💾 Archived View for schinkel.bevuta.com › files › convivial-tools.txt captured on 2023-11-14 at 07:52:03.

View Raw

More Information

⬅️ Previous capture (2023-11-04)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Tools for Conviviality - Ivan Illich

  • Acknowledgments
  • Introduction

 1. Two Watersheds
 2. Convivial Reconstruction
 3. The Multiple Balance
     1. Biological Degradation
     2. Radical Monopoly
     3. Overprogramming
     4. Polarization
     5. Obsolescence
     6. Frustration
 4. Recovery
     1. The Demythologization of Science
     2. The Rediscovery of Language
     3. The Recovery of Legal Procedure
 5. Political Inversion
     1. Myths and Majorities
     2. From Breakdown to Chaos
     3. Insight into Crisis
     4. Sudden Change

Acknowledgments

The multidimensional analysis of ceilings for industrial growth was first
formulated in a Spanish document co-authored by Valentina Borremans and myself
and submitted as a guideline for a meeting of two dozen Chilean socialists and
other Latin Americans at CIDOC (the Center for Intercultural Documentation) in
Cuernavaca, Mexico. The next version was presented at the Zeno Symposium
organized by Professor Richard Wollheim in Cyprus. It was published in Esprit,
Paris, March 1972, with criticisms by Th. Adam, Pierre Caussat, J. P.
Chevenement, Paul Fraisse, Yves Goussault, Pierre Kende, J. W. Lapierre, Michel
Panoff, Henri Pequignot, Jean Marie Domenach, and Paul Thibaud. A third version
served me and my deceased friend Greer Taylor as the basis for our
participation in the Canadian Conference on the Law in January 1972 in Ottawa.
Comments by David Weisstub, Nils Christie, Allen M. Linden, J. G. Castel, H. w.
Arthurs, José Antonio Viera-Gallo, J. C. Smith, and Bonaventura de Sousa
Santos, and other critical papers by jurists, will be published in mid-1973 in
Toronto. During the summer of 1972, participants in my CIDOC seminar
contributed very helpful papers. I’m especially grateful for the assistance of
John Bradley, John Brewer, José Maria and Veronica Bulnes, Martin Cohen, Irene
Curbelo de Diaz, Dennis Detzel, Joseph Fitzpatrick, Amnon Goldworth, Conrad
Johnson, Hartmut von Hentig, John MacKnight, Michael Maccoby, Leslie Marcus,
Francisco Mir6 Quesada, Marie-Noëlle Monteil, William Ophuls, Marta H. Reed,
Everett Reimer, Francisco Varela, Etienne Verne, Jacques Vidal and German
Zabala. Dennis Sullivan has patiently and critically assisted me in editing the
final version. After I had delivered this manuscript to the publisher, I
received valuable suggestions from J.P. Naik and his friends in India. These
have seeped into the text to the extent this can happen in the correction of
proofs. Second only to Valentina Borremans and Greer Taylor, Heinz von
Foerster, Erich Fromm, Hermann Schwember and AbrahĂ n Diaz Gonzales have exerted
the most decisive influence on the formulation of my ideas.

Introduction

During the next several years I intend to work on an epilogue to the industrial
age. I want to trace the changes in language, myth, ritual, and law which took
place in the current epoch of packaging and of schooling. I want to describe
the fading monopoly of the industrial mode of production and the vanishing of
the industrially generated professions this mode of production serves.

Above all I want to show that two-thirds of mankind still can avoid passing
through the industrial age, by choosing right now a postindustrial balance in
their mode of production which the hyperindustrial nations will be forced to
adopt as an alternative to chaos. To prepare for this task I submit this essay
for critical comment.

In its present form this book is the result of conversations at CIDOC in
Cuernavaca during the summer of 1972. Participants in my seminar will recognize
their ideas, and often their words. I ask my collaborators to accept my sincere
thanks, especially for their written contributions.

This essay has become too long to appear as an article and too intricate to be
read in several installments. It is a progress report. I respectfully thank
Ruth Nanda Anshen for issuing this tract as a volume, in World Perspectives,
published by Harper & Row.

For several years at CIDOC in Cuernavaca we have conducted critical research on
the monopoly of the industrial mode of production and have tried to define
conceptually alternative modes that would fit a postindustrial age. During tine
late sixties this research centered on educational devices. By 1970 we had
found that:

 1. Universal education through compulsory schooling is not possible.
 2. Alternative devices for the production and marketing of mass education are
    technically more feasible and ethically less tolerable than compulsory
    graded schools. Such new educational arrangements are now on the verge of
    replacing traditional school systems in rich and in poor countries. They
    are potentially more effective in the conditioning of job-holders and
    consumers in an industrial economy. They are therefore more attractive for
    the management of present societies, more seductive for the people, and
    insidiously destructive of fundamental values.
 3. A society committed to high levels of shared learning and critical personal
    intercourse must set pedagogical limits on industrial growth.

I have published the results of this research in a previous volume of World
Perspectives, entitled Deschooling Society. I clarified some of the points left
ill defined in that book by writing an article published in the Saturday Review
of April 19, 1971.

Our analysis of schooling has led us to recognize the mass production of
education as a paradigm for other industrial enterprises, each producing a
service commodity, each organized as a public utility, and each defining its
output as a basic necessity. At first our attention was drawn to the compulsory
insurance of professional health care, and to systems of public transport,
which tend to become compulsory once traffic rolls above a certain speed. We
found that the industrialization of any service agency leads to destructive
side effects analogous to the unwanted secondary results well known from the
overproduction of goods. we had to face a set of limits to growth in the
service sector Of any society as inescapable as the limits inherent in the
industrial production of artifacts. we concluded that a set of limits to
industrial growth is well formulated only if these limits apply both to goods
and to services which are produced in an industrial mode. So we set out to
clarify these limits.

I here submit the concept of a multidimensional balance of human life which can
serve as a framework for evaluating man’s relation to his tools. In each of
several dimensions of this balance it is possible to identify a natural scale.
When an enterprise grows beyond a certain point on this scale, it first
frustrates the end for which it was originally designed, and then rapidly
becomes a threat to society itself. These scales must be identified and the
parameters of human endeavors within which human life remains viable must be
explored.

Society can be destroyed when further growth of mass production renders the
milieu hostile, when it extinguishes the free use of the natural abilities of
society’s members, when it isolates people from each other and locks them into
a man-made shell, when it undermines the texture of community by promoting
extreme social polarization and splintering specialization, or when cancerous
acceleration enforces social change at a rate that rules out legal, cultural,
and political precedents as formal guidelines to present behavior. Corporate
endeavors which thus threaten society cannot be tolerated. At this point it
becomes irrelevant whether an enterprise is nominally owned by individuals,
corporations, or the slate, because no form of management can make such
fundamental destruction serve a social purpose.

Our present ideologies are useful to clarify the contradictions which appear in
a society which relies on the capitalist control of industrial production; they
do not, however, provide the necessary framework for analyzing the crisis in
the industrial mode of production itself. I hope that one day a general theory
of industrialization will be stated with precision, that it will be formulated
in terms compelling enough to withstand the test of criticism. Its concepts
ought to provide a common language for people in opposing parties who need to
engage in the assessment of social programs or technologies, and who want to
restrain the power of man’s tools when they tend to overwhelm man and his
goals. Such a theory should help people invert the present structure of major
institutions. I hope that this essay will enhance the formulation of such a
theory.

It is now difficult to imagine a modern society in which industrial growth is
balanced and kept in check by several complementary, distinct, and equally
scientific modes of production. Our vision of the possible and the feasible is
so restricted by industrial expectations that any alternative to more mass
production sounds like a return to past oppression or like a Utopian design for
noble savages. In fact, however, the vision of new possibilities requires only
the recognition that scientific discoveries can be useful in at least two
opposite ways. The first leads to specialization of functions,
institutionalization of values and centralization of power and turns people
into the accessories of bureaucracies or machines. The second enlarges the
range of each person’s competence, control, and initiative, limited only by
other individuals’ claims to an equal range of power and freedom.

To formulate a theory about a future society both very modern and not dominated
by industry, it will be necessary to recognize natural scales and limits. We
must come to admit that only within limits can machines take the place of
slaves; beyond these limits they lead to a new kind of serfdom. Only within
limits can education fit people into a man-made environment: beyond these
limits lies the universal schoolhouse, hospital ward, or prison. Only within
limits ought politics to be concerned with the distribution of maximum
industrial outputs, rather than with equal inputs of either energy or
information. Once these limits are recognized, it becomes possible to
articulate the triadic relationship between persons, tools, and a new
collectivity. Such a society, in which modern technologies serve politically
interrelated individuals rather than managers, I will call “convivial.”

After many doubts, and against the advice of friends whom I respect, I have
chosen “convivial” as a technical term to designate a modern society of
responsibly limited tools. In part this choice was conditioned by the desire to
continue a discourse which had started with its Spanish cognate. The French
cognate has been given technical meaning (for the kitchen) by Brillat-Savarin
in his Physiology of Taste: Meditations on Transcendental Gastronomy. This
specialized use of the term in French might explain why it has already proven
effective in the unmistakably different and equally specialized context in
which it will appear in this essay. I am aware that in English “convivial” now
seeks the company of tipsy jollyness, which is distinct from that indicated by
the OED and opposite to the austere meaning of modern “eutrapelia,” which I
intend. By applying the term “convivial” to tools rather than to people, I hope
to forestall confusion.

“Austerity,” which says something about people, has also been degraded and has
acquired a bitter taste, while for Aristotle or Aquinas it marked the
foundation of friendship. In the Summa Theologica, II, II, in the 186th
question, article 5, Thomas deals with disciplined and creative playfulness. In
his third response he defines “austerity” as a virtue which does not exclude
all enjoyments, but only those which are distracting from or destructive of
personal relatedness. For Thomas “austerity” is a complementary part of a more
embracing virtue, which he calls friendship or joyfulness. It is the fruit of
an apprehension that things or tools could destroy rather than enhance
eutrapelia (or graceful playfulness) in personal relations. [Hugo v. Rahner,
Man at Play, New York, 1972.]

Two Watersheds

The year 1913 marks a watershed in the history of modern medicine. Around that
year a patient began to have more than a fifty-fifty chance that a graduate of
a medical school would provide him with a specifically effective treatment (if,
of course, he was suffering from one of the standard diseases recognized by the
medical science of the time). Many shamans and herb doctors familiar with local
diseases and remedies and trusted by their clients had always had equal or
better results.

Since then medicine has gone on to define what constitutes disease and its
treatment. The Westernized public learned to demand effective medical practice
as defined by the progress of medical science. For the first time in history
doctors could measure their efficiency against scales which they themselves had
devised. This progress was due to a new perspective of the origins of some
ancient scourges; water could be purified and infant mortality lowered; rat
control could disarm the plague; treponemas could be made visible under the
microscope and Salvarsan could eliminate them with statistically defined risks
of poisoning the patient; syphilis could be avoided, or recognized and cured by
rather simple procedures; diabetes could be diagnosed and self-treatment with
insulin could prolong the life of the patient. Paradoxically, the simpler the
tools became, the more the medical profession insisted on a monopoly of their
application, the longer became the training demanded before a medicine man was
initiated into the legitimate use of the simplest tool, and the more the entire
population felt dependent on the doctor. Hygiene turned from being a virtue
into a professionally organized ritual at the altar of a science.

Infant mortality was lowered, common forms of infection were prevented or
treated, some forms of crisis intervention became quite effective. The
spectacular decline in mortality and morbidity was due to changes in
sanitation, agriculture, marketing, and general attitudes toward life. But
though these changes were sometimes influenced by the attention that engineers
paid to new facts discovered by medical science, they could only occasionally
be ascribed to the intervention of doctors.

Indirectly, industrialization profited from the new effectiveness attributed to
medicine; work attendance was raised, and with it the claim to efficiency on
the job. The destructiveness of new tools was hidden from public view by new
techniques of providing spectacular treatments for those who fell victims to
industrial violence such as the speed of cars, tension on the job, and poisons
in the environment.

The sickening side effects of modern medicine became obvious after World War
II, but doctors needed time to diagnose drug resistant microbes or genetic
damage caused by prenatal X-rays as new epidemics. The claim made by George
Bernard Shaw a generation earlier, that doctors had ceased to be healers and
were assuming control over the patient’s entire life, could still be regarded
as a caricature. Only in the mid-fifties did it become evident that medicine
had passed a second watershed and had itself created new kinds of disease.

Foremost among iatrogenic (doctor-induced) diseases was the pretense of doctors
that they provided their clients with superior health. First, social planners
and doctors became its victims. Soon this epidemic aberration spread to society
at large. Then, during the last fifteen years, professional medicine became a
major threat to health. Huge amounts of money were spent to stem immeasurable
damage caused by medical treatments. The cost of healing was dwarfed by the
cost of extending sick life; more people survived longer months with their
lives hanging on a plastic tube, imprisoned in iron lungs, or hooked onto
kidney machines. New sickness was defined and institutionalized; the cost of
enabling people to survive in unhealthy cities and in sickening jobs
sky-rocketed. The monopoly of the medical profession was extended over an
increasing range of everyday occurrences in every man’s life.

The exclusion of mothers, aunts, and other nonprofessionals from the care of
their pregnant, abnormal, hurt, sick, or dying relatives and friends resulted
in new demands for medical services at a much faster rate than the medical
establishment could deliver. As the value of services rose, it became almost
impossible for people to care. Simultaneously, more conditions were defined as
needing treatment by creating new specializations or paraprofessions to keep
the tools under the control of the guild.

At the time of the second watershed, preservation of the sick life of medically
dependent people in an unhealthy environment became the principal business of
the medical profession. Costly prevention and costly treatment became
increasingly the privilege of those individuals who through previous
consumption of medical services had established a claim to more of it. Access
to specialists, prestige hospitals, and life-machines goes preferentially to
those people who live in large cities, where the cost of basic disease
prevention, as of water treatment and pollution control, is already
exceptionally high. The higher the per capita cost of prevention, the higher,
paradoxically, became the per capita cost of treatment. The prior consumption
of costly prevention and treatment establishes a claim for even more
extraordinary care. Like the modern school system, hospital-based health care
fits the principle that those who have will receive even more and those who
have not will be taken for the little that they have. In schooling this means
that high consumers of education will get postdoctoral grants, while dropouts
learn that they have failed. In medicine the same principle assures that
suffering will increase with increased medical care; the rich will be given
more treatment for iatrogenic diseases and the poor will just suffer from them.

After this second turning point, the unwanted hygienic by-products of medicine
began to affect entire populations rather than just individual men. In rich
countries medicine began to sustain the middle-aged until they became decrepit
and needed more doctors and increasingly complex medical tools. In poor
countries, thanks to modern medicine, a larger percentage of children began to
survive into adolescence and more women survived more pregnancies. Populations
increased beyond the capacities of their environments and the restraints and
efficiencies of their cultures to nurture them. Western doctors abused drugs
for the treatment of diseases with which native populations had learned to
live. As a result they bred new strains of disease with which modern treatment,
natural immunity, and traditional culture could not cope. On a world-wide
scale, but particularly in the U.S.A., medical care concentrated on breeding a
human stock that was fit only for domesticated life within an increasingly more
costly, man-made, scientifically controlled environment. One of the main
speakers at the 1970 AMA convention exhorted her pediatric colleagues to
consider each newborn baby as a patient until the child could be certified as
healthy. Hospital-born, formula-fed, antibiotic-stuffed children thus grow into
adults who can breathe the air, eat the food, and survive the lifelessness of a
modern city, who will breed and raise at almost any cost a generation even more
dependent on medicine.

Bureaucratic medicine spread over the entire world. In 1968, after twenty years
of Mao’s regime, the Medical College of Shanghai had to conclude that it was
engaged in the training of “so-called first-rate doctors ... who ignore five
million peasants and serve only minorities in cities. They create large
expenses for routine laboratory examinations . . . Describe huge amounts of
antibiotics unnecessarily . . . and in the absence of hospital or laboratory
facilities have to limit themselves to explaining the mechanisms of the disease
to people for whom they cannot do anything, and to whom this explanation is
irrelevant.” In China this recognition led to a major institutional inversion.
Today, the same college reports that one million health workers have reached
acceptable levels of competence. These health workers are laymen who in periods
of low agricultural manpower needs have attended short courses, starting with
the dissection of pigs, gone on to the performance of routine lab tests, the
study of the elements of bacteriology, pathology, clinical medicine, hygiene,
and acupuncture, and continued in apprenticeship with doctors or previously
trained colleagues. These “barefoot doctors” remain at their work places but
are excused occasionally when fellow workers require their assistance. They
have responsibility for environmental sanitation, for health education,
immunization, first aid, primary medical care, post illness follow-up, as well
as for gynecological assistance, birth control, and abortion education. Ten
years after the second watershed of Western medicine had been acknowledged,
China intends to have one fully competent health worker for every hundred
people. China has proved that a sudden inversion of a major institution is
possible. It remains to be seen if this deprofessionalization can be sustained
against the overweening ideology of unlimited progress and pressures from
classical doctors to incorporate their barefoot homonym as part-time
professionals on the bottom rung of a medical hierarchy.

In the West during the sixties dissatisfaction with medicine grew in proportion
to its cost, reaching the greatest intensity in the U.S.A. Rich foreigners
flocked to the medical centers of Boston, Houston, and Denver to seek exotic
repair jobs, while the infant mortality of the U.S. poor remained comparable to
that in some tropical countries of Africa and Asia. Only the very rich in the
United States can now afford what all people in poor countries have: personal
attention around the deathbed. An American can now spend in two days of private
nursing the median yearly cash income of the world’s population.

Instead of exposing the systemic disorder, however, only the symptoms of “sick”
medicine are now publicly indicted in the United States. Spokesmen for the poor
object to the capitalist prejudices of the AMA and the income of doctors.
Community leaders object to the lack of community control over the delivery
systems of professional health maintenance or of sick care, believing that
laymen on hospital boards can harness professional medics. Black spokesmen
object to the concentration of research grants on the types of disease which
tend to strike the white, elderly, overfed foundation official who approves
them. They ask for research on sickle-cell anemia, which strikes only the
black. The general voter hopes that the end of the war in Vietnam will make
more funds available for an increase of medical production. This general
concern with symptoms, however, distracts attention from the malignant
expansion of institutional health care which is at the root of the rising costs
and demands and the decline in wellbeing.

The crisis of medicine lies on a much deeper level than its symptoms reveal and
is consistent with the present crisis of all industrial institutions. It
results from the development of a professional complex supported and exhorted
by society to provide increasingly “better” health, and from the willingness of
clients to serve as guinea pigs in this vain experiment. People have lost the
right to declare themselves sick; society now accepts their claims to sickness
only after certification by medical bureaucrats.

It is not strictly necessary to this argument to accept 1913 and 1955 as the
two watershed years in order to understand that early in the century medical
practice emerged into an era of scientific verification of its results. And
later medical science itself became an alibi for the obvious damage caused by
the medical professional. At the first watershed the desirable effects of new
scientific discoveries were easily measured and verified. Germ-free water
reduced infant mortality related to diarrhea, aspirin reduced the pain of
rheumatism, and malaria could be controlled by quinine. Some traditional cures
were recognized as quackery, but, more importantly, the use of some simple
habits and tools spread widely. People began to understand the relationship
between health and a balanced diet, fresh air, calisthenics, pore water and
soap. New devices ranging from toothbrushes to Band-Aids and condoms became
widely available. The positive contribution of modern medicine to individual
health during the early part of the twentieth century can hardly be questioned.

But then medicine began to approach the second watershed. Every year medical
science reported a new breakthrough. Practitioners of new specialties
rehabilitated some individuals suffering from rare diseases. The practice of
medicine became centered on the performance of hospital-based staffs. Trust in
miracle cures obliterated good sense and traditional wisdom on healing and
health care. The irresponsible use of drugs spread from doctors to the general
public. The second watershed was approached when the marginal utility of
further professionalization declined, at least insofar as it can be expressed
in terms of the physical well-being of the largest number of people. The second
watershed was superseded when the marginal disutility increased as further
monopoly by the medical establishment became an indicator of more suffering for
larger numbers of people. After the passage of this second watershed, medicine
still claimed continued progress, as measured by the new landmarks doctors set
for them-selves and then reached: both predictable discoveries and costs. For
instance, a few patients survived longer with transplants of various organs. On
the other hand, the total social cost exacted by medicine ceased to be
measurable in conventional terms. Society can have no quantitative standards by
which to add up the negative value of illusion, social control, prolonged
suffering, loneliness, genetic deterioration, and frustration produced by
medical treatment.

Other industrial institutions have passed through the same two watersheds. This
is certainly true for the major social agencies that have been reorganized
according to scientific criteria during the last 150 years. Education, the
mails, social work, transportation, and even civil engineering have followed
this evolution. At first, new knowledge is applied to the solution of a clearly
stated problem and scientific measuring sticks are applied to account for the
new efficiency. But at a second point, the progress demonstrated in a previous
achievement is used as a rationale for the exploitation of society as a whole
in the service of a value which is determined and constantly revised by an
element of society, by one of its self-certifying professional Ă©lites.

In the case of transportation it has taken almost a century to pass from an era
served by motorized vehicles to the era in which society has been reduced to
virtual enslavement to the car. During the American Civil War steam power on
wheels became effective. The new economy in transportation enabled many people
to travel by rail at the speed of a royal coach, and to do so with a comfort
kings had not dared dream of. Gradually, desirable locomotion was associated
and finally identified with high vehicular speeds. But when transportation had
passed through its second watershed, vehicles had created more distances than
they helped to bridge; more time was used by the entire society for the sake of
traffic than was “saved."

It is sufficient to recognize the existence of these two watersheds in order to
gain a fresh perspective on our present social crisis. In one decade several
major institutions have moved jointly over their second watershed. Schools are
losing their claim to be effective tools to provide education; cars have ceased
to be effective tools for mass transportation; the assembly line has ceased to
be an acceptable mode of production.

The characteristic reaction of the sixties to the growing frustration was
further technological and bureaucratic escalation. Self-defeating escalation of
power became the core-ritual practiced in highly industrialized nations. In
this context the Vietnam war is both revealing and concealing. It makes this
ritual visible for the entire world in a narrow theatre of war, yet it also
distracts attention from the same ritual being played out in many so-called
peaceful arenas. The conduct of the war proves that a convivial army limited to
bicycle speeds is served by the opponent’s escalation of anonymous power. And
yet many Americans argue that the resources squandered on the war in the Far
East could be used effectively to overwhelm poverty at home. Others are anxious
to use the $20 billion the war now costs for increasing international
development assistance from its present low of $2 billion. They fail to grasp
the underlying institutional structure common to a peaceful war on poverty and
a bloody war on dissidence. Both escalate what they are meant to eliminate.

While evidence shows that more of the same leads to utter defeat, nothing less
than more and more seems worthwhile in a society infected by the growth mania.
The desperate plea is not only for more bombs and more police, more medical
examinations and more teachers, but also for more information and research. The
editor-in-chief of the Bulletin of Atomic Scientists claims that most of our
present problems are the result of recently acquired knowledge badly applied,
and concludes that the only remedy for the mess created by this information is
more of it. It has become fashionable to say that where science and technology
have created problems, it is only more scientific understanding and better
technology that can carry us past them.

The cure for bad management is more management. The cure for specialized
research is more costly interdisciplinary research, just as the cure for
polluted rivers is more costly nonpolluting detergents. The pooling of stores
of information, the building up of a knowledge stock, the attempt to overwhelm
present problems by the introduction of more science is the ultimate attempt to
solve a crisis by escalation.

Convivial Reconstruction

The symptoms of accelerated crisis are widely recognized. Multiple attempts
have been made to explain them. I believe that this crisis is rooted in a major
twofold experiment which has failed, and I claim that the resolution of the
crisis begins with a recognition of the failure. For a hundred years we have
tried to make machines work for men and to school men for life in their
service. Now it turns out that machines do not “work” and that people cannot be
schooled for a life at the service of machines. The hypothesis on which the
experiment was built must now be discarded. The hypothesis was that machines
can replace slaves. The evidence shows that, used for this purpose, machines
enslave men. Neither a dictatorial proletariat nor a leisure mass can escape
the dominion of constantly expanding industrial tools.

The crisis can be solved only if we learn to invert the present deep structure
of tools; if we give people tools that guarantee their right to work with high,
independent efficiency, thus simultaneously eliminating the need for either
slaves or masters and enhancing each person’s range of freedom. People need new
tools to work with rather than tools that “work” for them. They need technology
to make the most of the energy and imagination each has, rather than more
well-programmed energy slaves.

I believe that society must be reconstructed to enlarge the contribution of
autonomous individuals and primary groups to the total effectiveness of a new
system of production designed to satisfy the human needs which it also
determines. In fact, the institutions of industrial society do just the
opposite. As the power of machines increases, the role of persons more and more
decreases to that of mere consumers.

Individuals need tools to move and to dwell. They need remedies for their
diseases and means to communicate with one another. People cannot make all
these things for themselves. They depend on being supplied with objects and
services which vary from culture to culture. Some people depend on the supply
of food and others on the supply of ball bearings.

People need not only to obtain things, they need above all the freedom to make
things among which they can live, to give shape to them according to their own
tastes, and to put them to use in caring for and about others. Prisoners in
rich countries often have access to more things and services than members of
their families, but they have no say in how things are to be made and cannot
decide what to do with them. Their punishment consists in being deprived of
what I shall call “conviviality.” They are degraded to the status of mere
consumers.

I choose the term “conviviality” to designate the opposite of industrial
productivity. I intend it to mean autonomous and creative intercourse among
persons, and the intercourse of persons with their environment; and this in
contrast with the conditioned response of persons to the demands made upon them
by others, and by a man-made environment. I consider conviviality to be
individual freedom realized in personal interdependence and, as such, an
intrinsic ethical value. I believe that, in any society, as conviviality is
reduced below a certain level, no amount of industrial productivity can
effectively satisfy the needs it creates among society’s members.

Present institutional purposes, which hallow industrial productivity at the
expense of convivial effectiveness, are a major factor in the amorphousness and
meaninglessness that plague contemporary society. The increasing demand for
products has come to define society’s process. I will suggest how this present
trend can be reversed and how modern science and technology can be used to
endow human activity with unprecedented effectiveness. This reversal would
permit the evolution of a life style and of a political system which give
priority to the protection, the maximum use, and the enjoyment of the one
resource that is almost equally distributed among all people: personal energy
under personal control. I will argue that we can no longer live and work
effectively without public controls over tools and institutions that curtail or
negate any person’s right to the creative use of his or her energy. For this
purpose we need procedures to ensure that controls over the tools of society
are established and governed by political process rather than by decisions by
experts.

The transition to socialism cannot be effected without an inversion of our
present institutions and the substitution of convivial for industrial tools. At
the same time, the retooling of society will remain a pious dream unless the
ideals of socialist justice prevail. I believe that the present crisis of our
major institutions ought to be welcomed as a crisis of revolutionary liberation
because our present institutions abridge basic human freedom for the sake of
providing people with more institutional outputs. This world-wide crisis of
world-wide institutions can lead to a new consciousness about the nature of
tools and to majority action for their control. If tools are not controlled
politically, they will be managed in a belated technocratic response to
disaster. Freedom and dignity will continue to dissolve into an unprecedented
enslavement of man to his tools.

As an alternative to technocratic disaster, I propose the vision of a convivial
society. A convivial society would be the result of social arrangements that
guarantee for each member the most ample and free access to the tools of the
community and limit this freedom only in favor of another member’s equal
freedom.

At present people tend to relinquish the task of envisaging the future to a
professional Ă©lite. They transfer power to politicians who promise to build up
the machinery to deliver this future. They accept a growing range of power
levels in society when inequality is needed to maintain high outputs. Political
institutions themselves become draft mechanisms to press people into complicity
with output goals. What is right comes to be subordinated to what is good for
institutions. Justice is debased to mean the equal distribution of
institutional wares.

The individual’s autonomy is intolerably reduced by a society that defines the
maximum satisfaction of the maximum number as the largest consumption of
industrial goods. Alternate political arrangements would have the purpose of
permitting all people to define the images of their own future. New politics
would aim principally to exclude the design of artifacts and rules that are
obstacles to the exercise of this personal freedom. Such politics would limit
the scope of tools as demanded by the protection of three values: survival,
justice, and self-defined work. I take these values to be fundamental to any
convivial society, however different one such society might be from another in
practice, institutions, or rationale.

Each of these three values imposes its own limits on tools. The conditions for
survival are necessary but not sufficient to ensure justice; people can survive
in prison. The conditions for the just distribution of industrial outputs are
necessary, but not sufficient to promote convivial production. People can be
equally enslaved by their tools. The conditions for convivial work are
structural arrangements that make possible the just distribution of
unprecedented power. A postindustrial society must and can be so constructed
that no one person’s ability to express him- or herself in work will require as
a condition the enforced labor or the enforced learning or the enforced
consumption of another.

In an age of scientific technology, the convivial structure of tools is a
necessity for survival in full justice which is both distributive and
participatory. This is so because science has opened new energy sources.
Competition for inputs must lead to destruction, while their central control in
the hands of a Leviathan would sacrifice equal control over inputs to the
semblance of an equal distribution of outputs. Rationally designed convivial
tools have become the basis for participatory justice.

But this does not mean that the transition from our present to a convivial mode
of production can be accomplished without serious threats to the survival of
many people. At present the relationship between people and their tools is
suicidally distorted. The survival of Pakistanis depends on Canadian grain, and
the survival of New Yorkers on world-wide exploitation of natural resources.
The birth pangs of a convivial world society will inevitably be violently
painful for hungry Indians and for helpless New Yorkers. I will later argue
that the transition from the present mode of production, which is
Overwhelmingly industrial, toward conviviality may start suddenly. But for the
sake of the survival of many people it will be desirable that the transition
does not happen all at once. I argue that survival in justice is possible only
at the cost of those sacrifices implicit in the adoption of a convivial mode of
production and the universal renunciation of unlimited progeny, affluence, and
power on the part of both individuals and groups. This price cannot be extorted
by some despotic Leviathan, nor elicited by social engineering. People will
rediscover the value of joyful sobriety and liberating austerity only if they
relearn to depend on each other rather than on energy slaves. The price for a
convivial society will be paid only as the result of a political process which
reflects and promotes the society-wide inversion of present industrial
consciousness. This political process will find its concrete expression not in
some taboo, but in a series of temporary agreements on one or the other
concrete limitation of means, constantly adjusted under the pressure of
conflicting insights and interests.

In this volume I want to offer a methodology by which to recognize means which
have turned into ends. My subject is tools and not intentions. The choice of
this subject makes it impossible to undertake several related, relevant, and
tempting tasks because:

 1. It would not serve my purpose to describe in detail any fictional community
    of the future. I want to provide guidelines for action, not for fantasy. A
    modern society, bounded for convivial living, could generate a new
    flowering of surprises far beyond anyone’s imagination and hope. I am not
    proposing a Utopia, but a procedure that provides each community with the
    choice of its unique social arrangements.

 2. I do not want to contribute to an engineering manual for the design of
    convivial institutions or tools, nor do I want to engage in a sales
    campaign for what would be obviously a better technology. My purpose is to
    lay down criteria by which the manipulation of people for the sake of their
    tools can be immediately recognized, and thus to exclude those artifacts
    and institutions which inevitably extinguish a convivial life style.
    Paradoxically, a society of simple tools that allows men to achieve
    purposes with energy fully under their own control is now difficult to
    imagine. Our imaginations have been industrially deformed to conceive only
    what can be molded into an engineered system of social habits that fit the
    logic of large-scale production. We have almost lost the ability to frame
    in fancy a world in which sound and shared reasoning sets limits to
    everybody’s power to interfere with anybody’s equal power to shape the
    world.

    The present world is divided into those who do not have enough and those
    who have more than enough, those who are pushed off the road by cars and
    those who drive them. The have-nots are miserable and the rich anxious to
    get more. A society whose members know what is enough might be poor, but
    its members would be equally free. Men with industrially distorted minds
    cannot grasp the rich texture of personal accomplishments within the range
    of modern though limited tools. There is no room in their imaginations for
    the qualitative change that the acceptance of a stable-state industry would
    mean; a society in which members are free from most of the multiple
    restraints of schedules and therapies now imposed for the sake of growing
    tools. Much less do most of our contemporaries experience the sober joy of
    life in this voluntary though relative poverty which lies within our grasp.

 3. I will focus on the structure of tools, not on the character structure of
    their users. The use of industrial tools stamps in an identical way the
    landscape of cities each having its own history and culture. Highways,
    hospital wards, classrooms, office buildings, apartments, and stores look
    everywhere the same. Identical tools also promote the development of the
    same character types. Policemen in patrol cars or accountants at computers
    look and act alike all over the world, while their poor cousins using
    nightstick or pen are different from region to region. The progressive
    homogenization of personalities and personal relationships cannot be
    stemmed without a retooling of society. Research on the social character
    traits that make retooling difficult or doubtful is complementary to what I
    propose. But I am not postulating the creation of a new man as a condition
    for a new society, nor am I pretending to know how either social character
    or cultures will change. A pluralism of limited tools and of convivial
    commonweals would of necessity encourage a diversity of life styles.

 4. It would distract from the core of my argument if I were to deal with
    political strategies or tactics. With the possible exception of China under
    Mao, no present government could restructure society along convivial lines.
    The managers of our major tools-nations, corporations, parties, structured
    movements, professions-hold power. This power is vested in the maintenance
    of the growth-oriented structures which they manipulate. These managers
    have the power to make major decisions; they can generate new demands for
    the output of their tools and enforce the creation of new social labels to
    fit them. They can even go so far as to limit the output of tools in the
    interest of maximizing benefits. But they have no power to reverse the
    basic structure of the institutional arrangements which they manage.

    The major institutions now optimize the output of large tools for lifeless
    people. Their inversion implies institutions that would foster the use of
    individually accessible tools to support the meaningful and responsible
    deeds of fully awake people. Turning basic institutions upside down and
    inside out is what the adoption of a convivial mode of production would
    require. Such an inversion of society is beyond the managers of present
    institutions.

    Today’s managers form a new class of men, selected for their character,
    competence, and interest-which enable them to both expand the productive
    society and promote the further operant conditioning of their clients. They
    hold and manage power no matter who lives in the illusion that he owns the
    tools. This class of power-holders must be eliminated, but this cannot be
    done by mass slaughter or replacement. The new Ă©lite would only claim more
    legitimacy in the manipulation of the inherited structured power.
    Management can be done away with only by eliminating the machinery that
    makes it necessary and, therefore, the demands for output that give it
    sway. In a convivial society there is little need for replacing the
    chairman of the board.

    In a society in which power-both political and physical-is bounded and
    spread by political decision there is place not only for a new flowering of
    products and characters, but also for a variety in forms of governance.
    Certainly, new tools would provide new options. Convivial tools rule out
    certain levels of power, compulsion, and programming, which are precisely
    those features that now tend to make all governments look more or less
    alike. But the adoption of a convivial mode of production does not of
    itself mean that one specific form of government would be more fitting than
    another, nor does it rule out a world federation, or agreements between
    nation-states, or communes, or many of the most traditional forms of
    governance. I restrict myself to the description of basic structural
    criteria within which the retooling of society can be achieved.

 5. A methodology by which to recognize when corporate tools become destructive
    of society itself requires the recognition of the value of distributory and
    participatory justice. I believe that my succinct statement will be
    sufficient to identify necessary restraints on tools, but it will also
    preclude that in this essay I reach any conclusion about a desirable degree
    of subordination of means to ends.

 6. The economics applicable to a postindustrial and convivial society can
    neither be ignored nor taken for granted. In a society that accepts
    politically defined limits on all types of industrial growth, many accepted
    terms will have to be redefined, but it is certain that in such a society
    inequality will not be excluded. In fact, each individual’s power to make
    effective changes would be greater than in preindustrial or in industrial
    times. Though they would be bounded, common tools would be incomparably
    more efficient than primitive, and more widely distributed than industrial,
    devices. Their products would accrue more to some than to others. The task
    of keeping net transfer of power within bounds requires the use of
    traditional as well as new economic devices. It will be argued that the
    limitation of tools cannot be effected before a corresponding new economic
    theory has been elaborated and has become operational. This is correct. I
    do propose that we use a dimensional analysis to obtain information about
    the major variables which can upset the balance of life, and that we rely
    on political process to identify the significant dimensions which man can
    control. I therefore propose an approach to the relationship between man’s
    ends and his means in which the key units of economics come to signify a
    dimensionless set of factors. Economics useful for the inversion of our
    present institutional structure starts out from politically defined
    limiting criteria. It is on these negative design criteria for
    technological devices that I want to focus attention.

A methodology, by which to recognize the public perversion of tools into
purposes, encounters resistance on the part of people who are used to measuring
what is good in terms of dollars. Plato knew that the bad statesman is he who
believes that the art of measurement is universal, and who jumbles together
what is greater or smaller and what is more fit to the purpose. Our present
attitudes toward production have been formed over the centuries. Increasingly,
institutions have not only shaped our demands but also in the most literal
sense our logic, or sense of proportion. Having come to demand what
institutions can produce, we soon believe that we cannot do without it.

The invention of education is an example of what I mean. We often forget that
education acquired its present sense only recently. It was unknown before the
Reformation, except as that part of early upbringing which is common to
piglets, ducks, and men. It was clearly distinguished from the instruction
needed by the young, and from the study in which some engaged later on in life
and for which a teacher was needed. Voltaire still called it a presumptuous
neologism, used only by pretentious schoolmasters.

The endeavor to put all men through successive stages of enlightenment is
rooted deeply in alchemy, the Great Art of the waning Middle Ages. John Amos
Comenius, a Moravian bishop of the seventeenth century, a self-styled
pansophist and pedagogue, is rightly considered one of the founders of the
modern school. He was among the first to propose seven or twelve grades of
compulsory learning. In his Magna Didactica he described schools as devices to
“teach everybody everything” and outlined a blueprint for the assembly-line
production of knowledge, which according to his method would make education
cheaper and better and make growth into full humanity possible for all. But
Comenius was not only an early theoretician of mass production, he was an
alchemist who adapted the technical language of his craft to describe the art
of rearing children. The alchemist sought to refine base elements by graduating
their spirits through twelve stages of successive enlightenment, so that for
their own and all the world’s benefit they might be transformed into gold. Of
course, alchemists failed no matter how often they tried, but each time their
“science” yielded new reasons for their failure, and they tried again.

The industrial mode of production was first fully rationalized in the
manufacture of a new invisible commodity, called “education.” Pedagogy opened a
new chapter in the history of the Ars Magna Education became the search for an
alchemic process that would bring forth a new type of man who would fit into an
environment created by scientific magic. But no matter how much each generation
spent on its schools, it always turned out that the majority of people were
certified as unfit for higher grades of enlightenment and had to be discarded
as unprepared for the good life in a man-made world.

Not only has the redefinition of learning as schooling made schools seem
necessary, it has also compounded the poverty of the unschooled with
discrimination against the uneducated. People who have climbed up the ladder of
schooling know where they dropped out and how uneducated they are. Once they
accept the authority of an agency to define and measure their level of
knowledge, they easily go on to accept the authority of other agencies to
define for them their level of appropriate health or mobility. It is difficult
for them to identify the structural corruption of our major institutions. Just
as they come to believe in the value of the “knowledge stock” they acquired in
school, so they come to believe that higher speeds save time and that income
levels define well-being or, as an alternative, that the production of more
services rather than more goods increases the quality of life.

The commodity called “education” and the institution called “school” make each
other necessary. The circle can be broken only by a widely shared insight that
the institution has come to define the purpose. Values abstractly stated are
reduced to mechanical processes that enslave men. This serfdom can be broken
only by the joyful self-recognition of the fool who assumes personal
responsibility for his folly.

The institutional definition of values has made it difficult to focus our
attention on the deep structure of social means. It is hard to imagine that the
division of sciences, of labor, and of professions has gone too far. It is
difficult to conceive of higher social effectiveness with lower industrial
efficiency. To recognize the nature of desirable limits to specialization and
output, we must focus our attention on the industrially determined shape of our
expectations. Only then can we recognize that the emergence of a convivial and
pluralist mode of production will follow the limitation of industrial
institutions.

In the past, convivial life for some inevitably demanded the servitude of
others. Labor efficiency was low before the steel ax, the pump, the bicycle,
and the nylon fishing line. Between the High Middle Ages and the Enlightenment,
the alchemic dream misled many otherwise authentic Western humanists. The
illusion prevailed that the machine was a laboratory-made homunculus, and that
it could do our labor instead of slaves. It is now time to correct this mistake
and shake off the illusion that men are born to be slaveholders and that the
only thing wrong in the past was that not all men could be equally so. By
reducing our expectations of machines, however, we must guard against falling
into the equally damaging rejection of all machines as if they were works of
the devil.

A convivial society should be designed to allow all its members the most
autonomous action by means of tools least controlled by others. People feel
joy, as opposed to mere pleasure, to the extent that their activities are
creative; while the growth of tools beyond a certain point increases
regimentation, dependence, exploitation, and impotence. I use the term “tool”
broadly enough to include not only simple hardware such as drills, pots,
syringes, brooms, building elements, or motors, and not just large machines
like cars or power stations; I also include among tools productive institutions
such as factories that produce tangible commodities like corn flakes or
electric current, and productive systems for intangible commodities such as
those which produce “education,” “health,” “knowledge,” or “decisions.” I use
this term because it allows me to subsume into one category all rationally
designed devices, be they artifacts or rules, codes or operators, and to
distinguish all these planned and engineered instrumentalities from other
things such as basic food or implements, which in a given culture are not
deemed to be subject to rationalization. School curricula or marriage laws are
no less purposely shaped social devices than road networks.

Tools are intrinsic to social relationships. An individual relates himself in
action to his society through the use of tools that he actively masters, or by
which he is passively acted upon. To the degree that he masters his tools, he
can invest the world with his meaning; to the degree that he is mastered by his
tools, the shape of the tool determines his own self-image. Convivial tools are
those which give each person who uses them the greatest opportunity to enrich
the environment with the fruits of his or her vision. Industrial tools deny
this possibility to those who use them and they allow their designers to
determine the meaning and expectations of others. Most tools today cannot be
used in a convivial fashion.

Hand tools are those which adapt man’s metabolic energy to a specific task.
They can be multipurpose, like some primitive hammers or good modern pocket
knives, or again they can be highly specific in design such as spindles, looms,
or pedal-driven sewing machines, and dentists’ drills. They can also be complex
such as a transportation system built to get the most in mobility out of human
energy-for instance, a bicycle system composed of a series of man-powered
vehicles, such as pushcarts and three-wheel rickshas, with a corresponding road
system equipped with repair stations and perhaps even covered roadways. Hand
tools are mere transducers of the energy generated by man’s extremities and fed
by the intake of air and of nourishment.

Power tools are moved, at least partially, by energy converted outside the
human body. Some of them act as amplifiers of human energy: the oxen pull the
plow, but man works with the oxen-the result is obtained by pooling the powers
of beast and man. Power saws and motor pulleys are used in the same fashion. On
the other hand, the energy used to steer a jet plane has ceased to be a
significant fraction of its power output. The pilot is reduced to a mere
operator guided by data which a computer digests for him. The machine needs him
for lack of a better computer; or he is in the cockpit because the social
control of unions over airplanes imposes his presence.

Tools foster conviviality to the extent to which they can be easily used, by
anybody, as often or as seldom as desired, for the accomplishment of a purpose
chosen by the user. The use of such tools by one person does not restrain
another from using them equally. They do not require previous certification of
the user. Their existence does not impose any obligation to use them. They
allow the user to express his meaning in action.

Some institutions are structurally convivial tools. The telephone is an
example. Anybody can dial the person of his choice if he can afford a coin. If
untiring computers keep the lines occupied and thereby restrict the number of
personal conversations, this is a misuse by the company of a license given so
that persons can speak. The telephone lets anybody say what he wants to the
person of his choice; he can conduct business, express love, or pick a quarrel.
It is impossible for bureaucrats to define what people say to each other on the
phone, even though they can interfere with-or protect-the privacy of their
exchange.

Most hand tools lend themselves to convivial use unless they are artificially
restricted through some institutional arrangements. They can be restricted by
becoming the monopoly of one profession, as happens with dentist drills through
the requirement of a license and with libraries or laboratories by placing them
within schools. Also, tools can be purposely limited when simple pliers and
screwdrivers are insufficient to repair modern cars. This institutional
monopoly or manipulation usually constitutes an abuse and changes the nature of
the tool as little as the nature of the knife is changed by its abuse for
murder.

In principle the distinction between convivial and manipulatory tools is
independent of the level of technology of the tool. What has been said of the
telephone could be repeated point by point for the mails or for a typical
Mexican market. Each is an institutional arrangement that maximizes liberty,
even though in a broader context it can be abused for purposes of manipulation
and control. The telephone is the result of advanced engineering; the mails
require in principle little technology and considerable organization and
scheduling; the Mexican market runs with minimum planning along customary
patterns.

Any institution that moves toward its second watershed tends to become highly
manipulative. For instance, it costs more to make teaching possible than to
teach. The cost of roles exceeds the cost of production. Increasingly,
components intended for the accomplishment of institutional purposes are
redesigned so that they cannot be used independently. People without cars have
no access to planes) and people without plane tickets have no access to
convention hotels. Alternate tools which are fit to accomplish the same
purposes with fewer claims are pushed off the market. For instance, civilized
correspondence becomes a lost art. During the last several years this barring
of alternatives has usually coincided with the increased power of the tool and
the development of more complex tool systems.

It is possible that not every means of desirable production in a postindustrial
society would fit the criteria of conviviality. It is probable that even in an
overwhelmingly convivial world some communities would choose greater affluence
at the cost of some restrictions on creativity. It is almost certain that in a
period of transition from the present to the future mode of production in
certain countries electricity would not commonly be produced in the backyard.
It is also true that trains must run on tracks and stop on schedule at a
limited number of points. Oceangoing vessels are built for one purpose; if they
were sailing clippers, they might be even more specialized for one route than
are present tankers. Telephone systems are highly determined for the
transmission of messages of a certain band width and must be centrally
administered even if they are limited to the service of only one area. It is a
mistake to believe that all large tools and all centralized production would
have to be excluded from a convivial society. It would equally be a mistake to
demand that for the sake of conviviality the distribution of industrial goods
and services be reduced to the minimum consistent with survival in order to
protect the maximum equal right to self-determined participation. Different
balances between distributive justice and participatory justice can prevail in
societies equally striving for post-industrial conviviality, depending on the
history, political ideals, and physical resources of a community.

What is fundamental to a convivial society is not the total absence of
manipulative institutions and addictive goods and services, but the balance
between those tools which create the specific demands they are specialized to
satisfy and those complementary, enabling tools which foster self-realization.
The first set of tools produces according to abstract plans for men in general;
the other set enhances the ability of people to pursue their own goals in their
unique way.

The criteria by which anticonvivial or manipulative tools are recognized cannot
be used to exclude every tool that meets them. These criteria, however, can be
applied as guidelines for structuring the totality of tools by which a society
desires to define the style and level of its conviviality. A convivial society
does not exclude all schools. It does exclude a school system which has been
perverted into a compulsory tool, denying privileges to the dropout. A
convivial society does not exclude some high-speed intercity transport, as long
as its layout does not in fact impose equally high speeds on all other routes.
Not even television must be ruled out-although it permits very few programmers
and speakers to define what their viewers may see-as long as the over-all
structure of society does not favor the degradation of everyone into a
compulsory voyeur. The criteria of conviviality are to be considered as
guidelines to the continuous process by which a society’s members defend their
liberty, and not as a set of prescriptions which can be mechanically applied.

At present the reverse guideline prevails, even in societies where the producer
is told that he is in the saddle. The socialist planner competes with the
free-market advocate in claiming that a society run on his principles is more
productive. In 1931 Stalin translated “control over the means of production” to
mean the increase of productivity by new methods used to control the producer.
In the midst of the U.S. Depression he launched Russia on an industrial race.
Since then a socialist policy has been considered one which serves the
industrially organized productivity of a socialist country. Stalin’s
reinterpretation of Marxism has since then served as a form of blackmail
against socialists and the left. It remains to be seen if after Mao’s death
China will also trade productive conviviality for institutional productivity.
The Stalinist interpretation of socialism has made it possible for socialists
and capitalists alike to agree on how to measure the level of development a
society has achieved. Societies in which most people depend for most of their
goods and services on the personal whim, kindness, or skill of another are
called “underdeveloped,” while those in which living has been transformed into
a process of ordering from an all-encompassing store catalogue are called
“advanced.” Stalinism makes it possible to interpret as revolutionary whatever
increases the amount of schooling, expands the road systems, or increases the
productivity of extraction and manufacture. To be revolutionary has come to
mean either to champion the nation that lags in production and to make its
members keenly aware of the lag, or to inflame the frantic and frustrated
attempts of underconsuming minorities in rich countries to catch up.

Every aspect of industrial societies has become part of a larval system for
escalating production and increasing the demand necessary to justify the total
social cost. For this reason, criticism of bad management, official dishonesty,
insufficient research, or technological lag distracts public attention from the
one issue that counts: careful analysis of the basic structure of tools as
means. It is equally distracting to suggest that the present frustration is
primarily due to the private ownership of the means of production, and that the
public ownership of these same factories under the tutelage of a planning board
could protect the interest of the majority and lead society to an equally
shared abundance. As long as Ford Motor Company can be condemned simply because
it makes Ford rich, the illusion is bolstered that the same factory could make
the public rich. As long as people believe that the public can profit from
cars, they will not condemn Ford for making cars. The issue at hand is not the
juridical ownership of tools, but rather the discovery of the characteristic of
some tools which make it impossible for anybody to “own” them. The concept of
ownership cannot be applied to a tool that cannot be controlled.

The issue at hand, therefore, is what tools can be controlled in the public
interest. Only secondarily does the question arise whether private control of a
potentially useful tool is in the public interest.

Certain tools are destructive no matter who owns them, whether it be the Mafia,
stockholders, a foreign company, the state, or even a workers’ commune.
Networks of multilane highways, long. range, wide-band-width transmitters,
strip mines, or compulsory school systems are such tools. Destructive tools
must inevitably increase regimentation, dependence, exploitation, or impotence,
and rob not only the rich but also the poor of conviviality, which is the
primary treasure in many so-called “underdeveloped” areas.

It has become difficult for contemporary man to imagine development and
modernization in terms of lower rather than higher energy use. High technology
has been mistakenly identified with powerful intervention in physical,
psychological, and social processes. The illusion that a high culture is one
that uses the highest possible quantities of energy must be overcome if we are
to get tools into focus. In classical societies power sources were very equally
distributed. Each man was born with the potential to use most of the power he
would need in a lifetime if his organism was properly maintained. Control over
larger amounts of physical energy was the result of psychic manipulation or of
political domination.

Men did not need power tools to build the Mexican pyramids of TeotihucĂ n or the
Philippine rice terraces of Ibagué. Their muscles provided the force to raise
St. Peter’s and to dig the channels of Angkor Vat. Runners carried the messages
between Caesar’s generals and between village chiefs and Inca planners. Hands
and feet moved the spindle and the loom, the pottery wheel and the saw. Human
metabolism provided the energy that powered classical agriculture, manufacture,
and war. Individual skills were the controls that shaped animal energy into
socially defined work. The energy that rulers could control was the sum of the
performance their subjects voluntarily or involuntarily conceded.

I do not claim that human metabolism provided all useful power, but I do claim
that in most cultures it was the main source of power. Men knew how to harness
some of the forces of the environment. They steered barges down the Nile: they
gentled beasts to draw the plow; they caught the wind in their sails: they
became experts in the construction of simple machines which combined the power
of men and of rain and of gravity. They also tamed fire in the forge and the
kitchen, but the total output of these sources remained secondary. Even Mongols
who lived on their mounts provided more energy with their muscles than with
their horsepower. All the energy tapped from the environment to build Athens
and Florence did not contribute as much controlled power to these classical
societies as did their men. Only when man lit fires to turn cities into ruins
or jungles into swiddens did he release—but certainly not control—energies that
overwhelmed the power of the people who used them.

The amount of physical power available to old societies can be estimated. It
can be expressed in multiples of the average man’s working time and metabolic
energy. lie can burn 2,500 calories a day, four-fifths of them just to stay
alive. They go into making his heart beat and his brain pulse. The remainder
can be externalized, but this does not mean that all of it can be transformed
into work. A large portion of the lifetime capacity of a man to act on his
physical and social environment is burnt running around while he grows up. More
is spent for chores that lie beyond his personal choice-but also beyond other
men’s reach. He consumes energy in getting tip, in preparing food, in seeking
protection from the cold, or in avoiding the slavedriver’s whip. If man is
deprived of the use of this power, hue becomes useless for work. Society can
give shape to these personal activities, but it cannot appropriate the energy
used on them for other tasks. Custom, language, and law can determine the form
of the slave’s pottery, but the master cannot take the last pots or the roof
away from his slaves, not if he wants them to go on slaving for him. A small
energy parcel from each man was the major source of physical power with which
temples were built, mountains were moved, cloth was woven, wars were waged, and
kings were carried around or amused.

Power was limited. It was proportional to the population. Its major source was
the muscles of individual men. Its efficient use depended on the stage of
development which hand tools had reached and the distribution of necessary
tools throughout the population. Tools all matched the impedance of manpower to
the task. Except by redirecting the forces of gravity and wind they did not and
could not act as amplifiers of this power. To control more power than others in
his society, a man had to lord it over his fellows. If a ruler could draw power
from sources other than men, his control over this power still depended on his
control over men. Each pair of oxen required a man to lead them. Even the forge
needed a boy to blow into the fire. Political control co incided with the
control over physical power, and the control of power depended entirely on
authority.

Equal power and equal direct control of power were both features of
preindustrial societies, but this did not guarantee an equal autonomy in the
exercise of this control. On a very primitive level the physical predominance
of one person made him into the lord of others. A slight advantage in
organization or weaponry made one people the master of another. The
appropriation of resources and tools created the basis of class societies and
fostered the rituals and myths that shaped men to fit into the class to which
they were assigned.

In a preindustrial society political control could extend only over the excess
power that people could produce. As soon as a population became efficient
enough to produce more power than was required to maintain it, people could be
deprived of control over this energy. They could be compelled to cede their
power to the decisions of others. They could be either taxed or enslaved. Part
of what they produced on their own could be taken from them, or they could be
put to work for the king or the village. Ideology, economic structure, and life
style tended to favor this concentration of excess energy under the control of
a few.

The degree to which this concentration of control polarized social benefits
varied from one culture to another. At best it improved the range within which
most members of society could employ their remaining energies. High peasant
cultures offer good examples. While all shared in the tasks of defending their
land from enemies or floods, each was also better dressed, housed, and fed. At
worst, the concentration of decisions over power led to the establishment of
empires which were expanded by mercenaries and fed from plantations worked by
slaves.

The total energy available to society increased rapidly toward the end of the
Iron Age, that is, between the time of Agrippa and the time of Watt. Most of
the radical technical mutations that came into existence before the scientific
discoveries in the field of electricity in fact came about early in the Middle
Ages. Because they used windpower far more effectively than any previous
invention, three-masted sailing ships made world-wide transportation possible.
Speedy transportation with regular deliveries was made possible by the building
of canals in Europe, a millennium after the same discovery was implemented in
Southeast Asia. A vastly increased application of nonhuman energy to industries
like brewing, dyeing, pottery-making, brick-making, sugar-refining, salt
manufacture, and transportation went parallel with the construction of vastly
improved water wheels and wind mills.

From the High Middle Ages to the late Renaissance, new social tools developed
that ensured the protection of the worker’s self image and dignity, although he
was now sometimes dwarfed by the size of machines. The guild system did indeed
give the worker a new claim to the monopoly over tools specific to his trade.
But the mill had not yet grown out of proportion to the miller. His monopoly
over grain-processing protected the guildsman, provided him with extra
holidays, and still maximized the services that he could render to his town.
Guilds were neither unions nor professional associations.

Lewis Mumford in his The Myth of the Machine: The Pentagon of Power points out
that one particular enterprise, namely mining, set the pattern for later modes
of mechanization by its callous disregard for human factors, by its
indifference to the pollution and destruction of the neighboring environment,
by its concentration upon the physico-chemical process for obtaining the
desired metal or fuel, and abo~re all by its topographic and mental isolation
from the organic world of the farmer and the craftsman, and the spiritual world
of the Church, the University and the City. In its destruction of the
environment and its indifference to the risks to human life, mining closely
resembles warfare—through likewise it often, through its confrontation of
danger and death, brings into existence a tough, self-respecting personality
... the soldier at his best. But the destructive animus of mining and its
punishing routine of work, along with its environmental poverty and disorder
were passed on to the new industries that used its products. These negative
social results offset the mechanical gains.

This new attitude toward gainful activity is well reflected in the introduction
of a new term to designate it. Tripaliare meant to torture on the trepalium,
which was first mentioned in the sixth century as an instrument of impalement
made out of three wooden sticks. By the twelfth century the word in both French
and Spanish expressed a painful experience to which man is subjected; only in
the sixteenth century did it become possible to use the verb trabajar
interchangeably with laborar and sudar on the job. Equally significant is what
happened in the English language. Things began to work—first medicines (1600)
and then physical tools (1650), even though these were not yet tools driven by
any outside power. The alchemist’s dream of making a homunculus in the test
tube slowly took the shape of creating robots to work for man, and to educate
men to work alongside them. The ideology of an industrial organization of tools
and a capitalist organization of the economy preceded by many centuries what is
usually called the Industrial Revolution. On Baconian premises Europeans began,
according to Mumford, to save time, shrink space, augment power, multiply
goods, over-throw organic norms and displace real organisms with mechanisms
that stimulated them or vastly magnified some single function they performed.
All these imperatives, which have become the groundwork of science as
technology in our present society, seem axiomatic and absolute only because
they remain unexamined. The same change of mind appears also in a transfer from
ritual regularity to mechanical regularity with an emphasis on time-keeping,
space-measuring, account-keeping, thus translating concrete objects and complex
events into abstract quantities. According to Mumford, it was this capitalistic
devotion to repetitive order that helped undermine the unmeasurable personal
balance between the workman and his tools.

New power meant a new relation to time. The lending of money against interest
was considered “against nature” by the Church: money naturally was a means of
exchange to buy necessities, not a capital that could work or bear fruits.
During the seventeenth century even the Church abandoned this view-though
reluctantly—to accept the fact that Christians had become capitalist merchants.
Time became like money: I now can have a few hours before lunch; how shall I
spend time? . . I am short of time so I can’t afford to spend that much time on
a committee; it’s not worth the time . . . It world be a waste of time; I’d
rather save an hour.

Scientists began to consider man as a power source. They sought to measure the
maximum daily exertion that might be expected from a man and compare both his
maintenance and his power to those of a horse. Man was reinvented as a source
of mechanical power. Prisoners condemned to the galleys were not much use most
of the time, since galleys were most of the time in port. Prisoners condemned
to the treadmills produced rotary power to which any of the new machines could
be hooked. Up to the early nineteenth century men in English prisons actually
labored on the treadmills to make machines work.

The new attitude of man to his tools during the Industrial Revolution, which
began as capitalism did in the fifteenth century, finally called for the
invention of new sources of power. The steam engine was a product of the
Industrial Revolution rather than the cause of it. Power plants soon became
mobile, and with the railroad the Iron Age and the Industrial Revolution came
to an end. Industrial ways became the status quo.

Immense new sources of power were tapped during the twentieth century, and much
of this power became self-governing. Man has now been almost replaced by
machines and reduced to being their operator. Fewer men are needed as gang
workers in the fields: slavery has become uneconomical. But also fewer men are
needed on the assembly line, as engineers have designed machines to perform the
tasks that mass production and industrialization had created in the centuries
before the steam engine. More power has become available, so more power is
used, the human slaveowner is replaced by the operant conditioning of men in
the mega-machine.

We have all grown up as children of our time, and therefore it is extremely
difficult to envisage a postindustrial yet human type of “work.” To reduce
industrial tools seems equivalent to a return to the tortured labor of the mine
and the factory, or to the labor of the U.S. farm hand who has to compete with
his mechanical neighbor. The worker who had to dip a heavy tire into a solution
of hot sulfur each time the machine asked for it was literally hooked onto his
apparatus. Agricultural labor also ceased to be what it was for a slave or a
farmer. For the slave it was labor at the service and behest of a master; for
the peasant it was his own work which be could organize and shape in accordance
with the demands of growing plants, hungry animals, and unpredictable weather.
The modern farmhand in the United States today who is deprived of power tools
is under a double pressure quite different from that of the classical slave: he
must measure up to performance standards set by farm hands elsewhere who use
machines, and he is constantly aware that he is underprivileged, exploited, and
abused because in an age of the megamachine he feels that he is used like a
component. The prospect that moving toward a convivial society might imply a
society with low power tools would seem to him like a return to the
exploitation of manpower by inefficient industrial machines in the early
periods of steam.

I have described three types of institutional arrangements within which tools
can be used. Certain tools can be used effectively within only one of these
arrangements. There are tools which can be used normally for fully satisfying,
imaginative, and independent work; others tend to be used primarily in
activities best labeled as labor; and, finally, certain machines can only be
operated. The same can be said about physical artifacts and about the set of
rules that define formal institutional arrangements. Cars are machines that
call for highways, and highways pretend to be public utilities while in fact
they are discriminatory devices. Compulsory schools constitute a huge
bureaucratic system; no matter how convivially a teacher tries to conduct his
class, his pupils learn through him to which class they belong.

Cars operate on highways as teachers operate in schools. Only in a very limited
sense can what the truck driver and the teacher do be called labor. Only
exceptionally will a teacher feel that his operations within the school system
do not directly interfere with his work.

The market characteristics of these three types of human activity help to
clarify the distinction among them. Labor can be purchased or sold in the
marketplace. Not work as an activity, but only the result of convivial work can
be marketed. Finally, the right to operate machines and to obtain the scarce
privileges that go with employment must be earned through the previous
consumption of certified treatments, which take the form of a curriculum of
schooling and testing along with successive jobs.

Tools for a convivial and yet efficient society could not have been designed at
an earlier stage of history. We now can design the machinery for eliminating
slavery without enslaving man to the machine. Science and technology are not
bound to the peculiar notion, seemingly characteristic of the last 150 years of
their application to production, that new knowledge of nature’s laws has to be
locked into increasingly more specialized and highly capitalized preparation of
men to use them. The sciences, which specialized out of philosophy, have become
the rationale for an increasing division of operations. The division of labor
has finally led to the labor-saving division of tools. New technology is now
used to amplify supply funnels for commodities. Public utilities are turned
from facilities for persons into arenas for the owners of expensive tools. The
use of science and technology constantly supports the industrial mode of
production, and thereby crowds off the scene all tool shops for independent
enterprise. But this is not the necessary result of new scientific discoveries
or of their useful application. It is rather the result of a total prejudice in
favor of the future expansion of an industrial mode of production. Research
teams are organized to remedy minor inefficiencies that hold up the further
growth of a specific production process. These planned discoveries are then
heralded as costly breakthroughs in the interest of further public service.
Research is now mostly oriented toward industrial development.

This unqualified identification of scientific advance with the replacement of
human initiative by programmed tools springs from an ideological prejudice and
is not the result of scientific analysis. Science could be applied for
precisely the opposite purpose. Advanced or “high” technology could become
identified with labor-sparing, work-intensive decentralized productivity.
Natural and social science can be used for the creation of tools, utilities,
and rules available to everyone, permitting individuals and transient
associations to constantly recreate their mutual relationships and their
environment with unenvisaged freedom and self-expression.

New understanding of nature can now be applied to our tools either for the
purpose of propelling us into a hyperindustrial age of electronic cybernetics
or to help us develop a wide range of truly modern and yet convivial tools.
Limited resources can be used to provide millions of viewers with the color
image of one performer or to provide many people with free access to the
records of their choice. In the first case, technology will be used for the
further promotion of the specialized worker, be lie a plumber, surgeon, or TV
performer. More and more bureaucrats will study the market, consult their
balance sheets, and decide for more people on more occasions about the range of
products among which they may choose. There will be a further increase of
useful things for useless people. But science can also be used to simplify
tools and to enable the layman to shape his immediate environment to his taste.
The time has come to take the syringe out of the hand of the doctor, as the pen
was taken out of the band of the scribe during the Reformation in Europe.

Most curable sickness can now be diagnosed and treated by laymen. People find
it so difficult to accept this statement because the complexity of medical
ritual has hidden from them the simplicity of its basic procedures. It took the
example of the barefoot doctor in China to show how modern practice by simple
workers in their spare time could, in three years, catapult health care in
China to levels unparalleled elsewhere. In most other countries health care by
laymen is considered a crime. A seventeen-year-old friend of mine was recently
tried for having treated some 130 of her high-school colleagues for VD. She was
acquitted on a technicality by the judge when expert counsel compared her
performance with that of the U.S. Health Service. Nowhere in the U.S.A. can her
achievement be considered “standard,” because she succeeded in making retests
on all her patients six weeks after their first treatment. Progress should mean
growing competence in self-care rather than growing dependence.

The possibilities of lay therapy also run up against our commitment to “better”
health, and have blinded us to the distinction between curable and incurable
sickness. This is a crucial distinction because as soon as a doctor treats
incurable sickness, he perverts his craft from a means to an end. He becomes a
charlatan set on providing scientific consolation in a ceremony in which the
doctor takes on the patient’s struggle against death. The patient becomes the
object of his ministrations instead of a sick subject who can be helped in the
process of healing or dying. Medicine ceases to be a legitimate profession when
it cannot provide each man or his next of kin with the tool to make this one
crucial differential diagnosis for himself.

New opportunities for the progressive expansion of lay therapy and the parallel
progressive reduction of professional medicine are rejected because life in an
industrial society has made us place such exaggerated value on standard
products, uniformity, and certified quality. Industrialized expectations have
blurred the distinction between personal vocation and standard profession. Of
course, any layman can grow up to become a general healer, but this (hoes not
mean that every layman must be taught how to heal. It simply means that in a
society in which people can and must take care of their neighbors and do so on
their own, some people will excel at using the best available tools. In a
society in which people can once again be born in their homes and die in their
homes and in which there is a place for cripples and idiots in the street, and
where a distinction is made between plumbing and healing, quite a few people
would grow up capable of assisting others to heal, to suffer, or to die.

Just as with proper social arrangements most people would grow up as readers
without having to be schooled and without having to recreate the pre-Gutenberg
profession of the scribe, so a sufficient number would grow up competent with
medical tools. This would make healing so plentiful that it would be difficult
to turn this competence into a monopoly or to sell it as a commodity.
Deprofessionalization means a renewed distinction between the freedom of
vocation and the occasional boost sick people derive from the quasi-religious
authority of the certified doctor.

Of course the deprofessionalization of most ordinary medicine could sometimes
substitute a quack for today’s impostor, but the threat of quackery becomes
less convincing as professionally caused damage grows. There just is no
substitute for the self-correcting judgment of the layman in socializing the
tools invented or use(l by the professional. Lifelong familiarity with the
specific dangers of a specific remedy is the best preparation for accepting or
rejecting it in time of crisis.

Take another tool—transportation—as an example. Under President Càrdenas in the
early thirties, Mexico developed a modern system of transportation. Within a
few years about 80 percent of the population had gained access to the
advantages of the automobile. Most important, villages had been connected by
dirt roads or tracks. Heavy, simple, and tough trucks traveled over them every
now and then, moving at speeds far below twenty miles per hour. People were
crowded together on rows of wooden benches nailed to the floor to make place
for merchandise loaded in the back and on the roof. Over short distances the
vehicle could not compete with people, who had been used to walking and to
carrying their merchandise, but long-distance travel had become possible for
all. instead of a man driving his pig to market, man and pig could go together
in a truck. Any Mexican could now reach any point in his country in a few days.

Since 1945 the money spent on roads has increased every year. It has been used
to build highways between a few major centers. Fragile cars now move at high
speeds over smooth roads. Large, specialized trucks connect factories. The old,
all-purpose tramp truck has been pushed back into the mountains or swamps. In
most areas either the peasant must take a bus to go to the market to buy
industrially packaged commodities, or he sells his pig to the trucker in the
employ of the meat merchant. He can no longer go to town with his pig. He pays
taxes for the roads which serve the owners of various specialized monopolies
and does so under the illusion that the benefits will ultimately spread to him.

In exchange for an occasional ride on an upholstered seat in an air-conditioned
bus, the common man has lost much of the mobility the old system gave him,
without gaining any new freedom. Research done in two typical large states of
Mexico-one dominated by deserts, the other by mountains and lush
growth—confirms this conclusion. Less than one percent of the population in
either state traveled a distance of over fifteen miles in any one hour during
1970. More appropriate pushcarts and bicycles, both motorized when needed,
would have presented a technologically much more efficient solution for 99
percent of the population than the vaunted highway development. Such pushcarts
could have been built and maintained by people trained on the job, and operated
on roadbeds built to Inca standards, yet covered to diminish drag. The usual
rationale given for the investment in standard roads and cars is that it is a
condition for development and that without it a region cannot be integrated
into the world market. Both claims are true, but can be considered as desirable
only if monetary integration is the goal of development.

During the last few years tire promoters of development have come to admit that
cars, as operated now, are inefficient. This inefficiency is blamed on the fact
that modern vehicles are designed for private ownership, not for the public
good. In fact, modern personnel transport is inefficient not because an
individual capsule rather than a cabin is the model for the largest number of
vehicles, or because these vehicles are now owned by their drivers. It is
inefficient because of the obsessive identification of higher speed with better
transport. Just as the demand for better health at all costs is a form of
mental sickness, so is the pretense of higher speed.

The railroads reflected the class societies they served simply by putting
different fares on the same speed. But when a society commits itself to higher
speeds, the speedometer becomes an indicator of social class. Any peasant could
accompany LĂ zaro CĂ rdenas on horseback. Today only his personal staff can
accompany a modern governor in his private helicopter. In capitalist countries
how often you can cover great distances is determined by what your can pay. In
socialist countries your velocity depends on the social importance the
bureaucracy attaches to you. In both cases the particular speed at which you
travel puts you into your class and company. Speed is one of the means by which
an efficiency-oriented society is stratified.

Fostered addiction to speed is also a means of social control. Transportation
in its various forms now swallows 23 percent of the U.S. gross expenditures.
The United States may be rich enough to allocate one-fourth of its energy
resources and human time to the enterprise of getting somewhere. Under Khufu,
Egyptians might have spent that much during a few years to build the Great
Pyramid and to get their ruler to the underworld. Unfortunately, however,
transportation exacts an ever higher percentage of the cash spent in a given
year within many a Latin-American municipality. The road degrades the
subsistence farmer and artisan, integrates the village into time money economy,
and swallows much of the available cash. It is true that modern transportation
does incorporate a region into the world market. It also trains the inhabitants
for the consumption of foreign goods and the acceptance of foreign values. For
example, throughout history Thailand was known for its klongs. These canals
crisscrossed the country; people, rice, and tax collectors all moved easily
along them. Some villages were cut off during the dry season, but their
seasonal rhythm of life turned this periodic isolation into an occasion for
meditation and festivities. A society that can afford long holidays and fill
them with activities is certainly not poor. During time Past half-decade major
klongs were filled in to build roads. Since bus drivers are paid by the number
of miles they can cover in a day, and since cars are still few, the Thais for a
short while will be able to circulate in their country at world-record bus
speeds. They will pay with the destruction of waterways that took millennia to
build. The economists argue that busses and trucks pump more money per year
through the economy. They do, but at the cost of depriving most Thais of the
independence which their sleek rice boats once granted each family. Of course,
car owners could never have competed with rice boats unless time World Bank had
financed roads for them and time Thai government had made new laws that
permitted them to profane the klongs.

The building trades are another example of an industry that modern
nation-states impose on their societies, thereby modernizing the poverty of
their citizens. The legal protection and financial support granted the industry
reduces and cancels opportunities for the otherwise much more efficient
self-builder. Quite recently Mexico launched a major program with the aim of
providing all workers with proper housing. As a first step, new standards were
set for the construction of dwelling units. These standards were intended to
protect the little man who purchases a house from exploitation by the industry
producing it. Paradoxically, these same standards deprived many more people of
the traditional opportunity to house themselves. The code specifies minimum
requirements that a man who builds his own house in his spare time cannot meet.
Besides that, the real rent for industrially built quarters is more than the
total income of 80 percent of the people. “Better housing,” then, can be
occupied only by those who are well-off or by those on whom the law bestows
direct rent subsidies.

Once dwellings that fall below industrial standards are defined as improper,
public funds are denied to the overwhelming majority of people who cannot buy
housing but could “house” themselves. The tax funds meant to improve the living
quarters of the poor are monopolized for the building of new towns next to the
provincial and regional capitals where government employees, unionized workers,
and people with good connections can live. These are all people who are
employed in the modern sector of the economy, that is, people who hold jobs.
They can be easily distinguished from other Mexicans because they have learned
to speak about their trabajo as a noun, while the unemployed or the
occasionally employed or those who live near the subsistence level do not use
the noun form when they go to work.

These people, who have work, not only get subsidies for the building of their
homes; the entire public-service sector is rearranged and developed to serve
them. In Mexico City it has been estimated that 10 percent of the people use 50
percent of the household water, and on tire high plain water is very scarce
indeed. The building code has standards far below those of rich countries, but
by prescribing certain ways in which houses must be built, it creates a rising
scarcity of housing. The pretense of a society to provide ever better housing
is the same kind of abberation we have met in the pretense of doctors to
provide better health and of engineers to provide higher speeds. The setting of
abstract impossible goals turns the means by which these are to be achieved
into ends.

What happened in Mexico happened all over Latin America during the decade of
the Alliance for Progress, including Cuba under Castro. It also happened in
Massachusetts. In 1945, 32 percent of all one-family housing units in
Massachusetts were still self-built: either built by their owners from
foundation to roof or constructed under the full responsibility of the owner.
By 1970 the proportion had gone down to 11 percent. Meanwhile, housing had been
discovered as a major problem. The technological capability to produce tools
and materials that favor self-building had increased in the intervening
decades, but social arrangements—like unions, codes, mortgage rules, and
markets-had turned against this choice.

Most people do not feel at home unless a significant proportion of the value of
their houses is the result of the input of their own labor. Convivial policies
would define what people who want to house themselves cannot get, and thereby
make sure that all can get access to some minimum of physical space, to water,
some basic building elements, some convivial tools ranging from power drills to
mechanized pushcarts, and, probably, to some limited credit. Such an inversion
of the present policy could give a post-industrial society modern homes almost
as desirable for its members as those which were standard for the old Mayas and
are still the rule in YucatĂ n.

Our present tools are engineered to deliver professional energies. Such
energies come in quanta. Less than a quantum cannot be delivered. Less than
four years of schooling is worse than none. It only defines the former pupil as
a dropout. This is equally true in medicine, transportation, and housing, as in
agriculture and in the administration of justice. Mechanical transportation is
worthwhile only at certain speeds. Conflict resolution is effective only when
the issue is of sufficient weight to justify the costs of court action. The
planting of new grains is productive only if the acreage and capital of the
farmer are beyond a certain size. Powerful tools created to achieve abstractly
conceived social goals inevitably deliver their output in quanta that are
beyond the reach of a majority. What is more, these tools are integrated.
Access to key positions in government or industry is reserved to those who are
certified consumers of high quanta of schooling. They are the individuals
chosen to run the plantation of mutant rubber trees, and they need a car to
rush from meeting to meeting. Productivity demands the output of packaged
quanta of institutionally defined values, and productive management demands the
access of an individual to all these packages at once.

Professional goal-setting produces goods for an environment produced by other
professions. Life that depends on high speed and apartment houses makes
hospitals inevitable. By definition all these are scarce, and get even scarcer
as they approach the standards set more recently by an ever-evolving
profession; thereby each unit or quantum appearing on the market frustrates
more people than it satisfies.

A just society would be one in which liberty for one person is constrained only
by the demands created by equal liberty for another. Such a society requires as
a precondition an agreement excluding tools that by their very nature prevent
such liberty. This is true for tools that are fundamentally purely social
arrangements, such as the school system, as well as for tools that are physical
machines. In a convivial society compulsory and open-ended schooling would have
to be excluded for the sake of justice. Age-specific, compulsory competition on
an unending ladder for lifelong privileges cannot increase equality but must
favor those who start earlier, or who are healthier, or who are better equipped
outside the classroom. Inevitably, it organizes society into many layers of
failure, with each layer inhabited by dropouts schooled to believe that those
who have consumed more education deserve more privilege because they are more
valuable assets to society as a whole. A society constructed so that education
by means of schools is a necessity for its functioning cannot be a just
society. Power tools having certain structural characteristics are inevitably
manipulative and must also be eliminated for the sake of justice. In a modern
society, energy inputs represent one of the major new liberties. Each man’s
ability to produce change depends on his ability to control low-entropy energy.
On this control of energy depends his right to give his meaning to the physical
environment. His ability to act toward the future lie chooses depends on his
control of the energy that gives shape to that future. Equal freedom in a
society that uses large amounts of environmental energy means equal control
over the transformation of that energy and not just an equal claim to what has
been done with it.

Most of the power tools now in use favor centralization of control. industrial
plants with their highly specialized tools give neither the worker nor most
engineers a choice over what use will be made of the energy they manage. This
is equally true, though less evident, of the high-powered consumer tools that
dominate our society. Most of them, such as cars and air conditioners, are too
costly to be available on an equal basis outside a few super rich societies.
Others, such as mechanical household devices, are so specialized in nature that
they in no way offer more freedom than much simpler hand tools. The monopoly of
industrial production deprives even privileged clients of control over what
they may get. Few people get the cars that most people want, and GM designers
can only build vehicles to fit the existing roads.

Nations and multinational corporations have become means for the spreading
empire of international professions. Professional imperialism triumphs even
where political and economic domination has been broken. Schools everywhere are
governed by pedagogues who read the same books on learning theory and
curriculum-planning. In a given year, schools produce more or less the same
model of pupils in every nation. Nineteen-fifty graduates are as obsolete in
Dakar as they are in Paris. The same iatrogenic sicknesses are produced all
over the world by doctors who administer chloromycin or steroid pills. Every
country tends to select those productive processes which are more
capital-intensive and promise greater cost-benefit ratios, so that the same
kind of technological unemployment is produced everywhere. Basic needs are
defined as those that international professions can meet. Since the local
production of these wares is to the advantage of highly schooled national
élites, a country’s doctors, teachers, and engineers will defend it as an
antidote to foreign domination. The knowledge capitalism of professional
imperialism subjugates people more imperceptibly than and as effectively as
international finance or weaponry.

The principal source of injustice in our epoch is political approval for the
existence of tools that by their very nature restrict to a very few the liberty
to use them in an autonomous way. The pompous rituals by which each man is
given a vote to choose between factions only cover up the fact that the
imperialism of industrial tools is both arbitrary and growing. Statistics which
prove increased outputs and high per capita consumption of professionally
defined quanta only veil the enormously high invisible costs. People get better
education, better health, better transportation, better entertainment, and
often even better nourishment only if the experts’ goals are taken as the
measurement of what ’better’ means. The possibility of a convivial society
depends therefore on a new consensus about time destructiveness of imperialism
on three levels: the pernicious spread of one nation beyond its boundaries; the
omnipresent influence of multinational corporations; and the mushrooming of
professional monopolies over production. Politics for convivial reconstruction
of society must especially face imperialism on this third level, where it takes
the form of professionalism. The public owner-ship of resources and of the
means of production, arid public control over the market and over net transfers
of power, must be complemented by a public determination of the tolerable basic
structure of modern tools. This means that politics in a postindustrial society
must be mainly concerned with the development of design criteria for tools
rather than as now with the choice of production goals. These politics would
mean a structural inversion of the institutions now providing and defining new
manmade essentials.

To invert politics, it will not be enough to show that a convivial life style
is possible, or even to demonstrate that it is more attractive than life in a
society ruled by industrial productivity. We cannot rest with the claim that
this inversion would bring society closer to meeting the goals now stated as
those of our major institutions. It is not even enough to show that a just or
socially equal order can become a reality only through a convivial
reconstruction of tools and the consequent redefinition of ownership and power.
We need a way to recognize that the inversion of present political purpose is
necessary for the survival of all people.

Most people have staked their self-images in the present structure and are
unwilling to lose their ground. They have found security in one of the several
ideologies that support further industrialization. They feel compelled to push
the illusion of progress on which they are hooked. They long for and expect
increase(h satisfaction, with less input of human energy and with more division
of competence. They value handicraft and personal care as luxuries, but the
ideal of a more labor-intensive, yet modern, production process seems to them
quixotic and anachronistic.

It seems absurd to prepare politicians who have pledged themselves to increased
outputs and better distribution of goods and services among their constituents
for the day when a majority of voters will choose limits for all rather than
promises of equal consumption. It appears equally hopeless to expect inverse
insight from humanitarian liberals who have come to feel that feeding the
starving millions is their vocation. They forget that people eat, and that
people die when they are fed. These self-appointed keepers of their brothers
make other people’s survival depend on their own growing efficiency. By
shifting from the production of guns to the production of grains they reduce
their sense of guilt amid increase their sense of power. They are blind to the
convergence of population growth and the failure of the green revolution, which
guarantees that feeding people now will escalate starvation by 1985. Their
hubris distracts them from understanding that only the renunciation of
industrial expansion can bring food and population into a balance in the
so-called backward countries. The attempt to feed people and to control their
increase are two mutually reinforcing, and very dangerous, illusions. Nor can
economists foresee institutional inversion when for them all institutions must
be evaluated according to the increase in their planned output and their
ability to externalize internal dis-economics in an unobtrusive way. The terms
and frameworks of economics have been shaped by the ideology of an irresistible
institutionalization of values that overarches otherwise opposed economic
creeds.

To translate the theoretical possibility of a postindustrial convivial life
style into a political program for new tools, it must soon be shown that the
prevailing fundamental structure of our present tools menaces the survival of
mankind. It must be shown that this menace is imminent and that the effects of
compulsive efficiency do more damage than good to most people in our
generation. For this purpose we must identify the range within which our
present institutions have become frustrating, and we must recognize another
range within which our tools become destructive of society as a whole.

The Multiple Balance

The human equilibrium is open. It is capable of shifting within flexible but
finite parameters. People can change, but only within bounds. In contrast, the
present industrial system is dynamically unstable. It is organized for
indefinite expansion and the concurrent unlimited creation of new needs, which
in an industrial environment soon become basic necessities.

Once the industrial mode of production has become dominant in a society, it may
still admit shifts from one type of output to another, but it does not admit
limits to the further institutionalization of values. Such growth makes the
incongruous demand that man seek his satisfaction by submitting to the logic of
his tools.

The demands made by tools on people become increasingly costly. This rising
cost of fitting man to the service of his tools is reflected in the ongoing
shift from goods to services in over-all production. Increasing manipulation of
man becomes necessary to overcome the resistance of his vital equilibrium to
the dynamic of growing industries; it takes the form of educational, medical,
and administrative therapies. Education turns out competitive consumers;
medicine keeps them alive in the engineered environment they have come to
require; bureaucracy reflects the necessity of exercising social control over
people to do meaningless work. The parallel increase in the cost of the defense
of new levels of privilege through military, police, and insurance measures
reflects the fact that in a consumer society there are inevitably two kinds of
slaves: the prisoners of addiction and the prisoners of envy.

Political debate must now be focused on the various ways in which unlimited
production threatens human life. This political debate will be misled by those
who insist on prescribing palliatives which only disguise the deep reasons why
the systems of health, transport, education, housing, and even politics and law
are not working. The environmental crisis, for example, is rendered superficial
if it is not pointed out that antipollution devices can only be effective if
the total output of production decreases. Otherwise they tend to shift garbage
out of sight, push it into the future, or dump it onto the poor. The total
removal of the pollution created locally by a large-scale industry requires
equipment, material, and energy that can create several times the damage
elsewhere. Making antipollution devices compulsory only increases the unit cost
of the product. This may conserve some fresh air for all, because fewer people
can afford to drive cars or sleep in air-conditioned homes or fly to a fishing
ground on the weekend, but it replaces damage to the physical environment with
further social disintegration. To shift from coal to atomic power replaces smog
now with higher radiation levels tomorrow. To relocate refineries overseas,
where pollution controls are less stringent, preserves Americans-not
Venezuelans-from unpleasant odors at the cost of higher levels of world-wide
poisoning.

The overgrowth of tools threatens persons in ways which are profoundly new,
though they are also analogous to traditional forms of nuisance and tort. These
threats are of a new kind, because their perpetrators and victims are the same
people: both operators and clients of inexorably destructive tools. Though some
people may cash in on the game at first, ultimately all lose everything they
have.

I will identify six ways in which all people of the world are threatened by
industrial development after passage through the second watershed: (1)
Overgrowth threatens the right to the fundamental physical structure of the
environment with which man has evolved. (2) Industrialization threatens the
right to convivial work. (3) The overprogramming of man for the new environment
deadens his creative imagination. (4) New levels of productivity threaten the
right to participatory politics. (5) Enforced obsolescence threatens the right
to tradition: the recourse to precedent in language, myth, morals, and
judgment. I will describe these five threats as distinct though interrelated
categories all having in common a destructive inversion of means into ends. (6)
Pervasive frustration by means of compulsory though engineered satisfaction
constitutes a sixth and more subtle threat.

I am typifying the hazards created by the overgrowth of tools in six categories
chosen so the damages can be recognized in traditional terms. That impersonal
tools placed at the service of the injured party should inevitably inflict the
injury is new, but the damage which threatens each person is not. These six
categories can serve in the recovery of procedural principles by which people
can expose and redress the present imbalance in the functioning of tools. These
underlying principles of moral, political, and juridical procedure I assume to
be three: recognition of the legitimacy of personal conflict, the dialectic
authority of history over present procedures, and the recourse to laymen or
peers for binding policy decisions. The radical functional inversion of our
major institutions constitutes a revolution much more profound than the shifts
in ownership or power usually proposed. It can be neither envisaged nor enacted
unless a basic structure of procedure is recovered and clearly agreed upon.
This structure can even now be discussed in concrete terms. I will therefore
refer to formal juristic concepts in illustrating my argument.

Biological Degradation

The precarious balance between man and the biosphere has been recognized and
has suddenly begun to worry many people. The degradation of the environment is
dramatic and highly visible. For years car traffic in Mexico City increased
steadily under a sparkling sky. Then, within a couple of years, smog descended
and soon became worse than in Los Angeles. This phenomenon can be easily
discussed and appreciated by people who have never studied science. Poisons of
unknown potency are discharged into the biotic system of the earth. There is no
way to retrieve some of them, nor any means to predict how some of them may
suddenly combine their action so that the whole earth, like Lake Erie or
Baikal, will die. Man has evolved to fit into one niche in the universe. The
earth is his home. This home is now threatened by the impact of man.

Overpopulation, excessive affluence, and faulty technology are usually
identified as the three trends which combine and threaten to break the
environmental balance. Paul Ehrlich points out that to face honestly the need
for population control and stabilized consumption may “expose one to the
painful criticism of being both anti-people and anti-poor,” but he also
emphasizes that “these unpopular measures offer mankind’s only hope for
averting unprecedented misery.” Ehrlich wants to implement birth control with
industrial efficiency. Barry Commoner insists that faulty technology, the third
element in the equation, accounts for most of the recent deterioration in the
quality of the environment. He exposes himself to the criticism of being an
antitechnological demagogue. Commoner wants to retool industry rather than
invert the basic structure of our tools.

Fascination with the environmental crisis has forced the debate about survival
to focus on only one balance threatened by tools. A one-dimensional dispute is
futile. Three trends have indeed been identified, each of them tending to upset
the balance between man and the physical environment. Overpopulation makes more
people dependent on limited resources. Affluence compels each person to use
more energy. Faulty technology degrades energy in an inefficient way.

If these three trends are considered to be the only significant threats, and
the physical environment is considered as the only fundamental milieu that is
threatened, only two central issues must be discussed: (i) To decide which
factor or trend has degraded the environment most, and which factor will impose
the greatest burden on the environment during the next few years. (2) To decide
which factor merits most attention because we can in some way reduce or invert
it. One party claims it is easier to do away with people, the other that it is
more feasible to reduce entropy-producing production.

Honesty requires that we each recognize the need to limit procreation,
consumption, and waste, but equally we must radically reduce our expectations
that machines will do our work for us or that therapists can make us learned or
healthy. The only solution to the environmental crisis is the shared insight of
people that they would be happier if they could work together and care for each
other. Such an inversion of the current world view requires intellectual
courage for it exposes us to the unenlightened yet painful criticism of being
not only antipeople and against economic progress, but equally against liberal
education and scientific and technological advance. We must face the fact that
the imbalance between man and the environment is just one of several mutually
reinforcing stresses, each distorting the balance of life in a different
dimension. In this view, overpopulation is the result of a distortion in the
balance of learning, dependence on affluence is the result of a radical
monopoly of institutional over personal values, and faulty technology is
inexorably consequent upon a transformation of means into ends.

The one-dimensional debate among proponents of various panaceas for the
ecological imbalance will only inspire the false expectation that somehow human
action can be engineered to fit into the requirements of the world conceived as
a technological totality. Bureaucratically guaranteed survival under such
circumstances means the expansion of industrial economics to the point where a
centrally planned system of production and reproduction is identified with the
guided evolution of the Earth. If such an industrially minded solution becomes
generally accepted as the only way of preserving a viable environment, the
preservation of the physical milieu can become the rationale for a bureaucratic
Leviathan at the levers which regulate levels of human reproduction,
expectation, production, and consumption. Such a technological response to
growing population, pollution, and affluence can be founded only on a further
development of the presently prevailing institutionalization of values. The
belief in the possibility of this development is founded on an erroneous
supposition, namely, that “The historical achievement of science and technology
has rendered possible the translation of values into technical tasks-the
materialization of values. Consequently, what is at stake is the redefinition
of values in technical terms, as elements in technological process. The new
ends, as technical ends, would then operate in the project and in the
construction of the machinery, and not only in its utilization.” [Herbert
Marcuse,One-Dimensional Man, Boston, 1970.]

The re-establishment of an ecological balance depends on the ability of society
to counteract the progressive materialization of values. Otherwise man will
find himself totally enclosed within his artificial creation, with no exit.
Enveloped in a physical, social, and psychological milieu of his own making, he
will be a prisoner in the shell of technology, unable to find again the ancient
milieu to which he was adapted for hundreds of thousands of years. The
ecological balance cannot be re-established unless we recognize again that only
persons have ends and that only persons can work toward them. Machines only
operate ruthlessly to reduce people to the role of impotent allies in their
destructive progress.

Radical Monopoly

When overefficient tools are applied to facilitate man’s relations with the
physical environment, they can destroy the balance between man and nature.
Overefficient tools corrupt the environment. But tools can also be made
overefficient in quite a different way. They can upset the relationship between
what people need to do by themselves and what they need to obtain ready-made.
In this second dimension overefficient production results in radical monopoly.

By radical monopoly I mean a kind of dominance by one product that goes far
beyond what the concept of monopoly usually implies. Generally we mean by
“monopoly” the exclusive control by one corporation over the means of producing
(or selling) a commodity or service. Coca-Cola can create a monopoly over the
soft-drink market in Nicaragua by being the only maker of soft drinks which
advertises with modern means. Nestlé might impose its brand of cocoa by
controlling the raw material, some car maker by restricting imports of other
makes, a television channel by licensing. Monopolies of this kind have been
recognized for a century as dangerous by-products of industrial expansion, and
legal devices have been developed in a largely futile attempt to control them.
Monopolies of this kind restrict the choices open to the consumer.

They might even compel him to buy one product on the market, but they seldom
simultaneously abridge his liberties in other domains. A thirsty man might
desire a cold, gaseous, and sweet drink and find himself restricted to the
choice of just one brand. He still remains free to quench his thirst with beer
or water. Only if and when his thirst is translated without meaningful
alternatives into the need for a Coke would the monopoly become radical. By
“radical monopoly” I mean the dominance of one type of product rather than the
dominance of one brand. I speak about radical monopoly when one industrial
production process exercises an exclusive control over the satisfaction of a
pressing need, and excludes nonindustrial activities from competition.

Cars can thus monopolize traffic. They can shape a city into their
image—practically ruling out locomotion on foot or by bicycle in Los Angeles.
They can eliminate river traffic in Thailand. That motor traffic curtails the
right to walk, not that more people drive Chevies than Fords, constitutes
radical monopoly. What cars do to people by virtue of this radical monopoly is
quite distinct from and independent of what they do by burning gasoline that
could be transformed into food in a crowded world. It is also distinct from
automotive manslaughter. Of course cars burn gasoline that could be used to
make food. Of course they are dangerous and costly. But the radical monopoly
cars establish is destructive in a special way. Cars create distance. Speedy
vehicles of all kinds render space scarce. They drive wedges of highways into
populated areas, and then extort tolls on the bridge over the remoteness
between people that was manufactured for their sake. This monopoly over land
turns space into car fodder. It destroys the environment for feet and bicycles.
Even if planes and buses could run as nonpolluting, nondepleting public
services, their inhuman velocities would degrade man’s innate mobility and
force him to spend more time for the sake of travel.

Schools tried to extend a radical monopoly on learning by redefining it as
education. As long as people accepted the teacher’s definition of reality,
those who learned outside school were officially stamped “uneducated.” Modern
medicine deprives the ailing of care not prescribed by doctors. Radical
monopoly exists where a major tool rules out natural competence. Radical
monopoly imposes compulsory consumption and thereby restricts personal
autonomy. It constitutes a special kind of social control because it is
enforced by means of the imposed consumption of a standard product that only
large institutions can provide.

The control of undertakers over burial shows how radical monopoly functions and
how it differs from other forms of culturally defined behavior. A generation
ago, in Mexico, only the Opening of the grave and the blessing of the dead body
were performed by professionals: the gravedigger and the priest. A death in the
family created various demands, all of which could be taken care of within the
family. The wake, the funeral, and the dinner served to compose quarrels, to
vent grief, and to remind each participant of the fatality of death and the
value of life. Most of these were of a ritual nature and carefully
prescribed-different from region to region. Recently, funeral homes were
established in the major cities. At first undertakers had difficulty finding
clients because even in large cities people still knew how to bury their dead.
During the sixties the funeral homes obtained control over new cemeteries and
began offering package deals, including the casket, church service, and
embalming. Now legislation is being passed to make the mortician’s
ministrations compulsory. Once he gets hold of the body, the funeral director
will have established a radical monopoly over burial, as medicine is at the
point of establishing one over dying.

The current debate over health-care delivery in the United States clearly
illustrates the entrenchment of a radical monopoly. Each political party in the
debate makes sick-care a burning public issue and thereby relegates health care
to an area about which politics has nothing important to say. Each party
promises more funds to doctors, hospitals, and drugstores. Such promises are
not in the interest of the majority. They only serve to increase the power of a
minority of professionals to prescribe the tools men are to use in maintaining
health, healing sickness, and repressing death. More funds will strengthen the
hold of the health industry over public resources and heighten its prestige and
arbitrary power. Such power in the hands of a minority will produce only an
increase in suffering and a decrease in personal self-reliance. More money will
be invested in tools that only postpone unavoidable death and in services that
abridge even further the civil rights of those who want to heal each other.
More money spent under the control of the health profession means that more
people are operationally conditioned into playing the role of the sick, a role
they are not allowed to interpret for themselves. Once they accept this role,
their most trivial needs can be satisfied only through commodities that are
scarce by professional definition.

People have a native capacity for healing, consoling, moving, learning,
building their houses, and burying their dead. Each of these capacities meets a
need. The means for the satisfaction of these needs are abundant so long as
they depend primarily on what people can do for themselves, with only marginal
dependence on commodities. These activities have use-value without having been
given exchange-value. Their exercise at the service of man is not considered
labor.

These basic satisfactions become scarce when the social environment is
transformed in such a manner that basic needs can no longer be met by abundant
competence. The establishment of radical monopoly happens when people give up
their native ability to do what they can do for themselves and for each other,
in exchange for something “better” that can be done for them only by a major
tool. Radical monopoly reflects the industrial institutionalization of values.
It substitutes the standard package for the personal response. It introduces
new classes of scarcity and a new device to classify people according to the
level of their consumption. This redefinition raises the unit cost of valuable
service, differentially rations privilege, restricts access to resources, and
makes people dependent. Above all, by depriving people of the ability to
satisfy personal needs in a personal manner, radical monopoly creates radical
scarcity of personal—as opposed to institutional-service.

Against this radical monopoly people need protection. They need this protection
whether consumption is imposed by the private interests of undertakers, by the
government for the sake of hygiene, or by the self-destructive collusion
between the mortician and the survivors, who want to do the best thing for
their dear departed. They need this protection even if the majority is now sold
on the professional’s services. Unless the need for protection from radical
monopoly is recognized, its multiple implementation can break the tolerance of
man for enforced inactivity and passivity.

It is not always easy to determine what constitutes compulsory consumption. The
monopoly held by schools is not established primarily by a law that threatens
punishment to parent or child for truancy. Such laws exist, but school is
established by other tactics: by discrimination against the unschooled, by
centralizing learning tools under the control of teachers, by restricting
public funds earmarked for baby-sitting to salaries for graduates from normal
schools. Protection against laws that impose education, vaccination, or life
prolongation is important, but it is not sufficient. Procedures must be used
that permit any party who feels threatened by compulsory consumption to claim
protection, whatever form the imposition takes. Like intolerable pollution,
intolerable monopoly cannot be defined in advance. The threat can be
anticipated, but the definition of its precise nature can result only from
people’s participation in deciding what may not be produced.

Protection against this general monopoly is as difficult as protection against
pollution. People will face a danger that threatens their own self-interest but
not one that threatens society as a whole. Many more people are against cars
than are against driving them. They are against cars because they pollute and
because they monopolize traffic. They drive cars because they consider the
pollution created by one car insignificant, and because they do not feel
personally deprived of freedom when they drive. It is also difficult to be
protected against monopoly when a society is already littered with roads,
schools, or hospitals, when independent action has been paralyzed for so long
that the ability for it seems to have atrophied, and when simple alternatives
seem beyond the reach of the imagination. Monopoly is hard to get 4d of when it
has frozen not only the shape of the physical world but also the range of
behavior and of imagination. Radical monopoly is generally discovered only when
it is too late.

Commercial monopoly is broken at the cost of the few who profit from it.
Usually, these few manage to evade controls. The cost of radical monopoly is
already borne by the public and will be broken only if the public realizes that
it would be better off paying the costs of ending the monopoly than by
continuing to pay for its maintenance. But the price will not be paid unless
the public learns to value the potential of a convivial society over the
illusion of progress. It will not be paid voluntarily by those who confuse
conviviality with intolerable poverty.

Some of the symptoms of radical monopoly are reaching public awareness, above
all the degree to which frustration grows faster than output in even the most
highly developed countries and under whatever political regime. Policies aimed
to ease this frustration may easily distract attention from the general nature
of the monopoly at its roots, however. The more these reforms succeed in
correcting superficial abuses, the better they serve to bolster the monopoly I
am trying to describe.

The first palliative is consumer protection. Consumers cannot do without cars.
They buy different makes. They discover that most cars are unsafe at any speed.
So they organize to get safer, better, and more durable cars and to get more as
well as wider and safer roads. Yet when consumers gain more confidence in cars,
the victory only increases society’s dependence on high-powered vehicles-public
or private-and frustrates even more those who have to, or would prefer to,
walk.

While the organized self-protection of the addict-consumer immediately raises
the quality of the dope and the power of the peddler, it also may lead
ultimately to limits on growth. Cars may finally become too expensive to
purchase and medicines too expensive to test. By exacerbating the
contradictions inherent in this institutionalization of values, majorities can
more easily become aware of them. Discerning consumers who are discriminatory
in their purchasing habits may finally discover that they can do better by
doing things for themselves.

The second palliative proposed to cure growing frustration with growing output
is planning. The illusion is common that planners with socialist ideals might
somehow create a socialist society in which industrial workers constitute a
majority. The proponents of this idea overlook the fact that anticonvivial and
manipulative tools can fit into a socialist society in only a very limited
measure. Once transportation, education, or medicine is offered by a government
free of cost, its use can be enforced by moral guardians. The underconsumer can
be blamed for sabotage of the national effort. In a market economy, someone who
wants to cure his flu by staying in bed will be penalized only through loss of
income. In a society that appeals to the “people” to meet centrally determined
production goals, resistance to the consumption of medicine becomes an act of
public immorality. Protection against radical monopoly depends on a political
consensus opposed to growth. Such a consensus is diametrically opposed to the
issues now raised by political oppositions, since these converge in the demand
to increase growth and to provide more and better things for more completely
disabled people.

Both the balance that defines man’s need for a hospitable environment and the
balance that defines everyone’s need for authentic activity are now close to
the breaking point. And still this danger does not concern most people. It must
now be explained why most people are either blind to this threat or feel
helpless to correct it. I believe that the blindness is due to the decline in a
third balance-the balance of learning-and that the impotence people experience
is the result of yet a fourth upset in what I call the balance of power.

Overprogramming

The balance of learning is determined by the ratio of two kinds of knowledge in
a society. The first is a result of the creative action of people on their
environment, and the second represents the result of man’s “trivialization” by
his manufactured milieu. Their first kind of knowledge is derived from the
primary involvement of people with each other and from their use of convivial
tools; the second accrues to them as a result of purposeful and programmed
training to which they are subjected. Speaking the mother tongue is learned in
the first way, while some pupils learn mathematics in the second. No sane
person would say that speaking or walking or nursing a child is primarily the
result of education, while competence in mathematics, ballet dancing, or
painting usually is.

The relation between what can be learned from ordinary living and what must be
learned as a result of intentional teaching differs widely with place and time.
It depends very much on rituals. All Muslims learn some Arabic as the result of
prayer. This learning evolves from interaction in a context bounded by
tradition. In much the same manner, peasants pick up the folk-lore of their
region. Class and caste also generate opportunities to learn. The rich acquire
“proper” table manners or accents and insist that these cannot be taught. The
poor learn to fend in dignity where no education could teach the rich to
survive.

Crucial to how much anyone can learn on his own is the structure of his tools:
the less they are convivial, the more they foster teaching. In limited and
well-integrated tribes, knowledge is shared quite equally among most members.
All people know most of what everybody knows. On a higher level of
civilization, new tools are introduced; more people know more things, but not
all know how to execute them equally well. Mastery of skill does not yet imply
a monopoly of understanding. One can understand fully what a goldsmith does
without being one oneself. Men do not have to be cooks to know how to prepare
food. This combination of widely shared information and competence for using it
is characteristic of a society in which convivial tools prevail. The techniques
used are easily understood by observing the artisan at work, but the skills
employed are complex and usually can be acquired only through lengthy and
programmed apprenticeship. Total learning expands when the range of spontaneous
learning widens along with access to an increasing number of taught skills and
both liberty and discipline flower. This expansion of the balance of learning
cannot go on forever; it is self-limiting. It can be optimized, but it cannot
be forcibly extended. One reason is that man’s life span is limited.
Another-just as inexorable-is that the specialization of tools and the division
of labor reinforce each other. When centralization and specialization grow
beyond a certain point, they require highly programmed operators and clients.
More of what each man must know is due to what another man has designed and has
the power to force on him.

The city child is born into an environment made up of systems that have a
different meaning for their designers than for their clients. The inhabitant of
the city is in touch with thousands of systems, but only peripherally with
each. He knows how to operate the TV or the telephone, but their workings are
hidden from him. Learning by primary experience is restricted to
self-adjustment in the midst of packaged commodities. He feels less and less
secure in doing his own thing. Cooking, courtesy, and sex become subject
matters in which instruction is required. The balance of learning deteriorates:
it is skewed in favor of “education.” People know what they have been taught,
but learn little from their own doing. People come to feel that they need
“’education."

Learning thus becomes a commodity, and, like any commodity that is marketed, it
becomes scarce. The nature of this scarcity is hidden-at a high cost-by the
many forms education takes. Education can be programmed preparation for life in
the future in the form of packaged, serial instructions produced by schools, or
it can be constant communication about ongoing life through the output of the
media and through the instructions built into consumer goods. Sometimes these
instructions are attached to the item and must be read. In more thoroughly
designed goods, the shape, color, and provoked associations speak to the user
about the way the item must be handled. Education can also become a periodic
remedy for workers whose original training gets left behind by industrial
innovation. When people become obsolete and need constantly to renew their
educational security, when the accountant must be reprogrammed for each new
generation of computers, then learning has indeed become scarce. Educator
becomes the most vulnerable and confusing issue in the society.

Everywhere the direct cost of training rises faster than the total output. This
has been interpreted in either of two ways. One interpretation assumes that
education is a means to a social end. From this perspective the capitalization
of man through knowledge inputs is a necessary requirement for higher
productivity. The disproportionate growth rate of the educational sector means
total production is nearing an asymptote. To avoid this, ways must be found to
increase the cost-benefit ratio in education. Schools will be the first victims
of a drive for rationalization in the production of knowledge capital. In my
opinion, this is unfortunate. Although the school is destructive and quite
inefficient, its traditional character protects at least some rights of the
pupil. Educators freed from the restraint of schools could be much more
effective and deadly conditioners.

The second interpretation starts from the opposite assumption. According to
this view, education is the most valuable output of institutional growth. The
transition to a stationary state in the production of goods and perhaps even of
energy will usher in an explosive growth in the production of invisible
commodities such as information, education, and fun. In this argument the
marginal utility of education also decreases, but this is no reason to limit
its production. Some economists go even further. In the name of a misnamed
quality of life they want to put the breaks on the manufacturing sector when it
interferes with the growth of the service sector, seemingly unaware of the
stultifying effects of escalating treatments. In neither of these two views is
a distinction made between learning by the use of convivial tools and learning
through manipulation. Both views skew the balance of learning by increasing
manipulative teaching and crushing autonomous questions. Those who treat
education as a means for production and those who treat education as the
supreme luxury product agree on the need for more education. They upset the
balance of learning in favor of more teaching. They assume that a modern world
is inevitably so alien that it has passed beyond the reach of people and can be
known only by mystagogues and disciples.

The transformation of learning into education paralyzes man’s poetic ability,
his power to endow the world with his personal meaning. Man will wither away
just as much if he is deprived of nature, of his own work, or of his deep need
to learn what he wants and not what others have planned that he should learn.
The overdetermination of the physical environment renders it hostile. Radical
monopoly makes people prisoners of welfare. Men overwhelmed by commodities are
rendered impotent and in their rage either kill or die. The corruption of the
balance of learning makes people into puppets of their tools.

Poets and clowns have always risen up against the oppression of creative
thought by dogma. They expose literal-mindedness with metaphor. They
demonstrate the follies of seriousness in a framework of humor. Their intimate
wonder dissolves certainties, banishes fears, and undoes paralysis. The prophet
can denounce creeds and expose superstitions and mobilize persons to use their
lights and wits. Poetry, intuition, and theory can offer intimations of the
advance of dogma against wit that may lead to a revolution in awareness. Only
the separation of Church and State, of compulsory knowledge from political
action, can redress the balance of learning. The law has been used, and can be
used again, to this purpose. The law has protected societies against the
exaggerated claims of its priests, and can protect it against the claims of
educators. Compulsory school attendance or other compulsory treatment is
analogous to compulsory attendance at a religious ritual. The law can
disestablish it. The law can be used against the rising cost of education, and
against the use of education in the reproduction of a class society.

To understand the rising cost of education, we must recognize two facts: first,
that nonconvivial tools create educational side effects which at some point
become intolerable and, second, that education which employs nonconvivial tools
is economically unfeasible. The first recognition opens our eyes to the
possibility of a society where work and leisure and politics would favor
learning and that could function with less formal education; the second
recognition permits us to set up educational arrangements that favor
self-initiated, self-chosen learning, and that relegate programmed teaching to
limited, clearly specified occasions.

Throughout the world, highly capitalized tools require highly capitalized men.
Following the Second World War, economic development penetrated even “backward”
areas. Spot industrialization created an intense demand for schools to program
people not only to operate but also to live with their new tools. The
establishment of more schools in Malaysia or Brazil teaches people the
accountant’s view of the value of time, the bureaucrat’s view of the value of
promotion, the salesman’s view of the value of increased consumption, and the
union leader’s view of the purpose of work. People are taught all this not by
the teacher but by the curriculum hidden in the structure of school. It does
not matter what the teacher teaches so long as the pupil has to attend hundreds
of hours of age-specific assemblies to engage in a routine decreed by the
curriculum and is graded according to his ability to submit to it. People learn
that they acquire more value in the market if they spend more hours in class.
They learn to value progressive consumption of curricula. They learn that
whatever a major institution produces has value, even invisible things such as
education or health. They learn to value grade advancement, passive submission,
and even the standard misbehavior that teachers like to interpret as a sign of
creativity. They learn disciplined competition for the favor of the bureaucrat
who presides over their daily sessions, who is called their teacher as long as
they are in class and their boss when they go to work. They learn to define
themselves as holders of knowledge stock in the specialty in which they have
made investments of their time. They learn to accept their place in society
precisely in the class and career corresponding to the level at which they
leave school and to the field of their academic specialization.

Industrial jobs are arranged so that the better-schooled fit into the scarcer
slots. Scarce jobs are defined as more productive, so people with less
schooling are barred from access to the more desirable goods produced in the
new industries. Industrially produced shoes, bags, clothes, frozen foods, and
soft drinks drive off the market equivalent goods that had been convivially
produced. As production becomes more centralized and more capital-intensive,
the screening process performed by tax-supported schools not only costs more
for those who get through it, but double-charges those who do not.

Education becomes necessary not only to grade people for jobs but to upgrade
them for consumption. As industrial output rises, it pushes the education
system to exercise the social control necessary for its efficient use. The
housing industry in Latin-American countries is a good example of the
educational diseconomies produced by architects. All the major cities in such
countries are surrounded by vast tracts of self-built favelas, barriadas, or
poblacìones. Components for new houses and utilities could be made very cheaply
and designed for self-assembly. People could build more durable, more
comfortable, and more sanitary dwellings, as well as learn about new materials
and systems. But instead of supporting the ability of people to shape their own
environment, the government deposits in these shantytowns public utilities
designed for people who live in standard modern houses. The presence of a new
school, a paved road, and a glass-and-steel police station defines the
professionally built house as the functional unit, and stamps the self-built
home a shanty. The law establishes this definition by refusing a building
permit to people who cannot submit a plan signed by an architect. People are
deprived of their ability to invest their own time with the power to produce
use-value, and are compelled to work for wages and to exchange their earnings
for industrially defined rented space. They are deprived also of the
opportunity to learn while building.

Industrial society demands that some people be taught before they can drive a
truck and that other people be taught before they can build a house. Others
must be taught how to live in apartment buildings. Teachers, social workers,
and policemen cooperate to keep people who have low-paying or occasional jobs
in houses they may not build or change. To accommodate more people on less
land, Venezuela and Brazil experimented with high-rise tenements. First, the
police had to dislodge people from their “slums” and resettle them in
apartments. Then the social workers had to socialize tenants who lacked
sufficient schooling to understand that pigs may not be raised on
eleventh-floor balconies nor beans cultivated in their bathtubs.

In New York people with less than twelve years of schooling are treated like
cripples: they tend to be unemployable, and are controlled by social workers
who decide for them how to live. The radical monopoly of overefficient tools
exacts from society the increasing and costly conditioning of clients. Ford
produces cars that can be repaired only by trained mechanics. Agriculture
departments turn out high-yield crops that can be used only with the assistance
of farm managers who have survived an expensive school race. The production of
better health, higher speeds, or greater yields depends on more disciplined
recipients. The real cost of these doubtful benefits is hidden by unloading
much of them on the schools that produce social control.

Pressure for more and better conditioning of people in the name of education
has led schools over their second watershed. Planners make programs more varied
and complex, but their marginal utility thereby declines. Compulsory attendance
has been extended to the point that it now can be defined by teachers as
independent study on the city streets, or as a field project supervised by the
weavers of TeotitlĂ n del Valle.

Parallel with the growing pretensions of school, other agencies discovered
their educational mission. Newspapers, television, and radio were no longer
just media of communication. They were pressed into the service of
socialization. Periodicals expanded to accommodate all fit news, which meant
that a few professional journalists got vast readerships, while the majority
was reduced to token representation in the “Letters to the Editor” section.

The industrial manufacture and marketing of knowledge reduce the access of
people to convivial tools for self-initiated learning. Witness the fate of the
book. The book is the result of two major inventions that enormously extended
the balance of learning: the alphabet and the printing press. Both techniques
are almost ideally convivial. Almost anybody can learn to use them, and for his
own purpose. They use cheap materials. People can take them or leave them as
they wish. They are not easily controlled by third parties. Even the Soviet
government cannot stop the samizdat circulation of subversive typescripts.

The alphabet and the printing press have in principle deprofessionalized the
recorded word. With the alphabet the merchant broke the monopoly of the priest
over hieroglyphs. With cheap paper and pencil, and later with the typewriter
and modern copying devices, a set of new techniques had in principle opened the
era of nonprofessional, truly convivial, communication by record. The tape
recorder and camera added new media to fully interactive communication. Yet the
manipulative nature of institutions and schooling for the acceptance of
manipulation have put these ideally convivial tools at the service of more
one-way teaching. Schools train people in the use of constantly revised
textbooks. They produce readers of instructions and of news. The per capita
purchase of nontechnical books by high-school graduates declines with the
increased percentage of people who finish high school. More books are written
for the school-trained specialist, and the self-initiated reading of books
declines. More people spend more time hooked on the curriculum defined by new
principals: the publisher, the producer, and the program director. Every week
they wait for Time.

Even the library has become a component of a schooled world. As the library got
“better,” the book was further withdrawn from the handy bookshelf. The
reference librarian placed himself between people and shelves; now he is being
replaced by the computer. Putting the book into huge deposits and into the
hands of computers, the New York Public Library has become so expensive to
operate that it now opens only from ten to six weekdays and is open only
partially on Saturdays. This means that its books have become the specialized
tool of readers who live on a grant to stay away from work and school.

At its best the library is the prototype of a convivial tool. Repositories for
other learning tools can be organized on its model, expanding access to tapes,
pictures, records, and very simple labs filled with the same scientific
instruments with which most of the major breakthroughs of the last century were
made.

Manipulative teaching tools raise the cost of learning. Now we only ask what
people have to learn and then invest in a means to teach them. We should learn
to ask first what people need if they want to learn and provide these tools for
them. Professional teachers laugh at the idea that people would learn more from
random access to learning resources than they can be taught. In fact, they
frequently cite as proof for their skepticism the declining use of libraries.
They overlook the fact that libraries are little used because they have been
organized as formidable teaching devices. Libraries are not used because people
have been trained to demand that they be taught. Neither are contraceptives,
and for analogous reasons we have to explore.

People must learn to live within bounds. This cannot be taught. Survival
depends on people learning fast what they cannot do. They must learn to abstain
from unlimited progeny, consumption, and use. It is impossible to educate
people for voluntary poverty or to manipulate them into self-control. It is
impossible to teach joyful renunciation in a world totally structured for
higher output and the illusion of declining costs.

People must learn why and how to practice contraception. The reason is clear.
Man has evolved in a small corner of the universe. His world is bounded by the
resources of the ecosphere, and can accommodate only a limited number of
people. Technology has transformed the characteristics of this niche. The
ecosphere now accommodates a larger number of people, each less vitally adapted
to the environment—each on the average having less space, less freedom to
survive with simple means, fewer roots in tradition. The attempt to make a
better environment has turned out to be as presumptuous as the attempt to
create better health, education, or communication. As a result there are now
more people, most of them less at home in the world. This large population can
survive because of new tools. In turn, it spurs the search for even more
powerful tools, and thereby demands more radical monopoly; this monopoly, in
its turn, calls for more and more education. But, paradoxically, what people
most need to learn, they cannot be taught or educated to do. If they are
voluntarily to keep their numbers and consumption within bounds, they must
learn to do so by living active and responsible lives, or they will
perish—passive though well informed, frustrated yet resigned. Voluntary and
therefore effective population control is impossible under conditions of
radical monopoly and overprogramming. An efficient, specialized birth control
program must fail in the same way that schools and hospitals fail. It can start
with a futile attempt at effective seduction. It will logically escalate to
enforced sterilization and abortion. Finally, it will provide a rationale for
mega-deaths.

Voluntary and effective contraception is now absolutely necessary. If such
contraception is not practiced in the very near future, humanity is in danger
of being crushed by its own size rather than by the power of its tools. But
this universal practice cannot possibly be the result of some miracle tool. A
new practice, inverse to the present, can only be the result of a new
relationship between people and their tools. The universal practice of
effective contraception is a necessary premise for the limitation of tools
which I advocate. But equally, the psychological inversion that will accompany
a limitation of tools is a premise for the convivial psychological pressure
necessary for effective contraception.

The devices needed for birth control are a paradigm for modern convivial tools.
They incorporate science in instruments that can be handled by any reasonably
prudent and well-apprenticed person. They provide new ways to engage in the
millenary practice of contraception, sterilization, and abortion. They are
cheap enough to be made universally available. They are made to fit alternate
tasks, beliefs, and situations. They are obviously tools that structure the
bodily relationship of each individual to himself and to others. To be
effective, some must be used by every adult, and many of them must be used
every day. Birth control is an immense task. It must be accomplished within one
decade. It can be accomplished only in a convivial manner. It is ridiculous to
try to control populations with tools which by their nature are convivial while
conditioning the population by formal education to fit more effectively into an
industrial and professional world. It is absurd to expect that Brazilian
peasants can be taught to depend on doctors for injections and prescriptions,
on lawyers for conflict resolution, and on teachers for learning to read, while
asking them to use the condom on their own. But it is equally fanciful to
expect that Indian doctors will allow illiterate but well-trained hospital
assistants to compete with them in the performance of sterilizations. If the
public realized that this delicate intervention could be equally or even more
carefully performed by a layman whose attention, dexterity, and programming
skills were refined in the weaving of saris, doctors would lose their monopoly
on all interventions which are economically feasible for any majority of
people. Professional taboos and industrial tools stand and fall together once
truly rational, postindustrial tools are available. Only the convergent use of
convivial tools in all significant areas of need-satisfaction can render their
use in each sector truly effective. Only among convivially structured tools can
people learn to use the new levels of power that modern technology can
incorporate in them.

Polarization

The present organization of tools impels societies to grow both in population
and in levels of affluence. This growth takes place at the opposite ends of the
privilege spectrum. The underprivileged grow in number, while the already
privileged grow in affluence. The underprivileged thus strengthen their
frustrating claims, while the rich defend their presumed rights and needs.
Hunger and impotence lead the poor to demand rapid industrialization, and the
defense of growing luxuries pushes the rich into more frantic production. Power
is polarized, frustration is generalized, and the alternative of greater
happiness at lower affluence is pushed into the blind spot of social vision.

This blindness is a result of the broken balance of learning. People who are
hooked on teaching are conditioned to be customers for everything else. They
see their own personal growth as an accumulation of institutional outputs, and
prefer what institutions make over what they themselves can do. They repress
the ability to discover reality by their own lights. The skewed balance of
learning explains why the radical monopoly of commodities has become
imperceptible. It does not explain why people feel impotent to correct those
profound disorders which they do perceive.

This helplessness is the result of a fourth disruption: the growing
polarization of power. Under the pressure of an expanding mega-machine, power
is concentrated in a few hands, and the majority becomes dependent on handouts.
New levels of luxuriant overproduction grow faster than the output of
commodities which this wanton production imposes.

A 3 percent increase in the standard of living of the U.S. population costs
twenty-five times as much as a similar increase in the living standard of
India, despite the greater size and more rapid growth of the Indian population.
Significant benefits for the poor demand a reduction of the resources used by
the rich, while significant benefits for the rich make murderous demands on the
resources of the poor. Yet the rich pretend that by exploiting the poor nations
they will become rich enough to create a hyperindustrial abundance for all. The
Ă©lites of poor countries share this fantasy.

The rich will get richer and many more of the poor will be-come destitute
during the next ten years. But anguish about the hungry should not prevent us
from understanding the structural problem of power distribution that
constitutes the fourth dimension of destructive overgrowth. Unchecked
industrialization modernizes poverty. Poverty levels rise and the gap between
rich and poor widens. These two aspects must be seen together or the nature of
destructive polarization will be missed.

Poverty levels rise because industrial staples are turned into basic
necessities and have a unit cost beyond what a majority could ever pay. The
radical monopoly of industries has created new types of demeaning poverty in
societies of sometimes profligate affluence. The former subsistence farmer is
put out of business by the green revolution. He earns more as a laborer, but he
cannot give his children their former diet. More importantly, the U.S. citizen
with ten times his income is also desperately poor. Both get increasingly less
at greater cost.

The other side of modernized poverty is related but distinct. The power gap
widens because control over production is centralized to make the most goods
for the greatest number. Whereas rising poverty levels are due to the structure
of industrial outputs, the gaping power lag is due to the structure of inputs.
To seek remedies for the former without simultaneously dealing with the latter
would only postpone and aggravate the world-wide modernization of poverty.

The surface effects of industrially concentrated power can be obviated by
income equalization. Progressive taxes without loopholes can be supplemented by
social security, income supports, and equal welfare benefits for all.
Confiscation of private capital beyond a certain limit can be attempted.
Keeping maximum close to minimum income is an even tougher way to stem personal
enrichment through the management of corporate power. But such curbs on
personal income will be effective only in regulating private consumption. It
has no effect on equalizing the privileges that really count in a society where
the job has become more important than the home. As long as workers are graded
by the amount of manpower capital they represent, those who hold high
denominations of knowledge stock will be certified for the use of all kinds of
timesaving privileges. The concentration of privileges on a few is in the
nature of industrial dominance.

With the introduction of agriculture and animal husbandry, patriarchal
government and some centralization of power became feasible. At this stage
political means could be used to get the power of many slaves under one man’s
control. One man could transform a multitude into a tool for the realization of
his design. Religion, ideology, and the whip were the principal means of
control. But the amount of power controlled was small. The centralization of
power which now seems normal could not have been imagined even a century ago.

In modern society, energy conversion enormously exceeds the body power of all
men. Manpower stands to mechanical power in a ratio of 1:15 in China and 1:300
in the U.S.A. Switches concentrate the control over this power more effectively
than whips ever could. The social distribution of control over power inputs has
been radically changed. If capital means the power to make effective change,
power inflation has reduced most people to paupers.

As tools get bigger, the number of potential operators declines. There are
always fewer operators of cranes than of wheelbarrows. As tools become more
efficient, more scarce resources are put at the service of the operator. On a
Guatemalan construction site, only the engineer gets air conditioning in his
trailer. He is also the only one whose time is deemed so precious that he must
be flown to the capital, and whose decisions seem so important that they are
transmitted by shortwave radio. He has of course earned his privileges by
cornering the largest amount of tax money and using it to acquire a university
degree. The Indio who works on the gang does not notice the relative increase
in privilege between him and his Ladino gang boss, but the geometricians and
draftsmen who also went to school, but did not graduate, feel the heat and the
distance from their families in a new and acute way. Their relative poverty has
been aggravated by their bosses’ claim to greater efficiency.

Never before have tools approached present power. Never before have they been
so integrated at the service of a small Ă©lite. Kings could not claim divine
right with as little challenge as executives claim services for the sake of
greater production. The Russians justify supersonic transport by saying it will
economize the time of their scientists. High-speed transportation, broad
band-width communication, special health maintenance, and unlimited
bureaucratic assistance are all explained as requirements to get the most out
of the most highly capitalized people.

A society with very large tools must rely on multiple devices to keep the
majority from claiming the most expensive packages of privilege. These must be
reserved for the most productive individuals. The most prestigious way to
measure a person’s productivity is by the price tag on his education
consumption. The higher a person’s knowledge capital, the greater the social
value placed on the decisions he “makes” and the more legitimate is his claim
to high-level packages of industrial outputs.

When the legitimacy of educational certification breaks down, other more
primitive forms of discrimination are bound to assume renewed importance.
People are judged to be less valuable manpower because they are born in the
Third World, because they are black, because they are women, because they
belong to the wrong group or party, or because they cannot pass the right
battery of tests. The scene is set for the multiplication of minority
movements, each one claiming its share, and each one destined to be foiled by
its own intent.

Hierarchies must rise and conglomerate as they extend over fewer and larger
corporations. A seat in a high-rise job is the most coveted and contested
product of expanding industry. The lack of schooling, compounded with sex,
color, and peculiar persuasions, now keeps most people down. Minorities
organized by women, or blacks, or the unorthodox succeed at best in getting
some of their members through school and into an expensive job. They claim
victory when they get equal pay for equal rank. Paradoxically, these movements
strengthen the idea that unequal graded work is necessary and that high-rise
hierarchies are necessary to produce what an egalitarian society needs. If
properly schooled, the black porter will blame himself for not being a black
lawyer. At the same time, schooling generates a new intensity of frustration
which ultimately can act as social dynamite.

It does not matter for what specific purpose minorities now organize if they
seek an equal share in consumption, an equal place on the pyramid of
production, or equal nominal power in the government of ungovernable tools. As
long as a minority acts to increase its share within a growth-oriented society,
the final result will be a keener sense of inferiority for most of its members.

Movements that seek control over existing institutions give them a new
legitimacy, and also render their contradictions more acute. Changes in
management are not revolutions. The shared control of workers and women, or
blacks and the young, does not constitute a social reconstruction if what they
claim to control are industrial corporations. Such changes are at best new ways
to administer an industrial mode of production which, thanks to these shifts,
continues unchallenged. More commonly, these changes are professional
insurgencies against the status quo. They expand management, and, at an even
faster rate, they degrade labor. A new desk usually means more
capital-intensive production in one firm and a new guarantee of so-called
underemployment somewhere else in society. A majority loses further productive
ability, and a minority is forced to seek new reasons and weapons to protect
its privilege.

New classes of underconsumers and of underemployed are one of the inevitable
by-products of industrial progress. Organization makes them aware of their
common plight. At present articulate minorities-often claiming the leadership
of majorities—seek equal treatment. If one day they were to seek equal work
rather than equal pay—equal inputs rather than equal outputs—they could be the
pivot of social reconstruction. Industrial society could not possibly resist a
strong women’s movement, for example, which would lead to the demand that all
people, without distinction, do equal work. Women are integrated into all
classes and races. Most of their daily activities are performed in
nonindustrial ways. Industrial societies remain viable precisely because women
are there to perform those daily tasks which resist industrialization. It is
easier to imagine that the North American continent would cease to exploit the
underindustrialization of South America than that it would cease to use its
women for industry-resistant chores. In a society ruled by the standards of
industrial efficiency, housework is rendered inhuman and devalued. It would be
rendered even less tolerable if it were given pro-forma industrial status. The
further expansion of industry would be brought to a halt if women forced upon
us the recognition that society is no longer viable if a single mode of
production prevails. The effective recognition that not two but several equally
valuable, dignified, and important modes of production must coexist within any
viable society would bring industrial expansion under control. Growth would
stop if women obtained equally creative work for all, instead of demanding
equal rights over the gigantic and expanding tools now appropriated by men.

Obsolescence

Convivial reconstruction demands the disruption of the present monopoly of
industry, but not the abolition of all industrial production. It does imply the
adoption of labor-intensive tools, but not the regression to inefficient tools.
It requires a considerable reduction of all kinds of now compulsory therapy,
but not the elimination of teaching, guidance, or healing for which individuals
take personal responsibility. Neither must a convivial society be stagnant. Its
dynamics depend on wide distribution of the power to make effective change. In
the present scheme of large-scale obsolescence a few corporate centers of
decision-making impose compulsory innovation on the entire society. Continued
convivial reconstruction depends on the degree to which society protects the
power of individuals and of communities to choose their own styles of life
through effective, small-scale renewal.

I have shown that social polarization is the result of two complementary
factors: the excessive cost of industrially produced and advertised products,
and the excessive rarity of jobs that are considered highly productive.
Obsolescence, on the other hand, produces devaluation—which is the result not
of a certain general rate of change but of change in those products which
exercise a radical monopoly. Social polarization depends on the fact that
industrial inputs and outputs come in units so large that most people are
excluded from them. Obsolescence, on the other hand, can become intolerable
even when people are not directly priced out of the market. Product elaboration
and obsolescence are two distinct dimensions of overefficiency, both of which
underpin a society of hierarchically layered privilege.

It does not really matter if forced obsolescence becomes destructive of old
models or of old functions, if Ford discontinues the distribution of spare
parts for its 1955 model, or if the police rule old cars off the road because
they lack features that safety lobbyists have made standard. Renewal is
intrinsic to the industrial mode of production coupled to the ideology of
progress. Products cannot be improved unless huge machines are retooled—and in
the technical sense engineers have given this word. To make this pay, huge
markets must be created for the new model. The most effective way to open a
market is to identify the use of what is new as an important privilege. If this
identification succeeds, the old model is devalued and the self-interest of the
consumer is wedded to the ideology of never-ending and progressive consumption.
Individuals are socially graded according to the number of years their bill of
goods is out of date. Some people can afford to keep up with the Joneses who
buy the latest model, while others still use cars, stoves, and radios that are
five to ten years old-and probably spend their vacations in places that are
just as many years out of style. They know where they fit on the social ladder.

The social grading of individuals by the age of the things they use is not just
a capitalist practice. Wherever the economy is built around the large-scale
production of elaborate and obsolescent packages of staples, it is only the
privileged who have access to the newest model of services and goods. Only a
few nurses get the most recent course in anesthesiological nursing, and only a
few functionaries get the new model of a “people’s car.” The members of this
minority within a minority recognize each other by the recent date at which the
products they use came onto the market, and it makes little difference whether
they use them at home or at work.

Industrial innovations are costly, and managers must justify their high cost by
producing measurable proof of their superiority. Under the rule of industrial
socialism, pseudo science will have to provide the alibi, while in market
economies, appeal can be made to a survey of consumer opinion. In any case,
periodic innovations in goods or tools foster the belief that anything new will
be proven better. This belief has become an integral part of the modern world
view. It is forgotten that whenever a society lives by this delusion, each
marketed unit generates more wants than it satisfies. If new things are made
because they are better, then the things most people use are not quite good.
New models constantly renovate poverty. The consumer feels the lag between what
he has and what he ought to get. He believes that products can be made
measurably more valuable and allows himself to be constantly re-educated for
their consumption. The “better” replaces the “good” as the fundamental
normative concept.

In a society caught up in the race for the better, limits on change are
experienced as a threat. The commitment to the better at any cost makes the
good impossible at all costs. Failure to renew the bill of goods frustrates the
expectation of what is possible, while renewal of the bill of goods intensifies
the expectations of unattainable progress. What people have and what they are
about to get are equally exasperating to them. Accelerating change has become
both addictive and intolerable. At this point the balance among stability,
change, and tradition has been upset; society has lost both its roots in shared
memories and its bearings for innovation. Judgment on precedents has lost its
value.

One of the major objections against a stationary-state economy is the fear that
the production of a limited and durable number of goods would set intolerable
limits on the freedom of innovation and of scientific exploration. This would
be justified if I were discussing the transition from the present industrial
society to its next model: clean and limited production of goods and unlimited
growth in the service sector. I am not, however, discussing the evolution of
industrial society, but the transition to a new mixed mode of production.

Industrial innovations are planned, trivial, and conservative. The renewal of
convivial tools would be as unpredictable, creative, and lively as the people
who use them. Scientific progress is also dulled by the present identification
of research with industrial development. Most of the cost of research derives
from its competitive nature and pressure; most of its tools are restricted to
people who have been carefully programmed to look at the world through the
prisms of profit and power; most of its goals are set by the need for more
power and efficiency. Leisurely scientific research does not exclude a bevatron
or some ultracentrifuges; removal of access restrictions now created by schools
would again admit the curious, rather than the orthodox, to the alchemist’s
vault; and study for its own sake would produce more surprises than team
research on how to eliminate production snags.

A changeless society would be as intolerable for people as the present society
of constant change. Convivial reconstruction requires limits on the rate of
compulsory change. An unlimited rate of change makes lawful community
meaningless. Law is based on the retrospective judgment of peers about
circumstances that occur ordinarily and are likely to occur again. If the rate
of change which affects all circumstances accelerates beyond some point, such
judgments cease to be valid. Lawful society breaks down. Social control does
not accommodate community participation and becomes the function of experts.
Educators define how people are to be trained and retrained throughout their
lives—shaped and reshaped until they fit the demands of industry and are
attracted by its profits. Ideologues define what is right or wrong. The tooling
of man for the milieu becomes the major industry when this milieu changes
beyond a certain rate; then man’s need for language and law, for memories and
myths, imposes limits to the change of tools.

Frustration

I have identified five realms in each of which the efficiency of tools can
upset the balance of life. Faulty technology can render the environment
uninhabitable. Radical monopoly can force the demand for affluence to the point
of paralyzing the ability to work. Overprogramming can transform the world into
a treatment ward in which people are constantly taught, socialized, normalized,
tested, and reformed. Centralization and packaging of institutionally produced
values can polarize society into irreversible structural despotism. And,
finally, engineered obsolescence can break all bridges to a normative past. In
each or several of these dimensions a tool can threaten survival by making it
unfeasible for most people to relate themselves in action to one of the great
dimensions of their environment.

In the assessment of society it is not sufficient to select just one of these
realms. Each one of these balances must be preserved.

Even clean and equally distributed electricity could lead to intolerable
radical monopoly of power tools over man’s personal energy. Not only compulsory
schools but pervasive teaching media can be used to upset the balance of
learning or to polarize society into an oppressive meritocracy. Any form of
engineering can lead to unendurable obsolescence. It is true that man’s
physical niche is threatened; but just as he evolved within one particular
physiological environment, so he also evolved within a social, political and
psychological environment which can also be irreversibly destroyed. Mankind may
wither and disappear because he is deprived of basic structures of language,
law, and myth, just as much as he can be smothered by smog. Future shock can
destroy what is human just as much as radical monopoly or social polarization.

I have argued that in each of five realms conceptual criteria can be used to
recognize escalating imbalance. These criteria serve as guidelines for
political processes by which the members of a technological society can develop
constitutive boundaries within which tools must be kept. Such boundaries
circumscribe the kind of power structures that can be kept under the control of
people. By growing beyond this range, tools escape political control. Man’s
ability to claim his rights is extinguished by his bondage to processes over
which he has no say. Biological functions, work, meaning, freedom, and
roots—insofar as he can still enjoy them-are reduced to concessions, which
optimize the logic of tools. Man is reduced to an indefinitely malleable
resource of a corporate state. Without constitutive limits translated into
constitutional provisions survival in dignity and freedom is squelched.

Present research is overwhelmingly concentrated in two directions: research and
development for breakthroughs to the better production of better wares and
general systems analysis concerned with protecting man for further consumption.
Future research ought to lead in the opposite direction; let us call it
counterfoil research. Counterfoil research also has two major tasks: to provide
guidelines for detecting the incipient stages of murderous logic in a tool; and
to devise tools and tool systems that optimize the balance of life, thereby
maximizing liberty for all.

Counterfoil research is not a new branch of science, nor is it some
interdisciplinary project. It is the dimensional analysis of the relationship
of man to his tools. It seems obvious that each person lives in several
concentric social environments. To each social environment there corresponds a
set of natural scales. This is true for the primary group, for the production
unit, for the city, the state, and the organization of men on the globe. To
each of these social environments there correspond certain characteristic
distances, periods, populations, energy sources, and energy sinks. In each of
these dimensions tools that require time periods or spaces or energies much
beyond the order of corresponding natural scales are dysfunctional. They upset
the homeostasis which renders the particular environment viable. At present we
tend to define human needs in terms of abstract goals and treat these as
problems to which technocrats can apply escalating solutions. What we need is
rational research on the dimensions within which technology can be used by
concrete communities to implement their aspirations without frustrating
equivalent aspirations by others.

The barriers beyond which destruction looms are of a different nature from the
boundaries within which a society freely constrains its tools. The former
establish the realm of possible survival; the latter determine the shape of a
culturally preferred environment. The former define the conditions for uniform
regimentation; the latter set the conditions of convivial justice. The
boundaries of doom are constitutive requirements common to all postindustrial
societies. Statutory characteristics setting more narrow bounds than those
absolutely necessary are the result of joint options made in a commonweal, as a
result of its members’ defining their life style and their level of liberty.

Supersonic transports could be easily ruled out to protect the environment, air
transport to avoid social polarization, cars to protect against radical
monopoly. The balance of purpose I want to highlight at this point provides a
further criterion by which to select desirable tools. In view of this balance
it might even be possible to exclude public transportation moving at high
velocity.

There is a form of malfunction in which growth does not yet tend toward the
destruction of life, yet renders a tool antagonistic to its specific aims.
Tools, in other words, have an optimal, a tolerable, and a negative range.
Tolerable overefficiency also disturbs a balance, but a balance of a subtler
and more subjective kind than those discussed before. The balance here
threatened is that between personal cost and return. It can be expressed more
generally as the perception of the balance between means and ends. When ends
become subservient to the tools chosen for their sake, the user first feels
frustration and finally either abstains from their use or goes mad. Compulsory
maddening behavior in Hades was considered the ultimate punishment reserved for
blasphemy. Sisyphus was forced to keep rolling a stone uphill, only to see it
roll back down. When maddening behavior becomes the standard of a society,
people learn to compete for the right to engage in it. Envy blinds people and
makes them compete for addiction.

Wherever the maximum velocity of any one type of commuter vehicle grows beyond
a certain mph, the travel time and the cost of transportation for the median
commuter is increased. If the maximum velocity at any one point of a commuter
system goes beyond a certain mph, most people are obliged to spend more time in
traffic jams, or waiting for connections, or recovering from accidents. They
will also have to spend more time paying for the transportation system they are
compelled to use.

The critical velocity depends to a certain extent on a variety of factors:
geography, culture, market controls, level of technology, and money flow. With
so many variables affecting a quantity, it would seem that its value could
fluctuate over a very wide range. Just the contrary is true. Once it is
understood that we refer to any vehicular velocity in the transportation of
people within a community, we find that the range within which the critical
velocity can vary is very narrow. It is, in fact, so narrow and so low that it
seems improbable and not worth the time of most traffic engineers to worry
about.

Commuter transportation leads to negative returns when it admits, anywhere in
the system, speeds much above those reached on a bicycle. Once the barrier of
bicycle velocity is broken at any point in the system, the total per capita
monthly time spent at the service of the travel industry increases.

High output leads to time lack. Time becomes scarce, partly because it takes
time to consume goods and to undergo therapies, and partly because dependence
on production makes abstention from it more costly. The richer we get in a
consumer society, the more acutely we become aware of how many grades of
value—of both leisure and labor—we have climbed. The higher we are on the
pyramid, the less likely we are to give up time to simple idleness and to
apparently nonproductive pursuits. The joy of listening to the neighborhood
finch is easily overshadowed by stereophonic recordings of “Bird Songs of the
World,” the walk through the park downgraded by preparations for a packaged
bird-watching tour into the jungle. It becomes difficult to economize time when
all commitments are for the long run. Staffan Linder points out that there is a
strong tendency for us to over-commit the future, so that w hen the future
becomes present, we seem to be conscious all the time of having an acute
scarcity, simply because we have committed ourselves to about thirty hours a
day instead of twenty-four. In addition to the mere fact that time has
competitive uses and high marginal utility in an affluent society, this
overcommitment creates a sense of pressure and harriedness.

Life in a society where speedy transportation is taken for granted renders time
scarce in both of these ways. Activities related to the use of speedy vehicles
by many people in a society occupy an increasing percentage of the time budget
of most members of that society, as the speed of the vehicles increases beyond
a certain point. Beyond this point the competition of transportation activities
with stationary activities becomes fierce, especially competition for the
allocation of limited real estate and available energy. This competition seems
to grow exponentially with the rise of speed. The time reserved for commuting
displaces both work and leisure time. Hence, the speedier vehicles are, the
more it becomes important to keep them filled at all times. If they are
individual capsules, they tend to become disproportionately costly and scarce.
If they are public vehicles, they tend to be large, and run at infrequent
intervals or along only a few routes.

As speed increases, the adaptation of life patterns to vehicles becomes more
tyrannical. It becomes necessary to make constant corrections and amendments to
the allocation of shorter periods. It becomes necessary to make appointments
and commitments months or even years ahead. Since some of these commitments,
which have been made at great cost, cannot be kept, there is a sense of
constant failure which produces a sense of constant tension. Man has only a
limited ability to submit to programming. When speed increases beyond a certain
point, the transportation system vies with other systems in exhausting human
tolerance for social controls.

Machines turn against men at a much lower level of power than would be ruled
out by the first five criteria. But while these criteria identify necessary
safeguards for life and liberty, the balance of purpose depends on a different
kind of value. Conceptual rather than empirical criteria can be set for the
constitutional limitation of power. It ought to be relatively easy for a
majority to rule what abuse it will take from any minority, or what damage it
will not expose its offspring to. The recognition of the most socially
desirable power of a tool is of a different nature; it can only be the outcome
of political procedure. The value obtained for time wasted on speed
transportation is conditioned by the consensus in a community about the level
of its freedom as a concrete option of its civilization.

Transportation beyond bicycle speeds demands power inputs from the environment.
Velocity translates directly into power, and soon power needs increase
exponentially. In the United States, 22 percent of the energy converted drives
vehicles, and another 10 percent keeps roads open for them. The amount of
energy is comparable to the total energy—except for domestic heating—required
for the combined economies of India and China. The energy used up in the United
States for the sole purpose of driving vehicles built to accelerate beyond
bicycle speed would suffice to add auxiliary motors to about twenty times that
many vehicles for people all over the world who want to move at bicycle speeds
and do not or cannot push the pedals because they are sick or old, or because
they want to transport a heavy load or move over a great distance, or because
they just want to relax. Simply on the basis of equal distribution on a
world-wide scale, speeds above those attained by bicycles could be ruled out.
It is of course mere fantasy to assume an egalitarian consensus sufficiently
strong to accept such a proposal. At closer inspection though, many communities
will find that the very same speed limit necessary for equal distribution of
mobility is also very close to the optimum velocity giving maximum value to
community life. At 20 mph constant speed Phileas Fogg could have made his trip
around the world in half of eighty days. Simulation studies would be useful for
exploring imaginative policies that seek optimal liberty with convivial power
tools. To whose advantage would Calcutta’s traffic flow stabilize if speeds
were limited to 10 mph? What price would Peru’s military pay for limiting the
nation’s speed to 20mph? What gains in equality, activity, health, and freedom
would result from limiting all other vehicles to the speed of bicycles and
sailing ships?

Negative returns are not unique to transportation. Ninety percent of all
medical care for patients with terminal diseases is unrelated to their health;
such treatment tends to increase suffering and disability without demonstrably
lengthening life. The maximum feasibility of service for the optimum care of an
individual patient lies within a certain range. Beyond this range medical bills
measure the health of a patient in the same way that GNP measures the wealth of
a nation. Both add on the same scale the market value of benefits and the
defensive expenditures which become necessary to offset the unwanted side
effects of their production. The technological escalation of medicine first
ceases to serve healing and then ceases to prolong life. It turns into a
death-denying ritual of terminal care: a final race in which the personality
best fitted to machines turns in the most spectacular performance.

Counterfoil research is concerned first with an analysis of increasing marginal
disutility and the menace of growth. It is then concerned with the discovery of
general systems of institutional structure which optimize convivial production.
This kind of research meets psychological resistance. Growth has become
addictive. Like heroin addiction, the habit distorts basic value judgments.
Addicts of any kind are willing to pay increasing amounts for declining
satisfactions. They have become tolerant to escalating marginal disutility.
They are blind to deeper frustration because they are absorbed in playing for
always mounting stakes. Minds accustomed to thinking that transportation ought
to provide speedy motion rather than reduction of the time and effort spent
moving are boggled by this contrary hypothesis. Man is inherently mobile, and
speeds higher than those he can achieve by the use of his limbs must be proven
to be of great social value to warrant support by public sacrifice.

Counterfoil research must clarify and dramatize the relationship of people to
their tools. It ought to hold constantly before the public the resources that
are available and the consequences of their use in various ways. It should
impress on people the existence of any trend that threatens one of the major
balances on which life depends. Counterfoil research leads to the
identification of those classes of people most immediately hurt by such trends
and helps people to identify themselves as members of such classes. It points
out how a particular freedom can be jeopardized for the members of various
groups which have otherwise conflicting interests. Counterfoil research
involves the public by showing that the demands for freedom of any group or
alliance can be identified with the implicit interest of all.

Withdrawal from growth mania will be painful, but mostly for members of the
generation which has to experience the transition and above all for those most
disabled by consumption. If their plight could be vividly remembered, it might
help the next generation avoid what they know would enslave them.

Recovery

I have discussed five dimensions on which the balance of life depends. In each
I have indicated tendencies that must be kept in equilibrium to maintain the
homeostasis which constitutes human life. I have argued that the control of
natural forces is functional only if the use of nature does not make nature
useless for man. I have argued that institutions are functional when they
promote a delicate balance between what people can do for themselves and what
tools at the service of anonymous institutions can do for them. Formal
instruction also depends on a balance. Special arrangements must never outweigh
opportunities for independent learning. An increase in social mobility can
render society more human, but only if at the same time there is a narrowing of
the difference in power which separates the few from the many. Finally, an
increase in the rate of innovation is of value only when with it rootedness in
tradition, fullness of meaning, and security are also strengthened.

A tool can grow out of man’s control, first to become his master and finally to
become his executioner. Tools can rule men sooner than they expect: the plow
makes man the lord of a garden but also the refugee from a dust bowl. Nature’s
revenge can produce children less fit for life than their fathers, and born
into a world less fit for them. Homo faber can be turned into a sorcerer’s
apprentice. Specialization can make his every day so complicated that it
becomes estranged from his activity. Addiction to progress can enslave all men
to a race in which none ever reaches the goal.

There are two ranges in the growth of tools: the range within which machines
are used to extend human capability and the range in which they are used to
contract, eliminate, or replace human functions. In the first, man as an
individual can exercise authority on his own behalf and therefore assume
responsibility. In the second, the machine takes over—first reducing the range
of choice and motivation in both the operator and the client, and second
imposing its own logic and demand on both. Survival depends on establishing
procedures which permit ordinary people to recognize these ranges and to opt
for survival in freedom, to evaluate the structure built into tools and
institutions so they can exclude those which by their structure are
destructive, and control those which are useful. Exclusion of the malignant
tool and control of the expedient tool are the two major priorities for
politics today. Multiple limits to overefficiency must be expressed in language
that is simple and politically effective. This urgent task is faced, however,
with three formidable obstacles: the idolatry of science, the corruption of
ordinary language, and loss of respect for the formal process by which social
decisions are made.

The Demythologization of Science

Above all, political discussion is stunned by a delusion about science. This
term has come to mean an institutional enterprise rather than a personal
activity, the solving of puzzles rather than the unpredictably creative
activity of individual people. Science is now used to label a spectral
production agency which turns out better knowledge just as medicine produces
better health. The damage done by this misunderstanding about the nature of
knowledge is even more fundamental than the damage done to the conceptions of
health, education, or mobility by their identification with institutional
outputs. False expectations of better health corrupt society, but they do so in
only one particular sense. They foster a declining concern with healthful
environments, healthy life styles, and competence in the personal care of one’s
neighbor. Deceptions about health are circumstantial. The institutionalization
of knowledge leads to a more general and degrading delusion. It makes people
dependent on having their knowledge produced for them. It leads to a paralysis
of the moral and political imagination.

This cognitive disorder rests on the illusion that the knowledge of the
individual citizen is of less value than the “knowledge” of science. The former
is the opinion of individuals. It is merely subjective and is excluded from
policies. The latter is “objective”—defined by science and promulgated by
expert spokesmen. This objective knowledge is viewed as a commodity which can
be refined, constantly improved, accumulated and fed into a process, now called
“decision-making.” This new mythology of governance by the manipulation of
knowledge-stock inevitably erodes reliance on government by people.

The world does not contain any information. It is as it is. Information about
it is created in the organism through its interaction with the world. To speak
about storage of information outside the human body is to fall into a semantic
trap. Books or computers are part of the world. They can yield information when
they are looked upon. We move the problem of learning and of cognition nicely
into the blind spot of our intellectual vision if we confuse vehicles for
potential information with information itself. We do the same when we confuse
data for potential decision with decision itself.

Overconfidence in “better knowledge” becomes a self-fulfilling prophecy. People
first cease to trust their own judgment and then want to be told the truth
about what they know. Overconfidence in “better decision-making” first hampers
people’s ability to decide for themselves and then undermines their belief that
they can decide.

The growing impotence of people to decide for themselves affects the structure
of their expectations. People are transformed from contenders for scarce
resources into competitors for abundant promises. Adjudication by ordeal is
replaced by recourse to secular rituals. These rituals are organized as
frenzied consumption of the offerings of some menu: a curriculum, a therapy, or
a court case. The promise that science will provide affluence for all and for
each according to his objectively verified merits deprives personal conflict of
its creative legitimacy. People who have unlearned how to decide about their
own rights on their own evidence become pawns in a world game operated by
mega-machines. No longer can each person make his or her own contribution to
the constant renewal of society. Recourse to better knowledge produced by
science not only voids personal decisions of the power to contribute to an
ongoing historical and social process, it also destroys the rules of evidence
by which experience is traditionally shared. The knowledge-consumer depends on
getting packaged programs funneled into him. He finds security in the
expectation that his neighbor and his boss have seen the same programs and read
the same columns. The procedure by which personal certainties are honestly
exchanged is eroded by the increasing recourse to exceptionally qualified
knowledge produced by a science, profession, or political party. Mothers poison
their children on the adman’s or the M.D.’s advice. Even in the courtroom and
in parliament, scientific hearsay-well hidden under the veil of expert
testimony-biases juridical and political decisions. Judges, governments, and
voters abdicate their own evidence about the necessity of resolving conflicts
in a situation of defined and permanent scarcity and opt for further growth on
the basis of data which they admittedly cannot fully understand.

When communities have grown overconfident in science, they leave it to experts
to set the upper limits on growth. This mandate rests on a fallacy. Experts can
define standards at levels slightly below those at which people complain with
too much force. They can keep the public sullen and forestall mutiny. But
closed peer groups cannot be entrusted with self-restraint in furthering their
expert knowledge. Nor can we expect them to be representative of the common
man. Scientific expertise cannot define what people will tolerate. No person
can abdicate the right to decide on this for himself. It is, of course,
possible to experiment on humans. Nazi doctors explored what the organism can
endure. They found out how long the average person can survive torture, but
this did not tell them anything about what someone can tolerate. These doctors
were condemned under a statute signed in Nuremberg two days after Hiroshima and
the day before the bomb was dropped on Nagasaki.

What a population will endure remains beyond experiment. We can tell what
happens to particular groups of people under extreme circumstances—in prison,
on an expedition, or in an experiment. Such precedents cannot serve as measures
for the privations which a society will tolerate as a result of tools or rules
made for its service. Scientific measurements may suggest that a certain
endeavor threatens a major balance of life. Only the informed judgment of a
majority of prudent men who act on the much more complex basis of everyday
evidence can determine how to limit individual and social goals. Science can
clarify the dimensions of man’s realm in the universe. Only a political
community can dialectically choose the dimensions of the roof under which its
members will live.

The Rediscovery of Language

Between 1830 and 1850 a dozen inventors formulated the law of the conservation
of energy. Most of them were engineers, and independently from each other they
redefined the floating life force of the universe in terms of work machines
could perform. Measurements that could be taken in the laboratory became the
scale by which the mysterious cosmic nexus—called vis viva for centuries—could
henceforth be defined.

During the same period industry successfully competed with other modes of
production for the first time. Industrial performance became the scale
according to which human effectiveness in the entire economy was now measured.
Housework, farming, handicraft, and subsistence activities ranging from the
making of preserves to the self-building of a home began to be viewed as
subsidiary or second-rate forms of production. The industrial mode first
degraded and later paralyzed the nexus of productive relationships which
coexisted in society.

This monopoly of one mode of production over all social relations is much more
profound than the competition of firms which overshadows it. In the surface
competition the winner is easily recognized as the more capital-intensive
factory, the better-organized business, the more exploitative and
better-protected branch of industry, the corporation that sheds diseconomies
the most unobtrusively or produces for war. On a broad scale this race takes
the form of a competition among multinational corporations and industrializing
nation-states. But this deadly game among giants diverts attention from the
ritual service which the game itself renders to the contestants. As the arena
of the contest expands, an industrial structure is imposed on world society.
The mode of corporate production establishes a radical monopoly not only over
resources and tools but also over the imagination and motivational structure of
people. Political systems compete to baptize the same expanding industrial
structure into opposing creeds, without recognizing that it is beyond their
control. The convergence of corporate monopolies on the deep structural level
of society can be called the industrialization of man. This trend must be
inverted if people are to be free. But the industrial corruption of language
itself makes this issue terribly difficult to formulate.

Language reflects the monopoly of the industrial mode of production over
perception and motivation. The tongues of industrial nations identify the
fruits of creative work and of human labor with the outputs of industry. The
materialization of consciousness is reflected in Western languages. Schools
operate by the slogan “education!” while ordinary language asks what children
“learn.” The functional shift from verb to noun highlights the corresponding
impoverishment of the social imagination. People who speak a nominalist
language habitually express proprietary relationships to work which they have.
All over Latin America only the salaried employees, whether workers or
bureaucrats, say that they have work; peasants say that they do it: “Van a
trabajar, pero no tienen trabajo.” Those who have been modernized and unionized
expect industries to produce not only more goods but also more work for more
people. Not only what men do but also what men want is designated by a noun.
“Housing” designates a commodity rather than an activity. People acquire
knowledge, mobility, even sensitivity or health. They have not only work or fun
but even sex.

This shift from verb to noun reflects a transformation in the idea of
ownership. “Possessing,” “holding,” and “seizing” no longer describe the
relationships people can have to corporations, such as systems of schools or
highways. Possessive statements made about tools come to mean the ability to
command their outputs, interest from capital, or merchandise, or some kind of
prestige connected with their operation. Fully industrialized man calls his own
principally what has been made for him. He says “my education,” “my
transportation,” “my entertainment,” “my health” about the commodities he gets
from school, car, show business, or doctor. Western languages, and above all
English, become almost inseparable from industrial production. Western men
might have to learn from other languages that ownership relations can be
restructured in a convivial way. For instance, in Micronesian tongues there
exist entirely distinct devices to express the relationship I have to my acts
(which can no longer be separated from me), to my nose (which can be cut off),
to my relatives (who were inflicted on me), to my canoe (without which I could
not be a full man), to a drink (which I serve you), or to the same drink (which
I intend to swallow).

In a society whose language has undergone this shift, predicates come to be
stated in terms of a commodity and claims in terms of competition for a scarce
resource. “I want to learn” is translated into “I want to get an education.”
The decision to do something is turned into the demand for a stake in the
gamble of schooling. “I want to walk” is restated as “I need transportation.”
The subject in the first case designates himself as an actor, and in the second
as a consumer. Linguistic change supports the expansion of the industrial
arena: competition for institutionalized values is reflected in the use of
nominal language. This competition for shares inevitably takes the form of a
game. People gamble for what they perceive as nouns. Of course, that
competition can be organized either as a zero-sum game, in which one wins when
another loses, or as a non-zero-sum game, in which both competitors get more
than if either had lost. Compulsory school could be construed as an example of
a zero-sum game: there are only winners and losers; by definition school
bestows privilege on fewer people than it degrades. An example of the second
would be the transition from private to public transport: at least for the time
being, more commuters could get faster wherever they want to go.

Conflict does not have to be a competition for scarce commodities. It could
also manifest disagreement about which conditions would best remove restraints
on autonomous action. Conflict can lead to the creation of new freedom; but
this possibility has been obscured by nominalist language. It can create for
both parties the right to do, and to do things which by definition are neither
commodities nor scarce. Conflict which leads to the right to walk, to
participate in shaping society, to speak and communicate equally, to live in
clean air or to use convivial tools deprives both adversaries of some affluence
for the sake of an incommensurable gain new liberty.

In some societies the corruption of language has crippled the political fantasy
to the point where the difference between a claim to commodities and a right to
convivial tools cannot be understood. Limits on tools cannot be publicly
discussed. Public blindness to urgent issues is not a new phenomenon. People
for decades refused to open their eyes to the urgency of population control,
for example. Limiting tools for the sake of freedom and conviviality is now
such an issue that cannot be raised. A limit on vehicular velocity as a major
election issue seems an implausible idea to the rich and an irrelevant idea to
the poor. People who are born next to highways cannot imagine a world without
speed, and the peasant in the Andes cannot grasp why anyone should travel that
fast. A slowdown as the condition for good transportation sounds shocking. To
recommend limits on tools sounds as deeply obscene today as the recommendation
for greater sexual frankness and freedom as a condition for a good marriage law
would have sounded a generation ago.

The operating code of industrial tools encroaches on everyday language and
reduces the poetic self-affirmation of men to a barely tolerated and marginal
protest. The consequent industrialization of man can be inverted only if the
convivial function of language is recuperated, but with a new level of
consciousness. Language which is used by a people jointly claiming and
asserting each person’s right to share in the shaping of the community becomes,
so to speak, a second-order tool to clarify the relationships of a people to
engineered instrumentalities.

The Recovery of Legal Procedure

Support of an ever-expanding productive society has become the overwhelmingly
dominant purpose of the existing structure of politics and law. The procedure
by which people decide what ought to be done has become subservient to the
ideology that corporations ought to produce more: more knowledge and decisions,
more goods and services. This perversion constitutes the third obstacle to the
translation of the need for a bounded society into actual social process.

Political parties, legislatures, and the juridical system have been
consistently used to foster and protect the growth of schools, unions,
hospitals, and road-systems, not to speak of industries. Gradually, not only
the police but even the courts and the legal system itself have come to be
thought of as tools made for the service of an industrial state. That they
sometimes protect individuals against industrial claims has become an alibi for
their habitual service of legitimizing the further concentration of power.
Along with the idolatry of scientific method and the corruption of language,
this progressive loss of confidence in political and legal processes is a major
obstacle to retooling society.

People come to understand that an alternative society is possible by using
clear language. They can bring it about by recovering consciousness of the deep
structure by which, in their society, decisions are made. Such a structure
exists wherever people form a community. Contradictory decisions can be the
outcome of the same process because the structure can be used to define
personal values and also to shore up institutional behavior. But the existence
of such conflicting results does not contradict the existence of a consistent
structure which generates them. People can decide to get an education in school
even though they have decided that it would be better to learn something on
their own. They can let themselves be taken to a hospital, though they have
decided to die at home. Just as cognitive dissonance is a foundation for
dialectics, so the simultaneous acceptance of contradictory norms proves the
existence of normative procedures.

Public confidence in the existence of shared procedures has been shaken because
these procedures are constantly misused. They have become tools to support
unlimited production through converging arguments that alternately take a
moral, a political, or a legal character. Christian churches preach meekness,
charity, and austerity but finance industrial programs; socialists enforce a
Stalinist mode of production, and the common law has come to favor the firm
over the individual. Soon the computer will be used to define at every juncture
what should be done for the growth of tools, unless people rediscover that they
share a deep commitment to formal procedures by which they can decide how their
present major institutions ought to be turned around.

Unless people agree on a process that can be continuously, convivially, and
effectively used to control society’s tools, the inversion of the present
institutional structure cannot be either enacted or, what is more important,
precariously maintained. Managers will always re-emerge to increase
institutional productivity and capture public support for the better service
they promise.

Three objections are usually made whenever law is proposed as a tool for the
inversion of society. One of them is rather superficial: not everybody can be a
lawyer, and so not everybody can operate the law on his own. This, of course,
is true only to some degree. Parajuridical systems could be set up in
particular communities and incorporated into the over-all structure. Much wider
scope could be given to alternative mechanisms to allow for greater
participation by the nonprofessional, such as mediation, conciliation, and
arbitration. But insofar as this objection is valid, it is also irrelevant to
my point. The law, as it deals with the regulation of large-scale production
agencies, can surely be decentralized, demystified and debureaucratized. But
even then some social concerns are, and could for a long time remain, complex
and of vast range, demanding corresponding legal tools. Precisely if it is to
be used for the negotiating of world-wide proscriptions among large
communities, each with its own centuries-old traditions, the law as the process
enabling us to regulate these concerns is and will remain a tool requiring some
experts to operate it. But this does not mean that such experts have to be
graduates of a law school, or that they must be members of a closed profession.

The second objection is completely relevant and much more profound: persons who
now operate the law as a social tool are deeply infected with the myths that
pervade a growth society. Their imagination of the possible and of the feasible
is determined by the lore of industry. It would be folly to expect the present
corporations of social engineers of a utilitarian society to turn into the
guardians of a convivial one. The critical importance of this observation is
complemented and underlined by a third objection. The juristic system is not
simply a set of written laws; it is a continuing process by which those laws
are made and then applied to actual situations. The law is used to impose a
given mind-set on all participants. The resulting content of the law embodies
the ideologies of lawmakers and judges. How they experience the ideology
inherent in a culture becomes established mythology in the laws they make and
apply. The body of laws that regulates an industrial society inevitably
reflects and reinforces its ideology, social character, and class structure.
“More” is always in the common good—more power to firms, professions, and
parties.

While this objection does indicate a fundamental difficulty against the use of
law in an inversion of society, it also misses the point. I carefully
distinguish between a body of laws and the purely formal structure by which it
is made, just as I have distinguished the use of slogans by which our
institutions operate from the use of ordinary language, and as I will later
distinguish between policies and formal political process. It is the latter and
not the former which are the second order of tools we need, can share, and have
to use.

It is almost impossible to insist strongly enough on the distinction between
means and ends in an epoch in which purposes have been reduced to operations,
in an epoch in which people raise consciousness, movements pretend to provide
“liberation,” languages rather than persons are said to “speak,” and
politicians make” revolutions. The law can again serve to highlight the general
difference between substance and what might be called not “due process” but
rather “due procedure.”

Two major complementary features of the common law make its formal structure
particularly applicable to the needs which arise in a profound crisis. One is
the inherent continuity of the system, and the other is its adversary nature.
Analogous features can be found in other law systems; I here choose the
Anglo-American system of law as an illustration of my more general point.

The continuity built into the lawmaking process does in one sense conserve the
substance of a body of laws. This is less obvious in the legislative stage.
Legislators are free to innovate at their own discretion, as long as they stay
within a constitutional framework. But they do also have to fit any new law
into the context of existing legislation, and this tends to ensure that new
legislation will not vary too widely from the over-all tradition of existing
law.

The function of the courts in providing continuity to the substance of the law
is more obvious. A court applies existing law to actual situations. Like cases
are decided alike, or the facts are found to be of a different significance
today. The law represents the sovereign authority of the past over the present
controversy, the continuity of a dialectic process. The court recognizes the
controversy as a social concern and incorporates its resolutions into the body
of the law. In the process the social experience of the past is readapted to
present needs. The present decision will in turn serve as reference in future
cases.

The continuity of the formal structure used in this process is of a different
order from the continuous embodiment of one set of prejudices in a set of laws.
Considered in this formal sense, the system of continuity is not designed to
preserve the content of any existing set of laws. It could even be used to
preserve the continuous development of a set of laws that fit an inverted
society. There is nothing in most constitutions that prevents the passage of
laws setting upper limits to productivity, privilege, professional monopoly, or
efficiency. In principle, the existing process of legislatures and courts can,
with a reversal of its focus, make and apply such law.

The adversary nature of the common law is equally important. The common law is
not formally concerned with what is ethically or technically good. It is a tool
for the understanding of mutualities that surface as actual conflicts. It
leaves to those directly concerned with a social interest the task of insisting
on the protection of their rights or the pursuit of their claims to what they
consider to be good. This works in both legislation and jurisprudence; the
decision is an act of balancing conflicting interests in a way that is
theoretically best for all.

It is obvious that during the last few generations this balance has been wholly
distorted in favor of a production-oriented society. But the current misuse of
the juristic structure is not a valid argument against its use for precisely
the opposite purpose. Interests wholly opposed to such a society, free from the
illusion that growth can overcome injustice, and concerned with limits, can in
principle use the same tool. It is not, of course, sufficient that new types of
plaintiffs appear; it is equally true that the growth illusions of legislators
must fade, and that parties must be brought forward to represent their interest
in a reassessment of what are now taken as facts.

Not only the legislative but also the juridical process depends on the
presentation of conflicting social interests by interested parties for
settlement by disinterested tribunals. These tribunals operate in a continuous
way. Ideally, judges are ordinary, prudent men or women indifferent to the
substance of the issue they are expected to reconcile, and experts in the
application of process. In practice, however, tribunals have also come to serve
the concentration of power and the increase of industrial production. Not only
do judges, like legislators, perceive that a conflict is best balanced when the
balance is tipped in favor of the over-all interest of corporations, but
society has also conditioned the plaintiffs always to demand more. A larger
share of institutional output constitutes the substance of a claim much more
frequently than protection against an institution which limits a person’s
freedom to do something on his own. But this abuse of the formal structure of
common law does not corrupt the structure itself.

An objection is frequently raised when adversary procedures are presented as a
major tool to oppose industrial growth. Society already heavily relies on such
proceedings. Their extension to new areas is continually recommended. Legal
reformers tend to provide new weapons to all classes of disadvantaged: blacks,
Indians, women, employees, cripples. As a result proceedings have become
cumbersome, costly, and only a few of the interested parties can come forward.
Decisions are often delayed until they have lost their relevance. Role-playing
is encouraged, and this often creates new tensions between artificial groups.
In going out of the way to create structures so that adversary processes may he
used, decisions are made scarce.

This objection is very relevant if it opposes the proliferation of adversary
proceedings in the resolution of conflicts between people. But neither the
conflict between individuals nor the competition between groups is the
substance of our issue. The fundamental conflict in society is about acts,
facts, and things on which people are opposed to corporations. Formal adversary
procedure is the paradigmatic tool for citizens to oppose the threat of
industry to their basic liberties. This is the process suited to the opposition
of two partners whom the law has rendered equal, in which the aggrieved party
is interested in disputing one fact or a relevant law or principle, and
considers this issue the only continuing interest he has in common with the
other. A group of citizens interested in retooling society is not concerned
with negotiations or mediation but with direct opposition to the industrial
mode of production and its undue expansion in a specific instance.

Like ordinary English, formal process is a convivial tool. Undoubtedly,
industrial institutions have entrenched themselves by corrupting the habitual
use of these tools by individuals and communities. Yet language and formal
process remain intrinsically distinct from the purposes for which they are
used. People can defend language and legal procedure as inherently theirs; they
can find in their inalienable natures the confidence to use their unchanged
formal structures to express contents entirely opposed to those for which they
were taught to use them in their childhood. The formal structure of law still
offers a process by which the ordinary citizen can present to society his own
practical interest in conflict with the interest of a corporation, even when
this corporation is an agency of the state, and even if this interest favors or
opposes any functioning or proposed program.

It would be absurd to expect that professionals who are experts in the corrupt
use of language or of law could suddenly think clearly and proceed rightly.
Educators who are aware of the breakdown of schools usually engage in a frantic
search for advice that permits them to teach more people about more things.
Doctors tend to believe that at least some of the generally useful knowledge
they hold cannot be expressed outside their hieratic code. It is useless to
expect the American Medical Association, the National Education Association, or
the association of traffic engineers to explain in ordinary language the
professional gangsterism of their colleagues. It would be equally fruitless to
count on present legislators, lawyers, and judges to recognize the independence
of what is right from the preconceived good, which for them is identical with
the higher output of goods by corporations. They are trained to adjust any
conflict in favor of over-all industrial growth. But just as an exceptional
doctor here and there helps people live responsibly, to suffer as a matter of
fact, and to face death, so an exceptional lawyer can help people use the
formal structure of the law to represent their interest in a convivial society.
Even though he will probably be frustrated in his claims, he can use the
courtroom drama to make his point.

Legal procedure applied to a society filled by optimism about its expanding
tools has turned into the most effective instrument for the social control of
people at the service of these tools. To advance an industrial society, the law
is systematically used for social engineering and the continually more complete
and effective elimination of waste and friction in the mega-machine.
Anglo-American industry has consistently been more successful, in the long run,
than the industry of socialist countries. Law is more effective than
centralized planning in bringing and keeping people under the rule of machines.
Yet the current misuse of the juristic structure is not a valid argument
against its use for precisely the opposite purpose, though it suggests caution
against overly optimistic hopes for such an inverted use.

Most of the present laws and present legislators, most of the present courts
and their decisions, most of the claimants and their demands are deeply
corrupted by an overarching industrial consensus: that more is better, and that
corporations serve the public interest better than men. But this entrenched
consensus does not invalidate my thesis that any revolution which neglects the
use of formal legal and political procedures will fail. Only an active majority
in which all individuals and groups insist for their own reasons on their own
rights, and whose members share the same convivial procedure, can recover the
rights of men against corporations.

The use of procedure for the purpose of hampering, stopping, and inverting our
major institutions will appear to their managers and addicts as a misuse of the
law and as subversion of the only order which they recognize. The use of due
convivial procedure appears corrupt and criminal to the bureaucrat, even one
who calls himself a judge.

Political Inversion

If within the very near future man cannot set limits to the interference of his
tools with the environment and practice effective birth control, the next
generations will experience the gruesome apocalypse predicted by many
ecologists. Faced with these impending disasters, society can stand in wait of
survival within limits set and enforced by bureaucratic dictatorship. Or it can
engage in a political process by the use of legal and political procedures.
Ideologically biased interpretations of the past have made the recognition of
political process increasingly difficult. Liberty has been interpreted as a
right to power tools, a right claimed without reasonable limitation by
individuals and private associations in capitalist countries and by the state
in socialist societies. Recovery becomes feasible only if the fundamental
structure of Western societies is clearly recognized and reclaimed. Analogous
efforts to recover entirely different formal structures will become necessary
when former political or cultural colonies shake off the Western mode of
production.

The bureaucratic management of human survival is unacceptable on both ethical
and political grounds. It would also be as futile as former attempts at mass
therapy. This does not, of course, mean that a majority might not at first
submit to it. People could be so frightened by the increasing evidence of
growing population and dwindling resources that they would voluntarily put
their destiny into the hands of Big Brothers. Technocratic caretakers could be
mandated to set limits on growth in every dimension, and to set them just at
the point beyond which further production would mean utter destruction. Such a
kakotopia could maintain the industrial age at the highest endurable level of
output.

Man would live in a plastic bubble that would protect his survival and make it
increasingly worthless. Since man’s tolerance would become the most serious
limitation to growth, the alchemist’s endeavor would be renewed in the attempt
to produce a monstrous type of man fit to live among reason’s dreams. A major
function of engineering would become the psychogenetic tooling of man himself
as a condition for further growth. People would be confined from birth to death
in a world-wide schoolhouse, treated in a world-wide hospital, surrounded by
television screens, and the man-made environment would be distinguishable in
name only from a world-wide prison.

The alternative to managerial fascism is a political process by which people
decide how much of any scarce resource is the most any member of society can
claim; a process in which they agree to keep limits relatively stationary over
a long time, and by which they set a premium on the constant search for new
ways to have an ever larger percentage of the population join in doing ever
more with ever less. Such a political choice of a frugal society remains a
pious dream unless it can be shown that it is not only necessary but also
possible: (1) to define concrete procedures by which more people are
enlightened about the nature of our present crisis and will come to understand
that limits are necessary and a convivial life style desirable; (2) to bring
the largest number of people into now suppressed organizations which claim
their right to a frugal life style and keep them satisfied and therefore
committed to convivial life; and (3) to discover and revalue the political or
legal tools that are accepted within a society and learn how to use them to
establish and protect convivial life where it emerges. Such procedures may
sound idealistic at the present moment. This is not proof that they cannot
become effective as the present crisis deepens.

Myths and Majorities

The ultimate obstacle to the restructuring of society is not the lack of
information about which limits are needed, nor the lack of people who would
accept them if they became inevitable, but the power of political myths.

Almost everyone in rich societies is a destructive consumer. Almost everyone
is, in some way, engaged in aggression against the milieu. Destructive
consumers constitute a numerical majority. Myth transforms them into a
political one. Numerical majorities come to form a mythical voting bloc on a
nonexistent issue; “they” are invoked as the unbeatable guardians of vested
interest in growth. This mythical majority paralyzes political action. At
closer inspection, “they” are a number of reasonable individuals. One is an
ecologist who takes a jet plane to a conference on protecting the environment
from further pollution. Another is an economist who knows that growing
efficiency renders work increasingly scarce; he tries to create new sources of
employment. Neither of them has the same interests as the slum-dweller in
Detroit who purchases his color TV on time. The three belong no more to a
voting bloc that will defend growth than clerks, repairmen, and salesmen are
somehow politically homogenized because each fears for his job, needs a car,
and wants medicine for his children.

There can be no such thing as a majority opposed to an issue that has not
arisen. A majority agitating for limits to growth is as ludicrous a concept as
one demanding growth at all cost. Majorities are not created by shared
ideologies. They develop out of enlightened self-interest. The most that even
the best of ideologies can do is interpret this interest. The stance each man
or woman takes when a social problem becomes an overwhelming threat depends on
two factors: the first is how a smoldering conflict erupts into a political
issue demanding attention and partisan action; the second is the existence of
new Ă©lites which can provide an interpretative framework for new-and hitherto
unexpected-alignments of interest.

From Breakdown to Chaos

I can only conjecture on how the breakdown of industrial society will
ultimately become a critical issue. But I can make rather firm statements about
the qualifications for providing guidance within the coming crisis. I believe
that growth will grind to a halt. The total collapse of the industrial monopoly
on production will be the result of synergy in the failure of the multiple
systems that fed its expansion. This expansion is maintained by the illusion
that careful systems engineering can stabilize and harmonize present growth,
while in fact it pushes all institutions simultaneously toward their second
watershed. Almost overnight people will lose confidence not only in the major
institutions but also in the miracle prescriptions of the would-be crisis
managers. The ability of present institutions to define values such as
education, health, welfare, transportation, or news will suddenly be
extinguished because it will be recognized as an illusion.

This crisis may be triggered by an unforeseen event, as the Great Depression
was touched off by the Wall Street Crash. Some fortuitous coincidence will
render publicly obvious the structural contradictions between stated purposes
and effective results in our major institutions. People will suddenly find
obvious what is now evident to only a few: that the organization of the entire
economy toward the “better” life has become the major enemy of the good life.
Like other widely shared insights, this one will have the potential of turning
public imagination inside out. Large institutions can quite suddenly lose their
respectability, their legitimacy, and their reputation for serving the public
good. It happened to the Roman Church in the Reformation, to Royalty in the
Revolution. The unthinkable became obvious overnight: that people could and
would behead their rulers.

Sudden change is of a different order than feedback or evolution. Observe the
whirlpools below a waterfall. For many seasons the eddies stay in the same
place no matter whether the water is high or low. Then, suddenly, one more
stone falls into the basin, the entire array changes, and the old can never be
reconstructed. People who invoke the specter of a hopelessly growth-oriented
majority seem incapable of envisaging political behavior in a crash. Business
ceases to be as usual when the populace loses confidence in industrial
productivity, and not just in paper currency.

It is still possible to face the breakdown of each of our various systems in a
separate perspective. No remedy seems to work, but we can still find resources
to support every remedy proposed. Governments think they can deal with the
breakdown of utilities, the disruption of the educational system, intolerable
transportation, the chaos of the judicial process, the violent disaffection of
the young. Each is dealt with as a separate phenomenon, each is explained by a
different report, each calls for a new tax and a new program. Squabbles about
alternative remedies give credibility to both: free schools vs. public schools
double the demand for education; satellite cities vs. monorails for commuters
make the growth of cities seem inexorable; higher professional standards in
medicine vs. more paramedical professions further aggrandize the health
professions. Since each of the proposed remedies appeals to some, the usual
solution is an attempt to try both. The result is a further effort to make the
pie grow, and to forget that it is pie in the sky.

The Coolidge approach to the warnings of the Depression is now applied to the
signs of a much more radical crisis. General systems analysis is trusted to
relate the institutional breakdowns to each other, which only leads to more
planning, centralization, and bureaucracy in order to achieve control over
population, affluence, and inefficient industry. Unemployment in the
manufacturing sector is supposed to be compensated for by growth in the output
of decisions, controls, and therapies. Fascination with industry and mechanical
production still blinds people to the possibility of a postindustrial society
in which several distinct modes of production would complement each other.
Trying to bring about an era which is both hyperindustrial and ecologically
feasible, they accelerate the breakdown of several other non-physical and
equally fundamental dimensions of the balance of life.

It would be a mere exercise in geomancy to predict which series of events will
play the role of the Wall Street Crash as catalyst of the first crisis of, not
just in, industrial society. But it would be folly not to expect in the very
near future an event whose effects will jam the growth of tools. When this
happens, the noise that accompanies the crash will distract attention from
seeing it in proper perspective.

We still have a chance to understand the causes of the coming crisis, and to
prepare for it. If we are to anticipate its effects, we must investigate how
sudden change can bring about the emergence into power of previously submerged
social groups. It is not calamity as such that creates these groups; it is much
less calamity that brings about their emergence; but calamity weakens the
prevailing powers which have excluded the submerged from participation in the
social process. It is the power of surprise that weakens control, that shakes
up the established controllers, and brings to the top those people who have not
lost their bearings.

When controls are weakened, those accustomed to control must seek new allies.
In the weakened economic-industrial state of the Great Depression, the
establishment could not do without organized labor, so organized labor got its
share of power within the structure. In the weakened labor market during the
Second World War, industry could not do without black labor. The blacks began
to assert their power.

Insight into Crisis

Forces tending to limit production are already at work within society. Public,
counterfoil research can significantly help these individuals become more
cohesive and self-conscious in their indictment of growth they consider
destructive. We can anticipate that their voices will acquire new resonance
when the crisis of overproductive society becomes acute. They form no
constituency, but they are spokesmen for a majority of which everyone is a
potential member. The more unexpectedly the crisis comes, the more suddenly
their velleities can turn into a program. But the ability to direct events at
that moment depends on how well these minorities grasp the profound nature of
the crisis, and know how to state it in effective language: to declare what
they want, what they can do, and what they do not need. The critical use of
ordinary language is the first pivot in a political inversion. A second pivot
is needed.

Further growth must lead to a multiple catastrophe. That people would accept
multiple limits to growth without catastrophe seems highly improbable. The
inevitable catastrophic event could be either a crisis in civilization or its
end: end by annihilation or end in B. F. Skinner’s world-wide concentration
camp run by a T. E. Frazier. The foreseeable catastrophe will be a true
crisis—that is, the occasion for a choice—only if at the moment it strikes the
necessary social demands can be effectively expressed. They must be represented
by people who can demonstrate that the breakdown of the current industrial
illusion is for them a condition for choosing an effective and convivial mode
of production. The preparation of such groups is the key task of new politics
at the present moment.

I have already argued that these groups must be prepared to provide a logically
coherent analysis of the catastrophic event and to communicate it in ordinary
language. I have argued that they must be prepared to propose the necessity for
a bounded society in practical terms that have general appeal. Sacrifice must
be shown as the inevitable price for different groups of people to get what
they want-or at least to be liberated from what has become intolerable. But
beyond using words to describe the limits as both necessary and appealing, the
leadership of these groups must be prepared to use a social tool that is fit to
ordain what is good enough for all. It must be a tool which, like language, is
respected by all; a tool which, like language, does not lose its power because
of the purpose to which it has been put in recent history; a tool which, like
language, possesses a fundamental structure that misuse cannot totally corrupt.

I have already argued that such a tool can only be the formal structure of
politics and law. At the moment of the crash which is industrial rather than
simply financial, the transformation of catastrophe into crisis depends on the
confidence an emerging group of clear-thinking and feeling people can inspire
in their peers. They must then argue that the transition to a convivial society
can be, and must be, the result of conscious use of disciplined procedure that
recognizes the legitimacy of conflicting interests, the historical precedent
out of which the conflict arose, and the necessity of abiding by the decision
of peers. Convivially used procedure guarantees that an institutional
revolution will remain a tool whose goals emerge as they are enacted; the
conscious use of procedure in a continually antibureaucratic sense is the only
possible protection against the revolution itself becoming an institution.
Whether the application of this procedure to the inversion of all major
institutions of society is then called a cultural revolution, or the
recuperation of the formal structure of law, or participatory socialism or a
return to the spirit of the Fueros de España, is merely a matter of labeling.

Sudden Change

When I speak about emerging interest groups and their preparation, I am not
speaking of action groups, or of a church, or of new kinds of experts. I am
above all not speaking about one political party which could assume power at a
moment of crisis. Management of the crisis would make catastrophe irreversible.
A well-knit, well-trained party can establish its power at the moment of a
crisis in which the choice to be made is one within an over-all system. Such
was the Great Depression. What was at issue was control over the tools of
production. Such were the events which brought the Marxists to power in Eastern
Europe. But the crisis I have described as imminent is not a crisis within
industrial society, but a crisis of the industrial mode of production itself.
The crisis I have described confronts people with a choice between convivial
tools and being crushed by machines. The only response to this crisis is a full
recognition of its depth and an acceptance of inevitable self-limitations. The
more varied the perspectives from which this insight is shared by interest
groups and the more disparate the interests that may be protected only by a
reduction of power within society, the greater the probability that the
inevitable will be recognized as such.

I am also not speaking about a majority opposed to growth on some abstract
principles. Such a majority is unfeasible. A well-organized Ă©lite, vocally
promulgating an antigrowth orthodoxy, is indeed conceivable. It is probably now
forming. But such a programmatic antigrowth Ă©lite would be highly undesirable.
By pushing people to accept limits to industrial output without questioning the
basic industrial structure of modern society, it would inevitably provide more
power to the growth-optimizing bureaucrats and become their pawn. One of the
first results of transition toward a stable-state industrial economy would be
the development of a labor-intensive, highly disciplined, and growing subsector
of production that would control people by giving them jobs. Such a stabilized
production of highly rationalized and standardized goods and services would
be—if this were possible—even further away from convivial production than the
industrial-growth society we have now.

The proponents of a bounded society have no need to put together some kind of
majority. A voting majority in a democracy is not motivated by the explicit
commitment of all its members to some specific ideology or to some particular
value. A voting majority in favor of a specific institutional limitation would
have to be composed of very disparate elements: those seriously aggrieved by
some aspect of overproduction, those who do not profit from it, and those who
may have objections to the over-all organization of society—but not directly to
the specific limit being set. How this functions in times of normal politics
can be well illustrated by the example of school. Some people are childless and
resent the school tax. Others feel they are taxed more heavily and served less
well than their peers in another district. Others object to tax support of
schools since they want to send their children to parochial schools. Others
object to compulsory schooling as such: some because it does harm to the young
and others because it fosters discrimination. All these people could form a
voting majority, but not a party or a sect. Under present circumstances they
might succeed in cutting school down to size, but thereby they would merely
assure its more legitimate survival. A majority vote to limit one major
institution tends to be conservative when business is as usual.

But a majority can have the contrary effect in a crisis which affects society
on a deeper level. The joint arrival of several institutions at their second
watershed is the beginning of such a crisis. The crash that will follow must
make it clear that industrial society as such—and not just its separate
institutions—has outgrown the range of its effectiveness.

The nation-state has become so powerful that it cannot per-form its stated
functions. Just as General Vo Nguyen Giap could use the U.S. military machine
to win his war, so the multinational corporations and professions can now use
the law and the two-party system to establish their empire. But while democracy
in the United States can survive a victory by Giap, it cannot survive one by
ITT and its like. As a total crisis approaches, it becomes more obvious that
the nation-state has grown into the holding corporation for a multiplicity of
self-serving tools, and the political party into an instrument to organize
stockholders for the occasional election of boards and presidents. In this
situation, parties support each voter’s right to claim higher levels of
individual consumption and to enforce thereby higher levels of industrial
consumption. People can claim cars, but the appropriation of society’s over-all
resources by a transportation system which determines that cars are useful is
left to the decision of experts. Such parties support a state whose only
purpose is the support of an increasing GNP, and they are obviously useless at
the moment of a general crash.

When business is normal, the procedural opposition between corporations and
clients usually heightens the legitimacy of the latter’s dependence. But at the
moment of a structural crisis not even the voluntary reduction of
overefficiency on the part of major institutions will keep any of them
functioning. A general crisis opens the way to social reconstruction. The loss
of legitimacy of the state as a holding corporation does not destroy, but
reasserts, the need for constitutional procedure. The loss of confidence in
parties that have become stockholders’ factions brings Out the importance of
adversary procedures in politics. A loss of credibility of opposing claims for
more individual consumption only highlights the importance of the use of
adversary procedures when the issue to be decided upon is the reconciliation of
opposing sets of society-wide limitations. The same general crisis that could
easily lead to one-man rule, expert government, and ideological orthodoxy is
also the great opportunity to reconstruct a political process in which all
participate.

The structures of political and legal procedures are integral to one another.
Both shape and express the structure of freedom in history. If this is
recognized, the framework of due procedure can be used as the most dramatic,
symbolic, and convivial tool in the political area. The appeal to law remains
powerful even where society makes access to legal machinery a privilege, or
where it systematically denies justice, or where it cloaks despotism in the
mantle of show tribunals. Even when he who upholds the formal structure of
ordinary language and procedure earns the scorn, ridicule, and persecution of
his fellow revolutionaries, the appeal of an individual to the formal structure
embedded in a people’s history remains the most powerful instrument to say the
truth and denounce the cancerous domination of the industrial dominance over
production as the ultimate form of idolatry. I feel almost unbearable anguish
when faced by the fact that only the word recovered from history should be left
to us as the power for stemming disaster. Yet only the word in its weakness can
associate the majority of people in the revolutionary inversion of inevitable
violence into convivial reconstruction.

Reconstruction for poor countries means adopting a set of negative design
criteria within which their tools are kept, in order to advance directly into a
postindustrial era of conviviality. The limits to choose are of the same order
as those which hyperindustrialized countries will have to adopt for the sake of
survival and at the cost of their vested interest. Such social reconstruction
cannot be supported by a high-powered army, both because the maintenance of
such an army would foil reconstruction and because no such army would be
powerful enough. Defense of conviviality is possible only if undertaken by the
people with tools they control. Imperialist mercenaries can poison or maim but
never conquer a people who have chosen to set boundaries to their tools for the
sake of conviviality.