đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș robert-graham-the-anarchist-current captured on 2024-07-09 at 05:24:15. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Anarchist Current Subtitle: Continuity and Change in Anarchist Thought Date: 2013 Source: Retrieved on 3<sup>rd</sup> February 2021 from [[https://robertgraham.wordpress.com/the-anarchist-current/][robertgraham.wordpress.com]] Authors: Robert Graham Topics: History, Anarchist movement Published: 2021-02-03 18:12:07Z
<em>The subtitle of Volume One of my anthology of anarchist writings,</em> Anarchism: A Documentary History of Libertarian Ideas<em>, was</em> <strong>From Anarchy to Anarchism</strong><em>. By this I meant to emphasize that people lived without states for tens of thousands of years, and therefore in a kind of âanarchy,â before the first states began to emerge about 6,000 years ago. Far from being impossible, as Thomas Hobbes and many other political commentators have argued, anarchy was a very successful form of human social organization which existed for the most of the time of human existence on this planet. Because these societies without states were preliterate, it is impossible to say to what degree this may have been a conscious choice. It is highly doubtful that people living in stateless societies ever identified themselves in opposition to the state, as âanarchistsâ of some sort, given that there were no states in existence for most of the time that people lived within these stateless societies. Anarchism, as an identifiable doctrine, could only emerge after the development of state forms and institutions, hence the subtitle, âFrom Anarchy to Anarchism.â</em>
<em>For Volume Three of the</em> <strong>Anarchism</strong> <em>anthology, I wrote an Afterword, â<strong>The Anarchist Current</strong>,â in which I discuss the evolution from living without states, or âanarchy,â to the origins of anarchist ideas and movements, after the rise of so-called âcivilization.â I then survey the development of anarchist ideas over time and across the globe, from the Daoists in ancient China to contemporary âOccupyâ and similar transnational movements against neo-liberalism. As the <strong>Afterword</strong> also serves as an extended introduction to the material in the the volumes of the</em> <strong>Anarchism</strong> <em>anthology, and the history of anarchist thought, I have decided to publish it in serial form here on my blog in the hope that this will pique peoplesâ interest in the original material contained in the anthology, of which the <strong>Afterward</strong> can of course only offer a glimpse (the material is referenced in the text by volume and selection numbers). I hope someday in the not too distant future to expand the <strong>Afterward</strong> into a book.</em>
Anarchism, George Woodcock once wrote, is like the river of the ancient Greek philosopher, Heraclitus: constantly changing, with different sources, eddies and currents, sometimes percolating below the surface, at other times bursting forth in revolutionary torrents, but generally moving âbetween the banks of certain unifying principlesâ (1977: 16). Contrary to popular misconceptions, those unifying principles are not chaos and terrorism, but a rejection of hierarchy, authority and exploitation, and an alternative vision of a society without domination based on freedom and equality. Anarchists reject the State and its institutions, advocating societies based on free association, without anyone having the power to dominate or exploit another.
Long before anyone consciously articulated anarchist ideas, people had lived in societies without a state for thousands of years. So-called primitive and prehistoric peoples lacked any formal institutions of government and hierarchical social structures based on relationships of command and obedience (*Clastres, Volume Two, Selection 64*). As the anthropologist Harold Barclay puts it, âTen thousand years ago everyone was an anarchistâ (1982: 39). Around 6000 years ago, the first hierarchical societies began to emerge in which a minority of their members assumed positions of prestige and authority, from which they came to exercise power over others (*Barclay, Volume Three, Selection 17*).
It took thousands of years for this process of state formation finally to encompass the entire globe, with some people continuing to live in stateless societies into the 20th century. Members of stateless societies lived in roughly egalitarian communities without rank or status (Taylor, 1982). For the most part, stateless societies had sustainable subsistence economies based on relationships of equality, reciprocity and mutual aid (*Clastres, Volume Two, Selection 64; Bookchin, Volume Three, Selection 26*; Sahlins (1974), Barclay (1982) and Kropotkin (1902)).
Relatively few states emerged from within their own societies: ancient Mesopotamia, Egypt, China, Mexico, Hawaii, Tahiti, Tonga, Samoa and possibly India (Barclay, 2003). State institutions were forced on most societies by external powers, or were created in response to such power. According to Barclay, a combination of factors led to the emergence of state forms: 1) increased population; 2) sedentary settlement; 3) horticulture/agriculture; 4) redistribution of wealth; 5) military organization; 6) secondary significance of kinship ties; 7) trading; 8) specialized division of labour; 9) individual property and control of resources; 10) a hierarchical social order; and 11) ideologies of superiority/inferiority (*Volume Three, Selection 17*).
As most people were innocent of government, having lived without it for thousands of years, they had nothing against which to compare their so-called primitive forms of social organization until it was too late. âAnarchyâ was for them a way of life, not a concept. Although they may have had nonhierarchical conceptions of their societies and the natural world (*Bookchin, Volume 3, Selection 25*), it is unlikely that they conceived of anarchy as some sort of ideal. Anarchist ideas only began to be articulated after people started living within hierarchical societies based on exploitation and domination. When looking for precursors of the anarchist idea, one must be careful then not to read too much into the writings of people who never identified themselves as anarchists and never explicitly endorsed anarchy as an ideal.
Daoism in ancient China helped give more formal expression to the nonhierarchical sensibilities of earlier human societies, eventually leading some Daoists to adopt an anarchist stance. John P. Clark has argued that the classic text, the Daode Jing (or Tao Te Ching), circa 400 BCE, evokes âthe condition of wholeness which preceded the rending of the social fabric by institutions like the state, private property, and patriarchyâ (1984: 168).
Writing around 300 CE, the Daoist sage Bao Jingyan gave the Daoist rejection of the hierarchical cosmology of the Confucians a more political slant, seeing it as nothing more than a pretext for the subjugation of the weak and innocent by the strong and cunning (*Volume One, Selection 1*). He harkened back to the âoriginal undifferentiatedâ condition of the world in which âall creatures found happiness in self-fulfillment,â expressing a nonhierarchical, ecological sensibility which eschews âthe use of force that goes against the true nature of things.â He noted that in âthe earliest times,â prior to the creation of a hierarchical social order, âthere was neither lord nor subjects.â He saw compulsory labour and poverty as the results of the division of people into ranks and classes. With the emergence of a hierarchical social order, everyone seeks to be above the other, giving rise to crime and conflict. The âpeople simmer with revolt in the midst of their poverty and distress,â such that to try to stop them from revolting âis like trying to dam a river with a handful of earth.â He prefered a life worth living to the religious promise of life after death.
In his commentary on Bao Jingyanâs text, Etienne Balazs argues that Bao Jingyan was âChinaâs first political anarchistâ (1964: 243). As with later self-proclaimed anarchists, Bao Jingyan opposed hierarchy and domination, seeing them as the cause of poverty, crime, exploitation and social conflict, rejected religious beliefs that justify such a state of affairs, predicted the revolt of the masses and advocated a society without hierarchy and domination where there are âneither lord nor subjects,â a phrase strikingly reminiscent of the 19th century European anarchist battle cry, âNeither God nor Master.â While similar ideas may have been expressed in ancient Greece by the Stoic philosopher, Zeno of Citium (333â262 BCE), only fragments of his writings have survived, making Bao Jingyanâs text perhaps the oldest extant to set forth a clearly anarchist position.
The Daoist sage Bao Jingyan argued that the strong and cunning forced and tricked the people into submitting to them. That the people may play a part in their own servitude is an idea that was explored in much greater detail by Ătienne de la BoĂ©tie (1530â1563), in his **Discourse on Voluntary Servitude** (*1552, Volume One, Selection 2*). Seeking to explain how the masses can be subjugated by a single tyrant, de la BoĂ©tie argued that it is the masses themselves âwho permit, or, rather, bring about, their own subjection, since by ceasing to submit they would put an end to their own servitude.â Despite de la BoĂ©tieâs focus on tyranny, rather than hierarchy and domination as such, as Murray Rothbard points out, de la BoĂ©tieâs critique of tyranny applies to all forms of government, whether democratic, monarchic or dictatorial, such that his arguments can easily be pressed on âto anarchist conclusions,â as they were by subsequent writers (1975: 20).
This idea that the power of the state depends on the voluntary submission or acquiescence of the people, such that state power can be abolished or undermined by the withdrawal of cooperation, was taken up by later anarchists, including William Godwin (*Volume One, Selection 4*), Leo Tolstoy (*Volume One, Selection 47*), Gustav Landauer (*Volume One, Selection 49*), Praxedis Guerrero (*Volume One, Selection 72*), Alex Comfort (*Volume Two, Selection 26*) and contemporary writers, such as Noam Chomsky (*Volume Two, Selection 68*) and Ed Herman (*Volume Three, Selection 40*), who have emphasized that so-called democratic states require an extensive propaganda apparatus to âengineerâ or âmanufactureâ the consent of the people to their own continuing domination and exploitation.
While religion has often served as both a justification and palliative for coercive authority, various heretical religious currents have emerged throughout human history denying the legitimacy of earthly authority (*Walter, Volume Two, Selection 43*). In the 1960s, Gary Snyder highlighted those strands of Buddhism that evinced an anarchist sensibility (*Volume Two, Selection 42*). In the 9th century, a minority among the Muâtazili Muslims argued that anarchy is preferable to tyranny (Crone, 2000), while another Islamic sect, the Kharijites, âdisputed any need at all for an imam, or head of state, as long as the divine law was carried outâ (Levy, 1957).
In Europe, several heretical Christian sects emerged during the Middle Ages and Reformation, rejecting human authority in favour of freedom and community. The Brethren of the Free Spirit adopted a libertarian amoralism similar to Max Stirnerâs egoism (*Volume One, Selection 11*), advocating total freedom for themselves while taking advantage of others (Marshall, 2008: 87â89). In contrast, the Taborites in Bohemia were egalitarians, seeking to abolish private property, taxes and political authority, asserting that âAll shall live together as brothers, none shall be subject to anotherâ (Marshall: 92). The Hussites and Moravian Brothers also advocated an egalitarian community without coercive authority, modeled after Christâs relationship with his apostles.
But it was not until the English Revolution (1642â1651) that Christian teachings were transformed into a body of ideas resembling modern anarchism. The Ranters advocated and practiced free love and the holding of all things in common, with some adopting a libertarian amoralism similar to that of the Brethren of the Free Spirit. The Diggers also advocated holding things in common, and sought to establish egalitarian communities on waste lands.
One of the Diggers, Gerrard Winstanley (1609â1676), published a pamphlet in 1649, **The New Law of Righteousness**, in which he advocated an early form of anarchist communism, drawing inspiration from the Bible (*Volume One, Selection 3*).
Winstanley argued that anyone getting âauthority into his hands tyrannizes over others,â whether husband, parent, master or magistrate. He saw private property, inequality and exploitation as the inevitable result of ârule and dominion, in one part of man-kinde over another.â He advocated making the earth the âcommon treasuryâ of all, such that anyone in need should be able to âtake from the next store-house he meets with.â There âshall be none Lord over others,â and âno need for Lawyers, prisons, or engines of punishment,â with the distinction between â**Mine and Thine**â having been abolished.
In opposing coercive authority, hierarchy and private property, Winstanley was careful to endorse means consistent with his ends. He endorsed a form of nonviolent direct action, while denouncing those who would replace one tyranny with another. For Winstanley, âthe manifestation of a righteous heart shall be known, not by his words, but by his actions,â for âTyrannie is Tyrannie in one as wel [sic] as in another; in a poor man lifted up by his valour, as in a rich man lifted up by his lands.â
Although couching his argument in religious terms, Winstanley conceived of God as âthe law of righteousness, reason and equityâ dwelling within all of us, a position similar to that later adopted by Leo Tolstoy. He advocated freedom for both men and women, applying his critique of hierarchy and domination not just to their more obvious manifestations, but also to relationships between husband and wife and parents and children.
Hounded by both parliamentary and royalist forces, the Digger movement did not survive the English Civil War. However, anarchist ideas continued to percolate underground in Europe, resurfacing during the Enlightenment and the 1789 French Revolution.
In 1676, Gabriel de Foigny, a defrocked priest, published in Geneva **Les Adventures de Jacques Sadeur dans la dĂ©couverte de la Terre Australe**, in which he depicted an imaginary society in Australia where people lived without government, religious institutions or private property. De Foigny was considered a heretic and imprisoned. A year after his death in 1692, an abridged English translation of **Les Adventures** appeared as **A New Discovery of Terra Incognita Australis.** According to Max Nettlau, de Foignyâs book became âwell known,â being âreprinted and translated many timesâ (1996: 12).
Jean Meslier, a priest from the Champagne area of France, wrote a political **Testament** in the 1720s in which he denounced the alliance of Church and State, calling on the people to keep for themselves âall the riches and goods you produce so abundantly with the sweat of your brow,â and to let âall the great ones of the earth and all nobles hang and strangle themselves with the priestsâ gutsâ (Joll: 14). Similar sentiments were expressed by the French **philosophe**, Denis Diderot, who wrote in 1772 that ânature has made neither servant nor masterâI want neither to give nor to receive laws⊠weave the entrails of the priest, for want of a rope, to hang the kingsâ (Berneri: 202). During the French Revolution this was transformed into the slogan, âHumanity will not be happy until the last aristocrat is hanged by the guts of the last priest.â Many variations on this slogan have followed since, with the Situationists during the May-June 1968 events in France calling for the last bureaucrat to be hanged by the guts of the last capitalist (Knabb: 344).
On the eve of the French Revolution of 1789, Sylvain MarĂ©chal (1750â1803) published some fables and satirical works evincing an anarchist stance, picturing in one âthe life of kings exiled to a desert island where they ended up exterminating each otherâ (Nettlau: 11). He attacked religion and promoted atheism. In 1796, in the face of the growing reaction, he published his âManifesto of the Equalsâ (*Volume One, Selection 6*), in which he called on the people of France to march over the bodies of âthe new tyrants, seated in the place of the old ones,â just as they had âmarched over the bodies of kings and priests.â MarĂ©chal sought âreal equality,â through âthe communal enjoyment of the fruits of the earth,â and the abolition not only of âindividual property in land,â but of âthe revolting distinction of rich and poor, of great and small, of masters and valets, of governors and governed.â
Anarchist tendencies emerged among the more radical elements during the first, or âGreat,â French Revolution of 1789, particularly among the **sans-culottes** and **enragĂ©s** who formed the backbone of the Revolution. Denounced as anarchists by their opponents, they did not entirely reject the label. In 1793, the **sans-culottes** of Beaucaire identified their allies as âthose who have delivered us from the clergy and nobility, from the feudal system, from tithes, from the monarchy and all the ills which follow in its train; those whom the aristocrats have called anarchists, followers of faction (**factieux**), Maratistsâ (Joll: 27).
The **sans-culottes** played an important role in the revolutionary âsectionsâ in Paris, directly democratic neighbourhood assemblies through which ordinary people took control of their lives. As Murray Bookchin has argued, the sections ârepresented genuine forms of self-managementâ that âawakened a popular initiative, a resoluteness in action, and a sense of revolutionary purpose that no professional bureaucracy, however radical its pretensions, could ever hope to achieveâ (*Volume Two, Selection 62*).
Unfortunately, other forces on the left, notably Robespierre and the Jacobins, adopted an authoritarian policy of revolutionary terror to fight the counter-revolution, leading the **enragĂ©** Jean Varlet (1764â1837) to denounce so-called ârevolutionary governmentâ as a monstrous âmasterpiece of Machiavellianismâ that purported to put the revolutionary authorities âin permanent insurrectionâ against themselves, which is patently absurd (*Volume One, Selection 5*).
Varlet and other **sans-culottes** and **enragĂ©s** had fought with the Jacobins against the more conservative Girondins, unwittingly helping the Jacobins to institute their own dictatorship. When Varlet saw his fellow revolutionaries âclapped in ironsâ by the Jacobins, he âretreated back into the ranks of the peopleâ rather than support âa disgusting dictatorship dressed up with the title of Public Safety.â He could not accept that âRobespierreâs ghastly dictatorshipâ could somehow vindicate the preceding dictatorship of the Girondins, nor that he and his fellow **enragĂ©s** could be blamed for being the unwitting dupes of the Jacobins, claiming that they had done ânothing to deserve such a harsh reproachâ (*Volume One, Selection 5*).
Varlet made clear that the Jacobin policy of mass arrests and executions, the so-called âReign of Terror,â far from protecting the gains of the revolution, was not only monstrous but counter-revolutionary, with âtwo thirds of citizensâ being deemed âmischievous enemies of freedomâ who âmust be stamped out,â **terror** being âthe supreme lawâ and torture âan object of veneration.â The Jacobin terror âaims to rule over heaps of corpsesâ under the pretext that âif the executioners are no longer the fathers of the nation, freedom is in jeopardy,â turning the people against the revolution as they themselves become its victims. Even with the overthrow of Robespierre in July 1794, Varlet warned that âhis ghastly system has survived him,â calling on the French people to take up their arms and their pens to overthrow the government, whatever its revolutionary pretensions.
Varlet, in rejecting his own responsibility for the Jacobin ascendancy to power, avoided a critique of revolutionary violence, simply calling on the people to rise yet again against their new masters, a call which went largely unanswered after years of revolutionary upheaval which had decimated the ranks of the revolutionaries and demoralized the people. There were a couple of abortive uprisings in Paris in 1795, but these were quickly suppressed.
Jean Varletâs English contemporary, William Godwin (1756â1836), developed an anarchist critique not only of revolutionary violence but of coercion as such, whether the institutionalized coercion of the law with its penal systems, or the individual coercion of a parent toward a child. Godwin wrote and revised his great philosophical work, **An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice** (*Volume One, Selection 4*), during the French Revolution, publishing the final revised edition in 1797, around the time that Napoleon was coming to power, three years after the fall of Robespierre.
Godwin argued that coercion, and its positive correlate, inducements offered by those with wealth and power, distort political debate and moral discussion by causing people to evaluate a policy or course of conduct in terms of the punishments or rewards attached to them, rather than on their intrinsic merits. Coercion and inducements also have a debilitating effect on both persons in power and the people who obey or accept them.
âDressed in the supine prerogatives of a master,â those in power are âexcused from cultivatingâ their rational faculties. Those who are forced to obey their rulers become resentful and fearful. Instead of being encouraged to think for themselves, they learn how to avoid detection and seek power for themselves so that they can effect their own purposes.
The deleterious consequences of coercion and inducements are not surmounted by parliamentary debates, or what is now referred to as âdeliberative democracyâ (Dryzek, 2000). In the first place, the laws and policies of the government are not the result of direct debate among the people, but the result of the debates of elected representatives who represent particular interests. Decisions are made by majority vote of the representatives, who invariably vote along party lines. Even when a debate is not cut short by the ruling party, the âminority, after having exposed, with all the power and eloquence, and force of reasoning, of which they are capable, the injustice and folly of the measures adopted, are obliged⊠to assist in carrying them into execution,â since all the representatives are required to uphold the law. For Godwin, ânothing can more directly contribute to the deprivation of the human understanding and characterâ than to require people to act contrary to their own reason.
During parliamentary debates, which must come to a close with a vote of the assembled representatives, the âorator no longer enquires after permanent conviction, but transitory effect. He seeks to take advantage of our prejudices than to enlighten our judgement. That which might otherwise have been a scene of patient and beneficent enquiry is changed into wrangling, tumult and precipitation.â
This is particularly true during revolutionary upheavals. Reasoned and impartial debate âcan scarcely be pursued when all the passions of man are afloat, and we are hourly under the strongest impressions of fear and hope, apprehension and desire, dejection and triumph.â Revolutions invariably provoke counter-revolution. When âwe lay aside arguments, and have recourse to the sword,â amidst âthe barbarous rage of war, and the clamorous din of civil contention, who shall tell whether the event will be prosperous or adverse? The consequence may be the riveting on us anew the chains of despotism.â To combat the counter-revolution, the revolutionaries suppress freedom of expression and resort to terror, organizing âa government tenfold more encroaching in its principles and terrible in its proceedingsâ than the old regime.
Despite regarding revolutions as being ânecessarily attended with many circumstances worthy of our disapprobation,â Godwin recognized that ârevolutions and violence have too often been coeval with important changes of the social system.â While we should âendeavour to prevent violence,â during revolutionary upheavals we cannot simply âturn away our eyes from human affairs in disgust, and refuse to contribute our labours and attention to the general weal.â Rather, we must take âproper advantage of circumstances as they arise, and not⊠withdraw ourselves because everything is not conducted according to our ideas of propriety.â Godwinâs critique of revolutionary violence must not therefore be misconstrued as tacit support for the injustices which the revolutionaries are seeking to overturn.
Since Godwinâs time, anarchists have continued to struggle with questions regarding recourse to violence and the role of anarchists during revolutionary struggles. The validity of Godwinâs warning, based on his own observations of the French Revolution, that revolution may result in a new tyranny because it is the strongest and not the most just who typically triumph, has been borne out by the experience of anarchists in subsequent revolutions. In the 20th century, both the Russian (*Volume One, Chapter 18*) and Spanish (*Volume One, Chapter 23*) revolutions resulted in dictatorships even more âghastlyâ than that of Robespierre, despite the presence of significant anarchist movements.
When anarchist movements began to emerge in 19th century Europe, Godwinâs work was relatively unknown. It was largely through the work of the anarchist historian, Max Nettlau (1865â1944), that the ideas of de la BoĂ©tie and Godwin were introduced to European anarchists, well after anarchism had emerged as an identifiable current of thought (Walter, 2007).
A younger contemporary of William Godwin was to have a noticeable influence on the development of anarchist ideas, the French writer, Charles Fourier (1772â1837). Fourier had lived through the French Revolution. Imprisoned for a time, he almost became another victim of the Terror. He witnessed the hoarding and profiteering that occurred during the Revolution and sought to develop a libertarian alternative by which everyone would not only be guaranteed their means of subsistence but would be able to engage in productive work which they themselves found fulfilling. âMorality teaches us to love work,â Fourier wrote, âlet it know, then, how to render work lovableâ (*Volume One, Selection 7*).
Fourier recognized that in order to survive in the emerging capitalist economy, workers were compelled to take whatever work they could find, regardless of their personal talents, aptitudes and preferences. They had to work long hours under deplorable conditions, only to see their employers reap the fruits of their labours while they continued to live in poverty. The new economy was ânothing but⊠a league of the minority which possesses, against the majority which does not possess the necessaries of life.â
Fourier, however, did not advocate revolution. He hoped to attract financial benefactors to fund the creation of communes or âphalanxesâ where each person would rotate through a variety of jobs each day, free to choose each task, doing what they found to be enjoyable, giving expression to their talents and passions. Each member of the phalanx would be guaranteed a minimum of material support and remunerated by dividends from the phalanxâs operations. While later anarchists agreed that work should be freely undertaken, enjoyable and fulfilling, rather than an onerous burden, they found Fourierâs more detailed plans regarding the organization of society to be too constrictive and his idea that wealthy benefactors would bankroll the abolition of their own privileged status naĂŻve.
Fourier was an early advocate of sexual liberation. Foreshadowing the work of Wilhelm Reich (*Volume One, Selection 119; Volume Two, Selection 75*), Fourier argued that people should be free to satisfy their sexual needs and desires, and that the repression of such desires is not only harmful to the individual but one of the foundations of a repressive society (*Guérin, Volume Two, Selection 76*).
In 1840, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809â1865) declared himself an anarchist in his groundbreaking book, **What is Property? An Inquiry into the Principle of Right and of Government**. Karl Marx (1818â1883), later Proudhonâs scornful opponent, at the time praised Proudhonâs book as âthe first resolute, pitiless and at the same time scientificâ critique of private property (Marx, 1845: 132). To the question posed by the title of the book, Proudhon responded that âproperty is theftâ (*Volume One, Selection 8*). According to Proudhon, the workers should be entitled to the full value of their labour, not the mere pittance the capitalists doled out to them while keeping the lionâs share for themselves. By arguing that, in this sense, âproperty is theft,â Proudhon was not giving expression to bourgeois notions of justice, as Marx later claimed (Marx, 1867: 178â179, fn. 2), but was expressing a view of justice held by many workers, that people should enjoy the fruits of their own labours.
That the capitalists were parasites exploiting the workers by depriving them of what was rightfully theirs was to become a common theme in 19th century socialist and anarchist propaganda. In the 1883 Pittsburgh Proclamation of the International Working Peopleâs Association (the so-called âBlack Internationalâ), the then anarchist collectivist Johann Most (1846â1906) put it this way: âthe propertied (capitalists) buy the working force body and soul of the propertyless, for the mere cost of existence (wages) and take for themselves, i.e. steal, the amount of new values (products) which exceeds the priceâ (*Volume One, Selection 55*).
Besides declaring property theft, Proudhon boldly proclaimed himself an anarchist, denouncing âthe government of man by manâ as âoppression.â It is government, through its laws and coercive mechanisms, that protects the property of the capitalists, condemning the workers to lives of servitude and misery. The only just form of society is one in which workers are free to associate, to combine their labour, and to exchange what they produce for products and services of equivalent value, instead of receiving wages âscarcely sufficient to support them from one day to another.â In a society based on equivalent exchange there would no longer be any need for government because those things which make government necessary, such as âpauperism, luxury, oppression, vice, crime and hunger,â would âdisappear from our midstâ (*Volume One, Selection 8*). Proudhon described this form of socialism as âmutualism.â
Proudhon was not the first to have drawn the connection between economic exploitation and political servitude. Bao Jingyan, Winstanley, Maréchal, Godwin and Fourier all made similar arguments. But Proudhon was the first to describe himself as an anarchist. Others were soon to follow.
In the 1840s there was an explosion of radical ideas and movements in Europe, culminating in a wave of revolutions that swept the continent in 1848â49. In Germany, radical intellectuals inspired by and reacting against the philosophy of Hegel, sometimes referred to as the âYoungâ or âLeft Hegelians,â began developing a â**ruthless criticism of everything existing**,â as Marx put it in 1843. The previous year, Bakunin had published his essay, âThe Reaction in Germany,â in which he described the revolutionary program as âthe negation of the existing conditions of the Stateâ and â the destruction of whatever order prevails at the time,â concluding with the now notorious phrase, the âpassion for destruction is a creative passion, too!â (*Volume One, Selection 10*). Max Stirnerâs masterpiece of nihilistic egoism, **The Ego and Its Own**, came out in 1844 (*Volume One, Selection 11*). Arnold Ruge, one of the most prominent of the âYoung Hegelians,â called for âthe abolition of all governmentâ in favour of âan ordered anarchy⊠the free community⊠of men who make their own decisions and who are in all respects equal comradesâ (Nettlau: 53â59).
Three aspects of the Young Hegelian critique had a lasting impact on Bakunin, and through him on the development of anarchist ideas. The first was the Young Hegelian critique of religion. The second was the development of a materialist worldview, from which all âdivine phantomsâ were banished. The third, which followed from the first two, was atheism. Bakunin and later anarchists were to denounce the alliance of Church and State, particularly the role of religion in pacifying the masses and in rationalizing their domination and exploitation, advocating a materialist atheism that emphasizes human agency because there are no divine or supernatural forces to protect or deliver the people from their earthly misery. The people can only liberate themselves through their own direct action.
Max Stirner (1806â1856) took the Young Hegelian critique of âdivine phantomsâ to its furthest extreme, attacking all ideal conceptions, whether of God, humanity, or good and evil, as âspooksâ or âwheels in the headâ which dominate the very consciousness of the unique individual, preventing him or her from acting freely.
In **The Ego and Its Own**, Stirner argued that through upbringing, education and indoctrination, people internalize abstract social norms and values, putting the individual âin the position of a country governed by secret police. The spy and eavesdropper, âconscience,â watch over every motion of the mind,â with âall thought and actionâ becoming âa matter of conscience, i.e. police business.â Anticipating radical Freudians like the anarchist psychoanalyst, Otto Gross (*Volume One, Selection 78*), Stirner observed that everyone âcarries his gendarme within his breast.â
Stirner advocated freedom âfrom the State, from religion, from conscience,â and from any other power or end to which the individual can be subjected. He rejected any concept of justice or rights, arguing that the unique individual is free to take whatever is in his or her power. Whenever the egoistâs âadvantage runs against the Stateâs,â he âcan satisfy himself only by crime.â After Stirnerâs writings were rediscovered in the late 1890s, this aspect of his critique was developed by individualist anarchists, such as Albert Joseph (âLibertadâ), into the doctrine of âillegalism,â which was used by the Bonnot Gang as an ideological cloak for their bank robberies in the early 1900s in France (Perry, 1987).
Stirner denounced socialism for seeking to replace the individual capitalist with a collective owner, âsociety,â to which the individual will be equally subject, but nevertheless argued that the workers need only stop labouring for the benefit of their employers and âregard the product of their labourâ as their own in order to bring down the State, the power of which rests on their slavery.
Another aspect of Stirnerâs thought that was to have some influence on later anarchists is his distinction between insurrection and revolution. Revolutions seek to rearrange society into a new order. Insurrection or rebellion, by contrast, is âa rising of individuals⊠without regard to the arrangements that spring from itâ (*Volume One, Selection 11*). In light of the defeats of the anarchists in the Russian and Spanish Revolutions, Herbert Read (1893â1968) sought to revive Stirnerâs distinction, arguing that anarchists must avoid creating âthe kind of machinery which, at the successful end of a revolution, would merely be taken over by the leaders of the revolution, who then assume the functions of governmentâ (*Volume Two, Selection 1*). During the 1960s, many of the younger anarchists endorsed the notion of âspontaneous insurrectionâ (*Volume Two, Selection 51*). More recently, Hakim Bey has argued in favour of the creation of âtemporary autonomous zones,â which can be seen as âan uprising which does not engage directly with the State, a guerilla operation which liberates an area (of land, of time, of imagination) and then dissolves itself to re-form elsewhere/elsewhen, **before** the State can crush itâ (*Volume Three, Selection 11*).
In one passage in **The Ego and Its Own**, Stirner described individuals as mere cogs in the â**State machine**.â In Proudhonâs 1846 publication, **The System of Economic Contradictions**, he argued that the first and âmost powerful of machines is the workshopâ The workshop degrades âthe worker by giving him a master.â The âconcentration of forces in the workshopâ and the introduction of machinery âengender at the same time overproduction and destitution,â rendering more and more workers redundant, such that in a capitalist economy it is continually necessary to âcreate new machines, open other markets, and consequently multiply services and displace otherâ workers. Industry and wealth, population and misery, âadvance, so to speak, in procession, one always dragging the other after itâ (*Volume One, Selection 9*).
This focus on and opposition to relationships of subordination in both the economic and political spheres sharply distinguished Proudhon and the anarchists from many of their socialist contemporaries. In his sarcastic attempt to demolish Proudhon, **The Poverty of Philosophy** (1847), Marx dismissed Proudhonâs critique of factory organization and machinery as a reactionary demand for a return to a pre-industrial utopia of skilled craft production. In the **Manifesto of the Communist Party** (1848), co-written with Friedrich Engels, Marx called for the centralization of âall instruments of production in the hands of the State⊠to increase the total of productive forces as rapidly as possible.â This would require the establishment of âindustrial armies, especially for agriculture.â
Proudhonâs solution to this problem was neither to advocate a return to a pre-industrial craft economy nor the creation of industrial armies, âfor it is with a machine as with a piece of artillery: the captain excepted, those whom it occupies are servants, slavesâ (*Volume One, Selection 9*). While Proudhon argued that free credit should be made available so that everyone would have the opportunity to engage in whatever productive activity they chose, he recognized from the outset the advantages of combining oneâs labour with the labour of others, creating a âcollective forceâ that in existing society was being exploited by the capitalists who reaped the benefit of the resulting increase in productive power. âTwo hundred grenadiers stood the obelisk of Luxor upon its base in a few hours,â Proudhon wrote in **What Is Property**, âdo you suppose that one man could have accomplished the same task in two hundred days?â (*Volume One, Selection 8*).
Proudhon therefore advocated workersâ control or worker self-management of industry, later referred to in France as âautogestion,â an idea that became a major tenet of subsequent anarchist movements (*GuĂ©rin, Volume Two, Selection 49*). In Proudhonâs proposals, all positions in each enterprise would be elected by the workers themselves, who would approve all by-laws, each worker would have the right to fill any position, âunpleasant and disagreeable tasksâ would be shared, and each worker would be given a âvariety of work and knowledgeâ so as to avoid a stultifying division of labour. Everyone would âparticipate in the gains and in the lossesâ of the enterprise âin proportion to his services,â with pay being âproportional to the nature of the position, the importance of the talents, and the extent of responsibilityâ (*Volume One, Selection 12*).
In early 1848, revolution broke out in Sicily, quickly spreading throughout the Italian peninsula. The February 1848 Revolution soon followed in France, with the king being overthrown and a provisional republican government proclaimed. There were revolutions in various parts of Germany and Eastern Europe (with Bakunin somehow managing to take a part in most of them until his arrest in Dresden in May 1849). Anarchist ideas began to gain some currency, particularly in France, in no small part due to Proudhonâs own efforts.
The provisional government in France instituted universal male suffrage, which Proudhon referred to as âthe counter-revolutionâ because the election of representatives, no matter how broad the electoral base, gives power to those representatives, not of the people, but of particular interests, legitimizing rule by those interests by making it appear that a government elected by universal suffrage represents the interests of the people. In fact, the Constituent Assembly elected in April 1848 was dominated by right-wing and bourgeois representatives. Rejection of and opposition to representative government and participation in parliamentary politics distinguished the anarchists from other socialist currents and helped lead to the split in the First International between Marx and his followers, who advocated the creation of national political parties to represent the interests of the working class, and the proto-anarchist anti-authoritarian federalists associated with Bakunin (*Volume One, Chapters 5 & 6*).
In **Confessions of a Revolutionary** (1849), Proudhon denounced the alliance between capital, religion and the state:
<em>âCapital</em>, which in the political field is analogous to <em>government</em>, in religion has <em>Catholicism</em> as its synonym. The economic idea of capitalism, the politics of government or of authority, and the theological idea of the Church are three identical ideas, linked in various ways. To attack one of them is equivalent to attacking all of them⊠What capital does to labour, and the State to liberty, the Church does to the spirit. This trinity of absolutism is as baneful in practice as it is in philosophy. The most effective means for oppressing the people would be simultaneously to enslave its body, its will and its reason.â (Nettlau: 43â44)
In **The General Idea of the Revolution in the 19<sup>th</sup> Century**, written from prison while Proudhon was incarcerated for having denounced Napoleon III as the personification of reaction, Proudhon wrote that the âfundamental, decisive ideaâ of the Revolution is this: âNO MORE AUTHORITY, neither in the Church, nor in the State, nor in land, nor in moneyâ (*Volume One, Selection 12*). He described the law as âspider webs for the rich and powerful, steel chains for the weak and poor, fishing nets in the hands of the government,â advocating in their place a â**system of contracts**â based on the notion of equivalent exchange (*Volume One, Selection 12*). While subsequent anarchists were, for the most part, to reject Proudhonâs notion of equivalent exchange, they concurred with Proudhon that social relationships should be based on free agreements between individuals directly and between the various voluntary associations to which they may belong (Graham, 1989).
In Spain, anarchists referred to these agreements as âpactsâ (**pactos**). In 1854, Francisco Pi y Margall (1824â1901), who introduced Proudhonâs ideas to a Spanish audience, argued that between âtwo sovereign entities there is room only for pacts. Authority and sovereignty are contradictions. Society based on **authority** ought, therefore, to give way to society based upon **contract**â (*Volume One, Selection 15*).
Not only in Spain, but throughout the nascent international anarchist movements, anarchists advocated contract, conceived as free agreement, as the means by which people would voluntarily federate into broader trade union, communal, regional and international organizations with no central authority above them, with each person and federated group being free to disassociate or secede from any federalist organization (Graham, 1989). They agreed with the argument put forward by Proudhon in his influential book, **On** **the Political Capacity of the Working Classes** (1865), that without the right of secession, federalism would be âmerely an illusion, empty boasting, a lieâ (*Volume One, Selection 18*).
In the aftermath of the 1848 French Revolution, Proudhon was not alone in advocating anarchy as a positive ideal. In 1850, the young journalist, Anselme Bellegarrigue, briefly published a newspaper, **LâAnarchie**, in which he argued that âanarchy is order, whereas government is civil warâ (*Volume One, Selection 13*), echoing Proudhonâs comment in **What Is Property** that society âfinds its highest perfection in the union of order with anarchyâ (*Volume One, Selection 8*).
The Italian revolutionary, Carlo Pisacane (1818â1857), demanded the abolition of all hierarchy and authority, to be replaced by a form of socialism similar to Proudhonâs mutualism, based on voluntary contract and âfree associationâ. Anticipating the doctrine of âpropaganda by the deed,â Pisacane argued that the most effective propaganda is revolutionary action, for ideas âspring from deeds and not the other way aroundâ (*Volume One, Selection 16*).
Joseph DĂ©jacque (1821â1864), the first person to use the word âlibertarianâ as a synonym for âanarchist,â conceived of anarchy as the âcomplete, boundless, utter freedom to do anything and everything that is in human natureâ (*Volume One, Selection 14*). Exiled from France after the 1848 Revolution, he called for the abolition of religion, private property, the patriarchal nuclear family, all authority and privilege, and for the âliberation of woman, the emancipation of the child.â
DĂ©jacqueâs anarchist critique was much broader than Proudhonâs. Proudhon saw the patriarchal nuclear family as the basis of society, and argued that womanâs place was in the home. He did not advocate the complete abolition of property, arguing instead for a fairer distribution of wealth based on individual contribution and equivalent exchange.
DĂ©jacque took Proudhon to task on both points, arguing for the complete abolition of âproperty and authority in every guiseâ (*Volume One, Selection 17*). He rejected Proudhonâs mutualism as a âsystem of contractsâ for determining each personâs âallotted measureâ of things instead of everyone having access to whatever their ânature or temperament requires.â DĂ©jacque believed that everyone should be âfree to consume and to produce as they see fit,â advocating a form of anarchist communism twenty years before similar views were to be adopted by anarchists associated with the anti-authoritarian wing of the First International (*Volume One, Chapter 8*).
Rejecting Proudhonâs views on women, DĂ©jacque argued that âthe issue of womanâs emancipationâ must be placed âon the same footing as the issue of emancipation of the proletarianâ (*Volume One, Selection 17*). He looked forward to âman and woman striding with the same step and heart⊠towards their natural destiny, the anarchic community; with all despotism annihilated, all social inequalities banished.â
Another French exile with anarchist sensibilities was Ernest Coeurderoy (1825â1862). In a passage from his **Days of Exile,** remarkably similar to comments made by Subcomandante Marcos in the 1990s, Coeurderoy identified himself with all of the oppressed, writing that:
âIn every land there are folk who are kicked out and driven away, killed and burnt out without a single voice of compassion to speak up for them. They are the Jews.âI am a Jew.
Skinny, untamed, restless men, sprightlier than horses and as dusky as the bastards of Shem, roam through the Andalusian countryside⊠The doors of every home are barred to them, in hamlet and town alike. A widespread disapproval weighs upon their breed⊠Such men are known as Gitanos.âI am a GitanoâŠ
In Paris one can see wayward boys, naked, who hide under the bridges along the canal in the mid-winter and dive into the murky waters in search of a **sou** tossed to them by a passing onlooker⊠Their trade consists in purloining scarves and pretending to ask for a light but swapping cigarettes. These are the Bohemians.âI am a BohemianâŠ
Everywhere, there are people banned from promenades, museums, cafes and theatres because a heartless wretchedness mocks their day wear. If they dare to show themselves in public, every eye turns to stare at them; and the police forbid them to go near fashionable locations. But, mightier than any police, their righteous pride in themselves takes exception to being singled out for widespread stigma.âI am one of that breedâ (1854).
Bellegarrigue, DĂ©jacque and Coeurderoy were dead or forgotten by the time the International Association of Workingmen (the First International) was founded in 1864 (*Volume One, Selection 19*). It was only after the emergence in Europe of self-identified anarchist movements in the 1870s that Pisacaneâs writings were rediscovered. Of the anarchists from the 1840s and 50s, only Proudhon and Pi y Margall continued to exercise some influence, but by then both identified themselves as federalists rather than anarchists (*Volume One, Selection 18*). Prouhonâs followers in the First International supported his mutualist ideas, advocating free credit, small property holdings and equivalent exchange. They agreed with Proudhon that a womanâs place was in the home and argued that only workingmen should be allowed into the First International, which meant that intellectuals, such as Karl Marx, should also be excluded. They shared Proudhonâs critical view of strikes, regarding them as coercive and ineffective, but in practice provided financial and other support to striking workers.
Within the First International there were more radical elements that gave expression to a renewed sense of militancy among European workers. These Internationalists, such as EugĂšne Varlin (1839â1871) in France, were in favour of trade unions, seeing them as a means for organizing the workers to press their demands through collective direct action, such as strikes and boycotts. The ultimate aim was for the workers to take control of their workplaces, replacing the state and capitalism with local, regional, national and international federations of autonomous workersâ organizations.
Opposing these âanti-authoritarianâ Internationalists were not only the orthodox Proudhonists, but Karl Marx and his followers, as well as some Blanquists, who favoured centralized organization and the subordination of the trade unions to political parties that would coordinate opposition to capitalism and seek to achieve state power, either through participation in bourgeois politics, revolution or a combination of both. Disagreements over the Internationalâs internal form of organization and participation in politics would lead to the split in the International in 1872.
By 1868 the International had adopted a policy in favour of strikes and collective ownership of the means of production. However, collective ownership did not necessarily mean state ownership, as many Internationalists advocated workersâ control of industry through the workersâ own organizations and continued to support other aspects of Proudhonâs mutualism, such as workersâ mutual aid societies, cooperatives and credit unions. Varlin, for example, organized a cooperative restaurant with Nathalie Lemel (who later converted Louise Michel to anarchism). Some Geneva Internationalists proposed that half of the cooperativesâ profits be paid into the workersâ âresistanceâ funds, with the cooperatives also providing workers with financial aid and credit during strikes (Cutler, 1985: 213, fn. 69).
Bakunin had begun to articulate a revolutionary anarchist position in the mid-1860s, prior to his entry into the International in 1868. He advocated socialism and federalism based on âthe most complete liberty for individuals as well as associations,â rejecting both bourgeois republicanism and state socialism (*Volume One, Selection 20*). He rejected any âcall for the establishment of a ruling authority of any nature whatsoever,â denouncing those revolutionaries who âdream of creating new revolutionary states, as fully centralized and even more despotic than the states we now haveâ (*Volume One, Selections 20 & 21*).
âWe do not fear anarchy,â declared Bakunin, âwe invoke it. For we are convinced that anarchy, meaning the unrestricted manifestation of the liberated life of the people, must spring from liberty, equality, the new social order, and the force of the revolution itself against the reaction.â The new social order will be created âfrom the bottom up, from the circumference to the center⊠not from the top down or from the center to the circumference in the manner of all authorityâ (*Volume One, Selection 21*).
Bakunin opposed any attempts to justify the sacrifice of human lives in the name of some ideal or âabstraction,â including patriotism, the state, God or even science. Someone who is âalways ready to sacrifice his own liberty⊠will willingly sacrifice the liberty of othersâ (*Volume One, Selection 20*). The revolutionary socialist, âon the contrary, insists upon his positive rights to life and to all its intellectual, moral, and physical joys.â In addition to rejecting any notions of individual self-sacrifice, Bakunin argued against revolutionary terrorism as counter-revolutionary. To âmake a successful revolution, it is necessary to attack conditions and material goods, to destroy property and the State. It will then become unnecessary to destroy men and be condemned to suffer the sure and inevitable reaction which no massacre had ever failed and ever will fail to produce in every societyâ (*Volume One, Selection 21*).
Bakunin argued that the means adopted by revolutionaries should be consistent with their ends. Accordingly, the International should itself be organized âfrom the bottom up⊠in accordance with the natural diversity of [the workersâ] occupations and circumstances.â The workersâ organizations would âbear in themselves the living seeds of the new society which is to replace the old world. They are creating not only the ideas, but also the facts of the future itself.â Consequently, he rejected the view that the majority of the workers, even within the International itself, should accept the â**fraternal command**â of those who claimed to know what is best for them, as this would divide the International âinto two groupsâone comprising the vast majority⊠whose only knowledge will be blind faith in the theoretical and practical wisdom of their commanders,â and a minority of âskilled manipulatorsâ in control of the organization (*Volume One, Selection 25*).
Bakuninâs anarchist critique went well beyond attacking property, religion and the state. In addition to arguing against hierarchical and authoritarian organization within the revolutionary movement itself, Bakunin sought to free women from their domestic burdens, with society taking collective responsibility for raising and educating children, enabling women to marry and divorce as they please. Bakunin rejected patriarchy in general, denouncing the âdespotism of the husband, of the father, of the eldest brother over the family,â which turns the family âinto a school of violence and triumphant bestiality, of cowardice and the daily perversions of the family homeâ (*Volume One, Selection 67*).
With respect to education, Bakunin argued that âone who knows more will naturally rule over the one who knows less.â After the revolution, unless differences in education and upbringing are eliminated, âthe human world would find itself in its present state, divided anew into a large number of slaves and a small number of rulersâ (*Volume One, Selection 64*). Bakunin looked forward to the day when âthe masses, ceasing to be flocks led and shorn by privileged priests,â whether secular or religious, âmay take into their own hands the direction of their destiniesâ (*Volume One, Selection 24*).
Bakunin argued against the rule of the more learned, the **savants,** the intellectuals and the scientists, whether within the International or in society at large. His targets here were the followers of Auguste Comte (1798â1857) and Karl Marx, with their pretensions to âscientific governmentâ and âscientific socialism.â To confide âthe government of societyâ to any scientific body, political party or group would result in the âeternal perpetuationâ of that groupâs power âby rendering the society confided to its care ever more stupid and consequently in need of its government and directionâ (*Volume One, Selection 24*). Bakunin was perhaps the first to develop this critique of the role of intellectuals, the ânew class,â and their rise to power, either by taking over leadership of the revolutionary workersâ movement or through control of the state bureaucracy, for the âState has always been the patrimony of some privileged class: the priesthood, the nobility, the bourgeoisie, and finally, after every other class has been exhausted, the bureaucratic class, when the State falls or rises⊠into the condition of a machineâ (*Volume One, Selection 22*).
Noam Chomsky has described Bakuninâs analyses and predictions in this regard as being perhaps âamong the most remarkable within the social sciencesâ (*Volume Two, Selection 68*). Subsequent anarchists adopted Bakuninâs critique (*Berti, Volume Two, Selection 67*) and his suggestion that the inequalities that arise from differences in knowledge can be prevented by âintegral education,â which breaks down the barriers between practical and scientific education, and by the elimination of any distinction between manual and âintellectualâ or âbrainâ work (*Volume One, Selection 64*). In his highly influential book, **Fields, Factories and Workshops** (1898), Peter Kropotkin set forth practical alternatives to the present âdivision of society into brain workers and manual workers,â with all its âperniciousâ distinctions, advocating, much like Fourier had before him, a daily combination of manual and intellectual work, human-scale technology and the integration of the fields, factories and workshops in a decentralized system of production, providing for âthe happiness that can be found in the full and varied exercise of the different capacities of the human beingâ (*Volume One, Selection 34*).
Bakunin was instrumental in spreading anarchist ideas among revolutionary and working class movements in Italy, Spain, Switzerland and Russia and within the International itself. According to Kropotkin, it was Bakunin more than anyone else who âestablished in a series of powerful pamphlets and letters the leading principles of modern anarchismâ (1912).
The Franco-Prussian War and the Paris Commune of 1870â1871 had a significant impact on emerging anarchist movements. Bakunin argued that the War should be turned into a mass uprising by the French workers and peasants against their domestic and foreign masters. To bring the peasants over to the side of the social revolution, Bakunin urged his fellow revolutionaries to incite the peasantry âto destroy, by direct action, every political, judicial, civil and military institution,â to âthrow out those landlords who live by the labour of othersâ and to seize the land. He rejected any notion of revolutionary dictatorship, warning that any attempt âto impose communism or collectivism on the peasants⊠would spark an armed rebellionâ that would only strengthen counter-revolutionary tendencies (*Volume One, Selection 28*).
Although it was Proudhon who had first proposed an alliance between the workers and peasants, it was Bakunin who saw the peasantry as a potentially revolutionary force. Bakunin and subsequent anarchists did not believe that a social revolution was only possible in advanced capitalist societies with a large industrial proletariat, as Marxists claimed, but rather looked to the broad masses of the exploited and downtrodden to overthrow their oppressors. Consequently, anarchists supported the efforts of indigenous peoples to liberate themselves from colonial domination and the local elites which benefitted from colonialism at their expense, particularly in Latin America with its feudalist latifundia system which concentrated ownership of the land in the hands of a few (*Volume One, Selections 71, 76 & 91*). In Russia, Italy, Spain and Mexico, anarchists sought to incite the peasants to rebellion with the battle cry of âLand and Libertyâ (*Volume One, Selections 71, 73, 85, 86, & 124*), while anarchists in China, Japan and Korea sought the liberation of the peasant masses from their feudal overlords (*Volume One, Selections 97, 99, 101, 104 & 105*).
Bakunin argued that the best way to incite the masses to revolt was ânot with words **but with deeds, for this is the most potent, and the most irresistible form of propaganda**â (*Volume One, Selection 28*). In Mexico, the anarchist Julio Chavez Lopez led a peasant uprising in 1868â1869, in which the insurgents would occupy a village or town, burn the land titles and redistribute the land among the peasants (Hart: 39). In September 1870, Bakunin participated in a short-lived attempt to create a revolutionary Commune in Lyon, proclaiming the abolition of mortgages and the judicial system (Leier: 258). He made a similar attempt with his anarchist comrades in Bologna in 1874.
In 1877, Bakuninâs associates, Carlo Cafiero (1846â1892), Errico Malatesta (1853â1932) and a small group of anarchists tried to provoke a peasant uprising in Benevento, Italy, by burning the local land titles, giving the villagers back their tax moneys and handing out whatever weapons they could find. Paul Brousse (1844â1912) described this as âpropaganda by the deed,â by which he did not mean individual acts of terrorism but putting anarchist ideas into action by seizing a commune, placing âthe instruments of production⊠in the hands of the workers,â and instituting anarchist communism (*Volume One, Selection 43*).
<br>
The inspiration for this form of propaganda by the deed was the Paris Commune of 1871, when the people of Paris proclaimed the revolutionary Commune, throwing out their national government. Varlin and other Internationalists took an active part in the Commune. After its bloody suppression by the Versailles government, during which Varlin was killed, several Communards were to adopt an explicitly anarchist position, including Elisée Reclus and Louise Michel.
The anti-authoritarian sections of the First International supported the Commune and provided refuge for exiled Communards. Bakunin commended the Communards for believing that the social revolution âcould neither be made nor brought to its full development except by the spontaneous and continued action of the massesâ (*Volume One, Selection 29*). James Guillaume thought that the Commune represented the revolutionary federalist negation of the nation State that âthe great socialist Proudhonâ had been advocating for years. By 1873, the Jura Federation of the International was describing the Commune as the first practical realization of the anarchist program of the proletariat. However, as David Stafford points out, the âmassacre of the Communards and the savage measures which followed it (it has been estimated that 30,000 people were killed or executed by the Versailles forces)â helped turn anarchists further away from Proudhonâs pacifist mutualism, which was seen as completely unable to deal with counter-revolutionary violence (Stafford: 20).
Louise Michel (1830â1905) had fought on the barricades when the French government sent in its troops to put down the Commune. The Union of Women for the Defence of Paris and the Care of the Wounded issued a manifesto calling for âthe annihilation of all existing social and legal relations, the suppression of all special privileges, the end of all exploitation, the substitution of the reign of work for the reign of capitalâ (*Volume One, Selection 30*). At Michelâs trial after the suppression of the Commune, she declared that she belonged âcompletely to the Social Revolution,â vowing that if her life were spared by the military tribunal, she would ânot stop crying for vengeance,â daring the tribunal, if they were not cowards, to kill her (*Volume One, Selection 30*).
Anarchists drew a number of lessons from the Commune. Kropotkin argued that the only way to have consolidated the Commune was âby means of the social revolutionâ (*Volume One, Selection 31*), with âexpropriationâ being its âguiding word.â The âcoming revolution,â Kropotkin wrote, would âfail in its historic missionâ without âthe complete expropriation of all those who have the means of exploiting human beings; [and] the return to the community⊠of everything that in the hands of anyone can be used to exploit othersâ (*Volume One, Selection 45*).
With respect to the internal organization of the Commune, Kropotkin noted that there âis no more reason for a government inside a commune than for a government above the commune.â Instead of giving themselves a ârevolutionaryâ government, isolating the revolutionaries from the people and paralyzing popular initiative, the task is to abolish âproperty, government, and the state,â so that the people can âthemselves take possession of all social wealth so as to put it in common,â and âform themselves freely according to the necessities dictated to them by life itselfâ (*Volume One, Selection 31*).
Following the suppression of the Commune, the conflict in the International between the anti-authoritarians and the supporters of top down political organization, such as Marx and his followers, came to a head. In response to Marxâs attempt to consolidate power in the Internationalâs General Council, and to make the conquest of political power by the working class a mandatory policy of the International, the Swiss Jura Federation denounced the fictitious unity the Council sought to create through âcentralization and dictatorship,â arguing that the âInternational, as the embryo of the human society of the future, is required in the here and now to faithfully mirror our principles of freedom and federationâ (*Volume One, Selection 26*).
After Bakunin and Guillaume were expelled, largely at Marxâs instigation, from the International on trumped up charges at the 1872 Hague Congress, the anti-authoritarian sections of the International held their own congress at St. Imier in Switzerland. The Congress declared âthe destruction of all political power,â rather than its conquest, as âthe first duty of the proletariat,â whose âaspirations⊠can have no purpose other than the establishment of an absolutely free economic organization and federation, founded upon the labour and equality of allâ (*Volume One, Selection 27*).
The St. Imier Congress extolled the benefits of militant trade union organization, for âit integrates the proletariat into a community of interests, trains it in collective living and prepares it for the supreme struggle.â The Congress embraced strike action âas a precious weapon in the struggle,â because it exposes âthe antagonism between labour and capitalâ and prepares âthe proletariat for the great and final revolutionary contestâ (*Volume One, Selection 27*). Whether the final revolutionary contest would be an insurrection, a general strike, or a combination of the two remained open to debate. At the time, many anarchists favoured insurrection, particularly those associated with the Italian Federation, which attempted insurrections in Bologna in 1874 and Benevento in 1877.
The proto-syndicalist elements in the anti-authoritarian wing of the International, exemplified by Guillaume, emphasized the need for organized working class resistance to the State and capital. This approach was particularly prominent in Spain and various parts of Latin America, where anarchists were involved in creating some of the first trade unions and workersâ federations.
In Spain this doctrine became known as anarchist âcollectivism,â which the Spanish veteran of the First International, JosĂ© Llunas Pujols (1850â1905), defined as â**a society organized on the basis of collective ownership, economic federation and the complete emancipation of the human being**â (*Volume One, Selection 36*). The âunit of organization would⊠be the trades section in each locality,â with administrative tasks performed by delegates who would be replaced if they failed to adhere to the mandates given to them by their respective sections (*Volume One, Selection 36*). This form of working class direct democracy, similar to the âWorker Democracyâ advocated by Proudhon in **On** **the Political Capacity of the Working Classes** (*Volume One, Selection 18*), was later taken up by the anarcho-syndicalists (*Volume One, Chapter 12*).
Following the defeat of the Paris Commune, the International was outlawed in much of Europe, making it extremely difficult for anarchists to maintain or create revolutionary working class organizations. Although the anti-authoritarian International outlasted the Marxist wing by several years, it eventually split between the anarchist communists, who favoured insurrectionary methods, the proto-syndicalists who favoured federations of revolutionary unions, and more moderate federalists who eventually embraced state socialism, such as CĂ©sar de Paepe from Belgium.
It was from among the debates within the anti-authoritarian International that the doctrine of anarchist communism emerged in the 1870s. François Dumartheray published a pamphlet in February 1876 advocating anarchist communism, and ElisĂ©e Reclus spoke in favour of it at the March 1876 Lausanne Congress of the anti-authoritarian International. By the fall of 1876, the Italian Federation considered âthe collective ownership of the products of labour to be the necessary complement of the [anarchist] collectivistâ program of common ownership of the means of production (Nettlau: 139). Anarchist communism was debated at the September 1877 Verviers Congress of the anti-authoritarian International, with Paul Brousse and the Italian anarchist, Andrea Costa, arguing in favour, and the Spanish anarchists, TomĂĄs GonzĂĄlez Morago and JosĂ© GarcĂa Viñas, defending the collectivist view, shared by Proudhon and Bakunin, that each person should be entitled to the full product of his or her labour.
At the October 1880 Congress of the Jura Federation, the delegates adopted an anarchist communist position, largely as the result of Cafieroâs speech, âAnarchy and Communismâ (*Volume One, Selection 32*). Cafiero defined the communist principle as â**from each and to each according to his will**,â with everyone having the right to take what they will âwithout demanding from individuals more work than they would like to give.â With production being geared towards satisfying peopleâs wants and needs, instead of the financial demands of the military, the state and the wealthy few, there will be no âneed to ask for more work than each wants to give, because there will be enough products for the morrow.â
Cafiero argued against the collectivist position on the basis that âindividual distribution of products would re-establish not only inequality between men, but also inequality between different kinds of work,â with the less fortunate being relegated the â**dirty** work,â instead of it being âvocation and personal taste which would decide a man to devote himself to one form of activity rather than another.â Furthermore, with âthe ever-increasing tendency of modern labour to make use of the labour of previous generationsâ embodied in the existing economic infrastructure, âhow could we determine what is the share of the product of one and the share of the product of another? It is absolutely impossible.â With respect to goods which are not sufficiently abundant to permit everyone to take what they will, Cafiero suggested that such goods should be distributed ânot according to **merit** but according to **need,**â much as they are in present-day families, with those in greater need, such as children and the elderly, being given the larger portions during periods of scarcity (*Volume One, Selection 32*).
Kropotkin further developed the theory of anarchist communism in a series of pamphlets and books, the best know and most influential being **The Conquest of Bread** (*Volume One, Selection 33*), and **Fields, Factories and Workshops** (*Volume One, Selection 34)*. The **Conquest of Bread** helped persuade many anarchists, including former collectivists in Spain, anarcho-syndicalists (*Volume One, Selections 58, 84, 95 & 114*), and anarchists in Japan, China and Korea (*Volume One, Selections 99, 106 & 108*), to adopt an anarchist communist position, sometimes referred to, particularly in Spain, as âlibertarian communismâ (*Volume One, Selection 124*).
In **Fields, Factories and Workshops**, Kropotkin set forth his vision of a decentralized anarchist communist society âof integrated, combined labour⊠where each worker works both in the field and in the workshop,â and each region âproduces and itself consumes most of its own agricultural and manufactured produce.â At âthe gates of your fields and gardens,â there will be a âcountless variety of workshops and factories⊠required to satisfy the infinite diversity of tastes⊠in which human life is of more account than machinery and the making of extra profits⊠into which men, women and children will not be driven by hunger, but will be attracted by the desire of finding an activity suited to their tastesâ (*Volume One, Selection 34*). This remarkably advanced conception of an ecologically sustainable society inspired many subsequent anarchists, including Gustav Landauer (1870â1919) in Germany (*Volume One, Selection 111*), and through him the kibbutz movement in Palestine (*Buber, Volume Two, Selection 1*6, and Horrox, 2009), the anarchist communists in China (*Volume One, Selection 99*), the âpureâ anarchists of Japan (*Volume One, Selection 106*), and the anarchist advocates of libertarian communism in Spain (*Volume One, Selection 124*).
Paul and Percival Goodman updated Kropotkinâs ideas in **Communitas** (1947), proposing not only the integration of the fields, factories and workshops, but also the home and the workplace, providing for decentralized, human-scale production designed âto give the most well-rounded employment to each person, in a diversified environment,â based on âsmall units with relative self-sufficiency, so that each community can enter into a larger whole with solidarity and independence of viewpointâ (*Volume Two, Selection 17*). In the 1960s, Murray Bookchin (1921â2006) argued that âthe anarchist concepts of a balanced community, a face-to-face democracy, a humanistic technology, and a decentralized society⊠are not only desirable, they are also necessaryâ to avoid ecological collapse and to support a libertarian society (*Volume Two, Selection 48*), a point made earlier by Ethel Mannin (*Volume Two, Selection 14*). Kropotkin continues to influence and inspire âgreenâ anarchists, such as Graham Purchase, who advocates an anarchist form of bioregionalism (*Volume Three, Selection 28*), and Peter Marshall, with his âliberation ecologyâ (*Volume Three, Selection 30*).
There is another aspect of Kropotkinâs conception of anarchist communism that had far-reaching implications, and this is his vision of a free society which âseeks the most complete development of individuality combined with the highest development of voluntary association in all its aspects.â These âever changing, ever modified associationsâ will âconstantly assume new forms which answer best to the multiple aspirations of allâ (*Volume One, Selection 41*). Some Italian anarchist communists, such as Luigi Galleani (1861â1931), argued for an even more fluid concept of voluntary association, opposing any attempts to create permanent organizations, whether an anarchist federation or a revolutionary trade union, arguing that any formal organization inevitably requires its members to âsubmit for the sake of disciplineâ and unity to âprovisions, decisions, [and] measures⊠even though they may be contrary to their opinion and their interestâ (*Volume One, Selection 35*).
As Davide Turcato points out (2009), the debate between âanti-organizationalists,â such as Galleani, and the âorganizationalists,â such as Malatesta, âwas a debate of great sophistication,â which developed many ideas which were to âbecome common currency in the sociological literature, particularly through the work of Robert Michels,â who recognized that âanarchists were the first to insist upon the hierarchical and oligarchic consequences of party organization.â
Most anarchist communists, including Kropotkin and Malatesta, believed that nonhierarchical organization is possible and desirable, although one must always be on guard against oligarchic and bureaucratic tendencies. In our day, Colin Ward (1924â2010), drawing explicitly on Kropotkinâs theory of voluntary association, has endeavoured to show that anarchist ideas regarding âautonomous groups, workersâ control, [and] the federal principle, add up to a coherent theory of social organization which is a valid and realistic alternative to the authoritarian, hierarchical institutional philosophy which we see in application all around usâ (*Volume Two, Selection 63*).
There were ongoing debates among anarchists regarding methods and tactics. Cafiero agreed with the late Carlo Pisacane that âideals spring from deeds, and not the other way aroundâ (*Volume One, Selections 16 & 44*). He argued that anarchists should seize every opportunity to incite âthe rabble and the poorâ to violent revolution, âby word, by writing, by dagger, by gun, by dynamite, sometimes even by the ballot when it is a case of voting for an ineligible candidateâ (*Volume One, Selection 44*).
Kropotkin argued that by exemplary actions âwhich compel general attention, the new idea seeps into peopleâs minds and wins converts. One such act may, in a few days, make more propaganda than thousands of pamphletsâ (1880).
Jean Grave (1854â1939) explained that through propaganda by the deed, the anarchist âpreaches by example.â Consequently, contrary to Cafiero, âthe means employed must always be adapted to the end, under pain of producing the exact contrary of oneâs expectationsâ. For Grave, the âsurest means of making Anarchy triumph is to act like an Anarchistâ (*Volume One, Selection 46*). Some anarchists agreed with Cafiero that any method that brought anarchy closer was acceptable, including bombings and assassinations. At the 1881 International Anarchist Congress in London, the delegates declared themselves in favour of âillegalityâ as âthe only way leading to revolutionâ (Cahm: 157â158), echoing Cafieroâs statement from the previous year that âeverything is right for us which is not legalâ (*Volume One, Selection 44*).
After years of state persecution, a small minority of self-proclaimed anarchists adopted terrorist tactics in the 1890s. Anarchist groups had been suppressed in Spain, Germany and Italy in the 1870s, particularly after some failed assassination attempts on the Kaiser in Germany, and the Kings of Italy and Spain in the late 1870s, even before Russian revolutionaries assassinated Czar Alexander II in 1881. Although none of the would be assassins were anarchists, the authorities and capitalist press blamed the anarchists and their doctrine of propaganda by the deed for these events, with the Times of London describing anarchism in 1879 as having ârevolution for its starting point, murder for its means, and anarchy for its idealsâ (Stafford: 131).
Those anarchists in France who had survived the Paris Commune were imprisoned, transported to penal colonies, or exiled. During the 1870s and 1880s, anarchists were prosecuted for belonging to the First International. In 1883, several anarchists in France, including Kropotkin, were imprisoned on the basis of their alleged membership, despite the fact that the anti-authoritarian International had ceased to exist by 1881. At their trial they declared: âScoundrels that we are, we claim bread for all, knowledge for all, work for all, independence and justice for allâ (Manifesto of the Anarchists, Lyon 1883).
Perhaps the most notorious persecution of the anarchists around this time was the trial and execution of the four âHaymarket Martyrsâ in Chicago in 1887 (a fifth, Louis Lingg, cheated the executioner by committing suicide). They were convicted and condemned to death on trumped up charges that they were responsible for throwing a bomb at a demonstration in the Chicago Haymarket area in 1886.
When Emile Henry (1872â1894) threw a bomb into a Parisian cafĂ© in 1894, describing his act as âpropaganda by the deed,â he regarded it as an act of vengeance for the thousands of workers massacred by the bourgeoisie, such as the Communards, and the anarchists who had been executed by the authorities in Germany, France, Spain and the United States. He meant to show to the bourgeoisie âthat those who have suffered are tired at last of their sufferingâ and âwill strike all the more brutally if you are brutal with themâ (1894). He denounced those anarchists who eschewed individual acts of terrorism as cowards.
Malatesta, who was no pacifist, countered such views by describing as âultra-authoritariansâ those anarchists who try âto justify and exalt every brutal deedâ by arguing that the bourgeoisie are just âas bad or worse.â By doing so, these self-described anarchists had entered âon a path which is the most absolute negation of all anarchist ideas and sentiments.â Although they had âentered the movement inspired with those feelings of love and respect for the liberty of others which distinguish the true Anarchist,â as a result of âa sort of moral intoxication produced by the violent struggleâ they ended up extolling actions âworthy of the greatest tyrants.â He warned that âthe danger of being corrupted by the use of violence, and of despising the people, and becoming cruel as well as fanatical prosecutors, exists for allâ (*Volume One, Selection 48*).
In the 1890s, the French state brought in draconian laws banning anarchist activities and publications. Bernard Lazare (1865â1903), the writer and journalist then active in the French anarchist movement, denounced the hypocrisy of the defenders of the status quo who, as the paid apologists for the police, rationalized the far greater violence of the state. He defiantly proclaimed that no âlaw can halt free thought, no penalty can stop us from uttering the truth⊠and the Idea, gagged, bound and beaten, will emerge all the more lively, splendid and mightyâ (*Volume One, Selection 62*).
Malatesta took a more sober approach, recognizing that âpast history contains examples of persecutions which stopped and destroyed a movement as well as of others which brought about a revolution.â He criticized those âcomrades who expect the triumph of our ideas from the multiplication of acts of individual violence,â arguing that âbourgeois society cannot be overthrownâ by bombs and knife blows because it is based âon an enormous mass of private interests and prejudices⊠sustained⊠by the inertia of the masses and their habits of submission.â While he argued that anarchists should ignore and defy anti-anarchist laws and measures where able to do so, he felt that anarchists had isolated themselves from the people. He called on anarchists to âlive among the people and to win them over⊠by actively taking part in their struggles and sufferings,â for the anarchist social revolution can only succeed when the people are âready to fight and⊠to take the conduct of their affairs into their own handsâ (*Volume One, Selection 53*).
The Haymarket Martyrs were part of the so-called âBlack International,â the International Working Peopleâs Association. The IWPA drew its inspiration from the anti-authoritarian International, and adopted a social revolutionary anarchist program at its founding Congress in Pittsburgh in 1883, openly advocating armed insurrection and the revolutionary expropriation of the capitalists by the workers themselves (*Volume One, Selection 55*). Following the example of the anti-authoritarian International of the 1870s, the IWPA sought to create revolutionary trade unions that would press for the immediate demands of the workers, for example the 8 hour day, while preparing for the social revolution. Around the same time, similar ideas were being propounded by the Workersâ Federation of the Spanish Region (*Volume One, Selection 36*), and by anarchists involved in working class movements in Latin America.
But by 1894 in Europe, when Malatesta again urged anarchists to go to the people, many agreed with him that after âtwenty years of propaganda and struggle⊠we are today nearly strangers to the great popular commotions which agitate Europe and Americaâ (*Volume One, Selection 53*). One of those anarchists was Fernand Pelloutier (1867â1901). Sensing growing disillusionment among the workers with the electoral tactics of the socialist parties, some anarchists had again become involved in the trade union movement. Pelloutier argued that through participation in the trade unions, anarchists âtaught the masses the true meaning of anarchism, a doctrineâ which can readily âmanage without the individual dynamiterâ (*Volume One, Selection 56*). It was from this renewed involvement in the workersâ struggles that anarcho-syndicalism was born (*Volume One, Chapter 12*).
Pelloutier argued, as Bakunin had before him (*Volume One, Selection 25*), that revolutionary trade union organizations, unlike the state, are based on voluntary membership and therefore operate largely on the basis of free agreement. Any trade union âofficialsâ are subject to âpermanent revocability,â and play a coordinating rather than a âdirectorialâ role. Through their own autonomous organizations, the workers will come âto understand that they should regulate their affairs for themselves,â and will be able to prevent the reconstitution of state power after the revolution by taking control of âthe instruments of production,â seeing âto the operation of the economy through the free grouping,â rendering âany political institution superfluous,â with the workers having already become accustomed âto shrug off tutelageâ through their participation in the revolutionary trade union, or âsyndicalist,â movement (*Volume One, Selection 56*).
Also noteworthy in Pelloutierâs call for renewed anarchist involvement in the workersâ movement was his endorsement of anarchist communism as the ultimate goal of the revolutionary syndicalist movement. However, in France, after Pelloutierâs death, the revolutionary syndicalist organization, the ConfĂ©dĂ©ration GĂ©nĂ©rale du Travail (CGT), adopted a policy of nonaffiliation with any party or doctrine, including anarchism. CGT militants, such as Pierre Monatte, claimed that within the CGT all doctrines enjoyed âequal toleranceâ (*Volume One, Selection 60*). The CGT focused on the means of revolutionary action, such as direct action and the general strike, instead of arguing over ideology.
This was in contrast to anarcho-syndicalist union federations, such as the Workersâ Federations of the Argentine Region (FORA) and the Uruguayan Region (FORU), which, as with Pelloutier, recommended âthe widest possible study of the economic-philosophical principles of anarchist communismâ (*Volume One, Selection 58*). The anarcho-syndicalists sought to organize the workers into revolutionary trade unions through which they would abolish the state and capitalism by means of general strikes, factory occupations, expropriation and insurrection. For the most part, their ultimate goal was anarchist communism, the abolition of wage labour, private property and the state, and the creation of free federations of worker, consumer and communal associations, whether in Latin America (*Volume One, Selection 95*), Russia (*Volume One, Selection 84*), Japan (*Volume One, Selection 107*), Spain (*Volume One, Selection 124*), or elsewhere.
Anarcho-syndicalists were behind the reconstitution of the International Workersâ Association (IWA/AIT) in 1922, with a membership of about two million workers from 15 countries in Europe and Latin America. At their founding Congress, they explicitly endorsed âlibertarian communismâ as their goal and rejected any âform of statism, even the so-called âDictatorship of the Proletariatâ,â because dictatorship âwill always be the creator of new monopolies and new privilegesâ (*Volume One, Selection 114*).
Anarchists who sought to work within revolutionary working class organizations or popular movements adopted different approaches regarding the proper relationship between their anarchist ideals and these broader based social movements. Some, such as AmadĂ©e Dunois (1878â1945), argued that anarchists needed their own organizations to coordinate their activities, to support their work within the trade unions and to spread their ideas, infusing the workersâ organizations âwith the anarchist spiritâ (Dunois, 1907). This model of dual organization was similar to what Bakunin had advocated during the First International, when he urged his comrades in his revolutionary brotherhood, the Alliance of Social Revolutionaries, which adhered to Bakuninâs anarchist program, to join the International in order to steer it in an anarchist direction.
Antonio Pellicer Paraire (1851â1916), a veteran of the anarchist Workersâ Federation of the Spanish Region (*Volume One, Selection 36*), acknowledged in an article from 1900 that, given the existing state of the workersâ movement, âparallel or dual organization has to be accepted,â with the anarchists maintaining their own revolutionary groups, but he argued that the primary focus must be on creating libertarian workersâ federations in which each worker is an equal and active participant, so as to prevent the development of a trade union bureaucracy and a de facto executive assuming control of the organization. Each organization must in turn retain âtheir autonomy and independence, free of meddling by other groups and with no one having methods, systems, theories, schools of thought, beliefs, or any faith shoved down his throatâ (*Volume One, Selection 57*). Only through the self-activity of the masses can an anarchist society hope to be achieved.
In his posthumously published work, **The Anarchist Conception of Syndicalism** (1920), Neno Vasco (1878â1920), who was active in the Brazilian and Portuguese anarchist movements, warned of the dangers of self-proclaimed anarchist groups, âpopulated more by rebels than by anarchists,â seizing the initiative and forcing âemancipationâ on the people by claiming âthe right to act on its behalf,â instead of prompting the people âto look to its own liberation,â with âthe persons concernedâ taking matters âdirectly in hand.â For example, the provision of suitable housing âshould be left to the tenants themselves,â a point later emphasized by Giancarlo de Carlo (*Volume Two, Selection 18*) and Colin Ward (1983), and âall the other production, transport and distribution services⊠should be entrusted to the workers working in each sector.â
Anarchists did not limit their involvement in popular struggles to the workersâ movement. Anarchists were also involved in various libertarian education movements that sought to bring to the masses the âintegral educationâ of which Bakunin spoke, in order to ensure âthat in the future no **class** can rule over the working masses, exploiting them, superior to them because it knows moreâ (*Volume One, Selection 64*).
In Europe, North America, Latin America, China and Japan, Francisco Ferrer (1859â1909) inspired the âModern Schoolâ movement which sought to liberate children from the authoritarian strictures of religious and state controlled schools by creating schools outside of the existing education system in which children would be free to pursue their individual inclinations and interests. Ferrer argued that, in contrast, religious and state schools imprison âchildren physically, intellectually, and morally, in order to direct the development of their faculties in the paths desiredâ by the authorities, making children âaccustomed to obey, to believe, to think according to the social dogmas which govern us,â and education âbut a means of domination in the hands of the governing powersâ (*Volume One, Selection 65*).
Ferrer had himself been influenced by earlier experiments in libertarian education in England and France by anarchists like Louise Michel and Paul Robin (1837â1912). His execution by Spanish authorities in 1909, rather than putting an end to the Modern School movement, gave it renewed inspiration.
In France, SĂ©bastien Faure (1858â1942) founded the âla Rucheâ (Beehive) free school in 1904. La Ruche was noteworthy for providing boys and girls with equal educational opportunities, sex education, and for its rejection of any form of punishment or constraint, all very radical approaches during an era when girls were either excluded or segregated, information regarding sex and contraception was censored, even for adults, and corporal punishment of students was routine. Faure, as with Godwin before him, rejected any system of punishments and rewards because âit makes no appealâ to the childâs reasoning or conscience, producing âa slavish, cowardly, sheepish breed⊠capable of cruelty and abjectionâ (*Volume One, Selection 66*)âŠ
Herbert Read (1893â1968) later expanded on the role of modern education in creating a submissive populace, much as Ferrer and Faure had before him. Through the education system, âeverything personal, everything which is the expression of individual perceptions and feelings, is either neglected, or subordinated to some conception of normality, of social convention, of correctness.â Read therefore advocated libertarian education, emphasizing the creative process and âeducation through art,â arguing that it âis only in so far as we liberateâ children, âshoots not yet stunted or distorted by an environment of hatred and injustice, that we can expect to make any enduring change in societyâ (*Volume Two, Selection 36*).
Paul Goodman (1911â1972) described the school system as âcompulsory mis-education,â which perpetuated a society in which youth are âgrowing up absurd.â His friend Ivan Illich (1926â2002) was later to advocate âdeschooling societyâ as a way of combating the commodification of social life, where everything, and everybody, becomes a commodity to be consumed (*Volume Two, Selection 73*). By the 1960s and 1970s, people were again experimenting in libertarian education (*Volume Two, Selection 46*), something which anarchists had been advocating since the time of William Godwin.
Louise Michel felt that women were âfamished for learningâ and could not understand why men would try to cripple womenâs intelligence, âas if there were already too much intelligence in the world.â For Michel, discrimination against girls and women was the greatest barrier to âthe equality of the sexes.â What women âwant is knowledge and education and liberty.â She looked forward to the day when men and women âwill no more argue about which sex is superior than races will argue about which race is foremost in the worldâ (*Volume One, Selection 68*).
Bakunin opposed the legal institution of marriage, arguing that the âunion of a man and a woman must be freeâ (*Volume One, Selection 67*). Carmen Lareva, an early anarchist feminist in Argentina who wrote for **La Voz de la Mujer** in the 1890s, one of the first explicitly anarchist feminist papers written by and for women, decried how the anarchist advocacy of âfree loveâ was distorted by opponents of anarchism into the claim that anarchists wanted to liberate women only to turn them âinto concubines, sordid playthings for manâs unrestrained passions.â Lareva argued that it was existing society, with its inequality, sexual hypocrisy and exploitation, which drove women to prostitution and forced them into marriages in which the woman âis required to feign love of someone she simply detestsâ in exchange for food and housing (*Volume One, Selection 69*).
Emma Goldman (1869â1940) argued that the only difference between a married woman and a prostitute was âthat the one has sold herself into chattel slavery during life, for a home or a title, and the other one sells herself for the length of time she desires.â She demanded âthe independence of woman; her right to support herself; to live for herself; to love whomever she pleases, or as many as she pleases,â in the here and now, not after the revolution (*Volume One, Selection 70*). Real sexual liberation meant that women should have free access to contraception so that they could be sexually active while still being free to decide whether and when to have children. Both Goldman and the American anarchist, Ezra Heywood (1829â1893), were imprisoned by U.S. authorities for trying to make birth control information and devices available to women.
âOfficial morality,â wrote ElisĂ©e Reclus in 1894, âconsists in bowing humbly to oneâs superiors and in proudly holding up oneâs head before oneâs subordinatesâ (*Volume One, Selection 38*). True morality can only exist between equals. âIt is not only against the abstract trinity of law, religion, and authorityâ that anarchists declare war, according to Kropotkin, but the inequality that gives rise to âdeceit, cunning, exploitation, depravity, vice⊠It is in the name of equality that we are determined to have no more prostituted, exploited, deceived and governed men and women.â
This sense of justice and solidarity, âwhich brings the individual to consider the rights of every other individual as equal to his own,â has been successively widened, from the clan, to the tribe, to the nation, to the whole of humankind, until it is transcended by a âhigher conception of âno revenge for wrongs,â and of freely giving more than one expects to receive from his neighboursâ (*Volume One, Selection 54*). For Kropotkin, acting morally is not only natural, but a means of self-fulfillment.
What anarchists sought to achieve was a world in which everyone is free to develop his or her talents and abilities to their fullest. This is impossible as long as workers are required to engage in labour merely to eke out an existence, taking whatever jobs they can get, women must work at home and in the factory or office, subject to their husbands and fathers at home, to their bosses at work, and to conventional morality always, and children must be trained to accept their lot in life and to obey their âbetters.â
It is for these reasons that anarchism, Kropotkin wrote, ârefuses all hierarchical organizationâ (*Volume One, Selection 41*). As Charlotte Wilson (1854â1944), who helped found the English language anarchist newspaper, **Freedom**, with Kropotkin in 1886, explained, âall coercive organizationâ with its âmachine-like regularity is fatal to the realizationâ of the anarchist ideal of self-fulfillment for all, not just the privileged few (*Volume One, Selection 37*).
The English anarchist, Charlotte Wilson, argued that when âeach worker will be entirely free to do as nature prompts⊠to throw his whole soul into the labour he has chosen, and make it the spontaneous expression of his intensest purpose and desire⊠labour becomes pleasure, and its produce a work of artâ (*Volume One, Selection 37*). For artists in bourgeois society, Jean Grave observed that they must sell their works to survive, âa situation which leads those who would not die of hunger to compromise, to vulgar and mediocre art.â To âlive their dream, realize their aspirations, they, too, must workâ for the social revolution. Even when possible, it âis vain for them to entrench themselves behind the privileges of the ruling classes,â for âif there is debasement for him who is reduced to performing the vilest tasks to satisfy his hunger, the morality of those who condemn him to it is not superior to his own; if obedience degrades, command, far from exalting character, degrades it alsoâ (*Volume One, Selection 63*).
Oscar Wilde (1854â1900), who for a time described himself as an anarchist, agreed with Grave, in **The Soul of Man Under Socialism**, that with the abolition of private property, all will be free âto choose the sphere of activity that is really congenial to them, and gives them pleasure.â However, Wilde did not look forward to the day when manual and intellectual labour would be combined, for some forms of manual labour are so degrading that they cannot be performed with dignity or joy: âMan is made for something better than disturbing dirt. All work of that kind should be done by machine.â
Wilde spoke in favour of anarchist socialism as providing the basis for true individualism and artistic freedom. He believed that the only form of government suitable to the artist âis no government at all. Authority over him and his art is ridiculous,â whether exercised by a government or by public opinion (*Volume One, Selection 61*). Wilson agreed that public opinion, âthe rule of universal mediocrity,â is âa serious danger to individual freedom,â but in a free society âit can only be counteracted by broader moral cultureâ (*Volume One, Selection 37*). For Wilde, this meant that âArt should never try to be popular. The public should try to make itself artisticâ (*Volume One, Selection 61*).
In turn of the century France, much of the artistic avant-garde allied themselves with anarchism, including such painters as Camille Pissarro, Paul Signac, Charles Maurin and Maximilien Luce, and writers like Paul Adam, Adolphe RettĂ©, Octave Mirbeau and Bernard Lazare. Jean Grave would include their work in his anarchist papers, **La RĂ©volte**, and later, **Les Temps Nouveaux**. When the French authorities again prosecuted anarchists simply for expressing their subversive ideas in the mid-1890s, Lazare wrote in **La RĂ©volte**: âWe had the audacity to believe that not everything was for the best in the best of all possible worlds, and we stated and state still that modern society is despicable, founded upon theft, dishonesty, hypocrisy and turpitudeâ (*Volume One, Selection 62*).
As can be seen, the anarchist critique of existing society was never limited to denouncing the state, capitalism and the church. It extended to the patriarchal family, the sexual exploitation and subjection of women, censorship, conformism, authoritarian education, and hierarchical and coercive forms of organization in general, no matter where they might be found, whether in the school, at the workplace or within the revolutionary movement itself.
The anarchist critique of science and technology goes back at least to Proudhon, who denounced machinery which, âafter having degraded the worker by giving him a master, completes his degeneracy by reducing him from the rank of artisan to that of common labourerâ (*Volume One, Selection 9*). Carlo Pisacane argued that technological innovation under capitalism simply concentrates economic power and wealth âin a small number of hands,â while leaving the masses in poverty (*Volume One, Selection 16*).
Other anarchists have argued that once the people take control of technology, it can be redesigned to eliminate onerous toil, much like Oscar Wilde suggested, to make workplaces safer and to increase production for the benefit of all. Carlo Cafiero recognized that in capitalist economies, the worker has reason to oppose the machinery âwhich comes to drive him from the factory, to starve him, degrade him, torture him, crush him. Yet what a great interest he will have, on the contrary, in increasing their number when he will no longer be at the service of the machines and when⊠the machines will themselves be at his service, helping him and working for his benefitâ (*Volume One, Selection 32*).
Gustav Landauer took a more critical position, arguing in 1911 that âthe capitalist system, modern technology and state centralism go hand in hand⊠Technology, allied with capitalism, makes [the worker] a cog in the wheels of the machine.â Consequently, the technology developed under capitalism cannot provide the basis for a free society. Rather, workers must âstep out of capitalism mentally and physically,â and begin creating alternative communities and technologies designed to meet their needs in conditions which they themselves find agreeable (*Volume One, Selection 79*). In the early 1960s, Paul Goodman (1911â1972) suggested some criteria âfor the humane selection of technology: utility, efficiency, comprehensibility, repairability, ease and flexibility of use, amenity and modestyâ (*Volume Two, Selection 70*), the use of which would result in something which Goodmanâs friend, Ivan Illich (1926â2002), described as âconvivial tools,â enabling âautonomous and creative intercourse among persons and⊠with their environmentâ (*Volume Two, Selection 73*).
Nineteenth century anarchists often extolled the virtues of modern science, particularly in contrast to religious belief, as part of their critique of the role of organized religion in supporting the status quo. In **What is Property**, Proudhon looked forward to the day when âthe sovereignty of the will yields to the sovereignty of reason, and must at last be lost in scientific socialismâ (*Volume One, Selection 8*). JosĂ© Llunas Pujols wrote in 1882 that in an anarchist society, âthe political State and theology would⊠be supplanted by Administration and Scienceâ (*Volume One, Selection 36*), echoing Saint Simonâs comment that in an enlightened society, the government of man will be replaced by the âadministration of thingsâ. In the conclusion to his 1920 anarchist program, Malatesta summed up what anarchists want as âbread, freedom, love, and science for everybodyâ (*Volume One, Selection 112*).
However, this did not mean that anarchists were uncritical supporters of science. One of the most widely published and translated anarchist pamphlets in the late 19th and early 20th centuries was Bakuninâs essay, **God and the State**, in which he discussed the limitations of scientific theory and research, and warned against the danger of entrusting our affairs to scientists and intellectuals. Bakunin argued that science âcannot go outside the sphere of abstractions,â being âas incapable of grasping the individuality of a man as that of a rabbit.â Because science cannot grasp or appreciate the existential reality of individual human beings, âit must never be permitted, nor must anyone be permitted in its name, to governâ individuals. Those claiming to govern in the name of science would yield âto the pernicious influence which privilege inevitably exercises upon men,â fleecing âother men in the name of science, just as they have been fleeced hitherto by priests, politicians of all shades, and lawyers, in the name of God, of the State, of judicial Rightâ (*Volume One, Selection 24*).
Even Kropotkin, who argued in **Modern Science and Anarchism** (1912) that anarchism âis a conception of the Universe based on the mechanical [kinetic] interpretation of phenomenaâ that ârecognizes no method of research except the scientific one,â never suggested that scientists should have a privileged role in society, nor that scientific hypotheses should be regarded as akin to human laws that need to be enforced by some authority. He decried the introduction of âartificial modes of expression, borrowed from theology and arbitrary power, into [scientific] knowledge which is purely the result of observationâ (*Volume One, Selection 52*), and argued that all theories and conclusions, including those of the anarchists, are subject to criticism and must be verified by experiment and observation.
Kropotkin no more endorsed âthe government of scienceâ than Bakunin did (*Volume One, Selection 24*). Instead, he looked forward to:
âA society in which all the mutual relations of its members are regulated, not by laws, not by authorities, whether self-imposed or elected, but by mutual agreement⊠and by a sum of social customs and habitsânot petrified by law, routine, or superstition, but continually developing and continually readjusted, in accordance with the ever-growing requirements of a free life, stimulated by the progress of science, invention, and the steady growth of higher idealsâ (**Modern Science and Anarchism**: 59).
The anarchist communist revolutionary Peter Kropotkin noted in **Modern Science and Anarchism** that among the scientific works that appeared in the mid-19th century, âthere was none which exercised so deep an influence as **The Origins of Species**, by Charles Darwin.â What Darwin demonstrated, Kropotkin argued, was that âman⊠was the product of a slow physiological evolution; that he drew his origin from a species of animals which gave birth both to man and the now-living apes and monkeys; that the âimmortal mindâ and the âmoral senseâ of man had developed in the same way as the intelligence and the social instincts of a chimpanzee or an ant.â
While anarchists welcomed Darwinâs ideas regarding evolution because they undermined the authority of religion by discrediting notions of divine creation and design, they also had to contend with the apologists of a rapacious capitalism, the âSocial Darwinists,â who used Darwinâs notion of âthe struggle for existenceâ to attack egalitarianism and to argue against social reform in general. As Kropotkin put it, there was âno infamy in civilized society, or in the relations of the whites towards the so-called lower races, or of the strong towards the weak, which would not have found its excuse in this formula.â
To combat the ideas of the Social Darwinists, Kropotkin wrote a series of essays, later published as **Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution** (1902), in which he sought to demonstrate âthe overwhelming importance which sociable habits play in Nature and in the progressive evolution of both the animal species and human beings.â It is from these practices of mutual aid, Kropotkin argued, that moral feelings are developed, leading him to conclude that âin the ethical progress of man, mutual supportânot mutual struggleâhas had the leading partâ (*Volume One, Selection 54*). Kropotkinâs notion of mutual aid and his critique of Social Darwinism was very influential in anarchist circles, not only in Europe but also in Latin America and Asia.
Some opponents of revolutionary change argued that the notion of âprogressive evolutionâ was inconsistent with the anarchist commitment to social revolution. As ElisĂ©e Reclus observed in 1891, the âword Evolution, synonymous with gradual and continuous development in morals and ideas, is brought forward in certain circles as though it were the antithesis of that fearful word, Revolution, which implies changes more or less sudden in their action⊠entailing some sort of catastrophe.â It was Reclus, not Kropotkin, who first developed the idea that revolutionary upheavals are part of a natural evolutionary process, an accelerated period of evolutionary change, such that revolution and evolution âare fundamentally one and the same thing, differing only according to the time of their appearance.â Turning Social Darwinism on its head, he argued that as âpowerful as may be the Master,â and the âprivileged classesâ in general, they âwill be weak before the starving masses leagued againstâ them. âTo the great evolution now taking place will succeed the long expected, the great revolutionâ (*Volume One, Selection 74*). This was a common theme among late 19th and early 20th century anarchists, including anarchists in Japan (*Volume One, Selection 102*) and China (*Volume One, Selections 97, 100 & 102*).
Anarchist supporters of science also had to contend with the development of a racist ethnology, purportedly based on scientific theory and research, which was used to justify colonial exploitation and war against the so-called âinferiorâ races. In his 1904 essay, ironically entitled âOur Indians,â the Peruvian anarchist intellectual, Manuel GonzĂĄlez Prada (1848â1919), marveled at what âa handy inventionâ ethnology was in the hands of those who seek to justify white domination: âOnce one has accepted that Mankind is divided into superior and inferior races and acknowledged the white manâs superiority and thus his right to sole governance of the Planet, there cannot be anything more natural than suppression of the black man in Africa, the redskin in the United States, the Tagalog in the Philippines and the Indian in Peruâ (*Volume One, Selection 91*).
While GonzĂĄlez Prada questioned the âscienceâ behind racist doctrines, pointing out that there âis such a mish-mash of blood and colouring, every individual represents so many licit or illicit dalliances, that when faced by many a Peruvian we would be baffled as to the contribution of the black man or the yellow man to their make-up: none deserves the description of pure-bred white man, even if he has blue eyes and blond hair,â he argued that rather than âgoing around the world spreading the light of [European] art and science, better to go around dispensing the milk of human kindness,â for âwhere the âstruggle for existenceâ is enunciated as the rule of society, barbarism rules.â GonzĂĄlez Prada agreed with Kropotkin that the true mark of progress and civilization is the degree to which practices and institutions of mutual aid are spread throughout society, such that âdoing good has graduated from being an obligation to being a habitâ (*Volume One, Selection 91*).
From the time that explicitly anarchist ideas emerged from Europe in the 1840s, anarchists have denounced the artificial division of peoples into competing nations and states as an unceasing source of militarism, war and conflict, and as a means by which the ruling classes secure the obedience of the masses. âIt is the governments,â Proudhon wrote in 1851, âwho, pretending to establish order among men, arrange them forthwith in hostile camps, and as their only occupation is to produce servitude at home, their art lies in maintaining war abroad, war in fact or war in prospect. The oppression of peoples and their mutual hatred are two correlative, inseparable facts, which reproduce each other, and which cannot come to an end except simultaneously, by the destruction of their common cause, governmentâ (*Volume One, Selection 12*).
In **Moribund Society and Anarchy** (1893), Jean Grave asked, âwhat can be more arbitrary than frontiers? For what reason do men located on this side of a fictitious line belong to a nation more than those on the other side? The arbitrariness of these distinctions is so evident that nowadays the racial spirit is claimed as the justification for parceling peoples into distinct nations. But here again the distinction is of no value and rests upon no serious foundation, for every nation is itself but an amalgamation of races quite different from each other, not to speak of the interminglings and crossings which the relations operating among nations, more and more developed, more and more intimate, bring about everyday⊠To the genuine individual all men are brothers and have equal rights to live and to evolve according to their own wills, upon this earth which is large enough and fruitful enough to nourish all⊠Instead of going on cutting each otherâs throats [the workers] ought to stretch out their hands across the frontiers and unite all their efforts in making war upon their real, their only enemies: authority and capitalâ (*Volume One, Selection 76*).
Having drawn the connection between racism, patriotism and war, Grave went on to deal with colonialism, âthis hybrid product of patriotism and mercantilism combinedâbrigandage and highway robbery for the benefit of the ruling classes!â Bakunin had earlier remarked that âto offend, to despoil, to plunder, to assassinate or enslave oneâs fellowman is ordinarily regarded as a crime. In public life, on the other hand, from the standpoint of patriotism, when these things are done for the greater glory of the State, for the preservation or the extension of its power, it is all transformed into duty and virtueâ (*Volume One, Selection 20*).
In his discussion of colonialism, Grave observed in a similar vein that when someone breaks âinto his neighbourâs house,â stealing whatever he can, âhe is a criminal; society condemns him. But if a government finds itself driven to a standstill by an internal situation which necessitates some external âdiversionâ; if it be encumbered at home by unemployed hands of which it knows not how to rid itself; of products which it cannot get distributed; let this government declare war against remote peoples which it knows to be too feeble to resist it, let it take possession of their country, subject them to an entire system of exploitation, force its products upon them, massacre them if they attempt to escape this exploitation with which it weighs them down⊠It is no longer called robbery or assassination⊠this is called âcivilizingâ undeveloped peoplesâ (*Volume One, Selection 76*).
Anarchists opposed colonial domination and exploitation, as well as militarism, war and the State. At the 1907 International Anarchist Congress in Amsterdam, the delegates declared themselves âenemies of all armed force vested in the hands of the Stateâbe it army, gendarmerie, police or magistracyâ and expressed their âhope that all the peoples concerned will respond to any declaration of war by insurrectionâ (*Volume One, Selection 80*). Unfortunately, when war broke out in Europe in 1914, the peoples concerned did not respond with insurrection against their warring masters but for the most part rushed off to slaughter. This caused a very small minority of anarchists, including some very prominent ones, such as Grave and Kropotkin, to support the war against Germany in order to defend English and French âlibertiesâ against German imperialism.
Most anarchists opposed the war, with a group including Malatesta, Emma Goldman, Alexander Berkman, Luigi Bertoni, George Barrett, Ferdinand Domela Niewenhuis and Alexander Schapiro issuing an International Anarchist Manifesto Against War (1915), in which they argued that France, with âits Biribi [penal battalions in Algeria], its bloody conquests in Tonkin, Madagascar, Morocco, and its compulsory enlistment of black troops,â and England, âwhich exploits, divides, and oppresses the population of its immense colonial Empire,â were hardly deserving of anarchist support (*Volume One, Selection 81*). Rather, it is the mission of anarchists who, Malatesta wrote, âwish the end of all oppression and of all exploitation of man by man⊠to awaken a consciousness of the antagonism of interests between dominators and dominated, between exploiters and workers, and to develop the class struggle inside each country, and the solidarity among all workers across the frontiers, as against any prejudice and passion of either race or nationalityâ (*Volume One, Selection 80*).
Prior to the First World War, anarchism had become an international revolutionary movement, with the largest anarchist movements in countries with anarcho-syndicalist trade union organizations, such as Spain, Italy, Portugal, Argentina, Brazil, Mexico and Uruguay, or like minded revolutionary syndicalist movements, as in France. In the early 1900s, anarchist ideas were introduced to Japan (*Volume One, Selection 102*) and China (*Volume One, Selections 96â99*). Anarchists and syndicalists, despite the efforts of the Marxists and social democrats to exclude the anarchists from the international socialist movement, formed the extreme left wing of the socialist and trade union movements. Anarchist ideas regarding direct action, autonomous social organization, anti-parliamentarianism, expropriation, social revolution and the general strike were gaining more currency, particularly after the 1905 Russian Revolution, and the Mexican Revolution of 1910.
In January 1905, Czarist troops massacred scores of protesters at a demonstration in St. Petersburg, precipitating a general strike and the formation of the first âsoviets,â or workersâ councils in Russia (Voline, 1947: 96â101). Following Russiaâs defeat in its war against Japan in February 1905, unrest spread throughout Russia, culminating in a countrywide general strike in October 1905. The Czar was forced to promise constitutional reforms, which he soon reneged upon. Nevertheless, the great general strike of October 1905 made a deep impression on workers and revolutionaries around the world, giving renewed credence to anarchist ideas, for it was the anarchists who had been advocating the general strike as a revolutionary weapon since the time of the First International (*Volume One, Selection 27*). The Marxist social democrats had been dismissing the general strike as âgeneral nonsenseâ for years (Joll: 193).
Kropotkin observed that âwhat exasperated the rulers mostâ about the general strike âwas that the workers offered no opportunity for shooting at them and reestablishing âorderâ by massacres. A new weapon, more terrible than street warfare, had thus been tested and proved to work admirablyâ (1905: 280). Despite this practical vindication of anarchist ideas, Malatesta was careful to point out the limitations of the general strike. Instead of âlimiting ourselves to looking forward to the general strike as a panacea for all ills,â Malatesta warned, anarchists needed to prepare for the insurrection or civil war which would inevitably follow the workersâ seizure of the means of production. For it is not enough for the workers to halt production; to avoid being forced by their own hunger back to work, the workers need to provide for themselves (*Volume One, Selection 60*).
As the anarchist pacifist Bart de Ligt (1883â1938) put it in the 1930s, âthe workers must not strike by going home or into the streets, thus separating themselves from the means of production and giving themselves over to dire poverty but⊠on the contrary, they must stay on the spot and control these means of productionâ for their own benefit (*Volume One, Selection 120*). Maurice Joyeux (1910â1991), following the May-June 1968 events in France, described such action as the âself-managerialâ general strike, by which the workers directly take control of the means of production (*Volume Two, Selection 61*).
No revolutionary group could claim credit for the 1905 Russian Revolution. As Kropotkin noted, the October 1905 general strike âwas not the work of any revolutionary organization. It was entirely a workingmenâs affairâ (1905: 278). What the anarchists could do was point to the 1905 Russian Revolution as a practical vindication of their ideas, enabling them to reach a much broader audience inspired by these events.
While the Russian workers were able to bring Russia to a standstill in October 1905, it was during the 1910 Mexican Revolution that expropriation was first applied on a wide scale by landless peasants and indigenous peoples. Anarchists in Mexico had been advocating that the people seize the land and abolish all government since the late 1860s, when Julio Chavez Lopez declared that what they wanted was âthe land in order to plant it in peace and harvest it in tranquility; to leave the system of exploitation and give liberty to allâ (*Volume One, Selection 71*).
In 1878, the anarchist group La Social advocated the abolition of the Mexican state and capitalism, the creation of autonomous federated communes, equal property holdings for those who worked the land, and the abolition of wage labour. When the government renewed its campaign of expropriation of peasant lands in favour of foreign (primarily U.S.) interests and a tiny group of wealthy landowners, the anarchists urged the peasants to revolt. Anarchist inspired peasant rebellions spread throughout Mexico, lasting from 1878 until 1884 (Hart: 68â69). Another peasant rebellion broke out in Veracruz in 1896, leading to a lengthy insurgency that continued through to the 1910 Mexican Revolution (Hart: 72).
In 1906 and 1908, the anarchist oriented Liberal Party of Mexico (PLM) led several uprisings in the Mexican countryside. On the eve of the 1910 Mexican Revolution, the PLM issued a manifesto, âTo Arms! To Arms for Land and Liberty,â written by the anarchist Ricardo Flores MagĂłn (1874â1922). He urged the peasants to take âthe Winchester in handâ and seize the land, for the land belongs âto all men and women who, by the very fact that they are living, have a right to share in common, by reason of their toil, all that wealth which the Earth is capable of producingâ (*Volume One, Selection 73*). The PLM organized the first armed insurrections against the DĂaz dictatorship in the late fall of 1910, beginning a revolution that was to last until 1919. Throughout Mexico, the largely indigenous peasantry arose in rebellion, seizing the land and redistributing it among themselves.
Anarchists outside of Mexico regarded this expropriation of the land by the Mexican peasantry as yet another vindication of their ideas. As Voltairine de Cleyre (1866â1912) put it, âpeasants who know nothing about the jargon of the land reformers or of the Socialistsâ knew better than the âtheory spinners of the citiesâ how to âget back the land⊠to ignore the machinery of paper landholding (in many instances they have burned the records of the title deeds) and proceed to plough the ground, to sow and plant and gather, and keep the product themselvesâ (*Volume One, Selection 71*). This was the model of the peasant social revolution that Chavez Lopez had tried to instigate in 1869, that Bakunin had advocated during the 1870 Franco-Prussian War (*Volume One, Selection 28*), and that anarchists in Europe and Latin America had been trying to instigate for years.
In Japan, KĂŽtoku ShĂ»sui (1871â1911), who had begun his political career as an orthodox Marxist, embraced anarchism in 1905, introducing anarchist communist and anarcho-syndicalist ideas to Japanese radicals. KĂŽtoku advocated the creation of interlinked trade union and cooperative organizations to provide the basis for anarchist communes âat the time of or in the aftermath of a revolution,â an idea that can be traced back to Bakunin, Guillaume and the anarchist currents in the First International. He argued in favour of working class direct action and anti-parliamentarianism: the workers âmust act for themselves without relying on slow moving parliaments.â The workers would strike to improve their working conditions while pushing âon to the general strike,â while the hungry would expropriate food from the rich, instead of waiting for legal reforms (*Volume One, Selection 102*). He translated Kropotkin into Japanese, and anarcho-syndicalist material, such as Siegfried Nachtâs 1905 pamphlet, **The Social General Strike**.
In 1910, Akaba Hajime, another Japanese anarchist, published **The Farmersâ Gospel**, in which he called for the âreturn to the âvillage communityâ of long ago, which our remote ancestors enjoyed. We must construct the free paradise of âanarchist communism,â which will flesh out the bones of the village community with the most advanced scientific understanding and with the lofty morality of mutual aidâ (Crump, 1996). The Japanese anarchist feminist, ItĂŽ Noe (1895â1923), pointed to the Japanese peasant village as an example of living anarchy, âa social life based on mutual agreementâ and mutual aid (*Volume One, Selection 104*). As with anarchists in Europe and Latin America, the Japanese anarchists sought to unite the workers and peasants in the struggle for a free society.
Despite the execution of KĂŽtoku in 1911 following the infamous Japanese treason trials, which were used to smash the nascent Japanese anarchist movement, Akabaâs imprisonment and death in 1912, and the 1923 police murder of ItĂŽ Noe and her companion, Ćsugi Sakae, another prominent anarchist (*Volume One, Selection 103*), the anarchists remained a significant force on the Japanese left throughout the 1920s.
In 1907, a group of Chinese anarchists created the Society for the Study of Socialism in Tokyo. Two of the Societyâs founders, Liu Shipei (1884â1919) and Zhang Ji (1882â1947), were in contact with KĂŽtoku ShĂ»sui, who introduced them to the ideas of Kropotkin and the anarcho-syndicalists. Liu, Zhang and KĂŽtoku all spoke about anarchism at the Societyâs founding meeting (Scalapino & Yu). Zhang contributed to **Balance**, a Chinese anarchist journal published in Tokyo, which in 1908 ran a series of articles calling for a peasant revolution in China and âthe combination of agriculture and industry,â as proposed by Kropotkin in **Fields, Factories and Workshops** (Dirlik: 104). Following KĂŽtokuâs example, Zhang also translated Nachtâs pamphlet on **The Social General Strike** into Chinese.
Liu and his wife, He Zhen, published another Chinese anarchist journal in Tokyo, **Natural Justice**. He Zhen advocated womenâs liberation, a particularly pressing concern in China, where foot-binding and concubinage were still common practices. She was familiar with the debates in Europe regarding womenâs suffrage but argued that âinstead of competing with men for power, women should strive for overthrowing menâs rule,â a position close to that of Louise Michel and Emma Goldman. She criticized those women who advocated sexual liberation merely âto indulge themselves in unfettered sexual desires,â comparing them to prostitutes, a view similar to that of European and Latin American anarchist women, such as Carmen Lareva, who were also concerned that the anarchist notion of âfree loveâ not be confused with making women sexually available to men (*Volume One, Selection 69*). He Zhen insisted that âwomen should seek their own liberation without relying on men to give it to themâ (*Volume One, Selection 96*). Womenâs liberation became a common cause for the Chinese anarchists, who rejected the traditional patriarchal family and often lived in small communal groups.
Chinese anarchists in Guangzhou began labour organizing in 1913, creating the first Chinese trade unions, inspired by Shifu (1884â1915), the anarchist communist who became known as âthe soul of Chinese anarchismâ (Krebs). Heavily influenced by Kropotkin, Shifu advocated anarchist communism, the abolition of all coercive institutions, freedom and equality for men and women, and voluntary associations where no one will âhave the authority to manage others,â and in which there will âbe no statutes or regulations to restrict peopleâs freedomâ (*Volume One, Selection 99*).
In the conclusion to his 1914 manifesto, âThe Goals and Methods of the Anarchist-Communist Party,â Shifu referred to the âwar clouds [filling] every part of Europe,â with âmillions of workers⊠about to be sacrificed for the wealthy and the nobilityâ (*Volume One, Selection 99*). Kropotkinâs subsequent support for the war against Germany shocked anarchists throughout the world, and was particularly damaging in Russia where his position was seen as support for Czarist autocracy (Avrich, 1978: 116â119; 136â137). However, as the war continued, the anarchists who maintained their anti-war, anti-militarist and anti-statist position began again to find a sympathetic ear among the workers and peasants who bore the brunt of the inter-imperialist slaughter in Europe, and who were to arise **en masse** in February 1917 in Russia, overthrowing the Czar.
In addition to the various revolutionary currents that existed within the anarchist movement prior to the outbreak of World War I, individualist anarchism began to emerge as a distinct current in the United States and Europe. In contrast to many contemporary individualists, particularly in the United States, who sometimes identify themselves as âanarcho-capitalists,â a concept most anarchists would regard as hopelessly self-contradictory (Volume Three, Chapter 9), the individualist anarchists of the late 19th and early 20th centuries were anti-capitalist.
The leading individualist anarchist in the United States was Benjamin Tucker (1854â1939). Tucker was a great admirer of Proudhon, translating **What Is Property** (1876) and Volume One of **The System of Economic Contradictions** (1888) into English. Nevertheless, when describing Proudhonâs anarchism, Tucker in reality set forth his own view of anarchism as âthe logical carrying out of the Manchester doctrine; **laissez faire** the universal rule,â a position which Proudhon would have rejected. Tucker was opposed to compulsory taxation, state currencies, regulation of the banking system, tariffs, patents, and the large corporations, the âtrusts,â that were building their own monopolies on the basis of these state âmonopolies.â He denounced revolutionary anarchists, such as Kropotkin and Johann Most, as âCommunists who falsely call themselves anarchists,â particularly for their advocacy of expropriation, which Tucker regarded as inconsistent with anarchist ends (Tucker, 1888).
Yet despite Tuckerâs discovery of Max Stirnerâs egoism in the late 1880s (Martin: 249â254), Tucker remained a self-righteous ideologue disapproving of those anarchists who advocated armed struggle, expropriation and social revolution. Stirner, on the other hand, would have had no reason to condemn expropriation or the use of force, having suggested that the dispossessed simply take from the rich because âI give myself the right of property in taking property to myself.â In fact, Stirner can be seen as the original advocate of anarchist âillegalism,â when he argued that âin all cases where [the egoistâs] advantage runs against the Stateâs,â the egoist âcan satisfy himself only by crimeâ (Volume One, Selection 11). It was this aspect of Stirnerâs egoism that was seized upon by individualist anarchists in Europe around the turn of the century, who articulated and sometimes put into practice a much more radical conception of individualist anarchism than had been developed in the United States by Tucker and his associates, one which did not shy away from violence and which regarded itself as revolutionary.
In 1909, the then individualist anarchist, Victor Kibalchich (better known by his later moniker, Victor Serge (1890â1947), after he went over to Bolshevism), wrote in France that the anarchist âchooses the methods of struggle, according to his power and circumstance. He takes no account of any conventions which safeguard property: for him, force alone counts. Thus, we have neither to approve or disapprove of illegal actions⊠The anarchist is always illegalâtheoretically. The sole word âanarchistâ means rebellion in every senseâ (Perry: 50).
Kibalchich was associated with some of the future members of the âBonnot Gang,â which conducted the first bank robbery using getaway cars in late December 1911. Soon after the robbery, during which a bank clerk was shot, Kibalchich wrote that the shooting âproved that some men have at least understood the virtues of audacity. I am not afraid to own up to it: I am with the banditsâ (Perry: 90). However, after Bonnot was killed in a shoot out and Kibalchich was put on trial along with survivors of the gang, he tried to distance himself from the âbandits,â claiming that he was merely an anarchist âpropagandistâ who did ânot pretend to defendâ his former comrades, âfor a gulf separates philosophical anarchistsâ from those who seek to justify their crimes in the name of anarchism (Perry: 158â159).
It was the kind of betrayal Kibalchich was to repeat in Russia after the 1917 Revolution when he renounced anarchism altogether, throwing his support behind the Bolshevik dictatorship. When justifying the Bolsheviksâ violent suppression of the anarchist movement, Kibalchich (now Serge) again drew a distinction between âcounter-revolutionaryâ armed anarchist groups who hid common criminals within their ranks, and âideologicalâ anarchists, who were allegedly left alone to make their âineffectiveâ propaganda (Serge, 1930). It was a distinction Lenin and the Bolsheviks were happy to make, but never honour (Berkman, 1925: 91 & 142â151).
Emile Armand (1872â1962), a more consistent individualist anarchist writing in France in 1911, supported âillegalism⊠with certain reservations.â For him, the individualist âanarchist seeks to live without gods or masters; without bosses or leaders; a-legally, bereft of laws as well as of prejudices; amorally, free of obligations as well as of collective morality.â The European individualists shared the anti-organizationalist critique of all formal organization but, as with Tucker and his associates, opposed anarchist communism. The individual, Armand wrote, âwould be as much of a subordinate under a communist system as he is today.â Armand believed that individual autonomy could only be guaranteed by individual ownership of the means necessary to support oneself, the product of oneâs own labour, and the goods one receives in exchange with others. He was much clearer than Tucker in opposing âthe exploitation of anyone by one of his neighbours who will set him to work in his employ and for his benefitâ (Volume One, Selection 42).
Both Tucker and the European individualists developed a conception of anarchism representing an incoherent amalgam of Stirnerian egoism and Proudhonian economics, although the European individualists were more consistent in their extremism. The problem for both is that while an egoist will not want to be exploited or dominated by anyone else, there is no reason why he or she would not exploit or dominate others. If the egoist can use existing power structures, or create new ones, to his or her advantage, then there is no reason for the egoist to adopt an anarchist stance. Furthermore, when each person regards the other simply as a means to his or her ends, taking and doing whatever is in his or her power, as Stirner advocated, it would seem unlikely that a Proudhonian economy of small property holders exchanging their products among one another would be able to function, for Proudhonâs notions of equivalent exchange and economic justice would carry no weight, even if they were feasible in a modern industrial economy.
Armand rejected Proudhonâs notion of contract, arguing that âevery contract can be voided the moment it injures one of the contracting parties,â since the individual is âfree of all obligations as well as of collective morality.â At most, the individualist âis willing to enter into short-term arrangements onlyâ as âan expedient,â being âonly ever answerable to himself for his deeds and actionsâ (Volume One, Selection 42).
Tucker, despite his attempts to base his anarchism on Stirnerâs egoism, believed that contracts freely entered into should be binding and enforceable. In addition, he advocated the creation of âself-defenceâ associations to protect peopleâs property, opening the way, Kropotkin argued, âfor reconstituting under the heading of âdefenceâ all the functions of the stateâ (1910: 18). Anarchist communists, such as Kropotkin, did not âsee the necessity of⊠enforcing agreements freely entered uponâ by people in an anarchist society, for even in existing society the âsimple habit of keeping oneâs word, the desire of not losing confidence, are quite sufficient in an overwhelming majority of cases to enforce the keeping of agreementsâ (1887: 47 & 53). Force is only necessary to maintain relationships of subordination and exploitation, âto prevent the labourers from taking possession of what they consider unjustly appropriated by the few; and⊠to continually bring new âuncivilized nationsâ under the same conditionsâ (1887: 52).
In 1916, echoing Bakuninâs position during the Franco-Prussian War, Russian anarchists who rejected Kropotkinâs pro-war stance called for the âimperialist warâ in Europe to be transformed into an all embracing social revolution (Geneva Group of Anarchist-Communists, 1916: 44â47). In February 1917, the long sought after Russian Revolution began with relatively spontaneous uprisings for which, much like the 1905 Russian Revolution, no particular group could claim credit.
For the anarchists, the âFebruary Revolutionâ was another vindication of their view of social revolution. âAll revolutions necessarily begin in a more or less spontaneous manner,â wrote the Russian anarchist Voline. The task for revolutionary anarchists is to work with the insurgent people to enable them to take control of their own affairs, without any intermediaries, and to prevent the reconstitution of state power. For Voline and the anarchists, effective âemancipation can be achieved only by the **direct, widespread, and independent action of those concerned, of the workers themselves**, grouped, not under the banner of a political party or of an ideological formation, but in their own class organizations (productive workersâ unions, factory committees, co-operatives, etc.) on the basis of concrete action and self-government, **helped, but not governed**, by revolutionaries working in the very midst of, and not above the massâ (*Volume One, Selection 87*).
The anarchists therefore opposed the Provisional Government which replaced the Czarist regime and pressed for the expropriation by the workers and peasants themselves of the means of production and distribution, a process the workers and peasants had already begun, with workers taking over their factories and peasants seizing the land that they had worked for generations. Anarchist communists expropriated the homes of the rich and called for the creation of revolutionary communes (Avrich, 1978: 125â126 & 130).
Many anarchists supported and participated in the peasant and worker âsovietsâ that sprang up across Russia, following a pattern similar to the 1905 Russian Revolution. The anarcho-syndicalist, Gregory Maksimov, described the soviets as having âbeen brought into being by the proletariat spontaneously, by revolutionary means, and with that element of improvisation which springs from the needs of each locality and which entails (a) the revolutionizing of the masses, (b) the development of their activity and self-reliance, and (c) the strengthening of their faith in their own creative powersâ (*Volume One, Selection 83*).
When Lenin rejected the orthodox Marxist view that Russia had to proceed through a âbourgeoisâ revolution and the development of a capitalist economy before socialism could be implemented, calling for a proletarian revolution that would replace the Russian state with worker and peasant soviets modeled after the Paris Commune, he was not only recognizing what was already happening, but adopting a position so close to the anarchists that both orthodox Marxists and many anarchists regarded the Bolsheviks as the anarchistsâ allies (Avrich, 1978: 127â130). Many anarchists worked with the Bolsheviks to overthrow the Provisional Government in October 1917, and to dissolve the newly elected Constituent Assembly in January 1918.
Soon after the October Revolution, some anarchists began to realize that rather than pushing the social revolution forward, the Bolsheviks were seeking to establish their own dictatorship, subordinating the soviets to their party organization. Maksimov therefore proclaimed in December 1917 that the anarchists âwill go with the Bolsheviks no longer, for their âconstructiveâ work has begun, directed towards what we have always fought⊠the strengthening of the state. It is not our cause to strengthen what we have resolved to destroy. We must go to the lower classes to organize the work of the thirdâand perhaps the lastârevolutionâ (*Volume One, Selection 83*).
Because the soviets, as âpresently constituted,â were being transformed by the Bolsheviks into organs of state power, Maksimov argued that the anarchists âmust work for their conversion from centres of authority and decrees into non-authoritarian centres,â linking the âautonomous organizationsâ of the workers together (*Volume One, Selection 83*). But as the Bolsheviks continued to consolidate their power, subordinating not only the soviets but also the trade unions to their ârevolutionaryâ government, the anarcho-syndicalists began to emphasize the role of the factory committees in furthering the cause of the anarchist social revolution and in combatting both capitalism and the nascent Bolshevik dictatorship.
At their August 1918 congress, the Russian anarcho-syndicalists described the factory committee as âa fighting organizational form of the entire workersâ movement, more perfect than the soviet of workersâ, soldiersâ and peasantsâ deputies in that it is a basic self-governing producersâ organization under the continuous and alert control of the workers⊠With the aid of the factory committees and their industry-wide federations, the working class will destroy both the existing economic slavery and its new form of state capitalism which is falsely labelled âsocialismâ,â which the Bolsheviks were in the process of establishing (*Volume One, Selection 84*).
A similar approach was put forward by anarchists in Italy during the factory occupations in 1919â1920, and by anarchists in Germany. Malatesta, returning to Italy in late 1919, argued, as he had before in his debates with the syndicalists (*Volume One, Selection 60*), that general strikes were not sufficient to bring about a revolution. The anarchists therefore âput forward an idea: the take-over of factories,â which would constitute âan exercise preparing one for the ultimate general act of expropriationâ (Malatesta, 1920: 134). The Italian factory occupation movement peaked in September 1920, with armed workers running their own factories using a factory committee form of organization, but ended that same month when reformist trade union and socialist leaders negotiated an agreement with the government that returned control of the factories to their capitalist owners.
In Germany, anarchists fought to establish a system of workersâ councils, most notably in Bavaria, where Gustav Landauer and Erich Muhsam were directly involved in the short lived Council Republic of 1919. However, the Bavarian Revolution was crushed by troops sent in by the more conservative Social Democrats, whom Landauer had been denouncing as the scourge of the socialist movement for years (*Volume One, Selections 79 & 111*). Landauer was brutally murdered, and Muhsam was imprisoned for several years (Kuhn, 2011: 8â10).
Both the soviet and factory committee models of revolutionary organization were very influential in anarchist circles. At the founding congress of the reconstituted anarcho-syndicalist International Workersâ Association in early 1922, the delegates declared themselves in favour of âa system of free councils without subordination to any authority or political partyâ (*Volume One, Selection 114*). Nevertheless, some anarchists voiced concerns regarding the limitations of soviet and factory council modes of organization.
Maksimov pointed to the danger of the soviets being transformed into representative bodies instead of direct organs of libertarian self-management (*Volume One, Selection 83*). More recently, Murray Bookchin has argued that âcouncil modes of organization are not immune to centralization, manipulation and perversion. These councils are still particularistic, one-sided and mediated forms of social management,â being limited to the workersâ self-management of production, âthe preconditions of life, not the conditions of lifeâ (*Volume Two, Selection 62*). Following the May-June 1968 events in France, Maurice Joyeux pointed out that factory committees need to coordinate their actions during the revolutionary process in order to spread and succeed, and then, after the revolution, to coordinate production and distribution, leading him to suggest that broader trade union federations would be better able to undertake this coordinating role (*Volume Two, Selection 61*).
The Russian Revolution raised another issue of fundamental importance to revolutionary anarchists: how to deal with counter-revolution, whether from the left or the right. From 1918 to 1921, Russia was racked by civil war. Many anarchists took the position that in order to protect the gains of the 1917 Revolution, they had no choice but to work with the Bolsheviks (the âRedsâ) in preventing Czarist counter-revolutionaries (the âWhitesâ) from forcing a return to the old order, with all the reprisals and massacres of the revolutionaries that that would entail. According to Paul Avrich, during the civil war âa large majority [of anarchists] gave varying degrees of support to the beleaguered regime,â leading Lenin in 1919 to compliment some anarchists for âbecoming the most dedicated supporters of Soviet powerâ (1978: 196â197).
Other anarchists argued that there were alternatives to simply supporting the Bolsheviks in their struggle against the White counter-revolutionaries, thereby strengthening the Bolshevik dictatorship. Instead, they argued for ârelentless partisan war, here, there and everywhere,â as Voline put it in February 1918 (Avrich, 1973: 107). But it was only in Ukraine that anarchists were able to instigate a popular insurgency, with the anarchist Nestor Makhno leading a peasant and worker guerrilla army (the âMakhnovshchinaâ) against a variety of forces, from occupying German and Austrian troops, to local strongmen (the âHetmanâ), to the Whites, and when necessary, to the Bolsheviks themselves (*Volume One, Selections 85 & 86*).
When the Makhnovists liberated an area, they would abolish all decrees issued by the Whites and the Reds, leaving it to âthe peasants in assemblies, [and] the workers in their factories and workshopsâ to decide for themselves how to organize their affairs. The land was to be returned to âthose peasants who support themselves through their own labour,â and the âfactories, workshops, mines and other tools and means of productionâ to the workers themselves (*Volume One, Selection 85*).
The Makhnovists denounced âthe bourgeois-landlord authority on the one hand and the Bolshevik-Communist dictatorship on the other.â They would throw out the Bolshevik secret police, the Cheka, from areas that had been under Bolshevik control and reopen the presses and meeting places that the Bolsheviks had shut down, proclaiming that âfreedom of speech, press, assembly, unions and the like are inalienable rights of every worker and any restriction on them is a counter-revolutionary act.â The Makhnovists called upon the soldiers of the Red Army, sometimes with some success, to desert and join the Makhnovists in their struggle for âa non-authoritarian labourersâ society without parasites and without commissar-bureaucratsâ *(Volume One, Selection 85*).
Despite their opposition to âstate militia, policemen and armies,â which they would declare abolished in the areas they had liberated (*Volume One, Selection 85*), the Makhnovist insurgents adopted some aspects of more conventional military organization, including a chain of command and conscription, and sometimes carried out âsummary executionsâ (Avrich, 1988: 114 & 121).
Many anarchists who were still free to do so, such as Voline, Aaron Baron and Peter Arshinov, went to Ukraine to support the Makhnovists, setting up the Nabat confederation, one of the more effective anarchist organizations during the Revolution and Civil War. But as Peter Arshinov noted, âthree years of uninterrupted civil wars made the southern Ukraine a permanent battlefield,â making it difficult for the anarchists and Makhnovists to accomplish anything positive (*Volume One, Selection 86*). Yet for five months in early 1919, âthe Gulyai-Polye regionâ where Makhno was based âwas virtually free of all political authority,â giving the anarchists a chance, albeit a very brief one, to put their constructive ideas into practice by helping the peasants and workers to set up libertarian communes and soviets (Avrich, 1988: 114).
A âseries of Regional Congresses of Peasants, Workers and Insurgentsâ was held, the third in April 1919, âin defiance of a ban placed upon itâ by the Bolsheviks (Avrich, 1988: 114â115). After âtwo Cheka agents [who] were sent to assassinate Makhno were caught and executedâ in May 1919, and the Makhnovists called upon the Red Army soldiers to join them, Trotsky outlawed the Makhnovists, sending in troops to dismantle their peasant communes (Avrich, 1988: 115). Despite subsequent temporary alliances to fight the Whites, by early 1921, the Bolsheviks had crushed the Makhnovist movement.
Unlike the Bolsheviks, the Makhnovists were able to garner significant support among the Ukrainian peasantry, who resented Bolshevik seizures of their grain and food, seeing that âthe bread taken by force from [them] nourishes mainly the enormous governmental machineâ being created by the Bolsheviks. For the revolution to succeed, the anarchists believed that the masses âmust feel truly free; they must know that the work they do is their own; they must see in every social measure which is adopted the manifestation of their will, their hopes and their aspirationsâ (*Volume One, Selection 86*).
The defeat of the Makhnovists in Ukraine and the anarchist movement in Russia led Arshinov and Makhno to argue that anarchists needed to rethink their approach. In 1926, now in exile, they published the Organizational Platform of the Libertarian Communists, calling for the creation of a General Union of anarchists based on theoretical and tactical unity, collective responsibility and federalism (*Volume One, Selection 115*). Although, for the most part, the Platform merely restated the Makhnovist conception of anarchism, it generated considerable controversy in anarchist circles. The Platform argued in favour of military organization based on âunity in the plan of operations and unity of common command,â ârevolutionary self-discipline,â and âtotal submission of the revolutionary army to the masses of worker and peasant organizations common throughout the country.â Despite its insistence on revolutionary self-discipline and contrary to the practice of the Makhnovists during the Civil War, the Platform rejected any form of conscription, stating that âall coercion will be completely excluded from the work of defending the revolution,â marking a return to rather than a departure from anarchist principles (*Volume One, Selection 115*).
It was the Platformâs emphasis on the need for theoretical and tactical unity, and the notion of âcollective responsibility,â that caused the greatest debate. The Platform argued that âthe tactical methods employed by separate members and groups within the Union should⊠be in rigorous concord both with each other and with the general theory and tactic[s] of the Union.â Collective responsibility ârequires each member to undertake fixed organizational duties, and demands execution of communal decisions.â The Platform took the position that revolutionary activity in collective areas of life âcannot be based on the personal responsibility of individual militants,â describing such an approach as âirresponsible individualismâ (*Volume One, Selection 115*).
The General Union of anarchists was to strive âto realize a network of revolutionary peasant [and worker] economic organizationsâ and unions, âfounded on anti-authoritarian principles,â with the General Union serving as âthe organized vanguard of their emancipating processâ (*Volume One, Selection 115*). Voline and several other exiled Russian anarchists argued against any anarchist organization assuming a vanguard role. For them, the social revolution âmust be the free creation of the masses, not controlled by ideological or political groups,â for the âslightest suggestion of direction, of superiority, of leadership of the masses⊠inevitably implies that the masses must⊠submit to it.â A General Union of âanarchistsâ that âorients the mass organizations (workers and peasants) in their political direction and is supported as needed by a centralized army is nothing more than a new political powerâ (*Volume One, Selection 115*).
Voline and his associates found the Platformâs conception of social and economic organization âmechanicalâ and simplistic, with its scheme for the coordination of production and consumption by workersâ and peasantsâ soviets, committees and unions run by elected delegates subject to recall. They saw in such organizations a danger of âimmobility, bureaucracy [and] a tendency to authoritarianism that will not be changed automatically by the principle of voting.â They thought a âbetter guaranteeâ of freedom lies âin the creation of a series of other, more mobile, even provisional organs which arise and multiply according to the needs that arise in the course of daily living and activities,â offering âa richer, more faithful reflection of the complexity of social lifeâ (*Volume One, Selection 115*).
While the Voline group acknowledged that ideological differences among anarchists, and the resulting disunity, were partly responsible for the failure of the Russian anarchist movement, they argued that there were other factors at play, including the âexisting prejudices, customs [and] educationâ of the masses, the fact that they âlook for accommodation rather than radical change,â and the repressive forces lined up against them (*Volume One, Selection 115*). For Voline, what was needed was not a more centralized and disciplined party type organization, but a âsynthesisâ of all the âjust and valid elementsâ of the various anarchist currents, including syndicalism, communism and individualism (*Volume One, Selection 116*). Foreshadowing subsequent ecological conceptions of anarchism (*Volume Two, Selection 48*; *Volume Three, Chapter 6*), Voline argued that anarchism should reflect the âcreative diversityâ of life itself, achieving unity through âdiversity and movementâ (*Volume One, Selection 116*).
Malatesta responded to the Platform by emphasizing that âin order to achieve their ends, anarchist organizations must, in their constitution and operation, remain in harmony with the principles of anarchism.â He argued that the proposed General Union of anarchists should be seen for what it really was, âthe Union of a particular fraction of anarchists.â He regarded as authoritarian the proposal for a âUnion Executive Committeeâ to âoversee the âideological and organizational conductââ of the Unionâs constitutive organizations and members, arguing that such an approach would turn the Union into âa nursery for heresies and schismsâ (*Volume One, Selection 115*).
For Malatesta, what the Platformists were proposing was a form of representative government based on majority vote, which âin practice always leads to domination by a small minority.â While anarchist organizations and congresses âserve to maintain and increase personal relationships among the most active comrades, to coordinate and encourage programmatic studies on the ways and means of taking action, to acquaint all on the situation in the various regions and the action most urgently needed in each; to formulate the various opinions current among the anarchists⊠their decisions are not obligatory rules but suggestions, recommendations, proposals to be submitted to all involved, and do not become binding and enforceable except on those who accept them, and for as long as they accept themâ (*Volume One, Selection 115*).
Since the publication of the Platform in 1926, anarchists have continued to debate which forms of organization are compatible with an anarchist vision of a free society. Some have championed various forms of direct democracy, whether in factory committees (*Volume Two, Selection 59*) or community assemblies (*Volume Two, Selection 62*). Others have followed Kropotkin, Voline and Malatesta in arguing in favour of more fluid, ad hoc organizations forming complex horizontal networks of voluntary associations (*Volume Two, Selection 63*; *Volume Three, Selection 1*).
Malatesta suggested that the Russian Platformists were âobsessed with the success of the Bolsheviks,â hence their desire âto gather the anarchists together in a sort of disciplined army which, under the ideological and practical direction of a few leaders, would march solidly to the attack of the existing regimes, and after having won a material victory would direct the constitution of a new societyâ (*Volume One, Selection 115*). But for those so inclined, there were other organizations for them to join, namely the various Communist Parties that were soon organized in Europe, Asia and the Americas under Russian tutelage.
Despite the creation of an anarcho-syndicalist International in early 1922 (*Volume One, Selection 114*), many anarchists and syndicalists, and the trade unions in which they were influential, affiliated instead with the Comintern (Communist International) and its related organizations. In addition, many anarchist and syndicalist groups and organizations were forcibly suppressed, by the Bolsheviks in Russia, the Fascists in Italy, the new ârevolutionaryâ government in Mexico, military dictatorships in Portugal, Spain and Latin America, and the âdemocraticâ government of the United States, which deported scores of radicals in 1919 (including Emma Goldman and Alexander Berkman), imprisoned Mexican anarchists like Ricardo Flores MagĂłn, and enacted âcriminal syndicalismâ laws to prohibit revolutionary syndicalist speech and action.
When Alexander Berkman and Emma Goldman arrived in Russia in 1919, they were sympathetic to the Bolsheviks, whom they regarded as sincere revolutionaries. They began to take a more critical stance after making contact with those anarchists who still remained at liberty. Eventually they realized that the Bolsheviks were establishing their own dictatorship under the guise of fighting counter-revolution. Berkman noted how the âcivil war really helped the Bolsheviki. It served to keep alive popular enthusiasm and nurtured the hope that, with the end of war, the ruling Party will make effective the new revolutionary principles and secure the people in the enjoyment of the fruits of the Revolution.â Instead, the end of the Civil War led to the consolidation of a despotic Party dictatorship characterized by the âexploitation of labour, the enslavement of the worker and peasant, the cancellation of the citizen as a human being⊠and his transformation into a microscopic part of the universal economic mechanism owned by the government; the creation of privileged groups favoured by the State; [and] the system of compulsory labour service and its punitive organsâ (*Volume One, Selection 88*).
âTo forget ethical values,â wrote Berkman, âto introduce practices and methods inconsistent with or opposed to the high moral purposes of the revolution means to invite counter-revolution and disaster⊠Where the masses are conscious that the revolution and all its activities are in their own hands, that they themselves are managing things and are free to change their methods when they consider it necessary, counter-revolution can find no support and is harmless⊠the cure for evil and disorder is more liberty, not suppressionâ (*Volume One, Selection 117*).
Emma Goldman drew similar lessons from the Russian Revolution, arguing that âto divest oneâs methods of ethical concepts means to sink into the depths of utter demoralization⊠No revolution can ever succeed as a factor of liberation unless the MEANS used to further it be identical in spirit and tendency with the PURPOSES to be achieved.â For Goldman, the essence of revolution cannot be âa violent change of social conditions through which one social class, the working class, becomes dominant over another class,â as in the Marxist conception. For the social revolution to succeed, there must be âa fundamental transvaluation of values⊠ushering in a transformation of the basic relations of man to man, and of man to society,â establishing âthe sanctity of human life, the dignity of man, the right of every human being to liberty and well-beingâ (*Volume One, Selection 89*).
In conceiving the social revolution as âthe mental and spiritual regeneratorâ of human values and relationships, Goldman was adopting a position close to that of Gustav Landauer, the anarchist socialist martyred during the short-lived Bavarian Revolution in 1919. Before the war, he criticized those revolutionaries who regard the state as a physical âthingâakin to a fetishâthat one can smash in order to destroy.â Rather, the âstate is a relationship between human beings, a way by which people relate to one another⊠one destroys it by entering into other relationships, by behaving differently to one another.â If the state is a kind of social relationship, then âwe are the stateâ and remain so âas long as we are not otherwise, as long as we have not created the institutions that constitute a genuine community and society of human beingsâ (*Volume One, Selection 49*).
This positive conception of social revolution as the creation of egalitarian communities was later expanded upon by Landauerâs friend, the Jewish philosopher, Martin Buber (1878â1965). Consciously seeking to build upon Landauerâs legacy, Buber called for the creation of âa community of communities,â a federation of village communes âwhere communal living is based on the amalgamation of production and consumption, production being understood⊠as the organic union of agriculture with industry and the handicrafts as wellâ (*Volume Two, Selection 16*). Such a vision drew upon both Landauer and Kropotkin, particularly the latterâs **Fields, Factories and Workshops** (*Volume One, Selection 34*). This vision was shared by some of the early pioneers of the kibbutz movement in Palestine (Horrox, 2009), and by Gandhi and his followers in India (*Volume Two, Selection 32*). It received renewed impetus after the Second World War, with the development of communitarian and ecological conceptions of anarchism by people like Paul Goodman (*Volume Two, Selections 17 & 70*) and Murray Bookchin (*Volume Two, Selections 48 & 74*).
Those anarchists who were not seduced by the seeming âsuccessâ of the Bolsheviks in Russia were faced with an equally formidable opponent in the various fascist movements that arose in the aftermath of the First World War. As with the Communists, the Fascists championed centralized command and technology, and did not hesitate to use the most brutal methods to suppress and annihilate their opponents. One of the first and most perceptive critics of fascism was the Italian anarchist, Luigi Fabbri (1877â1935), who aptly described it as âthe preventive counter-revolution.â For him, fascism constituted âa sort of militia and rallying pointâ for the âconservative forces in society,â âthe organization and agent of the violent armed defence of the ruling class against the proletariat.â Fascism arose from the militarization of European societies during the First World War, which the ruling classes had hoped would decapitate âa working class that had become overly strong, [by] defusing popular resistance through blood-letting on a vast scaleâ (*Volume One, Selection 113*).
Fascism put the lie to the notion of a âdemocraticâ state, with the Italian judiciary, police and military turning a blind eye to fascist violence while prosecuting and imprisoning those who sought to defend themselves against it. Consequently, Fabbri regarded a narrow âanti-fascistâ approach as being completely inadequate. Seeing the fascists as the only enemy âwould be like stripping the branches from a poisonous tree while leaving the trunk intact⊠The fight against fascism can only be waged effectively if it is struck through the political and economic institutions of which it is an outgrowth and from which it draws sustenance,â namely âcapitalism and the state.â While âcapitalism uses fascism to blackmail the state, the state itself uses fascism to blackmail the proletariat,â dangling fascism âover the heads of the working classesâ like âsome sword of Damocles,â leaving the working class âforever fearful of its rights being violated by some unforeseen and arbitrary violenceâ (*Volume One, Selection 113*).
The anarchist pacifist Bart de Ligt regarded fascism as âa politico-economic state where the ruling class of each country behaves towards its own people as for several centuries it has behaved to the colonial peoples under its heel,â an inverted imperialism âturned against its own people.â Yet fascism was not based on violence alone and enjoyed popular support. As de Ligt noted, fascism âtakes advantage of the peopleâs increasing misery to seduce them by a new Messianism: belief in the Strong Man, the Duce, the FĂŒhrerâ (*Volume One, Selection 120*).
The veteran anarcho-syndicalist, Rudolf Rocker (1873â1958), argued that fascism was the combined result of the capitalistsâ urge to dominate workers, nations and the natural world, the anonymity and powerlessness of âmass man,â the development of modern mass technology and production techniques, mass propaganda and the substitution of bureaucratic state control over every aspect of social life for personal responsibility and communal self-regulation, resulting in the dissolution of âsociety into its separate partsâ and their incorporation âas lifeless accessories into the gears of the political machine.â The reduction of the individual to a mere cog in the machine, together with the constant âtutelage of our acting and thinking,â make us âweak and irresponsible,â Rocker wrote, âhence, the continued cry for the strong man who is to put an end to our distressâ (*Volume One, Selection 121*). Drawing on Freud, Herbert Read argued that it is the âobsessive fear of the father which is the psychological basis of tyrannyâ and âat the same time the weakness of which the tyrant takes advantageâ (*Volume One, Selection 130*).
Rocker noted how in Germany fascism had assumed a brutally racist character, with German capitalists citing Nazi doctrines of racial superiority to justify their own domination and to dismiss human equality, and therefore socialism, as biological impossibilities. Writing in 1937, Rocker foresaw the genocidal atrocities which were to follow, citing this comment by the Nazi ideologue, Ernst Mann: âSuicide is the one heroic deed available to invalids and weaklingsâ (*Volume One, Selection 121*).
The Italian anarchist, Camillo Berneri (1897â1937), described fascism as âthe triumph of the irrational.â He documented and dissected the noxious racial doctrines of the Nazis, which, on the one hand, portrayed the âAryanâ and âNordicâ German people as a superior race, but then, in order to justify rule by an elite, had to argue that the âruling strataâ were of purer blood (Berneri, 1935). As Rocker observed, âevery class that has thus far attained to power has felt the need of stamping their rulership with the mark of the unalterable and predestined.â The idea that the ruling class is a âspecial breed,â Rocker pointed out, originated among the Spanish nobility, whose âblue bloodâ was supposed to distinguish them from those they ruled (*Volume One, Selection 121*). It was in Spain that the conflict between the âblue bloods,â capitalists and fascists, on the one hand, and the anarchists, socialists and republicans, on the other, was to reach a bloody crescendo when revolution and civil war broke out there in July 1936.
Anarchists who sought to understand the popular appeal of fascism turned to the work of the dissident Marxist psychoanalyst, Wilhelm Reich (1897â1957). Reich was unpopular in Marxist circles, having described Soviet Communism as âred fascism,â which resulted in his expulsion from the Communist Party. In his book, **The Mass Psychology of Fascism**, Reich discussed the role of the patriarchal nuclear family, legal marriage, enforced monogamy, religion and sexual repression in creating an authoritarian character structure (Volume One, Selection 119).
Reichâs work was similar to the earlier psychoanalytic anarchist critique of Otto Gross (1877â1920), who argued on the eve of the First World War, echoing Max Stirner, that previous revolutions âcollapsed because the revolutionary of yesterday carried authority within himself.â Gross believed that â**the root of all authority lies in the family**,â and that âthe combination of sexuality and authority, as it shows itself in the patriarchal family still prevailing today, claps every individuality in chainsâ (Volume One, Selection 78). Although he put greater emphasis than Reich on the âinner conflictâ between âthat which belongs to oneselfâ and the â**authority that has penetrated into our own innermost self,**â Gross also called for the sexual liberation of women and for a struggle âagainst the father and patriarchyâ (Volume One, Selection 78).
The Japanese anarchist feminist, Takamure Itsue (1894â1964), argued that the ruling class viewed sexual fulfillment âas a mere extravagance for everyone except themselvesâ and âbabies as eggs for their industrial machines⊠to be chained up within the confinement of the marriage system,â with the burdens of pregnancy, child birth and child rearing being imposed on women. She acknowledged the changes in sexual relations arising from the development of birth control, which potentially gave women more control over their lives, but as with Carmen Lareva and He Zhen before her, warned against mere âpromiscuity.â For her, âgenuine anarchist loveâ was based on mutual respect, such that those who seek it can ânever be satisfied with recreational sexâ (Volume One, Selection 109). The liberalization of marriage laws and the legalization of birth control were not enough, for men would continue to view women as sex objects and deny responsibility for child care.
In Spain, FĂ©lix MartĂ Ibåñez argued that sexual revolution, because it involves the transformation of individual attitudes and relationships, can neither be imposed from above nor completely suppressed by the ruling authorities. The sexual revolution must begin now, âby means of the book, the word, the conference and personal example.â Only then will people be able to âcreate and forge that sexual culture which is the key to liberationâ (Volume One, Selection 121). That this would be no easy task was highlighted by LucĂa SĂĄnchez Saornil, one of the founders of the Mujeres Libres anarchist womenâs group in Spain. She criticized those anarchist men who used notions of sexual liberation as a pretext for looking âupon every woman who passes their way as a target for their appetitesâ (Volume One, Selection 123). Such conduct either results in the reduction of women to âa plaything of masculine whims,â or alienates them from participation in the anarchist movement.
Some anarchists felt that Reichâs analysis overemphasized the role of sexual repression in the rise of fascism. A Spanish article suggested that a âcompletely healthy and well-balanced individual in terms of his sexual life may be a long way off from being a perfect socialist and a convinced revolutionary fighter,â for âan individual free of bourgeois sexual prejudice may lack all sense of human solidarityâ (Volume One, Selection 119).
Others were more enthusiastic. Marie Louise Berneri (1918â1949) endorsed Reichâs argument that the âfear of pleasurable excitationâ caused by conventional morality and the legally mandated patriarchal family âis the soil on which the individual re-creates the life-negating ideologies which are the basis of dictatorship.â She also drew on the work of the anthropologist, Bronislaw Malinowski, whose studies indicated that in those societies where peopleâs sex lives are âallowed to develop naturally, freely and unhampered **through every stage of life, with full satisfaction**â there are âno sexual perversions, no functional psychoses, no psychoneuroses, no sex murder,â in marked contrast to societies based on the âpatriarchal authoritarian family organization.â Berneri accepted Reichâs claim that when his patients âwere restored to a healthy sex-life, their whole character altered, their submissiveness disappeared, they revolted against an absurd moral code, against the teachings of the Church, against the monotony and uselessness of their workâ (Volume Two, Selection 75). In other words, they became social revolutionaries.
Paul Goodman drew the connection between the repression of homosexual impulses among adolescent males and the war machine. These âboysâ are made to feel âashamed of their acts; their pleasures are suppressed and in their stead appear fistfights and violence.â In the army, âthis violent homosexuality, so near the surface but always repressed and thereby gathering tension, turns into a violent sadism against the enemy: it is all knives and guns and bayonets, and raining bombs on towns, and driving oneâs lust in the guise of anger to fuck the Japsâ (Volume Two, Selection 11).
The libertarian communist, Daniel GuĂ©rin (1904â1988), wrote that âpatriarchal society, resting on the dual authority of the man over the woman and of the father over the children, accords primacy to the attributes and modes of behaviour associated with virility. Homosexuality is persecuted to the extent that it undermines this construction. The disdain of which woman is the object in patriarchal societies is not without correlation with the shame attached to the homosexual act.â While GuĂ©rin urged people âto pursue simultaneously both the social revolution and the sexual revolution, until human beings are liberated completely from the two crushing burdens of capitalism and puritanism,â he agreed with Emma Goldman, MartĂ Ibåñez, and Paul Goodman that the process of sexual liberation must begin now, not after the revolution. Yet, as with Goodman, he also recognized that the gay liberation movement of the 1960s and 70s âcreated a whole generation of âgayâ young men, profoundly apolitical⊠a million miles from any conception of class struggle,â casting doubt on the Reichian view that sexual liberation leads to social revolution (Volume Two, Selection 76).
Alex Comfort (1920â2000), who was also a pioneer of sexual liberation, suggested that part of the appeal of fascism lay in peopleâs consciousness of their own mortality and fear of death. Since âto admit that I am an individual I must also admit that I shall cease to exist,â people take refuge in the belief in âan immortal, invisible and only wise society, which can exact responsibilities and demand allegiances⊠Each sincere citizen feels responsibility to society in the abstract, and none to the people he kills⊠Fascism is a refuge from Death in death.â (Volume Two, Selection 20).
In Asia during the 1920s and 30s, the anarchists faced obstacles similar to those of their European comrades. The success of the Bolsheviks in Russia led to the creation of Marxist-Leninist Communist parties in various parts of Asia. The anarchists had until then been the most influential revolutionary movement in China. By the late 1920s, the anarchists had been eclipsed by the Chinese Communist Party and the Guomindang, who fought each other, and the Japanese, for control of China over the next twenty years.
Chinese anarchists rejected the Marxist notion of the dictatorship of the proletariat, concentrating all power âin the hands of the state,â because this would result in the âsuppression of individual freedomâ (*Volume One, Selection 100*). The Chinese anarchists did not regard Marxist state socialism as sufficiently communist, for during the alleged âtransitionâ from socialism to communism, a wage system and some forms of private property would be retained.
Huang Lingshuang (1898â1982), one of the more noteworthy Chinese anarchist critics of Marxism, rejected the Marxist view that society must progress through successive stages of economic and technological development before communism can be achieved. Drawing on the work of European anthropologists, Huang Lingshuang was able to more clearly distinguish between cultural change and biological evolution than Kropotkin, who had largely conflated the two. Huang Lingshuang argued that, contrary to the Marxist theory of historical materialism, the âsame economic and technological conditions do not necessarily result in the same culture,â cultural and economic changes do ânot occur at the same rate,â and not every society goes through the same economic stages of development in the same order (*Volume One, Selection 100*). Rudolf Rocker made similar arguments in **Nationalism and Culture** (*Volume One, Selection 121*).
In contrast to the decline of the Chinese anarchist movement in the 1920s, according to John Crump, âthe anarchists in Japan were organisationally stronger than ever before, and there was a corresponding flowering of ideas and theories, particularly among the anarchist communistsâ (Crump, 1996). The anarchist communists identified themselves as âpure anarchists.â They criticized the anarcho-syndicalist concept of workersâ control of the existing means of production. As Hatta ShĂ»zĂŽ (1886â1934) put it, âin a society which is based on the division of labour, those engaged in vital production⊠would have more power over the machinery of coordination than those engaged in other lines of production.â
The Japanese âpure anarchistsâ therefore proposed a decentralized system of communal production âperformed autonomously on a human scale,â where âproduction springs from consumption,â being designed to meet local and individual wants and needs, in contrast to existing systems of production, where consumption is driven by the demands of production. Under such a system of decentralized human scale production, people âcan coordinate the work process themselves,â such that there is no need for a âsuperior body and there is no place for powerâ (*Volume One, Selection 106*).
Japanese anarcho-syndicalist advocates of class struggle agreed that the existing authoritarian system of production should be replaced by âcommunal property⊠where there is neither exploiter nor exploited, neither master nor slave,â with society being ârevived with spontaneity and mutual free agreement as an integral wholeâ (*Volume One, Selection 107*). However, in order to create such a society a profound revolutionary transformation was required. The anarcho-syndicalists argued that it was only by participating in the workersâ daily struggles against the capitalist system that anarchists would be able to inspire a revolutionary movement capable of creating the anarchist community to which the âpure anarchistsâ aspired.
Contrary to the claims of the âclass struggleâ anarcho-syndicalists though, the âpure anarchistsâ did not hold themselves aloof from the workersâ struggles but convinced the anarchist Zenkoku Jiren labour federation to adopt a âpure anarchistâ position which emphasized that their goal was not to take over the existing means of production, replacing the capitalists and the government with a trade union administration, but to create a decentralized system of communal production based on human-scale technology, a position similar to that developed by Murray Bookchin in the 1960s (*Volume Two, Selections 48, 62 & 74*).
The Zenkoku Jiren reached out to Japanese tenant farmers, seeing them âas the crucial social force which could bring about the commune-based, alternative society to capitalismâ advocated by the âpure anarchistsâ (Crump, 1996). The appeal of this vision to radical Japanese workers and farmers is illustrated by the fact that by 1931, the Zenkoku Jiren had about 16,000 members, whereas the more conventional anarcho-syndicalist federation, the JikyĂŽ, had only 3,000.
In the early 1930s, as the Japanese state began a concerted push for imperialist expansion by invading Manchuria, the state authorities renewed their campaign against the Japanese anarchist movement, which was staunchly anti-imperialist. In the face of the Japanese occupation of Manchuria, the Japanese Libertarian Federation had called on all people to âcease military production, refuse military service and disobey the officersâ (*Volume One, Selection 110*). Anarchist organizations were banned and hundreds of anarchists arrested. By 1936, the organized anarchist movement in Japan had been crushed.
Japan annexed Korea in 1910, around the same time that Japanese authorities had made their first attempt to destroy the nascent Japanese anarchist movement by executing several leading anarchists, including KÎtoku Shûsui (*Volume One, Selection 102*). The Japanese occupation of Korea gave rise to a national liberation movement to free the Korean people from Japanese exploitation and domination. Some of the more radical elements in the liberation movement gravitated toward anarchism.
In 1923, a prominent member of the movement, Shin Chaeho (1880â1936), published his âDeclaration of the Korean Revolutionâ in which he argued that when driving out their Japanese exploiters, the Korean people must be careful not to âreplace one privileged group with another.â The goal of the Korean revolution should be the creation of a world in which âone human being will not be able to oppress other human beings and one society will not be able to exploit other societies.â The revolution must therefore be a ârevolution of the masses.â To succeed in constructing a free society, the revolution must destroy foreign rule, the âprivileged classâ that benefits from it, the âsystem of economic exploitation,â âsocial inequalityâ and âservile cultural thoughtsâ created by conformist forms of âreligion, ethics, literature, fine arts, customs and public moralsâ (*Volume One, Selection 105*).
In emphasizing the constructive role of destruction, Shin Chaeho was expressing a viewpoint shared by many anarchists that can be traced back to Proudhon and Bakunin (*Volume One, Selection 10*). He also recognized that to win the masses over to the cause of the revolution, they must be convinced that the revolution will result in material improvements and greater freedom for themselves, not simply the expulsion of their foreign rulers. As Kropotkin put it, for âthe revolution to be anything more than a word⊠the conquest of the day itself must be worth the trouble of defending; the poor of yesterday must not find themselves even poorer todayâ (*Volume One, Selection 45*).
This was one of the reasons why Kropotkin had entitled his most sustained argument in favour of anarchist communism **The Conquest of Bread** (*Volume One, Selection 33*). When Korean anarchists began publishing their own paper in 1928, they called it **Talhwan**, or **Conquest**, and championed anarchist communism, calling for the abolition of capitalism and government (*Volume One, Selection 108*). They also rejected the Marxist âstate capitalismâ that was being created in the Soviet Union through the âdespotic and dictatorialâ policies of the Soviet Communist Party (the Bolsheviks).
Korean anarchists, including Shin Chaeho, were instrumental in forming the Eastern Anarchist Federation in 1927, which had members from Korea, China, Vietnam, Taiwan and Japan. Most of their work and publications had to be carried out from exile, and even then at great risk to themselves. Shin Chaeho was arrested by Japanese authorities in Taiwan in 1928 and died in prison in 1936. However, after the defeat of Japan in the Second World War, it was only in Korea that a significant anarchist movement reemerged in southeast Asia.
In China, the Marxist Communists under the leadership of Mao Zedong had seized control by 1949. They no more tolerated an independent anarchist movement than had the Communists in the Soviet Union. In Japan, the U.S. occupiers engineered the purging of radicals, whether Marxist or anarchist, from positions of influence within the trade union movement, and the reform of rural landholdings, creating âa new class of landowning small farmersâ who âthen became a bastion of political conservatismâ hostile rather than sympathetic toward anarchism (Crump, 1996).
During the war, some Korean anarchists participated in the Korean Provisional Government in exile. Their desire for Korean independence superseded their commitment to anarchist ideals. Before the war, the Korean Anarchist Federation had rejected the establishment of a ânational united frontâ (*Volume One, Selection 108*). After the war, Yu Lim, who had served as a cabinet minister in the Provisional Government, urged the anarchists to support an independent Korean government to prevent Korea from falling âinto the hands of either the Stalinists to the north or the imperialistic compradore-capitalists to the southâ (*Volume Two, Selection 9*).
Other Korean anarchists, while seeking âto cooperate with all genuinely revolutionary nationalist groups of the left,â continued to call for âtotal liberationâ through the âfree federation of autonomous units covering the whole countryâ (*Volume Two, Selection 9*). At the conclusion of the war in 1945, grass roots committees for the reconstruction of Korea sprang up across the country, and peasants and workers began forming independent unions. However, this process of social reconstruction âfrom the bottom upwardâ came to a halt after the Soviet Union and the United States imposed their own ânationalâ governments in the north and south in 1948, leading to the divisive and inconclusive Korean War (1950â1953).
The Spanish anarchist movement which Bakunin had helped inspire experienced its greatest triumphs and most tragic defeats during the Spanish Revolution and Civil War (1936â1939). The two most prominent anarchist groups in Spain were the Iberian Anarchist Federation (the FAI) and the anarcho-syndicalist trade union confederation, the ConfederaciĂłn Nacional del Trabajo (the CNT). The FAI was a federation of anarchist revolutionaries which sought to foment social revolution and to keep the CNT on an anarchist path. This âdual organizationâ model had been followed in Spain since the days of the First International, when Bakunin recruited Spanish radicals into his Alliance of Social Revolutionaries. Members of the Alliance were to ensure that the Spanish sections of the International adopted Bakuninâs collectivist anarchist program.
By the 1930s, the Spanish anarchist movement had moved toward an anarchist communist position, although the doctrine of âanarchism without adjectives,â which originated in the debates between the anarchist collectivists and anarchist communists in the 1890s, continued to be influential. Diego Abad de SantillĂĄn (1897â1983), who played a prominent role in the Argentine and Spanish anarchist movements, saw anarchism as representing a broad âhumanistic cravingâ which âseeks to defend manâs dignity and freedom, regardless of circumstances and under every political system, past, present and future.â Anarchism must therefore be without adjectives because it is not tied to any particular economic or political system, nor is anarchy only possible at a certain stage of history or development. Abad de SantillĂĄn argued that anarchism âcan survive and assert its right to exist alongside plough and team of oxen as readily as alongside the modern combine-harvester; its mission in the days of steam was the same as it is in the age of the electric motor or jet engine or the modern age of the computer and atomic powerâ (*Volume Two, Selection 53*).
Despite his endorsement of âanarchism without adjectives,â Abad de SantillĂĄn did not shy away from controversy. Although he participated in the anarcho-syndicalist movements in Argentina and Spain, he urged anarchists ânot to forget that the Syndicate is, as an economic by-product of capitalist organization, a social phenomenon spawned by the needs of its day. Clinging to its structures after the revolution would be tantamount to clinging to the cause that spawned it: capitalismâ (*Volume One, Selection 94*).
On the eve of the Spanish Revolution, when the CNT reaffirmed its commitment to libertarian communism (*Volume One, Selection 124*), Abad de SantillĂĄn argued not only that people should be free to choose between âcommunism, collectivism or mutualism,â but that âthe prerequisiteâ of such freedom is a certain level of material abundance that can only be achieved through an integrated economic network of productive units (*Volume One, Selection 125*).
The greatest controversy in which Abad de SantillĂĄn was involved arose from the decisions by the CNT during the Spanish Civil War to accept posts in the Catalonian governing council in September 1936 and, in November 1936, the central government in Madrid. In December 1936, Abad de SantillĂĄn became the Councillor of Economy in the regional government in Catalonia (the **Generalitat**). Not only did the âmilitantsâ of the FAI fail to prevent this fatal compromise of anarchist principles, some of the CNT ministers were themselves members of the FAI (such as Juan GarcĂa Oliver, who became the Minister of Justice in the Madrid government, and Abad de SantillĂĄn himself). The decision to join the government was engineered by the National Committee of the CNT (which became the de facto ruling council of the CNT during the course of the Civil War) in order to obtain arms and financing, neither of which were forthcoming.
The decision of the CNT leadership to join the Spanish government was sharply criticized by many well known anarchists, including Camillo Berneri, SĂ©bastien Faure, and Alexander Schapiro. Writing for the IWA publication, **The International**, the Swedish anarcho-syndicalist Albert Jensen (1879â1957) pointed out that it was by way of revolution that the workers in Catalonia had prevented General Franco from seizing power when he began the military revolt against the republican government in July 1936. Anarchists and syndicalists stormed military barracks, seized weapons and began collectivizing industry, while the republican government was in a state of virtual collapse. However, in order to maintain a âunited frontâ against fascism, and to avoid imposing their own **de facto** dictatorship, the CNT-FAI decided it was better to work within the republican government rather than against it.
The problem was that, as Jensen pointed out, during a civil war the government âmust have recourse always to dictatorship,â governing by decree and imposing military discipline, so instead of imposing an âanarchistâ dictatorship the CNT-FAI was propping up a âcounter-revolutionaryâ dictatorship, which hardly constituted âloyalty to [anarchist] ideasâ and principles. âWounded unto death, the State received new life thanks to the governmental participation of the CNT-FAI.â If the CNT-FAI had to work with other anti-fascists, whether capitalists or the authoritarian Communists loyal to Moscow, it would have been better for the CNT-FAI to remain outside the government, taking the position that âunder no pretext, would they tolerate any attack on the revolutionary accomplishments and that they would defend these with all the necessary meansâ (*Volume One, Selection 127*).
In the factories and in the countryside, in areas that did not immediately fall under fascist control, there was a far-reaching social revolution. Spanish peasants collectivized the land and workers took over their factories. In the factories, the workers in assembly would make policy decisions and elect delegates to coordinate production and distribution. In the countryside, village and town assemblies were held in which all members of the community were able to participate.
In âthe agrarian regions and especially in Aragon,â observed Gaston Leval (1895â1978), âa new organism appeared: the Collective.â The collective was not a trade union or syndical organization, âfor it encompasses all those who wish to join it whether they are producers in the classic economic sense or not.â Neither was it a commune or municipal council, as it âencompasses at the same time the Syndicate and municipal functions.â The âwhole population,â not merely the producers, âtakes part in [the] managementâ of the collective, dealing with all sorts of issues, âwhether it is a question of policy for agriculture, for the creation of new industries, for social solidarity, medical service or public educationâ (*Volume One, Selection 126*).
Although the anarchist collectives were ultimately destroyed, first by the Stalinist Communists in republican areas, and then by the fascists as they subjugated all of Spain, they constitute the greatest achievement of the Spanish anarchist movement. Through the crucible of the social revolution itself, the Spanish people developed this new, more inclusive form of libertarian organization which transcended the limits of anarcho-syndicalist trade union and factory committee forms of organization, inspiring generations to come.
Those anarchists who attempted to work within the republican government were consistently outmaneuvered by the Republicans, Socialists and Communists. The areas in which anarchists were free to implement their ideas continued to shrink, but it was the May Days in Barcelona in 1937 that effectively marked the end of the anarchist social revolution in Spain. Factories and services under anarchist inspired workersâ self-management were attacked by Republican and Communist forces while they did battle with the anarchist militias, and several prominent anarchists were murdered, including Camillo Berneri and the Libertarian Youth leader, Alfredo Martinez. The CNT leadership negotiated a truce with the Republican government rather than engage in a âcivil warâ within the civil war. Hundreds of anarchists were killed in the fighting, and many more were imprisoned. The Socialists and Communists, unsuccessful in having the CNT declared illegal, forced them out of the government and continued their campaign of âdecollectivizationâ and disarmament of the anarchist groups.
Given this disastrous turn of events, Abad de SantillĂĄn had second thoughts about the CNTâs policy of collaboration. By April 1937, he had already ceased being a member of the Catalonian cabinet. The following year he denounced those âanarchistsâ who had used their positions within the movement âas a springboard to defect to the other side where the pickings are easier and the thorns less sharp,â obtaining âhigh positions of political and economic privilege.â The CNT-FAIâs participation âin political power,â which he had also once âthought advisable due to circumstances, in light of the war,â had demonstrated âyet again what Kropotkin once said of the parliamentary socialists: âYou mean to conquer the State, but the State will end up conquering youââ (*Volume One, Selection 128*).
Abad de SantillĂĄn noted that the self-styled anarchist âavant-garde,â who fancied themselves the âbest trained, most prestigious, sharpest witted,â himself included, were not âin the vanguard of economic and social changeâ but instead âproved a hindrance, a brake, a hurdle to that change.â He had to admit that the âbroad massesâ of the Spanish people âwere better prepared than their supposed mentors and guides when it came to revolutionary reconstruction.â For Abad de SantillĂĄn, by âstanding with the State and thus against the people,â anarchists who were working within the Republican government were ânot only committing an irreparable act of betrayal of the revolution,â they were âalso betraying the war effort, because we are denying it the active support of the people,â who were becoming increasingly alienated from the Republican government as it sought to dismantle the anarchist collectives and other organs of self-management that had been created by the people themselves (*Volume One, Selection 128*).
Under the pressure of civil war, the CNT-FAI came more and more to resemble a conventional political party. The CNTâs National Committee would negotiate with the Republican government, and then present whatever deals they could get to the membership as a **fait accompli**. In effect, the âinverseâ pyramidal federalist structure of the CNT was turned upside down, as the CNT began to function as a top-down political organization. The anarchist militias were dissolved, broken up or absorbed into the Communist dominated Republican army and subjected to strict military discipline (Richards, 1972).
Looking back on the Revolution and Civil War, JosĂ© Peirats (1908â1989), active in the CNT and later its historian, believed that âthose of us who consistently opposed collaboration with the government had as our only alternative a principled, heroic defeat.â Nevertheless, he was sympathetic to those principled anarchists for whom âthe only solution was to leave an indelible mark on the present without compromising the future,â through their âconstructive revolutionary experiments like the collectives, artistic and cultural achievements, new models of free, communal living.â This entailed âstaying out of intrigues, avoiding complicity with the counterrevolution within the government, protecting the organization and its militants from the vainglory of rulers or the pride of the newly rich.â The seemingly insurmountable difficulties in maintaining these revolutionary achievements in the midst of civil war caused Peirats to question not these achievements, but âthe idea of revolutionâ itself, conceived as a mass armed uprising seeking to overthrow the existing regime which inevitably degenerates into civil war (Peirats: 188â189), a critique further developed by Luc Bonet (*Volume Three, Selection 12*). This process of rethinking revolution was to be continued by many anarchists after the Spanish Revolution and the Second World War.
One of the anarchists involved in rethinking anarchism around the time of the Spanish Revolution and Civil War was the English poet, art critic and essayist, Herbert Read (1893â1968). In **Poetry and Anarchism** (1938), Read acknowledged that âto declare for a doctrine so remote as anarchism at this stage of history will be regarded by some critics as a sign of intellectual bankruptcy; by others as a sort of treason, a desertion of the democratic front at the most acute moment of its crisis; by still others as mere poetic nonsense.â Read sought to âbalance anarchism with surrealism, reason with romanticism, the understanding with the imagination, function with freedomâ (*Volume One, Selection 130*). He developed an ecological conception of anarchism emphasizing spontaneity and differentiation. He saw society as âan organic beingâ in which communities âcan live naturally and freelyâ and individuals can âdevelop in consciousness of strength, vitality and joy,â with progress being âmeasured by the degree of differentiation within a societyâ (*Volume Two, Selection 1*). It was partly through Readâs writings that Murray Bookchin was later inspired to draw the connections between ecology and anarchism (*Volume Two, Selection 48*).
Read noted that even âif you abolish all other classes and distinctions and retain a bureaucracy you are still far from the classless society, for the bureaucracy is itself the nucleus of a class whose interests are totally opposed to the people it supposedly serves.â Taking advantage of the bureaucratic structure of the modern state, the professional politician rises to power, âhis motive throughout [being] personal ambition and megalomaniaâ (*Volume One, Selection 130*), a notion further developed by Alex Comfort in his post-war book, **Authority and Delinquency in the Modern State**, in which he argued that the bureaucratic state, through its power structures, provides a ready outlet for those with psychopathic tendencies (*Volume Two, Selection 26*).
Read sought to reverse the rise to power of professional politicians and bureaucrats by advocating a âreturn to a functional basis of representation,â by which he meant the development of decentralized but federated organs of self-management, as had long been advocated by anarchists from Proudhon and Bakunin to the anarcho-syndicalists. The professional politician would be replaced by the â**ad hoc** delegate,â who would continue to work within his or her area, such that there would be âno whole-time officials, no bureaucrats, no politicians, no dictatorsâ (*Volume One, Selection 130*).
Arguing that âreal politics are local politics,â Read proposed that local councils or âgovernmentsâ composed of delegates from the community and the functional groups that comprise it âcontrol all the immediate interests of the citizen,â with âremoter interestsâquestions of cooperation, intercommunication, and foreign affairsâ[being] settled by councils of delegates elected by the local councils and the [workersâ] syndicates.â Read admitted that this was a system of government, but distinguished this conception of local and functional organization from the âautonomous State,â which âis divorced from its immediate functions and becomes an entity claiming to control the lives and destinies of its subjects,â such that âliberty ceases to existâ (*Volume One, Selection 130*).
Bearing in mind the difficulties recently faced by the Spanish anarchists in the Spanish Revolution and Civil War, at the beginning of the Second World War Herbert Read warned against the revolutionary seizure of power, instead looking forward to âa spontaneous and universal insurrectionâ (*Volume Two, Selection 1*), but one which would employ nonviolent methods, for people âcannot struggle againstâ the modern state, armed with atomic bombs, â**on the plane of force**⊠Our action must be piecemeal, non-violent, insidious and universally pervasiveâ (*Volume Two, Selection 36*). Alex Comfort took a similar position, arguing that the âvery states which are able to make and use atomic weapons are singularly vulnerable, by their very complexity, to the attacks of individual disobedienceâ (*Volume Two, Selection 12*).
Paul Goodman described this process as âDrawing the Line, beyond which [we] cannot cooperate.â But although we âdraw the line in their conditions; we proceed on our conditions,â replacing âthe habit of coercion [with] a **habit** of freedom⊠Our action must be aimed, not at a future establishment; but⊠at fraternal arrangements today, progressively incorporating more and more of the social functions into our free society,â for the creation of a âfree society cannot be the substitution of a ânew orderâ for the old order; it is the extension of spheres of free action until they make up most of the social lifeâ (*Volume Two, Selection 11*).
Read, Comfort and Goodman all advocated various forms of non-violent direct action, including war resistance and opposition to conscription through such means as draft evasion. Such attitudes were dangerous and unpopular, particularly during the Second World War. Anarchists who practiced draft resistance were imprisoned in France, England and the United States. It was only in the early 1960s in France, and a few years later in the United States, that mass draft resistance movements emerged in opposition to the French war in Algeria and the U.S. war in Vietnam (*Volume Two, Selection 31*).
At the beginning of the Second World War, a group of anarchists in Geneva wrote that it is âan indispensable right, without which all other rights are mere illusionsâ, that âno one should be required to kill others or to expose themselves to being killed.â For them, the âworst form of disorder is not anarchy,â as critics of anarchism claim, âbut war, which is the highest expression of authorityâ (*Volume Two, Selection 3*). That expression of authority was to result in the loss of tens of millions of lives in Europe and Asia during the next six years, culminating in the U.S. atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki in August 1945. As Marie Louise Berneri remarked, anarchist acts of violence pale in comparison. A single bombing raid âkills more men, women and children than have been killed in the whole history, true or invented, of anarchist bombs.â When Italian anarchists tried to assassinate Mussolini, they were denounced as terrorists, but when âwhole citiesâ are rubbed âoff the mapâ as part of the war effort, reducing âwhole populations to starvation, with its resulting scourge of epidemics and disease all over the world,â the workers âare asked to rejoice in this wholesale destruction from which there is no escapingâ (*Volume Two, Selection 4*).
When anarchists resort to violence, they are held criminally responsible, and their beliefs denounced as the cause. When government forces engage in the wholesale destruction of war, no one (at least among the victors) is held responsible, belief in authority is not seen as the cause, and the very nation states which brought about the conflict are supposed to bring, as Marie Louise Berneri remarked, âpeace and order⊠with their bombsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 4*).
In response to the comments of a U.S. Army sergeant surveying a bombed out area in Germany that in âmodern war there are crimes not criminals⊠Murder has been mechanized and rendered impersonal,â Paul Goodman wrote that âit is ridiculous to say that the crime cannot be imputed or that any one commits it without intent or in ignorance⊠The steps [the individual] takes to habituation and unconsciousness are crimes which entail every subsequent evil of enslavement and mass-murderâ (*Volume Two, Selection 11*).
Alex Comfort noted that modern bureaucratic societies âhave removed at least one of the most important bars to delinquent action by legislators and their executive, in the creation of a legislature which can enact its fantasies without witnessing their effects, and an executive which abdicates all responsibility for what it does in response to superior orders.â The âindividual citizen contributes to [this] chiefly by obedience and lack of conscious or effective protestâ (*Volume Two, Selection 26*). Comfort argued that the individual, by making âhimself sufficiently numerous and combative,â can render the modern state impotent âby his withdrawal from delinquent attitudes,â undermining âthe social support they receiveâ and the power of the authorities âwhose policies are imposed upon society only through [individual] acquiescence or co-operationâ (*Volume Two, Selection 26*).
At the beginning of the war, Emma Goldman had written that the âState and the political and economic institutions it supports can exist only by fashioning the individual to their particular purpose; training him to respect âlaw and orderâ; teaching him obedience, submission and unquestioning faith in the wisdom and justice of government; above all, loyal service and complete self-sacrifice when the State commands it, as in war.â For her, âtrue liberation, individual and collective, lies in [the individualâs] emancipation from authority and from belief in itâ (*Volume Two, Selection 2*).
Herbert Read held a similar position, but focused on the role of modern education in creating a submissive populace, much had Francisco Ferrer before him (*Volume One, Selection 65*). Through the education system, âeverything personal, everything which is the expression of individual perceptions and feelings, is either neglected, or subordinated to some conception of normality, of social convention, of correctness.â Read therefore advocated libertarian education, emphasizing the creative process and âeducation through artâ (1943), arguing that it âis only in so far as we liberateâ children, âshoots not yet stunted or distorted by an environment of hatred and injustice, that we can expect to make any enduring change in societyâ (*Volume Two, Selection 36*).
Paul Goodman described the school system as âcompulsory mis-educationâ (1964), which perpetuated a society in which youth are âgrowing up absurdâ (1960). His friend Ivan Illich was later to advocate âdeschooling societyâ as a way of combating the commodification of social life, where everything, and everybody, becomes a commodity to be consumed (*Volume Two, Selection 73*). By the 1960s and 1970s, people were again experimenting in libertarian education (*Volume Two, Selection 46*), something which anarchists had been advocating since the time of William Godwin.
In the immediate aftermath of the Second World War, Dwight Macdonald (1905â1982) wrote that the âbrutality and irrationality of Western social institutions has reached a pitch which would have seemed incredible a short generation ago; our lives have come to be dominated by warfare of a ferocity and on a scale unprecedented in history,â leading him to conclude that the âAnarchistsâ uncompromising rejection of the State, the subject of Marxian sneers for its âabsolutistâ and âUtopianâ character, makes much better sense in the present era than the Marxian relativist and historical approachâ (*Volume Two, Selection 13*).
Macdonald argued that in the face of these harsh realities, âwe must reduce political action to a modest, unpretentious, personal levelâone that is real in the sense that it satisfies, here and now, the psychological needs, and the ethical values of the particular persons taking part in it.â He suggested forming âsmall groups of individualsâ into â**families**â who âlive and make their living in the everyday world but who come together⊠to form a **psychological** (as against a geographical) community.â Through these groups their âmembers could come to know each other as fully as possible as human beings (the difficulty of such knowledge of others in modern society is a chief source of evil), to exchange ideas and discuss as fully as possible what is âon their mindsâ (not only the atomic bomb but also the perils of child-rearing), and in general to learn the difficult art of living with other people.â The members of these groups would âpreachâ their âidealsâor, if you prefer, make propagandaâby word and by deed, in the varied everyday contacts of the group members with their fellow men,â working âagainst Jim Crow [racist laws]â in the United States, âor to further pacifism,â and supporting individuals âwho stand up for the common idealsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 13*).
The pacifist David Dellinger (1915â2004), writing a few years later in the anarchist journal, **Resistance**, went a step further, arguing for the creation of small communes âcomposed of persons who have the same type of disgust at the economic selfishness of society that the conscientious objector has concerning war and violence.â In these âexperimentalâ communities, âeconomic resourcesâ would be shared, âso that the total product provides greater strength and freedom for the members than they would be able to achieve, ethically, as isolated individuals,â while providing âdaily pleasures and satisfactionsâ by âfinding time to do things together that are funâ (*Volume Two, Selection 40*).
The âfamiliesâ of like minded individuals proposed by Macdonald would today be described as affinity groups, a form of organization that had been utilized for decades by anarchists, particularly anarchist communists wary of the more formal organizational structures of the anarcho-syndicalists (*Grave, Volume One, Selection 46*). As Murray Bookchin pointed out, the FAI in Spain had been based on an affinity group structure. In the 1960s, Bookchin helped to popularize this intimate form of non-hierarchical organization, which combines ârevolutionary theory with revolutionary lifestyle in its everyday behaviour.â Much like the âfamiliesâ advocated by Macdonald, each affinity group would seek âa rounded body of knowledge and experience in order to overcome the social and psychological limitations imposed by bourgeois society on individual development,â acting âas catalysts within the popular movement.â For Bookchin, the aim of anarchist affinity groups is not to subordinate âthe social forms created by the revolutionary people⊠to an impersonal bureaucracyâ or party organization, but âto advance the spontaneous revolutionary movement of the people to a point where the group can finally disappear into the organic social forms created by the revolutionâ itself (*Volume Two, Selection 62*).
Similarly, the small-scale communes advocated by Dellinger had long been a part of many anarchist movements, in Europe, the Americas, and in China, arising from the need and desire of anarchists to create daily living arrangements consistent with their ideals, and as an alternative to hierarchical and authoritarian social institutions, such as the patriarchal nuclear family. What distinguished these types of communes from affinity groups were the factors highlighted by Dellinger himself, primarily living together and sharing financial resources. In the 1960s and early 1970s, there was a flourishing of communal groups, particularly in North America, created by disaffected youth seeking to create alternate lifestyles. In Europe, the various squatting movements often adopted communal living arrangements, for example in the Christiania âfreetownâ in Copenhagen.
While many anarchist communes were short-lived, some have been remarkably resilient. In Uruguay, for example, the Communidad del Sur group, which originated in the social struggles of the 1950s, sought to create libertarian communities based on self-management, including productive enterprises (*Volume Three, Selection 56*). Assets were shared, compensation was based on need, education, work and art were integrated, and people lived communally. Despite a long period of exile in Sweden that began in the 1970s due to growing state repression, the Communidad group eventually returned to Uruguay where it continues to promote the creation of a self-managed ecological society through its own ongoing experiments in community living. For the Communidad group, the ârevolution consists of changing social relationships,â much as Gustav Landauer had argued previously (*Volume One, Selection 49*). Fleshing out their âideals of equality and sociability in a free space,â the Communidad group has sought to inspire the creation of that âcommunity of communitiesâ long envisioned by anarchists like Landauer, Martin Buber, Paul Goodman and many others (*Volume Two, Selection 60*).
After the Second World War, despite the âCold Warâ between the Soviet Union and the United States, anarchists sought to keep alive their libertarian vision of a free and equal society in which every individual is able to flourish. Marie Louise Berneri coined the phrase, âNeither East nor West,â signifying anarchist opposition to all power blocs (*Volume Two, Selection 10*). Anarchists continued to oppose colonialism and the imperialist expansion of the Soviet and American empires (*Volume Two, Selections 8, 9, 28, 29 & 31*).
Due to their opposition to both dominant power blocs, during the Cold War organized anarchist movements faced almost insurmountable obstacles, similar to the situation faced by the Spanish anarchists during the Revolution and Civil War. In Bulgaria, there was a significant pre-war anarchist communist movement which reemerged briefly after the defeat of Nazi Germany, but which was quickly suppressed by their Soviet âliberators.â The Bulgarian anarchists repudiated fascism as an âattempt to restore absolutism [and] autocracy⊠with the aim of defending the economic and spiritual dominance of the privileged classes.â They rejected âpolitical democracyâ (representative government) because âits social foundations [are] based on the centralized State and capitalism,â resulting in âchaos, contradictions and crime.â As for State socialism, âit leads to State capitalismâthe most monstrous form of economic exploitation and oppression, and of total domination of social and individual freedomâ (*Volume Two, Selection 7*).
The program of the Bulgarian Anarchist Communist Federation is noteworthy today for its emphasis on anarchist federalism as âa dense and complex networkâ of village communities, regional communes, productive enterprises, trade unions, distribution networks and consumer organizations that would be âgrouped in a general confederation of exchange and consumption for satisfying the needs of all inhabitantsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 7*). Such network forms of organization mark an advance over the âinverse pyramidâ structure that had long been advocated by anarcho-syndicalists, which was much more prone to being transformed into a more conventional, hierarchical form of organization during times of crisis, as in Spain. By the early 1950s, many anarcho-syndicalists were advocating similar horizontal networks based on factory councils and community assemblies, resembling a âhoneycomb,â as Philip Sansom put it, in which âall the cells are of equal importance and fit into each other,â instead of control being âmaintained from the centreâ (*Volume Two, Selection 58*).
Within their own organizations, the Bulgarian anarchist communists advocated a form of consensus decision-making. However, while âthe decision of the majority is not binding on the minority,â in practice âthe minority generally rallies to the decision of the majority,â after the majority has had an opportunity to demonstrate the wisdom of its position. Thus, while the minority was not bound to follow the decisions of the majority, the majority was not prevented from acting in accordance with its own views, such that the minority could not assume de facto authority over the majority by refusing to agree with the majority decision, as sometimes happens under other forms of consensus decision-making. The Bulgarian anarchist communists recognized that in broader based mass organizations that were not specifically anarchist in orientation, majority rule would generally prevail, but even then âthe minority may be freed from the obligation to apply a general decision, on condition that it does not prevent the execution of such a decisionâ (*Volume Two, Selection 7*). In this regard, their position is remarkably similar to that of contemporary advocates of participatory democracy, such as Carole Pateman (1985: 159â162; see also Graham, 1996), and anarchist advocates of various forms of direct democracy (*Volume Three, Chapter 2*).
Given the difficult political circumstances faced by anarchists in the aftermath of the Second World War, it should not be surprising that there was a resurgence of anarchist attitudes in the arts, for it was on the cultural terrain that anarchists had the greatest freedom of action. In Quebec, the Automatistes, who were loosely affiliated with the Surrealists, issued their â Global Refusalâ manifesto in 1948, in which they foresaw âpeople freed from their useless chains and turning, in the unexpected manner that is necessary for spontaneity, to resplendent anarchy to make the most of their individual giftsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 22*).
The Surrealists recognized their affinity with the anarchists, sharing their âfundamental hostility towards both power blocs,â and seeking with them to bring about âan era from which all hierarchy and all constraint will have been banishedâ (*Volume Two, Selection 23*). AndrĂ© Breton (1896â1966) noted that it was âin the black mirror of anarchism that surrealism first recognized itself,â but admitted that the surrealists, along with many others on the left, had for too long supported the Soviet Union, mesmerized by âthe idea of efficiencyâ and the hope for a worldwide social revolution. Now it was time âto return to the principlesâ which had allowed the libertarian ideal âto take form,â arriving at a conception of anarchism as, in the words of Georges Fontenis (1920â2010), âthe expression of the exploited masses in their desire to create a society without classes, without a State, where all human values and desires can be realizedâ (*Volume Two, Selection 23*).
In the 1940s, Herbert Read, who had helped introduce Surrealism to English audiences, extolled modern art for breaking through âthe artificial boundaries and limitations which we owe to a one-sided and prejudiced view of the human personality.â For Read, all âtypes of art are not merely permissible, but desirable⊠Any kind of exclusiveness or intolerance is just as opposed to the principles of liberty as social exclusiveness or political intolerance.â He argued that only in an anarchist society would everyone be free to develop âthe artist latent in each one of usâ (*Volume Two, Selection 19*).
Alex Comfort agreed with Read that âin truly free communities art is a general activity, far more cognate with craft than it can ever be in contemporary organized life.â He looked forward to the creation of communities in which âart could become a part of daily activity, and in which all activity [is] potentially creativeâ (*Volume Two, Selection 20*).
As Richard Sonn has put it, âIn the anarchist utopia the boundaries between manual and intellectual labour, between art and craft, dissolve. People are free to express themselves through their work. Artistry pervades life, rather than being restricted to museum walls and bohemian artist studiosâ (*Volume Three, Selection 38*). In contrast, as David Wieck (1921â1997) noted, in existing society we âtake it for granted that a small number of people, more or less talented, shall makeâone would say âcreateââunder the usual consumption-oriented conditions of the market, our âworks of art,â our âentertainment,â while the rest of us are spectatorsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 39*).
Holley Cantine, Jr. (1911â1977) saw art as a form of play which âmust disguise itselfâ in adulthood âas useful work in order to be socially acceptable.â The artist must either find a market for his or her art, put him or herself at the service of some cause, or live the life of an impoverished bohemianâin neither case âis the artist really free⊠Only a relative handful of spontaneous artists, who give no thought to any standards but their own satisfaction, can be said to function in the realm of pure art.â
For Cantine, a free society is one in which everyone âworks, according to his capacity, when there is work to do, and everyone plays the rest of the time,â much as people do in ânon-status societies,â where âplay is regarded as natural for everyone, whenever the immediate pressure of the environment permitsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 21*), an observation confirmed by the anthropological studies conducted by Pierre Clastres (1934â1977) in South America (*Volume Two, Selection 64*).
In New York, Julian Beck (1925â1985) and Judith Malina (1926â2015) founded the Living Theatre in 1947, which sought to break down the barriers between playwright and performer, and between performer and audience. The Living Theatre staged plays by people like Paul Goodman, whose use of âobsceneâ language in the late 1940s and 1950s helped keep the Theatre in trouble with the authorities, when censorship laws were much stricter than in the USA today.
The Theatre developed a more and more improvisational approach, with the actors designing their own movements and the director ultimately âresigning from his authoritarian positionâ (*Volume Two, Selection 24*). By the late 1960s, the Theatre abandoned the confines of the playhouse altogether, pioneering guerilla street theatre and performance art in Europe and Latin America (*Volume Two, Selection 25*).
Richard Sonn has argued that only âanarchists can claim that not the state, not the military, not even the economy, but rather culture is central to it both as movement and as idealâ (*Volume Three, Selection 38*).
For Max Blechman, art âacts as a reminder of the potential joy of life, and as an anarchic force against all that which usurps it. It functions as a perpetual reminder that all meaningful life involves a stretching of the limits of the possible, not toward an absolute, but away from absolutes and into the depths of imagination and the unknown. This creative adventure, at the bottom of all great art, is the power which, if universalized, would embody the driving force of social anarchyâ (*Volume Three, Selection 39*).
Not all anarchists were enamoured with the turn toward personal liberation, alternative lifestyles and cultural change in the aftermath of the Second World War. In Italy, the class struggle anarchists of the Impulso group denounced these anarchist currents as counter-revolutionary, much as Murray Bookchin did many years later (Bookchin, 1995).
The Impulso group described these approaches as âresistencialism,â a term suggested in 1949 by the French anarchist paper, **Ătudes Anarchistes**, to describe the new perspectives and approaches being developed by anarchists in the English speaking countries in the aftermath of the Second World War which emphasized resistance to authoritarian and hierarchical modes of thought and organization, and the creation of libertarian alternatives here and now, regardless of the prospects of a successful social revolution.
What the Impulso groupâs critique illustrates is the degree to which these new conceptions and approaches had spread beyond England and the USA by 1950, when they published their broadside, for much of their attack is directed toward the Italian anarchist journal, **VolontĂ **, belying the claim that the ânewâ anarchism was a largely âAnglo-Saxonâ phenomenon (*Volume Two, Selection 38*).
The **VolontĂ ** group, with which Camillo Berneriâs widow, and long time anarchist, Giovanna Berneri (1897â1962) was associated, had begun exploring new ideas and analyses which have since become the stock in trade of so-called âpost-modernâ anarchists (*Volume Three, Chapter 12*), including a critique of conventional conceptions of rationality and intellectual constructs which seek to constrain thought and action within a specific ideological framework. As one contributor to **VolontĂ ** put it, âAll ideologues are potential tyrantsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 38*).
The Impulso group denounced **VolontĂ ** for celebrating âirrationalismâ and âchaos,â turning anarchism into âa motley, whimsical subjective representation,â and for abandoning any concept of class struggle. For the Impulso group, anarchism was instead âthe ideology of the working and peasant class, the product of a reasoned re-elaboration of revolutionary experiences, the theoretical weapon for the defence of the unitary, ongoing interests of the labouring class, the objective outcome of a specific historic process,â illustrating the degree to which the class struggle anarchists had incorporated into their outlook several Marxian elements (*Volume Two, Selection 38*).
For them, there were âthree vital coefficients to the act of revolution: the crisis in the capitalist system⊠active participation by the broad worker and peasant masses⊠and the organized action of the activist minority.â To the criticism that the âmassesâ can never become self-governing if led by an elite activist minority, the Impulso group responded that an informed, consciously anarchist minority cannot betray the revolution because its theory âis not only the correct general theoryâ but the correct theory âespecially in relation to the activist minority and its nature, its functions, [and] its limitationsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 38*).
This claim that an activist minority of anarchists would never effectively assume positions of authority because their general theory eschews such a role is not particularly persuasive on either theoretical or historical grounds. No matter how well informed by or committed to anarchist principles, the âactivist minority,â armed with their âcorrectâ theory will, as Malatesta had said of the Platformists, be prone âto excommunicate from anarchism all those who do not accept their program,â promoting sectarianism rather than creating a unified movement (*Volume One, Selection 115*).
Neno Vasco (1920) and other anarchists had long argued that the focus of anarchist minorities should instead be on fostering the self-activity of the masses. This is because by âacting directly,â as Murray Bookchin has written, âwe not only gain a sense that we can control the course of social events again; we recover a new sense of selfhood and personality without which a truly free society, based on self-activity and self-management, is utterly impossibleâ (*Volume Three, Selection 10*). That being informed and guided by anarchist theory does not prevent one from assuming a more conventional leadership role was demonstrated by those CNT-FAI âmilitantsâ who joined the Republican government in Spain during the 1936â39 Revolution and Civil War (*Volume One, Selections 127 & 128*).
The Impulso group saw themselves performing a âlocomotive function,â pulling the masses toward liberation through the revolutionary upheaval that would inevitably result from the crisis of international capitalism, committing themselves to âa harsh self-disciplineâ (*Volume Two, Selection 38*), the kind of self-abnegation that Bakunin had warned against earlier (*Volume One, Selection 20*).
Despite the denunciations of the Impulso group, it was the ânewâ anarchism pioneered by the so-called âresistencialistsâ that was to inspire radicals in the 1960s, with people like the Cohn-Bendit brothers writing, âAct with others, not for them. Make the revolution here and now,â for âit is for yourself that you make the revolution,â not some abstract ideal to which all should be sacrificed (*Volume Two, Selection 51*).
The **Impulso** group remained committed to an essentially Marxist view of progressive historical development, the kind of view that Dwight Macdonald argued had literally been exploded by the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki (*Volume Two, Selection 13*). One can no longer claim that from âout of present evil will come future good,â wrote Macdonald, when âfor the first time in history, humanity faces the possibility that its own activity may result in the destruction not of some people or some part of the world, but of all people and the whole world for all timeâ (*Volume Two, Selection 13*).
The **Impulso** group clung to the view that as the result of an objective historical process, the working class developed âunitary, ongoing interests,â impelling it to fulfill its âhistorical roleâ of abolishing capitalism (*Volume Two, Selection 38*). That the working class has unitary interests is a concept that has been criticized by other anarchists since at least the time of Bakunin, who argued against Marx that city workers âwho earn more and live more comfortably than all the other workers,â by virtue of their ârelative well-being and semibourgeois positionâ form a kind of âaristocracy of labour⊠unfortunately only too deeply saturated with all the political and social prejudices and all the narrow aspirations and pretensions of the bourgeoisieâ (1872: 294).
Macdonald pointed to the post-War âfailure of the European masses to get excited about socialist slogans and programs,â suggesting that the âman in the streetâ feels âas powerless and manipulated vis-Ă -vis his socialist mass-organization as⊠towards his capitalistic employers and their social and legal institutionsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 13*). For Louis Mercier Vega (1914â1977), social stratification within the âworking classâ makes it necessary âto speak of several working classes,â each with conflicting interests. âWage differentials,â for example, âmake class consciousness that much harder to achieve⊠encouraging collusion between (private or state) management and privileged brackets of wage-earners. They accentuate rather than curtail the tendency to retain a sub-proletariat reduced to low wages and readily disposed of in the event of a crisis or economic slow-down, alongside groups of workers, employees and officials locked into complex [regulatory] arrangements wherein their docility and diligence are reflected in their wage levelsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 45*).
The **Impulso** group implicitly accepted the Marxist view of historical stages of development which other anarchists, from Bakunin onward, have also challenged. Even before Bakuninâs conflict with Marx in the First International, one of the points of disagreement between Marx and Proudhon was whether an anarchist form of socialism could be achieved before capitalism created the technology that would produce an abundance of goods allegedly necessary to sustain a socialist society (Marx, 1847). Anarchists promoted peasant revolutions in a variety of circumstances, rather than waiting for the development of an urban proletariat as suggested by the Marxist view of history.
Gustav Landauer rejected that âartifice of historical development, by whichâas a matter of historical necessityâthe working class, to one extent or another, is called by Providence to take for itself the role of the present day ruling classâ (*Volume One, Selection 40*). For Landauer, âthe miracle that materialism and mechanism assumeâthat⊠fully-grown socialism grows not out of the childhood beginnings of socialism, but out of the colossal deformed body of capitalismâthis miracle will not come, and soon people will no longer believe in itâ (*Volume One, Selection 49*). Huang Lingshuang and Rudolf Rocker later put forward similar critiques of the Marxist theory of history.
In the 1950s, some anarchists were influenced by the contemporaneous critique of Marxist âhistoricismâ that was being developed by philosophers such as Karl Popper (1957). Writing in the early 1960s, the Chilean anarchist Lain Diez urged anarchists to reject all âhistoricist systemsâ based on âthe supremacy (in terms of decision making in menâs affairs) of History⊠which, unknown to men, supposedly foists its law upon them,â for this ânew and jealous divinity has its intermediaries who, like the priests of the ancient religions, interpret its intentions, prophesying as they did and issuing thunderous anathemas against miscreants refusing to be awed by their revelationsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 47*). More recently, Alan Carter has presented a thoroughgoing anarchist critique of Marxist âtechnological determinismâ (1988), emphasizing the role of the state in creating and enforcing âthe relations of production that lead to the creation of the surplus that the state requiresâ to finance the âforces of coercionâ necessary to maintain state power, turning Marxâs theory of history on its head (*Volume Three, Selection 19*).
The **Impulso** group was most concerned that the ânewâ anarchism represented by the âresistencialistsâ would lead anarchists away from their historic commitment to revolution, a concern not without foundation. In the 1950s in Australia, for example, the Sydney Libertarians developed a critique of anarchist âutopianism,â which for them was based on the supposed anarchist over-emphasis on âco-operation and rational persuasionâ (*Volume Two, Selection 41*), a critique later expanded upon by post-modern anarchists (*Volume Three, Chapter 12*). In response, without endorsing the more narrow approach of the **Impulso** group, one can argue that these sorts of critiques are themselves insufficiently critical because they repeat and incorporate common misconceptions of anarchism as a theory based on an excessively naĂŻve and optimistic view of human nature (Jesse Cohen, *Volume Three, Selection 67*).
For the Sydney Libertarians, not only is it unlikely that a future anarchist society will be achieved, it is unnecessary because âthere are anarchist-like activities such as criticizing the views of authoritarians, resisting the pressure towards servility and conformity, [and] having unauthoritarian sexual relationships, which can be carried on for their own sake, here and now, without any reference to supposed future ends.â They described this kind of anarchism as âanarchism without endsâ, âpessimistic anarchismâ and âpermanent protest,â stressing âthe carrying on of particular libertarian activities within existing societyâ regardless of the prospects of a successful social revolution (*Volume Two, Selection 41*).
The resurgence of anarchism during the1960s surprised both âpessimistic anarchistsâ and the more traditional âclass struggleâ anarchists associated with the **Impulso** group, some of whom, such as Pier Carlo Masini, abandoned anarchism altogether when it appeared to them that the working class was not going to embrace the anarchist cause. Other class struggle anarchists, such as AndrĂ© Prudhommeaux (*1902â1968*), recognized that the masses were âunmovedâ by revolutionary declamations âheralding social revolution in Teheran, Cairo or Caracas and Judgment Day in Paris the following day at the latest,â because when ânothing is happening,â to make such claims is âlike calling out the fire brigade on a hoax.â To gain the support of the people, anarchists must work with them to protect their âcivil liberties and basic rights by means of direct action, civil disobedience, strikes and individual and collective revolution in all their many formsâ (*Volume One, Selection 30*).
By the early 1960s, peace and anti-war movements had risen in Europe and North America in which many anarchists, following Prudhommeauxâs suggestion, were involved. Anarchist influence within the social movements of the 1960s did not come out of nowhere but emerged from the work of anarchists and like-minded individuals in the 1950s, most of whom, like Prudhommeaux, had connections with the various pre-war anarchist movements. There was growing dissatisfaction among people regarding the quality of life in post-war America and Europe and their prospects for the future, given the ongoing threat of nuclear war and continued involvement of their respective governments, relying on conscript armies, in conflicts abroad as various peoples sought to liberate themselves from European and U.S. control.
In the post-WW II era, anarchists continued to oppose colonialism and imperial domination but were wary of those who sought to take advantage of national liberation struggles to facilitate their own rise to power, much like the state socialists had tried to harness popular discontent in Europe, and had succeeded in doing in Russia and China.
Drawing on James Burnhamâs concept of the managerial revolution (1941), while rejecting his pessimistic and politically conservative conclusions, the anarcho-syndicalist Geoffrey Ostergaard (1926â1990) warned of the âincreasingly powerful managerial classâ which holds out the prospect of âemancipation but in reality hands over the workers to new masters,â turning trade unions and other popular forms of organization into âmore refined instruments for disciplining the workersâ after the intellectuals, trade union leaders and party functionaries succeed in riding waves of popular discontent to assume positions of power (*Volume Two, Selection 27*).
French anarchists associated with the Groupe Anarchiste dâAction Revolutionnaire recognized the âproliferation of nation-statesâ as âan irreversible historical trend, a backlash against world conquestâ by European powers, and that although ânational emancipation movements do not strive for a libertarian society,â such a society âis unattainable without them. Only at the end of a widespread process of geographical, egalitarian redistribution of human activities can a federation of peoples supplant the array of states.â
Nevertheless, anarchists could afford ânational liberation movements only an eminently critical support,â for the mission of anarchists remains âto undermine the foundations of all⊠nationalist world-views, as well as every colonial and imperial institution. The bulwark of exploitation and oppression, injustice and misery, hatred and ignorance is still the State whosoever it appears with its retinueâArmy, Church, Partyâthwarting men and pitting them against one another by means of war, hierarchy and bureaucracy, instead of binding them together through cooperation, solidarity and mutual aid â (*Volume Two, Selection 31*).
Mohamed SaĂŻl (1894â1953), an Algerian anarchist who fought with the Durruti Column in Spain, regarded Algerian nationalism as âthe bitter fruit of French occupation.â He suggested that âthe Algerian people, released from one yoke, will hardly want to saddle itself with another one,â given their strong village ties and historic resistance to central authorities, whether Turk, Arab or French. While things did not work out as he had hoped, his fellow Kabyles have continued the ârevolt against authoritarian centralismâ for which he praised them (*Volume Two, Selection 28; Volume Three, Selection 50*).
During the 1950s, Cuban anarchists were directly involved in the struggle to overthrow the U.S. supported Batista dictatorship but at the same time had to fight against Marxist domination of the revolutionary and labour movements. They encouraged the âworkers to prepare themselves culturally and professionally not only to better their present working conditions, but also to take over the technical operation and administration of the whole economy in the new libertarian societyâ (*Volume Three, Selection 55*).
After Castro seized power, they struggled in vain to maintain an independent labour movement and to prevent the creation of a socialist dictatorship. Outside of Cuba, Castroâs victory divided anarchists, particularly in Latin America, with some arguing that to support the revolution one must support the Castro regime, similar to the arguments that had been made earlier by the âBolshevikâ anarchists in Russia. Others came to doubt the efficacy of armed struggle and violent revolution, such as the anarchists associated with the Comunidad del Sur group in Uruguay, who turned their focus towards building alternative communities (*Volumes Two and Three, Selection 60*).
In post-independence India, the Gandhian Sarvodaya movement provided an example of a non-violent movement for social change which aspired to a stateless society. Vinoba Bhave (1895â1982), one of the movementâs spiritual leaders, noted that âsarvodaya does not mean good government or majority rule, it means freedom from government,â with decisions being made at the village level by consensus, for self-government âmeans ruling you own self,â without âany outside power.â
What seemed wrong to Bhave was not that the Indian people were governed by this or that government, but that âwe should allow ourselves to be governed at all, even by a good governmentâ (*Volume Two, Selection 32*). He looked forward to the creation of a stateless society through the decentralization of political power, production, distribution, defence and education to village communities.
Bhaveâs associate, Jayaprakash Narayan (1902â1979), drew the connections between their approach, which emphasized that a âharmonious blending of nature and culture is possible only in comparatively smaller communities,â and Aldous Huxleyâs anarchist tinged vision of a future in which each person âhas a fair measure of personal independence and personal responsibility within and toward a self-governing group,â in which âwork possesses a certain aesthetic value and human significance,â and each person âis related to his natural environment in some organic, rooted and symbiotic wayâ (*Volume Two, Selection 32*).
The Sarvodaya movementâs tactics of Gandhian non-violence influenced the growing anarchist and peace movements in Europe and North America (*Volume Two, Selection 34*), while the Sarvodayans shared the antipathy of many anarchists toward the centralization, bureaucratic organization, technological domination, alienation and estrangement from nature found in modern industrial societies.
Paul Goodman summed up the malaise affecting people in advanced industrial societies during the 1950s in his essay, âA Public Dream of Universal Disasterâ (*Volume Two, Selection 37*), in which he noted that despite technological advances and economic growth, âeverywhere people are disappointed. Even so far, then, there is evident reason to smash things, to destroy not this or that part of the system (e.g., the upper class), but the whole system en bloc; for it offers no promise, but only more of the same.â
With people paralyzed by the threat of nuclear annihilation, seeking release from their pent up hostility, frustration, disappointment and anger through acquiescence to âmass suicide, an outcome that solves most problems without personal guilt,â only âadventurous revolutionary social and psychological actionâ can have any prospect of success (*Volume Two, Selection 38*).
As Goodmanâs contemporary, Julian Beck, put it, we need to âstorm the barricades,â whether military, political, social or psychological, for âwe want to get rid of all barricades, even our own and any that we might ever setupâ (*Volume Two, Selection 24*). What is necessary, according to Dwight Macdonald, is âto encourage attitudes of disrespect, skepticism [and] ridicule towards the State and all authorityâ (*Volume Two, Selection 13*).
This challenge to conventional mores, fear and apathy came to fruition in the 1960s as anarchists staged various actions and âhappenings,â often in conjunction with other counter-cultural and dissident political groups, from the Yippies showering the floor of the New York Stock Exchange with dollar bills, causing chaos among the stock traders, to the Provos leaving white bicycles around Amsterdam to combat âautomobilismâ and to challenge public acceptance of private property (*Volume Two, Selection 50*).
Macdonald thought that the âtotalization of State power today means that only something on a different plane can cope with it, something which fights the State from a vantage point which the Stateâs weapons can reach only with difficulty,â such as ânon-violence, which⊠confuses [the stateâs] human agents, all the more so because it appeals to traitorous elements in their own heartsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 13*). As Richard Gregg described it, non-violent resistance is a kind of âmoral ju-jitsuâ which causes âthe attacker to lose his moral balanceâ by taking away âthe moral support which the usual violent resistance⊠would render himâ (*Volume Two, Selection 34*).
The anti-war movements in Europe and North America that began to emerge during the late 1950s started as âBan the Bombâ or anti-nuclear peace movements, the primary aim of which was to reduce and eliminate nuclear weapons. These movements began to adopt a more expansive anti-war approach as draft resistance movements also began to emerge, first in France in response to the war in Algeria, and then in the U.S. as the war in Vietnam escalated and intensified.
Many people in the various peace movements were pacifists. Some of them began to move towards an anarchist position as they came to realize that the banning of nuclear weapons was either unlikely or insufficient given the existing system of international power relations. Many came to agree with Randolf Bourne that âwar is the health of the stateâ and became advocates of non-violent revolution, for one âcannot crusade against war without crusading implicitly against the Stateâ (*Volume Two, Selection 34*).
Veteran anarchists, such as Vernon Richards, despite recognizing the limitations of peace marches, realized that for âsome the very fact of having broken away from the routine pattern of life to take partâ in a march, and âfor others the effort of will needed to join a demonstration for the first time in their lives, are all positive steps in the direction of ârebellionâ against the Establishment,â for there âare times when the importance of an action is for oneselfâ (*Volume Two, Selection 33*).
Some of the people opposed to conscription in France and the U.S. also gravitated toward anarchism, as they came to realize not only that meaningful draft resistance was illegal, thereby making them criminals, but also the degree to which those in positions of power were prepared to use force not only against their âexternalâ enemies but against their own people to prevent the undermining of their authority. As Jean Marie Chester wrote in France in the early 1960s, the young draft resisters had, âthrough their refusal, unwittingly stumbled upon anarchismâ (*Volume Two, Selection 31*).
Unlike more conventional conceptions of civil disobedience, where demonstrators emphasize that their disobedience is an extraordinary reaction to an extreme policy, accepting the punishment meted out to them because they do not want to challenge the legitimacy of authority in general, anarchist disobedience and direct action suffer from no such contradictions but instead seek to broaden individual acts of disobedience into rejection of institutional power by encouraging people to question authority in all its aspects. From individual acts of revolt and protest, and experience of the repressive measures the State is prepared to resort to in response, will come a growing recognition of the illegitimacy of State power and the hierarchical and exploitative relationships which that power protects. As the Dutch Provos put it, the âmeans of repressionâ the authorities âuse against usâ will force them âto show their real nature,â making âthemselves more and more unpopular,â ripening âthe popular conscience⊠for anarchyâ (*Volume Two, Selection 50*).
During the 1960s, anarchist ideas were reintroduced to student rebels, anti-war protesters, environmentalists and a more restless general public by people like Murray Bookchin (*Volume Two, Selection 48*), Daniel GuĂ©rin (*Volume Two, Selection 49*), the Cohn-Bendit brothers (*Volume Two, Selection 51*), Jacobo Prince (*Volume Two, Selection 52*), Nicolas Walter (*Volume Two, Selection 54*) and Noam Chomsky (*Volume Two, Selection 55*). While libertarian socialist intellectuals such as Claude Lefort from the **Socialisme ou Barbarie** group, who came from a Marxist background, regarded the anarchist ideas and actions of the student radicals of the May-June 1968 events in France as the âbrilliant inventionâ of ânaĂŻve prodigies,â the Cohn-Bendit brothers, who were directly involved, replied that, to the contrary, those events were âthe result of arduous research into revolutionary theory and practice,â marking âa return to a revolutionary traditionâ that the Left had long since abandoned, namely anarchism (*Volume Two, Selection 51*).
Anarchists had long been advocates of decentralized, human scale technology and sustainable communities. In the 1940s, Ethel Mannin drew the connections between increasing environmental degradation, existing power structures and social inequality, writing that as long as âMan continues to exploit the soil for profit he sows the seeds of his own destruction, not merely because Nature becomes his enemy, responding to his machines and his chemicals by the withdrawal of fertility, the dusty answer of an ultimate desert barrenness, but because his whole attitude to life is debased; his gods become Money and Power, and wars and unemployment and useless toil become his inevitable portionâ (*Volume Two, Selection 14*). Murray Bookchin expanded on this critique in the 1960s, arguing that the âmodern city⊠the massive coal-steel technology of the Industrial Revolution, the later, more rationalized systems of mass production and assembly-line systems of labour organization, the centralized nation, the state and its bureaucratic apparatusâall have reached their limits,â undermining ânot only the human spirit and the human community but also the viability of the planet and all living things on itâ (*Volume Two, Selection 48*).
Bookchin was fundamentally opposed to those environmentalists who looked to existing power structures to avert ecological collapse or catastrophe. This was because the ânotion that man is destined to dominate nature stems from the domination of man by manâand perhaps even earlier, by the domination of woman by man and the domination of the young by the oldâ (*Volume Three, Selection 26*). Consequently, the way out of ecological crisis is not to strengthen or rely on those hierarchical power structures which have brought about that crisis, but through direct action, which for Bookchin is âthe means whereby each individual awakens to the hidden powers within herself and himself, to a new sense of self-confidence and self-competence; it is the means whereby individuals take control of society directly, without ârepresentativesâ who tend to usurp not only the power but the very personality of a passive, spectatorial âelectorateâ who live in the shadows of an âelectââ(*Volume Three, Selection 10*).
In Mutual Aid, Kropotkin argued not only that the state was unlikely to effect positive social change, given the interests it represents, but that reliance on state power renders people less and less capable of collectively managing their own affairs, for in âproportion as the obligations towards the State [grow] in numbers the citizens [are] evidently relieved from their obligations towards each other.â As Michael Taylor puts it, under âthe state, there is no practice of cooperation and no growth of a sense of the interdependence on which cooperation depends.â Because environmental crisis can only be resolved through the action and cooperation of countless individuals, instead of strengthening the state people should heed the anarchist call for decentralization, by seeking to disaggregate âlarge societies⊠into smaller societies,â and by resisting âthe enlargement of societies and the destruction of small ones,â thereby fostering the cooperation and self-activity upon which widespread social change ultimately depends (*Volume Two, Selection 65*). Otherwise, as Paul Goodman argued, we are stuck in âa vicious circle, for⊠the very exercise of abstract power, managing and coercing, itself tends to stand in the way and alienate, to thwart function and diminish energy⊠the consequence of the process is to put us in fact in a continual emergency, so power creates its own need.â For the emergency or crisis to be effectively resolved, there must be âa profound change in social structure, including getting rid of national sovereign powerâ (*Volume Two, Selection 36*).
In his discussion of the emergence of hierarchical societies which âgradually subverted the unity of society with the natural world,â Murray Bookchin noted the important role played by âthe patriarchal family in which women were brought into universal subjugation to menâ (*Volume Three, Selection 26*). Rossella Di Leo has suggested that hierarchical societies emerged from more egalitarian societies in which there were âasymmetriesâ of authority and prestige, with men holding the social positions to which the most prestige was attached (*Volume Three, Selection 32*). In contemporary society, Nicole Laurin-Frenette observes, âwomen of all classes, in all trades and professions, in all sectors of work and at all professional levels [continue] to be assigned tasks which are implicitly or explicitly defined and conceived as feminine. These tasks usually correspond to subordinate functions which entail unfavourable practical and symbolic conditionsâ (*Volume Three, Selection 33*).
In the late 1960s and early 1970s, a radical feminist movement emerged that shared many affinities with anarchism and the ecology movement. Peggy Kornegger argued that âfeminists have been unconscious anarchists in both theory and practice for yearsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 78*). Radical feminists regarded âthe nuclear family as the basis for all authoritarian systems,â much as earlier anarchists had, from Otto Gross (*Volume One, Selection 78*), to Marie Louise Berneri (*Volume Two, Selection 75*) and Daniel GuĂ©rin (*Volume Two, Selection 76*). Radical feminists also rejected âthe male domineering attitude toward the external world, allowing only subject/object relationships,â developing a critique of âmale hierarchical thought patternsâin which rationality dominates sensuality, mind dominates intuition, and persistent splits and polarities (active/passive, child/adult, sane/insane, work/play, spontaneity/organization) alienate us from the mind-body experience as a **Whole** and from the **Continuum** of human experience,â echoing the much older critique of Daoist anarchists, such as Bao Jingyan (*Volume One, Selection 1*).
Kornegger noted that as âthe second wave of feminism spread across the [U.S.] in the late 60s, the forms which womenâs groups took frequently reflected an unspoken libertarian consciousness,â with women breaking off âinto small, leaderless, consciousness-raising groups, which dealt with personal issues in our daily lives,â and which âbore a striking resemblanceâ to âanarchist affinity groupsâ (see Bookchin, *Volume Two, Selection 62*), with their âemphasis on the small group as a basic organizational unit, on the personal and political, on antiauthoritarianism, and on spontaneous direct actionâ (*Volume Two, Selection 78*).
As Carol Ehrlich notes, radical feminists and anarchist feminists âare concerned with a set of common issues: control over oneâs body; alternatives to the nuclear family and to heterosexuality; new methods of child care that will liberate parents and children; economic self-determination; ending sex stereotyping in education, in the media, and in the workplace; the abolition of repressive laws; an end to male authority, ownership, and control over women; providing women with the means to develop skills and positive self-attitudes; an end to oppressive emotional relationships; and what the Situationists have called âthe reinvention of everyday lifeâ.â Despite the Situationistsâ hostility toward anarchism, many anarchists in the 1960s and 70s were influenced by the Situationist critique of the âsociety of the spectacle,â in which âthe stage is set, the action unfolds, we applaud when we think we are happy, we yawn when we think we are bored, but we cannot leave the show, because there is no world outside the theater for us to go toâ (*Volume Two, Selection 79*).
Some anarchist women were concerned that the more orthodox âfeminist movement has, consciously or otherwise, helped motivate women to integrate with the dominant value system,â as Ariane Gransac put it, for âif validation through power makes for equality of the sexes, such equality can scarcely help but produce a more fulsome integration of women into the system of manâs/womanâs domination over his/her fellow-man/womanâ (*Volume Three, Selection 34*). âLike the workersâ movement in the past, especially its trade union wing,â Nicole Laurin-Frenette observes, âthe feminist movement is constantly obliged to negotiate with the State, because it alone seems able to impose respect for the principles defended by feminism on womenâs direct and immediate opponents, namely menâhusbands, fathers, fellow citizens, colleagues, employers, administrators, thinkersâ (*Volume Three, Selection 33*). For anarchists the focus must remain on abolishing all forms of hierarchy and domination, which Carol Ehrlich has described as âthe hardest task of allâ (*Volume Two, Selection 79*). Yet, as Peggy Kornegger reminds us, we must not give up hope, that âvision of the future so beautiful and so powerful that it pulls us steadily forwardâ through âa continuum of thought and action, individuality and collectivity, spontaneity and organization, stretching from what is to what can beâ (*Volume Two, Selection 78*).
In criticizing the subordinate position of women, particularly in marriage, anarchist feminists often compared the position of married women to that of a prostitute (Emma Goldman, *Volume One, Selection 70*). More recently, Carole Pateman has developed a far-reaching feminist critique of the contractarian ideal of reducing all relationships to contractual relationships in which people exchange the âpropertyâ in their persons, with particular emphasis on prostitution, or contracts for sexual services, noting that: âThe idea of property in the person has the merit of drawing attention to the importance of the body in social relations. Civil mastery, like the mastery of the slave-owner, is not exercised over mere biological entities that can be used like material (animal) property, nor exercised over purely rational entities. Masters are not interested in the disembodied fiction of labour power or services. They contract for the use of human embodied selves. Precisely because subordinates are embodied selves they can perform the required labour, be subject to discipline, give the recognition and offer the faithful service that makes a man a masterâ (*Volume Three, Selection 35*).
What distinguishes prostitution contracts from other contracts involving âproperty in the personâ is that when âa man enters into the prostitution contract he is not interested in sexually indifferent, disembodied services; he contracts to buy sexual use of a **woman** for a given period⊠When womenâs bodies are on sale as commodities in the capitalist market⊠men gain public acknowledgment as womenâs sexual masters.â Pateman notes that âcontracts about property in persons [normally] take the form of an exchange of obedience for protection,â but the âshort-term prostitution contract cannot include the protection available in long-term relations.â Rather, the âprostitution contract mirrors the contractarian idealâ of âsimultaneous exchangeâ of property or services, âa vision of unimpeded mutual use or universal prostitutionâ (*Volume Three, Selection 35*).
In the 1970s, Ivan Illich, who was close to Paul Goodman, called for the âinversion of present institutional purposes,â seeking to create a âconvivial society,â by which he meant âautonomous and creative intercourse among persons, and intercourse of persons with their environment.â For Illich, as with most anarchists, âindividual freedom [is] realized in mutual personal interdependence,â the sort of interdependence which atrophies under the state and capitalism. The problem with present institutions is that they âprovide clients with predetermined goods,â making âcommodities out of health, education, housing, transportation, and welfare. We need arrangements which permit modern man to engage in the activities of healing and health maintenance, learning and teaching, moving and dwelling.â He argued that desirable institutions are therefore those which âenable people to meet their own needs.â
Where Illich parted company with anarchists was in his endorsement of legal coercion to establish limits to personal consumption. He proposed âto set a legal limit to the tooling of society in such a way that the toolkit necessary to conviviality will be accessible for the autonomous use of a maximum number of peopleâ (*Volume Two, Selection 73*). For anarchists, one of the problems with coercive legal government is that, in the words of Allan Ritter, the âremoteness of its officials and the permanence and generality of its controls cause it to treat its subjects as abstract strangers. Such treatment is the very opposite of the personal friendly treatmentâ appropriate to the sort of convivial society that Illich sought to create (*Volume Three, Selection 18*).
Anarchists would agree with Illich that existing political systems âprovide goods with clients rather than people with goods. Individuals are forced to pay for and use things they do not need; they are allowed no effective part in the process of choosing, let alone producing them.â Anarchists would also support âthe individualâs right to use only what he [or she] needs, to play an increasing part as an individual in its production,â and the âguaranteeâ of âan environment so simple and transparent that all [people] most of the time have access to all the things which are useful to care for themselves and for others.â While Illichâs emphasis on âthe need for limits of per capita consumptionâ may appear to run counter to the historic anarchist communist commitment to a society of abundance in which all are free to take what they need, anarchists would agree with Illich that people should be in âcontrol of the means and the mode of productionâ so that they are âin the service of the peopleâ rather than people being controlled by them âfor the purpose of raising output at all cost and then worrying how to distribute it in a fair wayâ (*Volume Two, Selection 73*).
Illich proposed that âthe first step in a more general program of institutional inversionâ would be the âde-schooling of society.â By this he meant the abolition of schools which âenable a teacher to establish classes of subjects and to impute the need for them to classes of people called pupils. The inverse of schools would be opportunity networks which permit individuals to state their present interest and seek a match for it.â Illich therefore went one step beyond the traditional anarchist focus on creating libertarian schools that students are free to attend and in which they choose what to learn (*Volume One, Selections 65 & 66*), adopting a position similar to Paul Goodman, who argued that children should not be institutionalized within a school system at all (1964).
By replacing the commodity of âeducationâ with âlearning,â which is an activity, Illich hoped to move away from âour present world view, in which our needs can be satisfied only by tangible or intangible commodities which we consumeâ (*Volume Two, Selection 73*). The âcommodificationâ of social life is a common theme in anarchist writings, from the time when Proudhon denounced capitalism for reducing the worker to âa chattel, a thingâ (*Volume One, Selection 9*), to George Woodcockâs critique of the âtyranny of the clock,â which âturns time from a process of nature into a commodity that can be measured and bought and sold like soap or sultanasâ (*Volume Two, Selection 69*).
Illich criticized those anarchists who âwould make their followers believe that the maximum technically possible is not simply the maximum desirable for a few, but that it can also provide everybody with maximum benefits at minimum cost,â describing them as âtechno-anarchistsâ because they âhave fallen victim to the illusion that it is possible to socialize the technocratic imperativeâ (*Volume Two, Selection 73*). It is not clear to whom Illich was directing these comments, but a few years earlier Richard Kostelanetz had written an article defending what he described as âtechnoanarchism,â in which he criticized the more common anarchist stance critical toward modern technology (*Volume Two, selection 72*).
Kostelanetz suggested that âby freeing more people from the necessity of productivity, automation increasingly permits everyone his artistic or craftsmanly pursuits,â a position similar to that of Oscar Wilde (*Volume One, Selection 61*). Instead of criticizing modern technology, anarchists should recognize that the âreal dehumanizerâ is âuncaring bureaucracy.â Air pollution can be more effectively dealt with through the development of âless deleterious technologies of energy production, or better technologies of pollutant-removal or the dispersion of urban industry.â Agreeing with Irving Horowitzâs claim that anarchists ignored âthe problems of a vast technology,â by trying to find their way back âto a system of production that was satisfactory to the individual producer, rather than feasible for a growing mass society,â Kostelanetz argued that anarchists must now regard technology as âa kind of second nature⊠regarding it as similarly cordial if not ultimately harmonious, as initial natureâ (*Volume Two, Selection 72*).
In response to Horowitzâs comments, David Watson later wrote that the argument âis posed backwards. Technology has certainly transformed the world, but the question is not whether the anarchist vision of freedom, autonomy, and mutual cooperation is any longer relevant to mass technological civilization. It is more pertinent to ask whether freedom, autonomy, or human cooperation themselves can be possible in such a civilizationâ (Watson: 165â166). For Murray Bookchin, âthe issue of disbanding the factoryâindeed, of restoring manufacture in its literal sense as a manual art rather than a muscular âmegamachineââhas become a priority of enormous social importance,â because âwe must arrest more than just the ravaging and simplification of nature. We must also arrest the ravaging and simplification of the human spirit, of human personality, of human community⊠and humanityâs own fecundity within the natural worldâ by creating decentralized ecocommunities âscaled to human dimensionsâ and âartistically tailored to their natural surroundingsâ (*Volume Two, Selection 74*).
The contractarian ideal seeks to reduce all relationships to contractual relationships, ultimately eliminating the need for any public political process. Murray Bookchin has argued to the contrary that there is, or should be, a genuine public sphere in which all members of a community are free to participate and able to collectively make decisions regarding the policies that are to be followed by that community. Community assemblies, in contrast to factory councils, provide everyone with a voice in collective decision making, not just those directly involved in the production process (*Volume Two, Selection 62*). Such assemblies would function much like the anarchist âcollectivesâ in the Spanish Revolution documented by Gaston Leval (*Volume One, Selection 126*).
Questions arise however regarding the relationship between community assemblies and other forms of organization, whether workersâ councils, trade unions, community assemblies in other areas, or voluntary associations in general. In addition to rejecting simple majority rule, anarchists have historically supported not only the right of individuals and groups to associate, network and federate with other individuals and groups but to secede or disassociate from them. One cannot have voluntary associations based on compulsory membership (*Ward: Volume Two, Selection 63*).
Disregarding the difficulties in determining the âwillâ of an assembly (whether by simple majority vote of those present, as Bookchin advocated, or by some more sophisticated means), except in rare cases of unanimity one would expect genuine and sincere disagreements over public policy decisions to continue to arise even after the abolition of class interests. The enforcement of assembly decisions would not only exacerbate conflict, it would encourage factionalism, with people sharing particular views or interests uniting to ensure that their views predominate. In such circumstances, âpositive altruism and voluntary cooperative behaviourâ tend to atrophy (*Taylor, Volume Two, Selection 65*), as the focus of collective action through the assemblies becomes achieving coercive legal support for oneâs own views rather than eliciting the cooperation of others (Graham, 2004).
<biblio>
Avrich, Paul. **Anarchist Portraits**. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988.
<br>
<em>The Anarchists in the Russian Revolution</em>. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973. Editor.
<br>
<em>The Russian Anarchists</em>. New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1978.
Balazs, Etienne. **Chinese Civilization and Bureaucracy**. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1964. Trans. H.M. Wright.
Bakunin, Michael. âThe International and Karl Marxâ (1872). **Bakunin on Anarchism**. Ed. S. Dolgoff. Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1980.
Barclay, Harold. **People Without Government**. London: Kahn & Averill, 1982.
<br>
<em>The State</em>. London: Freedom Press, 2003.
Berkman, Alexander. **The Bolshevik Myth** (1925). London: Pluto Press, 1989.
Berneri, Camillo. âThe Racist Deliriumâ (1935). Robert Grahamâs Anarchism Weblog: [[https://robertgraham.wordpress.com][robertgraham.wordpress.com]].
Berneri, Marie Louise. **Journey Through Utopia**. London: Routlege & Kegan Paul, 1950 (republished by Freedom Press, 1982).
Bookchin, Murray. **Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism**. San Francisco: AK Press, 1995.
Burnham, James. **The Managerial Revolution**. New York: John Day Co., 1941.
Cahm, Caroline. **Kropotkin and the Rise of Revolutionary Anarchism, 1872â1886**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
Carter, Alan. **Marx: A Radical Critique**. Brighton: Wheatsheaf, 1988.
Clark, John P. âMaster Lao and the Anarchist Prince.â **The Anarchist Moment**. Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1984.
Coeurderoy, Ernest. âCitizen of the World.â Jours dâexil (1854). Robert Grahamâs Anarchism Weblog: [[https://robertgraham.wordpress.com][robertgraham.wordpress.com]].
Crone, Patricia. âNinth-Century Muslim Anarchists.â **Past and Present**, No. 167. 2000.
Crump, John. **The Anarchist Movement in Japan**. London: Pirate Press, 1996.
Cutler, Robert. **From Out of the Dustbin: Bakuninâs Basic Writings, 1869â1871**. Ann Arbor: Ardis Publishers, 1985.
Dryzek, John S. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
Dunois, AmadĂ©e. âAnarchism and Organization.â **International Anarchist Congress, Amsterdam, 1907**. Robert Grahamâs Anarchism Weblog:
<br>
[[https://robertgraham.wordpress.com][robertgraham.wordpress.com]].
Geneva Group of Anarchist-Communists. âReplyâ (1916). **The Anarchists in the Russian Revolution**. Ed. P. Avrich. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973.
Goodman, Paul. **Compulsory Mis-Education**. New York: Horizon Press, 1964.
<br>
<em>Growing Up Absurd</em>. New York: Vintage Books, 1960.
Graham, Robert. âThe Anarchist Contract.â **Reinventing Anarchy, Again**. Ed. H. Erhlich.
<br>
San Francisco: AK Press, 1996.
<br>
âReinventing Hierarchy: The Political Theory of Social Ecology.â **Anarchist Studies**. Vol. 12, No. 1, 2004.
<br>
âThe Role of Contract in Anarchist Ideology.â **For Anarchism: History, Theory** **and Practice**. Ed. D. Goodway. London: Routledge, 1989.
Hart, John M. **Anarchism and the Mexican Working Class, 1860â1931**. Austin: University of Texas, 1987.
Henry, Emile. âA Terroristâs Defenceâ (1894). **The Anarchist Reader**. Ed. G. Woodcock. Fontana, 1977.
Horrox, James. **A Living Revolution: Anarchism in the Kibbutz Movement**. San Francisco: AK Press, 2009.
Joll, James. **The Anarchists. 2<sup>nd</sup> Edition**. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980.
Kuhn, Gabriel. Introduction to E. Musham, **Liberating Society From the State and Other Writings**. Oakland: PM Press, 2011.
Knabb, Ken. Situationist International Anthology. Berkeley: Bureau of Public Secrets, 1981.
Krebs, Edward S. **Shifu, Soul of Chinese Anarchism**. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998.
Kropotkin, Peter. âAnarchism.â **Encyclopedia Britannica**, 11th Ed. (1910). Reprinted in **Anarchism and Anarchist Communism**. Ed. N. Walter. London: Freedom Press, 1987.
<br>
<em>Anarchist Communism</em> (1887). Reprinted in <em>Anarchism and Anarchist Communism</em>. Ed. N. Walter.
<br>
<em>Modern Science and Anarchism</em> (1912). In <em>Evolution and Environment</em>. Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1995.
<br>
<em>Memoirs of a Revolutionist</em> (1899). New York: Dover, 1971.
<br>
<em>Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution</em> (1902). Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1989.
<br>
âThe Revolution in Russiaâ (1905). **Selected Writings on Anarchism and Revolution**. Ed. M. Miller. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1973. Also at http://
<br>
robertgraham.wordpress.com.
<br>
âThe Spirit of Revoltâ (1880). **Kropotkinâs Revolutionary Pamphlets**. Ed. R.N. Baldwin. New York: Dover, 1970.
Leier, Mark. **Bakunin: The Creative Passion**. New York: Thomas Dunne, 2006.
Levy, Reuben. **The Social Structure of Islam**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1957.
Malatesta, Errico. âThe Occupation of the Factoriesâ (1920). **Life and Ideas**. London: Freedom Press, 1965.
<em>Manifesto of the Anarchists</em>. Lyon, 1883. Robert Grahamâs Anarchism Weblog: [[https://robertgraham.wordpress.com][robertgraham.wordpress.com]].
Marshall, Peter. **Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism**. London: Harper Perennial, 2008.
Marx, Karl. **Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume 1** (1867). Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976.
<br>
âFor a Ruthless Criticism of Everything Existingâ (1843). **The Marx-Engels Reader**. 2nd Ed. Ed. Robert C. Tucker. New York: Norton, 1972.
<br>
<em>The Holy Family</em> (1845). <em>Selected Writings</em>. Ed. D. McLellan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.
<br>
<em>Manifesto of the Communist Party</em> (1848). <em>The Marx-Engels Reader</em>.
<br>
<em>The Poverty of Philosophy</em> (1847). New York: International Publishers, 1963.
Nacht, Siegfried (Arnold Roller). **The Social General Strike**. Chicago, 1905. [[http://libertarian-labyrinth.org/archive/The_Social_General_Strike][libertarian-labyrinth.org]].
Nettlau, Max. **A Short History of Anarchism**. London: Freedom Press, 1996.
Pateman, Carole. **The Problem of Political Obligation**. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1985.
Paterson, R.W.K. **The Nihilistic Egoist: Max Stirner**. London: Oxford University Press,
<br>
1971.
Peirats, José. **Anarchists in the Spanish Revolution** (1964). Detroit: Black & Red, 1977.
Perry, Richard. **The Bonnot Gang**. London: Rebel Press, 1987.
Popper, Karl. **The Poverty of Historicism**. London: Routledge, 1957.
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph. **Confessions of a Revolutionary** (1849). Selected Writings. Ed. S. Edwards. New York: Anchor Books, 1969.
Read, Herbert. **Education Through Art**. London: Faber & Faber, 1943.
Reich, Wilhelm. **The Mass Psychology of Fascism** (1933). New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1970.
Richards, Vernon. **Lessons of the Spanish Revolution (1936â1939)**. London: Freedom Press, 1972.
Rothbard, Murray. Introduction to Ătienne de la BoĂ©tie, **The Discourse on Voluntary** **Servitude**. Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1975.
Sahlins, Marshall. **Stone Age Economics**. London: Tavistock Publications, 1974.
Scalapino, R. & Yu, G.T. **The Chinese Anarchist Movement**. Berkeley: Center for Chinese Studies, 1961.
Serge, Victor. **Year One of the Russian Revolution** (1930). New International. Vol. XV, No. 2. February 1949.
Sonn, Richard D. **Anarchism and Cultural Politics in Fin-de-Siecle France**. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1989.
Stafford, David. **From Anarchism to Reformism: A Study of the Political Activities of** **Paul Brousse, 1870â90**. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1971.
Taylor, Michael. **Community, Anarchy and Liberty**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Tucker, Benjamin. âState Socialism and Anarchismâ (1888). **The Anarchist Reader**. Ed. G. Woodcock.
Turcato, Davide. âMaking Sense of Anarchism.â Introduction. **Anarchism: A** **Documentary History of Libertarian Ideas, Volume Two**. Montreal: Black Rose Books, 2009.
Vasco, Neno. âAnarchosyndicalism and Anarchist Communism.â **The Anarchist Conception of Syndicalism** (1920). Robert Grahamâs Anarchism Weblog: [[https://robertgraham.wordpress.com][robertgraham.wordpress.com]].
Voline. âThe Peopleâ (1917). **The Anarchists in the Russian Revolution**. Ed. P. Avrich.
<br>
<em>The Unknown Revolution</em> (1947). Detroit: Black & Red, 1974.
Walter, Nicolas. **The Anarchist Past and Other Essays**. Nottingham: Five Leaves Publications, 2007.
Ward, Colin. **Anarchy in Action.** New York: Harper, 1973.
<br>
<em>Housing: An Anarchist Approach</em>. London: Freedom Press, 1983.
Watson, David. **Against the Megamachine**. Brooklyn: Autonomedia.
Wilde, Oscar. **The Soul of Man Under Socialism** (1891). Chicago: Charles H. Kerr, 1984.
Woodcock, George. **The Anarchist Reader**. Fontana, 1977. Editor.
</biblio>