights of others or the welfare of the community.â[4] Many tribal councils throughout the world were really councils of elders, an institution that never completely disappeared (as the word âaldermanâ suggests), even though they were overlaid by warrior societies, chiefdoms, and kingships.
Patricentricity, in which male values, institutions, and forms of behavior prevail over female ones, seems to have followed gerontocracy. Initially, this shift may have been fairly harmless, inasmuch as preliterate and early aboriginal societies were largely domestic communities in which the authentic center of material life was the home, not the âmenâs houseâ so widely present in tribal societies. Male rule, if such it can be strictly called, takes on its most severe and coercive form in patriarchy, an institution in which the eldest male of an extended family or clan has a life-and-death command over all members of the group. Women are by no means the exclusive or even the principal target of the patriarchâs domination. The sons, like the daughters, may be ordered how to behave and whom to marry and may be killed at the whim of the âold man.â So far as patricentricity is concerned, however, the authority and prerogative of the male are the product of a slow, often subtly negotiated development in which the male fraternity tends to edge out the female sorority by virtue of the formerâs growing âcivilâ responsibilities. Increasing population, marauding bands of outsiders whose migrations may be induced by drought or other unfavorable conditions, and vendettas of one kind or another, to cite common causes of hostility or war, create a new âcivilâ sphere side by side with womanâs domestic sphere, and the former gradually encroaches upon the latter. With the appearance of cattle-drawn plow agriculture, the male begins to invade the horticultural sphere of woman, who had used the simple digging stick, and her earlier economic predominance in the communityâs life is thereby diluted. Warrior societies and chiefs carry the momentum of male dominance to the level of a new material and cultural constellation. Male dominance becomes extremely active and ultimately yields a world that is managed by male elites who dominate not only women but also other men.
âWhyâ hierarchy emerges is transparent enough: the infirmities of age, increasing population, natural disasters, certain technological changes that privilege male activities of hunting and caring for animals over the horticultural functions of females, the growth of civil society, the spread of warfare. All serve to enhance the maleâs responsibilities at the expense of the femaleâs. Marxist theorists tend to single out technological advances and the presumed material surpluses they produce to explain the emergence of elite strataâindeed, of exploiting ruling classes. However, this does not tell us why many societies whose environments were abundantly rich in food never produced such strata. That surpluses are necessary to support elites and classes is obvious, as Aristotle pointed out more than two millennia ago. But too many communities that had such resources at their disposal remained quite egalitarian and never âadvancedâ to hierarchical or class societies.
It is worth emphasizing that hierarchical domination, however coercive it may be, is not to be confused with class exploitation. Often the role of high-status individuals is very well-meaning, as in the case of commands given by caring parents to their children, of concerned husbands and wives to each other, or of elderly people to younger ones. In tribal societies, even where a considerable measure of authority accrues to a chiefâand most chiefs are advisers rather than rulersâhe usually must earn the esteem of the community by interacting with the people, and he can easily be ignored or removed from his position by them. Many chiefs earn their prestige, so essential to their authority, by disposing of gifts, and even by a considerable disaccumulation of their personal goods. The respect accorded to many chiefs is earned, not by hoarding surpluses as a means to power but by disposing of them as evidence of generosity.
Classes tend to operate along different lines. Power is usually gained by the acquisition of wealth, not by its disposal; rulership is guaranteed by outright physical coercion, not simply by persuasion; and the state is the ultimate guarantor of authority. That hierarchy is more entrenched than class can perhaps be verified by the fact that women have been dominated for millennia, despite sweeping changes in class societies. By the same token, the abolition of class rule and economic exploitation offers no guarantee whatever that elaborate hierarchies and systems of domination will disappear.
In nonhierarchical and even some hierarchical societies, certain customs guide human behavior along basically decent lines. Of primary importance in early customs was the âlaw of the irreducible minimumâ (to use Radinâs expression), the shared notion that all members of a community are entitled to the means of life, irrespective of the amount of work they perform. To deny anyone food, shelter, and the basic means of life because of infirmities or even frivolous behavior would have been seen as a heinous denial of the very right to live. Nor were the resources and things needed to sustain the community ever completely privately owned: overriding individualistic control was the broader principle of usufructâthe notion that the means of life that were not being used by one group could be used, as need be, by another. Thus unused land, orchards, and even tools and weapons, if left idle, were at the disposition of anyone in the community who needed them. Lastly, custom fostered the practice of mutual aid, the rather sensible cooperative behavior of sharing things and labor, so that an individual or family in fairly good circumstances could expect to be helped by others if their fortunes should change for the worse. Taken as a whole, these customs became so sedimented into society that they persisted long after hierarchy became oppressive and class society became predominant.
âNature,â in the broad sense of a biotic environment from which humans take the simple things they need for survival, often has no meaning to preliterate peoples. Immersed in nature as the very universe of their lives it has no special meaning, even when they celebrate animistic rituals and view the world around them as a nexus of life, often imputing their own social institutions to the behavior of various species, as in the case of âbeaver lodgesâ and humanlike spirits. Words that express our conventional notions of nature are not easy to find, if they exist at all, in the languages of aboriginal peoples.
With the rise of hierarchy and human domination, however, the seeds are planted for a belief that nature not only exists as a world apart, but that it is hierarchically organized and can be dominated. The study of magic reveals this shift clearly. Early forms of magic did not view nature as a world apart. Its worldview tended to be such that a practitioner essentially pleaded with the âchief spiritâ of the game to coax an animal in the direction of an arrow or a spear. Later, magic becomes almost entirely instrumental; the game is coerced by magical techniques to become the hunterâs prey. While the earliest forms of magic may be regarded as the practices of a generally nonhierarchical and egalitarian community, the later forms of animistic beliefs betray a more or less hierarchical view of the natural world and of latent human powers of domination.
We must emphasize, here, that the idea of dominating nature has its primary source in the domination of human by human and the structuring of the natural world into a hierarchical Chain of Being (a static conception, incidentally, that has no relationship to the evolution of life into increasingly advanced forms of subjectivity and flexibility). The biblical injunction that gave to Adam and Noah command of the living world was above all an expression of a **social** dispensation. Its idea of dominating nature can be overcome only through the creation of a society without those class and hierarchical structures that make for rule and obedience in private as well as public life. That this new dispensation involves changes in attitudes and values should go without saying. But these attitudes and values remain vaporous if they are not given substance through objective institutions, the ways in which humans concretely interact with each other, and in the realities of everyday life from childrearing to work and play. Until human beings cease to live in societies that are structured around hierarchies as well as economic classes, we shall never be free of domination, however much we try to dispel it with rituals, incantations, ecotheologies, and the adoption of seemingly ânaturalâ ways of life.
The idea of dominating nature has a history that is almost as old as that of hierarchy itself. Already in the Gilgamesh Epic of Mesopotamia, a drama that dates back some 7,000 years, the hero defies the deities and cuts down their sacred trees in his quest for immortality. The Odyssey is a vast travelogue of the Greek warrior, albeit a more canny than a heroic one, who essentially dispatches the nature deities that the Hellenic world inherited from its less well-known precursors. That elitist societies devastated much of the Mediterranean basin as well as the hillsides of China provides ample evidence that hierarchical and class societies had begun a sweeping remaking and despoliation of the planet long before the emergence of modern science, âlinearâ rationality, and âindustrial society,â to cite causal factors that are invoked so freely in the modern ecology movement. Second nature, to be sure, did not create a Garden of Eden in steadily absorbing and inflicting harm on first nature. More often than not, it despoiled much that was beautiful, creative, and dynamic in the biotic world, just as it ravaged human life itself in murderous wars, genocide, and acts of heartless oppression. Social ecology refuses to ignore the fact that the harm elitist society inflicted on the natural world was more than matched by the harm it inflicted on humanity; nor does it overlook the fact that the destiny of human life goes hand-in-hand with the destiny of the nonhuman world.
But the customs of the irreducible minimum, usufruct, and mutual aid cannot be ignored, however troubling the ills produced by second nature may seem. These customs persisted well into history and surfaced almost explosively in massive popular uprisings, from early revolts in ancient Sumer to the present time. Many of those demanded the recovery of caring and communitarian values when these were under the onslaught of elitist and class oppression. Indeed, despite the armies that roamed the landscape of warring areas, the tax-gatherers who plundered ordinary village peoples, and the daily abuses that were inflicted by overseers on workers, community life still persisted and retained many of the cherished values of a more egalitarian past. Neither ancient despots nor feudal lords could fully obliterate them in peasant villages and in the towns with independent craft guilds. In ancient Greece, religions based on austerity and, more significantly, a rational philosophy that rejected the encumbering of thought and political life by extravagant wants, tended to scale down needs and delimit human appetites for material goods. They served to slow the pace of technological innovation to a point where new means of production could be sensitively integrated into a balanced society. Medieval markets were modest, usually local affairs, in which guilds exercised strict control over prices, competition, and the quality of the goods produced by their members.
But just as hierarchies and class structures tend to acquire a momentum of their own and permeate much of society, so too the market began to acquire a life of its own and extended its reach beyond limited regions into the depths of vast continents. Exchange ceased to be primarily a means to provide for modest needs, subverting the limits imposed upon it by guilds or by moral and religious restrictions. Not only did it place a high premium on techniques for increasing production; it also became the procreator of needs, many of which are simply useless, and gave an explosive impetus to consumption and technology. First in northern Italy and the European lowlands, laterâand most effectivelyâin England during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the production of goods exclusively for sale and profit (the capitalistic commodity) rapidly swept aside all cultural and social barriers to market growth.
By the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, the new industrial capitalist class with its factory system and commitment to limitless expansion began to colonize the entire world, and finally, most aspects of personal life. Unlike the feudal nobility, which had its cherished lands and castles, the bourgeoisie had no home but the marketplace and its bank vaults. As a class, they turned more and more of the world into an ever-expanding domain of factories. Entrepreneurs of the ancient and medieval worlds had normally gathered their profits together to invest in land and live like country gentryâgiven the prejudices of their times against âill-gottenâ gains from trade. On the other hand, the industrial capitalists of the modern world spawned a bitterly competitive marketplace that placed a high premium on industrial expansion and the commercial power it conferred, and functioned as though growth were an end in itself.
It is crucially important, in social ecology, to recognize that industrial growth does not result from a change in a cultural outlook alone, and least of all, from the impact of scientific rationality on society. It stems above all from harshly objective factors churned up by the expansion of the market itself, factors that are largely impervious to moral considerations and efforts at ethical persuasion. Indeed, despite the close association between capitalist development and technological innovation, the most driving imperative of the capitalist market, given the dehumanizing competition that defines it, is the need to grow, and to avoid dying at the hands of savage rivals. Important as greed or the power conferred by wealth may be, sheer survival requires that an entrepreneur must expand his or her productive apparatus to remain ahead of other entrepreneurs and try, in fact, to devour them. The key to this law of life-to survival-is expansion, and greater profit, to be invested in still further expansion. Indeed, the notion of progress, once identified by our ancestors as a faith in the evolution of greater human cooperation and care, is now identified with economic growth.
The effort by many well-intentioned ecology theorists and their admirers to reduce the ecological crisis to a cultural rather than a social problem can easily become obfuscatory. However ecologically concerned an entrepreneur may be, the harsh fact is that his or her very survival in the marketplace precludes a meaningful ecological orientation. To engage in ecologically sound practices places a morally concerned entrepreneur at a striking, and indeed, fatal disadvantage in a competitive relationship with a rivalânotably one who lacks any ecological concerns and thus produces at lower costs and reaps higher profits for further capital expansion.
Indeed, to the extent that environmental movements and ideologies merely moralize about the âwickednessâ of our anti-ecological society, and emphasize change in personal life and attitudes, they obscure the need for social action. Corporations are skilled at manipulating this desire to be present as an ecological image. Mercedes-Benz, for example, declaims in a two-page ad, decorated with a bison painting from a Paleolithic cave wall, that âwe must work to make more environmentally sustainable progress by including the theme of the environment in the planning of new products.â[5] Such deceptive messages are commonplace in Germany, one of western Europeâs worst polluters. Advertising is equally self-serving in the United States, where leading polluters piously declare that for them, âEvery day is Earth Day.â
The point social ecology emphasizes is not that moral and spiritual change is meaningless or unnecessary, but that modern capitalism is structurally amoral and hence impervious to any moral appeals. The modern marketplace has imperatives of its own, irrespective of who sits in the driverâs seat or grabs on to its handlebars. The direction it follows depends not upon ethical factors but rather on the mindless âlawsâ of supply and demand, grow or die, eat or be eaten. Maxims like âbusiness is businessâ explicitly tell us that ethical, religious, psychological, and emotional factors have absolutely no place in the impersonal world of production, profit, and growth. It is grossly misleading to think that we can divest this brutally materialistic, indeed, mechanistic, world of its objective character, that we can vaporize its hard facts rather than trans forming it.
A society based on âgrow or dieâ as its all-pervasive imperative must necessarily have a devastating ecological impact. Given the growth imperative generated by market competition, it would mean little or nothing if the present-day population were reduced to a fraction of what it is today. Insofar as entrepreneurs must always expand if they are to survive, the media that have fostered mindless consumption would be mobilized to increase the purchase of goods, irrespective of the need for them. Hence it would become âindispensableâ in the public mind to own two or three of every appliance, motor vehicle, electronic gadget, or the like, where one would more than suffice. In addition, the military would continue to demand new, more lethal instruments of death, of which new models would be required annually.
Nor would âsofterâ technologies produced by a grow-or-die market fail to be used for destructive capitalistic ends. Two centuries ago, the forests of England were hacked into fuel for iron forges with axes that had not changed appreciably since the Bronze Age, and ordinary sails guided ships laden with commodities to all parts of the world well into the nineteenth century. Indeed, much of the United States was âclearedâ of its forests, wildlife, soil, and aboriginal inhabitants with tools and weapons that would have been easily recognized, however much they were modified, by Renaissance people who had yet to encounter the Industrial Revolution. What modern technics did was to accelerate a process that was well under way at the close of the Middle Ages. It did not devastate the planet on its own; it abetted a phenomenon, the ever-expanding market system that had its roots in one of historyâs most fundamental social transformations: the elaboration of hierarchy and class into a system of distribution based on exchange rather than complementarity and mutual aid.
Social ecology is an appeal not only for moral regeneration but also, and above all, for social reconstruction along ecological lines. It emphasizes that an ethical appeal to the powers that be (that embody blind market forces and competitive relationships), taken by itself, is likely to be futile. Indeed, taken by itself, it often obscures the real power relationships that prevail today by making the attainment of an ecological society seem merely a matter of âattitude,â of âspiritual change,â or of quasi-religious redemption.
Although always mindful of the need for spiritual change, social ecology seeks to redress the ecological abuses that society has inflicted on the natural world by going to the structural as well as the subjective sources of notions like the âdomination of nature.â That is, it challenges the entire system of domination itself and seeks to eliminate the hierarchical and class edifice that has imposed itself on humanity and defined the relationship between nonhuman and human nature. It advances an ethics of complementarity in which human beings must play a supportive role in perpetuating the integrity of the biosphere, as potentially, at least, the most conscious products of natural evolution. Indeed humans are seen to have a moral responsibility to function creatively in the unfolding of that evolution. Social ecology thus stresses the need for embodying its ethics of complementarity in palpable social institutions that will give active meaning to its goal of wholeness, and of human involvement as conscious and moral agents in the interplay of species. It seeks the enrichment of the
evolutionary process by diversification of life-forms. Notwithstanding romantic views, âMother Natureâ does not necessarily âknow best.â To
oppose activities of the corporate world does not mean that one has to
become naively romantic and âbiocentric.â By the same token, to applaud
humanityâs potential for foresight and rationality, and its technological
achievements, does not mean that one is âanthropocentric.â The loose
usage of such buzzwords, so commonplace in the ecology movement, must
be brought to an end by reflective discussion.
Social ecology, in effect, recognizes thatâlike it or notâthe future of
life on this planet pivots on the future of society. It contends that evolution,
whether in first nature or in second, is not yet complete. Nor are the two
realms so separated from each other that we must choose one or the othereither natural evolution with its âbiocentricâ halo, or social evolution, as
we have known it up to now, with its âanthropocentricâ haloâas the basis
for a creative biosphere. We must go beyond both the natural and the social
toward a new synthesis that contains the best of both. Such a synthesis will
transcend them in the form of a creative, self-conscious, and therefore âfree
nature,â in which human beings intervene in natural evolution with their
best capacitiesâtheir moral sense, their unprecedented degree of conceptual thought, and their remarkable powers of communication.
But such a goal remains mere verbiage unless it can be given logistical
and social tangibility. How are we to organize a âfree natureâ that goes
beyond the rhetoric so plentiful in the ecology movement? Logistically,
âfree natureâ is unattainable without the decentralization of cities into
confederally united communities sensitively tailored to the natural areas
in which they are located. It means the use of ecotechnologies, and of solar,
wind, methane, and other sources of energy, the use of organic forms of
agriculture, the design of humanly scaled, versatile industrial installations
to meet regional needs of confederated municipalities. It means, too, an
emphasis not only on recycling, but on the production of high-quality goods
that can last for generations. It means the substitution of creative work for
insensate labor and an emphasis on artful craftspersonship in preference
to mechanized production. It means the leisure to be artful and engage in
public affairs. One would hope that the sheer availability of goods and the
freedom to choose oneâs material lifestyle would sooner or later influence
people to adopt moderation in all aspects of life as a response to the
âconsumerismâ that is promoted by the capitalist market.[6]
But no ethics or vision of an ecological society, however inspired, can
be meaningful unless it is embodied in a living politics. By âpoliticsâ I do
not mean the statecraft practiced by what we call âpoliticiansâânamely,
representatives elected or selected to formulate policies as guidelines for
social life and to manage public affairs. To social ecology, politics means
what it once meant in the democratic *polis* of Athens some two thousand
years ago the formation of policy by popular assemblies and their administration by mandated, carefully supervised boards of coordinators who
could easily be recalled if they failed to abide by the decisions of the
assemblyâs citizens. I am very mindful that Athenian politics, even in its
most democratic periods, was marred by the existence of slavery, patriarchy, and the exclusion of the stranger from public life. In this respect, it
differed very little from most of the Mediterranean civilizationsâand Asian
ones of the time. What made Athenian politics unique, however, was that
it produced institutions that were extraordinarily democraticâeven directly soâby comparison with republican institutions in the so-called
âdemocraciesâ of the Western world. Either directly or indirectly they
inspired later, more all-encompassing democracies, such as certain medieval towns, the little-known âsectionsâ of Paris (which were essentially
forty-eight neighborhood assemblies) that propelled the French Revolution
in a highly radical direction in 1793, New England town meetings, and
more recent attempts at civic self-governance.[7]
Any community, however, risks the danger of becoming parochial,
even racist, if it tries to live in isolation and develop a seeming self-sufficiency. Hence, the need to extend ecological politics into confederations of
ecocommunities, and to foster a healthy interdependence, rather than an
introverted, stultifying independence. Social ecology would embody its
ethics in a politics of confederal municipalism, in which municipalities
cojointly gain rights to self-governance through networks of confederal
councils, to which towns and cities would send their mandated, recallable
delegates to adjust differences. All decisions would have to be ratified by
a majority of the popular assemblies of the confederated towns and cities.
This institutional process could occur in the neighborhoods of giant cities
as well as in networks of small towns. In fact, the formation of numerous
âtown hallsâ has already repeatedly been proposed in cities as large as New
York and Paris, only to be defeated by well-organized elitist groups that
sought to centralize power, rather than allow its decentralization.
Power will always belong to elite strata if it is not diffused, in
face-to-face democracies, among the people, who are *empowered* as partly
autonomous, partly social beingsâthat is to say, as free individuals, but as
individuals responsible to popular institutions. Empowerment of the people in this sense will constitute a challenge to the nation-stateâthe principal source of nationalism, a regressive ideology, and of statism, the principal source of coercion. Diversity of cultures is obviously a desideratum, the
source of cultural creativity, but never can it be celebrated in a nationalistic
âapartnessâ from the general interests of humanity as a whole, without a
regression into folkdom and tribalism.
The full reality of citizenship has begun to wane, and its disappearance would mark an irrevocable loss in human development. Citizenship.
in the classical sense of the term, meant a lifelong, ethically oriented
education to participation in public affairs, not the empty form of national
legitimation that it so often indicates today. It meant the cultivation of an affiliation with the interests of the community, one in which the communal interest was placed above personal interest, or, more properly, in which the personal interest was congruent with and realized through the common.
Property, in this ethical constellation, would be shared and, in the best of circumstances, belong to the community as a whole, not to producers (âworkersâ) or owners (âcapitalistsâ). In an ecological society composed of a âCommune of communes,â property would belong, ultimately, neither to private producers nor to a nation-state. The Soviet Union gave rise to an overbearing bureaucracy; the anarcho-syndicalist vision to competing âworker-controlledâ factories that ultimately had to be knitted together by a labor bureaucracy. From the standpoint of social ecology, property âinterestsâ would become generalized, not reconstituted in different conflicting or unmanageable forms. They would be **municipalized**, rather than nationalized or privatized. Workers, farmers, professionals, and the like would thus deal with municipalized property as citizens, not as members of a vocational or social group. Leaving aside any discussion of such visions as the rotation of work, the citizen who engages in both industrial and agricultural activity, and the professional who also does manual labor, the communal ideas advanced by social ecology would give rise to individuals for whom the collective interest is inseparable from the personal, the public interest from the private, the political interest from the social.
The step-by-step reorganization of municipalities, their confederation into ever-larger networks that form a dual power in opposition to the nation-state, the remaking of the constituents of republican representatives into citizens who participate in a direct democracyâall may take a considerable period of time to achieve. But in the end, they alone can potentially eliminate the domination of human by human and thereby deal with those ecological problems whose growing magnitude threatens the existence of a biosphere than can support advanced forms of life. To ignore the need for these sweeping but eminently practical changes would be to let our ecological problems fester and spread to a point where there would no longer be any opportunity to resolve them. Any attempt to ignore their impact on the biosphere or deal with them singly would be recipe for disaster, a guarantee that the anti-ecological society that prevails in most of the world today would blindly hurtle the biosphere as we know it to certain destruction.
[1] Murray Bookchin, âEcology and Revolutionary Thought,â initially published in the ecoanarchist journal **New Directions in Libertarian Thought** (Sept., 1964), and collected, together with all my major essays of the sixties in **Post-Scarcity Anarchism** (Berkeley: Ramparts Press, 1972; republished, Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1977). The expression âethics of complementarityâ is from **The Ecology of Freedom** (San Francisco: Cheshire Books, 1982; revised edition, Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1991).
[2] Neil Evernden, **The Natural Alien** (Toronto: University of Toronto Press,1986), p. 109.
[3] Quoted in Alan Wolfe, âUp from Humanism,â in **The Arnerican Prospect** (Winter, 1991), p. 125.
[4] Paul Radin, **The World of Primitive Man** (New York: Grove Press, 1960), p. 211.
[5] See **Der Spiegel** (Sept. 16, 1991), pp. 144â45.
[6] All of these views were spelled out in the essay âEcology and Revolutionary Thoughtâ by this writer in 1965, and were assimilated over time by subsequent ecology movements. Many of the technological views advanced a year later in âToward a Liberatory Technologyâ were also assimilated and renamed âappropriate technology,â a rather socially neutral expression in comparison with my original term âecotechnology.â Both of these essays can be found in **Post-Scarcity Anarchism**.
[7] See the essay âThe Forms of Freedom,â in **Post-Scarcity Anarchism**, âThe Legacy of Freedom,â in **The Ecology of Freedom**, and âPatterns of Civic Freedomâ in **The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship** (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1987).