đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș document â€ș daniel-guerin-for-a-libertarian-communism captured on 2023-07-22 at 20:09:02. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âŹ…ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: For a Libertarian Communism
Date: 2017
Notes: Published by PM Press under the the *Revolutionary Pocketbooks* series. <br> Edited and introduced by David Berry. Translation by Mitchell Abidor.
Authors: David Berry, Daniel Guérin, Mitchell Abidor
Topics: Pierre Joseph Proudhon, Libertarian communism, Anarcho communism, Libertarian marxism, PM press
Published: 2019-08-19 13:25:45Z

Foreword and Acknowledgements

by

David Berry

This volume contains a selection of texts by the French revolutionary activist and historian Daniel GuĂ©rin (1904–1988), published here in English translation for the first time. They were written between the 1950s and 1980s and appeared in France in a series of collections: **Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire** [Youth of Libertarian Socialism] (Paris: Riviere, 1959), **Pour un Marxisme libertaire** [For a Libertarian Marxism] (Paris: Laffont, 1969), and **A la recherche d’un communisme libertaire** [In Search of a Libertarian Communism] (Paris: Spartacus, 1984). A further version of the collection was published after his death: **Pour le communisme libertaire** [For Libertarian Communism] (Paris: Spartacus, 2003). All of these contain slightly different selections of texts around a common core of recurrent pieces, and the same is true of this English edition. We have tried to choose those texts which would be of most interest to present-day readers, but which also give a good understanding of GuĂ©rin’s developing analysis of the failings of the Left and of his belief that the only way forward was through some kind of synthesis of Marxism and anarchism.

We are grateful to the Spartacus collective, to Daniel Guerrier, and to Anne Guérin for permission to publish these translations.

The footnotes are GuĂ©rin’s except where indicated; additional explanatory material is followed by my initials. We have tried (where possible and practical) to provide references to English translations of GuĂ©rin’s sources, and I am grateful to Iain McKay for his help with this. I would also like to thank Chris Reynolds, Martin O’Shaughnessy, and Christophe Wall-Romana for their help in tracking down the source of GuĂ©rin’s reference to Armand Gatti;

and Danny Evans and James Yeoman for their advice regarding films about the Spanish Revolution.

Guérin was a prolific writer on an exceptionally wide range of topics, and relatively little has been translated into English. A list of his publications in English can be found at the end of the volume. For further information, including a full bibliography and links to texts available online, please visit the website of the Association des Amis de Daniel Guérin (the Association of the Friends of Daniel Guérin) at [[https://www.danielguerin.info/]].

List of Acronyms

AL | Alternative Libertaire (Libertarian Alternative), founded 1991

CFDT | Confederation Française Democratique du Travail (Democratic French Labour Confederation), founded 1964

CGT | Confederation Generale du Travail (General Labour Confederation), founded 1895

CGTU | Confederation Generale du Travail Unitaire (Unitary General Labour Confederation), 1921–1936

CNT | Confederation Nationale du Travail (National Labour Confederation), founded 1946

FA | Federation Anarchiste (Anarchist Federation), founded 1945

FCL | Federation Communiste Libertaire (Libertarian Communist Federation), 1953–1957

FEN | Federation de l‘Education Nationale (National Education Federation), 1948–1992

FO | Force Ouvriere (Workers’ Power), founded 1947

FSU | Federation Syndicale Unitaire (Unitary Trade Union Federation), founded 1992

JAC | Jeunesse Anarchiste Communiste (Communist Anarchist Youth), founded 1967

OCL | Organisation Communiste Libertaire (Libertarian Communist Organization), founded 1976

ORA | Organisation rĂ©volutionnaire Anarchiste (Anarchist Revolutionary Organization), 1967–1976

PCF | Parti Communiste Française (French Communist Party), founded 1920

PCI | Parti Communiste Internationaliste (Internationalist Communist Party), 1944–1968

PS-SFIO | Parti Socialiste-Section Française de l’Internationale Ouvriere (Socialist Party, French Section of the Workers’ International), 1905–1969

PSOP | Parti Socialiste Ouvrier et Paysan (Workers’ and Peasants’ Socialist Party), 1938–1940

SUD | Solidaires, Unitaires, Democratiques (Solidarity, Unity, Democracy), founded 1988

UGAC | Union des Groupes Anarchistes-Communistes (Union of Communist-Anarchist Groups), 1961–1968

UTCL | Union des travailleurs communistes libertaires (Union of Libertarian Communist Workers), 1974–1991

Introduction

The Search for a Libertarian Communism:

Daniel GuĂ©rin and the “Synthesis” of Marxism and Anarchism

I have a horror of sects, of compartmentalisation, of people who are separated by virtually nothing and who nevertheless face each other as if across an abyss.

— Daniel GuĂ©rin[1]

As he once wrote of the fate suffered by anarchism, Daniel GuĂ©rin (1904–1988) has himself been the victim of unwarranted neglect and, in some circles at least, of undeserved discredit. For although many people know of GuĂ©rin, relatively few seem aware of the breadth of his contribution. His writings cover a vast range of subjects, from fascism and the French Revolution to the history of the European and American labour movements; from Marxist and anarchist theory to homosexual liberation; from French colonialism to the Black Panthers; from Paul Gauguin to French nuclear tests in the Pacific—not to mention several autobiographical volumes. As an activist, GuĂ©rin was involved in various movements and campaigns: anticolonialism, antiracism, antimilitarism, and homosexual liberation. This is a man who counted among his personal friends Francois Mauriac, Simone Weil, C.L.R. James, and Richard Wright, to name but a few of the famous names which litter his autobiographies. His youthful literary efforts provoked a letter of congratulation from Colette; he met and corresponded with Leon Trotsky; and he had dinner “en tĂȘte-Ă -tĂȘte” with Ho Chi Minh. Jean-Paul Sartre

judged his reinterpretation of the French Revolution to be “one of the only contributions by contemporary Marxists to have enriched historical studies.”[2] The gay liberation activist Pierre Hahn believed his own generation of homosexuals owed more to GuĂ©rin than to any other person, and the Martinican poet AimĂ© CĂ©saire paid tribute to his work on decolonization. Noam Chomsky considers GuĂ©rin’s writings on anarchism to be of great importance to the development of contemporary socialist thought.

Yet despite such assessments, and although there is widespread and enduring interest in GuĂ©rin among activists, he has been badly neglected by academic researchers in France and especially in the English-speaking world. This is doubtless due to a combination of factors: GuĂ©rin never held an academic post or any leadership position (except briefly at the Liberation as director of the Commission du Livre, a government agency that oversaw the book publishing industry); he was consistently anti-Stalinist during a period when the influence of the French Communist Party, both among intellectuals and within the labour movement, was overwhelming; he never fit easily into ideological or political pigeonholes and was often misunderstood and misrepresented; and in France in the 1960s and 1970s, his bisexuality was shocking even for many on the Left. GuĂ©rin was, in a word, a “troublemaker.” [3]

Concerned that his reinterpretation of the French Revolution, **La Lutte de classes sous la Premiere Republique, 1793–1797** (1946), had been misunderstood, in 1947, Daniel GuĂ©rin wrote to his friend, the socialist Marceau Pivert, that the book was to be seen as “an introduction to a synthesis of anarchism and Marxism-Leninism I would like to write one day.” [4] What exactly did GuĂ©rin mean by this “synthesis,” and how and why had he come to be convinced of its necessity? For as Alex Callinicos has commented, “genuinely innovative syntheses are rare and difficult to arrive at. Too often attempted syntheses amount merely to banality, incoherence, or eclecticism.” [5]

It must however be noted from the outset that Guérin had no pretensions to being a theorist: he saw himself first and foremost as an activist and secondly as a historian.[6] Indeed, from the day in 1930 when he abandoned the poetry and novels of his youth, all his research and writings were concerned more or less directly with

his political commitments.[7] His developing critique of Marxism and his later interest in the relationship between Marxism and anarchism were motivated by his own direct experience of active participation in revolutionary struggles on a number of fronts; they can thus only be clarified when studied in relation to social and political developments.

Although GuĂ©rin, in some of his autobiographical or semi-autobiographical writings, had a tendency to divide his life into more or less distinct “phases,” and despite the fact that his political or ideological trajectory may seem to some to be rather protean, I would argue that there was in fact an underlying ideological consistency—even if changing circumstances meant that his “organisational options” (as he put it) changed in different periods of his life. A historical materialist all his life, he remained attached to a revolutionary socialism with a strong ethical or moral core. Although it was many years before he found an organisation which lived up to his expectations, he was always at heart a libertarian communist, developing an increasingly strong belief in the need for a “total revolution” which would attach as much importance to issues of race, gender, and sexuality as to workplace-based conflict. Whether specifically in his commitment to anticolonialism or to sexual liberation, or more generally in his emphasis on what today would be called intersectionality, GuĂ©rin was undoubtedly ahead of his time.

Early Influences

Despite coming from the **“grande bourgeoisie”**—a background which he would come to reject—GuĂ©rin owed much to the influence of his branch of the family: humanist, liberal and cultured, both his parents had been passionately pro-Dreyfus, both were influenced by Tolstoy’s ethical and social ideas, and his father’s library contained **The Communist Manifesto** as well as works by BenoĂźt Malan, Proudhon, and Kropotkin.[8] The young Daniel seems to have been particularly influenced by his father’s pacifism and was also deeply affected by his own reading of Tolstoy’s **Diaries** and **Resurrection.**[9] In the context of the increasingly polarised debates of the inter-war period between the Far Right and Far Left (“Maurras **versus** Marx” as he put it), he identified with the “Marxist extreme Left” from a relatively early age.[10] His later “discovery” of the Parisian working

class and of the concrete realities of their everyday existence (to a large extent through his homosexual relationships with young workers) reinforced a profound “workerism” which would stay with him for the rest of his life.[11]

The Bankruptcy of Stalinism and Social Democracy

This workerism would lead him in 1930–1931 to join the syndicalists grouped around the veteran revolutionary Pierre Monatte: typically, perhaps, GuĂ©rin’s first real active involvement was in the campaign for the reunification of the two major syndicalist confederations, the CGT (dominated at that time by the PS-SFIO, the Socialist Party) and the CGTU (dominated by the PCF, the French Communist Party). His workerism was also responsible for a strong attraction towards the PCF, far more “proletarian” than the Socialist Party, despite his “visceral anti-Stalinism” and what he saw as the Party’s “crass ideological excesses, its inability to win over the majority of workers, and its mechanical submission to the Kremlin’s orders.”[12] Yet GuĂ©rin was no more impressed with the PS, which he found petty-bourgeois, narrow-minded, dogmatically anticommunist, and obsessed with electioneering:

The tragedy for many militants of our generation was our repugnance at having to opt for one or the other of the two main organisations which claimed, wrongly, to represent the working class. Stalinism and social democracy both repelled us, each in
its own way. Yet those workers who were active politically were in one of these two parties. The smaller, intermediate groups and the extremist sects seemed to us to be doomed to impotence and marginalisation. The SFIO, despite the social conformism of its leadership, at least had the advantage over the Communist Party of enjoying a certain degree of internal democracy, and to some extent allowed revolutionaries to express themselves; whereas the monolithic automatism of Stalinism forbade any critics from opening their mouths and made it very difficult for them even to stay in the party.[13]

Hence his decision to rejoin the SFIO in 1935, shortly before the creation by Marceau Pivert of the **Gauche révolutionnaire** (Revolutionary

Left) tendency within the party, of which he would become a leading member. GuĂ©rin was attracted by Pivert’s “Luxemburgist,” libertarian and syndicalist tendencies.[14] He was consistently on the revolutionary wing of the **Gauche rĂ©volutionnaire** and of its successor, the **Parti socialiste ouvrier et paysan** (PSOP, or Workers’ and Peasants’ Socialist Party, created when the GR was expelled from the SFIO in 1938), and, in the Popular Front period, he drew a clear distinction between what he called the “Popular Front no. 1”—an electoral alliance between social democracy, Stalinism, and bourgeois liberalism—and the “Popular Front no. 2”—the powerful, extra-parliamentary, working-class movement, which came into conflict with the more moderate (and more bourgeois) Popular Front government.[15] He viewed the “entryism” of the French Trotskyists in these years as a welcome counterbalance to the reformism of the majority of the Socialist Party.[16]

Indeed, in the 1930s, GuĂ©rin agreed with Trotsky’s position on many issues: on the nature of fascism and how to stop it; on war and revolutionary proletarian internationalism; on opposition to the collusion between “social-patriotism” (i.e., mainstream social democracy) and “national-communism” (i.e., the PCF) as well as any pact with the bourgeois Radicals; and on the need to fight actively for the liberation of Europe’s colonies. As GuĂ©rin comments after recounting in glowing terms his sole meeting with Trotsky in Barbizon (near Fontainebleau) in 1933: “On a theoretical level as well as on the level of political practice, Trotsky would remain, for many of us, both a stimulus to action and a teacher.” [17]

Ultimately, GuĂ©rin’s experience of the labour movement and of the Left in the 1930s—as well as his research on the nature and origins of fascism and Nazism[18]—led him to reject both social democracy and Stalinism as effective strategies for defeating fascism and preventing war. Indeed, the Left—“divided, ossified, negative, and narrow-minded” in GuĂ©rin’s words—bore its share of responsibility and had made tragic errors.[19] The SFIO was criticised by GuĂ©rin for its electoralism and for allowing its hands to be tied by the **Parti radical-socialiste,** “a bourgeois party whose corruption and bankruptcy were in large part responsible for the fascist explosion”; for its incomprehension of the nature of the capitalist state, which led to the impotence of Leon Blum’s 1936 Popular

Front government; for its failure to take fascism seriously (and to aid the Spanish Republicans), despite the warnings, until it was too late; and for its obsessive rivalry with the PCF. The PCF was equally harshly criticised by GuĂ©rin—for what seemed to him to be its blind obedience to the Comintern, the criminal stupidity of the Comintern’s “third period” and for its counter-revolutionary strategy both in Spain and in France.[20]

As for Trotsky, GuĂ©rin disagreed with him over the creation of the Fourth International in 1938, which seemed to him premature and divisive. More generally, GuĂ©rin was critical of what he saw as Trotsky’s tendency continually to transpose the experiences of the Russian Bolsheviks onto contemporary events in the West, and of his “authoritarian rigidness.” Trotskyism, GuĂ©rin argued, represented “the ideology of the infallible leader who, in an authoritarian fashion, directs the policy of a fraction or of a party.” [21] What GuĂ©rin wanted to see was “the full development of the spontaneity of the working class.” [22] Writing in 1963, GuĂ©rin would conclude with regard to such disputes over revolutionary tactics:

The revolutionary organisation which was lacking in June 1936 was not, in my opinion, an authoritarian leadership emanating from a small group or sect, but an organ for the coordination of the workers’ councils, growing directly out of the occupied workplaces. The mistake of the **Gauche rĂ©volutionnaire** was not so much that it was unable, because of its lack of preparation, to transform itself into a revolutionary party on the Leninist or Trotskyist model, but that it was unable ... to help the working class to find for itself its own form of power structure to confront the fraud that was the Popular Front no. 1.[23]

So as GuĂ©rin summarised the state of the Left in the 1930s: “Everything made the renewal of the concepts and methods of struggle employed by the French Left both indispensable and urgent.” [24] These debates on the Left regarding tactics (working-class autonomy or “Popular Frontism”) and the role of the “avant-garde” or, in syndicalist terms, the “activist minority” **(minoritĂ© agissante)** would recur in the postwar years, and GuĂ©rin’s position would vary little.

The Break from Trotskyism

Despite GuĂ©rin’s reservations about Trotskyism, his analysis of the nature of the Vichy regime was very similar to that put forward by the Fourth International, and he was also impressed with Trotsky’s manifesto of May 1940, “Laguerre imperialiste et la revolution proletarienne mondiale” [Imperialist War and the World Proletarian Revolution], including it in a collection of Trotsky’s writings on the Second World War he would edit in 1970.[25] He worked with the Trotskyists in the resistance, not least because they remained true to their internationalism and to their class politics.[26] They rejected, for instance, what GuĂ©rin saw as the PCF’s demagogic nationalism. GuĂ©rin was thus closely involved with the Trotskyists’ attempts to organise extremely dangerous anti-militarist and anti-Nazi propaganda among German soldiers. He also contributed to the activities of a group of Trotskyist workers producing newsletters carrying reports of workplace struggles against both French employers and the German authorities.

However, an extended study tour of the United States from 1946 to 1949, which included visits to branches or prominent militants of the Socialist Workers’ Party and the breakaway Workers’ Party, represented a turning point in GuĂ©rin’s “Trotskyism.” In a 1948 letter to Marceau Pivert, he commented on his unhappiness with the Trotskyists’ tendency to “repeat mechanically old formulae without rethinking them, relying lazily and uncritically on the (undeniably admirable) writings of Trotsky.”[27] Looking back thirty years later, he would conclude: “It was thanks to the American Trotskyists, despite their undeniable commitment, that I ceased forever believing in the virtues of revolutionary parties built on authoritarian, Leninist lines.”[28]

The “Mother of Us All”

Unlike many on the Left associated with postwar ideological renewal, most of whom would focus on a revision or reinterpretation of Marxism, often at a philosophical level (Sartre, Althusser, or Henri Lefebvre, for example), GuĂ©rin the historian began with a return to what he saw as the source of revolutionary theory and praxis: in 1946, he published his study of class struggle in the First French Republic (1793–1797).[29] The aim of the book was to “draw

lessons from the greatest, longest and deepest revolutionary experience France has ever known, lessons which would help regenerate the revolutionary, libertarian socialism of today,” and to “extract some ideas which would be applicable to our time and of direct use to the contemporary reader who has yet to fully digest the lessons of another revolution: the Russian Revolution.”[30] Applying the concepts of permanent revolution and combined and uneven development, inspired by Trotsky’s **History of the Russian Revolution,** GuĂ©rin argued that the beginnings of a conflict of class interest could already be detected within the revolutionary camp between an “embryonic” proletariat—the **bras nus** (manual workers), represented by the **EnragĂ©s**—and the bourgeoisie—represented by Robespierre and the Jacobin leadership. For GuĂ©rin, the French Revolution thus represented not only the birth of bourgeois parliamentary democracy, but also the emergence of “a new type of democracy,” a form of working-class direct democracy as seen, however imperfectly, in the **“sections”** (local popular assemblies), precursors of the Commune of 1871 and the Soviets of 1905 and 1917.[31] In the second edition of the work (1968) he would add “the Commune of May 1968” to that genealogy.

Similarly, this interpretation tended to emphasise the political ambivalence of the bourgeois Jacobin leadership which “hesitated continually between the solidarity uniting it with the popular classes against the aristocracy and that uniting all the wealthy, property-owning classes against those who owned little or nothing.”[32] For GuĂ©rin, the essential lesson to be drawn from the French Revolution was thus the conflict of class interest between the bourgeoisie and the working classes. Bourgeois, social democratic, and Stalinist interpretations of the Revolution—like those of Jean Jaures, Albert Mathiez, and so many others—which tended to maintain the “cult of Robespierre” and to reinforce the labour movement’s dependence on bourgeois democracy, were thus to be rejected.[33]

<em>Class Struggle in the First Republic</em> has been described by Eric Hobsbawm, himself a longstanding Communist Party member, as “a curious combination of libertarian and Trotskyist ideas—not without a dash of Rosa Luxemburg.”[34] It not only shocked many academic historians of the Revolution—especially those with

more or less close links to the PCF (Georges Lefebvre, and especially Albert Soboul and George Rude)—but also those politicians who, in GuĂ©rin’s words, “have been responsible for perverting and undermining true proletarian socialism.”[35] The fallout was intense and the ensuing debate lasted for many years; indeed, GuĂ©rin is still today regarded with distrust by many historians influenced by the Republican and mainstream Marxist (non-Trotskyist) interpretations of the Revolution as a bourgeois revolution.[36] GuĂ©rin brought that whole historiographical tradition into question. The political significance was that the Revolutionary Terror had been used as a parallel to justify Bolshevik repression of democratic freedoms and repression of more leftist movements. Stalin had been compared to Robespierre. The Jacobin tradition of patriotism and national unity in defence of the bourgeois democratic Republic has been one of the characteristics of the dominant tendencies within the French Left, and therefore central to the political mythologies of the Popular Front and the Resistance. GuĂ©rin, as Ian Birchall has put it, “was polemicizing against the notion of a Resistance uniting all classes against the foreign invader.”[37]

What is more, the PCF had been campaigning since 1945 for unity at the top with the SFIO, and in the 1956 elections called for the re-establishment of a Popular Front government. GuĂ©rin, as we have seen, argued that alliance with the supposedly “progressive” bourgeoisie in the struggle against fascism was a contradiction at the heart of the Popular Front strategy. His conception of the way forward for the Left was very different. At a time when fascism in the form of Poujadism looked as if it might once more be a real threat, GuĂ©rin argued that what was needed was a “genuine” Popular Front, that is, a grassroots social movement rather than a governmental alliance, a truly popular movement centred on the working classes that would bring together the labour movement and all socialists who rejected both the pro-American SFIO and the pro-Soviet PCF:

And if we succeed in building this new Popular Front, let us not repeat the mistakes of the 1936 Popular Front, which because of its timidity and impotence ended up driving the middle classes towards fascism, rather than turning them away from it as had
been its aim. Only a combative Popular Front, which dares to attack big business, will be able to halt our middle classes on the slope which leads to fascism and to their destruction.[38]

The Developing Critique of Leninism

GuĂ©rin’s friend and translator, C.L.R. James, wrote in 1958 of the political significance of GuĂ©rin’ s revisiting the history of the French Revolution:

Such a book had never yet been produced and could not have been produced in any epoch other than our own. It is impregnated with the experience and study of the greatest event of our time: the development and then degeneration of the Russian Revolution, and is animated implicitly by one central concern: how can the revolutionary masses avoid the dreadful pitfalls of bureaucratisation and the resurgence of a new oppressive state power, and instead establish a system of direct democracy?[39]

It was in very similar terms that GuĂ©rin expressed the central question facing the Left in a 1959 essay, “La Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e.”[40] This is an important text in GuĂ©rin’s ideological itinerary, continuing the political analysis he began in **La Lutte de classes sous la PemiĂšre RĂ©publique** and developed in **La Revolution** française **et nous** [The French Revolution and Us] (written in 1944 but not published until 1969) and “Quand le fascisme nous devançait” [When Fascism Was Winning] (1955).[41]

In “La RĂ©volution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e,” GuĂ©rin argued that the “Jacobin” traits in Marxism and particularly in Leninism were the result of an incomplete understanding on Marx and Engels’ part of the class nature of Jacobinism and the Jacobin dictatorship, to be distinguished according to GuĂ©rin from the democratically controlled **contrainte rĂ©volutionnaire** (“revolutionary coercion”) exercised by the popular **sections.** Thus by applying a historical materialist analysis to the experiences of the French revolutionary movement, GuĂ©rin came to argue, essentially, that “authentic” socialism (contrary to what had been argued by Blanqui or Lenin) arose spontaneously out of working-class struggle and that it was fundamentally libertarian. Authoritarian conceptions of party organisation and

revolutionary strategy had their origins in bourgeois or even aristocratic modes of thought.

GuĂ©rin believed that when Marx and Engels referred—rather vaguely—to a “dictatorship of the proletariat” they envisaged it as a dictatorship exercised by the working class as a whole, rather than by an avant-garde. But, he continued, Marx and Engels did not adequately differentiate their interpretation from that of the Blanquists. This made possible Lenin’s later authoritarian conceptions: “Lenin, who saw himself as both a ‘Jacobin’ and a ‘Marxist,’ invented the idea of the dictatorship of a party substituting itself for the working class and acting by proxy in its name.”[42] This, for GuĂ©rin, was where it all started to go badly wrong: “The double experience of the French and Russian Revolutions has taught us that this is where we touch upon the central mechanism whereby direct democracy, the self-government of the people, is transformed, gradually, by the introduction of the revolutionary ‘dictatorship,’ into the reconstitution of an apparatus for the oppression of the people.”[43]

GuĂ©rin’s leftist, class-based critique of Jacobinism thus had three related implications for contemporary debates about political tactics and strategy. First, it implied a rejection of “class collaboration” and therefore of any type of alliance with the bourgeois Left (Popular Frontism). Second, it implied that the revolutionary movement should be uncompromising, that it should push for more radical social change and not stop halfway (which, as Saint-Just famously remarked, was to dig one’s own grave), rejecting the Stalinist emphasis on the unavoidability of separate historical “stages” in the long-term revolutionary process. Third, it implied a rejection both of the Leninist model of a centralised, hierarchical party dominating the labour movement and of the “substitutism” (substitution of the party for the proletariat) which had come to characterise the Bolshevik dictatorship.

This critique clearly had its sources both in GuĂ©rin’s reinterpretation of the French Revolution and in the social and political conditions of the time. **La Revolution franrçaise et nous** was informed by GuĂ©rin’s critique of social democratic and Stalinist strategies before, during, and after the war. “La rĂ©volution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e” was written at a significant historic moment for socialists in France:

after the artificial national unity of the immediate postwar years had given way to profound social and political conflict; as Guy Mollet’s SFIO became increasingly identified with the defence of the bourgeois status quo and the Western camp in the cold war; as the immensely powerful postwar PCF reeled under the effects of the Hungarian uprising of 1956 and of the Khrushchev revelations the same year; and as the unpopular and politically unstable Fourth Republic collapsed in the face of a threatened military coup. It was this situation which made renewal of the Left so necessary. In 1959, GuĂ©rin also picked up on the results of a survey of the attitudes of French youth towards politics, which indicated to him two things: first, that what alienated the younger generation from “socialism” was “bureaucrats and purges,” and second, that, as one respondent put it, “French youth are becoming more and more anarchist.”[44] Ever the optimist, GuĂ©rin declared:

Far from allowing ourselves to sink into doubt, inaction, and despair, the time has come for the French Left to begin again from zero, to rethink its problems from their very foundations .... The necessary synthesis of the ideas of equality and liberty ... cannot and must not be attempted, in my opinion, in the framework and to the benefit of a bankrupt bourgeois democracy. It can and must only be done in the framework of socialist thought, which remains, despite everything, the only reliable value of our times. The failure of both reformism and Stalinism imposes on us the urgent duty to find a way of reconciling (proletarian) democracy with socialism, freedom with Revolution.[45]

From Trotskyism to New Left to Anarchism

What GuĂ©rin would thus do which was quite remarkable in post-Liberation France was endeavour to separate Marxism from Bolshevism—his continued friendly and supportive contacts with a number of Trotskyists notwithstanding—and it is noteworthy that he had contact in this period with a number of prominent non-orthodox Marxists. After 1945, especially, he was involved (centrally or more peripherally) in a number of circles or networks, and according to the sociologist Michel Crozier (who, since their

meeting in America, saw GuĂ©rin as something of a mentor) GuĂ©rin self-identified in the late 1940s and early 1950s—“the golden age of the Left intelligentsia”—as an “independent Marxist.”[46]

C.L.R. James, for instance, has already been mentioned. He and GuĂ©rin appear to have met in the 1930s; they became good friends, GuĂ©rin visited him while in the USA in 1949, and they corresponded over many years. Convinced of the contemporary relevance and of the importance of GuĂ©rin’s analysis, James even began to translate **La Lutte de classes** into English, and described the book as “one of the most important modern textbooks in ... the study of Marxism” and “one of the great theoretical landmarks of our movement.”[47]

Similarly, GuĂ©rin had first met Karl Korsch in Berlin in 1932, and visited him in his exile in Cambridge, Massachusetts, in 1947, where according to GuĂ©rin they spent many hours together.[48] The two would collaborate a decade later in their bibliographical researches on the relationship between Marx and Bakunin.[49] Also during his time in the USA in 1947, GuĂ©rin became friendly with a group of refugee Germans in Washington, D.C., dissident Marxists, “as hospitable as they were brilliant,” connected with the so-called Frankfurt School: Franz Neumann, Otto Kirchheimer and Herbert Marcuse.[50]

In France, GuĂ©rin already knew the leading figures in the Socialisme ou Barbarie group from their days in the Fourth International’s PCI (Internationalist Communist Party) together: GuĂ©rin’s papers contain a number of texts produced by the so-called Chaulieu-Montal Tendency in the late 1940s.[51] It is interesting to note that the Socialisme ou Barbarie group’s theses on the Russian Revolution feature in the list of theories and authors discovered by the Algerian nationalist and revolutionary, Mohammed Harbi, thanks to his first meeting with GuĂ©rin (at a meeting of the PCI discussion group, the “Cercle Lenine”) in 1953.[52] In 1965 GuĂ©rin took part, with Castoriadis, Lefort, and Edgar Morin, in a forum on “Marxism Today” organised by Socialisme ou Barbarie (whose work Morin would describe a few years later as representing “an original synthesis of Marxism and anarchism”[53]). GuĂ©rin also contributed to Morin’s **Arguments** (1956–1962), an important journal launched in response to the events of 1956 with a view to a “reconsideration not only of Stalinist Marxism, but of the Marxist way of thinking,”[54] and

he had been centrally involved with the French “Titoists” around Clara Malraux and the review **Contemporains** (1950–1951).[55]

The present state of our knowledge of these relationships does not enable us to be precise regarding the nature, extent or direction of any influence which might have resulted, but the least we can say is that Guérin was at the heart of the Left-intellectual ferment which characterised these years, that he had an address book, as his daughter Anne recently put it,[56] as fat as a dictionary and that he shared many of the theoretical preoccupations of many leading Marxists in the twenty years or so following the Second World War, be it the party-form, bureaucracy, alienation or sexual repression.

In the mid-to-late 1950s, like other former or “critical” Trotskyists, as well as ex-members of the FCL (the Libertarian Communist Federation, banned in 1956[57]), GuĂ©rin belonged—though “without much conviction”—to a series of Left-socialist organisations: the **Nouvelle Gauche** [New Left], the **Union de la Gauche Socialiste** [Union of the Socialist Left], and, briefly, the **Parti Socialiste Unifie** [Unified Socialist Party].[58] But it was also around 1956 that GuĂ©rin “discovered” anarchism. Looking back on a 1930 boat trip to Vietnam and the small library he had taken with him, GuĂ©rin commented that of all the authors he had studied—Marx, Proudhon, Georges Sorel, Hubert Lagardelle, Fernand Pelloutier, Lenin, Trotsky, Gandhi, and many others—“Marx had, without a doubt, been preponderant.”[59] But having become increasingly critical of Leninism, GuĂ©rin discovered the collected works of Bakunin, a “revelation” which rendered him forever “allergic to all versions of authoritarian socialism, whether Jacobin, Marxist, Leninist, or Trotskyist.”[60] GuĂ©rin would describe the following ten years or so (i.e., the mid-1950s to the mid-1960s)—which saw the publication notably of the popular anthology **Ni Dieu ni MaĂźtre** and of **L’Anarchisme,** which sold like hotcakes at the Sorbonne in May 1968-as his “classical anarchist phase.”[61] He became especially interested in Proudhon, whom he admired as the first theorist of **autogestion,** or worker self-management;[62] Bakunin, representative of revolutionary, working-class anarchism, close to Marxism, GuĂ©rin insisted, yet remarkably prescient about the dangers of statist communism; and Max Stirner, appreciated as a precursor of 1968 because of his determination to attack bourgeois prejudice and puritanism.

The discovery of Bakunin coincided with the appearance of the Hungarian workers’ committees and the Soviet suppression of the Hungarian uprising in 1956. These events provoked GuĂ©rin into studying the councilist tradition, which had come to be seen by many as representing a form of revolutionary socialist direct democracy in contrast to the Bolshevik-controlled **soviets.**[63] It was also during the 1950s that GuĂ©rin, moving on from his study of the French Revolution, had begun to research the political debates and conflicts within the First International and more generally the relationship between Marxism and anarchism.

Guérin and Anarchism

GuĂ©rin had had no contact with the anarchist movement before the Second World War, other than to read E. Armand’s individualist anarchist organ **L’en dehors.** [64] According to Georges Fontenis, a leading figure in the postwar anarchist movement, GuĂ©rin began to have direct contact with the then Anarchist Federation (FA) in 1945, when the second edition of his **Fascism and Big Business** was published. The FA’s newspaper, **Le Libertaire,** reviewed GuĂ©rin’s books favourably, and in the 1950s, he was invited to galas of the FA and (from 1953) of the FCL to do book signings. He got to know leading anarchist militants and would drop in at the FCL’s offices on the Quai de Valmy in Paris. Fontenis described him as being “an active sympathiser” at that point.[65] His new-found sympathies certainly seem to have been sufficiently well-known for the US embassy in Paris to refuse him a visa to visit his wife and daughter in 1950 on the grounds that he was both a Trotskyist **and** an anarchist.[66] The ideological stance of the FCL (“libertarian Marxism”) and its position on the Algerian war (“critical support” for the nationalist movement in the context of the struggle against French bourgeois imperialism) proved doubly attractive to the anticolonialist GuĂ©rin.[67] In part for these reasons, 1954 (the beginning of the Algerian war of independence) represented the beginning of a relationship, notably with Fontenis (leading light of the FCL), which as we shall see would ultimately take GuĂ©rin into the ranks of the “libertarian communist” movement.

In 1959, GuĂ©rin published a collection of articles entitled **jeunesse du socialisme libertaire:** literally the youth—or perhaps the

rise, or invention—of libertarian socialism. This represented both a continuation of the critique of Marxism and Leninism begun during the war, and—as far as I am aware—GuĂ©rin’s first analysis of the nineteenth—century anarchist tradition. Significantly, a copy of this collection has been found with a handwritten dedication to Maximilien Rubel, “to whom this little book owes so much.”[68] A few years later, in 1965, he would publish both **Anarchism: From Theory to Practice** and the two-volume anthology **No Gods No Masters.** The purpose was to “rehabilitate” anarchism, and the anthology represented the “dossier of evidence”:

Anarchism has for many years suffered from an undeserved disrepute, from an iniustice which has manifested itself in three ways.

Firstly, its detractors claim that it is simply a thing of the past. It did not survive the great revolutionary tests of our time: the Russian Revolution and the Spanish Revolution. It has no place in the modern world, a world characterised by centralisation, by large political and economic entities, by the idea of totalitarianism. There is nothing left for the anarchists to do but, “by force of circumstance” as Victor Serge put it, to “join the revolutionary Marxists.”

Secondly, the better to devalue it, those who would slander anarchism serve up a tendentious interpretation of its doctrine. Anarchism is essentially individualistic, particularistic, hostile to any form of organisation. It leads to fragmentation, to the egocentric withdrawal of small local units of administration and production. It is incapable of centralizing or of planning. It is nostalgic for the “golden age.” It tends to resurrect archaic social forms. It suffers from a childish optimism; its “idealism” takes no account of the solid realities of the material infrastructure. It is incurably petit-bourgeois; it places itself outside of the class movement of the modern proletariat. In a word, it is “reactionary.”

And finally, certain of its commentators take care to rescue from oblivion and to draw attention to only its most controversial deviations, such as terrorism, individual assassinations, propaganda by explosives and so on.[69]

Although, as we have seen, he referred to the two books **(Anarchism** and **No Gods No Masters)** as representing his “classical anarchist” phase, and despite his assertion that the basics of anarchist doctrine were relatively homogeneous, elsewhere he was very clear that both books focussed on a particular **kind** of anarchism. To begin with, “the fundamental aspect of these doctrines” was, for GuĂ©rin, that **“anarchy,** is indeed, above all, synonymous with **socialism.** The anarchist is, first and foremost, a socialist whose aim is to put an end to the exploitation of man by man. Anarchism is no more than one of the branches of socialist thought .... For Adolph Fischer, one of the Chicago martyrs, ‘every anarchist is a socialist, but every socialist is not necessarily an anarchist.’” [70]

In **Pour un Marxisme libertaire** (1969), GuĂ©rin described himself as coming from the school of “anti-Stalinist Marxism,” but as having for some time been in the habit of “delving into the treasury of libertarian thought.” Anarchism, he insisted, was still relevant and still very much alive, “provided that it is first divested of a great deal of childishness, utopianism and romanticism,”[71] He went on to comment that because of this openness towards the contribution of anarchism, his book, **Anarchism,** had been misunderstood by some, and that it did not mean that he had become an “ecumenical” anarchist, to use Georges Fontenis’ term.[72] In “Anarchisme et Marxisme” (written in 1973), GuĂ©rin emphasised that his book on anarchism had focussed on “social, constructive, collectivist or communist anarchism” because this was the kind of anarchism which had most in common with Marxism.[73]

The reason GuĂ©rin gave for focussing on this kind of anarchism, as opposed to insurrectionist, individualist or illegalist anarchism or terrorism, was that it was entirely relevant to the problems faced by contemporary revolutionaries: “libertarian visions of the future ... invite serious consideration. It is clear that they fulfil to a very large extent the needs of our times, and that they can contribute to the building of our future.”[74]

But is this really “classical anarchism,” as GuĂ©rin put it, given the insistence on “constructive anarchism, which depends on organisation, on self-discipline, on integration, on federalist and noncoercive centralisation”; the emphasis on experiments in workers’ control in Algeria, Yugoslavia and Cuba; the openness to

the idea that such states could be seen as socialist and capable of reform in a libertarian direction?[75] This was not the conclusion of English anarchist Nicolas Walter, whose review of **Ni dieu ni maftre** commented that “the selection of passages shows a consistent bias towards activism, and the more intellectual, theoretical and philosophical approach to anarchism is almost completely ignored .... There is a similar bias towards revolution, and the more moderate, pragmatic and reformist approach to anarchism is almost completely omitted as well.”[76] As for GuĂ©rin’s **L’Anarchisme,** Walter detected a similar bias towards Proudhon and Bakunin, and was surprised at the emphasis on Gramsci, “which might be expected in a Marxist account [of the Italian workers’ councils after the Great War] but is refreshing in an anarchist one.” Walter was also sceptical about the attention paid to Algeria and Yugoslavia. In summary, however, these two books were “the expression of an original and exciting view of anarchism.”[77]

So GuĂ©rin’s two books arguably represented an original departure, and it is worth quoting some remarks made by Patrice Spadoni who worked alongside GuĂ©rin in different libertarian communist groups in the 1970s and 1980s:

It has to be said that Daniel GuĂ©rin’s non-dogmatism never ceased to amaze us. In the 1970s, a period in which there was so much blinkeredness and sectarianism, in our own ranks as well as among the Leninists, Daniel would often take us aback. The young libertarian communists that we were ... turned pale with shock when he sang the praises of a Proudhon, of whom he was saying “yes and no” while we said “no and no”; then we would go white with horror, when he started quoting Stirner whom we loathed-without having really read him; then we became livid, when he began a dialogue with social-democrats; and finally, we practically had a melt-down when he expressed respect, albeit without agreeing with them, for the revolt of the militants associated with **Action directe.**[78]

Two of these taboos are worth picking up on when considering the extent to which GuĂ©rin’s take on anarchism was a novel one: Proudhon and Stirner.

Proudhon and the Fundamental Importance of Self-management

Proudhon had already ceased to be an ideological reference for any section of the French anarchist movement by at least the time of the Great War, except for a small minority of individualists opposed to any kind of collective ownership of the means of production. Most anarchists referred to either Kropotkin or Bakunin. This was partly because of the ambiguities in Proudhon’s own writings regarding property, and partly because of the increasingly reactionary positions adopted by some of his “Mutualist” followers after his death in 1865.

The fact that Proudhon is so central to GuĂ©rin’s “rehabilitation” of anarchism is thus surprising and tells us something about what he was trying to do and how it is he came to study anarchism in such depth: whereas Proudhon had already for many years been commonly referred to as the “pere de l’anarchie,” the “father of anarchy,” GuĂ©rin refers to him as the “pere de l’autogestion,” the “father of self-management.” This is the crux of the matter: GuĂ©rin was looking for a way to guarantee that in any future revolution, control of the workplace, of the economy and of society as a whole would remain at the base, that spontaneous forms of democracy—like the soviets, in the beginning—would not be hijacked by any centralised power.[79] Marx, GuĂ©rin insisted, hardly mentioned workers’ control or self-management at all, whereas Proudhon paid it a great deal of attention.[80] Workers’ control was, for GuĂ©rin, “without any doubt the most original creation of anarchism, and goes right to the heart of contemporary realities.”[81] Proudhon had been one of the first to try to answer the question raised by other social reformers of the early nineteenth century. As GuĂ©rin put it: “Who should manage the economy? Private capitalism? The state? Workers’ organisations? In other words, there were—and still are—three options: free enterprise, nationalisation, or socialisation (i.e., self-management).”[82] From 1840 onwards, Proudhon had argued passionately for the third option, something which set him apart from most other socialists of the time, who, like Louis Blanc, argued for one form or another of state control (if only on a transitional basis). Unlike Marx, Engels and others, GuĂ©rin argued, Proudhon saw workers’ control

as a concrete problem to be raised now, rather than relegated to some distant future. As a consequence, he thought and wrote in detail about how it might function: “Almost all the issues which have caused such problems for present-day experiments in self-management were already foreseen and described in Proudhon’s writings.” [83]

Stirner the “Father of Anarchism”?

As for Stirner—generally anathema to the non-individualist wing of the anarchist movement-the answer lies in what GuĂ©rin perceived to be Stirner’s latent homosexuality, his concern with sexual liberation and his determination to attack bourgeois prejudice and puritanism: “Stirner was a precursor of May ’68.”[84] His “greatest claim to originality, his most memorable idea, was his

discovery of the “unique” individual.... Stirner became, as a consequence, the voice of all those who throw down a challenge to normality.” [85]

What we can see here, underlying GuĂ©rin’s approving summary of the meaning and importance of Stirner, is someone who had for many years been forced to suffer in silence because of the endemic homophobia of the labour movement, someone who had been forced by society’s moral prejudices to live a near-schizoid existence, totally suppressing one half of his personality. It was GuĂ©rin’s personal experience of and outrage at the homophobia of many Marxists and what seemed to be classical Marxism’s exclusive concern with materialism and class that accounts in large part for his sympathy with Stirner.

So to the extent that GuĂ©rin insists that every anarchist is an individualist—at the same time as being a “social” anarchist **(anarchiste societaire)—to** the extent that he approves of Stirner’s emphasis on the uniqueness of each individual, it is because he admires the determination to resist social conformism and moral prejudice. GuĂ©rin certainly had no truck with the precious “freedom of the individual” which by the 1920s had already become the stock mantra of those anarchists who rejected any attempt to produce a more ideologically and organisationally coherent revolutionary movement or who wished to ground their action in a realistic (or in GuĂ©rin’s words “scientific”) analysis of social conditions.

For a “Synthesis” of Marxism and Anarchism

So having called himself a “libertarian socialist” in the late 1950s before going through an “anarchist phase” in the 1960s, by 1968 GuĂ©rin was advocating “libertarian Marxism,” a term he would later change to “libertarian communism” in order not to alienate some of his new anarchist friends (though the content remained the same). In 1969, with Georges Fontenis and others GuĂ©rin launched the **Mouvement communiste libertaire** (MCL), which attempted to bring together various groups such as supporters of Denis Berger’s **Voie communiste,** former members of the FCL and individuals such as Gabriel Cohn-Bendit who had been associated with Socialisme ou Barbarie.[86] GuĂ©rin was responsible for the organisation’s paper, **Guerre de classes (Class War).** In 1971, the MCL merged with another group to become the **Organisation communiste libertaire** (OCL). In 1980, after complex debates notably over the question of trade union activity, GuĂ©rin-who rejected ultra-Left forms of **“spontaneisme”** which condemned trade unionism as counter-revolutionary—would ultimately join the **Union des travailleurs communistes libertaires** (UTCL), created in 1978. He would remain a member until his death in 1988.[87]

Looking back on those years, Georges Fontenis would write: “For us [the FCL], as for GuĂ©rin, ‘libertarian Marxism’ was never to be seen as a fusion or a marriage, but as a living synthesis very different from the sum of its parts.”[88] How should we interpret this?

GuĂ©rin was always keen to emphasise the commonalities in Marxism and anarchism, and underscored the fact that, in his view at least, they shared the same roots and the same objectives. Having said that, and despite the fact that Rubel seems to have influenced GuĂ©rin, GuĂ©rin’s study of Marx led him to suggest that those such as Rubel who saw Marx as a libertarian were exaggerating and/or being too selective.[89] Reviewing the ambivalent but predominantly hostile relations between Marx and Engels, on the one hand, and Stirner, Proudhon, and Bakunin, on the other, GuĂ©rin concluded that the disagreements between them were based to a great extent on misunderstanding and exaggeration on both sides: “Each of the two movements needs the theoretical and practical contribution of the other,” GuĂ©rin argued, and this is why he saw the expulsion of

the Bakuninists from the International Working Men’s Association Congress at The Hague in 1872 as “a disastrous event for the working class.” [90]

“Libertarian communism” was for GuĂ©rin an attempt to “revivify everything that was constructive in anarchism’s contribution in the past.” We have noted that his **Anarchism** focused on “social, constructive, collectivist, or communist anarchism.”[91] GuĂ©rin was more critical of “traditional” anarchism, with what he saw as its knee-jerk rejection of organisation, and particularly what he considered to be its Manichean and simplistic approach to the question of the “state” in modern, industrial and increasingly internationalised societies. He became interested particularly in militants such as the Spanish anarchist Diego Abad de Santillan, whose ideas on “integrated” economic self-management contrasted with what GuĂ©rin insisted was the naive and backward-looking “libertarian communism” of the Spanish CNT advocated at its 1936 Saragossa conference by Isaac Puente and inspired, GuĂ©rin thought, by Kropotkin.[92] Such a policy seemed to GuĂ©rin to take no account of the nature of modern consumer societies and the need for economic planning and coordination at national and transnational level. In this connection, GuĂ©rin also became interested in the ideas of the Belgian collectivist socialist Cesar de Paepe—who argued against the anarchists of the Jura Federation in favour of what he called an “an-archic state”—on the national and transnational organisation of public services within a libertarian framework.[93]

On the other hand, GuĂ©rin’s libertarian Marxism or communism did not reject those aspects of Marxism which still seemed to GuĂ©rin valid and useful: (i) the notion of alienation, much discussed since Erich Fromm’s 1941 **Fear of Freedom,** and which GuĂ©rin saw as being in accordance with the anarchist emphasis on the freedom and autonomy of the individual; (ii) the insistence that the workers shall be emancipated by the workers themselves; (iii) the analysis of capitalist society; and (iv) the historical materialist dialectic, which for GuĂ©rin remained

one of the guiding threads enabling us to understand the past and the present, on condition that the method not be applied rigidly, mechanically, or as an excuse not to fight on the false
pretext that the material conditions for a revolution are absent, as the Stalinists claimed was the case in France in 1936, 1945 and 1968. Historical materialism must never be reduced to a determinism; the door must always be open to individual will and to the revolutionary spontaneity of the masses.[94]

Indeed, following his focus on anarchism in the 1960s, GuĂ©rin returned in the 1970s to his earlier researches on Marxism, and in his new quest for a synthesis of the two ideologies he found a particularly fruitful source in Rosa Luxemburg, in whom he developed a particular interest and he played a role in the wider resurgence of interest in her ideas. She was for GuĂ©rin the only German social democrat who stayed true to what he called “original” Marxism, and in 1971 he published an anthology of her critical writings on the pre-1914 SFIO, as well as an important study of the notion of spontaneity in her work.[95] GuĂ©rin saw no significant difference between her conception of revolutionary working-class spontaneity and the anarchist one, nor between her conception of the “mass strike” and the syndicalist idea of the “general strike.” Her criticisms of Lenin in 1904 and of the Bolshevik Party in the spring of 1918 (regarding the democratic freedoms of the working class) seemed to him very anarchistic, as did her conception of a socialism propelled from below by workers’ councils. She was, he argued, “one of the links between anarchism and authentic Marxism,” and for this reason she played an important role in the development of GuĂ©rin’s thinking about convergences between certain forms of Marxism and certain forms of anarchism. [96]

GuĂ©rin was convinced that a libertarian communism which represented such a synthesis of the best of Marxism and the best of anarchism would be much more attractive to progressive workers than “degenerate, authoritarian Marxism or old, outdated, and fossilised anarchism.”[97] But he was adamant that he was not a theorist, that libertarian communism was, as yet, only an “approximation,” not a fixed dogma:

It cannot, it seems to me, be defined on paper, in absolute terms. It cannot be an endless raking over of the past, but must rather be a rallying point for the future. The only thing of which I am
convinced is that the future social revolution will have nothing to do with either Muscovite despotism or anaemic social-democracy; that it will not be authoritarian, but libertarian and rooted in self-management, or, if you like, councilist.[98]

Conclusion

To what extent, then, can we say that GuĂ©rin succeeded in producing a “synthesis”? Assessments by fellow revolutionaries have varied. GuĂ©rin himself used to complain that many militants were so attached to ideological pigeonholing and that quasi-tribal loyalties were so strong that his purpose was frequently misunderstood, with many who identified as anarchists criticising him for having “become a Marxist,” and vice versa.[99] Yet GuĂ©rin was always very clear that there have been many different Marxisms and many different anarchisms, and he also insisted that his understanding of “libertarian communism” went beyond or transcended (“**dĂ©passe**”)

both anarchism and Marxism.[100]

Nicolas Walter, in a broadly positive review of GuĂ©rin’s work, and apparently struggling to characterise his politics, described him as “a veteran socialist who became an anarchist” and as “a Marxist writer of a more or less Trotskyist variety” who had gone on to attempt a synthesis between Marxism and anarchism before finally turning to “a syndicalist form of anarchism.”[101]

George Woodcock, in a review of Noam Chomsky’s introduction to the Monthly Review Press edition of GuĂ©rin’s **Anarchism,** insisted that “neither is an anarchist by any known criterion; they are both left-wing Marxists”-their failing having been to focus too narrowly on the economic, on workers’ control, on an “obsolete,” “anarchosyndicalist” perspective.[102] Such a judgement is clearly based on a particular and not uncontentious conception of anarchism.

The opposite conclusion was drawn by another anarchist, Miguel Chueca, who has argued that if we look at all the major issues dividing anarchists from Marxists—namely, according to GuĂ©rin’s **Pour un Marxisme libertaire,** the post-revolutionary “withering away” of the state, the role of minorities (or vanguards or avant-gardes) and the resort to bourgeois democratic methods—then “the ‘synthesis’ results, in all cases, in a choice in favour of the

anarchist position.”[103] Chueca seems to have based his conclusion on an essentialist view of anarchism (in the singular) and of Marxism, and on an identification of Marxism with Leninism. He appears to disregard some significant issues, such as GuĂ©rin’s insistence on the historical materialist dialectic, and the need for centralised (albeit “non-coercive”) economic planning.

Writing from a sympathetic but not uncritical, Trotskyist perspective, Ian Birchall suggests that ultimately GuĂ©rin’s greatest achievement was his practice as a militant:

GuĂ©rin’s greatness lay in his role as a mediator rather than as a synthesist. Over six decades he had a record of willingness to cooperate with any section of the French left that shared his fundamental goals of proletarian self-emancipation, colonial liberation and sexual freedom. He was a vigorous polemicist, but saw no fragment of the left, however obscure, as beneath his attention .... He was also typically generous, never seeking to malign his opponents, however profoundly he disagreed with them .... He was always willing to challenge orthodoxy, whether Marxist or anarchist .... Yet behind the varying formulations one consistent principle remained: “The Revolution of our age will be made from below—or not at all.”[104]

Others have embraced GuĂ©rin’s theoretical contribution and it is clear that his ideas on a “libertarian Marxism” or “libertarian communism” were enormously influential from the 1960s onwards, and many today (notably, but not only, those in France close to the organisation **Alternative libertaire’**[105]) see in him a precursor and are admiring of his theoretical and practical contribution to the search for a libertarian communism—albeit as a contribution which needed further development in the context of the social struggles of the 1980s and beyond. Indeed GuĂ©rin was the first to accept that he had not yet seen the “definitive crystalisation of such an unconventional and difficult synthesis,” which would “emerge from social struggles” with “innovative forms which nobody today can claim to predict”: [106]

It would be pointless today to try to paper over the cracks in the more or less crumbling and rotting edifice of socialist doctrines, to plug away at patching together some of those
fragments of traditional Marxism and anarchism which are still useful, to launch oneself into demonstrations of Marxian or Bakuninian erudition, to attempt to trace, merely on paper, ingenious syntheses or tortuous reconciliations.... To call oneself a libertarian communist today, does not mean looking backwards, but towards the future. The libertarian communist is not an exegete, but a militant.[107]

----

A version of this introduction was first published in Alex Prichard, Ruth Kinna, Saku Pinta, and David Berry (eds.), **Libertarian Socialism: Politics in Black and Red** (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012; 2nd edition, Oakland: PM Press, 2017).

[1] Daniel Guérin, **Front populaire, Révolution manquée. Témoignage militant**

(Aries: Editions Actes Sud, 1977), p. 29. All translations in this introduction are the present author’s, unless stated otherwise.

[2] In **Questions de mĂ©thode,** quoted in Ian Birchall, ‘Sartre’s Encounter with

Daniel GuĂ©rin’, **Sartre Studies International** vol. 2, no. 1 (1996), p. 46.

[3] See Louis Janover, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin, le trouble-fetĂȘ’ in **L’Homme et la sociĂ©tĂ©** no. 94 (1989), thematic issue on ‘Dissonances dans la Revolution’, pp. 83–93.

[4] Letter to Marceau Pivert, 18 November 1947, Bibliotheque de Documentation Internationale Contemporaine (hereafter BDIC), Fonds GuĂ©rin, F” **e.** Res 688/10/2. **La Lutte de classes sous la Premiere Republique, 1793–1797** [Class Struggle under the First Republic] (Paris: Gallimard, 1946; new edition 1968), 2 vols.

[5] Alex Callinicos (ed.), **Marxist Theory** (Oxford University Press, 1989), p. 108.

[6] Daniel GuĂ©rin, **A la recherche d’un communisme libertaire** (Paris: Spartacus,

1984), pp. 10–1.

[7] See D. Berry, ‘Metamorphosis: The Making of Daniel GuĂ©rin, 1904–1930’ in **Modern & Contemporary France** vol. 22, no. 3 (2014), pp. 32I-42, and ‘From Son of the Bourgeoisie to Servant of the Revolution: The Roots of Daniel GuĂ©rin’s Revolutionary Socialism’ in **Moving the Social-journal of Social History and the History of Social Movements** no. 51 (2014), pp. 283–311.

[8] On Malon, see K. Steven Vincent, **Between Marxism and Anarchism: Benoit Malon and French Reformist Socialism** (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992). On Proudhon and Kropotkin, see Iain McKay’s edited anthologies, both of which have useful introductions: **Property Is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Reader** (Oakland: AK Press, 2011) and **Direct Struggle Against Capital: A Peter Kropotkin Anthology** (Oakland: AK Press, 2014).

[9] Cf. Alexandre Christoyannopoulos, ‘Leo Tolstoy on the State: A Detailed Picture of Tolstoy’s Denunciation of State Violence and Deception’, in **Anarchist Studies** vol. 16, no. 1 (Spring 2008), pp. 20–47.

[10] Daniel GuĂ©rin, **Autobiographie de jeunesse, d’une dissidence sexuelle au socialisme** (Paris: Belfond, 1972), pp. 126–7. Charles Maurras was the leader of the right-wing, nationalist and royalist movement, **Action française.**

[11] For more detail, see D. Berry, “‘Workers of the World, Embrace!” Daniel GuĂ©rin, the Labour Movement and Homosexuality’ in **Left History** vol. 9, no. 2 (Spring/Summer 2004), pp. 11–43. See also Peter Sedgwick, ‘Out of Hiding: The Comradeships of Daniel GuĂ©rin’, **Salmagundi** vol. 58, no. 9 (June 1982), pp. 197–220.

[12] Guérin, A la recherche, p. 9; Guérin, **Front populaire,** p. 23.

[13] Guérin, **Front populaire,** p. 147.

[14] See Thierry Hohl, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin, ‘pivertiste’. Un parcours dans la Gauche

rĂ©volutionnaire de la STIO (1935–1938)’ in **Dissidences** 2 (2007), pp. 133–49, and Jacques Kergoat, **Marceau Pivert, ‘socialiste de gauche’** (Paris: Les Editions de l’Atelier/Editions Ouvrieres, 1994). **‘Luxembourgisme’** was an identifiable current on the French left opposed to both Bolshevism and social democracy from around 1928–31. See Alain Guillerm’s preface to the third edition of Rosa Luxembourg, **Marxisme et Dictature: La democratie selon Unine et Luxembourg** (Paris: Spartacus, 1974).

[15] GuĂ©rin’s **Front populaire** is a classic ‘revolutionist’ interpretation of the

Popular Front experience.

[16] What has since become known as ‘entryism’ (‘entrisme’ in French) was originally referred to as ‘the French turn’ (‘le tournant frarn;ais’). This was the new tactic proposed by Trotsky in 1934 in response to the growing fascist threat across Europe, and the first instance of it was the suggestion in June of that year that the French Trotskyists enter the PS in order to contribute to the development of a more radical current within the party. See Daniel Bensald, **Les trotskysmes** (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2002), pp. 31–2 and Alex Callinicos, **Trotskyism** (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1990), pp. 18–9.

[17] GuĂ©rin, **Front populaire,** p. 104. GuĂ©rin’s **Fascisme et grand capital** (Paris:

Gallimard, 1936) was inspired by Trotsky.

[18] GuĂ©rin, **La Peste brune a passe par Iii** (Paris: Librairie du Travail, 1933), translated as **The Brown Plague: Travels in Late Weimar and Early Nazi Germany** (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1994); **Fascisme et grand capital** (Paris: Gallimard, 1936), trans. **Fascism and Big Business** (New York: Monad Press, 1973). **Fascism** has been criticised by some for tending towards reductionism: see Claude Lefort, ‘L’analyse Marxiste et le fascisme’, **Les Temps modernes** 2 (November 1945), pp. 357–62. GuĂ©rin defended himself vigorously against such criticisms, and many regard his analysis as fundamentally correct: see for example Alain Bihr’s introduction to the 1999 edition of **Fascisme et grand capital** (Paris: Editions Syllepse and Phenix Editions), pp. 7–14.

[19] GuĂ©rin, ‘Quand le fascisme nous devançait’, in **La Peste brune** (Paris:

Spartacus, 1996), pp. 21–2.

[20] Ibid., p. 25.

[21] GuĂ©rin, **Front populaire,** pp. 150, 156–7, 365.

[22] Ibid., p. 157.

[23] Ibid., p. 213.

[24] Ibid., p. 23.

[25] See Jean van Heijenoort, ‘Manifeste: La France sous Hitler et PĂ©tain’, in Rodolphe Prager (ed.), **Les congres de la quatriĂšme internationale (manifestes, theses, resolutions)** (Paris: La Breche, 1981) vol. II, pp. 35–44; L. Trotsky, ‘La guerre imperialiste et la revolution proletarienne mondiale’ in D. GuĂ©rin (ed.), **Sur la deuxieme guerre mondiale** (Brussels: Editions la Taupe, 1970), pp. 187–245. An English-language version of the manifesto is available on the Marxists Internet Archive at [[https://www.marxists.org/history/etoV document/fi/1938-1949/emergconf/fi-emergo2.htm]].

[26] Interview with Pierre Andre Boutang in **GuĂ©rin,** television documentary by Jean-Jose Marchand (1985; broadcast on FR3, 4 & 11 September 1989). For more details, see D. Berry, ‘“Like a Wisp of Straw Amidst the Raging Elements”: Daniel GuĂ©rin in the Second World War’, in Hanna Diamond and Simon Kitson (eds.), **Vichy, Resistance, Liberation: New Perspectives on Wartime France (Festschrift in Honour of H.R. Kedward)** (Oxford: Berg, 2005), pp.143–54.

[27] Letter to Marceau Pivert, 2 Januaury 1948, BDIC, Fonds GuĂ©rin, F°Δ RĂ©s 688/9/1.

[28] Daniel GuĂ©rin, **Le Feu du Sang. Autobiographie politique et chamelle** (Paris: Editions Grasset & Fasquelle, 1977), p. 149. On GuĂ©rin’s tour of the U.S., see ibid., pp. 143–219. GuĂ©rin’s researches led to the publication of the two-volume **Ou va le peuple americain?** (Paris: Julliard, 1950–51). Sections of this would be published separately as **Decolonisation du Noir americain** (Paris: Minuit, 1963), **Le Mouvement ouvrier aux Etats-Unis** (Paris: Maspero, 1968), **La concentration economique aux Etats-Unis** (Paris: Anthropos, 1971)—which included a 33pp. preface by the Trotskyist economist Ernest Mandel—and **De l’Oncle Tom aux Pantheres: Le drame des Noirs americains** (Paris: UGE, 1973). Translations: **Negroes on the March: A Frenchman’s Report on the American Negro Struggle,** trans. Duncan Ferguson (New York: George L. Weissman, 1956), and **100 Years of Labour in the USA,** trans. Alan Adler (London: Ink Links, 1979). For a discussion of GuĂ©rin’s analysis, see also Larry Portis, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin et les Etats-Unis: l’optimisme et l‘intelligence’ in **Agone** 29–30 (2003), pp. 277–89.

[29] GuĂ©rin, **La Lutte de classes sous la Pemiere Republique, 1793–1797,** 2 vols. (Paris: Gallimard, 1946; 2nd edition 1968). See also Denis Berger, ‘La revolution plurielle (pour Daniel GuĂ©rin)’ in E. Balibar, J.-S. Beek, D. Bensald et al., **Permanences de la Revolution. Pour un autre bicentenaire** (Paris: La Breche, 1989), pp. 195–208; David Berry, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin a la Liberation. De l’historien de la Revolution au militant rĂ©volutionnaire: un toumant

ideologique’, **Agone** 29–30 (2003), pp. 257–73; Michel Lequenne, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin, l’homme de 93 et le probleme de Robespierre’, **Critique communiste** 130–1 (May 1993), pp. 31–4; Julia Guseva, ‘La Terreur pendant la Revolution et l‘interpretation de D. GuĂ©rin’, **Dissidences** 2 (2007), pp. 77–88; Jean-Numa Ducange, ‘Comment Daniel GuĂ©rin utilise-t-il l’reuvre de Karl Kautsky sur la Revolution française dans **La Lutte de classes sous la premiere Republique,** et pourquoi?’, ibid., pp. 89-m. Norah Carlin, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin and the working class in the French Revolution’, **International Socialism** 47 (1990), pp. 197–223, discusses changes made by GuĂ©rin to **La Lutte de classes** for the 1968 edition.

[30] GuĂ©rin, **La Revolution française et nous** (Paris: Maspero, 1976), pp. 7–8. Note that the reference to ‘libertarian socialism’ is in the preface to **La Revolution française et nous,** written thirty years after the main text and after GuĂ©rin had moved closer to anarchism.

[31] Cf. Murray Bookchin’s comments on the **sections** in ‘The Forms of Freedom’ (1968) in **Post-Scarcity Anarchism** (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1971), p.165.

[32] Guérin, **La Lutte de classes** (1968), vol. I, p. 31.

[33] Ibid., p. 58.

[34] E.J. Hobsbawm, **Echoes of the Marseillaise: Two Centuries Look Back on the French Revolution** (London: Verso, 1990), p. 53.

[35] Guérin, **La Revolutionfrançaise et nous,** p. 7.

[36] For an overview, see Olivier Betoume and Aglaia I. Hartig, **Penser l’histoire de la Revolution. Deux siecles de passionfrançaise** (Paris: La Decouverte, 1989), esp. pp. 110–4. For a recent reassessment of the long-running dispute between GuĂ©rin and G. Lefebvre, see Antonio de Francesco, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin et Georges Lefebvre, une rencontre improbable’, **La Revolutionfrançaise,** [[http://lrf.revues.org/index162.html]], date accessed 28 March 2011.

[37] Ian Birchall, ‘Sartre’s Encounter with Daniel GuĂ©rin’, **Sartre Studies International** vol. 2, no. 1 (1996), p. 46.

[38] GuĂ©rin, ‘Faisons le point’, **Le Liberateur politique et social pour la nouvelle gauche** (12 February 1956). A populist, reactionary and xenophobic anti-taxation movement of small shopkeepers, founded by Pierre Poujade in 1953, ‘Poujadisme’ had “more than a hint of fascism” as Rod Kedward has put it—see **La Vie en Bleu. France and the French since 1900** (London: Penguin, 2006), p. 376. It was as a representative of Poujade’s party that Jean-Marie Le Pen was elected to the National Assembly in 1956.

[39] C.L.R. James, ‘L’actualite de la Revolution française’, **Perspectives socialistes: Revue bimensuelle de ‘Union de la Gauche Socialiste** 4 (15 February 1958), pp. 20–1.

[40] GuĂ©rin, ‘La Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e’, in **]eunesse du socialisme libertaire** (Paris: Riviere, 1959), pp. 27–63. See ‘The French Revolution De-Jacobinized’ in the present collection.

[41] **La Revolution française et nous** was originally intended as the preface to **La Lutte de classes.** ‘Quand le fascisme nous devançait’ was originally commissioned for a special issue of **Les Temps Modernes** on the state of the left, but

was then rejected by Sartre for being too critical of the PCF, according to a letter from GuĂ©rin to C.L.R. James, 10 August 1955. BDIC, Fonds GuĂ©rin, F°Δ 721/60/5.

[42] GuĂ©rin, ‘La Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e’, p. 43.

[43] Ibid., pp. 43–4.

[44] GuĂ©rin, ‘Preface’, in **Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire,** pp. 7–8.

[45] GuĂ©rin, ‘La Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e’, 30–1.

[46] Michel Crozier, **Ma Belle Epoque. Memoires.1947–1969** (Paris: Fayard, 2002),

pp. 79 **er** 86.

[47] GuĂ©rin, **Le Feu du sang,** p. 218; Kent Worcester, **C.LR. James. A Political Biography** (Albany: SUNY, 1996), p. 201; James, letter to GuĂ©rin, 24 May 1956, BDIC, Fonds GuĂ©rin, F°Δ 721/57/2.

[48] GuĂ©rin, **Le Feu du sang,** p. 189. In his account of these meetings, GuĂ©rin refers positively to the collection **La Contre-revolution bureaucratique** (Paris: UGE, 1973), which contained texts by Korsch, Pannekoek, Ruhle and others taken from **International Council Correspondence, Living Marxism** and **International Socialism.** The councilists had previously republished in translation an article of GuĂ©rin’s from the French syndicalist journal **Revolution proletarienne:** ‘Fascist Corporatism’, in **International Council Correspondence** vol. 3, no. 2 (February 1937), pp. 14–26. (I am grateful to Saku Pinta for bringing this to my attention.) On Korsch, see Douglas Kellner (ed.), **Karl Korsch: Revolutionary Theory** (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1977), which includes a lengthy biographical study.

[49] Guérin/Korsch correspondence, April-June 1954. Karl Korsch Papers,

Intemationaal Instituut voor Sociale Geschiedenis (hereafter USG), Boxes 1–24.

[50] Guérin, **Le Feu du sang,** p. 156.

[51] Guérin Papers, USG, Box 1, Folder 14. Pierre Chaulieu and Claude Montal were the pseudonyms of Cornelius Castoriadis and Claude Lefort respectively.

[52] The list also included James Guillaume’s history of the IWMA, Victor Serge’s **Memoirs of a Revolutionary,** Voline’s **The Unknown Revolution,** Makhno, and the many publications of the Spartacus group created by Rene Lefeuvre. Mohammed Harbi, **Une Vie debout. Memoires politiques, Tome I: 1945–1962** (Paris: La Decouverte, 2001), pp. 109–12. Harbi incorrectly describes the Cercle Lenine as being connected to the PCF; see **La Verite,** 1 January 1954. On the different analyses of the nature of the USSR, see Marcel van der Linden, **Western Marxism and the Soviet Union. A Survey of Critical Theories and Debates Since 1917** (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2007); on Castoriadis and Lefort, see pp. 116–8.

[53] Edgar Morin, ‘L’Anarchisme en 1968, **Magazine litteraire** 19 (1968), available at [[https://www.theyliewedie.org/ressources/biblio/fr/Morin_Edgar_-_L'anarchisme_en_1968.html]], accessed 13 April 2021.

[54] See Edgar Morin, ‘La refome de pensee’, in **Arguments, 1956–1962** (Toulouse:

Privat, 1983), vol. I, p. ix.

[55] For an explanation of why Yugoslavia’s break with the Soviet bloc in 1948

was so important to the extreme left in the west, see the semi-autobiographical account in chapter 5, ‘Les “annees yougoslaves”’, of **Le Trotskisme. Une histoire sansfard** (Paris: Editions Syllepse, 2005) by Guenn’s friend and comrade Michel Lequenne.

[56] Anne GuĂ©rin, ‘Les ruptures de Daniel GuĂ©rin. Notice biographique’, in Daniel GuĂ©rin, **De l’Oncle Tom aux Pantheres noires** (Pantin: Les bons caracteres, 2010), p. 9.

[57] On the FCL, see Georges Fontenis, **Changer le monde: Histoire du mouvement communiste libertaire, 1945–1997** (Paris: Alternative libertaire, 2000) and, for a more critical view, Philippe Dubacq, **Anarchisme et Marxisme au travers de la Federation communiste libertaire (1945–1956),** Noir **et Rouge** 23 (1991).

[58] Guérin, **Le Feu du sang,** p. 233.

[59] Guérin, **A la recherche,** p. 9.

[60] Ibid., p. 9.

[61] Ibid., p. 10. **L’Anarchisme, de la doctrine a la pratique** (Paris: Gallimard, 1965); **Ni Dieu ni Maftre, anthologie de l’anarchisme** (Lausanne: La Cite-Lausanne, 1965). Both have been republished several times since, and **L’Anarchisme** has been translated into more than 20 languages. They have been published in English as **Anarchism: From Theory to Practice** (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970), with an introduction by Noam Chomsky, and **No Gods No Masters: An Anthology of Anarchism** (Edinburgh: AK Press, 1998).

[62] This is not uncontentious-indeed Ernest Mandel takes issue with Guérin

over this question in his anthology **Controle ouvrier, conseils ouvriers, autogestion** (Paris: Maspero, 1970), p. 7.

[63] See GuĂ©rin’s 1969 article, ‘Conseils ouvriers et syndicalisme rev olutionnaire. L’exemple hongrois, 1956’ in A la recherche, pp. 111–5; the same piece was republished as ‘Syndicalisme rĂ©volutionnaire et conseillisme’ in **Pour le communisme libertaire,** pp. 155–62.

[64] Letters to the author, 12 and 26 February 1986. **L'en dehors** appeared weekly, 1922–39, and used to campaign for complete sexual freedom, regarding homosexuality as an entirely valid form of ‘free love’. See Richard D. Sonn, **Sex, Violence, and the Avant-Garde: Anarchism in Interwar France** (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2010).

[65] Georges Fontenis, ‘Le long parcours de Daniel GuĂ©rin vers le communisme

libertaire’, special number of **Alternative Libertaire** on GuĂ©rin (1998), p. 37.

[66] Guérin, **Le Feu du sang,** p. 228.

[67] It is also noteworthy that GuĂ©rin would include a section on decolonisation in his **Anarchism** and found material from Proudhon and Bakunin which supported the FCL’s position. See Sylvain Pattieu, **Les camarades des freres: Trotskistes et libertaires dans la guerre d’Algene** (Paris: Syllepse, 2002); Sidi Mohammed Barkat (ed.), **Des Franfais contre la terreur d’état (Algerie 1954–1962)** (Paris: Editions Reflex, 2002); Sylvain Boulouque, **Les anarchistes franfais face aux guerres coloniales (1945–1962)** (Lyon: Atelier de creation libertaire, 2003).

[68] According to a note by the editors in Guérin, **Pour le communisme libertaire**

(Paris: Spartacus, 2003), p. 5. Rubel (1905–96) had had links with the councilist movement and would publish the short text, ‘Marx theoricien de l’anarchisme’ [Marx, theoretician of anarchism] in his **Marx, critique du Marxisme** [Marx, critic of Marxism] (Paris: Editions Payot, 1974; new edition 2000), a collection of articles previously published between 1957 and 1973· The text has since been published as a booklet, **Marx theoricien de l’anarchisme** (Saint-Denis: Vent du ch’min, 1983; Geneva: Editions Entremonde, 2010). His argument in brief was that ‘under the name communism, Marx developed a theory of anarchism; and further, that in fact it was he who was the first to provide a rational basis for the anarchist utopia and to put forward a project for achieving it: Marxists Internet Archive, [[https://www.marxists.org/archive/rubel/1973/marx-anarchism.htm]], accessed 29 March 2011.

[69] Preface of 1970 to GuĂ©rin (ed.), **Ni Vieu ni Maftre. Antholoqie de l’anarchisme**

(Paris: La Decouverte, 1999), vol. I, pp. 6–7. See pp. 41–3 in this volume.

[70] **L’Anarchisme,** p. 21.

[71] Daniel Guérin, **Pour un Marxisme libertaire** (Paris: Robert Laffont, 1969), p. 7.

[72] Georges Fontenis, ‘Le long parcours’, p. 38.

[73] ‘Anarchisme et Marxisme’, p. 237, in **L’Anarchisme** (1981 edition), pp. 229–52. For an English-language version, see the booklet **Anarchism & Marxism** (Sanday, Orkney: Cienfuegos Press, 1981), or ‘Marxism and Anarchism’, in David Goodway (ed.), **For Anarchism: History, Theory and Practice** (London: Routledge, 1989), pp. 109–26.

[74] **L’Anarchisme,** pp. 13–4.

[75] **Anarchism,** p. 153.

[76] Nicolas Walter, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin’s Anarchism’, **Anarchy** vol. 8, no. 94 (1968), p. 378.

[77] Ibid., p. 381.

[78] Patrice Spadoni, ‘La synthese entre l’anarchisme et le Marxisme: “Un point de ralliement vers l’avenir”’, **Alternative Libertaire** special number (2000), p. 43. GuĂ©rin, **Proudhon oui et non** (Paris: Gallimard, 1978),

[79] See his ‘1917–1921, de l’autogestion a la bureaucratie sovietique’, in **De la Revolution d’octobre a l‘empire eclate: 70 ans de reflexions sur la nature de l’URSS** (Paris: Alternative libertaire/UTCL, n.d.); ‘Proudhon et l’autogestion ouvriere’ in **L'ActualitĂ© de Proudhon** (Bruxelles: Universite libre de Bruxelles, 1967), pp. 67–87; ‘L’Espagne libertaire’, editorial introduction to part of **Autogestion et socialisme,** special issue on ‘Les anarchistes et l’autogestion’ nos. 18/19 (janvier-avril 1972), pp. 81–2; ‘L’autogestion contemporaine’, **Nair et rouge** nos. 31/32 (octobre 1965-fevrier 1966), pp. 16–24.

[80] See similarly critical remarks about Marxism’s neglect of this issue by Castoriadis in an interview for a special issue of the UTCL’s magazine on the usefulness (or otherwise) of Marxism for libertarian communists: ‘Marx aujourd’hui. Entretien avec Cornelius Castoriadis’ **Lutter!** no. 5 (May 1983), pp. 15–8. GuĂ©rin’s article on ‘Marx et Engels militants’ appeared in the same issue, pp. 19–20.

[81] **L’Anarchisme,** p. 16.

[82] ‘Proudhon pere de l’autogestion’ (1965) in **Proudhon oui et non** (Paris:

Gallimard, 1978), p. 165.

[83] Ibid., p. 191.

[84] GuĂ©rin, **Ni Dieu ni Maltre,** vol. I, p. 12. GuĂ©rin began his anthology of anarchist texts with the ‘precursor’ Stirner; he also added an appendix on Stirner to the 1981 edition of **L’Anarchisme.** See also D. GuĂ©rin, **Homosexualite et Revolution** (Saint-Denis: Le Vent du ch’min, 1983), p. 12,

and ‘Stirner, “Pere de l’anarchisme”?’, **La Rue** 26 (ler et 2eme trimestre 1979), pp. 76–89. GuĂ©rin also believed Proudhon to have been a repressed homosexual: see ‘Proudhon et l’amour “unisexual”’ in **Arcadie** nos. 133/134 (janvier/ fevner 1965).

[85] ‘Stirner, “Pere de l’anarchisme”?’, p. 83.

[86] See Fontenis, **Changer le monde,** pp. r61-2 and 255–6.

[87] The UTCL’s manifesto, adopted at its Fourth Congress in 1986, was republished (with a dedication to GuĂ©rin) by the UTCL’s successor organisation, Alternative Libertaire: **Un projet de societe communiste libertaire** (Paris: Alternative libertaire, 2002). See also Theo Rival, **Syndicalistes et libertaires: Une histoire de /‘Union des travailleurs communistes libertaires (1974–1991)** (Paris: Editions d’Altemative libertaire, 2013).

[88] Fontenis, **Changer le monde,** p. **Bo,** note i. See also David Berry, ‘Change the world without taking power? The libertarian communist tradition in France today’, **journal of Contemporary European Studies** vol. 16, no. 1 (Spring 2008), pp. 111–30.

[89] GuĂ©rin, ‘Anarchisme et Marxisme’, in **L’Anarchisme** (1981), p. 250.

[90] Ibid., p. 248.

[91] Ibid., p. 237.

[92] On Abad de Santillan, see the section on ‘L’Espagne libertaire’, in **Les anarchistes et l’autogestion,** special issue on ‘Autogestion et socialisme’ nos. 18–19 (1972), pp. 81–117, including an introduction by GuĂ©rin.

[93] See GuĂ©rin, **Ni Dieu ni Maltre,** vol. I, pp. 268–91.

[94] GuĂ©rin, ‘Anarchisme et Marxisme’, in **L’Anarchisme** (1981), p. 252.

[95] Rosa Luxemburg, **Le socialisme en France, 1898–1912** (Paris: Belfond, 1971), with an introduction by GuĂ©rin, pp. 7–48; **Rosa Luxemburg et la spontaniite rĂ©volutionnaire** (Paris: Flammarion, 1971). Typically for GuĂ©rin, the second half of the latter volume brings together a number of texts representing different opinions on the subject. The following year he took part in a debate with Gilbert Badia, Michael Lowy, Madeleine Reberioux, Denis Vidal-Naquet and others on the contemporary relevance of Luxemburg’s ideas. Gilbert Badia et al., ‘Rosa Luxemburg et nous: Debat’, **Politique aujourd’hui: Recherches et pratiques socialistes dans le monde** (1972), pp. 77–106. Looking back at the revival of interest in Luxemburg in the 1960s and 70s, Lowy recently commented: ‘There seems to be a hidden connection between the rediscovery of Rosa Luxemburg and eras of heightened contestation.’ Lowy, ‘Rosa Luxemburg, un Marxisme pour le XXIe siecle’,

p. 59, **Contretemps** 8 (2010), pp. 59–63. This is a special issue devoted to Luxemburg’s continuing relevance to revolutionary politics.

[96] GuĂ©rin, ‘Anarchisme et Marxisme’, p. 233. As the co-editor (with Jean-Jacques Lebel) of a collection entitled ‘Changer la Vie’ for the publisher Pierre Belfond, GuĂ©rin took the opportunity to republish Trotsky’s **Our Political Tasks** (1904), in which the young Trotsky was very critical of Lenin’s ‘Jacobinism’ and of what he called the ‘dictatorship over the proletariat’: Leon Trotsky, **Nos tiiches politiques** (Paris: Belfond, 1970). Luxemburg’s ‘Organizational Questions of Russian Social Democracy’ is also included in the volume as an appendix. It is noteworthy that the English-language version of **Our Political Tasks,** produced in the 1970s by the Trotskyist New Park Publications, omits the sections in which Trotsky was most critical of Lenin. (Unfortunately, the Marxists Internet Archive have used the same partial translation.)

[97] GuĂ©rin, ‘Anarchisme et Marxisme’, p. 252.

[98] GuĂ©rin, A la recherche, pp. 10–1.

[99] GuĂ©rin, ‘Pourquoi communiste libertaire?’, in A **la recherche,** p. 17.

[100] GuĂ©rin, ‘Un communisme libertaire, pour quoi?’, A la recherche, pp. 123–5. Cf. Bookchin’s remark that ‘the problem is not to “abandon” Marxism, or to “annul” it, but to transcend it dialectically’: Murray Bookchin, ‘Listen, Marxist.” in **Post-Scarcity Anarchism** (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1971), p. 177.

[101] Nicolas Walter, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin’s Anarchism’, **Anarchy** vol. 8, no. 94 (1968),

pp. 376–82. GuĂ©rin was not entirely unknown to English readers at the time. **Freedom** had published a translation of a 1966 interview on 30 September 1967.

[102] George Woodcock, ‘Chomsky’s Anarchism’ in **Freedom,** 16 November 1974.

pp. 4–5.

[103] Miguel Chueca, ‘Anarchisme et Marxisme. La tentative de Daniel GuĂ©rin d’unir les deux philosophies et ‘l’anarchisme’ de Marx vu par Maximilien Rubel’ in **Refractions** no. 7, available at [[http://www.plusloin.org/refractions/ refractions7/chueca1.htm]] (accessed 29 August 2006).

[104] Ian Birchall, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin’s Dialogue with Leninism’ in **Revolutionary History** vol. 9, no. 2 (2006), pp. 194–5.

[105] See Irene Pereira, **Un nouvel esprit contestataire. La grammaire pragmatiste du syndicalisme d’action directe libertaire** (Unpublished PhD, Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, Paris, 2009; supervised by Luc Boltanski); Patrice Spadoni, ‘Daniel GuĂ©rin ou le projet d’une synthese entre l’anarchisme et le Marxisme’ in Philippe Corcuff and Michael Lowy (eds.), **Changer le monde sans prendre le pouvoir? Nouveaux libertaires, nouveaux communistes,** special issue of **Contretemps,** no. 6 (February 2003), pp. 118–26; Olivier Besancenot and Michael Lowy, **Affinites rillolutionnaires: Nos etoiles rouges et noires-Pour une solidarite entre marxistes et libertaires** (Paris: Editions Mille et Une Nuits, 2014). GuĂ©rin’s daughter Anne has claimed recently that GuĂ©rin was the ‘Maitre a penser’ of both Daniel Cohn-Bendit and the

Trotskyist Alain Krivine-Biographical preface to Daniel GuĂ©rin, **De l’Oncle Tom aux Pantheres noires** (Pantin: Les Bons caracteres, 2010), p. 8. See also Christophe Bourseiller’s comment that “the politics of the **Mouvement communiste libertaire** derived largely from the theoretical reflexion of Daniel GuĂ©rin.” **Histoire generale de “l‘ultra-gauche”** (Paris: Editions Denoel, 2003), p. 484. In 1986 GuĂ©rin also contributed to the UTCL’s ‘Projet communiste libertaire’, which was republished by Alternative Libertaire in 1993 and again in 2002: **Un projet de societe communiste libertaire** (Paris: Alternative Libertaire, 2002). The ‘Appel pour une alternative libertaire’ of 1989 (which ultimately led to the creation of AL) was also co-written by GuĂ©rin: see GuĂ©rin, **Pour le communisme libertaire** (Paris: Spartacus, 2003), pp. 181–6.

[106] Guérin, A la recherche, p. 10.

[107] GuĂ©rin, ‘Un communisme libertaire, pour quoi?’, in A la recherche, p. 123.

For a Libertarian Communism

Why “Libertarian Communist”?

My education was anti-Stalinist Marxist. But for a good long while I have been foolhardy enough to draw heavily on the treasure chest of libertarian thought, ever relevant and alive on condition that it is first stripped of a not insignificant number of childish, utopian, and romantic notions as little useful as they are out of date.

Hence a misunderstanding that is all but inevitable but embittered by a certain bad faith on the part of my opponents: the Marxists have turned their backs on me as an anarchist, and the anarchists, because of my Marxism, have not always wanted to view me as one of them.

A young, neophyte—and hence sectarian—Marxist even thought he saw in my writings the assuaging of a consciousness that was “torn” between Marxism and anarchism and tossed desperately back and forth between the two, when in fact it is without the least such vacillation or any concern for my personal intellectual comfort that I believe in both the need for and the practicability of a synthesis between Marxism and anarchism.

Recently a working-class newspaper of Trotskyist bent and, let it be said in passing, of high quality, assured its readers that I had gone over from Marxism to anarchism. Taking advantage of the right to respond that was democratically afforded me, I responded to this inaccurate statement, the fruit of a basic need to catalogue everyone, that I was making “a contribution to the search for a synthesis between Marxism and anarchism.” “A synthesis,” I added, “that since May ’68 has moved from the realm of ideas to that of

action.”

But I was still seeking a denomination, since in order to communicate we all need a label. The one I had decided on ten years ago, that of “libertarian socialist,” no longer seemed to me appropriate, for there are many kinds of socialism, from social democratic reformism to “revisionist communism” and an adulterated humanism. In short, the word “socialism” belongs to the category of debased words.

[Italian students with whom I had debated Marxism and anarchism in general and self-management in particular, provided me with the label: these young people call themselves libertarian Marxists. In truth this is not a discovery: the protesters of May in France, red and black flags mixed together, were libertarian Marxists, without being aware of it or calling themselves such.]

Hence the title of this book. Assembled here are a certain number of texts, varied in their subject matter and the periods in which they were written, but which all converge from various roads on the approach to a libertarian communism.

The short book published under the title **Anarchism** might have created a double misunderstanding: that I espoused all the ideas laid out in it for information purposes, and also that I showed myself unable to draw from this digest a synthesis of my own devising, which would be valid in the present and the future.[108] This supposition was doubly inexact, for I willingly effaced myself before the subject. In the present collection I attempt to fly with my own wings. At my own risk.

[The materials presented here are followed by the date they were written, though some retouching was done in order to bring the style and content up to date.]

The revolution that is rising before us will be—already is—libertarian communist.

<right>

[May 1969]

</right>

----

Note: The paragraphs in square brackets were present in the original 1969 version of this article (‘Pourquoi “marxiste libertaire”?’), but omitted from subsequent editions.

[108] GuĂ©rin is referring to **L’Anarchisme, de la doctrine Ă  la pratique** first published in 1965 by Gallimard. It was published in English as **Anarchism: From Theory to Practice** (Monthly Review Press, 1970), with an Introduction by Noam Chomsky. [DB]

The Rehabilitation of Anarchism

Anarchism has long been a victim of an undeserved discredit, of an injustice that has manifested itself in three ways.

First, its defamers insist that anarchism is dead, that it has not resisted the great revolutionary tests of our time: the Russian Revolution and the Spanish Revolution. That it no longer has a place in the modern world, characterized as this is by centralization, large-scale political and economic units, and the totalitarian concept. All that is left to the anarchists, as Victor Serge said, is, “by the force of events to go over to revolutionary Marxism.”[109]

Second, its detractors, in order to better discredit it, propose an absolutely tendentious vision of its doctrine. Anarchism is said to be essentially individualist, particularist, and resistant to any form of organization. It aims at fracturing and atomizing, at the retreat into themselves of local units of administration and production. It is said to be incapable of unity, centralization, and planning. It’s nostalgic for “the Golden Age.” It aims for the reviving of outmoded forms of society. It sins by a childish optimism; its “idealism” fails to take into account the solid reality of the material infrastructure.

Finally, certain commentators are interested solely in wresting from oblivion and publicizing only its most controversial deviations, like individual assassinations and propaganda by the deed.

In revisiting the question I’m not simply trying to retrospectively repair a triple injustice or trying to write a work of erudition. It seems to me, in fact, that anarchism’s constructive ideas are still alive; that they can, on condition they be reexamined and closely scrutinized, assist contemporary socialist thought in making a new start.

Nineteenth-century anarchism is clearly distinguishable from twentieth-century anarchism. Nineteenth-century anarchism was essentially doctrinal. Though Proudhon had played a more or less

central role in the revolution of 1848, and the disciples of Bakunin were not totally foreign to the Paris Commune, these two nineteenth-century revolutions in their essence were not libertarian revolutions, but to a certain extent rather “Jacobin” revolutions. On the contrary, the twentieth century is, for the anarchists, one of revolutionary practice. They played an active role in the two Russian Revolutions and, even more, in the Spanish Revolution.

The study of the authentic anarchist doctrine, as it was formed in the nineteenth century, shows that anarchy is neither disorganization, disorder, nor atomization, but the search for true organization, true unity, true order, and true centralization, which can only reside, not in authority, coercion, or compulsion exercised from the top down, but in free, spontaneous, federalist association from the bottom up. As for the study of the Russian and Spanish revolutions and the role played in them by the anarchists, it shows that contrary to the false legend believed by some, these great and tragic experiences show that libertarian socialism was largely in the right against the socialism I’ll call “authoritarian.” Throughout the world, socialist thought over the course of the fifty years that followed the Russian Revolution, of the thirty years that followed the Spanish Revolution, has remained obsessed with a caricature of Marxism, bursting with its dogmas. In particular, the internecine quarrel between Trotsky and Stalin, which is the one best known to the advanced reader, if it contributed to wresting Marxism-Leninism from a sterilizing conformism, did not truly cast complete light on the Russian Revolution, because it did not address—could not address—the heart of the problem.

For Voline, anarchist historian of the Russian Revolution, to speak of a “betrayal” of the revolution, as Trotsky does, is insufficient as an explanation: “How was that betrayal possible in the aftermath of so beautiful and total a revolutionary victory? This is the real question .... What Trotsky calls betrayal was, in fact, the ineluctable effect of a slow degeneration due to incorrect methods .... It was the degeneration of the revolution ... that led to Stalin, and not Stalin who caused the revolution to degener.” Voline asks: “Could Trotsky really ‘explain’ the drama since, along with Lenin, he himself contributed to the disarming of the masses.”[110]

The assertion of the late, lamented Isaac Deutscher, according to which the Trotsky-Stalin controversy would “continue and reverberate for the rest of the century” is debatable.[111] The debate that should be reopened and continued is perhaps less that between Lenin’s successors, which is already outdated, but rather that between authoritarian socialism and libertarian socialism. In recent time anarchism has come out of the shadow to which it was relegated by its enemies.

Materials for a fresh examination of anarchism are today available to those who are impassioned about social emancipation and in search of its most effective forms. And also, perhaps, the materials for a synthesis, one both possible and necessary, between the two equally fertile schools of thought: that of Marx and Engels and that of Proudhon and Bakunin. Ideas, it should be said, contemporary in their flowering and less distant from each other than might be thought. Errico Malatesta, the great Italian anarchist, observed that all the anarchist literature of the nineteenth century “was impregnated with Marxism.”[112] And in the other direction, the ideas of Proudhon and Bakunin contributed in no small degree to enriching Marxism.

<right>

[1965]

</right>

[109] Serge’s preface to Joaquin Maurin, **RĂ©volution et Contre-Revolution en Espagne**

(Rieder, 1937).

[110] See Voline’s **The Unknown Revolution,** 1917–1921 (Book 2, Part V, Ch. 7), first published in French in 1947. Voline was the pseudonym of Vsevolod Mikhailovich Eikhenbaum (1882–1945), a prominent Russian anarchist who took part in both the Russian and Ukrainian revolutions before being forced into exile by the Bolsheviks. [DB]

[111] See Deutscher’s biography of Trotsky, **The Prophet Armed, The Prophet Unarmed** and **The Prophet Outcast** (first published 1954–63).

[112] Malatesta, polemic of 1897 quoted by Luigi Fabbri, **Dittoturae Rivoluzione**

(1921).

Proudhon and Workers’ Self-Management

The problem is one with a certain topicality. In effect, it revolves around the question already touched on by the social reformers of the nineteenth century and posed with even more perplexity by the men of today: who should manage the economy? Is it private capitalism? Is it the state? Is it the associated workers? In other words, three options existed and continue to exist: free enterprise, nationalization, and socialization, i.e., self-management.

From 1848 Pierre-Joseph Proudhon was the ardent advocate of the third solution. In this he set himself apart from the socialists of his time, supporters of at least transitional state management. Their spokesman was Louis Blanc in his pamphlet on **The Organization of Labor** (1840).[113] It was Louis Blanc who was Proudhon’s **bĂȘte noire,** rather than Marx and Engels, whose **Communist Manifesto,** written in German in 1847, he was not aware of. Louis Blanc’s influence makes itself felt in the **Manifesto,** where it was a question of “centralizing all the instruments of production in the hands of the state.” State centralization crops up constantly in it, like a litany: “Centralization of credit in the hands of the state with state capital and its exclusive monopoly.” “Centralization in the hands of the state of all means of transport.” “The organization of industrial armies, particularly for agriculture.”

It’s true that the authors of the **Manifesto,** still following Louis Blanc, envisaged a later stage, no longer statist but clearly libertarian, from which, the proletariat having destroyed classes and thus class antagonism, the state would disappear and production would—finally—be managed by the workers.

But the end of the transitional statist period was relegated to a distant future, was more or less considered utopian and, because of this, it was felt unnecessary to lay out the problems of workers’

self-management before its time. When one reads Marx one is surprised at the rarity, the brevity, and the summary nature of the passages concerning the free association of producers. On the other hand Proudhon who, because he was of working-class origins and upbringing, considered self-management a concrete, immediate problem, studied its functioning in depth and in detail. This is why those of our contemporaries who consider the problem of self-management or who try to put it into practice gain far more from the works of Proudhon than from those of Marx. Before trying to lay out the Proudhonian conception of workers’ self-management it is necessary to briefly recall, in contrast, his rejection of “authoritarian” management of the economy. Since he could not have read the **Communist Manifesto** and could only have had imperfect knowledge of Marxist thought, notably through the **Poverty of Philosophy,** written in French, it is principally against Louis Blanc, his compatriot and direct adversary, that Proudhon multiplied his attacks:

The state is the patrimony, it’s the blood and the life of Louis Blanc. Hit out at the state and Louis Blanc is a dead man.

Once the economic revolution is accomplished, must the state and the government remain? With the economic revolution ... the state should completely disappear.[114]

“The instruments of production and exchange should not be entrusted to the state. Being to the workers what the hive is to bees, their management should be entrusted to workers’ associations.”[115] Only thus “large-scale industry which, through the alienation of popular power, lowers the wage earner to a state worse than slavery, becomes one of the main organs of freedom and public happiness.”[116] “We associated producers or those on the path of association.” Proudhon proclaims in the style of a manifesto, “have no need of the state .... Exploitation by the state is still monarchy, still wage labor ... **We** no more want government of man by man than exploitation of man by man. Socialism is the opposite of governmentalism .... We want these associations to be ... the first nucleus of a vast federation of companies and enterprises, united by the common bond of the democratic and social republic.”[117]

Let us now see what the workers’ self-management which Proudhon opposed to the transitional state management dear to both Louis Blanc and Karl Marx consisted of.

The revolution of February 1848 saw a spontaneous blossoming of workers’ productive associations born in Paris and Lyon. It was this nascent self-management, rather than the political revolution, which was, for the Proudhon of 1848, “the revolutionary fact.” It had not been invented by a theoretician or preached by doctrinaires. It was not given its initial impetus by the government. It came from the people. And Proudhon implored the workers throughout the republic to organize in the same way; that they draw to them, first small property, small merchants, and small industry, then large property and large enterprises, and then the most extensive operations (mines, canals, railroads, etc.), and in so doing “become the masters of everything.”[118]

There’s a tendency today to only recall Proudhon’s desire, naive to be sure, and doubtless anti-economic, to ensure the survival of small-scale artisanal and commercial enterprise. There is certainly no lack of texts where Proudhon takes the side of small producers. Georges Gurvitch observed in the rich little book he dedicated to Proudhon that the writer had entitled a postscript to his **Confessions of a Revolutionary** (1851): “Apotheosis of the middle class,” and that he’d “dreamed of a reconciliation of the proletariat and the middle class.”[119] In his posthumous book, **The Theory of Property,** Proudhon made the following clarification:

The object of workers’ associations is not to replace individual action by collective action, as was madly believed in 1848, but rather that of ensuring all the entrepreneurs of small and middle industry the benefit of the discoveries, machines, improvements and procedures otherwise unavailable to modest enterprises and fortunes.

But Proudhonian thought is ambivalent on this point. Proudhon was a living contradiction. He railed against property, the source of injustice and exploitation, and celebrated it to the extent that he saw in it a guarantee of personal independence. What is more, we too often have the tendency to confuse Proudhon with the tiny so-called Proudhonian coterie that, according to Bakunin, formed around him in the final years of his life. This fairly reactionary coterie was, he said, “stillborn.”[120] Within the first International it vainly attempted to oppose private ownership of the means of production to collectivism. And if it did not live long it was mainly because most of its followers, easily convinced by

Bakunin’s arguments, did not hesitate to abandon their supposedly Proudhonian concepts in favour of collectivism.

In any case, the last Mutualists, as they called themselves, only partially rejected collective property. They only fought against it in agriculture, given the individualism of the French farmer, but they accepted it in transport, and in the case of industrial self-management they called for the thing while rejecting the name.[121] If they were so afraid of the name it was mainly because the temporary united front formed against them by Bakunin’s collectivist disciples and certain authoritarian Marxists, barely disguised supporters of state management of the economy—like Lucraft at the Basel Congress[122]—did nothing to reassure them. Marxist defamation did the rest, attributing to Proudhon the somewhat reactionary point of view of his epigones.

In fact, Proudhon was in step with his time. As Pierre Haubtmann pointed out in his magisterial thesis, “He has often been incorrectly presented as hostile to the very principle of large-scale industry. There is no doubt that at the sight of the Moloch factory—like the tentacular state—he reflexively recoils in fear, which leads him, in reaction, to lean towards small businesses and decentralization. But as concerns economic life, it would be a serious error to think that he was hostile to the principle of mass production. On the contrary, he speaks to us at length and enthusiastically of the need for powerful workers’ productive associations. Of their role and their grandiose future. He thus accepts and even desires large-scale industry .... But he wants to humanize it, to exorcise its evil power, to socialize it by handing its fate over to a community of workers, equal, free, and responsible.”[123] Proudhon understands it is impossible to go backwards. He is realistic enough to see, as he writes in his **Notebooks,** that “small-scale industry is as foolish as small-scale culture.”[124]

As for large-scale modern industry, demanding a significant number of workers, he is decisively collectivist: “In the future large-scale industry and large-scale agriculture must be born of association.”[125]

In **General Idea of Revolution in the Nineteenth Century** (1851) Proudhon several times returned to this modernist and, I might say, futurist concept: “The workers’ companies, a protest against wage

labor, are called on to play a considerable role in the near future. This role will above all consist in the management of the great instruments of labor and of certain tasks, which “demand’ both a great division of functions and a great collective force.”[126]

In his **Justice** (1858) Proudhon waxes indignant that people have dared to present him as an enemy of technical progress.[127] In his final work, which appeared shortly after his death, **On the Political Capacity of the Working Class,** he again confirms: “The construction of railroads should have been entrusted to workers’ companies. If it’s a matter of large-scale manufacturing, extractive, maritime or steel industries, it is clear that there is place for association. No one any longer contests this.”[128]

In my book **Anarchism** I already listed the essential conditions for workers’ self-management:

- Every associated individual has an undivided share in the property of the company.

- Every worker must assume his share of unpleasant and difficult tasks.

- He must pass through a variety of work and instruction and positions in the company that ensure him an encyclopedic education. Proudhon insists absolutely on “having the worker go through the series of industrial operations to which he is connected. In this way the division of labor can no longer be a cause of degradation for the worker; on the contrary, it is the instrument of his education and the guarantor of his security.”[129]

Pierre Haubtmann, commenting on Proudhon, remarked that for Marx it’s the “automatic workshop”—we would say automation—which, through the division of labor and the reduction of working hours, both pushed to the extreme, will allow every man to achieve “total development.” Machinery extending man, disalienation will enter into play, not in work, but in leisure. Proudhon is hardly seduced by such a perspective. For him, man is essentially a producer. He wants him to constantly be at work. We’re at antipodes from the exuberant **Right to be Lazy** by Paul Lafargue.[130] For the ferocious Puritan, for the “Saint Paul of socialism” that Proudhon

was, leisure is not far from being a synonym for lust.[131] He expects “disalienation” from a mode of production that would give the

worker a synthetic vision of the labor process.[132]

Gurvitch, contrasting Marx and Proudhon, underlines the following passage from **Justice:** “The spirit is no longer in the worker; it has passed over to the machine. What should be the virtue of the worker has become his degradation.” This evil can only be corrected “if the collective forces alienated for the profit of a few exploiters are

returned to labor as a whole.”[133]

Proudhon counts on an increase in productivity under self-management, thanks to the joy of disalienated labor.

After this digression, according to Proudhon the essential conditions of self-management are:

- Functions are elective and the rules are submitted for the approval of the associates.

- Remuneration is proportional to the nature of the function, the importance of the talent, and the breadth of the responsibility. Each associate participates in the profits in proportion to his services.

- Everyone is free to quit the association at will, to regulate his hours, and liquidate his share.

- The associated workers select their leaders, their engineers, their architects, and their accountants. Proudhon insists on the fact that the proletariat is still lacking in certain abilities. It must be recognized that “due to the insufficiency of its insights and its lack of business expertise the working class is still incapable of managing interests as large as those involved in commerce and large-scale industry, and consequently falls short of achieving its destiny. Men are lacking among the proletariat.”[134]

Hence the need to join to workers’ self-management “industrial and commercial notables” who will initiate the workers in the disciplines of business and who will be paid a fixed wage: “There is room for everyone under the sun of the revolution.”[135]

Let us note in passing that this libertarian understanding of self-management is at antipodes from the paternalistic and statist

“self-management” laid out by Louis Blanc in a decree of September 15, 1849.[136] The author of **The Organization of Labor** wanted to create workers’ associations under the aegis of and sponsored by the state. He envisioned an authoritarian division of profits: 25 percent for the amortization of capital, 25 percent for social assistance funds, 25 percent for reserve funds; 25 percent to be shared among the workers.

Proudhon wanted nothing to do with a “self-management” of this kind. No compromise was possible for an intransigent individual like him. The associated workers were not “to submit to the state” but “to be the state itself.”[137] “The association ... can do everything, reform everything without the assistance of the authorities, conquer and force authority itself to submit.”

Proudhon wanted “to march to government through association and not to association through government.”[138]

He warned against the illusion that the state, as dreamed of by the authoritarian socialists, could tolerate free self-management. How “could it accept, alongside a centralized power, the formation of enemy centers?” From which this warning, whose intransigence becomes prophetic: “Nothing is doable through the initiative, spontaneity, and independent actions of individuals and collectivities as long as they face the colossal force with which the state is invested by centralization.”[139]

In fact, Proudhon anticipates here the tragedy of contemporary self-management, as experienced in both Yugoslavia and Algeria within the framework of a dictatorial state.

In fact, it is the libertarian and not the statist concept of self-management that prevailed at the congresses of the First International. At the Lausanne Congress (1867) the rapporteur, the Belgian Cesar de Paepe, having proposed making the state the owner of the enterprises to be nationalized, Charles Longuet, at the time a libertarian, added: “Agreed, on the condition that it be understood that we define the state as the collective of citizens ... and also that these services will not be administered by state functionaries but by workers’ companies.” The debate was picked up again the following year (1868) at the Brussels Congress and the same rapporteur was careful to make the requested rectification: “Collective property will belong to the entire society, but it will be conceded to workers’ associations. The state will now be only

the federation of various groups of workers.” The proposal, thus, refined, was adopted.[140]

The optimism Proudhon demonstrated in 1848 relating to self-management was somewhat belied by the lesson of facts. A few years later, in 1857, he subjected the workers’ organizations still in existence to a harsh critique. Their inspiration had been naive, illusory, and utopian. They had paid the price for inexperience. They had fallen into particularism and exclusivism. They had functioned like a collective managerial class and been swept along by the ideas of hierarchy and supremacy. All the abuses of capitalist societies “were exaggerated in these so-called fraternal companies.” They had been torn by discord, rivalries, defections, and betrayals. Their managers, once they had been initiated into the business, had withdrawn “to set themselves up as bosses and bourgeois.” Elsewhere, it was the associates who had called for the sharing out of products. Of the several hundred workers’ associations created in 1848, twenty remained nine years later. And Proudhon opposed a notion of “universal” and “synthetic” self-management to that narrow and particularist mentality. The task for the future was far more than the “assembling into societies of a few hundred workers;” it was nothing less than “the economic reconstituting of a nation of thirty-six million souls.” The future workers’ associations, “instead of acting for the profit of a **few**,” must work for all.[141] Self-management thus demanded “a certain education” of the self-managers. “One is not born an associate; one becomes **one**.” The most difficult task of the associations was that of “civilizing the associates.” What they had lacked—and here Proudhon renewed his warning of 1851—was “men issued from the working masses who had learned at the school of the exploiters to do without them,” It was less a matter of forming “a mass of capital” than a “fund of men.”[142]

On the legal plane Proudhon had initially envisaged entrusting the property of their enterprises to the workers’ associations. Now, as Georges Gurvitch points out, he rejected his original notion “of ownership by groups of producers.”[143] In order to do this he distinguished, in a posthumous work, between possession and property.[144] Property is absolutist, aristocratic, feudal, despotic; possession is democratic, republican, egalitarian: it consists in the usufructuary enjoyment of a non-cedable, indivisible and inalienable concession. The producers

would receive, as **“allods,”** like the ancient Germans, their instruments of production. They would not be the owners. This “higher formulation” of ownership would unite all the advantages of property and association without any of the drawbacks. What would succeed property would be, as Gurvitch says, federative co-property attributed not to the state, but to all the producers, united in a vast agricultural and industrial federation. The economic federation would come to “counterbalance” the state, a state this time not erased from the Proudhonian map, but transformed from top to bottom.

And Proudhon sees a revised and corrected self-management in the future: “It’s no longer vain rhetoric that proclaims it: it’s economic and social necessity. The moment approaches when we’ll only be able to advance under these new conditions .... The classes ... must be resolved into one sole association of producers.”[145]

On what bases will the exchanges between the various workers’ associations be ensured? Proudhon initially maintained that the exchange value of all merchandise could be measured by the amount of labor necessary for its production. The various production associations would sell their goods at cost. The workers, paid with “labor bonds,” would purchase merchandise at exchange posts or in social stores at cost.

This so-called Mutualist conception was a tad utopian, in any case difficult to apply under capitalism. The People’s Bank, founded by Proudhon in early 1849, succeeded in obtaining some 20,000 members in six weeks, but its existence was to be brief. To be sure, the sudden rise to power of Prince-President Louis Bonaparte had something to do with this. But it was illusory to think that Mutualism would spread and to exclaim as Proudhon did that “it was truly the new world, the society of “promise’ which, grafted onto the old world, gradually transformed it!”

It appears that Pierre Haubtmann was correct in stressing in his thesis the illusory character of the Mutualism of the years 1846–1848. But he perhaps attacked Proudhon too vigorously in the way that he invokes the sins of his youth, which would quickly be corrected by his concrete and more positive visions of workers’ self-management.

Remuneration based on the evaluation of working hours was debatable for various reasons. Around 1880 the anarchist

communists (or “libertarian communists”) of the school of Kropotkin, Malatesta, ElisĂ©e Reclus, Carlo Cafiero and others did not fail to criticize it. In the first place, in their eyes it was unjust: “Three hours of Peter’s labor,” Cafiero objected, “are often worth five hours of Paul’s.” Factors other than duration intervene in the determination of the value of labor: the intensity, the professional and intellectual education required, etc. We must also take into account the worker’s family responsibilities. One finds the same objections in the **Critique of the Gotha Program,** written by Karl Marx in 1875, but hushed up by German social democracy until 1891. and which the libertarian communists thus were not aware of when they argued against Proudhon.

What is more, maintains the school of Kropotkin, under a collectivist regime the worker remains a wage earner, a slave to the community that purchases and keeps an eye on the quantity of his labor. Remuneration proportionate to the hours of labor furnished by each cannot be an ideal, but at best a temporary expedient. We must have done with morality based on accounting ledgers, with the philosophy of “must and have to.”

This mode of remuneration proceeds from a watered down individualism in contradiction with collective ownership of the means of production. It is incapable of implementing a profound and revolutionary transformation of man. It’s incompatible with anarchism. A new form of ownership demands a new form of remuneration: the services rendered society cannot be evaluated in monetary units. Needs must be placed above services. All the products produced by the labor of all should belong to all, and each should freely take his share. To each according to his needs; this must be the motto of libertarian communism.[146]

But Malatesta, Kropotkin, and their friends seem to have been unaware that Proudhon himself at least partially foresaw their objections and in the end revised his original conception. His **Theory of Property,** published posthumously, explained that it was only in his **First Memorandum on Property,** that of 1840, that he supported the equality of salaries to the equality of labor. “I had forgotten to say two things; first that labor is measured by a composite of duration and intensity; second, that there should not be included in the worker’s wage either the amortization of his educational costs and

the work he undertook on his own as a non-paid apprentice, or the insurance premiums against the risks he runs, and which are far from being the same in all professions.”

Proudhon asserted he had “repaired” this “omission” in his subsequent writings, where he had the unequal costs and risks paid for by the mutual insurance cooperative societies.[147] We note here that Proudhon in no way considered the remuneration of association members a salary, but rather a distribution of profits, freely decided by associated workers and those jointly responsible. If not, as Pierre Haubtmann notes, self-management makes no sense.

The libertarian communists also reproached Proudhon’s Mutualism and the more consistent collectivism of Bakunin for not having wanted to prejudge the form that the remuneration of labor would take under a socialist regime. These critics seem to lose sight of the fact that the two founders of anarchism were careful not to prematurely imprison society in a rigid framework. On this point they wanted to preserve the greatest latitude for the workers’ associations. For Bakunin collectivism had to be practiced “under varied forms and conditions, which will be determined in each locale, in each region, and each commune by its degree of civilization and the will of the population.”[148]

But the libertarian communists themselves provide the justification for this flexibility, for this refusal of premature solutions when, contrary to their impatient expectations, they insist that in the ideal regime of their choice “labor will produce much more than is needed for all.” In fact, it is only when the era of abundance arrives that “bourgeois” norms of remuneration can give way to specifically “communist” norms. And not before this, as Marx and Lenin saw

with a certain lucidity, though not without statist prejudice.[149]

In 1884, writing the program of an anarchist International still in a state of limbo, Malatesta admitted that communism would only be immediately realizable in extremely limited sectors and that “for the rest” one must “transitionally” accept collectivism. “In order to be realizable, communism requires a great moral development of the members of society, an elevated and profound feeling of solidarity that the revolutionary outburst will perhaps not suffice in producing, which is even more likely in that at the beginning the material conditions favoring such a development will be lacking.”[150]

After Malatesta, the anarchist Fernand Pelloutier, having become a revolutionary syndicalist, would be even more categorical: “No one believes ... that the imminent revolution will realize pure communism. Since it will in all likelihood break out before anarchist education has been completed, men will not be mature enough to absolutely rule themselves. We must take men as they are, as the old society left them to us.”[151]

Among the norms inherited from bourgeois economics, there is one whose maintenance under collectivism or self-management raises thorny problems, to wit, competition. Just as in Proudhon’s eyes private property in the products of labor constitutes a guarantee for the producer of their personal independence, competition is “the expression of social spontaneity,” the guarantor of the “freedom” of associations. In addition, it constitutes, for a long time to come, an irreplaceable stimulant without which “an immense relaxation would succeed the ardent tension of industry.” “Remove competition ... and society, deprived of its motive force, would stop like a pendulum whose spring is loose.”[152] Proudhon proposed practical recipes: “Vis-a-vis society, the workers’ company commits to always providing the products and services requested of it at a price close to cost.... To this effect the workers’ company forbids itself any [monopolistic] coalitions, accepts the law of competition, and places its books and archives at the disposal of society, which, as the sanction of its right of control, preserves the ability to dissolve it.”[153] “Competition and association mutually support each other .... The most deplorable error of socialism is that of having regarded [competition] as the overturning of society. There can be no question of destroying competition .... It’s a question of finding its equilibrium, I would even say its organization.”[154]

This attachment to the principle of competition earned Proudhon the sarcasm of Louis Blanc. “We are unable to understand those who imagined some strange coupling of two opposing principles. Grafting association onto competition is a poor idea. It means replacing eunuchs with hermaphrodites.”[155]

Louis Blanc wanted to “arrive at a uniform price” fixed by the state and to prevent any competition between the workshops of one industry. Proudhon replied that prices “are only settled by competition,” that is, by the consumer’s ability to “to do without the services of those who overstate them.”[156]

To be sure, Proudhon did not hide the evils of competition, which he had abundantly described in his **Philosophy of Poverty.** He knew it was a source of inequality. He admitted that “in competition victory is assured to the largest battalions.” As long as it is “anarchic” (in the pejorative sense of the term), as it only exists for the profit of private interests, it necessarily engenders civil war and, in the end, oligarchy. “Competition kills competition.”[157]

But in Proudhon’s opinion the absence of competition would be no less pernicious. He cited the example of the state-run tobacco office. This monopoly, from the very fact that it is free of competition, is too dear a service and its productivity is insufficient. If all industries were subject to such a regime, the nation, according to him, would no longer be able to balance its receipts and expenses.[158]

However the competition dreamed of by Proudhon is not the unfettered competition of the capitalist economy, but a competition endowed with a higher principle that “socializes” it; a competition that operates on the basis of an honest exchange in a spirit of solidarity; a competition which, while safeguarding individual initiative, will return the wealth currently diverted by capitalist appropriation to the collective.[159]

It is clear that there is something utopian in this conception. Competition and the so-called market economy inevitably produce inequality and exploitation, even if the departure point is a situation of perfect equality. They can only be joined to workers’ self-management transitionally, as a necessary lesser evil while waiting for the development within the self-managers of a mentality of “sincerity of exchange,” as Proudhon called it[160] and above all, when society has passed from the stage of penury to that of abundance and competition loses its entire raison d’ĂȘtre.

But in this transitional period it seems desirable that competition should be limited, as is the case today in Yugoslavia, to the sphere of the means of consumption, where it at least has the advantage of defending the interests of the consumer.[161]

Nevertheless, in Yugoslavia competition too often leads to excesses and irrationalities which the authoritarian adversaries of the market economy take pleasure in denouncing. Useful both as a stimulant to the spirit of enterprise and as a means of struggle against the high cost of living, it too often sustains among the

Yugoslavian self-managers a selfish and quasi-capitalist mentality from which concern for the general interest is absent.

It should be noted that workers’ self-management in Yugoslavia is criticized by the Cubans and the Chinese, precisely because of its inability to reconcile competition and socialism.

Well before the authoritarian “communists” of today denounced the coupling of self-management and competition, the libertarian communists of the 1880s attacked the Proudhonian collectivist economy based on the principle of struggle, where all that would be done would be reestablishing among the competitors equality at the starting point in order to then cast them into a battle necessarily resulting in victors and vanquished, where the exchange of products would end by being carried out in accordance with supply and demand, “which would mean descending into competition, into the bourgeois world.” This language very much resembles that of certain detractors of the Yugoslav experience in the communist world. They think it necessary to direct at self-management the hostility inspired in them by the competitive market economy, as if the two notions were inseparable from each other. This was—and I speak of him in the past tense—the case of Che Guevara, for example, who mistrusted self-management because he thought it synonymous with competition.[162]

Proudhon, to return to him, sees quite clearly that management by workers’ associations can only be unitary. He insists on “the need for centralization and unity.” I do not find in him “that provincialism closed to the wide world” that some think they saw. He asks the question: “Aren’t the workers’ companies for the exploitation of large-scale industries an expression of unity? What we put in place of government is industrial organization. What we put in place of political centralization is economic centralization.”

For Proudhon, self-management is society finally “alive, organized;” “the highest degree of freedom and order which humanity can achieve.” And in a burst of enthusiasm he exclaims, “Here we are free, emancipated from our embryonic shell. All relations have been inverted. Yesterday we walked upside down. We are changing our existence. This, in the nineteenth century, is the revolution.”[163]

Nevertheless, despite his concern for unity, Proudhon dreads authoritarian planning, which is why he instinctively prefers to it

competition of solidaristic inspiration. But, in a more consistent fashion, anarchism has since made itself the advocate for democratic and libertarian planning, elaborated from the bottom up by the confederation of self-managed enterprises.

It is in this way that Bakunin glimpsed the possibilities of a planning on a worldwide scale which open up to self-management: “The workers’ cooperative associations are a new fact in history. We are witnessing their birth and we can only sense but not determine at this time the immense development that without any doubt will ensue and the new political and social conditions that will arise in the future. It is possible and even quite probable that one day, going beyond the limits of communes, provinces, and even current states, they will provide all of human society with a new constitution, divided not into nations, but into industrial groups.” They will thus form “an immense economic federation” with, at its summit, a supreme assembly. In light of “data as broad as it is precise and detailed, of worldwide statistics, they will combine supply and demand in order to guide, determine, and distribute among the different countries the production of international industry in such a way that there will no longer be, or almost no longer be, commercial and industrial crises, forced stagnation, and any wasted effort or capital.”[164]

The Proudhonian conception of management by workers’ associations bore within it an ambiguity. It was not always specified if self-managed groups would remain in competition with capitalist enterprises, if, as is today said in Algeria, the socialist sector would co-exist with the private sector or if, on the contrary, production as a whole would be socialized and placed under self-management.

Bakunin, unlike his teacher Proudhon, whose ideas are hesitant on this point, is a consistent collectivist. He clearly sees the dangers of the coexistence of these two sectors. The workers, even associated, cannot assemble the capital capable of fighting against big bourgeois capital. And what is more, the danger exists that within the workers’ association there will arise, from the contagion of the capitalist environment, “a new class of exploiters of the labor of the proletariat.”

Self-management contains within it all the seeds of the economic emancipation of the working masses, but it can only develop

all these seeds when “capital, industrial establishments, primary materials, and tools ... will become the collective property of productive workers’ associations, both industrial and agricultural, freely organized and federated among themselves.” “The social transformation can only occur in a radical and definitive fashion by methods acting upon all of society,” that is, by a social revolution transforming private property into collective property. In such a social organization the workers will collectively be their own capitalists, their own bosses. The only things left to private property will be “those things that are truly for personal use.”[165]

As long as the social revolution has not been accomplished Bakunin, while admitting that productive cooperatives have the advantage of accustoming workers to managing their own affairs, that they create the first seeds of collective workers’ action, thought that these islands within capitalist society could only have limited effectiveness, and he incited workers “to occupy themselves less with cooperation than with strikes.”[166] As Gurvitch notes, this is the opposite position from Proudhon’s, who nourished illusions about the rapid absorption of the capitalist economy by workers’ self-management, underestimated the importance of unions and made too little of the right to strike.[167]

By Way of a Conclusion

Proudhon’s ideas on self-management do not form a body of homogeneous doctrine, perfectly adjusted, free of any hesitation or ambiguity. Far from it. Contradictions abound in it.

There is a Mutualist Proudhon who defends, exalts, and attempts to save the independent small producer from the implacable wheel of progress and there is a resolutely collectivist Proudhon who does not hesitate to march with his time, with technical progress, with technology, with large-scale industry.

There is an optimistic Proudhon who in 1848 covers in flowers the spontaneously born workers’ associations, and there is a pessimistic Proudhon who, a few years later, in 1857, will draw up a severe balance sheet of the failure of these associations.

There is a dreamer Proudhon who imagines Mutualism susceptible of partial application within the capitalist regime and who persuades himself that the socialist sector, from its own dynamism,

will spread, and there is a Proudhon who is much more realistic, and as a result reticent on this point.

There is, as concerns the legal status of property under self-management, a disintegrationist Proudhon who, at first, envisages entrusting it to the workers’ associations themselves in accordance with the principle “the factories to the workers,” and there is an integrationist Proudhon who will later prefer placing all producers in one vast agricultural and industrial federation.

There is a simplistic Proudhon who proposes an extremely arguable definition of labor value, and there is a subtler Proudhon who then admits that the duration of labor cannot be the sole basis for this calculation and who strives to repair what he calls his “omissions.”

There is the Proudhon who puts private property on trial, and there is a Proudhon who praises it, just as there is a Proudhon who celebrates the virtues of competition and there is a Proudhon who insists on its evils. It’s only quite rarely that he succeeds in constructing a true synthesis of contradictory notions, and this is why he hides his failures while flattering himself only for having “balanced” the antinomies.

There is a decentralizing and federalist Proudhon, who mistrusts all planning for fear of reviving authority, and there is a Proudhon who does not hesitate to prescribe economic centralization and stresses the unitary character of production.

There is a Proudhon who, by affirming the capacities of the working class and its duty to radically separate itself from bourgeois institutions, opens the way to modern working-class syndicalism, and there is a Proudhon who underestimates struggles for specific demands, haunted as he is by the formation of workers’ production cooperatives.

Here we touch on what is perhaps the most serious omission in the Proudhonian conception of self-management. It fails to be articulated and coordinated by an anarcho-syndicalism or a revolutionary syndicalism of the type that made possible the admirable experience of the Spanish collectivizations of 1936. When Proudhon alludes to “a vast agricultural and industrial federation,” he fails to dig deeper in the syndicalist manner into that notion which, under his pen, remains unarticulated and vague.

There is a Proudhon who, in the first part of his militant life, was strictly concerned with economic organization, who mistrusted everything having to do with politics, and there is a second Proudhon who will cease neglecting the problem of territorial administration, who will base it on the autonomous commune,[168] though failing to connect in a sufficiently precise and coherent manner communal power on one side and workers’ production associations on the other.

Finally, there is a Proudhon who categorically refuses any form of state—to the point that he issued a sectarian rejection of the sponsoring of workers’ associations by a socialist-leaning state—and there is also a Proudhon who no longer considers himself an anarchist but rather a federalist, and who participates in the state.

These, briefly recalled, are some of the omissions and failings concerning workers’ self-management in Proudhonian thought.

But alongside these weaknesses, how many lucid points of view, how many prophetic insights! The reader of Proudhon, if he is up to date on the concrete problems posed by the practice of self-management in Yugoslavia [in the 1950s and the early ‘60s], and in Algeria [from independence until Boumedienne’s coup d’état, 1962–1965], constantly finds himself on familiar ground. Almost all the difficulties that form the drama of contemporary self-management can be found announced and described in Proudhon’s writings. In it they are the object of heart-rending warnings, whether it’s on the question of the incompatibility of the tentacular state and free self-management, or of the lack of men prepared for self-management, or of the lack of technical cadres, or of the unavoidability—at least during a transitional period—of a market economy containing a certain degree of competition, and, finally, on the difficulty of establishing total communism prematurely, which will only be practicable when abundance reigns and the consumer will only have to draw from the pile. On all these points Proudhon illuminates the future with a powerful spotlight.

But even when he hesitates, when he contradicts himself, when he changes his mind, he provides his reader with a precious lesson in relativism.

It is thrilling to witness the flowering of a creative mind ever in movement, forever seeking, never fixed, never dogmatic,

tumultuous to be sure, sometimes allowing himself to be carried away by a quip, by improvisation, by failure to reflect, but capable of correcting himself, revising himself, of accepting lessons from the facts, of evolving in the light of experience.

And in any case Proudhon had his excuses. First, in laying the foundations for workers’ self-management, he entered a domain so virgin and new that no one could serve as his guide. Second, the contradictions were less in his ideas than in the object they reflected. Workers’ self-management, by its very nature, is contradictory. It is condemned to waver between two poles: on one side the autonomy of production groups, necessary so that each member feels truly free and “disalienated.” On the other hand, the need for coordination in order to have the general interest prevail over selfish ones.

This coordination, I think, can be ensured under optimal conditions by revolutionary working-class syndicalism, which is best qualified to play such a role, since it is the direct and authentic emanation of the workers. But where it is lacking, where it is degenerated and bureaucratized, where it is insufficiently structured, where it is underestimated, tamed, regarded as a poor relation, like a fifth wheel, the role of coordinator inevitably falls to the state, a state which, by the force of circumstances, wants above all to perpetuate itself, to constantly extend its remit, to infringe on any forms of autonomy, to nibble away at freedom.

In the final analysis the most profound contradiction that rends workers’ self-management springs from the historical backwardness of the education of the proletariat. The capitalist regime, as well as the unionism of immediate demands that is its corollary, did not prepare the workers, or prepared them poorly, for their self-management functions.

For an entire period they are thus obliged to seek outside their ranks the experts, technical cadres, accountants, etc. Where the cadres barely exist, as in Algeria, the functioning of self-management is seriously hindered: someone recently observed that Algerian self-management requires two hundred thousand accountants and the country’s government envisages the accelerated education of twenty thousand. But where these experts exist, at least partially, their intrusion from without subordinates self-management.

“Guardianship organizations,” when they provide technical assistance to self-managed enterprises, tend to substitute themselves for the self-managers and to become managers in their stead.

These serious drawbacks can only be eliminated when the fusion “of science and the working class” dreamed of by Ferdinand Lassalle and, after him, by Rosa Luxemburg will allow the abolition of guardianship. As the masses gradually educate themselves the social base upon which the guardians rest will fade away. They will only be “executive organs,” controllable and revocable by the “conscious actions” of the workers.[169]

Socialism is fated to remain a vain word, a demagogic and hollow option, as long as the workers are not able to manage production for themselves, as long as they are enslaved, or allow themselves to be enslaved, by a parasitic bureaucracy imitating the bosses whose place they cannot wait to take.

In countries like Yugoslavia and Algeria, where self-management still suffers from many vices in its functioning, it at least has the advantage of allowing the masses to do their apprenticeship both in democracy and management, of stimulating their enthusiasm at work (on the condition, of course, of ensuring them-which is not always the case-equitable remuneration). It inculcates in them the sense of their responsibilities, instead of maintaining, as is the case under the yoke of the omnipotent state, millennial habits of passivity, submission, and the inferiority complex left to them by a slavish past.

At the end of such an apprenticeship self-management is, in a way, condemned to succeed. For if this is not the case socialism will have failed in its historical mission. As Proudhon observed: “Upon the response that will be given ... depends the entire future of the workers. If that response is in the affirmative a new world opens before humanity. If it is in the negative, the proletariat can give up all hope ... : In this world there is no hope for them.”[170]

<right>

[1965, in **Pour un Marxisme libertaire**]

</right>

[113] Louis Blanc (1811–1882) was a leading socialist reformer who popularised the demand, “From each according to their abilities, to each

according to their needs.” A member of the republican provisional government installed after the revolution of February 1848, he would later be a member of parliament under the Third Republic, sitting with the extreme left. In 1848, he famously pushed for the creation of cooperative workshops, to be financed at least initially by the state, in order to provide employment and promote cooperativism within a framework of economic regulation. [DB]

[114] **Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle** (1851; 1926 edition), pp. 363–4. [These quotes are from the first article in a polemic between Proudhon and Blanc entitled ‘Resistance to the Revolution’, extracts in **Property Is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology** (Oakland: AK Press, 2011). —DB]

[115] **Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle** (1851; 1926 edition), pp. 277–8, 329. [‘General Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth Century’, **Property Is Theft!,** pp. 583–4, 595 —DB]

[116] **Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle** (1851; 1926 edition), pp. 280.

[Ibid., **Property Is Theft!,** p. 585 —DB]

[117] ‘Election Manifesto’, **Le Peuple,** 8 November 1848. [‘Election Manifesto of

<em>Le Peuple’, Property Is Theft!,</em> pp. 376–8.]

[118] Ibid., p. 375.

[119] Georges Gurvitch, **Proudhon** (PUF, 1965).

[120] **Theorie de la propriete** (A.Lacroix, Verboeckhoven & Cie, 1866), p. 183.

[121] **Archives Bakounine** (Champ Libre, 1973–83), ed. Arthur Lehning, vol. I, p. 241.

[122] James Guillaume, **Le Collectivisme de /‘Internationale** (Neuchatel, 1904), p. 12.

[123] Benjamin Lucraft, 1809–1897, was a craftsman from London, a leading Chartist and a member of the committee of the International Working Men’s Association. As a delegate to the Basel congress (1869), he argued not only for land nationalisation, but for the large-scale cultivation of the land by the state on behalf of the people. [DB]

[124] Pierre Haubtmann, **P J. Proudhon, genese d’un antitheiste** (unpublished doc toral thesis), pp. 994–5. [Haubtmann also published several books on Proudhon’s life and work. —DB]

[125] **Carnets,** vol. III, p. 114.

[126] Ibid. [See K. Steven Vincent, **Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and the Rise of French Republican Socialism** (New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 156—DB]

[127] **Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle** (1851; 1926 edition), p. 175 ; ‘General Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth Century’, **Property Is Theft!,** p. 558. [DB]

[128] **De la justice dans la Revolution et dans l’Eglise** (Marcel Riviere, 1858), vol. III, pp. 459–93, quoted in Georges Gurvitch, **Proudhon et Mane une confrontation** (Centre de documentation universitaire, 1964), p. 93.

[129] **De la capacite politique,** pp. 171 & 190. [Quotation from “The Political Capacity of the Working Classes.” **Property Is Theft!,** p. 748; also seep. 759 —DB]

[130] **Idee generale,** pp. 277–83 & 329. [“General Idea of the Revolution”, **Property Is Theft!,** pp. 583–6 —DB]

[131] Paul Lafargue, **Le Droit a la Paresse** (first published 1880).

[132] See my study, ‘Proudhon et l’amour unisexuel’ in **Essai sur la revolution sexuel/e apres Reich et Kinsey** (Belfond, 1963).

[133] See K. Marx, **Poverty of Philosophy** and Haubtmann, P **J. Proudhon, genese d’un antitheiste,** pp. 998–9.

[134] **De la justice,** vol. III, p. 91; Gurvitch, **Proudhon et Marx.**

[135] **De la justice,** vol. III, p. 115.

[136] **Idee generate,** p. 283. **[General Idea of the Revolution** (London: Pluto Press,

1989), p. 224 — DB]

[137] Proudhon, **Les Confessions d’un rĂ©volutionnaire pour servir a l’histoire de la revo — lution de Fevrier (1848)** (Marcel Riviere, 1929 edition), pp. 257–60.

[138] ‘Manifeste de la democratie anarchiste’ [Manifesto of anarchist democ racy] in **Le Peup/e,** 22, 26 & 31 March 1848.

[139] **Carnets,** vol. III, pp. 211 & 312.

[140] **De la capacite politique** (Marcel Riviere, 1924 edition), pp. 329 & 403.

[141] Jacques Freymond (ed.), **La Premiere Internationale** (Droz, 1962), vol. I, pp.

151 & 365–465.

[142] ‘Conclusion’ in **Manuel du speculateur a la Bourse** (Garnier, 1857).

[143] Extracts from the conclusion of the **Stock Exchange Speculator’s Manual**

(1857) can be found in **Property Is Theft!,** pp. 610–7. [DB]

[144] Gurvitch, **Proudhon et Marx,** pp. 46 & 108.

[145] **Theorie de la propriete.**

[146] Ibid.

[147] Malatesta, **Programme et organisation de L’Association internationale des travailleurs** (Florence, 1884); Kropotkine, **La Conquete du pain** (Stock, 1890); Kropotkine, **Ulnarchie, sa philosophie, son ideal** (Stock, 1896), pp. 27–8 & 31; Kropotkine, **La Science moderne et l!Zlnarchie** (Stock, 1913), pp. 82–3 & 103. [“Program and Organisation of the International Working Men’s Association”, **The Method of Freedom: An Errico Malatesta Reader** (Oakland: AK Press, 2014); Kropotkin, **The Conquest of Bread** (Oakland: AK Press, 2006),

“Anarchy: Its Philosophy and Ideal” and “modern Science and Anarchism” are contained in edited form in the Kropotkin anthology, **Anarchism: A Collection of Revolutionary Writings** (New York: Dover Press, 2002)].

[148] **Theorie de la propriete,** p. 22.

[149] Bakounine, ** ƒuvres** (Stock, 1895–1913), vol. VI, p. 401.

[150] Marx, **Lettre sur le programme de Gotha;** Lenine, **L’Etat et la Revolution** (1917).

[151] Malatesta, **Programme et organisation de l'Association internationale des travailleurs. [Method of Freedom,** pp. 47–8 —DB]

[152] Femand Pelloutier, ‘L’anarchisme et les syndicats ouvriers’, in **Les Temps nouveaux,** 2 November 1895. [‘Anarchism and the Workers’ Union’ in **No Gods No Masters** (Oakland: AK Press, 2005), pp. 409–15 —DB]

[153] **Philosophie de la misere,** in ** ƒuvres completes** (A. Lacroix, Verboeckhoven &

Cie, 1867), vol. I, p. 225.

[154] **Idee generate de la Revolution au Xixeme siecle,** p. 281. **[Property Is Theft!,** p.

585—DB]

[155] **Philosophie de la misere,** in ** ƒuvres completes** (A. Lacroix, Verboeckhoven &

Cie, 1867), vol. I, p. 208.

[156] Ibid., p. 210.

[157] Ibid.

[158] Ibid., pp. 209, 211 & 234.

[159] **Philosophie de la misere,** vol. I, pp. 186 & 215.

[160] Ibid., pp. 209 & 217.

[161] Ibid., vol. II, p. 414.

[162] Albert Meister, **Socialisme et Autogestion, l‘experience yougoslave** (Seuil, 1964),

p.334.

[163] Cf. Ernest Germain, ‘La loi de la valeur, l’autogestion et les investissements dans l’economie des Etats ouvriers’, in **Quatrieme Internationale,** February-March 1964.

[164] **Idee generale,** pp. 202–3, 301–2, 342, 420, 428.

[165] ‘Programme et statuts de la Fratemite rĂ©volutionnaire’ (1865) in Max

Nettlau, **Michel Bakounine** (London: 1896), vol. I, p. 224.

[166] Bakounine, ** ƒuvres,** vol. V. pp. 216–8; **Archives Bakounine,** vol. i, 2nd Part,

article from **Al Rubicone,** 3 January 1872.

[167] In **Archives,** vol. I, 2nd Part, p. 73.

[168] Gurvitch, **Proudhon et Marx,** p. 113. 57. **De la justice,** vol. I, p. 320; **Contradictions politiques** (1862), p. 237 & 245–6.

[169] Rosa Luxemburg, ‘Masse et chefs’ [‘Geknickte Hoffnungen’, 1903], in

<em>Marxisme contre dictature</em> (Spartacus, 1974), pp. 36–7.

[170] Proudhon, **Manuel du speculateur,** ‘Conclusion’.

Three Problems of the Revolution

Voline, libertarian historian of the Russian Revolution after having been an actor and witness, wrote, “A fundamental problem was left to us by the preceding revolutions: above all I mean those of 1789 and 1917. Arising in large part against oppression, animated by a powerful surge of freedom, and proclaiming freedom as their essential goal, why did these revolutions descend into new dictatorships carried out by other dominating and privileged strata, into a new slavery of the popular masses? What would the conditions be that would allow a revolution to avoid this sad end? Is this end due to passing factors, to errors or mistakes that could be avoided in the future? And in the latter case, what would be the means to eliminate the danger that threatens the imminent revolutions?”[171]

With Voline, I think that the two great historical experiences of the French and Russian Revolutions are indissolubly connected. Despite the differences in periods, environment, and “class content,” the problems they raise, the pitfalls they ran up against, were fundamentally the same. At the very most, in the first revolution they manifested themselves in a more embryonic form than in the later one. And so the men of today can only hope to find the path to their future definitive emancipation if they are able to distinguish between what was progress and what was failure in these two experiences in order to draw the lessons for the future.

In my opinion the basic cause for the relative failure of the two greatest revolutions in history resides not, to borrow again from Voline, in “historic inevitability,” or simply in the subjective “errors” of revolutionary actors. The revolution bears within itself a serious contradiction (a contradiction which fortunately—and we will return to the subject—is not irremediable and is attenuated with time): it can only arise, it can only vanquish if it issues from

the depths of the popular masses, from their irresistible spontaneous uprising; but although the class instinct drives the popular masses to break their chains, they are yet lacking in education and consciousness. And since, in their formidable but tumultuous and blind drive towards liberty, they run up against privileged, conscious, educated, organized, and tested social classes, they can only vanquish the resistance they meet if they succeed in obtaining in the heat of the struggle, the consciousness, the science, the organization, and the experience they lack. But the very fact of forging the weapons I have just listed summarily, and which alone can ensure their superiority over the enemy, bears an immense peril within it: that of killing the spontaneity that is the very spirit of the revolution; that of compromising freedom through organization; that of allowing the movement to be confiscated by an elite minority of more educated, more conscious, more experienced militants who, to begin with, offer themselves as guides in order, in the end, to impose themselves as chiefs and to subject the masses to new forms of the oppression of man by man.

For as long as socialism has been capable of reflecting on this problem, for as long as it has been aware of this contradiction, more or less since the beginning of the nineteenth century, socialism has not ceased to struggle with it, to waver between the two opposing poles of freedom and order. Every one of its thinkers and actors has laboriously and stumblingly striven, at the price of many hesitations and contradictions, to resolve the fundamental dilemma of the revolution. Proudhon, in his famous **Memoire sur la PropriĂ©tĂ©** (1840), thought he had found the synthesis when he optimistically wrote: “the highest perfection of society is found in the unity of order and anarchy.” But a quarter of a century later he melancholically noted: “These two ideas, freedom ... and order, stand together .... They cannot be separated, nor can one be absorbed in the other; we must resign ourselves to living with both, with keeping them in balance .... No political force has yet provided the true solution to the harmony of freedom and order.”[172]

Today an immense empire, constructed under the sign of “socialism” (and of “communism”), seeks painfully, without design, and sometimes convulsively to escape the iron shackles of an “order” founded on coercion in order to find the road to freedom which its

millions of subjects, daily more experienced and conscious, aspire to. The problem has been posed in an ever-more-burning fashion, and the final word has not been spoken.

If we look at it more closely, the problem has three relatively distinct aspects, though they are intimately connected.

1. In the period of revolutionary struggle, what parts should spontaneity and consciousness, the masses and the leaders, play?

2. Once the old oppressive regime has been overthrown, what form of political and administrative organization must be substituted for the one just defeated?

3. Finally, who should administer the economy and how should it be administered after the abolition of private property (a problem that is posed in all its magnitude for the proletarian revolution but which was posed only embryonically for the French Revolution)?

On each of these three questions, the socialists of the nineteenth century hesitated, shilly-shallied, contradicted themselves, and confronted each other. Which socialists?

Broadly speaking, three main currents can be distinguished:

a. Those I will call authoritarian, the statists and centralists,

some the heirs of the Jacobin and Blanquist tradition of the French Revolution, others of the German (or more precisely, Prussian) tradition of the military discipline of the State with a capital “S”[173]

b. Those I will call anti-authoritarian, the libertarians, some

of them heirs of the direct democracy of 1793, of the communalist and federalist idea, and others of Saint-Simonian apoliticism aspiring to substitute “the administration of things” for political government.

c. Finally, the so-called scientific socialists (Marx and Engels), laboriously striving, not always coherently or successfully, and often for purely tactical reasons (for they had to make concessions to the two wings of the working-class movement) to reconcile the two aforementioned currents, to find

a compromise between the authoritarian and libertarian ideas.

Let us try to briefly summarize the attempts made by these three currents of socialist thought to resolve the three fundamental problems of the revolution.

Spontaneity and Consciousness

The authoritarians do not have faith in the capacity of the masses to achieve consciousness on their own and, even when they claim the contrary, they have a panic fear of the masses. If they are to be believed, the masses are still degraded by centuries of oppression. They need to be guided and led. A small elite of leaders must be substituted for them to teach them revolutionary strategy and lead them to victory.

The libertarians, on the contrary, maintain that the revolution must be the work of the masses themselves, of their spontaneity, of their free initiative, of their creative faculties, as unsuspected as they are formidable. They put people on guard against the chiefs who, in the name of greater consciousness, aspire to impose themselves on the masses in order to then despoil them of the fruits of their victory.

As for Marx and Engels, they at times placed the accent on spontaneity and at others on consciousness. But their synthesis remains a shaky, uncertain, and contradictory one. It must also be said that the libertarians do not always escape the same reproach. We find in Proudhon, juxtaposed to the optimistic exaltation of “the political capacity of the working classes,” pessimistic passages

in which he casts doubt on said capacity and joins the authoritarians in their suggestion that the masses must be led from above.[174] In the same way Mikhail Bakunin does not always succeed in ridding himself of the “48er” conspiratorialism of his youth and, immediately after relying on the irresistible primal instincts of the masses, he turns around and calls for the invisible “infiltration” of the latter by conscious leaders organized in secret societies. From which this strange back and forth: those he accuses, at times not without basis, of authoritarianism, catch him in the act of authoritarian Machiavellianism.

The two antagonistic tendencies of the First International mutually condemned each other, each with a certain amount of reason, for backstage maneuvers to ensure control of the movement.[175] We had to wait for Rosa Luxemburg for a more or less viable synthesis to be proposed between spontaneity and consciousness. But Trotsky compromised this laboriously obtained equilibrium in order to take the contradiction to its extreme. At certain moments he is “Luxemburgist.” As can be seen in his **1905** (1907) and his **History of the Russian Revolution** (1930), he has a feeling and an instinct for revolution from below; he places the accent on the autonomous actions of the masses, but in the end, after having brilliantly combatted them, he rallies to Lenin’s Blanquist conception of organization[176] and, once in power, he would act in a more authoritarian fashion than the leader of the school. Finally, in the harsh combat of his exile, he would shelter behind a now sanctified Lenin in order to put Stalin on trial, and this identification would prevent him until his final day from setting free the element of Luxemburgism within him.

The Question of Power

The authoritarians maintain that the popular masses, led by their chiefs, must substitute for the bourgeois state their own state adorned with the epithet “proletarian,” and that, in order to ensure the permanence of the latter, they must push to the extreme the means of coercion used by the former (centralization, discipline, hierarchy, police). This schema draws from libertarians—and this for more than a century—cries of fright and horror. What is the use, they ask, of a revolution that would be satisfied with replacing one repressive apparatus for another? Uncompromising enemies of the state, of every form of state, they expect from the proletarian revolution the complete and definitive abolition of state coercion. They want to substitute the free federation of associated communes and bottom-up direct democracy for the old oppressive state.

Marx and Engels sought their way between the extremes of these two tendencies. They bore the Jacobin imprint, but on one hand contact with Proudhon around 1844 and the influence of Moses Hess,[177] and on the other the critique of Hegelianism and the discovery of “alienation” rendered them somewhat libertarian. They

rejected the authoritarian statism of the Frenchman Louis Blanc as

well as that of the German Lassalle.[178] They declared themselves supporters

of the abrogation of the state. But only in the long run. The

state, “the governmental hodgepodge,” must continue in the aftermath

of the revolution, but only for a time. As soon as the material

conditions are realized that will allow for it to be done away with it

will “wither away.” And while waiting for that day, we must strive

to “immediately attenuate as much as possible its most harmful

eff ects.”[179] This immediate perspective justly worries the libertarians.

The survival, even “provisional,” of the state says nothing good to

them, and they prophetically announce that once reestablished

the Leviathan will obstinately refuse to resign.[180] The libertarians’

dogged criticism placed Marx and Engels in an embarrassing position,

and there were times when they made so many concessions

to their ideological adversaries that at a certain moment the debate

over the state between socialists seemed to have no point or to

be nothing but a simple quibble over words. Alas, this beautiful

harmony lasted but a morning.

But the Bolshevism of the twentieth century reveals that this

was not a simply verbal dispute. Marx and Engels’ transitory state

becomes, already in its embryonic form with Lenin and even more

with Lenin’s successors, a tentacular monster, which in no uncertain

terms proclaims its refusal to wither away.

The Management of the Economy

Finally, what form of property should replace private capitalism?

The authoritarians have no hesitation in responding. Since

their main defect is a lack of imagination, and since they fear the

unknown, they fall back on forms of administration and management

plagiarized from the past. The state will swoop up in

its immense net all of production, all of exchange, all of finance.

“State capitalism” will survive the social revolution. The bureaucracy,

already gigantic under Napoleon, under the King of Prussia, and

under the Tsar, will no longer be satisfied under a socialist regime

with levying taxes and raising armies and increasing the police

force: it will extend its tentacles over the factories, the mines, the

banks, and the means of transport. The libertarians issue a cry of

fright. This exorbitant expansion of the powers of the state looks

to them to be the grave of liberty. Max Stirner was one of the first

to rise up against the statism of the communist society.[181] Proudhon

shouted no less loudly, and Bakunin followed him: “I detest communism,” he declared in a speech, “because it necessarily arrives at

the centralization of property in the hands of the state, while I ...

want the organization of society and collective and social property

from the bottom up by way of free association, and not from the

top down by means of some form of authority.”[182]

But the anti-authoritarians are not unanimous in formulating

their counter-proposal. Stirner suggests a “free association”

of “egoists,” too philosophical in inspiration and also too unstable.

Proudhon, more concretely, suggests a combination—which

in some ways is retrograde, petit-bourgeois, corresponding to the

already outmoded state of small-scale industry—of small-scale

commerce, of artisanal production: private property must be safe-guarded.

Small producers, remaining independent, must offer each

other mutual aid. At the very most he accepts collective property

in a certain number of sectors, which he agrees have already been

conquered by large-scale industry: transport, mines, etc. But both

Stirner and Proudhon, each in his own fashion, leave themselves

open to the blistering critique administered them—a little unjustly,

it must be said—by Marxism.

Bakunin for his part separates himself deliberately from

Proudhon. For a brief time, he constituted a united front with Marx

within the First International against his former teacher. He rejects

post-Proudhonian individualism. He learns the lessons of industrialization.

He calls for collective property. He presents himself as

neither a communist nor a Mutualist but a collectivist. Production

should be managed, both on a local basis by “the solidarization

of communes” and on an occupational basis by groups or associations

of workers. Under the influence of the Bakuninists the

Basel Congress of the First International in 1869 decided that in

the future society “the government will be replaced by councils of

workers’ organisations.”[183] Marx and Engels waver and hedge. In the

<em>Communist Manifesto</em> of 1848, inspired by Louis Blanc, they’d adopted

the easy omni-statist solution. But later, under the influence of the

Paris Commune of 1871 and the pressure of the anarchists, they

would temper this statism and speak of “the self-government of the

producers.”[184] But these hints at anarchism would not last long and

Marx and Engels would almost immediately return, in their fight to

the death with Bakunin and his disciples, to a more authoritarian

and statist phraseology.

So it is not totally without reason (though not always with

total good faith) that Bakunin accused the Marxists of concentrating

all of industrial and agricultural production in the hands of

the state. In Lenin the statist and authoritarian tendencies, super-imposed

on an anarchism they contradict and annihilate, already

exist in germ, and under Stalin, “quantity” being transformed into

“quality,” they degenerate into an oppressive state capitalism that

Bakunin, in his occasionally unfair criticism of Marx, seems to

have anticipated.

This brief historical reminder is only of interest insofar as it

can assist us in orienting ourselves in the present. The lessons we

will draw from them allow us to understand, in a striking and dramatic

way, that despite many conceptions that seem today to be

outmoded, childish, or proved wrong by experience (for example

their “apoliticism”, on the essential questions the libertarians were

in the right against the authoritarians. The latter let loose rivers of

insults on the former, calling their program “a jumble of ideas from

beyond the grave,” reactionary utopias, outdated and decadent.[185] But

it can be seen today, as Voline stresses, that it is the authoritarian

idea that, far from belonging to the future, is nothing but a survival

from the old, bourgeois world, worn out and moribund.[186] If there

is a utopia, it is that of so-called state communism, whose bankruptcy

is so patent that its own beneficiaries (concerned above all

with safeguarding their interests as a privileged caste) seek today,

laboriously and stumblingly, the means to amend it and evade it.

The future belongs neither to classical capitalism nor, as the

late Merleau-Ponty tried to persuade us, to a capitalism revised and

corrected by a “neoliberalism” or by social democratic reformism.[187]

Their dual bankruptcy is no less resounding than that of state communism.

The future still belongs, more than ever belongs, to communism,

but a libertarian communism. As Kropotkin prophetically

announced in 1896, our era “will bear the effects of the reawakening

of libertarian ideas .... The next revolution will no longer be the

Jacobin revolution.”[188]

The three fundamental problems of the Revolution that we

outlined above can and must finally find their solution. We are

no longer in the era of the stammering, stumbling socialist thinkers

of the nineteenth century. The problems are no longer posed

abstractly, but rather concretely. Today we have at our disposal

an abundant harvest of practical experiences. The technique of

Revolution has been immensely enriched. The libertarian idea is

no longer inscribed in the clouds, but emerges from the facts themselves,

from the most profound and authentic aspirations, even

when they are repressed, of the popular masses.

The problem of spontaneity and consciousness is easier to

resolve today than a century ago. If the masses, as a result of the

oppression they suffer, are still a bit behindhand in understanding

the bankruptcy of the capitalist system, if they are still lacking in

education and political lucidity, they have made up a large part of

the historic delay. Everywhere, in the advanced capitalist countries,

as well as in the developing countries and those subject to so-called

communism, they have made a great leap forward. They are much

harder to dupe. They know the full extent of their rights. Their

knowledge of the world and their own destiny has been considerably

enriched. If the deficiencies of the French proletariat prior to

1840, because of its inexperience and small numbers, gave birth to

Blanquism, if that of the Russian proletariat before 1917 gave birth

to Leninism, and that of the new, exhausted proletariat broken up

following the civil war of 1918–1920 and those newly uprooted from

the countryside gave birth to Stalinism, today the laboring masses

have less need to abdicate their power into the hands of authoritarian

and supposedly infallible tutors.

What is more, thanks notably to Rosa Luxemburg, the idea

has penetrated socialist thought that even if the masses are not yet

completely mature, even if the fusion of science and the working

class dreamed of by Lassalle has not yet taken place, the only way

to catch up and to remedy this deficiency is to assist the masses in

doing their apprenticeship in direct democracy from the bottom

up.[189] It is in developing, encouraging, and stimulating their free

initiatives; it is in inculcating in them the sense of their responsibilities

instead of maintaining in them, as state “communism” does

(whether in power or in opposition), the age-old habits of passivity,

submission, and feeling of inferiority passed on to them by a past

of oppression. Even if this apprenticeship is at times difficult, even

if the rhythm is at times slow, even if it cripples society with supplementary

costs, even if it can only be effected at the cost of some

“disorder,” these difficulties, these delays, these supplementary costs,

these growing pains, are infinitely less harmful than the false order,

the false brilliance, the false “efficiency” of state “communism,”

which obliterate man, kill popular initiative, and finally dishonor

the very idea of communism.[190]

As concerns the problem of the state, the lessons of the

Russian Revolution are clearly written on the wall. Liquidating

the power of the masses, as was done in the immediate aftermath

of the triumph of the Revolution; reconstructing over the ruins of

the former state machine a new oppressive apparatus even more

perfected than the previous one, one fraudulently baptized “party

of the proletariat,” often by absorbing into the new regime the

“experts” of the defunct regime (still imbued with their former

authority); allowing the construction of a new privileged class

which considers its own survival as an end in itself and which perpetuates

the state that ensures that survival, is not the model to

be followed. What is more, if we take literally the Marxist theory

of the “withering away” of the state, the material conditions that

had provoked and, according to the Marxists, legitimized the

reconstruction of a state apparatus, should allow us today to do

without that cumbersome gendarme so eager to remain in place

that is the state.

Industrialization, though developing unevenly in each country,

is taking giant steps throughout the world. The discovery of new

sources of energy with unlimited possibilities is enormously accelerating

this evolution. The totalitarian state engendered by poverty

and which justifies itself by this poverty, daily becomes ever more

superfluous. As for the management of the economy, all the experiments

carried out, both in the quintessential capitalist countries

like the United States as well as those in the countries subjected to

state “communism,” demonstrate that the future, at least for large

sectors of the economy, no longer belongs to gigantic production

units. Gigantism, which dazzled the late Yankee captains of industry

as well as the communist Lenin, belongs to the past. **Too Big:** this

is the name of a book on the evils of this plague on the American

economy.[191] For his part Khrushchev, that wily boor, finally grasped,

though late and timidly, the need for industrial decentralization. It

was long believed that the sacrosanct imperatives of the planned

economy demanded state management of the economy. Today it is

realized that top-down planning, bureaucratic planning, is a frightful

source of disorder and waste and, as Merleau-Ponty said, “It does

not plan.”[192] Charles Bettelheim showed us, in a book that was too

often conformist at the time it was written, that it could only function

efficiently if it was managed from the bottom up and not from

the top down, if it emanated from the lower echelons of production

and was constantly subject to their control—while in the USSR this

control by the masses shines by its absence. Without any doubt,

the future belongs to the autonomous management of enterprises

by associations of workers. What remains to be worked out is the

mechanism, delicate to be sure, of their federation, of the harmonizing

of varied interests in a free order. From this point of view the

attempt at a synthesis between anarchism and statism promoted

by the now undeservedly forgotten Belgian socialist CĂ©sar de Paepe

deserves exhumation.[193]

On other levels the evolution of technology and the organization

of labor open the road to a socialism from the bottom up. The

most recent research in the field of the psychology of work leads

to the conclusion that production is only “efficient” if it does not

crush man, if it associates instead of alienating him, if it appeals to

his initiative, his full cooperation, and if it transmutes his drudgery

into joyful labor, a condition that is not fully realizable either

in the industrial barracks of private capitalism or those of state

capitalism. What is more, the acceleration of the means of transport

facilitates enormously the exercise of direct democracy. For

example: thanks to airplanes, in a few hours the delegates of local

branches of American labor unions—the most modern of which,

such as those of the automobile workers, are dispersed across a

whole continent—can be easily assembled.

But if we want to regenerate socialism, turned upside down by

the authoritarians, and put it back on its feet, we must act quickly.

In 1896 Kropotkin forcefully said that as long as socialism has an

authoritarian and statist face it will inspire a certain mistrust in the

workers and, because of this, it will see its efforts compromised and

its later development paralyzed.[194] Private capitalism, historically

condemned, only survives today because of the arms race on the

one hand and the bankruptcy of state “communism” on the other.

We cannot ideologically defeat big business and its so-called free

enterprise, under cover of which a handful of monopolies dominate,

we cannot see off nationalism and fascism, ever ready to rise from

the ashes, unless we are capable of producing in practice a concrete

substitute for state pseudo-communism. As for the so-called

socialist countries, they will only escape their current impasse if we

assist them, not in liquidating, but in completely rebuilding their

socialism. Khrushchev came crashing down for having hesitated

too long between the past and the future. The GomuƂkas, Titos, and

Dubčeks—despite their good will, their desire for de-Stalinization,

and their antistatist tendencies—risk grinding to a halt, wobbling

on the tightrope where they stand in an unstable equilibrium and,

in the long run, will fail if they do not acquire the audacity and

clear-sightedness that will allow them to define the essential bases

for a libertarian communism.[195]

The Revolution of our time will be made from the bottom up—or

it will not be made at all.

<right>

[1958, in **Jeunesse du Socialisme Libertaire**]

</right>

[171] **La Revolution Inconnue,** 1917–1921 (1969 edn.), p. 19. In **The Ego and Its Own**

(1845), Max Stirner had already announced as the “principle of Revolution”

this pessimistic axiom: “Always there is only a new master set in the old

one’s place, and the overturning is a-building up .... Since the master

rises again as state, the servant appears again as subject.” [English translation

by Steven T. Byington (1907) —DB].

[172] In **De la capacite politique des classes ouvrieres** (MarcelRiviere edn., 1924), p. 200.

[173] Louis-Auguste Blanqui (1805–1881), although from a bourgeois background,

was a hugely influential revolutionary socialist republican

and was involved in various attempted insurrections from an early age.

‘Blanquism’ is characterised by a lack of faith in working-class movements

and by the belief that bourgeois society could only be destroyed by a

violent coup effected by a small group of revolutionaries who would then

introduce a new and more just social order. [DB]

[174] Proudhon in **De la capacite,** pp. 88 & 119.

[175] Cf. Karl Marx, **L’alliance de la democratie socialiste et** I’ **association internationale des travailleurs. Rapport et documents publies par ordre du congres international de La Haye** (London: A. Darson; Hamburg: 0. Meissner, 1873).

[176] See his **Terrorism and Communism** (1920).

[177] An early socialist who met Marx and Engels in the 1840s, Hess (1812–1875)

envisaged the realisation of the ideals of freedom and equality through

the achievement of communism. [DB]

[178] A contradictory figure in early German socialism, Ferdinand Lassalle

(1825–1864) was a republican and democrat, and insisted on the necessary

role of the state in socialism. [DB]

[179] In Engels’ 1891 preface to the first French edition of Marx, **La Guerre civile en France** (Bibliotheque d’etudes socialistes, 1901).

[180] Thomas Hobbes’ **Leviathan** (1651) is, among other things, an apologia for

despotism.

[181] See **The Ego and Its Own.**

[182] Speech to the 1868 Bern congress of the Ligue de la paix et de la liberte,

in **Memoire de la Federationjurassienne** (Sonvillier, 1873), p. 28.

[183] Oscar Testut, **L’Internationale** (1871), p. 154.

[184] Marx in **The Civil War in France.**

[185] See the end of ch. 6 in Plekhanov, **Anarchisme et Socialisme, force et violence**

(Librairie de l’Humanite, 1923), as well as the preface by Eleanor

Marx-Aveling.

[186] Voline, op. cit., pp. 218 and 229.

[187] The philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961) was a prominent

member of the left intelligentsia in the postwar years. Influenced by Marx,

he was a member of the editorial committee of Sartre’s review **Les Temps modernes** (until the two fell out in 1952); he also played a leading role in

the **Union des Forces Democratiques** created in 1958 by various elements of

the non-communist left to oppose General Charles de Gaulle’s attempt to

become president of a reformed Republic. [DB]

[188] Kropotkin, **L’Anarchie, sa philosophie, son ideal** (Stock, 1896), p. 51.

[189] Cf. the 1904 text by Rosa Luxemburg reproduced as an appendix to the

French translation of Trotsky, **Nos taches politiques** (Belfond, 1970 [1904]).

[This is a reference to Luxemburg’s ‘Organizational Questions of the

Russian Social Democracy’, available on the Marxists Internet Archive at

[[https://www.Marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1904/questions-rscl/index.

htm]]; Guérin, with the anarchist artist Jean-Jacques Lebel, was the editor

of the series in which Trotsky’s **Our Political Tasks,** a critique of Lenin and

Leninism, was published. —DB]

[190] “Socialism” in the 1969 version published in D. GuĂ©rin, **Pour un Marxisme libertaire** (Laffont, 1969). [MA & DB]

[191] Morris Ernst, **Too Big** (New York, 1940).

[192] ‘Reforme ou maladie senile du communisme’, **L’Express,** 23 November 1956.

[193] Cesar de Paepe, ‘De l‘organisation des services publics dans la societe

future’, 1874, in **Ni dieu ni maftre, anthologie de l’anarchisme,** 1969 edition, p. 317. [Now available in a slightly abridged translation in **No Gods No Masters: An Anthology of Anarchism** (Oakland: AK Press, 2005) —DB] Cf. G.D.H. Cole,

<em>A History of Socialist Thought</em> (London: Macmillan, 1958), vol. II, pp. 204–7.

[194] Kropotkin, op. cit., pp. 31–3.

[195] The so-called GomuƂka’s thaw was a short period in 1956 when, encouraged

by Khrushchev’s famous speech to the Twentieth Congress of the

Soviet Communist Party denouncing Stalin, the Polish Communist leader

initiated a certain liberalization under the banner of a “Polish road to

socialism.” Tito’s split with Stalin in 1948 and the adoption of the principle

of self-management as the basis of a democratic socialist economy in

1950 meant that Yugoslavia was seen by many anti-Stalinist socialists in

the west as a beacon of hope (which is why Yugoslavian self-management

was discussed, albeit critically, in GuĂ©rin’s 1965 book, **Anarchism: From Theory to Practice).** Alexander Dubček was the figurehead of the “Prague

Spring” of 1968 whose aim was “socialism with a human face.” All these

attempts were crushed. [DB]

The French Revolution De-Jacobinized

Today, we are surrounded by nothing but ruins. The ideologies that

were drummed into us, the political regimes that we were made

to submit to or were held up as models are all falling to pieces. As

Edgar Quinet said, we have lost all our baggage.[196]

Fascism, the ultimate and barbarous form of man’s domination

of man, collapsed a quarter century ago in a bloodbath. And the very

people who clung to it like a life raft, who had called it to the rescue

against the working class, even at the point of foreign bayonets,

got skinned in the adventure and are forced, even though they still

secretly prefer it, to offer their merchandise in a camouflaged form.

The least that can be said is that bourgeois democracy was not

reinvigorated by the crushing defeat of fascism. In any event, it had

made the latter’s bed and showed itself incapable of standing in its

way. It no longer has a doctrine or any faith in itself. It has not succeeded

in restoring its image by capturing for its benefit the fervor

of the French popular masses against Hitlerism. The Resistance lost

its raison d’ĂȘtre on the day its enemy disappeared. Its false unity

immediately disintegrated. Its myth was deflated. The politicians

of the postwar period were the most pitiful we have ever endured.

They themselves vaporized the overly credulous confidence of those

who, for want of anything better, turned to London against Vichy.[197]

Bourgeois democracy showed itself to be totally incapable of resolving

the problems and contradictions of the postwar period, contradictions

even more insoluble than they were before the so-called

crusade undertaken to find a solution to them. It was only able to

survive at home through a shameful and hypocritical caricature of

fascist methods, and abroad through colonial wars and even wars of

aggression. It has capitulated. Its succession is open. And the anachronistic

Fifth Republic was only able to put an ineffective band-aid

on the wound, one more harmful than the previous medicines and,

what is more, ephemeral.[198]

And then Stalinism, which claimed and which many believed

to be made of sterner stuff and to be historically destined to substitute

itself for the moribund (fascist or “democratic”) forms of

bourgeois domination, collapsed in its turn in the scandal of the

ignominies revealed in Khrushchev’s secret report, in the horrors

of the Hungarian repression, and the invasion of Czechoslovakia.[199]

But a world that is collapsing is also a world being reborn. Far

from allowing ourselves to fall into doubt, inaction, confusion or

despair, the time has come for the French working-class movement

to start again from zero, to rethink the very bases of its problems,

to remake, as Quinet said, all of its baggage of ideas.

It was a concern of that order that, in the days following the

Liberation, led me to go back to the French Revolution.[200] If my intentions

were not clear enough and if as a result and through my fault,

they escaped many of my readers and opponents, a British critic

nevertheless understood: “Each generation must re-write history

for itself. If the nineteenth century in Western Europe was the

century of Liberty, the present century is that of Equality. The twin

ideals of the French Revolution, so long separated by the political

ascendancy of nineteenth-century Liberalism, are coming together

again. This **rapprochement,** dictated by the course of events and the

direction of the historical process itself, makes new demands on all

who aspire to describe and interpret that process. If the twin ideals

which Western civilization owes so largely to the French Revolution

are to be again reconciled in action, they must surely be also—and

perhaps first—reconciled in the description of their evolution by

historians.” And this anonymous critic found it “natural that when

France is passing through a phase of political and economic reconstruction

... she should seek guidance from a more many-sided

social interpretation of her history.” [201]

But in my opinion, the necessary synthesis of the ideas of

equality and liberty that this critic recommended in far too vague

and confused a fashion cannot and must not be attempted within

the framework and for the benefit of a bankrupt bourgeois democracy.

It can and should be within the framework of socialist (and

communist) thought, which remains, despite it all, the sole solid

value of our epoch. The dual failures of reformism and Stalinism

place before us the urgent duty of reconciling proletarian democracy

and socialism, freedom and Revolution.

And it was precisely the French Revolution that first provided

us with the material for this synthesis. For the first time in history

the antagonistic notions of freedom and coercion, of state power

and the power of the masses confronted each other, clearly if

not fully, in its immense crucible. From this fertile experience,

as Kropotkin saw, emerged the two great currents of modern

socialist thought on the basis of which we can remake our ideological

“baggage” only if we finally succeed in finding the correct

synthesis.[202]

The return to the French Revolution has, until today, been

relatively fruitless, because modern revolutionaries, all of whom

have nevertheless studied it closely and passionately, have only

been concerned with superficial analogies, with formal points of

resemblance with this situation, or that political group, or some

other personality of their time. It would be quite amusing to recapitulate

all these fantasies, sometimes brilliant, sometimes simply

absurd, about which historians of the Russian Revolution like Boris

Souvarine, Erich Wollenberg, and Isaac Deutscher were right to

have reservations.[203] But we would need pages and pages to do this,

and we have better things to do. If, on the other hand, we abandon

the little game of analogies and attempt to get to the heart of the

problems of the French Revolution and analyze its internal mechanism,

we could draw lessons from it which would be extremely

useful for understanding the present.

The Direct Democratization of 1793

The first thing to emphasise is that the French Revolution was the

first coherent, wide-scale, historical manifestation of a new type

of democracy. The Great Revolution was not simply, as too many

republican historians believed, the cradle of parliamentary democracy:

because at the same time that it was a bourgeois revolution

it was also the embryo of proletarian revolution, it bore within

itself the seed of a new form of revolutionary power whose features

would become more distinct over the course of the revolutions of

the late nineteenth and the twentieth centuries. The thread that

runs from the Commune of 1793 to that of 1871, and from that to the

soviets of 1905 and 1917, is clear.

I would here like to limit myself to briefly summarizing some

of the general features of the “direct democracy” of 1793.

If we step into the “sections,” the popular societies of the Year

II,[204] we have the feeling of a reinvigorating immersion in democracy.

The periodic self-purging of each “popular society,” each candidate

mounting the podium to offer him or herself to the scrutiny of

all; the concern to ensure the most perfect possible expression of

the popular will, to prevent its stifling by the golden-tongued or

by idlers; permitting the working people to lay down their tools

without any financial sacrifice and so to fully participate in public

life; ensuring permanent control of the representatives by the represented;

and the placing of the two sexes on a level of complete

equality in deliberations.[205] ... These are some of the features of a

democracy truly propelled from the bottom up.

The General Council of the Commune of 1793, at least until the

decapitation of its magistrates by the bourgeois central power, also

offers us a remarkable example of direct democracy. The members

of the Council were the delegates of their respective sections, constantly

in contact with them and under the control of those who

gave them their mandates, always up to date on the will of the base

through the admission of popular delegations to the sittings of the

Council. At the Commune there was no such thing as the “separation

of powers” between the executive and the legislative. The

members of the Council were both administrators and legislators.

These modest sans-culottes did not become professional politicians;

they remained the men of their professions or trades, still exercising

them to the extent that their functions on the Commune allowed

this, and ready to exercise them again at the end of their mandates.[206]

But of all these features the most admirable one is doubtless the

maturity of a direct democracy experimented with for the first time

in a relatively backward country, barely out of the night of feudalism

and absolutism, still plunged in illiteracy and age-old habits of

submission. No “anarchy,” no confusion in this unprecedented and

improvised management by the people. To convince oneself of this

it is enough to leaf through the minutes of the popular societies, of

the sittings of the general council of the Commune. There one can

see the masses, as if aware of their natural tendency to indiscipline,

animated by an ever present concern for self-discipline. They organize

their deliberations and they impose order on those who might be

tempted to provoke disorder. Even though in 1793 their experience

of public life was relatively recent, even though most of the sans-culottes,

guided it is true by educated petit-bourgeois, did not yet

know how to read or write, they already demonstrated a capacity

for self-management that even today the bourgeoisie, anxious to

preserve its monopoly over public affairs, persists against all the

evidence in denying. And certain revolutionary theoreticians, full

of a sense of intellectual superiority, sometimes also tend to underestimate

this capacity of the masses for self-government.

Direct Democracy and Vanguard

But at the same time the difficulties and contradictions of self-management

made their appearance. The lack of education and the relative

backwardness of their political consciousness were obstacles

to the masses’ full participation in public life. Not all of the people

have a sense of their true interests. While some demonstrated

extraordinary lucidity for the period, others allowed themselves

to be led astray. The revolutionary bourgeoisie took advantage of

the prestige it earned in its uncompromising struggle against the

remnants of the **ancien régime** to inculcate in the sans-culottes a

seductive but false ideology which in fact went against their aspirations

for full equality. If we flick through the voluminous collection

of reports from the secret agents of the Ministry of the Interior, we

can see that informers reported comments made on the streets by

men of the people, the contents of which are sometimes revolutionary,

sometimes counter-revolutionary.[207] And these remarks are

all lumped together and considered to be the expressions of the

<em>vox populi</em> without any attempt to discriminate among them or to

analyze their obvious contradictions.

The relative confusion of the people, notably of manual

workers deprived of education, left the field open to better educated

or more conscious minorities. This was how the Maison Commune

Section, made up largely of masons, a small core group “got it to do

whatever they wanted.”[208] In many popular societies, despite all the

care taken and the concern to ensure the most perfect functioning

of democracy, factions led the dance in one direction or the other,

and they sometimes even opposed each other.

The great lesson of 1793 is not just that direct democracy is

viable, it is also that the vanguard of a society, when it is still a

minority in relation to the mass of the country that it carries along

with it, cannot avoid, in that life-or-death battle that is a revolution,

imposing its will on the majority, first and preferentially through

persuasion, and, if persuasion fails, by force.

It was in the experience of the French Revolution that Marx

and Engels found the source for their famous notion of the “dictatorship”

of the proletariat. Unfortunately, it was never truly elaborated

by its authors. Without claiming, like Kautsky in the period

when he was a reformist, that in their work it is nothing but a

<em>Wörtchen,</em> a little word occasionally used but of no importance,[209]

one is forced to say that they only ever used it too briefly and too

vaguely in their writings. And when in particular they discover it in

the French Revolution the terms they employ are far from clear and

are debatable.[210] In fact, the revolutionaries of the Year II, convinced

though they were of the need for exceptional measures, for having

recourse to force, had a horror of using the word dictatorship. The

Commune of 1793, like its heir of 1871, wanted to guide and not

“impose its supremacy.” Marat himself, the sole revolutionary of his

time who called for a dictatorship, was forced to resort to careful

language: he asked for a guide and not a master. But even in this

veiled form he scandalized his brothers in arms and earned their

loud protests.

Let it be understood: democracy had just issued its first cry. The

tyrant had just been overthrown and the Bastille razed. The word

“dictatorship” had a bad ring to it. It evoked the idea of a descent

once again into tyranny, into personal power. In fact, for the men

of the eighteenth century, nourished on memories of antiquity, dictatorship

had a precise and formidable meaning. They recalled—and

the **Encyclopedia** was there to remind them—that the Romans,

“having driven out their kings saw themselves obliged, in difficult

times, to temporarily create a dictator enjoying greater power than

any enjoyed by the ancient kings.” They recalled that later, the institution

having degenerated, Sulla and Caesar proclaimed themselves

perpetual dictators and exercised absolute sovereignty, in the latter

case going as far as being suspected of having monarchist aims.

They did not want either a new monarch or a new Caesar.

The men of 1793 had an even clearer memory of England. How

could they forget that a century earlier Oliver Cromwell had overthrown

an absolute monarch, usurped popular power, established

a dictatorship, and even attempted to have himself crowned king?

They feared a new Cromwell like the plague, and this was one of

their complaints against Robespierre on the eve of Thermidor.[211]

Finally, the rank-and-file sans-culottes, the men and women

of the popular societies, instinctively distrusted the word dictatorship,

for it would have represented only a portion of revolutionary

reality: they first of all wanted to convince, to open to everyone the

doors to the nascent democracy, and they only resorted to force

when those they wanted to convince and admit into democracy

answered them with lead.

Perhaps they intuited that it is always an error to borrow words

from the enemy’s vocabulary. “The sovereignty of the people,” as

Henri de Saint-Simon pointed out, is one of those unfortunate borrowings.

From the day they administer themselves the people are

the sovereigns of no one. “The Despotism of liberty” (a phrase the

men of ’93 sometimes used in preference to “dictatorship” for it has

a more collective resonance) and “dictatorship of the proletariat” are

no less antonymic. The form of coercion that the proletarian vanguard

finds itself forced to exercise against counter-revolutionaries

is of so fundamentally different a nature from the past forms of

oppression, and it is compensated for by so advanced a degree of

democracy for the formerly oppressed, that the word dictatorship

clashes with that of proletariat.

Such was the opinion of the libertarian collectivists like

Bakunin, who were of course aware that the possessing classes

would not voluntarily renounce their privileges and that they must

be forced to do so, and who were determined to “organize a revolutionary

force capable of triumphing over reaction”; but at the same

time they categorically rejected any slogan of “so-called revolutionary

dictatorship, even as a revolutionary transition,” even if it is

“revolutionary in the Jacobin manner.”[212] As for reformists, they not

only reject the words “dictatorship of the proletariat,” but also what

we have just seen defined as valid, namely the idea of revolutionary

constraint or coercion. And so, for too long, Marxist revolutionaries

have not dared to express any reservations concerning the words

used, for fear of being suspected of “opportunism” regarding their

essence.[213]

The inappropriateness of the terms appears still more clearly

if we go back to the sources. The Babouvists (followers of Babeuf)

were the first to speak of revolutionary “dictatorship.”[214] Although

they had the merit of drawing a clear lesson from the bourgeoisie’s

theft of the revolution, we know that they appeared too late, at

a moment when the masses had surrendered. A minuscule and

isolated minority, they doubted the people’s capacity to lead themselves,

at least in the near term, and they called for a dictatorship,

either the dictatorship of one man or that of “hands wisely and

resolutely revolutionary.”[215]

The German communist Weitling and the French revolutionary

Blanqui borrowed this concept of dictatorship from the Babouvists.[216]

Incapable of joining up with a mass movement that was still

embryonic, with a proletariat still too ignorant and demoralized to

govern itself, they believed that small, bold minorities could seize

power by surprise and establish socialism from above by means

of the most rigorous dictatorial centralization, while waiting for

the people to be mature enough to share power with their leaders.

While the idealist Weitling envisaged a personal dictatorship, that

of “a new messiah,” Blanqui, more realistic, closer to the nascent

working-class movement, spoke of a “Parisian dictatorship,” that is,

a dictatorship of the Parisian proletariat, though in his mind the

proletariat was only capable of exercising this “dictatorship” in the

person of one man, through the intermediary of its educated elite,

of Blanqui and his secret society.[217]

Marx and Engels, though opposed to the Blanquists’ minoritarian

and voluntarist concepts, in 1850 made them the concession

of adopting the famous formula,[218] going as far as identifying communism

and Blanquism.[219] There is no doubt that in the minds of

the founders of scientific socialism, revolutionary coercion seemed

to be exercised by the working class and not, as in the case of the

Blanquists, by a vanguard detached from the class.[220] But they did

not differentiate such an interpretation of the “dictatorship of the

proletariat” clearly enough from that of the Blanquists. Later Lenin,

claiming to adhere both to Jacobinism and Marxism, would invent

the concept of the dictatorship of one party substituting itself for

the working class and acting in its name.[221] And his disciples in the

Urals, taking his logic to its ultimate conclusion, frankly proclaimed,

without being disavowed, that the dictatorship of the proletariat

would be a dictatorship over the proletariat.[222]

From 1921 the German anarchist Rudolf Rocker, noting the

“bankruptcy of state ‘communism”’ in Russia would maintain that

the dictatorship of one class in and of itself is “absolutely unthinkable.”

and that in reality it is a matter of the dictatorship of one party

claiming to speak in the name of a class. And he would forcefully

rise up against the illusion of transforming the state, an organ of

oppression, into an organ for the liberation of the oppressed, baptized

“dictatorship” of the proletariat. “The state,” he wrote, “can

only be what it is, the defender of privilege and the exploitation of

the masses, the creator of new classes and monopolies. Whoever

does not know the role of the state does not grasp the essence of

the current social order and is incapable of showing humanity the

new horizons of its evolution.”[223]

The Reconstituting of the State

The dual experiences of the French and Russian Revolutions teach

us that we are touching upon the central point of a mechanism

at the end of which direct democracy, people’s self-management,

gradually mutates, through the establishing of the revolutionary

“dictatorship,” into the reconstitution of an apparatus for the oppression

of the people. Of course, the process was not exactly identical

in the two revolutions. The first was that of an essentially bourgeois

revolution, though already containing the embryo of proletarian

revolution. The second was an essentially proletarian revolution,

though having at the same time to fulfill the tasks of the bourgeois

revolution. In the first case it was not the “dictatorship” from

below, which had however already made an appearance, it was the

dictatorship from above, that of the bourgeois revolutionary government,

which provided the starting point for a new oppressive

apparatus. In the second case it was from the “dictatorship from

below,” that of the proletariat in arms, for whom the party almost

immediately substituted itself, that the oppressive apparatus was

finally reconstituted. But in the two cases, despite this important

difference, an analogy can be seen: the concentration of power, the

“dictatorship,” is presented as the product of necessity.[224] The revolution

is in danger from both within and without. The reconstituting

of the oppressive apparatus is invoked as indispensable for the

crushing of counter-revolution.

Was the “necessity”—the counter-revolutionary danger—really

the only reason for this abrupt turnabout? This is what most

left-wing historians claim. Georges Lefebvre assures us that the

Revolution could only be saved if the people were “organized and

led by bourgeois cadres,” It was necessary to bring together all the

nation’s forces for the benefit of the army. This could only occur by

means of a strong and centralized government. Dictatorship from

below could not succeed in this, since apart from the fact that it

lacked the needed abilities, it could not forego an overall plan and a

center of execution.[225] Albert Soboul considers that the direct democracy

of the sans-culottes was, due to its “weakness,” impracticable

in the crisis through which the republic was passing.[226] Before them,

Georges Guy-Grand, minimizing the political capacity of the popular

vanguard, maintained that “the people of Paris did not know what

to do with their riots. The riots were valid means of destroying, and

destruction must sometimes be done. But demolishing Bastilles,

massacring prisoners, aiming cannons at the Convention are not

enough to make a country live. When cadres needed to be reconstituted,

when industries and the government had to be made to

function, there was no choice but to rely on the sole elements available,

which were bourgeois.”[227]

But it is not certain that the Revolution could only be saved by

these techniques and from above. A relatively effective collaboration

had been established at the base between the administration

of staple goods and the popular societies, between the government

and the revolutionary committees. The reinforcement of central

power stifled and killed the initiative from below that had been

the heart of the Revolution. Bourgeois ability was substituted for

popular enthusiasm. The Revolution lost its essential strength, its

internal dynamic.

What is more, we must be wary of those who invoke the

pretext of “competence” to legitimize the exclusive and abusive use

of bourgeois expertise during a revolutionary period. First, because

men of the people are less ignorant, less incompetent than some

people claim in order to make their case. Second, because the plebeians

of 1793, when they were lacking in technical abilities, overcame

that deficiency by their sense of democracy and their higher awareness

of their obligations to the revolution. Finally, because the bourgeois

technicians, reputed to be indispensable and irreplaceable, too

often profited by their situation, which was considered impregnable,

to intrigue against the people and to even develop suspicious ties

with counter-revolutionaries. People like Carnot, Cambon, Lindet,

and BarĂšre were the agents of the great bourgeoisie and the sworn

enemies of the sans-culottes. During a revolution a man lacking in

competency but devoted body and soul to the people’s cause, when

he assumes civil or military responsibilities is worth more than a

competent individual ready to betray.

During the six months or so of the flourishing of direct democracy

the people demonstrated their creative genius; they revealed,

though in a still embryonic form, that there exist other revolutionary

techniques than those of the bourgeoisie, than one that is topdown.

Certainly it is the latter that prevailed at the time, for the

bourgeoisie had a maturity and an experience that conferred on it

an enormous advantage over the people. But Year II of the Republic,

if one knows how to decipher its message, foretells that the fertile

potential of revolutionary techniques from below will one day win

out in the proletarian revolution over the techniques inherited from

the Jacobin bourgeoisie. Albert Mathiez, accustomed, as Georges

Lefebvre admits, to “considering the Revolution from above.”[228] felt

that he needed to draw an enthusiastic parallel between the “harsh”

dictatorship of Public Safety of 1793 and that of 1920 in Russia.[229]

But even during the period when Mathiez was invoking the

revolutionary bourgeois dictatorship of 1793 in an attempt to legitimize

Lenin’s Jacobin dictatorship, the German anarchist Rudolf

Rocker supported the contrary thesis: “Referring to the French

Revolution to justify the tactics of the Bolsheviks in Russia,” he

said, demonstrates “a total misunderstanding of historical facts ....

Historical experience demonstrates the exact opposite: at every

decisive moment of the French Revolution the true initiative in

action rose directly from the people. The secret of the Revolution

resides in this creative activity of the masses.” On the other hand,

it was when Robespierre deprived the popular movement of its

autonomy and made it submit to central power, when he persecuted

the authentically revolutionary tendencies and crushed the

Left opposition, that the “ebbing of the Revolution, preface to 9

Thermidor and, later, to the Napoleonic dictatorship of the sword.”

began.[230] Rocker concluded with bitterness in 1921: “In Russia they

are repeating today what occurred in France in March 1794.”

The Embryo of a Plebeian Bureaucracy

Because the Great Revolution was not only bourgeois but was also

accompanied by an embryonic proletarian revolution, one sees in

it the germ of a phenomenon that will only assume its full scope

in the degeneration of the Russian Revolution. Already, in 1793,

democracy from below gave birth to a caste of parvenus differentiating

themselves from the masses and aspiring to commandeer

the popular revolution to their profit. In the ambivalent mentality

of these plebeians, revolutionary faith and material appetites were

closely intertwined. As JaurĂšs phrased it, the Revolution looked to

them to be “both an ideal and a career.”[231] They served the bourgeois

revolution at the same time that they used it. Robespierre and Saint-Just,

like Lenin in his time, denounced the appetite of this nascent

and already invasive bureaucracy.

A certain number of them entered into open conflict with the

Committee of Public Safety. If their attachment to bourgeois law

and property flowed from their greed, they nevertheless had individual

interests to defend against the revolutionary bourgeoisie.

The latter, in fact, only wanted to leave them as small a piece of

the pie as possible, first because that enormous budget-devouring

plebs was expensive; second, because the bourgeoisie distrusted its

origins among and its links to the people and, above all, the support

from the working-class quarters which it had obtained demagogically

with a view to occupying all posts; and finally because the

bourgeoisie intended to keep the control of the revolutionary government

in the hands of its tried and tested experts.

The struggle for power that opposed the plebeians to the

experts was a sharp one and, in the end, it was settled by the guillotine.

Certain important sectors such as the Ministry of War, the

secret funds,[232] and the war industries were the stakes in this rivalry.

The battle over the war industry was particularly revealing, for it

was here that two modes of economic management confronted

each other: free enterprise and what is today called state capitalism.

If the plebeians had achieved their goals and if the war industry

had been nationalized as they demanded, a portion of the profits

coveted and finally seized by the revolutionary bourgeoisie would

have gone into their pockets.

Trotsky, incompletely informed, is not totally correct when

he asserts that Stalinism “had no prehistory,” that the French

Revolution knew nothing that resembled the Soviet bureaucracy,

derived from a single revolutionary party and having its roots in

the collective ownership of the means of production.[233] I think, on

the contrary, that the HĂ©bertist plebeians were, in more ways than

one, a foreshadowing of the Russian bureaucrats of the Stalinist

era.

In the same way, once the generals of the **ancien régime,** traitors

to the revolution, were eliminated, there arose alongside the

devoted but incompetent sans-culotte generals a new type of young

chiefs risen from the ranks, capable but consumed by ambition and

who would later be the instruments of reaction and military dictatorship.

To a certain extent, these future Marshals of the Empire

were the prefiguration of Soviet marshals.

“Anarchy” Deduced from the French Revolution

The French Revolution had hardly ended before “theoreticians”

plunged into the analysis of its mechanisms and the search for

its lessons with passionate ardor and an often remarkable lucidity.

Their attention was concentrated essentially on two great problems:

that of permanent revolution and that of the state. What

they discovered first was that the Great Revolution, because it had

been only bourgeois, had betrayed popular aspirations and had to

be continued until the complete liberation of man. What they all

deduced from this was socialism.[234] Some of them also discovered

that within the Revolution a new type of people power, oriented

from the bottom up, had made its appearance on the historical

stage and that it had finally been supplanted by a powerfully reconstituted

top-down oppressive apparatus. And they wondered with

fright how the people could avoid seeing their revolution commandeered

in the future. From this they deduced anarchism.

The first person who saw this, in 1794, was the Enragé Varlet.[235]

In a short pamphlet written right after Thermidor he wrote this

prophetic sentence: “For any reasoning being, government and

revolution are incompatible.” And he accused the “revolutionary

government” of having, in the name of public safety, established

a dictatorship.[236] “This is the conclusion,” wrote two historians of

anarchism, “that the first of the EnragĂ©s drew from 1793, and that

conclusion is anarchist.”[237] Varlet’s pamphlet contained a profound

idea: a revolution led by the masses and a strong authority (against

the masses) are two incompatible things.

The Babouvists drew this conclusion in their turn. “The rulers,”

wrote Babeuf, “only make revolutions in order to continue governing.

We want to make one to eternally ensure the people’s happiness

through real democracy.” And Buonarotti, his disciple, foreseeing

the commandeering of future revolutions by new elites added,

“If there was formed within the state a class exclusively knowledgeable

about the principles of the social art, laws, and administration,

it would soon discover the secret of creating distinctions and

privileges for itself.”[238] Buonarotti deduced from this that only the

radical suppression of social inequalities, that only communism

would allow society to be rid of the scourge of the state: “A people

without property and without the vices and crimes it engenders

would not feel the need for the great number of laws under which

the civilized societies of Europe groan.”[239]

But the Babouvists were not able to draw all the consequences

of this discovery. Isolated from the masses, they contradicted themselves,

as we saw, by calling for the dictatorship of one man or of

a “wise” elite, which would later lead Proudhon to write that “the

negation of government, which shone briefly through the Enragés

and the Hebertists before being snuffed out, would have issued from

Babeuf’s doctrines, if Babeuf had been able to think through the

logical consequences of his own premise.”[240]

It is Proudhon who, in 1851, had the merit of having drawn from

the French Revolution a truly profound analysis of the problem of

the state. The author of **The General Idea of Revolution in the Nineteenth Century** started with a critique of bourgeois and parliamentary

democracy, of democracy from above, and of democracy by decree.[241]

He denounced its fraudulent nature. He attacked Robespierre, an

open enemy of direct democracy. He stressed the failings of the

democratic constitution of 1793, a departure point, to be sure, but

a bastard compromise between bourgeois democracy and direct

democracy, which promised the people everything and gave them

nothing and which, in any case, was no sooner promulgated than

its implementation was indefinitely put off.

Getting to the heart of the problem, Proudhon declared, after

Varlet, that “in proclaiming freedom of opinion, equality before

the law, the sovereignty of the people, and the subordination of

authority to the country, the Revolution made two incompatible

things of society and the government.” He affirms “the absolute

incompatibility of authority with freedom.” And he pronounced

a fiery condemnation of the state: “No authority, no government,

not even a people’s government: the Revolution resides in this ....

The government of the people will always be the swindling of

the people .... If the Revolution allows government [the state] to

survive somewhere, it will return everywhere.” And he attacks the

boldest of thinkers, the “authoritarian” socialists who, while admitting

the misdeeds of the state “still said that while government is

doubtless a scourge ... it was still a necessary evil. “This is why,” he

adds, “the most emancipatory revolutions have always ended in an

act of faith and submission to authority, why all revolutions have

only served to reconstitute tyranny.” “The people gave themselves

a tyrant instead of a protector. Everywhere and at all times the government,

however popular it was at its origin, after having shown

itself to be liberal for a certain time, gradually became exceptional

and exclusive.”

He harshly condemned the centralization carried out through

the decree of December 4, 1793.[242] This centralization was understandable

under the former monarchy, but “under the pretext of a

One and Indivisible Republic, to remove from the people the right

to dispose of their forces, to call those who speak in favor of liberty

and local sovereignty ‘federalists’ who are to be proscribed, means

putting the lie to the true spirit of the French Revolution, to its most

authentic tendencies. The system of centralization that prevailed

in ’93 was nothing but a transformed feudalism. Napoleon, who put

the final touches to it, testified to this.” Later, Bakunin, a disciple of

Proudhon, would echo him: “A strange thing, that great revolution

which, for the first time in history, proclaimed the freedom, not

only of the citizen, but of man; but in making itself the heir of the

monarchy it killed, it at the same time revived the negation of all

freedom: the centralization and omnipotence of the state.”[243]

But Proudhon’s thought goes farther and deeper. He fears that

the exercise of direct democracy, that the most ingenious formulas

aimed at promoting an authentic government of the people, by

the people—the fusing of the legislative and executive powers, the

election and revocability of functionaries recruited by the people

from within their number, and permanent popular control—that

this system, which may be “irreproachable” in theory, “in practice

encounters an insurmountable difficulty.” In fact, even in this

optimal hypothesis the risk remains of the incompatibility between

society and authority. “If the entire people, as sovereigns, becomes

the government, one seeks in vain where the governed would be ....

If the people, organized as the authority, has nothing above them, I

ask who is below?” There is no middle way, one must “either work

or rule.” “The people passing en masse over to the state, the state

no longer has the least reason to exist, since there no longer exists

a people: the result of the governmental equation is zero.”

How to escape this contradiction, this “vicious circle”?

Proudhon answers that the government must be dissolved in the

economic organization. “The governmental institution ... has its

raison d’ĂȘtre in economic anarchy. Since the Revolution puts an

end to this anarchy and organizes the industrial forces, there is no

longer a pretext for political centralization.”

The “Jacobin” Tradition

Bakunin in turn stresses that since their thought was “nourished”

by a certain theory, which “was nothing but the Jacobin political

system more or less modified for the use of revolutionary socialists,

the socialist workers of France never wanted to understand

[that] when, in the name of the Revolution, you want to build a

state, even if only a transitory state, it is a reactionary step and you

are working for despotism.”[244] To a certain extent the disagreement

between Marxists and anarchists flows from the fact that the former

do not always view the French Revolution in the same way as the

latter. Deutscher saw that within Bolshevism there were two spirits,

the Marxist and the Jacobin, a conflict that would never be resolved,

neither in Lenin nor in Trotsky.[245] As we will see, there can be found

within Bolshevism holdovers from Jacobinism more accentuated

than in the original Marxism. But I think that Marxism itself never

completely overcame an analogous contradiction. There is within

it a libertarian frame of mind as well as a Jacobin and authoritarian

frame of mind.

In my opinion, the origin of this duality can mainly be found

in an at times correct, but also at times erroneous appreciation of

the real content of the French Revolution. The Marxists see that the

latter betrayed popular aspirations because it was, objectively and

in its immediate results, a bourgeois revolution. But at the same

time they are blinded by an abusive application of the materialist

concept of history, which sometimes leads them to consider it

only from the point of view and within the limits of the bourgeois

revolution. Of course they are right to stress those relatively and

inarguably progressive features of the bourgeois revolution, but

there are moments when they present these features, which even

anarchists like Bakunin and Kropotkin, if not Proudhon, exalted in

a unilateral fashion, overestimating and idealizing them.

Because he was a Menshevik, Boris Nicolaevsky exaggeratedly

stresses this tendency of Marxism. But there is something true

about his analysis. And the German ultra-leftist of 1848, Gottschalk,

was not completely wrong in balking at the Marxist perspective

of “escaping the hell of the Middle Ages” only to “voluntarily leap

into the purgatory” of capitalism.[246] What Isaac Deutscher says of

the Russian Marxists prior to 1917—for, paradoxically, there was

much “Menshevism” in these “Bolsheviks”—is also, I think, valid

to a certain extent for the founders of Marxism: “Since they saw

in capitalism an indispensable halfway house on the road from

feudalism to socialism, they stressed the advantages of that halfway

house, its progressive features, its civilizing influence, its attractive

atmosphere and so on.”[247]

If we examine the many passages in Marx and Engels concerning

the French Revolution it has to be said that sometimes they

see and sometimes they lose sight of its character as a “permanent

revolution.” To be sure, they do see the revolution from below, but

only occasionally. To give an example, Marx does not hesitate to

present the humble supporters in the working-class quarters of

Jacques Roux and Varlet as the “main representatives” of the revolutionary

movement, but Engels nevertheless writes that to the

“proletariat” of 1793 “in its incapacity to help itself, help could, at best,

be brought in from without or down from above.”[248]

And so we can already understand better what Deutscher

means by Jacobin spirit, namely the tradition of bourgeois revolution

and dictatorship from above of 1793, somewhat idealized

and insufficiently differentiated from compulsion from below. And

by extension, we can understand the tradition of Babouvist and

Blanquist conspiratorialism which borrows the dictatorial and

minoritarian techniques of the bourgeois revolution in order to

put them at the service of a new revolution.

One can see why the anarchists discern in the socialism and

communism of the nineteenth century a certain “Jacobin,” “authoritarian,” “governmentalist” tendency; a propensity towards the “cult

of state discipline” inherited from Robespierre and the Jacobins;

that they define a “bourgeois frame of mind,” “a political legacy of

bourgeois revolutionism” to which they oppose the affirmation that

the “social revolutions of our day have nothing or almost nothing

to imitate in the revolutionary methods of the Jacobins of 1793.”[249]

Marx and Engels deserve this reproach far less than other

authoritarian and statist socialist currents of the nineteenth century.

But they had some difficulty in freeing themselves of the Jacobin

tradition. For example, they were slow in ridding themselves of the

Jacobin myth of the “rigorous centralization offered as a model by

the France of 1793.” They finally rejected it, under the pressure of the

anarchists, but not before having stumbled, hesitated, and modified

their analysis and, even after all these corrective measures, they

still went down the wrong road.[250] This wavering would allow Lenin

to forget the anti-centralist passages in their writings—notably a

clarification by Engels in 1885[251]—and to retain only “the facts cited

by Engels concerning the centralized French Republic from 1792 to

1799,” and to baptize Marx a “centralist.”[252]

Indeed, the Jacobin hold was much stronger on the Russian

Bolsheviks than it was on the founders of Marxism. And in large

part this deviation has its origin in an occasionally incorrect and

one-sided interpretation of the French Revolution. Lenin, it is true,

clearly saw its permanent revolution aspects. He demonstrated

that the popular movement, which he incorrectly called a “bourgeois

democratic revolution,” was far from reaching its objectives

in 1794, and that it would only succeed in doing so in 1871.[253] If total

victory was not won at the end of the eighteenth century, it was

because “the material bases for socialism” were still lacking.[254] The

bourgeois regime is only progressive in relation to the autocracy

that precedes it, as the final form of domination and “the most

fitting arena for the struggle of the proletariat against the bourgeoisie.”[255] Only the proletariat is capable of pushing the revolution

to its final end, “for it goes much further than the democratic

revolution.”[256]

But Lenin long rejected the concept of permanent revolution

and maintained that the Russian proletariat, after the conquest of

power, had to voluntarily limit itself to the bourgeois democratic

regime. This is why he often tends to overestimate the heritage of

the French Revolution, affirming that it will remain “perhaps for

all time the model for certain revolutionary methods,” and that the

historians of the proletariat should see in Jacobinism “one of the

culminating points that the oppressed class reached in the struggle

for its emancipation, [one of the] best examples of democratic

revolution.”[257] This is why he idealized Danton[258] and did not hesitate

to proclaim himself “Jacobin.”[259] This is why, with much exaggeration,

he attributes to bourgeois revolutionaries radical measures

against the capitalists and claimed to act, like them, with “Jacobin

inflexibility.”[260]

Lenin’s Jacobin attitudes brought him a sharp reply from

Trotsky in 1904. For the latter, who had not yet become a Bolshevik,

Jacobinism “is the maximum degree of radicalism that bourgeois

society can provide.” Modern revolutionaries must protect themselves

from Jacobinism as much as from reformism. Jacobinism

and proletarian socialism are “two molds, two doctrines, two tactics,

two psychologies separated by an abyss.” If both are intransigent,

their intransigence is qualitatively different. The attempt to introduce

Jacobin methods into the proletarian revolutions of the twentieth

century is nothing but opportunism. Just like reformism, it is

the expression of “a tendency to tie the proletariat to an ideology,

a tactic, and finally a psychology foreign and hostile to its class

interests.”[261]

Towards a Synthesis

In conclusion, the French Revolution was the source of two great

currents of socialist thought which, across the twentieth century,

have lasted until today: an authoritarian Jacobin current and a libertarian

current. One, of a “bourgeois disposition,” oriented from the

top down, is above all concerned with revolutionary effectiveness

and claims to be taking account of “necessities.” The other, of an

essentially proletarian spirit, is oriented from the bottom up, and

places the safeguarding of freedom to the fore. Between these two

currents numerous more or less shaky compromises have already

been elaborated.

Bakunin’s anarchist collectivism attempted to reconcile

Proudhon and Marx. Within the First International, Marxism

sought a middle way between Blanqui and Bakunin. The Commune

of 1871 was an empirical synthesis of Jacobinism and federalism.

Lenin himself, in **State and Revolution,** was tom between anarchism

and state “communism,” between mass spontaneity and Jacobin

iron discipline. Yet the real synthesis of these two currents is still

to be effected. As H.E. Kaminski wrote, it is not only necessary, it is

inevitable: “History itself constructs its compromises.”[262] The degeneration

of the Russian Revolution and the collapse and historical

bankruptcy of Stalinism places it more than ever on the agenda. It

alone will allow us to remake our “baggage of ideas” and to forever

prevent our revolutions being commandeered by new Jacobins utilizing

tanks, in comparison with which the guillotine of 1793 will

look like a toy.

<right>

[1956, in **Jeunesse du Socialisme Libertaire**]

</right>

[196] “Nous avons perdu nos bagages.” Edgar Quinet, **La Revolution** (Editions

Lacroix, Vanoeckhoven & Cie, 1869 [1865]), vol. I, p. 8. [Quinet was a

prominent republican writer and historian. —DB]

[197] ‘Vichy’ is shorthand for the quasi-fascist, collaborationist ‘French State’

created in 1940 under Marshal Petain with its capital in the southern spa

town of Vichy (the northern half of the country, including Paris, having

been occupied by German forces). [DB]

[198] France’s postwar Fourth Republic (1946–1958) was notorious for its political

instability and inability to resolve the Algerian war of independence;

it finally collapsed in 1958 under pressure from a generals’ putsch in

Algiers, and General Charles de Gaulle was made head of the government

(and later president). The Fifth Republic, which he created, saw a reduction

in the powers of parliament, a reinforced executive and the creation

of a semi-presidential regime, widely perceived at the time on the left

(including by Guérin) as being Bonapartist or quasi-fascist. Today there

are still widespread calls for its democratization or even for the creation

of a Sixth Republic. [DB]

[199] The Hungarian Revolution of 1956 and the Prague Spring of 1968 were

both crushed by Soviet bloc tanks. Both events led to a haemorrhage of

members from Western Communist Parties. [DB]

[200] **La lutte de classes sous la Premiere Republique, 1793–1797** (Paris: Gallimard,

1946; revised edition 1968), 2 vols.

[201] **Times Literary Supplement,** 15 November 1947. [GuĂ©rin’s text incorrectly gave

the year of publication as 1946. He also failed to notice that the author’s

name was given in the contents page: Professor David Thomson. —DB]

[202] See Kropotkin’s **The Great French Revolution, 1789–1793,** first published as **La Grande Revolution, 1789–1793** (Paris: Stock, 1909). Most historians of socialist

thought have failed to emphasise adequately the fact that these currents of

thought were not simply born in the minds of the nineteenth-century ideologists

(themselves the heirs of the **philosophes** of the eighteenth century),

but from the lived experience of class struggles, in particular that of 1793.

This gap is particularly evident in the chapter on the French Revolution

with which the late lamented G.D.H. Cole opened his monumental history

of socialist thought **(A History of Socialist Thought,** vol. I, 1953, pp. 11–2).

[203] Boris Souvarine, **Staline** (Editions Champs Libre, 1977 [1935]), p. 265; Erich

Wollenberg, **The Red Army** (London, 1970), pp. 78–80; Isaac Deutscher,

<em>Staline</em> (Gallimard, 1953), p. 7.

[204] As part of a broader move to do away with everything related to the prerevolutionary

regime and the reactionary influence of the Catholic Church,

a new Republican calendar, with months named after seasonal aspects

of the natural world, was instituted. ‘Year I’ began after the declaration

of the Republic in 1792. The calendar was later abolished by Napoleon,

but taken up again very briefly during the Paris Commune of 1871. [DB]

[205] See, amongst others, Marc-Antoine Jullien in the “Societe populaire” of

La Rochelle, 5 March 1793, in Edouard Lockroy, **Une mission en Vendee, 1793**

(Paris: Paul Ollendorf editeur, 1893), pp. 245–8, quoted in Daniel GuĂ©rin,

<em>La lutte de classes,</em> vol. I, pp. 177–8.

[206] See Paul Sainte-Claire Deville, **La Commune de l‘an II** (Paris: Pion, 1946).

[207] Pierre Caron, **Paris pendant la Terreur** (Paris: Alphonse Picard, 1910–1964),

6 vols.

[208] In Pierre Caron, **Paris pendant la Terreur,** vol. 6 (“observer” Boucheseiche,

29 March 1794).

[209] Karl Kautsky, **Die Diktatur des Proletariats** (Vienna 1918); published as **The Dictatorship of the Proletariat** in 1919 (National Labour Press) [DB]. See also

his **Materialistische Geschichtsauffassung** (1927), vol. II, p. 469. Cf. Lenin’s **The Proletarian Revolution and the Renegade Kautsky** (1918).

[210] Thus in his critique of the Erfurt Programme, Engels wrote that the democratic

republic was “the specific form for the dictatorship of the proletariat,

as the Great French Revolution has already shown.” ‘A Critique of the Draft

Social-Democratic Program of 1891’, **Marx-Engels Complete Works,** vol. 27. p. 217.

[211] When Saint-Just proposed the concentration of power in the hands of

Robespierre, the idea of a personal dictatorship caused a furore among

his colleagues, and Robert Lindet exclaimed: “We did not make the

Revolution in order to benefit one individual.” In Armand Montier, **Robert Lindet** (1899), p. 249. [Thermidor was a month in the revolutionary calendar,

and 9 Thermidor Year II was the date of the overthrow of Robespierre

and the Jacobins; “Thermidor” has thus come to be shorthand for counterrevolution.

—DB]

[212] Bakunin, article in **L'Egalite** (26 June 1869) reproduced as an appendix in

<em>Memoire de la Federationjurassienne</em> (Sonvillier, 1873); <em> ƒuvres</em> (Stock), vol. IV,

p. 344; ‘Programme de l‘Organisation rĂ©volutionnaire des Freres intemationaux’,

in **Ul.lliance internationale de la democratie socialiste et l’Association internationale des travailleurs** (London & Hamburg, 1873). It is true that

Bakunin, when under the influence of the Blanquists, would occasionally

use the word “dictatorship”, but he would always pull himself back immediately:

“dictatorship, but not one sanctioned by the officer’s sash, governmental

title or legal institution, and all the more powerful for having none

of the accoutrements of power” (Letter to Albert Richard, 1870, in Richard,

<em>Bakounine et l’Internationale a Lyon.</em> Cf. also Fritz Brupbacher, ‘Soixante ans

d’heresie’ in **Socialisme et Liberte** (Editions de la Baconniere Boudry, 1955),

p. 259.

[213] They shook with fear at the thought of contradicting Lenin, for whom

anyone who did not understand the necessity of dictatorship had understood

nothing about the Revolution and could therefore not be a true

revolutionary. See his ‘Contribution a l’histoire de la dictature’ (1920), in

V.I. Lenin, **De l’Etat** (Paris: Bureau d’editions, 1935).

[214] Gracchus Babeuf (1760–1797), guillotined for his part in the Conspiracy

of the Equals, was widely influential in the nineteenth century and is

regarded as a precursor of revolutionary socialism. See Ian Birchall, **The Spectre of Babeuf** (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2016). [DB]

[215] Philippe Buonarotti, **Conspiration pour /‘egaliti, dite de Babeuf** (Librairie

romantique, 1828), vol. I, pp. 93, 134, 139, 140. **[History of Babeuj’s ‘Conspiracy of Equals’** —DB]

[216] Wilhelm Weitling (1808–1871), a Prussian tailor, lived in Paris from 1837 to

1841 and was influenced by Charles Fourier, Robert Owen, Etienne Cabet

and early millenarian Christian movements. A member of the communist

League of the Just, he was admired by many leading revolutionaries of

the time, including Marx and Bakunin. [DB]

[217] Kautsky, **The Dictatorship of the Proletariat;** Preface by V.P. Volguine in Albert

Soboul, Pierre Angrand and Jean Dauty (eds.), **Textes choisis de Blanqui**

(Paris: Editions sociales, 1955), pp. 20 and 41; Maurice Dommanget, **Les idees politiques et sociales d’Auguste Blanqui** (Paris: Librairie Marcel Riviere,

1957), pp. 170–3.

[218] Cf. **Les Cahiers du bolchevisme,** 14 March 1933, p. 451.

[219] Marx, **La Lutte de classes en France** [1850] (Ed. Schleicher, 1900), p.147. [“The

<em>proletariat</em> rallies more and more around <em>revolutionary socialism,</em> around <em>communism,</em>

for which the bourgeoisie has itself invented the name of **Blanqui.**

This socialism is the **declaration of the permanence of the revolution,** the **class dictatorship** of the proletariat as the necessary transit point to the **abolition of class distinctions generally”** –Marxists Internet Archive. DB]

[220] Maximilien Rubel, **Karl Marx, pages choisies pour une ethique socialiste** (Paris:

Marcel Riviere, 1948), pp. 224–5.

[221] A reference to Lenin’s comment: “A Jacobin who wholly identifies himself

with the organisation of the proletariat—a proletariat conscious of its

class interests—is a revolutionary Social Democrat.” (Collected Works

7: p. 383) Rosa Luxemburg challenges this claim in her ‘Organizational

Questions of the Russian Social Democracy’, while Kropotkin stressed

the fundamentally bourgeois nature and role of the Jacobins in **La Science Moderne et l’Anarchie** (Paris, 1913) and **The Great French Revolution, 2789–1793**

(1909). [DB]

[222] Cf. Leon Trotski, **Nos taches politiques** [1904], notably the final chapter

entitled ‘Dictature sur le proletariat’.

[223] **Der Bankrott des russischen Staatskommunismus** (Berlin, 1921), pp. 28–31; published

in French as **Les soviets trahis par les bolcheviks** (Spartacus, 1973, new

edition 1998). [This text, whose title means “The Bankruptcy of Russian

State-Communism”, does not seem to have been translated into English. DB]

[224] Cf. Proudhon, **Idee generate de la Revolution** (1851) in **ƒuvres completes** (Paris:

Riviere, 1926), pp. 121–6; Deutscher, **Staline,** pp. 8–9.

[225] Georges Lefebvre, **Annales historiques ...** April-June 1947, p.175.

[226] Albert Soboul, ‘Robespierre and the Popular Movement of 1793–1794’ in

<em>Past and Present</em> (May 1954), p. 60.

[227] Georges Guy-Grand, **La Democratie et l’apres-guerre** (Paris: Gamier, 1920),

p.230.

[228] Georges Lefebvre, **Etudes sur la Revolutionjranfaise** (Paris: PUF, 1954), p. 21.

[229] Albert Mathiez, **L’Humanite,** 19 August 1920; quoted in Guy-Grand, op. cit.,

p. 225.

[230] **Der Bankrott,** op. cit.

[231] Jean Jaures (1859–1914), a schoolteacher and university lecturer turned

politician, was one of the principal figures in the history of French socialism.

Initially a left-wing republican, he was instrumental in creating and

became the leader of the French Socialist Party (opposed to the Socialist

Party of France led by the self-proclaimed Marxist Jules Guesde), and

in 1904 he founded the newspaper **L’Humanite** (which from 1920 would

be the paper of the French Communist Party). In 1905, the two socialist

parties merged to create the Unified Socialist Party, French Section of

the Workers’ International (PSU-SFIO). Because of his outspoken pacifism,

Jaures was assassinated by a nationalist in 1914 shortly before the

outbreak of war. [DB]

[232] The Ministry of War used the **fonds secrets** (secret funds) to fund intelligence

activities. [DB]

[233] Trotsky, **Staline** (Paris: UGE, 1979 [1948]), pp. 485, 556–60.

[234] The expression “permanent revolution” can be found in the writings of

Bakunin as well as in those of Blanqui and Marx. [See also Proudhon’s

‘Toast to the Revolution’, 17 October 1848: “From this it follows that revolution

is always in history and that, strictly speaking, there are not several

revolutions, but only one permanent revolution.” In **Property Is Theft!,** p.

359—DB]

[235] Jean-François Varlet (1764–1837) was a supporter of the sans-culotte

Hebert and was imprisoned more than once for his insurrectionism. [DB]

[236] Varlet, **L’Explosion,** 15 Vendemiaire, Year III.

[237] Alain Sergent and Claude Harmel, **Histoire de l’Anarchie** (Le Portulan, 1949),

p. 82. (Republished by Editions Champ Libre in 1984.)

[238] Born into the Italian nobility, Philippe Buonarroti (1761–1837) went to

France in 1793 and was granted French citizenship for his services to the

Revolution. He met Babeuf in prison after Thermidor and became a follower.

Buonarotti’s **History of Babeuf’s ‘Conspiracy of Equals’** (1828) was very

influential. [DB]

[239] Babeuf, **Tribun du peuple,** II, 294, 13 April 1796; Buonarroti, op. cit., pp. 264–6.

[240] Proudhon, **Idee genirale,** p. 195·

[241] Ibid., pp. 177–236.

[242] The decree of 14 Frimaire, Year II (by the revolutionary calendar)

strengthened the power of the central authorities in Paris (especially the

Committee of Public Safety and the Committee of General Security) and

reduced those of local authorities. [MA & DB]

[243] Bakunin, ** ƒuvres,** vol. I, p. 11.

[244] Bakunin, ** ƒuvres,** vol. II, pp. 108 and 232. It was the same for the German

socialists: Rudolf Rocker emphasised (in his **Johann Most,** Berlin, 1924, p. 53)

how Wilhelm Liebknecht, the co-founder with August Bebel of the Social

Democratic Workers’ Party of Germany, was “influenced by the ideas of

the old communist Jacobins.”

[245] Trotski, op. cit., p. 95

[246] Boris Nicolaevsky, **Karl Marx** (Paris: Gallimard, 1937), pp. 146 and 158.

[Nicolaevsky (1887–1966) was a Marxist revolutionary and member of

the Russian Social Democratic Labor Party. A prominent Menshevik intellectual,

he was deported from the USSR in 1922 and settled for a time

in Amsterdam where he became director of the International Institute

for Social History. His **Karl Marx: Man and Fighter** was first published in

German in 1933 and translated into English in 1936. —DB]

[247] Deutscher, **Stalin: A Political Biography** (Oxford University Press, 1967), p. 30.

Cf. also John Maynard, **Russia in Flux: Before October** (New York: Macmillan,

1955), p. 118.

[248] Marx in ch. 6 of **The Holy Family** (1845), available on the Marxists Internet

Archive at [[https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/holyfamily/]];

Engels, **Anti-Duhring,** translation from Marxists Internet Archive:

[[https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1877/anti-duhring/ch23.htm]].

[249] Proudhon, **Idee generale,** pp. 254–323; Bakunin, ** ƒuvres,** vol. II, pp. 108, 228,

296, 361–2; vol. VI, p. 257.

[250] Engels, **Karl Marx devant lesjures de Cologne** (Ed. Costes, 1939), p. 247 and

note; Marx, **Le Dix-Huit Brumaire de Louis-Bonaparte** (Ed. Scleicher freres,

1900), pp. 342–4; Marx, **La Guerre civile,** pp. 16, 46, 49; Engels, **Critique du programme d’Erjurt,** op. cit.

[251] See the note by Engels in the 1885 edition of Marx’s address of the Central

Committee to the Communist League’ where Marx proclaimed that

workers “must not only strive for a single and indivisible German republic,

but also within this republic for the most determined centralisation of

power in the hands of the state authority.” Engels noted that “this passage

is based on a misunderstanding” and that it was now “a well-known fact

that throughout the whole [Great French] revolution ... the whole administration

of the departments, arrondissements and communes consisted

of authorities elected by the respective constituents themselves, and that

these authorities acted with complete freedom within general state laws

[and] that precisely this provincial and local self-government ... became

the most powerful lever of the revolution.” (The **Marx-Engels Reader** [New

York: WW. Norton 0-’ Co, 1978), pp. 509–10) [DB]

[252] Lenin, **State and Revolution** (1917).

[253] Lenine, **Pages choisies** (Bureau d’edition, 1926–7), vol. II, pp. 372–3.

[254] Lenine, ** ƒuvres,** (First edition), vol. XX, p. 640.

[255] Lenin, **Pages choisies,** vol. II, p. 93.

[256] Lenin, **Pages choisies,** vol. II, pp. 115–6.

[257] Lenin, **Pages choisies,** vol. II, p. 296; ** ƒuvres,** vol. XX, p. 640.

[258] Lenin, **Pages choisies,** vol. III, p. 339.

[259] Lenin, ** ƒuvres,** vol. XX, p. 640; **Pages choisies,** vol. I, p. 192.

[260] Lenin, **ƒuvres,** vol. XXI, pp. 213, 227, 232.

[261] Trotsky, **Nos taches politiques,** p. 66.

[262] H.-E. Kaminski, **Bakounine, La vie d’un rĂ©volutionnaire** (Paris: Aubier, 1938), p.

17. [Republished by Editions La Table Ronde, 2003. Hanns-Erich Kaminski

(1899–1963) was a socialist journalist originally from Eastern Prussia. He

published a book about Italian fascism and campaigned for an alliance

of the German Socialist and Communist Parties in the face of the Nazi

threat. Having immigrated to Paris in 1933, he moved closer to anarchosyndicalist

circles and visited Barcelona in 1936. It was this experience

which led to a book about the Spanish Revolution **(Ceux de Barcelone,** 1937)

and the biography ofBakunin. In 1940 he immigrated to Argentina. —DB]

Two Indictments of Communism

Two books that appeared simultaneously, those of Tito’s prisoner

Milovan Djilas and Michel Collinet,[263] have led us to rethink the ideological

foundations of Bolshevism. Even though produced by two

men of different temperaments and origins and using quite divergent

methods, they reach more or less the same conclusions and

present more or less the same qualities, as well as the same defects.

One of their merits is to demonstrate that the Blanquist

concept of the party formulated by Lenin from 1901 contained at

least in germ the totalitarian communism of the Stalinist era. Djilas

and Collinet stress that the ideological monopoly of the leadership

of the party, in this case Lenin himself, claiming to embody the

objective aspirations of society,[264] was in fact an idealist conception

of history that would later result in the total monopolization of the

bureaucratic apparatus over that society.[265]

Where the two writers diverge is on the historical excuse of

“necessity.” Djilas, still incompletely freed of the authoritarian concepts

he was brought up on, believes that the success of the revolution,

which had to defend its very existence and the indispensable

industrialization of the USSR, required the establishment of a

tyranny. Collinet, on the contrary, condemns Lenin for having made

a virtue of necessity, and does not think totalitarian dictatorship

necessarily flowed from the tragic circumstances of the Civil War.[266]

While establishing a direct connection between Leninism and

Stalinism, the two authors stress, correctly, that under no circumstances

can the two regimes be confused and that differences of an

important nature distinguish them, and not simple “nuances,” as

Collinet once lets slip. Forms that were still revolutionary during

Lenin’s time were transformed into reactionary ones under Stalin.

Collinet and Djilas, in the most solid part of their work, provide

both brilliant and implacable descriptions of the privileged “new

class,” of the feudal bureaucracy that seized power in the USSR. For

Collinet today’s Russian society realizes “the most perfect absorption

of society by the state that history has ever seen,” and for

Djilas modern history has never recorded a regime oppressing the

masses in so brutal, inhumane, and illegal a fashion. The methods

it employed constitute “one of the most shameful pages of human

history.” And in a flight of inspiration, he opposes the idealism,

devotion, and spirit of sacrifice of communism of its early days to

the intolerance, corruption, stagnation, and intellectual decadence

of contemporary communism. The analysis of the “new class,” of

the way it exploits the working class and its poor economic management,

is more acute in Djilas than it is in Collinet: Djilas—and

this is the main interest of his book—is a witness who lived the

evil from within.

The two authors are in agreement in denouncing the thirst for

and obsession with power of the communist oligarchs, as well as in

stigmatizing the transformation of Marxism into a dogmatism, into

an essentially sterile and conservative scholasticism.

Both Collinet and Djilas reproach Trotsky, not without reason

and almost in the same terms, for having shown himself incapable,

despite the great merit of his indictment of Stalinism, of defining

sociologically and fully exposing the meaning of contemporary

communism. Why? Because he lacked perspective, according

to Djilas; because he persisted until his death in not questioning

Leninist ideas of organization according to Collinet. There is probably

something of the truth in both of these explanations.

But to my mind both books are marred by a certain number of

errors I would like to point out.

In the first place, they both show a total lack of understanding

of the concept of “permanent revolution.” Collinet makes the

mistake of considering Marx’s famous text of March 1850 an unimportant

accident in the history of Marxist thought, an ephemeral

“Blanquist” crisis from which the author quickly recovered.[267] He

and Djilas draw erroneous conclusions from a correct observation,

which is that the “permanent revolution” is more acutely manifested

in backward countries where it is easier to directly leap over

the capitalist stage from feudalism to socialism. But they are wrong

in concluding that revolutionary Marxism is only applicable to

underdeveloped countries and that it has no chance in highly industrialized

nations. Maintaining, for example, as Djilas does, that in

a country like Germany only reformism can carry the day means

forgetting that from 1918 to 1933 the German proletariat was on the

brink of victory on several occasions and that without the errors

caused by its being a satellite of Moscow, it would probably have

abolished the most advanced capitalism of Europe. In May ’68 did

we not see the working-class revolt in France a hair’s breadth from

overthrowing an advanced capitalism?

What is more, the two books insist insufficiently upon the

relatively progressive aspects of communism in power, although

both mention some of them. Collinet accepts that the national bourgeoisies

have been eliminated, the poor peasants liberated from the

yoke of big landowners and usurers, and that industrialization has

been carried out; Djilas that the collective ownership of the means

of production has allowed for the realization of rapid progress in

certain sectors of the economy. But the Yugoslav contradicts himself

by claiming against all evidence that no great scientific discoveries

have been made under the Soviet regime and that in this domain

the USSR probably trails tsarist Russia. And in the final conclusions

of these two books the progressive aspect is forgotten and the

balance sheet presented is too negative.

In the same way, concerning the possibilities for the evolution

of the post-Stalinist regime the two authors demonstrate a

pessimism that in my eyes is excessive. To be sure, they are right

in maintaining that the Khrushchev regime was that of a conservative

pragmatism lacking in ideas. They are also right in stressing

the relatively narrow limits of de-Stalinization and in being skeptical

about the democratization and the decentralization of the

regime, be it in Russia itself, Yugoslavia, or Poland. But at times

when reading them it seems that “dialectical” evolution is blocked,

that it forbids all hope. And yet, in other passages the two authors

admit that the break with the Stalinist past is profound, that something

has truly changed, that the domination of the “new class” has

been shaken, that liberation is on the march, and that the release

of popular discontent is irreversible. But they conclude that the

outcome will be irremediable ruin and the collapse of “communism”

without indicating with what the “monster” will be replaced.

An ambiguity all the more worrisome in that one senses in

their analysis a singular indulgence towards Western bourgeois

democracy, considered the sole alternative to “communist tyranny.”

It seems that for both Collinet and Djilas the Russian regime

alone is responsible for the Cold War and the division of the world

into two blocs. The capitalist and imperialist character of the

Western democracies is blurred. For Collinet financial capitalism

is a “mythical monster,” and even Djilas who has spent time in the

U.S., contests the idea that the Western governments are controlled

by a handful of monopolists. Collinet claims with a straight face

that there exist Western democracies “untainted by any vestiges

of imperialism,” and Djilas that the United States tend towards an

increasingly statist regime. The dangers that American big business

and its claim to world leadership present are conjured away.

Collinet goes even further when he attacks the Bandung Accords

which, according to him, are “nothing but a weapon against the

Western democracies,” and when he presents Mossadegh and Nasser

as instruments in the service of Russian expansionism.[268] The impact

of the indictment of Stalinist totalitarianism and the executioners

of the Hungarian people is considerably weakened by the blank

check issued the aggressors of Suez and Western colonialism.

Why do Collinet and Djilas both go off the rails at the end of

their analysis? In my opinion the real reason for their error is their

inability to find a third way outside of those of Stalinism and bourgeois

democracy. And the source of this inability is the refusal to

rally to libertarian Marxist ideas.

They make only vague and insufficient allusions to the great

conflict between authoritarian socialism and anarchist socialism

that so deeply divided the working-class movement of the nineteenth

century. They seem to be ignorant of the fact that the totalitarian

communism they denounce was condemned a century before

them in prophetic terms by Proudhon and Bakunin. For Collinet and

even more for Djilas authority directly exercised by the proletariat

in the absence of any state coercion is an “illusion” and a “utopia.”

And yet the two authors occasionally contradict themselves and

express unconscious libertarian aspirations. Collinet lets slip that

“the logic of democracy was not the Jacobin state, even animated

by good intentions, but the state, withering away and transferring

its functions to the entire social body.” And Djilas, after having

denounced the Jacobin-style intolerance of contemporary communists,

exalts “man’s imperishable aspiration for freedom,” and

announces as imminent the moment when industrialization will

render communism “superfluous.” Analyzing the demands of the

underground opposition currently maturing in the USSR, Collinet—who

is more precise than Djilas on this matter although, alas, he

does not go as far as he should—says that “they do not appear to

be demanding Western parliamentarism; rather their essence is

the independence of the people and their economic and cultural

organizations in relation to the party and state apparatuses.”

If Collinet and Djilas had more clearly deduced these libertarian

conclusions from their analyses they would have avoided

getting bogged down, due to their failure to clearly glimpse a third

way, in a pro-Western Menshevism that deprives their argument

of much of its force and persuasive power. None of this, of course,

justifies the prison sentence inflicted on the Yugoslav, which does

no honor to Tito’s regime.

The lesson: a revolutionary socialist who frees himself of

Marxist-Leninist Jacobinism is in great danger of falling into petitbourgeois

and counter-revolutionary ideologies. There is only one

healthy and certain way to “de-Jacobinize,” to distance oneself

from authoritarian socialism, and that is to go over to libertarian

Marxism, the only reliable value of our time, the only socialism that

has remained young, the only authentic socialism.

<right>

[1957, **in Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire**]

</right>

[263] Milovan Djilas, **The New Class: An Analysis of the Communist System** (Thames

& Hudson, 1957); Michel Collinet, **Du Bolchevisme: evolution et variations du Mandsmeteninisme** (Le Livre Contemporain, 1957). [Djilas, a former

Yugoslav Partisan and Communist leader and at one point touted to

succeed Tito as president, became increasingly critical of the Yugoslavian

system and was imprisoned in 1956. **The New Class** had been finished

before his arrest and was published in the USA in 1957, which led to

his being sentenced to a further seven years’ imprisonment. Eventually

released in 1966, he remained a dissident in Belgrade until his death in

1995. Collinet (1904–1977) was also a former Communist turned dissident,

and then became a member of the Socialist Party’s Revolutionary Left

faction and, later, the Workers’ and Peasants’ Socialist Party alongside

Guérin. He was active in the Resistance during the Second World War,

and remained a member of the Socialist Party after the Liberation. —DB]

[264] It is regrettable that neither Collinet nor Djilas quote the remarkable

pages (pp. 157, 205) that, well before them, Valine, in his **Revolution inconnue,**

dedicated to the Bolsheviks’ claim to infallibility.

[265] Nevertheless, Collinet and Djilas both exaggerate Lenin’s dogmatic rigidity

and underestimate his surprising intellectual flexibility and his ability

to revise his positions in light of facts, aptitudes that on every occasion

disconcerted his dull lieutenants and in a large measure compensated for

the failing for which he is criticized.

[266] Collinet here joins Valine without stating so (op. cit., pp. 180–2).

[267] **Address of the Central Committee to the Communist League,** London, March

1850. [DB]

[268] The Bandung Conference of 1955 brought together twenty-nine Asian and

African countries, mostly former colonies, with the aim of promoting economic

and cultural cooperation and opposing colonialism and neo-colonialism.

Mohammad Mosaddegh was the democratically elected prime

minister of Iran who was removed from power in a coup organised by

British and US intelligence agencies in 1953. Gamal Abdel Nasser led the

overthrow of the Egyptian monarchy in 1952 and nationalized the Suez

Canal in 1956, which led to invasion by Britain, France, and Israel. [DB]

May, a Continuity, a Renewal

With the exception of that by Cohn-Bendit, what is striking about

some of the countless books written a tad too hastily about May

’68 is the relative absence of references or insufficient references to

the revolutionary past.[269] The books in which this omission can be

found were written in general by young people. The young were

the initiators of May and feel a legitimate pride in it. Through May,

many discovered the Revolution, a Revolution that not all of them

knew beforehand from books, or only knew it poorly due to the

falsified versions that had been presented to them. From which a

strange point of view develops which leads them to believe that in

France everything began with May ’68, that May was an absolutely

original creation without any direct ties to French working-class

and revolutionary traditions.

Claude Lefort displayed an illusion of this kind when in an

article in **Le Monde,**[270] he boldly asserted that “with the May movement

... something new is being announced ... an opposition

that does not yet know what to call itself, but which challenges the

power structure in such a way that it cannot be confused with the

movements of the past.”

It is true that Lefort in this case was carried away by the ardor

of a polemic against the various Trotskyist groups he reproaches,

not without reason, with seeking to recuperate and monopolize the

May movement at the risk of fossilizing it. But in making his case

he exaggeratedly tips the balance in a direction opposite to that of

the Trotskyist tradition, and I do not share his opinion that May is

so radically different from the movements of the past.

To be sure, what is new, what is absolutely novel in May is that

we witnessed the first act of an extended social revolution whose

detonator was constituted not by workers, as in the past, but for

the first time by students. Nevertheless, this peculiarity of May only

concerns the first two weeks of the famous month, when it was the

students who built the barricades and held the streets. The second

phase of the “May revolution,” the far more important one, that

which more profoundly shook the political power and the bosses,

which gave rise to the alarm of the property-owning class and the

flight of their capital, was a revolution of the working class in the

style and at the level of the great social crises of the past.

One wonders whether the reason certain people tend to overestimate

the originality of the May revolution is that it arose during

a historical stage when the Revolution had been emptied of all

content in France; when it had been betrayed, perverted, erased

from the map by two powerful political steam-rollers, two sterilizers

of critical thinking: Stalinism and Gaullism. If May looked

boldly anti-establishment, if it seemed to bring into question all

established values and authorities as Claude Lefort seems to think,

is it not because Stalinism for the last forty years and Gaullism

for the past ten had caused the French to lose the habit of radical

contestation, of libertarian protest? A habit, a taste, a tradition that

had been theirs for almost 150 years.

Let us take the time to travel into our past and rediscover the

countless May ‘68s of our national and social history.

For my part, scratching and digging behind the misleading

façade constructed by bourgeois historians, I attempted to revive

the mass movement of the revolution of 1793, extraordinary and

unbelievable because it occurred in a France still more or less

plunged in the darkness of absolutism, aristocracy, and clericalism.

I followed step by step the bold incursions in the direction of the

revolutions of the future dared by the sans-culotte vanguard, so far

in advance of its time: the practice of direct democracy, the omnipotence

of the power of the street. I compared, and how could one

not, the Enragés of 1793 and those of 1968 by stressing this phrase

of Jacque Roux, precursor of Daniel Cohn-Bendit: “Only the young

are capable of the degree of ardor necessary to make a revolution.”

When I had to describe the burst of vitality, of good sense, of

good humor, more good-natured than cruel, that cast the people

into the great adventure of de-Christianization in 1793 and led to the

overturning of idols, I gave the chapter dedicated to this subject an

expression borrowed from May ’68: “All power to the imagination.”

For what we have here is the same creative genius.

All the social revolutions in France that followed that of 1793

and were born of its traditions were, like their predecessor, an exuberant

festival of recovered freedom and an enormous collective

release.

To a certain extent that was the case with the general strike in

Paris in 1840, at the very moment when the idea of socialism was

born in people’s minds. This general strike is too little known, for

here, too, the bourgeois historians, with the exception of Octave

Festy, were no doubt superficial and negligent by design.

And what should we say about the tumultuous, fertile revolution

of 1848, which bred so many ideas that emerged over several

months from a popular crucible in turmoil, when so many public

meetings and vast assemblies of the people where held, when so

many newspapers, pamphlets, and tracts were born.

The libertarian explosion that was the Commune of 1871, the

direct heir of that of 1793, was of the same kind. It is often hidden

from us, or relegated to second place, by authors who have their

eyes almost exclusively fixed on its civil war aspects. But during the

short span of time when revolutionary Paris was able to blossom

during a relative respite before it was subjected to the fatal aggression

of the Versaillais, what a flowering, what an overflowing of

joy and liberty! Armand Gatti, in the beautiful text he wrote in

May ’68 to comment on the projection of slides on the walls, perfectly

grasped the parallels between “May ’68” and the Commune.[271]

Likewise, it would be giving a one-sided vision of the May revolution

to reduce it to a series of street battles and to minimize the

general contestation and the direct democracy. The confrontation

with the CRS was the price that had to be paid to open the festival

of freedom at the Sorbonne.[272]

The same libertarian impulse can be found in the great strike

that followed the end of World War I in France just fifty years ago,

combined with the mutinies of French sailors refusing to go to

war with the Russian soviets. Do people know that on June 8, 1919,

Toulon was the theater of a genuine insurrection, where sailors,

soldiers, and workers fought shoulder to shoulder in the streets,

stones in hand, against the gendarmes?[273]

For my part, I was fortunate enough, along with millions of

other militants, to live through June ’36, the immediate precursor to

the workers’ May ’68. And along with all of them I can testify that

France, paralyzed by the general strike and the factory occupations,

and with the power of the masses master of the country, was on a

par with the workers’ uprising we lived through a year ago. Like

the preceding explosions, the “revolution” of 1936 was an impressive

festival of popular joy. Parades of millions of demonstrators filled

the streets, just as on May 13, 1968. And in the factories, of which

the workers had become masters, we participated in an immense

popular festival, an enormous Bastille Day, one far more spontaneous

than the one celebrated every year by the bourgeois republican

tradition.[274]

Having participated in many debates in the lecture halls of the

occupied university buildings in May, I can attest to the fact that

the passionate and vibrant crowds that squeezed into them, far

from turning their backs on the revolutionary past, were eager to

find a continuity in it, to quench their thirst at that eternal spring

of libertarian energy, which many of them had just discovered.

The rebirth of anarchism during May ’68 might have seemed

surprising. But looked at more closely, the French working class,

and by extension the French people, has always retained an anarchist—or rather anarcho-syndicalist—substratum. Contrary to

appearances, the CGT’s tradition of class struggle and direct action

which flourished from 1895 to 1914 never died. Many militants, and

even leaders, who have since become Stalinist “Communists,” have

not completely succeeded in killing within themselves a repressed

nostalgia for anarcho-syndicalism. The union split of 1921, the creation

of the CGTU and then its Bolshevization did not cause the

old syndicalist ferment to vanish from the consciousness of the

workers.[275]

The general strikes of 1936 and 1968, both of which were accompanied

by a wave of occupations, were spontaneous mass mobilizations

of the rank and file, and were authentically anarcho-syndicalist.

Despite the maneuvers of counter-revolutionary bureaucrats

like Georges SĂ©guy,[276] the CGT of today in large measure remains,

deep in its heart, anarcho-syndicalist, and that is what infuriates

the aforementioned individual.

Finally, if anarchism was rediscovered in May, or rather entered

into symbiosis with Marxism, there is no need to go far to find the

cause: it is quite simply because at the moment that it blooms every

social revolution can only be libertarian.

Only afterwards do the recuperators, the leaders who lay their

paws on the Revolution, disfigure it and stifle it.

The revolution of May was aware of this danger. Up till now it

has not succumbed. But beware!

<right>

[1969, in **Pour un Marxisme libertaire**]

</right>

[269] **Le Gauchisme, remede a la maladie senile du communisme** (Paris: Seuil, 1969).

[In fact, the book-published in English as **Obsolete Communism: The Left-Wing Alternative** (Oakland: AK Press, 2001)-was coauthored by Daniel and

his elder brother Gabriel. Daniel was associated with the anarchist group

Noir et Rouge and was extremely critical of the Anarchist Federation;

he became the figurehead of the revolutionary students’ movement of

May 1968. Gabriel was a member of the French Communist Party, but

left it in 1956 and was associated with the Socialisme ou Barbarie group

around Cornelius Castoriadis, as well as with other libertarian Marxist

networks. DB]

[270] **Le Monde,** April 5, 1969.

[271] This seems to refer to Gatti’s experimental play **Les 13 soleils de la rue St. Blaise,** produced by the Theatre de l‘Est Parisien. The award-winning poet,

dramatist, and filmmaker Annand Gatti was born in 1924, the son of an

Italian anarchist, and would take part in the armed resistance to Nazism.

After the war he worked as a journalist for many years before he produced

his first literary work and directed his first film. [DB]

[272] The CRS (Compagnies Republicaine de Securite) are the French riot police,

created in 1944. [DB]

[273] Cf. ‘Les Mutineries de la mer Noire’, **Les Cahiers de Mai** (July 1969).

[274] Commonly known in the English-speaking world as Bastille Day, 14 July

has been the official French national celebration day since 1880, and

marks not only the popular storming of the Bastille fortress, a symbol of

absolutist monarchism, on 14 July 1789, but also the ‘Festival of Federation’

of 14 July 1790, which was organized by the supporters of constitutional

monarchy and was intended to promote national unity in order to prevent

any rolling back of constitutional changes and any further social conflict

leading to more radical reforms. [DB]

[275] The Confederation Generale du Travail (General Labour Confederation)

was the first national trade union organisation in France, and before the

First World War was strongly influenced by anarchism, leading to the

militant practice dubbed ‘revolutionary syndicalism’. Increasingly moderate

during and after the Great War, the movement split in the 1920s, with

a Communist-dominated minority creating the CGTU (Unitary CGT). [DB]

[276] Georges Seguy had been a Communist Party (PCF) member since the 1940s

and was general secretary of the CGT (which since the Liberation of 1945

had been dominated by the PCF) from 1967 to 1982. [DB]

Self-Management in Revolutionary Spain, 1936–1937

Self-management in revolutionary Spain is relatively little known.

Even within the Republican camp it was more or less passed over

in silence or disparaged. The horrible civil war submerged it, and

still submerges it today in people’s memories. It is not mentioned

at all in the film **To Die in Madrid**.[277] And yet, it was perhaps the most

positive legacy of the Spanish Revolution: the attempt at an original

form of socialist economy.

In the wake of the revolution of July 19, 1936, the swift popular

response to the Francoist coup d’état, many agricultural estates

and factories had been abandoned by their owners. Agricultural

day laborers were the first to decide to continue cultivating the

land. Their social consciousness seems to have been even higher

than that of the urban workers. They spontaneously organized

themselves into collectives. In August a union conference was held

in Barcelona representing several hundred thousand agricultural

workers and small farmers. The legal blessing only occurred shortly

afterwards: on October 7, 1936, the central Republican government

nationalized the lands of “persons involved in the fascist rebellion.”

The agricultural collectives gave themselves dual management,

both union and communal, with the communalist spirit predominating.

At general assemblies peasants elected a management committee

of eleven members in each village. Aside from the secretary,

all of the members continued to work with their hands. Labor was

mandatory for all healthy men between eighteen and sixty. The

peasants were divided into groups of ten or more, with a delegate

at their head. Each group was assigned a zone of cultivation or a

function in accordance with the age of its members and the nature

of the task. Every evening the management committee received

the delegates of the groups. They frequently invited the residents

to a general assembly of the neighborhood for an account of their

activity.

Everything was held in common, except personal savings, and

livestock and fowl destined for family consumption. The artisans,

hairdressers, and cobblers were grouped in collectives. The sheep

of the community, for example, were distributed in groups of three

to four hundred, entrusted to two shepherds and methodically distributed

across the mountain.

Wage labor and, partially at least, money were abolished. Each

worker or family received in remuneration for his labor a bond

denominated in pesetas that could only be exchanged for consumer

goods in communal stores, often located in churches or their out-buildings.

The unused sum was credited to the individual’s reserve

account. It was possible to withdraw pocket money from this sum

in limited amounts. Rent, electricity, medical care, pharmaceutical

products, and old age assistance were free, as was school, which was

often located in a former convent and mandatory for all children

below fourteen, for whom manual labor was prohibited.

Membership in the collective was voluntary. No pressure was

exercised on small landowners. They could, if they wished, participate

in common tasks and place their products in the communal

stores. They were admitted to general assemblies, benefiting from

most of the advantages of the community. They were only prevented

from owning more land than they could cultivate and one condition

was posed: that their person or property not disturb the collective

order. In most socialized villages the number of individuals who

stood on their own, peasants or merchants, grew ever smaller.

The communal collectives were united in cantonal federations,

above which were provincial federations. The land of a cantonal federation

formed one holding, without boundary markings. Solidarity

between villages was pushed to the extreme. Compensation funds

allowed for the assisting of the least favored collectives.

From One Province to Another

Rural socialization varied in importance from one province to

another. In Catalonia, a land of small and mid-sized property, where

farmers had strong individualist traditions, it was reduced to a few

tiny islands, the peasant union confederation wisely preferring to

first convince landowners by the exemplary success of a few pilot

collectives.

On the other hand, in Aragon more than three quarters of the

lands were socialized. The passage of a Catalan militia, the famous

Durruti Column, en route for the north to fight the Francoists, and the

subsequent creation of a revolutionary power issued from the rank

and file, the only one of its kind in Republican Spain, stimulated the

creative initiative of the agricultural workers. Around 450 collectives

were formed, bringing together 600,000 members. In the province of

Levante (its capital Valencia), the richest in Spain, some 600 collectives

arose. They took in 43 percent of all localities, 50 percent of citrus

production and 70 percent of its distribution. In Castile 300 collectives

were formed with 100,000 members on the initiative of 1,000 volunteers

sent as experts in self-management by Levante. Socialization

also touched Extremadura and a portion of AndalucĂ­a. There were a

few attempts at it in Asturias, but they were quickly repressed.

It should be noted that this socialism from the base was not, as

some believe, the work of the anarchists alone. According to Gustave

Leval’s testimony, those engaged in self-management were often

“anarchists without knowing it.”[278] Among the latter provinces enumerated

above, it was the socialist, Catholic, and in Asturias even

Communist peasants who took the initiative in self-management.

When it was not sabotaged by its enemies or hindered by the

war, agricultural self-management was an unquestionable success.

The land was united into one holding and cultivated over great

expanses according to a general plan and the directives of agronomists.

Small landowners integrated their plots with those of the

community. Socialization demonstrated its superiority both over

large absentee landholdings, which left a part of the land unplanted,

and over smallholdings, cultivated with the use of rudimentary

techniques, inadequate seeding, and without fertilizer. Production

increased by 30–50 percent. The amount of cultivated land

increased, working methods were improved, and human, animal,

and mechanical energy used more rationally. Farming was diversified,

irrigation developed, the countryside partially reforested, nurseries

opened, pigsties constructed, rural technical schools created,

pilot farms set up, livestock selected and increased, and auxiliary

industries set in motion, etc.

In Levante, the initiatives taken for the marketing of agricultural

goods deserve mention. The war having caused a temporary

closing of foreign markets and of the part of the internal market

controlled by Franco, the oranges were dried; and wherever a greater

quantity than previously was obtained, essence was extracted from

the peel and orange honey, orange wine, medical alcohol, and pulp

for the saving of blood from slaughterhouses for use to feed fowl was

produced. Factories concentrated orange juice. When the peasant

federation succeeded in reestablishing relations with French ports it

ensured the marketing of agricultural goods through its warehouses,

its trucks, its cargos, and its sales outlets in France.

These successes were due, for the most part, to the people’s initiative

and intelligence. Though a majority were illiterate, the peasants

demonstrated a socialist consciousness, practical common sense, and

a spirit of solidarity and sacrifice that inspired admiration in foreign

visitors. Fenner Brockway of the Independent Labour Party, after a

visit to the collective of Segorbe, testified to this: “The mood of the

peasants, their enthusiasm, the way in which they made their contributions

to the common effort, their pride in it, all of this is admirable.”

The Sabotage of Self-management

However, there was no lack of difficulties. Credit and foreign

commerce, by the will of the bourgeois Republican government,

remained in the hands of the private sector. To be sure, the state

controlled the banks, but it avoided putting them at the service of

self-management. Lacking circulating funds, many collectives lived

on what they had seized at the time of the July 1936 revolution.

Afterwards they had to resort to makeshift methods, like seizing

jewelry and precious objects belonging to the churches, convents,

Francoists, etc. Self-management also suffered from a lack of agricultural

machinery and, to a lesser degree, a lack of technical cadres.

But the most serious obstacle was the hostility, at first hidden

and then open, of the various political general staffs of Republican

Spain. Even a party of the Far Left such as the Workers’ Party of

Marxist Unification (POUM) was not always well disposed towards

the collectives.[279] This authentically popular movement, the herald

of a new order, spontaneous and improvised, and jealous of its

autonomy, offended the machine of the Republican state as much

as it did private capitalism. It united against it both the property-owning

class and the apparatuses of the parties of the Left in power.

Self-management was accused of breaking the “unity of the front”

between the working class and the petit bourgeoisie and thus of

playing into the hands of the Francoist enemy. Which did not

prevent the detractors from refusing weapons to the revolutionary

vanguard, reduced, in Aragon, to confronting the fascist machineguns

barehanded, and then to be attacked for “inertia.”

On the radio the new Catalonian minister of the economy,

Comorera, a Stalinist, incited peasants not to join the collectives,

suggested to the small landowners that they combat them, and

at the same time took resupplying from the hands of the workers’

unions and favored private commerce. Thus encouraged from above,

the dark forces of reaction increasingly sabotaged the experiment

in self-management.

In the end, the government coalition, after the crushing of the

“Barcelona Commune” in May 1937 and the outlawing of the POUM,

did not hesitate to liquidate agricultural self-management by any

means necessary. A decree dated August 10, 1937, pronounced the

dissolution of the revolutionary authority in Aragon on the pretext

that it “remained outside the centralizing current.” One of its main

inspirations, Joaquin Ascaso, was indicted for “sale of jewelry” destined,

in reality, for procuring funds for the collectives. Immediately

afterwards, the nth Division of Commandant Lister (a Stalinist),

supported by tanks, went into action against the collectives. The

leaders were arrested, their offices occupied and then shut down,

the management committees dissolved, the communal stores

robbed, the furniture smashed, and the flocks dispersed. Around

30 percent of the collectives of Aragon were completely destroyed.

In Levante, in Castile, in the provinces of Huesca and Teruel,

armed attacks of the same kind were perpetrated—by Republicans—against

agricultural self-management. It survived—barely—in

certain regions that had not yet fallen into the hands of the

Francoists, notably in Levante.

Industrial Self-management

In Catalonia, the most industrialized region of Spain, self-management

also demonstrated its worth in industry. Workers whose employers

had fled spontaneously set to keeping their factories working. In

October 1936 a union congress was held in Barcelona representing

600,000 workers with the object of socializing industry. The workers’

initiative was ratified by a decree of the Generalitat, the Catalan government,

on October 24, 1936. Two sectors were created, one socialist,

the other private. The socialized factories were those with more than

a hundred workers (those with between fifty and a hundred could be

socialized at the request of three quarters of the workers), those whose

owners had been declared “seditious” by a popular tribunal or who

had abandoned its running, and finally those whose importance to

the national economy justified their being removed from the private

sector (in fact, a number of enterprises in debt were socialized).

The socialized factories were led by a management committee

with between five and thirteen members, representing the various

services, elected by the workers in a general assembly, with a two-year

term, half of them to be renewed every year. The committee

selected a director to whom it delegated all or part of its powers. In

the key factories the selection of the director had to be approved by

the regulatory body. In addition, a government inspector was placed

on every management committee.

The management committee could be revoked either by the

general assembly or by a general council of the branch of industry

(composed of four representatives of the management committees,

eight from the workers’ unions, and four technicians named by the

regulatory body). This general council planned the work and determined

the distribution of profits. Its decisions were legally binding.

In those enterprises that remained in private hands, an elected

workers’ committee controlled the working conditions “in close

collaboration with the employer.”

The decree of October 24, 1936, was a compromise between the

aspiration for autonomous management and the tendency towards

state oversight and planning, as well as a transition between capitalism

and socialism. It was written by an anarchist minister and

accepted by the CNT (National Confederation of Labor), the anarchist

union, because the anarcho-syndicalists participated in the

Catalan government.

In practice, despite the considerable powers granted the general

councils of the branches of industry, worker self-management risked

leading to a selfish particularism, each production unit concerned

only about its own interests. This was remedied by the creation of

a central equalization fund, allowing for the equitable distribution

of resources. In this way the surplus of the Barcelona bus company

was transferred to the less profitable tram company.

Exchanges occurred between industrial and peasant collectives,

the former exchanging underwear or clothing for the olive

oil of the latter.

In the suburbs of Barcelona, in the commune of Hospitalitet,

on whose borders farmers were involved in the planting of crops,

the agricultural and industrial (metals, textile, etc.) self-managed

organizations joined together in one communal authority elected

by the people, which ensured the provisioning of the city.

Outside of Catalonia, notably in Levante, industrial self-management

was experimented with in a few locations. This was the

case in Alcoy, near Alicante, where 20,000 textile workers and steel workers

managed the socialized factories and created consumer

cooperatives, as well as in ClastellĂłn de la Plana, where the steel

factories were integrated into larger units under the impetus of a

technical commission in daily contact with each of its management

committees.

But like agricultural self-management, industrial self-management

faced the hostility of the administrative bureaucracy,

the authoritarian socialists, and the Communists. The central

Republican government refused it any credits, even when the

Catalan minister of the economy, the anarchist Fabregas, offered

the billions on deposit in the savings banks as a guarantee for

the advances to self-management. When he was replaced in 1937

by Comorera the latter deprived the self-managed factories of

the primary material they lavished on the private sector. It also

neglected to ensure the deliveries ordered by the Catalan administration

to the socialized enterprises.

Industrial Self-management Dismantled

Later, the central government used the pretext of the needs of

national defense to seize control of the war industries. By a decree of

August 23, 1937, it suspended the application of the Catalan socialization

decree of October 1936 in the steel and mining industries,

said to be “contrary to the spirit of the constitution.” The former

supervisors and the directors removed under self-management or,

more precisely, who had not wanted to accept posts as technicians

in self-managed enterprises, resumed their posts, with revenge in

their hearts.

Catalan industrial self-management nevertheless survived in

other branches until the crushing of Republican Spain in 1939. But

industry having lost its main outlets and lacking in primary materials

the factories that did not work for national defense were only

able to operate with severely reduced staff and hours.

In short, Spanish self-management, hardly born, was restrained

within the strict framework of a war fought with classic military

methods in the name (or under cover) of which the republic clipped

the wings of its vanguard and compromised with internal reaction.

Despite the unfavorable conditions under which it took place

and the brevity of its existence, which prohibits an evaluation and

accounting of its results, the experiment opened new perspectives

for socialism, for an authentic socialism, animated from the bottom

up, the direct emanation of the workers of the country and the

cities.[280]

<right>

[1984, in **À la recherche d’un communisme libertaire**]

</right>

[277] A 1962 documentary by Frédéric Rossif. English-language films in which

the collectivizations do feature include Ken Loach’s **Land and Freedom**

(1995); see also Mark Littlewood, **Ethel MacDonald: An Anarchist’s Story**

(2007), [[http://www.spanishcivilwarfilm.com]]. [DB]

[278] Gaston Leval, **Espagne libertaire 36–39** (Editions du Cercle/Editions de la

Tete de feuilles, 1971). [Published in English as **Collectives in the Spanish Revolution** (London: Freedom Press, 1975) —DB]

[279] The POUM was formed by Andreu Nin and Joaquin Maurin in 1935 and

was affiliated internationally to the so-called London Bureau alongside

the ILP (Independent Labour Party) in Britain and the PSOP (Workers’

and Peasants’ Socialist Party) in France (of which GuĂ©rin was a prominent

member at the time). [DB]

[280] See Sam Dolgoff, **Anarchist Collectives: Workers’ Self-management in the Spanish Revolution, 1936–39** (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1975); Frank Mintz,

<em>Anarchism and Workers’ Self-management in Revolutionary Spain</em> (Oakland: AK

Press, 2012). [DB]

Libertarian Communism, the Only Real Communism

It is time to outline a synthesis of all my work and attempt to

sketch a program, at the risk of seeing myself accused of engaging

in “metapolitics.”

It would be futile to engage in a sort of replastering of an

edifice of cracked and worm-eaten socialist doctrines, to struggle

to patch together some of the surviving solid fragments of traditional

Marxism and anarchism, to indulge in Marxist or Bakuninist

scholarship, to seek to trace, merely on paper, tortuous connections.

If in this book we have often turned to the past it was of course

not, as the reader will have understood, to dwell on it self-indulgently.

To learn from it, to draw from it, yes, for previous experience

is rich in teachings, but with an eye to the future.

The libertarian communism of our time, which blossomed in

the French May ’68, goes far beyond communism and anarchism.

Calling oneself a libertarian communist today does not mean

looking backwards, but rather drafting a sketch of the future.

Libertarian communists are not exegetes, they are militants. They

understand that it is incumbent upon them to change the future,

no more, no less. History has backed them against the wall. The

hour of the socialist revolution has rung everywhere. Like the moon

landing, it has entered the realm of the immediate and the possible.

The precise definition of the forms of a socialist society no longer

belong to the realm of utopia. The only people lacking in realism

are those who close their eyes to these truths.

What will be the guiding lines that we are going to follow to

accomplish the Revolution which, as Gracchus Babeuf said, will be

the final one?

To start with, before going into action, libertarian communists

assess the exact nature of objective conditions; they attempt

to evaluate accurately the balance of power in every situation.

Here the method elaborated by Karl Marx and which has not aged,

namely historical and dialectical materialism, remains the surest

of compasses, an inexhaustible mine of models and guideposts.

On condition, however, that it be treated as Marx did himself, that

is, without doctrinal rigidity, and that it avoid mechanistic inflexibility;

on condition that, sheltering beneath its wing, one does

not eternally invent poor pretexts and pseudo-objective reasons to

excuse oneself from pushing things to the limit, to sow confusion,

to miss the revolutionary opportunity every time it presents itself.

Libertarian communism is a communism that rejects determinism

and fatalism, which gives space to individual will, intuition,

imagination, the rapidity of reflexes, the profound instinct of the

large masses, who are wiser at moments of crisis than the reasonings

of the “elite,” who believe in the element of surprise and provocation,

in the value of audacity, who do not allow themselves to

be encumbered and paralyzed by a weighty, supposedly “scientific”

ideological apparatus, who do not prevaricate or bluff, who avoid

both adventurism and fear of the unknown.

Libertarian communists have learned from experience how

to set about things: they hold in contempt the impotent shambles

of disorganization as much as the bureaucratic ball and chain of

over-organization.

Libertarian communists, faithful on this point to both Marx

and Bakunin, reject the fetishism of the single, monolithic, and

totalitarian party, just as they avoid the traps of a fraudulent and

demobilizing electoralism.

Libertarian communists are, in their essence, internationalists.

They consider the global struggles of the exploited as a whole. But

they nonetheless take into account the specificity and the original

forms of socialism in each country. They only conceive internationalism

to be proletarian if it is inspired from the bottom up, on a level

of complete equality, without any form of subordination to a “big

brother” who thinks himself stronger and cleverer.

Libertarian communists never sacrifice the revolutionary struggle

to the diplomatic imperatives of the so-called socialist empires and, like

Che Guevara, do not hesitate to send them both packing if their aberrant

fratricidal quarrels cause mortal harm to the cause of universal socialism.

When the moment of the revolutionary test of strength arrives,

libertarian communists will attack at both the center and the periphery,

in the political and administrative fields as well as the economic.

On the one hand, they will deal mercilessly, with all their might,

and if necessary by means of armed struggle, with the bourgeois

state and the entire complex machinery of power, be it at the level

of the capital, the regions, the departments, or the municipalities;

they will never make the mistake, on the pretext of “apoliticism,” of

neglecting, underestimating, or abstaining from dismantling the

citadels, the political centers, from which the enemy’s resistance

is directed. But at the same time, combining the economic and

political struggles, they will at their workplaces take control of all

posts held by the bosses and wrest the means of production from

those who monopolize them, in order to hand them over to their

real, rightful owners: the self-managing workers and technicians.

Once that revolution is victoriously and completely accomplished,

libertarian communists do not smash the state in order to

reestablish it in another even more oppressive form through the

colossal expansion of its capacities. Rather, they want the transmission

of all power to a confederation of federations, that is, to a

confederation of communes, themselves federated in regions, a confederation

of revolutionary workers’ unions preexisting the revolution

or, failing that, the confederation of workers’ councils born of

the revolution, which does not exclude the eventuality of a merger

of the latter two. Elected for a short mandate and not eligible for

reelection, the delegates to these various bodies are controllable and

revocable at all times.

Libertarian communists shun any particularist atomization

into small units, communes, and workers’ councils, and aspire to a

federalist coordination, one which is both close-knit and freely consented

to. Rejecting bureaucratic and authoritarian planning, they

believe in the need for coherent and democratic planning, inspired

from the bottom up.

Because they are of their time, libertarian communists want to

wrest the media, automation, and computers from the maleficent

monopolists and place them at the service of liberation.

Hardened authoritarians and sceptics maintain that the

imperatives of contemporary technology are incompatible with

a libertarian communist society. On the contrary, the libertarian

communists intend to unleash a new technological revolution, this

time oriented towards both higher productivity and a shorter work

day, towards decentralization, decongestion, de-bureaucratization,

dis-alienation, and a return to nature. They condemn the degrading

mentality of the so-called consumer society while preparing to raise

consumption to its highest level ever.

Libertarian communists carry out this gigantic overturning at

the price of the least possible disorder, neither too slowly nor too

soon. They know that a wave of the magic wand cannot instantly

effect the most profound social transformation of all time. They

do not lose sight of the fact that with the hominid distorted by

millennia of oppression, obscurantism, and egoism, time will be

needed to form a socialist man or socialist woman. They agree to

transitions while refusing to see them perpetuated. And so it is that

while assigning as the ultimate goal, to be reached by stages, the

withering away of competition, the free provision of public and

social services, the disappearance of money, and the distribution

of abundance according to the needs of each; that while aiming at

association within self-management of agriculturalists and artisans,

at the cooperative reorganization of commerce, it is not their plan

to abolish overnight competition and the laws of the marketplace,

remuneration according to labor accomplished, small farming, and

artisanal and commercial property.

They do not think superfluous the temporary assistance of

active minorities who are more educated and conscious, whatever

name they might give themselves, minorities whose contribution

is unavoidable in bringing the rearguard to full socialist maturity,

but who will not stay on stage one day longer than necessary and

will merge as quickly as possible into the egalitarian association

of producers.

The libertarian communists do not offer us yet another “groupuscule.”

For them the guiding lines that we have just laid out coincide

with the basic class instinct of the working class.

In my opinion—and long, arduous, and painful experience

has demonstrated this—apart from libertarian communism there

is no real communism.

<right>

[1969, in **Pour un Marxisme libertaire**]

</right>

Appendices

Appendix I:

The Libertarian Communist Platform of 1971[281]

humanity, which is a succession of exploitative societies. In every

era thinkers have arrived at an idea that calls their society into

question. But it was with the advent of modern capitalist society

that the division of society into two fundamental, antagonistic

classes clearly appeared, and it is through class struggle, the

motor of the evolution of capitalist society, that the road was

constructed that leads from revolt to the achieving of revolutionary

consciousness.

Today, because it has changed form, class struggle is sometimes

denied by those who insist on either the bourgeoisification

and integration of the working class, or the birth of a new working

class that will supposedly insert itself naturally, as it were, into

the decision-making centers of capitalist society. In fact, the old

social strata are disappearing, the polarization into two fundamental

classes is growing more acute, and there is always some spot in

the world where the class war is being reignited.

Whatever the ideological forms it assumes, the capitalist mode

of production is, globally, a unity. Whether it be in the form which,

based originally on “liberalism,” is headed towards state monopoly

capitalism, or that of state bureaucratic capitalism, capitalism

cannot but increase the exploitation of labor in order to attempt to

escape the mortal crisis threatening it. Massacres, the general collapse

of living conditions, as well as the exploitation and alienation

peculiar to this or that human group (women, the young, racial or

sexual minorities, etc.) are manifestations that cannot be separated

from the division of society into two classes: that which disposes

of wealth and the lives of workers, and creates and perpetuates the

superstructures (customs, moral values, law, culture in general), and

that which produces wealth.

The proletariat can today be defined broadly as follows: those

who, at one level or another, create surplus value or contribute to

its realization. Added to the proletariat are those who, belonging

to non-proletarian strata, rally to proletarian objectives (such as

intellectuals and students).

<br>

are not the results of mechanical necessities independent of the

activities of the exploited. The class struggle is not simply a phenomenon

to be observed: it is the driver that constantly modifies

the situation and the facts of capitalist society. Revolution is its

conclusion. It is the exploited taking into its hands the instruments

of production and exchange, of weapons, and the destruction of the

centers and means of state power.

To be sure, the class struggle is punctuated with difficulties,

failures, and bloody defeats, but proletarian action periodically

reemerges, more powerful and more extensive.

1. In the first instance it manifests itself at the level of direct

confrontation in the workplace. It also manifests itself

at the level of problems of daily life, in struggles against

the oppression of women, the young, and minorities; in

the questioning of education, culture, art, and values. But

these struggles must never be separated from the class

struggle. Attacking the state and the superstructures also

means attacking capitalist domination. Fighting for better

working conditions or wage increases means carrying on

the same struggle. But it is clear that posing the problem of

lifestyle, rather than just that of wage levels, gives the struggle

a more radical aspect when this means the development

of a mass movement demanding a whole new conception

of life rather than merely quantitative improvements.

2. Historical analysis makes clear a profound tendency,

expressed by the workers through their direct struggles

against capital and the state, towards self-organization, and

the structures of classless society appear embryonically in

the forms assumed by revolutionary action. The tendency

towards autonomous action can be seen in the course of

the most everyday struggles: wildcat strikes, expropriations,

various forms of direct action opposed to bureaucratic

leadership, action committees, rank-and-file committees,

etc. With the demand for power at workers’ general

assemblies and the insistence on the revocability of delegates,

it is true self-management that is on the agenda.

For us there is no historic and formal break between the proletariat

rising to power and its struggles to achieve this, rather a

continuous and dialectical development of self-management techniques,

starting from the class struggle and ending with the victory

of the proletariat and the establishment of a classless society.

A specifically proletarian mode of organization, “council power,”

arose during revolutionary periods like the Paris Commune (1871),

Makhnovist Ukraine (1918–1921), the Italian workers’ councils

(1918–1922), the Bavarian council republic (1918–1919), the Budapest

Commune (1919), the Kronstadt Commune (1921), the Spanish

Revolution (1936–1937), the Hungarian revolt (1956), the Czech revolt

(1968), and May ’68.

The power of the councils, achieving generalized self-management

in all realms of human activity, can only be defined through

historical practice itself, and any attempt at a definition of the new

world can only be an approximation, a proposal, an investigation.

The appearance and generalization of direct forms of workers’

power implies that the revolutionary process is already quite

advanced. Nevertheless, it should be presumed that at this stage

bourgeois power is still far from being totally liquidated. And so

a provisional dual power is established between the revolutionary

and socialist structures put in place by the working classes and, on

the other hand, the counter-revolutionary forces.

During this period the class struggle, far from being attenuated,

reaches its climax, and it is here that the words class war take

on all their sharpness: the future of the revolution depends on the

outcome of this war. Nevertheless, it would be dangerous to view

the process in accordance with well-defined norms. Indeed, the

nature of state power (i.e., counter-revolutionary power) in its fight

against the councils can take on different forms. What is fundamental

is that council power is antagonistic to all state power, since

it expresses itself within society itself through general assemblies,

whose delegates in the various organizations that have been established

are nothing but its expression and can be recalled at any time.

At this point authority and society are no longer separate, the

maximal conditions having been realized for the satisfaction of the

needs, tendencies, and aspirations of individuals and social groups,

humanity escaping from its condition as object to become the creative

subject of its own life.

And so it is obvious that the revolution cannot be made through

intermediaries: it is the product of the spontaneous movement of

the masses and not of a general staff of specialists or a so-called

vanguard that is alone conscious and charged with the leadership

and direction of struggles. When the word “spontaneous” is used

here its use should not at all be interpreted as adherence to a so-called

spontaneist idea privileging mass spontaneity at the expense

of revolutionary consciousness, which is its indispensable complement

and which surpasses it. In other words, an incorrect use of the

notion of spontaneity would consist in likening it to a “disordered,”

“instinctive” activity that would be incapable of engendering revolutionary

consciousness, as was claimed by Kautsky and later by

Lenin in his **What Is to Be Done?**

It is no less obvious that the revolution cannot be a simple

political and economic restructuring of the old society. Instead, by

all at once overturning all realms through the smashing of capitalist

production relations and the state, it is not only political and

economic, but also at every moment cultural, and it is in this sense

that we can utilize the idea of total revolution.

<br>

the historic consciousness of the proletariat. It is, in fact, those militant

workers who are at the forefront of offensive combat, and those

who maintain a certain degree of consciousness even in periods of

retreat.

The revolutionary organization is a place for meetings,

exchanges, information, and reflection which enable the development

of revolutionary theory and practice, which are nothing but

two aspects of one movement. It brings together militants who

recognize each other at the same level of reflection, activity, and

cohesion. It can on no account substitute itself for the proletarian

movement itself or impose a leadership on it or claim to be its fully

achieved consciousness.

On the other hand, it must strive to synthesize the experiences

of struggle, helping to acquire the greatest possible degree of revolutionary

consciousness and the greatest possible coherence in that

consciousness, which is to be seen not as a goal or as existing in

the abstract, but as a process.

In summary, the revolutionary organization’s role is to support

the proletarian vanguard and to assist in the self-organization of the

proletariat by playing—either collectively or through the intervention

of militants—the role of propagator, catalyst, and revealer, and

by allowing the revolutionaries that compose it coordinated and

convergent interventions in the areas of information, propaganda,

and support for exemplary actions.

A consequence of this conception of the revolutionary organization

is its mission to disappear not through a mechanical decision,

but when it no longer corresponds to the functions that justify it. It

will then dissolve in the classless society.

Revolutionary praxis is carried out within the masses, and

theoretical elaboration only has meaning if it is always connected

to the struggles of the proletariat. In this way revolutionary theory

is the opposite of ideological verbiage papering over the absence of

any truly proletarian praxis.

What this means is that the purpose of the revolutionary

organization is to bring together militants in agreement with the

above and independently of any Marxist, anarchist, councilist,

or libertarian communist label, the label serving to cover in fact

the top-down and elitist understanding of the vanguard that is of

course found among Leninists, but also among so-called anarchists.

The revolutionary organization does not exclusively invoke

any particular theoretician or any preexisting organization, though

recognizing the positive contributions of those who systematized,

refined, and spread the ideas drawn from the mass movement.

Rather it positions itself as heir of the various manifestations of

the anti-authoritarian workers current of the First International,

a current which is historically known under the name of communist

anarchism or libertarian communism, a current which

the so-called anarchist currents have, unfortunately, often grossly

caricatured.

The revolutionary organization is self-managed. In its structures

and functioning it must prefigure the non-bureaucratic society

that will see the distinction between order-givers and order-followers

disappear and that will establish delegation solely for technical

tasks and with the corrective of permanent recall.

Technical knowledge and competencies of all kinds must be

as widespread as possible to ensure an effective rotation of tasks.

Discussion and the elaboration of ideas must thus be the task of

all militants and, even more than the indispensable organizational

norms, which can always be revised, it is the level of coherence and

the consciousness of responsibilities reached by all concerned that

is the best antidote to any bureaucratic deviation.

----

(This platform was discussed and adopted during a meeting

held in Marseille on July 11, 1971. It had been called by the Mouvement

Communiste Libertaire [MCL, Libertarian Communist Movement],

founded by groups and individuals most of whom had come out

of the former Federation Communiste Libertaire [FCL, Libertarian

Communist Federation], the Jeunesse Anarchiste Communiste

[JAC, Communist Anarchist Youth], and the Union des Groupes

Anarchistes-Communistes [UGAC, Union of Communist-Anarchist

Groups] in the wake of May 1968 and within the framework of the

fusion of several local groups of the Organisation révolutionnaire

Anarchiste [ORA, Anarchist Revolutionary Organization]. I actively

participated in the discussion concerning its final version on the

basis of a draft proposed by Georges Fontenis.[282] It was published in

November 1971 in **Guerre de Classes** [Class War], newspaper of the

Organisation Communiste Libertaire [OCL, Libertarian Communist

Organization].)

<right>

[In **À la recherche d’un communisme libertaire,** 1984]

</right>

[281] In 1969, Guérin had helped launch the Mouvement Communiste Libertaire

(Libertarian Communist Movement), and two years later the MCL merged

with a number of other groups to create the Organisation Communiste

Libertaire (Libertarian Communist Organization). This was the OCL’s

manifesto. [DB]

[282] Georges Fontenis (1920–2010) was one of the leading figures in the

postwar revolutionary movement in France. He played an important

role in the reconstruction and reform of the French anarchist movement

(notably through the creation of the FCL), and in supporting those fighting

for Algerian independence in the 1950s and 1960s. A prominent activist

in May ’68, he would go on to help (re)create a libertarian communist

movement in the 1970s. He was also in later life one of the pillars of the

Free Thought (La Libre Pensee) movement. Having joined the Union of

Libertarian Communist Workers (UTCL) in 1980, he would subsequently

become a member of Alternative Libertaire, and would remain a member

until his death at the age of ninety. [DB]

Appendix II:

The 1989 “Call for a Libertarian Alternative”

Since the winter of 1986–1987, struggles have followed one after

the other. They demand to be given a combative and innovative

expression.

The signatories of this appeal address all those women and

men who think that under current social and political circumstances

a new revolutionary alternative must be established. In our

eyes, the creation of a revolutionary movement capable of building

on and taking forward the newly revived struggles requires us to

take two complementary paths:

- The formation of a new organization for a libertarian communism,

which is what this appeal is proposing;

- The emergence of a vast and necessarily pluralist, anti-capitalist,

self-management movement, to which organized

libertarians will immediately contribute and where they

will be active alongside other political tendencies.

We have entered a period of agitation and struggle that lays

bare the inability of the Left and the union leaderships to respond

to the aspirations of the population.

The “Socialist” Party (PS) manages capitalism, espouses its

logic, and abandons any wish to transform society, even social

democratic reformism. It opposes the interests of all popular strata.

Under cover of “entering modernity” it wants to implement a political

and social consensus with the Right and between the different

classes. An electoral machine above all, the PS is a party of notables

and technocrats where everything is decided at the summit, without

any real democracy.

The French “Communist” Party (PCF) has not had a revolutionary

perspective for some time. Its leadership makes use of

social discontent, but the only model for society it has to offer is a

still terribly bureaucratic USSR. It has a completely undemocratic

organizational framework and imposes an unbearable grip on huge

swaths of the union and social movements.

The union movement is confronted with the reemergence of

struggles, but also with aspirations for self-organization that are

being vigorously expressed. The chasm has never been so wide

between unionized and non-unionized workers, between on the

one hand union organizations that choose and self-manage their

own battles, and on the other hand the fossilized union apparatuses

which are often tied to the PS or the PCF.

The revolutionary, alternative, and ecological Left, with all

its variants, does not propose a credible and attractive alternative.

The top-down and centralized errors and myths inherited from

Leninism continue to weigh heavily on some. On others, it is the

strong temptation to integrate into institutional electoral politics

and to constitute a “radical reformist axis” due to the repeated

abandonment by social democracy of its project once it reaches

power.

The balance sheet of the libertarian movement, such as it

exists today, is no more positive and a debate over this point is

necessary. For various reasons, we have not succeeded in putting

forward a contemporary alternative. And many errors continue,

here and there, to tarnish our image: divisions, disorganization, a

certain sectarianism, sometimes an unreasoning cult of spontaneity,

as well as the retreat into initiatives that have the merit of

testifying to an ethical refusal of an alienating society, but which

are nevertheless far too ideological and fail to provide the means of

acting on social reality.

The signatories of this appeal affirm that there is room for a

new libertarian struggle, one which is non-dogmatic, non-sectarian,

and attentive to what is happening and what is changing in society.

A struggle which is open and at the same time organized to be

effective. A coherent, well-defined message, but one that is nevertheless

not carved in stone, that is forever the object of reflection

and renewal.

It is the aspirations expressed in the struggles for equality,

self-organization, and the rejection of the neoliberal logic that lead

us to this conclusion. It is also the road left open by the collapse

of yesterday’s dominant models: social democracy, Leninism, and

Stalinism. Many militants would be open to the ideas of a resolutely

anti-capitalist and libertarian current if it were able to engage with

contemporary problems.

Finally, many anarchists and other anti-authoritarians have

distinguished themselves, some very actively, in the recent battles

in the union movement, in the student movement, in the fight

against racism and for equality, and in support of the struggles of

the Kanak people.[283] Many among them feel the movement is in need

of modernization in order to pursue and strengthen their struggles,

going beyond the structures and divisions within libertarianism

that have most often been inherited from the past.

We propose to base ourselves on these practices in order to

organize together a libertarian alternative that responds to the challenges

of our time.

This perspective rests on a statement of fact: none of the

current libertarian groups is capable of sufficiently representing

this alternative. This objective statement in no way questions the

value of the work of the various existing organizations. We do

not reject them. On the contrary, we invite all organizations, local

groups, reviews, and individuals to follow the process, to express

themselves and participate in it. Their various experiences must not

be rejected and forgotten. A new organization will be all the more

rich if it were to succeed in bringing together and capitalizing on

the many contributions that preceded it. But we have to do things

differently if we are to respond to a new situation. The best way

forward seems to us to be one that would take social and militant

practice as its starting point as an element of a process under the

control of rank-and-file individuals and collectives speaking from

their experience, beyond the traditional divisions.

The initiative we are putting forward is therefore the work of

a collective of individual signatories and we invite everyone to join

in this process.

A contemporary affirmation of a libertarian communism

is possible, elaborated on the basis of our social practice and an

analysis of society that takes into account its profound economic,

sociological, and cultural transformations:

- An aggressive, resolutely anti-capitalist, class struggle orientation

in the conditions of today’s society.

- A strategy of counter-powers where workers, the young,

and the unemployed organize themselves and impose profound

transformations through their autonomous struggles.

This is a strategy that we oppose to that of change

through institutional methods, the actions of parties and

office-holders, and the illusion of political reformism.

Basing ourselves on these struggles we can today defend a

resolutely extra- and anti-parliamentary struggle without

imprisoning ourselves in purely ideological campaigns.

- A self-management perspective and a combative strategy

with revolution as its goal is practicable now: this libertarian

struggle will base itself in social movements and

the practice of its militants, practices that are broad-based,

inclusive, and carried out without sectarianism. Practices

that imply not only the self-management of struggles but

also involvement in trade union activity in all of today’s

organizations (i.e., as much in the CFDT, the CGT, the FEN,

and even FO as in the CNT and the independent unions).[284]

But also a class-based approach outside as well as inside

the workplace, in all aspects of life and society. Struggles

against the patriarchal order. Against racism and for

equality. Against imperialism, dictatorships, and apartheid.

Against militarism. Against nuclear energy and for

the defense of the environment. Struggles both of young

people in education and those who are either unemployed

or in casualized employment.

This libertarian affirmation anchored in present-day realities

is very much within the lineage of one of the major currents in the

history of the workers’ movement.

We are referring—without dogmatism, without wishing to

produce a naive apologia, and thus not without a critical spirit,

but with a total independence of mind—to the anti-authoritarians

of the First International, to the revolutionary syndicalists, to the

anarcho-syndicalists, to the libertarian communists or anarchistcommunists,

without neglecting the contribution of council communism,

trade unionism, self-management currents, feminism, and

ecology. Without losing sight of the fact that it is the struggles of

the workers themselves, the social movements of yesterday and

today that sustain our reflections.

Bringing all of this heritage to bear on contemporary issues

implies syntheses and much modernization on the way to a new

political current facing towards the future.

We do not fetishize organization, but in order to elaborate and

defend this struggle, organization is a necessity.

An organization means: the pooling of resources, experiences,

different focuses, and political education; a place for debate for the

elaboration of collective analyses; a means of quickly circulating

information and of coordination; the search for a strategy which

engages with present-day realities; a platform that expresses our

identity.

We must seek a form of self-management of organization that

is both democratic and federalist; that does not lead to confusion;

that organizes convergences without denying differences; that

offers a collective framework without hindering the free speech

and activity of all. A self-managed organization, where the main

orientations are decided democratically by all, by consensus or, if

not, by vote. An effective organization with the necessary structures

and means. An organization aimed at international practices and an

international dimension at a time when Europe is in preparation.[285]

It has always been the case that the anti-capitalist struggle cannot

be contained within the narrow framework of each state.

We must also stress that we are not proposing a sect that will

have no other end than its own growth. We must create a form

of activism where commitment will not be all-consuming and

alienating.

One of the assets of a new organization could be the publishing

of a new type of press capable of reaching a broader public, which

would be the expression of a current and an organization, certainly,

but also an open tribune: a press self-managed by the militants; a

a portion of its columns as a permanent forum, open and pluralistic,

where the militants of social movements and of revolutionary, libertarian,

and self-management currents could express themselves.

----

(This Appeal was signed in May 1989 by around a hundred libertarians,

political, trade union and social movement activists, members

of various organizations and of none.)

<right>

[In **Pour le communisme libertaire,** 2003]

</right>

[283] The Kanak are the indigenous people of New Caledonia (a French colonial

possession in the Pacific). [DB]

[284] As the editors of **Pour le communisme libertaire** (the 2003 Spartacus edition

of the collection of articles on which the present volume is based) point

out, the reference to the various trade union federations and confederations

should be updated: “As much in the CGT and the FSU, even in FO,

and perhaps the CFDT, as in the CNT and the SUD unions.” The CNT

(Confederation Nationale du Travail, or National Labour Confederation)

was founded in 1946 and modelled on the Spanish CNT. The manifesto’s

general point is clear: the important thing is to fight for revolutionary

practices in **all** the union organizations. [DB]

[285] This text was written a few years after the Single European Act of 1986,

which paved the way for the creation of a single market and single currency,

but before their actual creation and the emergence of the European

Union. [DB]

Bibliography

<strong>English translations of works by Daniel Guérin</strong><br>

(in chronological order of first publication)

<biblio>

<em>Fascism and Big Business</em> (New York: Pioneer Press, 1939; Monad Press

& Pathfinder Press for Anchor Foundation, 1973; Pathfinder

Press, 1994); 1939 edition translated by Frances and Mason

Merrill, introduced by Dwight Macdonald.

<em>Negroes on the March: A Frenchman’s Report on the American Negro Struggle</em> (New York: George L. Weissman, 1956); translated and

edited by Duncan Ferguson.

<em>The West Indies and Their Future</em> (London: Dennis Dobson, 1961); translated

by Austryn Whainhouse.

‘The Czechoslovak Working Class in the Resistance Movement’ in

Ken Coates (ed.), **London Bulletin** no. 9 (April 1969), pp. 15–18.

‘The Czechoslovak Working Class in the Resistance Movement’

in Ken Coates (ed.), **Czechoslovakia and Socialism** (Nottingham:

Bertrand Russell Peace Foundation, 1969), pp. 79–89.

<em>Anarchism: From Theory to Practice</em> (New York: Monthly Review Press,

1970); translated by Mary Klopper, introduced by Noam

Chomsky.

<em>Class Struggle in the First French Republic: Bourgeois and Bras Nus, i793- 1795</em> (London: Pluto, 1977); translated by Ian Paterson.

<em>The Writings of a Savage: Paul Gauguin,</em> ed. Daniel Guérin (New York:

Viking Press, 1978); translated by Eleanor Levieyx, introduced

by Wayne Andersen.

100 **Years of Labor in the USA** (London: Ink Links, 1979); translated

by Alan Adler.

<em>Anarchism and Marxism</em> (Sanday, Orkney: Cienfuegos Press, 1981);

from a talk given in New York on 6 November 1973, with an

introduction by Guérin.

‘Lutte Ouvriere/Daniel GuĂ©rin: Trotsky and the Second World War’

in **Revolutionary History** vol. 1, no. 3 (1988), available online at

[[http://www.revolutionaryhistory.co.uk/rho103fdglt.html]].

‘Marxism and Anarchism’ in David Goodway (ed.), **For Anarchism: History, Theory and Practice** (London: Routledge [History

Workshop Series], 1989), pp. 109–26; translated by David

Goodway.

<em>The Brown Plague: Travels in Late Weimar and Early Nazi Germany</em>

(Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1994); translated and

introduced by Robert Schwartzwald.

‘A Libertarian Marx?’ in **Discussion Bulletin** [Industrial Union Caucus

in Education, USA] no. 86(November-December1997), pp. 3–5.

<em>No Gods No Masters: An Anthology of Anarchism</em> (Edinburgh: AK Press,

1998, 2nd edition 2005), 2 vols., translated by Paul Sharkey.

</biblio>

About the Author

<strong>Daniel GuĂ©rin</strong> (1904–1988) was a prominent member of the French

left for half a century, and arguably one of the most original and

most interesting. One of the first on the left to attach central importance

to the struggle against colonialism, he became one of the

best-known figures in anticolonial campaigns throughout the 1950s

and ‘6os. He was also one of the first in France to warn of the rising

dangers of fascism, publishing **The Brown Plague** in 1933 and **Fascism and Big Business** in 1936. He met Leon Trotsky in 1933 and would

work with the Trotskyist resistance during the war; a respected

member of the Fourth International during the 1940s, he was a

close, personal friend of Michel Raptis (alias Pablo) until his death.

His controversial, libertarian Marxist interpretation of the French

Revolution, **Class Struggle in the First Republic, 1793–1797** (1945, 2nd

ed. 1968) was judged by his friend C.L.R. James to be “one of the

great theoretical landmarks of our movement” and by Sartre to be

“one of the only contributions by contemporary Marxists to have

enriched historical studies.” Increasingly critical of what he saw as

the authoritarianism inherent in Leninism, he influenced a generation

of activists with his “rehabilitation” of anarchism through his

<em>Anarchism</em> and the anthology <em>No Gods No Masters,</em> before playing a

role in the resurgence of interest in Rosa Luxemburg and becoming

better known for his attempts to promote a “synthesis” of Marxism

and anarchism. He was also regarded by 1968 as the grandfather of

the gay liberation movement in France and in the 1970s as a leading

light in antimilitarist campaigns. His writings have been repeatedly

republished both in French and in translation.

About the Editor

<strong>David Berry</strong> has a BA in French and German from Oxford University,

an MA in French Studies from the University of Sussex, and a DPhil

in history, also from Sussex. He is currently a senior lecturer in politics

and history at Loughborough University, UK. His publications

include **A History of the French Anarchist Movement, 1917–1945** (AK

Press, 2009); **New Perspectives on Anarchism, Labour and Syndicalism: The Individual, the National and the Transnational** (Cambridge Scholars

Publishing, 2010), coedited with Constance Bantman; **Libertarian Socialism: Politics in Black and Red** (PM Press, 2011), coedited with Alex

Prichard, Ruth Kinna, and Saku Pinta; and several journal articles

and book chapters on Daniel Guérin. He is currently preparing a

biography of Guérin to be published by PM Press.

About the Translator

<strong>Mitchell Abidor</strong> is the principal French translator for the Marxists

Internet Archive. PM Press’s collections of his translations include

<em>Anarchists Never Surrender: Essays, Polemics, and Correspondence on Anarchism, 1908–1938</em> by Victor Serge; <em>Voices of the Paris Commune;</em>

and **Death to Bourgeois Society: The Propagandists of the Deed.** His other

published translations include **The Great Anger: Ultra-Revolutionary Writing in France from the Atheist Priest to the Bonnot Gang; Communards: The Paris Commune of 1871 as Told by Those Who Fought for It;** and **A Socialist History of the French Revolution** by Jean Jaures.

Home