đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș murray-bookchin-post-scarcity-anarchism-book captured on 2023-07-22 at 20:31:47. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Post-Scarcity Anarchism Date: 1986 Source: [[https://libcom.org/files/Post-Scarcity%20Anarchism%20-%20Murray%20Bookchin.pdf][libcom.org]], [[https://archive.org/stream/revhosatx60/Murray_Bookchin_Post-Scarcity_Anarchism(b-ok.org)_djvu.txt][Internet Archive]], [[https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/murray-bookchin-listen-marxist][Anarchist Library]], [[https://www.marxists.org/archive/bookchin/1970/discussion.htm][Marxists.org]]. Notes: First and Second Introduction, âPost-Scarcity Anarchismâ, âEcology and Revolutionary Thoughtâ, âTowards a Liberatory Technologyâ, and âThe Forms of Freedomâ are taken from the second edition published by Black Rose Books. âListen Marxist!â is taken from The Anarchist Library. Third Introduction, âNote on Affinity Groupsâ, âThe MayâJune Events in Franceâ, and âDesire and Needâ are taken from the Third edition published by AK Press. âDiscussion on âListen, Marxist!ââ was taken from the first edition from the Marxists Internet Archive. Authors: Murray Bookchin Topics: Green anarchism, Anti work, Social ecology, Ecology, Sociology, Eco anarchy Published: 2019-09-17 12:25:42Z
We normally live completely immersed in the presentâto
such a degree, in fact, that we often fail to see how much
our own social period differs from the pastâindeed from a
mere generation ago. This captivity to the contemporary
can be very insidious. It may shackle us unknowingly to
the most reactionary aspects of tradition, be they obsolete
values and ideologies, hierarchical forms of organization,
or one-sided modes of political behavior. Unless our roots
in contemporary life are broadened by a rich perspective,
they may easily distort our understanding of the world as
it really is, as well as its rich potentialities for the future.
For the world is changing profoundly, more profoundly
than many of us seem to recognize. Until very recently,
human society developed around the brute issues posed by
unavoidable material scarcity and their subjective counterpart in denial, renunciation and guilt. The great historic
splits that destroyed early organic societies, dividing man
from nature and man from man, had their origins in the
problems of survival, in problems that involved the mere
maintenance of human existence.[1] Material scarcity provided the historic rationale for the development of the
patriarchal family, private property, class domination and
the state; it nourished the great divisions in hierarchical
society that pitted town against country, mind against sensuousness, work against play, individual against society,
and, finally, the individual against himself.
[1] By âorganic societiesâ I mean forms of organization in which the
community is united by kinship ties and by common interests in
dealing with the means of life. Organic societies are not yet divided
into the classes and bureaucracies based on exploitation that we find
in hierarchical society.
Whether this long and tortuous development could have
followed a different, more benign, course is now irrelevant.
The development is largely behind us. Perhaps like the
mythic apple, which, once bitten, had to be consumed
completely, hierarchical society had to complete its own
bloody journey before its demonic institutions could be
exorcised. Be that as it may, our position in that historic
drama differs fundamentally from that of anyone in the
past. We of the twentieth century are literally the heirs of
human history, the legatees of manâs age-old effort to free
himself from drudgery and material insecurity. For the
first time in the long succession of centuries, this centuryâand this one aloneâhas elevated mankind to an entirely new level of technological achievement and to an
entirely new vision of the human experience.
We of this century have finally opened the prospect of
material abundance for all to enjoyâa sufficiency in the
means of life without the need for grinding, day-to-day
toil. We have discovered resources, both for man and industry, that were totally unknown a generation ago. We
have devised machines that automatically make machines.
We have perfected devices that can execute onerous tasks
more effectively than the strongest human muscles, that
can surpass the industrial skills of the deftest human
hands, that can calculate with greater rapidity and precision than the most gifted human minds. Supported by this
qualitatively new technology, we can begin to provide
food, shelter, garments, and a broad spectrum of luxuries
without devouring the precious time of humanity and
without dissipating its invaluable reservoir of creative energy in mindless labor. In short, for the first time in history we stand on the threshold of a post-scarcity society.
The word âthresholdâ should be emphasized here for in
no way has the existing society realized the post-scarcity
potential of its technology. Neither the material âprivilegesâ that modern capitalism seems to afford the middle classes nor its lavish wasting of resources reflects the
rational, humanistic, indeed unalienated, content of a
post-scarcity society. To view the word âpost-scarcityâ
simply as meaning a large quantity of socially available
goods would be as absurd as to regard a living organism
simply as a large quantity of chemicals.[2] For one thing,
scarcity is more than a condition of scarce resources: the
word, if it is to mean anything in human terms, must
encompass the social relations and cultural apparatus that
foster insecurity in the psyche. In organic societies this
insecurity may be a function of the oppressive limits established by a precarious natural world; in a hierarchical society it is a function of the repressive limits established by
an exploitative class structure. By the same token, the
word âpost-scarcityâ means fundamentally more than a
mere abundance of the means of life: it decidedly includes
the kind of life these means support. The human relationships and psyche of the individual in a post-scarcity society
must fully reflect the freedom, security and self-expression
that this abundance makes possible. Post-scarcity society,
in short, is the fulfillment of the social and cultural potentialities latent in a technology of abundance.
[2] Hence the absurdity of Tom Haydenâs use of the expression
âpost-scarcityâ in his recent book, *The Trial*. Haydenâs fear that the
youth culture might slip into âpost-scarcity hedonismâ and become
socially passive suggests that he has yet to understand fully the
meaning of âpost-scarcityâ and the nature of the youth culture.
Capitalism, far from affording âprivilegesâ to the middle
classes, tends to degrade them more abjectly than any
other stratum in society. The system deploys its capacity
for abundance to bring the petty bourgeois into complicity
with his own oppressionâfirst by turning him into a commodity, into an object for sale in the marketplace; next by
assimilating his very wants to the commodity nexus.
Tyrannized as he is by every vicissitude of bourgeois society, the whole personality of the petty bourgeois vibrates
with insecurity. His soporificsâcommodities and more
commoditiesâare his very poison. In this sense there is
nothing more oppressive than âprivilegeâ today, for the
deepest recesses of the âprivilegedâ manâs psyche are fair
game for exploitation and domination.
But by a supreme twist of dialectical irony, the poison is
also its own antidote. Capitalismâs capacity for abundanceâthe soporific it employs for dominationâstirs up
strange images in the dream world of its victims. Running
through the nightmare of domination is the vision of freedom, the repressed intuition that what-is could be otherwise if abundance were used for human ends. Just as abundance invades the unconscious to manipulate it, so the
unconscious invades abundance to liberate it. The foremost contradiction of capitalism today is the tension between what-is and what-could-beâbetween the actuality of
domination and the potentiality of freedom. The seeds for
the destruction of bourgeois society lie in the very means
it employs for its self-preservation: a technology of abundance that is capable of providing for the first time in
history the material basis for liberation. The system, in a
sense, is in complicity against itself. As Hegel put it in
another context: âThe struggle is too late; and every
means taken makes the disease worse...â{1}
If the struggle to preserve bourgeois society tends to be
self-vitiating, so too is the struggle to destroy it. Today the
greatest strength of capitalism lies in its ability to subvert
revolutionary goals by the ideology of domination. What
accounts for this strength is the fact that âbourgeois ideologyâ is not merely bourgeois. Capitalism is the heir of
history, the legatee of all the repressive features of earlier
hierarchical societies, and bourgeois ideology has been
pieced together from the oldest elements of social domination and conditioningâelements so very old, so intractable,
and so seemingly unquestionable, that we often mistake
them for âhuman nature.â There is no more telling commentary on the power of this cultural legacy than the
extent to which the socialist project itself is permeated by
hierarchy, sexism and renunciation. From these elements
come all the social enzymes that catalyze the everyday
relationships of the bourgeois worldâand of the so-called
âradical movement.â
Hierarchy, sexism and renunciation do not disappear
with âdemocratic centralism,â a ârevolutionary leadership,â a âworkersâ state,â and a âplanned economy.â On
the contrary, hierarchy, sexism, and renunciation function
all the more effectively if centralism appears to be âdemocratic,â if leaders appear to be ârevolutionaries,â if the
state appears to belong to the âworkers,â and if commodity production appears to be âplanned.â Insofar as the
socialist project fails to note the very existence of these
elements, much less their vicious role, the ârevolutionâ
itself becomes a facade for counterrevolution. Marxâs
vision notwithstanding, what tends to âwither awayâ after
this kind of ârevolutionâ is not the state but the very
consciousness of domination.
Actually, much that passes for a âplanned economyâ in
socialist theory has already been achieved by capitalism;
hence the capacity of state capitalism to assimilate large
areas of Marxist doctrine as official ideology. Moreover, in
the advanced capitalist countries, the very progress of technology has removed one of the most important reasons for
the existence of the âsocialist stateââthe need
(in the words of Marx and Engels) âto increase the total of
productive forces as rapidly as possible.â{2} To loiter any
longer around the issues of a âplanned economyâ and a
âsocialist stateââissues created by an earlier stage of capitalism and by a lower stage of technological developmentâwould be sectarian cretinism. The revolutionary
project must become commensurate with the enormous
social possibilities of our time, for just as the material
preconditions of freedom have expanded beyond the most
generous dreams of the past, so too has the vision of freedom. As we stand on the threshold of a post-scarcity society, the social dialectic begins to mature, both in terms of
what must be abolished and what must be created. We
must bring to an end not only the social relations of bourgeois society, but also the legacy of domination produced
by long millennia of hierarchical society. What we must
create to replace bourgeois society is not only the classless
society envisioned by socialism, but the nonrepressive utopia envisioned by anarchism.
Until now we have been occupied primarily with the
technological capabilities of bourgeois society, its potential
for supporting a post-scarcity society, and the tension this
creates between what-is and what-could-be. Let there be
no mistaken notion that this tension floats in some vague
fashion between theoretical abstractions. The tension is
real, and it finds daily expression in the lives of millions.
Often intuitively, people begin to find intolerable the
social, economic and cultural conditions that were passively accepted only a decade or so ago. The growth of the
black liberation movement over the past ten years (a movement that has heightened every sensibility of black people
to their oppression) is explosive evidence of this development. Black liberation is being joined by womenâs liberation, youth liberation, childrenâs liberation and gay liberation. Every ethnic group and virtually every profession is
in a ferment that would have seemed inconceivable a mere
generation ago. The âprivilegesâ of yesterday are becoming
the ârightsâ of today in almost dizzying succession among
students, young people generally, women, ethnic minorities, and, in time, among the very strata on which the
system has traditionally relied for support. The very concept of ârightsâ is becoming suspect as the expression of a
patronizing elite which bestows and denies ârightsâ and
âprivilegesâ to inferiors. A struggle against elitism and hierarchy as such is replacing the struggle for ârightsâ as the
main goal. It is not *justice* any longer that is being demanded, but rather *freedom*. Moral sensibilities to
abusesâeven the most minor abuses by earlier standardsâare reaching an acuity that would have seemed inconceivable only a few years ago.
The liberal euphemism for the tension between actuality
and potentiality is ârising expectations.â What this sociological phrase fails to reveal is that these âexpectationsâ
will continue to âriseâ until Utopia itself is achieved. And
for good reason. What goads the âexpectationsâ into ârisingââindeed, into escalating with each ârightâ that is
gainedâis the utter irrationality of the capitalist system
itself. When cybernated and automatic machinery can
reduce toil to the near vanishing point, nothing is more
meaningless to young people than a lifetime of toil. When
modern industry can provide abundance for all, nothing is
more vicious to poor people than a lifetime of poverty.
When all the resources exist to promote social equality,
nothing is more criminal to ethnic minorities, women and
homosexuals than subjugation. These contrasts could be
extended indefinitely, covering all the issues that have
produced the social agony of our era.
In attempting to uphold scarcity, toil, poverty and subjugation against the growing potential for post-scarcity, leisure, abundance and freedom, capitalism increasingly
emerges as the most irrational, indeed the most artificial,
society in history. The society now takes on the appearance of a totally *alien* (as well as alienating) force. It
emerges as the âother,â so to speak, of humanityâs deepest
desires and impulses. On an ever-greater scale, potentiality
begins to determine and shape oneâs everyday view of actuality, until a point is reached where everything about the
societyâincluding its most âattractiveâ amenitiesâseems
totally insane, the result of a massive social lunacy.
Not surprisingly, subcultures begin to emerge which emphasize a natural diet as against the societyâs synthetic
diet, an extended family as against the monogamous
family, sexual freedom as against sexual repression, tribalism as against atomization, community as against urbanism, mutual aid as against competition, communism as
against property, and, finally, anarchism as against hierarchy and the state. In the very act of refusing to live by
bourgeois strictures, the first seeds of the Utopian lifestyle
are planted. Negation passes into affirmation; the rejection
of the present becomes the assertion of the future within
the rotting guts of capitalism itself. âDropping outâ becomes a mode of dropping inâinto the tentative, experimental, and as yet highly ambiguous, social relations of
Utopia. Taken as an end in itself, this lifestyle is not utopia; indeed, it may be woefully incomplete. Taken as a
means, however, this lifestyle and the processes leading to
it are indispensable in remaking the revolutionary, in
awakening his sensibilities to how much must be changed
if the revolution is to be complete. The lifestyle is indispensable in preserving the integrity of the revolutionary, in
providing him with the psychic resources to resist the subversion of the revolutionary project by bourgeois values.
The tension between actuality and potentiality, between
present and future, acquires apocalyptic proportions in the
ecological crisis of our time. Although a large part of this
book will deal with environmental problems, several
broad conclusions should be emphasized. Any attempt to
solve the environmental crisis within a bourgeois framework must be dismissed as chimerical. Capitalism is inherently anti-ecological. Competition and accumulation
constitute its very law of life, a law which Marx pungently
summarized in the phrase, âproduction for the sake of
production.â Anything, however hallowed or rare, âhas its
priceâ and is fair game for the marketplace. In a society of
this kind, nature is necessarily treated as a mere resource
to be plundered and exploited. The destruction of the
natural world, far from being the result of mere hubristic
blunders, follows inexorably from the very logic of capitalist production.
The schizoid attitude of the public toward technologyâan attitude that mingles fear with hopeâshould not be
dismissed lightmindedly. This attitude expresses a basic intuitive truth: the same technology that could liberate man
in a society organized around the satisfaction of human
needs must inevitably destroy him in a society organized
around âproduction for the sake of production.â To be
sure, the Manichean dualism imputed to technology is not
a feature of technology as such. The capacities of modern
technology to create or destroy are simply the two faces of
a common social dialecticâthe negative and positive features of hierarchical society. If there is any truth to Marxâs
claim that hierarchical society was âhistorically necessaryâ
in order to âdominateâ nature, we should never forget that
the concept of âdominatingâ nature emerged from the
domination of man by man. Both men and nature have
always been the common victims of hierarchical society.
That both are now faced with ecological extinction is evidence that the instruments of production have finally
become too powerful to be administered as instruments of
domination.
Today, as we stand at the end of hierarchical societyâs
development, its negative and positive aspects can no
longer be reconciled. Not only do they stand opposed to
each other irreconcilably, they stand opposed to each
other as mutually exclusive wholes. All the institutions and
values of hierarchical society have exhausted their âhistorically necessaryâ functions. No longer is there any social rationale for property and classes, for monogamy and
patriarchy, for hierarchy and authority, for bureaucracy
and the state. These institutions and values, together with
the city, the school and the instrumentalities of privilege,
have reached their historical limits. In contrast to Marx, we
would have little quarrel with Bakuninâs view that the institutions and values of hierarchical society were *always* a
âhistorically necessary evil.â If Bakuninâs verdict seems to
enjoy a moral superiority over Marxâs today, this is because
the institutions have finally lost their moral authority.[3]
[3] Hence the reactionary aspect of the socialist project, which still
retains the concepts of hierarchy, authority and the state as part of
humanityâs postrevolutionary future. By implication this project also
retains the concepts of property (ânationalizedâ) and classes
(âproletarian dictatorshipâ). The various âorthodoxâ Marxists
(Maoists, Trotskyists, Stalinists and the hybridized sects that combine all three tendencies) mediate the negative and positive features
of the overall social development ideologicallyâ*precisely* at a time
when they have never been more irreconcilable objectively.
By the same token, the coming revolution and the
utopia it creates must be conceived of as wholes. They can
leave no area of life untouched that has been contaminated
by domination.[4] From the revolution there must emerge a
society that transcends all the splits of the past; indeed,
one must emerge that offers every individual the feast of a
many-sided, rounded and total experience.
[4] Hence the revolutionary core of the womenâs liberation movement, which has brought the very syntax and musculature of domination into public view. In so doing, the movement has brought
everyday life itself, not just abstractions like âSociety,â âClass,â and
âProletariat,â into question. Here I must apologize for using terms
like âman,â âmankind,â and âhumanityâ and the masculine gender
in this book. In the absence of substitutes for âpeopleâ and âindividualsâ my wording would have become awkward. Our language
must also be liberated.
In describing this utopia as âanarchism,â I might have
also used an equivalent expressionââanarcho-communism.â Both terms denote a stateless, classless, decentralized society in which the splits created by propertied
society are transcended by new, unalienated human relationships. An anarchist or anarcho-communist society presupposes the abolition of private property, the distribution
of goods according to individual needs, the complete dissolution of commodity relationships, the rotation of work,
and a decisive reduction in the time devoted to labor. As
this description stands, however, we have little more than
the anatomy of a free society. The description lacks an
account of the physiology of freedomâof freedom as the
process of communizing. The description, in effect, lacks
those subjective dimensions that link the remaking of
society to the remaking of the psyche.
Anarchists have probably given more attention to the
subjective problems of revolution than any other revolutionary movement. Viewed from a broad historical perspective, anarchism is a libidinal upsurge of the people, a
stirring of the social unconscious that reaches back, under
many different names, to the earliest struggles of humanity
against domination and authority. Its commitment to doctrinal shibboleths is minimal. In its active concern with the
issues of everyday life, anarchism has always been preoccupied with lifestyle, sexuality, community, womenâs liberation and human relationships. Its central focus has always
been the only meaningful goal social revolution can haveâthe remaking of the world so that human beings will be
ends in themselves and human life a revered, indeed a marvelous, experience. For most radical ideologies, this goal
has been peripheral. More often than not, these ideologies,
by emphasizing abstractions over people, have reduced
human beings to a means âironically in the name of âthe
Peopleâ and âFreedom.â
The difference between socialists and anarchists reveals
itself not only in conflicting theories but also in conflicting
types of organization and praxis. I have already noted that
socialists organize into hierarchical bodies. By contrast,
anarchists base their organizational structures on the âaffinity groupââa collective of intimate friends who are no
less concerned with their human relationships than with
their social goals. The very mode of anarchist organization
transcends the traditional split between the psyche and the
social world. If the need arises, there is nothing to prevent
the affinity groups from coordinating into fairly large
movements (the Spanish anarchists, for example, built a
nationwide federation of thousands out of this nuclear
form). The movements, however, have the advantage that
control over the larger organization lies always with the
affinity groups rather than with the coordinating bodies.
All action, in turn, is based on voluntarism and self-discipline, not on coercion and command. Praxis, in such an
organization, is liberatory in the personal as well as in the
social arena. The very nature of the group encourages the
revolutionary to revolutionize himself.
This liberatory approach to praxis is carried still further
in the anarchist conception of âdirect action.â Generally,
direct action is regarded as a tactic, as a method of abolishing the state without recourse to state institutions and
techniques. Although the foregoing interpretation is correct as far as it goes, it hardly goes far enough. Direct
action is a basic revolutionary strategy, a mode of praxis
intended to promote the individuation of the âmasses.â Its
function is to assert the identity of the particular within
the framework of the general. More important than its
political implications are its psychological effects, for
direct action makes people aware of themselves as individuals who can affect their own destiny.[5]
[5] I should add here that the slogan âPower to the peopleâ can only
be put into practice when the power exercised by social elites is
dissolved into the people. Each individual can then take control of
his daily life. If âPower to the peopleâ means nothing more than
power to the âleadersâ of the people, then the people remain an
undifferentiated, manipulatable mass, as powerless after the revolution as they were before. In the last analysis, the people can never
have power until they disappear as a âpeople.â
Finally, anarchist praxis also emphasizes spontaneityâa
conception of praxis as an inner process, not an external,
manipulated process. Its critics notwithstanding, this concept does not fetishize mere undifferentiated âimpulse.â
Like life itself, spontaneity can exist on many different
levels; it can be more or less permeated by knowledge,
insight and experience. In a free society, the spontaneity
of a three-year-old would hardly be of the same order as
that of a thirty-year-old. Although both would be free to
develop without restraint, the behavior of the thirty-year-old would be based on a more defined and more informed
self. By the same token, spontaneity may be more informed in one affinity group than in another, more seasoned by knowledge and experience.
But spontaneity is no more an organizational âtechniqueâ than direct action is merely an organizational tactic. Belief in spontaneous action is part of a still larger
beliefâthe belief in spontaneous development. Every
development must be free to find its own equilibrium.
Spontaneity, far from inviting chaos, involves releasing the
inner forces of a development to find their authentic order
and stability. As we shall see in the articles that follow,
spontaneity in social life converges with spontaneity in
nature to provide the basis for an ecological society. The
ecological principles that shaped organic societies re-emerge in the form of social principles to shape Utopia.
But these principles are now informed by the material and
cultural gains of history. Natural ecology becomes social
ecology. In Utopia man no more returns to his ancestral
immediacy with nature than anarcho-communism returns
to primitive communism. Whether now or in the future,
human relationships with nature are always mediated by
science, technology and knowledge. But whether or not
science, technology and knowledge will improve nature to
its own benefit will depend upon manâs ability to improve
his social condition. Either revolution will create an ecological society, with new ecotechnologies and ecocommunities, or humanity and the natural world as we know it
today will perish.
Every revolutionary epoch is a period of convergence
when apparently separate processes collect to form a
socially explosive crisis. If our own revolutionary epoch
often seems more complex than earlier ones, this is because the processes that have been collecting together are
more universal than they have ever been in the past. Our
point of departure has no comforting historical precedents
on which to rely. Earlier revolutionary epochs at least
dealt with familiar institutional categoriesâthe family, religion, property, toil and the state were taken for granted,
even if their forms were challenged.[6] Hierarchical society
had not exhausted these categories. Its development into
more commanding and comprehensive social relations was
still unfulfilled.
[6] This situation did not change with the Russian Revolution or the
âsocialistâ revolutions that have occurred since then. The institutional categories have not disappeared; at most the names have
changed.
In our time, however, this development has reached the
point of saturation. There is no future for hierarchical society to claim, and for us there are the alternatives only of
utopia or social extinction. So heavily are we laden with
the debris of the past and so pregnant are we with the
possibilities of the future that our estrangement with the
world reaches the point of anguish. Past and future superimpose themselves on each other like latent images emerging in a double exposure. The familiar is there, but, like
the psychedelic posters whose letters take the form of
writhing human limbs, it blends elusively with the strange.
A slight shift in position and the given reality is inverted
completely. Learning to live appears to us the only mode
of survival, play the only mode of work, the personal the
only mode of the social, the abolition of sex roles the only
mode of sexuality, tribalism the only mode of the family,
sensuality the only mode of rationality. This interweaving
of the old and new, with its incredible inversions, is not
the usual âdoublespeakâ of the established order; it is an
objective fact, which reflects the vast social changes that
are in birth.
Every revolutionary epoch, moreover, not only brings
together apparently separate processes but also converges
them on a specific locus in time and space where the social
crisis is most acute. In the seventeenth century this center
was England; in the eighteenth and nineteenth, France; in
the early twentieth, Russia. The center of the social crisis
in the late twentieth century is the United Statesâan industrial colossus that produces more than half of the
worldâs goods with little more than five percent of the
worldâs population. Here is the Rome of world capitalism,
the keystone of its imperial arch, the workshop and
marketplace of its commodities, the den of its financial
wizardry, the temple of its culture, and the armory of its
weapons. Here, too, is the center of the world counterrevolutionâand the center of the social revolution that can
overthrow hierarchical society as a world-historical system.
To ignore the strategic position of the United States,
both historically and internationally, would reveal an incredible insensitivity to reality. To fail to draw all the
implications of this strategic position and act upon them
accordingly would be negligence of criminal proportions.
The stakes are too great to allow for obscurantism. America, it must be emphasized, occupies the most advanced
social terrain in the world. America, more than any other
country, is pregnant with the most important social crisis
in history. Every issue that bears on the abolition of hierarchical society and on the construction of utopia is more
apparent here than elsewhere. Here lie the resources to
annul and transcend what Marx called the âprehistoryâ of
humanity. Here, too, are the contradictions that produce
the most advanced form of revolutionary struggle. The
decay of the American institutional structure results not
from any mystical âfailure of nerveâ or from imperialist
adventures in the Third World, but primarily from the
overripeness of Americaâs technological potential. Like
hanging fruit whose seeds have matured fully, the structure
may fall at the lightest blow. The blow may come from the
Third World, from major economic dislocations, even from
premature political repression, but fall the structure must,
owing to its ripeness and decay.
In a crisis of this magnitude, the core problems of hierarchical society can be reached from *every* facet of life, be
they personal or social, political or ecological, moral or
material. Every critical act and movement erodes the
domestic and imperial edifice. To repel any expression of
discontent with sectarian harangues, borrowed from entirely different arenas and eras of social conflict, is simply
blindness. Carried to its logical conclusions, the struggle
for black liberation *is* the struggle against imperialism; the
struggle for a balanced environment *is* the struggle against
commodity production; the struggle for womenâs liberation *is* the struggle for human freedom.
True, a great deal of the pursuit of this discontent can
be diverted into established institutional channels for a
time. But only for a time. The social crisis is too deep and
world-historical for the established institutions to contain
it. If the system failed to assimilate the black movement,
the âlove generation,â and the student movement of the
sixties, it was not for want of institutional flexibility and
resources. Despite the Cassandra-like forebodings of the
American âleft,â these movements essentially rejected
what the established institutions had to offer. More precisely, their demands increased as each one was met. At
the same time, the physical base of the movements expanded. Radiating out from a few isolated urban centers,
black, hippie, and student radicalism percolated through
the country, penetrating high schools as well as universities, suburbs as well as ghettoes, rural communities as well
as cities.
To challenge the value of these movements because their
recruits are often white middle-class youth begs the question. There is perhaps no better testimony to the instability of bourgeois society than the fact that many militant radicals tend to come from the relatively affluent
strata. It is conveniently forgotten that the fifties had
Cassandras of a different typeâthe âOrwell generation,â
which warned that bureaucratic society was engineering
American youth into polished conformity with the establishment. According to the predictions of that time,
bureaucratic society was to acquire its main support from
succeeding generations of young people. The ebbing generation of the thirties, it was argued, would be the last
repository of radical, humanistic values. As it turned out,
the very reverse occurred. The generation of the thirties
has become one of the most willfully reactionary sectors
of society, while the young people of the sixties have become the most radical.
In this seeming paradox, the contradiction between
scarcity and the potential for post-scarcity appears in the
form of outright confrontation. A generation whose entire
psyche has been shaped by scarcityâby the depression and
insecurities of the thirtiesâconfronts another whose
psyche has been influenced by the potential for a postscarcity society. White middle-class youth has the real
privilege of rejecting false âprivilege.â In contrast to their
depression-haunted parents, young people are disenchanted by a flatulent consumerism that pacifies but never
satisfies. The generation gap is real. It reflects an objective gap that increasingly separates America today from its
own social history, from a past that is becoming archaic.
Although this past has yet to be interred, a generation is
emerging that may well prove to be its gravediggers.
To criticize this generation for its âbourgeois rootsâ exhibits the wisdom of a dunce who doesnât know that his
most serious remarks are evoking laughter. All who live in
bourgeois society have âbourgeois roots,â be they workers
or students, young people or old, black people or white.
How much of a bourgeois one becomes depends exclusively upon what one accepts from bourgeois society. If
young people reject consumerism, the work ethic, hierarchy and authority, they are more âproletarianâ than the
proletariatâa bit of semantic nonsense that should encourage us to inter the threadbare elements of socialist
ideology together with the archaic past from which they
derive.
If this nonsense still commands any attention today, it
is due to the anemic character of the revolutionary project
in the United States. American revolutionaries have yet to
find a voice that relates to American issues. First World
problems are not Third World problems; the two, moreover, are not bridged by retreating to ideologies that deal
with nineteenth-century problems. Insofar as American
revolutionaries mechanically borrow their formulas and
slogans from Asia and Latin America, they do the Third
World a grave disservice. What the Third World needs is a
revolution in America, not isolated sects that are incapable
of affecting the course of events. To promote that revolution would be the highest act of internationalism and solidarity with oppressed people abroad; it would require an
outlook and a movement that speak to the problems
unique to the United States. We need a cohesive, revolutionary approach to American social problems. Anyone
who is a revolutionary in the United States is *necessarily*
an internationalist by virtue of Americaâs world position,
so I need make no apologies for the attention I give to this
country.
The articles that make up this book must be seen as a
unified whole. What essentially unifies them is the view
that manâs most visionary dreams of liberation have now
become compelling necessities. All the articles are written
from the perspective that hierarchical society, after many
bloody millenia, has finally reached the culmination of its
development. The problems of scarcity, from which
emerged propertied forms, classes, the state and all the
cultural paraphernalia of domination, can now be resolved
by a post-scarcity society. In reaching the point where
scarcity can be eliminated, we find that a post-scarcity
society is not merely desirable or possible, but absolutely
necessary if society is to survive. The very development of
the material preconditions for freedom makes the achievement of freedom a social necessity.
If humanity is to live in balance with nature, we must turn
to ecology for the essential guidelines of how the future
society should be organized. Again, we find that what is
desirable is also necessary. Manâs desire for unrepressed,
spontaneous expression, for variety in experience and surroundings, and for an environment scaled to human dimensions must also be realized to achieve natural equilibrium.
The ecological problems of the old society thus reveal the
methods that will shape the new. The intuition that all of
these processes are converging toward an entirely new way
of life finds its most concrete confirmation in the youth
culture. The rising generation, which has been largely
spared the scarcity psychosis of its parents, anticipates the
development that lies ahead. In the outlook and praxis of
young people, which range from tribalism to a sweeping
affirmation of sensuousness, one finds those cultural prefigurations that point to a future utopia.
Though I devote most of my discussion to what is new in
the current social development, I definitely do not mean
to ignore what is old. Exploitation, racism, poverty, class
struggle and imperialism are still with usâand in many
respects have deepened their grip on society. These issues
can never fade from revolutionary theory and praxis until
they are resolved completely. There is little I can contribute to these issues, however, that has not been exhaustively discussed by others. What justifies my Utopian
emphasis is the nearly total lack of material on the potentialities of our time. If no effort is made to enlarge this
meagerly explored area, even the traditional issues of the
radical movement will appear to us in a false lightâas traditional. This would distort our very contact with the familiar. Although the issues raised by exploitation are not
supplanted by those of alienation, the development of the
former is profoundly influenced by the development of
the latter.
Let us turn to an example of what this means. The
traditional workersâ movement will never reappear. Despite
rank and file revolts, âbread and butterâ issues are often
too well contained by bourgeois unionism to form the
basis for the old socialist type of labor union. But workers
may yet form radical organizations to fight for changes in
the quality of their lives and workâultimately for workersâ
management of production. Workers will not form radical
organizations until they sense the same tension between
what-is and what-could-be that many young people feel
today. I believe they will have to undergo major changes in
their valuesâand not merely those values that involve the
factory, but those that involve their lives. Only when life
issues dominate factory issues will factory issues be assimilated to life issues. Then the economic strike may one day
become a social strike and culminate in a massive blow
against bourgeois society.
That young people in working-class families have increasingly responded to the culture of their white middle-class peers is one of the most hopeful signs that the factory
will not be impervious to revolutionary ideas. Once it has
taken root, a cultural advance, like a technological advance, is ever more widely diffusedâparticularly among
people whose minds have not been hardened by conditioning and age. The youth culture, with its freedom of the
senses and spirit, has its own innate appeal. The spread of
this culture to the high schools and elementary schools is
one of the most subversive social phenomena in the world
today.
The articles in this book are a careful elaboration of the
ideas raised in the foregoing pages. They appeal for a new
emphasis on the problems of freedom, the environment,
sex roles and lifestyle, and they advance broad Utopian
alternatives to the present social order. These emphases, I
am convinced, are absolutely indispensable to the development of the revolutionary project in America.
Most of the articles were written between 1965 and
1968, a mere few years ago by the calendar, but ages ago
ideologically. The hippie movement was just getting underway in New York when âEcology and Revolutionary
Thoughtâ was published, and the disastrous SDS convention of June 1969 had yet to occur when âListen, Marxist!â was completed. Most of the articles were published in
were published in underground papers or republished in
âNew Leftâ collections. Except for some deletions and the
inclusion of several paragraphs, most of my changes have
been stylistic.
One article, âThe Forms of Freedom,â has been substantially rewritten to remove any misunderstanding about
my views on workersâ councils. That these forms will be
necessary to take over and operate the economy in a postrevolutionary period is a view Iâve held for many yearsâwith the proviso, of course, that the councils (I prefer the
term âfactory committeesâ) are controlled completely by
workersâ assemblies. Originally, this article limited its discussion of workersâ councils to a critique of their defects
as policy-making bodies. In rewriting portions of âThe
Forms of Freedomâ I have tried to distinguish the function of these councils as administrative organs from policy-making organs.
The dedication of this book to Josef Weber and Allan
Hoffman is more than a sentimental gesture to two of my
closest comrades. Josef Weber, a German revolutionary
who died in 1958 at the age of fifty-eight, formulated
more than twenty years ago the outlines of the Utopian
project developed in this book. Moreover, for me he was a
living link with all that was vital and libertarian in the great
intellectual tradition of German socialism in the pre-Leninist era. From Allan Hoffman, whose death in a truck
accident this year at the age of twenty-eight was an irreparable loss to the commune movement in California, I
acquired a broader sense of the totality sought by the
counterculture and youth revolt.
I owe very much to my sisters and brothers in the
as well as for the warmth of real human relationships. In a
sense, what is of worth in this book draws from the insights of many people whom I knew on the Lower East
Side in New York, at Alternate U, and in groups and collectives throughout the country.
To themâ*Salud!*
<br>
Murray Bookchin
New York
AugustâOctober 1970
It would be easy to revise this book, to âupdateâ it and
give it greater contemporaneity since its publication by Ramparts
Books fifteen years ago. Several publishers have asked me to
do so since the book went out of print in the early eighties.
But I have resisted, often unconsciously. There are works that
should not be touchedâand *Post-Scarcity Anarchism* is perhaps
one of them. Whether deservedly or not, the book has entered
into the literature of modern anarchism and voices in a reasonably
coherent way some of the more inspired ideals of the sixties.
To alter the book would be to violate a wondrous period of
history itselfâa period that produced a new, almost magical
romance with life that I regard as imperishable if the human
spirit is to come into its fulfillment.
It is also a book that was more influential than many ecological
and radical theorists are likely to admit. I still hear its thoughts
echoed in widely disparate places. That an ecological perspective
had a rich radical content and would surface as an issue that
socialist and anarchist theorists would be obliged to deal with
was a very remote idea in the early sixties, however commonplace
it has become today.
In any case, the bookâs sale ran into many thousands in
North America and Europe. Some of its essays, particularly
âListen, Marxist!â (1969), were circulated in sizable numbers
ânot only in its original pamphlet form which I left unsigned,
but in anthologies and as articles in the widely read âunderground
pressâ of the time. Much the same can be said for âEcology
and Revolutionary Thought,â which I initially printed in my
theoretical newsletter, *Comment*, in 1964 and republished a
year later in the British monthly *Anarchy*.
The past fifteen years since the bookâs publication, however,
have seen major changes in the radical âconstituencyâ for
which it was written. American radicalism has indeed made
its âlong march through the institutions,â to use Rudi Dutschkeâs
phrase, from the stormy student campuses of the sixties to the
more serene faculty rooms of the eighties. Its buoyant populism
has been abandoned for a restful Marxism. The journey, far
from widening the horizon of the Marxist âprofessorial,â to
use Theodore Draperâs term, has turned it into a more âdiscriminatingâ body, a word I use in a highly partisan sense.
Today, almost anyoneâs book will make its way into the bibliographies of this professoriat if it is labelled âMarxist,â
irrespective of the hodge-podge of ideas the term is obliged
to encompass. Use the word âanarchist,â and the book is
likely to be consigned to academic oblivion, even such historically important writers as a Peter Kropotkin or a Paul
Goodman.
Which is not to say that I am convinced that these writers
will disappear from the radical tradition: there are more long-range factors that ultimately single out pioneering books and
ideas from epigones who try to restate them in less original
and more socially acceptable ways. What troubles me about
epigonic writing is the way it obscures and hybridizes ideas.
It is disconcerting, to say the least, to see attempts to meld an
ecologism that is clearly libertarian in its view of nature with
a Marxism that is structured around the domination of nature
as a historic desideratum. Not only do such efforts violate the
meaning of social ecology (as I choose to call my ideas) but
also the thrust of Marxâs own ideas. Just as I stress in my
writings the fecundity, creativity, and complexity of nature as
a potential ârealm of freedom,â so Marxâs writings deal with
nature as âstingy,â as mere object for human exploitation,
and as a grim ârealm of necessityâ that dominates âmanâ in
his quest for a liberated worldâa world liberated not only
from human domination but the âdominationâ of humanity
by nature.
Indeed, Marxâs justification for the emergence of class society
and the State, not to speak of his âclass analysis,â stems from
an underlying imagery of the oppressed âsavageâ who must
âwrestleâ with an ungiving, intractable natural world. The
Victorian, largely *bourgeois*, origins of this imagery is an issue
I have discussed in some detail in other books.[7] To wed this
grim drama of social development to a libertarian conception
of nature as fecund, creative, and a potential ârealm of freedomâ
is not merely sloppy thinking; it is grossly obscurantist. One
can always, to sure, trot out a Gramsci or a Marcuse to paper
over blatant contradictions that deserve respect and serious
resolution. But to ignore them by prudently castling a veil of
silence over works that seek to explore them with care is to
divest ideas of their integrity and denature critical thinking as
such.
[7] See particularly my essay âMarxism as Bourgeois Sociologyâ in
critique of Marxism in *The Ecology of Freedom* (Palo Alto: Cheshire Books,
1982).
What also troubles me is the moral condition of contemporary
radicalism. There was a time, even as recently as the early
thirties, when radicals of all kinds formed an ethical community,
despite the many ideological differences that divided them.
Whether as socialists, anarchists, syndicalists, or populists,
they shared their views in free discourse, defended each otherâs
rights, and even aided each other in publishing works that were
ordinarily proscribed by the bourgeois press. Anarchists like
Emma Goldman could find solace and help from Marxists like
John Reed in times of difficulty, and anarchists like Sacco and
Vanzetii rallied universal support from the Left, including
Communists, despite their explicit criticisms of Soviet Russia.
These days are gone. The Left, today, is not only fragmented;
it is closeted into dogmatic strongholds, and many of its members
are notable not only for their lack of political influence but
their professorial spitefulness. Polemic has lost its fire and
honesty. It suffers from the sterility of the specialistâs âjournalâ:
jargonized, stilted, pedantic, insidiously backbiting, and unrestrained in its capacity to plagiarize. Socialism has become
an industry and its literary works are commodities. They are
often vended by ambitious careerists who have long traded
away their political ideals for their professional status. The
âNew Leftâ has aged badly. It lives in spiteful hatred of its
own youth and in fear of a revival of student militancy, a
revival that may jeopardize its academic positions and peer
recognition.
In many cases, a strangely symbiotic relationship exists between the academic Right and its leftist counterparts: a few
scholarly Marxists are not only a *sine qua non* for a sophisticated
college curriculum, but departments, even control of academic
journals and societies, are divided between Right and Left with
an unspoken understanding that the stability of a university,
even the effective control of the student body, depends upon
a delicate balance of forces between the two and a âpluralismâ
that replaces intellectual stimuli by paralysis. I need hardly
say that in this academic ecumene, anarchists are literally too
gauche to have a place in the academic firmament and their
literature must be closed out of reading lists and course adoptions.
If there is a reasonable amount of peace in the academy today,
it is due not only to the careerism of students in an economically
precarious world, but the careerism of their âradicalâ professors
in an academically tight market. The âprofessoriatâ has become
an interest in its own right and strategically tends to function
more as a safety valve for student dissent than a stimulusâ
a fact which more intelligent conservatives appreciate only too
well.
In rereading Post-Scarcity Anarchism, I find its sixties rebelliousness to be a healthy antidote to the prevailing mood
of calculated disenchantment and reformism that is so prevalent
within the âradicalâ movement today. The book spoke to a
time when words like ârevolution,â âuprising,â and even
âbourgeoisie,â were not seen as exotic terms. At the same
time it was meant to be a careful correction of the revolutionary
fervor that took possession of the young radicals I knew at the
time: their earnest belief that revolution was imminent. (See
pp. 34â35.) Already middle-aged in the sixties with a long
experience in the Left of the thirties behind me, I tried to warn
my younger comrades that âthere is no ârevolutionary situationâ
at this time in America...â Indeed, as I wrote, âThere is no
immediate prospect of a revolutionary challenge to the established
order.â Rather, there is âa greater susceptibility to radical
ideas than at any time since the populist resurgence of seventy
years ago... [but] still no reason to believe that the bulk of
white America will accept, much less support, the idea of
revolutionary change at the present time.â These lines were
published in the first issue of *Anarchos*, a magazine I launched
in 1967 with the cooperation of a few friends in New Yorkâs
Lower East Side.[8] What troubled me profoundly was the likelihood that revolutionary expectations among radical young
people were outpacing realityâa fear that was more than
amply justified, as the seventies were to show.
[8] See Robert Keller (pseud.): âRevolution in America,â *Anarchos*, No. 1,
February, 1968, p. 3.
Yet the sixties had done wondrous things, many of which
are sedimented into American life. Its linkage of the personal
with the political, of esthetic fantasy with social reality, of a
nonhierarchical society with a classless one, of libertarian process
with revolutionary endsâall, not to speak of its celebrated
flood of experiments in communal living, sexual freedom,
radical changes in dress, diet, educational techniques, and
culture as such, were latently revolutionary and expressly Utopian.
The notion, so prevalent today, that this constellation of what
was to be called a âcountercultureâ has been âco-optedâ is
grossly false. That business, ever on the lookout for new commercial opportunities, used bits and pieces of the counterculture
to its profit is not evidence of its co-optation but rather of its
fragmentation. One could say the same of the Paris Commune
of 1871 because the Rothschilds offered to meet its monetary
needs. To have co-opted the counterculture as a *whole*, even
in the name of profit, would have planted a revolutionary way
of experiencing reality in the very heart of the system.
In any case, America could not accept these social and
cultural changes overnight. To achieve them, even in part,
would have required years of enlightenment. The âNew Leftâ
and the counterculture, initially so generous, populist, and
anarchic in character, adopted a self-righteous and dogmatic
stance as the years went by. The Vietnam War and the âcultural
revolutionâ in China did these movements no service; as Barbara
Garson has observed somewhere, it gave them a âbandwagonâ
to hitch on to, a phenomenon we are witnessing today in the
case of Nicaragua. That the sixties opposed American imperialism is indubitably creditable and admirable, but certainly
not its adoption of Vietnam and China as âmodelsâ of revolutionary wisdom and a new society. Disconnected from the
American experience, the âNew Left,â became increasingly
isolated, even more than the counterculture, which was already
hemorrhaging from its own entanglement with drugs, musical
impresarios, and self-anointed gurus. Intolerance replaced an
understanding desire to educate the people; Marxist-Leninist
dogma, more closely akin to Stalinism than Marxism, filtered
through a political movement whose promising beginnings had
been sidetracked into a form of cultural terrorism, as intolerant
as the cultural conventions it professed to oppose.[9] Expectations
for social change began to exceed the real possibility for achieving
them so that failure, when it came, virtually demolished sizable
movements that seemed to have limitless possibilities for growth.
Americaâs vicious reaction to the shootings at Kent State Universityââthe National Guard should have shot more!â was
the characteristic reply of angry parents to their shocked childrenâthe popularity of Nixon, and finally the onset of economic
crises, placed a final seal on the closing of the sixties.
[9] Readers who still have a good knowledge of the period would do well
to contrast the good-natured playfulness of the Dutch *Provos* with the repellent
dogmatism of the French Situationists. The full measure of the degeneration
that occurred between 1965 and 1968 can be understood by placing these
two tendencies in juxtaposition to each other.
What stands out most sharply about this era was its innocence.
The cultural upwelling that tried to enchant everyday life foundered on its inability to understand the historic trends that
produced it. Everyday life, in effect, concealed the need to
grasp the larger social context in which the âNew Leftâ and
the counterculture flourished. What was painfully lacking was
the maturing, steadying effect of consciousness and a theoretical
coherence of ideas which would have united the disparate
threads of the âMovement,â as it came to be called, giving
it meaning, a sense of direction, and ultimately the organizational
structures that were needed to interlink it and make it socially
effective. Marxism, with its gospel of âclass analysisâ and
economic determinism, functioned as an inertial drag on the
âMovement,â not as a clarifying light. For the âMovementâ
was nothing if it was not *transclass*: people united by age, a
sense of community, ethnically, and, later, by genderânot
by their status in the ârelations of production.â Lacking an
adequate theoretical framework, indeed rooted in a typically
American framework that eschewed ideas and the value of
theory, the âMovement,â beleaguered by growing uncertainties
about its identity, became afraid of itself. It was seized by
fear: fear of its direction, isolation, exploitation, lack of power,
a loss of self-assurance that came from violated innocence,
and its vulnerability to the sharksâcommercial and lumpenâthat began to encircle it. Finally it succumbed to the economic
shocks that raised serious doubts about its material viability.
The sudden scramble of young people from New Yorkâs Lower
East Side after several highly publicized drug-related murders,
the premature symbolic âburial of the hippieâ in San Franciscoâs
Haight-Ashbury district, and the stormy immolation of the
Students for a Democratic Society at its Chicago convention
in June 1969, essentially brought the era to an end.
The sixties will not recurânor should it. What it addressed
was a sense of disempowerment, alienation, displacement, and
a need for existential meaning which a period, rich in the
goodies that filled a vacuous life, could not supply. Above all,
it sought an authentic and creative form of community. Not
that these problems are unique to the sixties. They have existed
in different forms and degrees since the end of the Second
World War. The distinctive nature of the era lay in the fact
that it saw the decay of a traditional society side-by-side with
an unprecedented period of material abundance. The tension
between the reality of social decay in a cultural sense and the
prospect of social reconstruction in a material sense unavoidably
produced unrest on the one hand and Utopian visions on the
other. Blacks provided the unrest in ghetto uprisings on a scale
that had never been seen before, a product not only of their
growing misery but also of their rising expectations. Compared
to the ghetto explosions, the campus ârevoltsâ were fairly
tame affairs, but necessary ones. White youth, largely middle-class in background, provided the necessary sense of vision,
such as it was or hoped to be.
But both were minorities within minorities. Black militants
were barely accepted by their own people, except when a sense
of shock was needed to give their more âresponsibleâ leaders
political clout. Leftist and countercultural youth were not really
accepted by the majority students and the ordinary run of young
people for whom they professed to speak, and, in the end,
were more frightening, with their diet of dogmas and judgemental
behavior, than inspiring. Sizable as both currents in the sixties
became, they never acquired the lasting allegiance of their own
kind. Nor did they try to earn it by painstaking education and
patient forebearance.
A future movement for basic social change will not satisfy
the needs of our timeâits sense of disempowerment, alienation,
displacement, meaning, and communityâunless it pieces
itself together *consciously*, bit by bit, with the aim of ideological
clarity and theoretical coherence. Education, in my view, is
the top âpriorityâ for a radicalization of our time. To step
rapidly out into another historic void will simply produce the
same fear and sense of isolation that brought the sixties to an
end. This education must speak clearly to the transclass phenomenaâthe re-emergence of âthe People,â as it wereâwith which the modern era started centuries ago, and it must
deal with problems that are best defined as ethical, not simply
economic.[10] Only by a supreme act of consciousness and ethical
probity can this society be changed fundamentally. That it
needs âobjective forcesâ to promote that consciousness and
ethics over and beyond educators is clear enough, but I hold
more than ever that the *study* group, not only the âaffinity
group,â is the indispensable form for this timeâespecially
in view of the appalling intellectual and cultural degradation
that marks our era.
[10] See particularly my essay âSpontaneity and Organizationâ in
As to the âobjective forcesâ at work that may yet open a
new period of social reconstruction, I have no reason whatever
to diminish the enormous importance I attached to ecological
problems thirty years ago. âEcology and Revolutionary
Thoughtâ is one of the most prescient works to appear in
radical theory. Its scope, projections, and anticipations, seen
from 1964 onward, are as valid today as they were more than
twenty years ago. That my identification of ârevolutionary
thoughtâ with anarchism has precluded its extensive use by
the Marxist professoriat is testimony to an inquisitorial dogmatism, indeed an ideological fanaticism, that deserves the
greatest contempt. Pilfered wholesale by many Marxists themselves, it stands as a lasting reproach to the myth that a radical
âcommunityâ exists in the United States. The fact that ecological
movements, at this writing, constitute the most serious source
of social opposition in Germany is a reminder that the essayâs
prognoses justify the emphasis I give to it in this foreword.
So, too, is the importance of feminismâparticularly
eco-feminism, which has drawn a good deal of inspiration from
the essay. Whether ecofeminism will go beyond the small-group syndrome that tends to marginalize it and bypass the
liberal politics of the National Organization of Women (NOW)
by becoming part of a larger, hopefully libertarian *Green*
movement in the English-speaking world remains to be seen.
The tendency of leftist feminists to withdraw into themselves
is a problem that cannot be overlooked. It stands in flat contradiction to the justly universal claims of feminism in its more
advanced forms to speak for âlife on earthâ against the assaults
of patriarchalism, market competition, and a sensibility of
domination and militarism.
The peace movement, another transclass âhistoric force,â
is faced with much the same problem of exclusivity and scope.
The attempt to gauge its successes or failures by whether it
can prevent the siting of nuclear missiles, bring the âsuperpowersâ to the ânegotiating table,â or achieve appreciable
arms reduction reveals a disturbing degree of naivete. Its authentic
and most on-going goal must ultimately be to oppose *militarism*,
not only to advocate disarmament. This means that its basic
orientation falls into the province of social ecology: to replace
the hierarchical and domineering sensibility and social relations
that link the domination of nature with the domination of human
by human. No less than feminism, the peace movement must
become part of a larger whole, a more encompassing coordination
of the many separate threads, vital as each may be in its own
right, into a well-focused and ultimately libertarian political
movement.
Finally, the popular impulse toward community, which today
stands in flat opposition to a homogenizing, atomizing, and
privatizing urbanismâone that threatens to destroy both the
city *and* the countrysideâhas moved to the forefront of the
âforcesâ to which I have alluded. English socialism today is
riddled by movements or tendencies that emphasize the locality
rather than the nation-state, a new âlocal socialismâ from
which there is much to be learned. In any case, it is only on
the local levelâin the village, town, city, or neighborhoodâthat a new politics can be developed, one which brings
together all of these âforcesâ as a form of ecological politics.
Here, in municipalities, where people live out their lives in
the most *immediate* and *personal* sense, we find the locus of
real popular power. This public sphere provides the existential
arena that makes for citizenship in an active sense. Social
ecology brings all of these threads together in its opposition
to hierarchy and domination as a critical theory and its emphasis
on participation and differentiation as a reconstructive theory.
Elsewhere, I have drawn a sharp distinction between politics
and statecraft.[11] Suffice it to say that politics, in my view, is
the recovery of the Greek notion of a local public sphereâthe municipalityâin contrast to the statecraft of the nationstate which we have so mistakenly designated as âpolitics.â
We have yet to give enough attention to the city as a terrain
for citizenship, self-empowerment, mutual aid, and a shared
sense of *humanitas* that transcends the parochialism of tribal
society and avoids the chauvinism of the nation-state. Yet the
radical tradition is filled with revolutionary movements structured
around the neighborhood or the city itself (the Parisian sections
of 1793â94, the Paris Commune of 1871, and the town-meeting
democracy of New England and the American Revolution, to
cite only a few). We have yet to reclaim the democratic content
of the great revolutions that liberal and Marxian historiography
designate as âbourgeoisââan interpretation with which I
emphatically disagree. This democratic content, I hold, has a
distinctly libertarian core and speaks directly to existing libertarian traditions in America and possibly in Europe. Tragically,
we have lost contact with our own radical traditions in Western
society and, due in no small measure to Marxism-Leninism,
have replaced them with ideologies and a vocabulary that is
utterly alien to our own communities.
[11] See my âTheses on Libertarian Municipalismâ in *Our Generation*,
Vol. 16, Nos. 3 & 4, my new introduction to *The Limits of the City* (Montreal:
Black Rose Books, 1986), where the article is republished, and my forthcoming
book *Urbanization Without Cities* (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1986).
What I have tried to summarize are the issues and ideas that
have come to the forefront of society since *Post-Scarcity Anarchism* was published. There was no environmental movement
when I wrote âEcology and Revolutionary Thoughtâ (1964);
no âappropriate technologyâ movement when I wrote âToward
a Liberatory Technologyâ (1965); no communitarian movement
of a political nature when I wrote âThe Forms of Freedomâ
(1968). It should be kept in mind that proposals for using solar
and wind energy, for example, had been abandoned by specialists
in the field when my essay on technology was written, and no
serious attention was given to community as a political phenomenon when I explored the need for liberatory institutions.
For the traditional Left, these issues could have existed on the
moon. Not only would it take a decade or more for Marxists
to regard these issues as more than trivial but to desist from
treating them as âpetty bourgeoisâ at best or outright âreactionaryâ at worst.
For the most part, my ideas since writing
book. There is very little I would want to discard since it was
written. Rather, I have elaborated ideas that were dealt with
in a fairly scanty fashion. Thus, I would want to develop
âForms of Freedomâ to include my ideas on libertarian municipalism, deepen my criticism of Marxism in âListen, Marxist!â and expand my discussion of technics and work in
âTowards a Liberatory Technology.â I would want to excise
my use of Brechtâs recipe for cynical socialism in the closing
lines of the essay and temper the importance 1 gave the technological âpreconditionsâ for freedom.
Do I hold that the abolition of âscarcityâ is such a âpreconditionâ in the *historic* sense emphasized by Marx? My
acceptance of this view, largely an inheritance of Marxists
who deeply influenced my thinking in the fifties, is not as
unqualified as it would seem to be in a quick reading of the
book. The original introduction, it should be noted, deals with
scarcity more as a contemporary issue than a historical one.
As I note: âWhether this long and tortuous development [around
material scarcity] could have followed a different, more benign,
course is now irrelevant. The development is now behind usâ
(p. 10). This equivocal statement was deliberately introduced
fifteen years ago because I was doubtful about the concept of
scarcity in a historical sense even as I seemed to argue for its
role in many parts of the book. Viewed as a drama of history
that our era has resolved technologically, I would have to say
that such an interpretation is now unsatisfactory in my eyes,
although the role of material deprivation in the past cannot be
ignored. Yet I would still title this book *Post-Scarcity Anarchism*
if I were to rewrite it. Capitalism is more of an economy than
a society, as Karl Polanyi pointed out years ago. In dissolving
most of the cultural, traditional, and ideological ties that kept
needs under a measure of control, the market system has created
a phenomenon that never existed in precapitalist or traditional
society as a whole: a fetishization of needs, not only Marxâs
celebrated âfetishization of commodities.â As I indicate in
force, not a subjective force. They become blind in the same
sense that the production of commodities becomes blind... To
break the grip of the âfetishization of needs,â to dispel it, is to
recover the *freedom of choice*, a project that is tied to the
freedom of the *self* to choose.â[12] Post-scarcity is a âpreconditionâ
under *capitalism* for exorcising the hold of the economy over
society, for creating a sufficiency in goods that permits the
individual to choose what he or she *really* needs or wants, in
short, for demystifying the economic by exploding it from
withinâby sheer abundanceâas an all-presiding agent over
the human condition. Put simply: under capitalism we must
try to achieve a level of abundance that renders abundance
meaningless and permits us to take possession of ourselves as
free people, capable of choosing the lifeways that suit us.
[12] Murray Bookchin: *The Ecology of Freedom* (Palo Alto: Cheshire Books,
1982), pp. 68â69.
By the same token, *Post-Scarcity Anarchism* does not fetishize
technology. Quite to the contrary: the reader is warned early
on in the book that âTechnology and the resources of abundance
furnish capitalism with the means of assimilating large sections
of society to the established system of hierarchy and authority.
They provide the system with the weaponry, the detecting
devices and the propaganda media for the threat as well as the
reality of massive repression. By their centralistic nature, the
resources of abundance reinforce the monopolistic, centralistic
and bureaucratic tendencies in the political apparatus. In short,
they furnish the State with historically unprecedented means
for manipulating and mobilizing the entire environment of lifeâand
for perpetuating hierarchy, exploitation, and unfreedomâ
Lest my emphasis on the liberatory potential of technology
be mistaken as an argument for technocracy, the essay âTowards
a Liberatory Technologyâ introduced themes that have taken
on vastly greater significance over the years. The image that
technology is now a matter of systematic design, not simply
of inspired invention; the enormous range of uses to which
âcybernatedâ devices lend themselves; the use of terms like
âminiaturizationâ to apply to technology as a whole; the notion
that there is an ecological approach to technology that takes
the form of ensembles of productive units, energized by solar
and windpower unitsâall, taken together, are still pioneering
concepts. They have yet to be fully assimilated by many environmentalists. The argument that we must recover local regional resources that were abandoned with the rise of a national
division of labor is a pillar of the best bioregional thinking of
the eighties. Finally, âThe Forms of Freedom,â written seventeen years ago, still constitutes the basis for my views on
libertarian municipalism (including the assembly as the authentic
basis for democracy) and for my criticism of syndicalism.
There is much I hope to expand in this essay in a future book
that will bear the same title. But there is little I would want
to change in it.
Limitations of space do allow me to itemize point by point
the ideas that are as relevant today as they were in the sixties.
Apart from my qualifying remarks on scarcity and my use of
words like âpreconditions,â *Post-Scarcity Anarchism* forms
an indispensable introduction to views I have elaborated in
later books and articles. Nor do I have any reason to eschew
the word âanarchist.â The libertarian tradition is as close to
me as it was two decades ago and I freely align with it as a
proponent, despite criticisms I have voiced of certain tendencies
within it. Its persistence is a deserved one. And the many
people in the ecology movement, not to speak of those on the
Left who acknowledge their debt to this tradition, as well as
those who use it without attribution, are living evidence of its
value for later generations.
Changing shifts in the world economy and technology have
made a number of items in the book somewhat dated. The
United States is no longer the producer of âmore than half of
the worldâs goodâ (pages 23 and 64), but rather a good deal
less than a third. This relative decline, however, has not altered
my view that it is the âkeystoneâ in the imperial arch of world
capitalism. Although its specific weight in production has diminished economically, its strategic position as a technological
innovator and its military power is as great as ever. Nor can
we judge the leading role a country can play by production
figures at any given time, as the Axis powers discovered to
their grief during the Second World War when a depression-ridden America with some of the lowest production figures per
capita in the world entered the war.
As to details: we can no longer speak of the need to increase
electric-power production fivefold in the remaining years of
the century. The estimates are now much smaller.
Research on thermoelectric junctions has been supplanted by
photoelectric junctions as of this writing. Electric
cars, with their demands for electric power, might do more to
increase pollution from power plants than to diminish it.
My inclusion of nuclear fuels as part of a mosaic of energy
sources was perhaps understandable two decades ago, especially
since I had so-called âcleanâ thermonuclear sources in mind,
but it now cuts across the entire grain of my thinkng.
The DDP-124 computer runs at 1.75 million cycles a second,
not 1.75 âbillion.â Whether this was a typographical error, I
do not know, but in any case it is wrong.[13]
[13] I wish to thank Laurence Moore of Ramparts Press for singling out most
of these errors in the book. Other observations which Larry made are interesting
enough, but they are largely differences about our interpetation of social
issues rather than mistakes of fact.
I have been warned by a publisher that the student-worker
movement that developed in France during MayâJune 1968 has
all but been forgotten and my comments on it have little relevance. Here, I feel obliged to emphasize that the contemporaneity of an event is no guide to whether it should or should
not be discussed. Not only has an entire generation described
itself as the âpeople of â68,â particularly in Europe, where
the year and its events are regarded as the highpoint of the
sixties; the â68 events themselves are too important in terms
of the message they offered and the way they unfolded to be
neglected. The failure of that great movement is no reason for
forgetfulness but, to the contrary, reason for the most searching
analyses. The two short pieces on âMayâJune,â as it was
called nearly twenty years ago, provide only part of such an
analysis but one that is indispensable to a discussion of the
way in which social movements develop in our era and the
way in which they may unfold in the future.
The intellectual and political elaborations I have made since
develop here. My criticisms of Marxism, which were anticipatory
by any standards, have become more complex and fundamental
since the publication of âListen, Marxist!â Yet, on rereading
this work, I find that it is as relevant today as it was when it
first appeared at the crucial SDS convention of June 1969. The
work is still being republished and its impact on potential
converts to Marxism is still as powerful as it was many years
ago. More elaborate criticisms for which the essay lays the
basis appear in *Toward an Ecological Society* and *The Ecology of Freedom*. My prediction in the pamphlet that soldiers could
play a revolutionary role, not simply workers, was to acquire
flesh-and-blood dimensions in Portugal, when rank-and-file
troops proved to be more revolutionary than many socialists
and their working-class followers. âListen, Marxist!â it should
be noted, was never seriously challenged by the Marxist press
in the sixties and seventies. Despite its enormous distribution,
it was carefully enveloped in a conspiracy of silence which
persists to this very day. Indeed, many of its ideas were simply
appropriated by so-called âneo-Marxistsâ years after its publication and hybridized with elements of the Marxian canon.
Since the publication of *Post-Scarcity Anarchism* my development of social ecology has moved ahead by enormous strides
and now includes works on nature philosophy, ecological ethics,
criticisms of sociobiology and other reactionary forms of biologism, and a more ecological approach to natural evolution.
My views on technology and social reconstruction, particularly
ecological politics based on libertarian municipalism, fill
hundreds of pages in *Towards an Ecological Society*, *The Ecology of Freedom*, the Black Rose edition of *The Limits of the City*, and my latest book, *The Modern Crisis*, a common
venture of Black Rose Books in Canada and New Society
Publishers and the Institute for Social Ecology in the United
States. Lastly, my book *Urbanization Without Cities* will be
published as of this writing by Sierra Club Books in San Francisco. This volume develops themes to which *The Limits of the City* forms an indispensable introduction. The two books
complement each other and should be explored by readers who
are interested in an ecological interpretation of politics and the
recovery of genuine citizenship.
I have found âpurityâ nowhere in this world except in the
mature music of Mozart and the moral probity of Fermin Salvochea, the Spanish anarchist âsaint.â Every idea advanced
in this book is, in some sense, very âimpureââand, worse,
has its antithesis in ideas and movements that are grossly wrong.
Social ecology, a term that is already finding its way into the
academic mainstream, is being cheapened by its antithesis in
sociobiology, antihumanism, and outright ecofascism. Nature
philosophy, such as I have advanced in my own writings, has
its antithesis in an all-inclusive application of systems theory,
reductionism as a mystique of a universal âOneness,â a myth
of âinterconnectednessâ that loses sight of all distinctions or
âmediationsâ (to use Hegelâs term), and outright appeals to
âblood-and-soilâ chauvinism or dialectical materialism. An
ecological ethics based on freedom has its antithesis in deterministic doctrines of ânatural law,â the âmorality of the gene,â
social Darwinism, and the ethics of the âlifeboatâ and âtriage.â
Libertarian visions of community and politics have their antithesis
in parliamentary politics, party organization, and electoral mobilization as distinguished from education. There is no magic
strategy or pure dogma that provides us with principles or a
practice that stands above the conflicts between right and wrong
or good and evilâunless it is so far removed from the real
world that it is insulated by distance and marginality from the
taint of experience. I do not have to be reminded that social
ecology can breed its opposite in utterly reactionary perversions
of its truth. Or that it can be coopted in name and tarnished
in spirit. Much of my life has been devoted to writing critical
articles against those who pervert or infiltrate authentically
ecological views with utterly alien notions that have been bred
by explicit reactionaries as well as self-styled âradicals.â
What the sixties should teach us, then, is that there is no
substitute for consciousness. Truth will emerge only from insight,
critical thinking, a reality principle that does not sacrifice principles to opportunistic gains, a moral probity that can resist
descent into the surrender of ideals. Education remains on the
order of the dayâindeed, more so today than earlier because
of the complexity of our problems and the massive drift toward
intellectual vulgarity.
What the sixties should also teach us is that a counterculture
is not enoughâimportant as it is. What we need are the firm
skeletal structures to support such a new cultureânotably,
a *political* movement that is libertarian and rescues the word
âpoliticsâ from the ignominy of statecraft. Impure as they
may be, there are still areas of lifeânotably, the municipalitiesâthat can be reclaimed as a new political sphere by an active
citizenry in popular assemblies, confederated, and ultimately
developed into a counterpower with counterinstitutions that
stand opposed to those of the nation-state. The eighties and
sixties now face each other in direct confrontationânot as
conflicting eras that raise opposing alternatives, but as complementary ones that, taken together, provide the opportunity
for fuller alternatives than those which existed twenty years
ago and today. Whether we can bring these complementary
decades together, each of which has so much to give to the
other, in a reconstructive politics that opens a new way to our
present-day impasse will determine the future of this century
and much of the one to come.
Murray Bookchin
September 1985
It is difficult to believe that some forty years have passed since I wrote âEcology and Revolutionary Thought,â one of the most influential works in this collection of 1960s essays. I tried to call the emerging consciousness of an environmental crisis âsocial ecology.â The word **ecology** was meant to emphasize the need for Wholeness, or as Georg LukĂĄcs and the Frankfurt School would have called it, âTotality.â **Social,** in turn, was meant to stand for âsocialism,â of the highly plastic kind that came into vogue during the interwar period, before Stalinism came to represent a cruel bureaucratic dogma. Properly nuanced and explored, the unconventional neo-socialism of LukĂĄcs and the pre-Hitler Eastern European academics imparted to the young Marxâs language a new configurationâa sort of double helix, as I visualized it, in which one strand of the helix (the âlegacy of freedomâ) interacted dialectically with the other (a developing âlegacy of dominationâ), creating an ever-expanding spiral, hopefully to broaden and encompass freedom at the expense of domination.
This configuration, I believed, would lead to the expansion of freedom at the expense of domination. Dualism would not disappear; indeed, there would be a vital interaction between the two in which what was authoritarian in one legacy would yield the expansion of freedom. Formalistic as this conception of social development must now seem, I was wrestling, in effect, with a problem with which the Marxists of my generation had contended for decades: if historic development is marked by circularity (as Hegel seemed to say a century earlier) and every end is marked by a new, more advanced beginning, what level could a communism that would succeed the âend of historyâ reach? Or was Hegelâs notion of circularity one of those philosophical myths that had to be supplanted by a notion of indefinite âprogressâ or, more dismally, by a gray liberalism of the kind suggested by Francis Fukuyama and his admirers?
My interest in the issue of the âend of historyâ was not metaphysical. When Fukuyamaâs book of that name appeared, the prospect of an end to humanity was not academic. Nuclear weapons, bioweapons, synthetic diseases, not to speak of climatic disruption on a vast scale and the actual extinction of thousands of species all portended the abiding reality of the end of life among advanced species, if not a vast die-off of ecologically sensitive species.
Accordingly, if history is marked by ascending spirals, the kind of society that would replace the modern capitalism was no longer a matter of dystopian speculation. Nothing, to be sure, exists indefinitely. Every society is obliged to consider the certainty of its ultimate demise. Long before nuclear weapons were produced, speculative writers turned their Imagination to the disappearance of humanityâone thinks of Jack London**âs The Scarlet Plague** or H. G. Wellsâs âThe War of the Worlds.â Judging by the tidal wave of fantasy that fills every conceivable form of electronic media today, we might assume that nearly every avenue of communication has been exploited to alert humanity of the likelihood of its self-extinction and every possible means for its extermination.
Ecology, in particular, has become the most realistic source of the new scenarios for supplanting the âinvasions,â âinventions,â and endless variety of methods for achieving our species self-extermination. Indeed, not since the end of the medieval world has the human species devoted so much of its literature and art to depictions of how our species will bring itself to a spectacular end.
Earlier accounts of our demise were represented by artists who saw the human types around them in terms of physical attributes edging on genuine fantasy. They had a simian, and not quite truly human, appearance. Subtle changes seem to have expressed the drift of artistic sensibility toward humanization rather than animalization. In an age of mechanizationâindeed, an Age of Steelâhuman life must cope with the requirements of giant factories, immensely destructive weapons, and murder on a mass scale. We are creating a radically new nature, a **second** nature, one that needs a mythic world of birdlike creatures to act as a counterweight to the harsh first nature from which we are emerging.
This fact alone has given ecology a centrality it never could have had several centuries ago. Ecology deals with the interface between first (âvirginalâ) nature and humanityâs second (âsyntheticâ) nature. In the first place, more than purely environmental issues as chemicals in food, organic gardening, and solar and wind power, ecological issues deal with technology conceptualized not only as a means to an end but as a defining aspect of the end we hope to achieve by such methods.
Installing an array of solar engines, for example, will not resolve our energy problems unless they are integrated into an ecological Whole that is, in a sense, truly a part of a larger environmental horizon. Solar engines
must be seen as a component of the Totality that includes moral, aesthetic, social, institutional, and creative factors, all sensitively interlaced with one another; in short, a technics that forms a unity with values and beauty. Technics, in short, seeks to raise and answer questions that by modern standards of beauty and truth are currently nontechnical, if not antitechnical. As Hegel or Schiller might have put it, they are part of the truth of the world, and are delicately and subtly interlaced with it. With its emphasis on unity in diversity, ecology-specifically social ecology creates a tapestry of life that weaves all the elements of development into a Whole that is ever-expanding and all-encompassing, bringing together the many with the one along a **developing** horizon of phenomena, both subjectively and objectively and, like a fermenting brew, turning the Many into a One without violating the identity of each.
Wedded to socialism, social ecology opens a new ecological terrain that gives it the calling to create a second nature, bringing freedom into the realm of first primeval nature. It not only obliges ecology to play the role of arbiter in refashioning first nature; it sees in first nature the terrain for remaking the world institutionally as well as ethically, along rational political lines. Far from being a neutral domain of knowledge, it is highly partisan and committed to the authentic welfare of life. Here science becomes a politics: it is completely involved in the problems and hopes of the world. Ecology becomes a political movement and, most important, a means for changing the world, not passively observing it.
Finally, social ecology provides the compass for negotiating humanityâs place in the natural world. It reveals the only dialectic that gives meaning to the natural world as a realm where mind can interpret first nature, employ it as a rational guide to an ever-developing wholeness, and use the Whole at every given stage as the means to make the parts meaningful in achieving self-awareness and creativity. In his virtually forgotten book, the great British archeologist of the 1920s and 1930s, V. Gordon Childe, not only wrote an account of the beginning of humanityâs self-consciousness but also showed how this capacity for self consciousness (unknown in any other life-form) took the concrete steps in fashioning a new second nature that reproduced not only old natural laws but also created new ones. In this great transcendental step (an **Aufhebung** equal only to the emergence of life itself) humanity became the principal medium for creating itself.
This was the most advanced form of political economy possible in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, and it was brilliantly critiqued, almost alone, by Karl Marx. Syndicalism was also the most comprehensive form of social theory that could have been devised at that time. Carried to its most simplified conclusion, syndicalism could easily be confused with anarchism, a form of unnuanced nihilism redolent of Artsybashevâs 1907 novel **Sanin,** which totally confused thousands of young Russians in the aftermath of the 1905 Revolution.
There can be no society as such without institutions, systems of governance, and laws. The only issue in question is whether these structures and guidelines are authoritarian or libertarian, for they constitute the very forms of social existence. The state is an ensemble, not of institutions as such, but of authoritarian institutions (usually controlled by classes), which is where anarchism gets lost in a tangle of highly confused individualistic concepts.
Why, then, did I title this collection **Post-Scarcity. Anarchism** and use that term in the essays within? I must acknowledge that my reasons were primarily propagandistic. The earliest essays in this book were published after I had become disillusioned with Marxist politics and was suffering from a exaggerated hostility to any form of directive radicalism. No less significantly, I was enamored of radical romanticism and myself suffered from a measure of confusion over the enormous differences between syndicalism and anarchism. In the 1970s, under the ubiquitous shadow of modern history, the Russian Revolution, I began to give zealous attention to the Spanish Civil Warâand only then did I nuance my own views and realize how distant were the anarchists and the anarcho-syndicalists from each other. This recognition also made it possible for me to properly situate how much Karl Marxâs writings could contribute to a new synthesis of socialist theory, one that could keep pace with changes that were going on over the past century.
Moreover, I was fortunate in developing a deeper insight into the changes that capitalism was undergoing and how they were producing new questions that required new answers. Of immense importance was the extent to which traditional Marxismâs âbreakdown theoryâ of capitalism was completely wrong. Capitalism, it was apparent to me, would not âdecomposeâ because it had to limit economic growth; rather, It was faced with a permanent breakdown because it was expanding (indeed, coming into its own as a dominant economy) by ravaging the planet and simplifying complex ecosystems, reducing the earthâs capacity to sustain advanced forms of life.
Today this thesis is not novelâit has been heard repeatedly. But when I first advanced it, it was regarded as a distraction from âpressing issuesâ like the class struggle and the coming âproletarian revolutionââconcepts that tenaciously cling to socialist theory like hungry leeches, notwithstanding the fact that history has kept them on hold for a half-century.
Social ecology, it should be emphasized, is not anarchism any more than it is individualism. It is decidedly a new form of libertarian socialism: libertarian in its concept of an organic and âfrom-the-ground-upâ mode of praxis; socialist in its belief that power must be conceived as confederal communities. As Gustav Lefrancais, a Parisian Communard of 1871, declared that he was a communalist, not an anarchist, please.â (See Kropotkinâs **Memoirs of a Revolutionist, G**rove Press, page 393.)
Today, Lefrancais might well have participated in regular municipal elections, as a libertarian municipalist. He might have called for the formation of popular municipal assemblies and tried to coordinate assemblies of municipalities into county-wide municipal confederations with diminishing authority, and into national confederations, each forming a dual power to supplant the parallel state institutions that, as components of the âlegacy of domination,â challenge their existence. A detailed account of a communalist political structure can be found in the closing chapter of my **From Urbanization to Cities..**
The oldest essay in this book, âEcology and Revolutionary Thought,â was published in 1964 in **Comment** and was revised for publication in **Post-Scarcity Anarchism** in 1971. In the early 1960s anarchism was a very scarce commodity in the United States and was preoccupied with refusals to vote with almost dogmatic fervor. I recall that it lived a fragile, almost senile existence in a small room in lower Manhattan; the majority of its members were pensioners, mostly foreign-born, and puzzled by the emerging 1960s âcounterculture.â When I emphasized to them the importance of technological development and the prospects it opened for a materially abundant socialist society, my âtried and tested fellow workersâ (to use the language of the time) denounced me as a Marxist but they might have denounced Diego Abad de SantillĂĄn, the Spanish FAIâs principal theorist in the 1930s, for many of the same reasons
I am pleased that, reprinted as it was repeatedly in anthologies and pamphlets, âEcology and Revolutionary Thoughtâ and âListen, Marxist!â were read by many thousands and led to conversions from standard brands of Social Democracy and even Stalinism to anarchism. The reader should note that âEcology and Revolutionary Thoughtâ was filled with predictions that have never been acknowledged, notably, that the use of fossil fuels would produce âa growing blanket of carbon dioxideâ and, âby intercepting heat radiated by the earth, (would) lead to more destructive storm patterns and, eventually, to melting of the polar ice caps, rising sea levels, and the inundation of vast land areasâ (page 60). I warned of toxic wastes in water and on land and many of the ills that beset the planet today. These predictions were unheard of at the time and have never been duly accredited.
A year later âToward a Liberatory Technology,â my account of the social and technological alternatives to the sources of the âecological crisis,â as I called it then, was less widely read but was widely pilfered. The world was afflicted by the pop rubbish of âradical ecologists,â exotic technicians and biologists like Buckminster Fuller, Barry Commoner, and the like, who in my view became celebrities more than serious social theorists. People who can on Monday applaud Paul Ehrlich, who flaunted neo-Malthusian opinions, then suddenly denounce the same neo-Malthusian views on Tuesday have hardly earned my admiration. But such is the way of the world, as my seventy years of active radicalism have taught me.
Murray Bookchin
<br>August 20, 2004
All the successful revolutions of the past have been particularistic revolutions of minority classes seeking to assert their specific interests over those of society as a whole. The great bourgeois revolutions of modern times offered an ideology of sweeping political reconstitution, but in reality they merely certified the social dominance of the bourgeoisie, giving formal political expression to the economic ascendancy of capital. The lofty notions of the ânation,â the âfree citizen,â of equality before the law,â concealed the mundane reality of the centralized state, the atomized isolated man, the dominance of bourgeois interest. Despite their sweeping ideological claims, the particularistic revolutions replaced the rule of one class by another, one system of exploitation by another, one system of toil by another, and one system of psychological repression by another.
What is unique about our era is that the particularistic revolution has now been subsumed by the possibility of the generalized revolutionâcomplete and totalistic. Bourgeois society, if it achieved nothing else, revolutionized the means of production on a scale unprecedented in history. This technological revolution, culminating in cybernation, has created the objective, quantitative basis for a world without class rule, exploitation, toil or material want. The means now exist for the development of the rounded man, the total man, freed of guilt and the workings of authoritarian modes of training, and given over to desire and the sensuous apprehension of the marvelous. It is now possible to conceive of manâs future experience in terms of a coherent process in which the bifurcations of thought and activity, mind and sensuousness, discipline and spontaneity, individuality and community, man and nature, town and country, education and life, work and play are all resolved, harmonized, and organically wedded in a qualitatively new realm of freedom. Just as the particularized revolution produced a particularized, bifurcated society, so the generalized revolution can produce an organically unified, many-sided community. The great wound opened by propertied society in the form of the âsocial questionâ can now be healed.
That freedom must be conceived of in human terms, not in animal termsâin terms of life, not of survivalâis clear enough. Men do not remove their ties of bondage and become fully human merely by divesting themselves of social domination and obtaining freedom in its *abstract* form. They must also be free *concretely*: free from material want, from toil, from the burden of devoting the greater part of their timeâindeed, the greater part of their livesâto the struggle with necessity. To have seen these material preconditions for human freedom, to have emphasized that freedom presupposes free time and the material abundance for abolishing free time as a social privilege, is the great contribution of Karl Marx to modern revolutionary theory.
By the same token, the *preconditions* for freedom must not be mistaken for the *conditions* of freedom. The *possibility* of liberation does not constitute its *reality*. Along with its positive aspects, technological advance has a distinctly negative, socially regressive side. If it is true that technological progress enlarges the historical potentiality for freedom, it is also true that the bourgeois control of technology reinforces the established organization of society and everyday life. Technology and the resources of abundance furnish capitalism with the means for assimilating large sections of society to the established system of hierarchy and authority. They provide the system with the weaponry, the detecting devices and the propaganda media for the threat as well as the reality of massive repression. By their centralistic nature, the resources of abundance reinforce the monopolistic, centralistic and bureaucratic tendencies in the political apparatus. In short, they furnish the state with historically unprecedented means for manipulating and mobilizing the entire environment of lifeâand for perpetuating hierarchy, exploitation and unfreedom.
It must be emphasized, however, that this manipulation and mobilization of the environment is extremely problematical and laden with crises. Far from leading to pacification (one can hardly speak, here, of harmonization), the attempt of bourgeois society to control and exploit its environment, natural as well as social, has devastating consequences. Volumes have been written on the pollution of the atmosphere and waterways, on the destruction of tree cover and soil, and on toxic materials in foods and liquids. Even more threatening in their final results are the pollution and destruction of the very ecology required for a complex organism like man. The concentration of radioactive wastes in living things is a menace to the health and genetic endowment of nearly all species. Worldwide contamination by pesticides that inhibit oxygen production in plankton or by the near-toxic level of lead from gasoline exhaust are examples of an enduring pollution that threatens the biological integrity of all advanced lifeformsâincluding man.
No less alarming is the fact that we must drastically revise our traditional notions of what constitutes an environmental pollutant. A few decades ago it would have been absurd to describe carbon dioxide and heat as pollutants in the customary sense of the term. Yet both may well rank among the most serious sources of future ecological imbalance and may pose major threats to the viability of the planet. As a result of industrial and domestic combustion activities, the quantity of carbon dioxide in the atmosphere has increased by roughly twenty-five percent in the past one hundred years, and may well double by the end of the century. The famous âgreenhouse effectâ which the increasing quantity of the gas is expected to produce has been widely discussed in the media; eventually, it is supposed, the gas will inhibit the dissipation of the worldâs heat into space, causing a rise in overall temperatures which will melt the polar ice caps and result in the inundation of vast coastal areas. Thermal pollution, the result mainly of warm water discharged by nuclear and conventional power plants, has had disastrous effects on the ecology of lakes, rivers and estuaries. Increases in water temperature not only damage the physiological and reproductive activities of the fish, they also promote the great blooms of algae that have become such formidable problems in waterways.
Ecologically, bourgeois exploitation and manipulation are undermining the very capacity of the earth to sustain advanced forms of life. The crisis is being heightened by massive increases in air and water pollution; by a mounting accumulation of nondegradable wastes, lead residues, pesticide residues and toxic additives in food; by the expansion of cities into vast urban belts; by increasing stresses due to congestion, noise and mass living; and by the wanton scarring of the earth as a result of mining operations, lumbering, and real estate speculation. As a result, the earth has been despoiled in a few decades on a scale that is unprecedented in the entire history of human habitation of the planet. Socially, bourgeois exploitation and manipulation have brought everyday life to the most excruciating point of vacuity and boredom. As society has been converted into a factory and a marketplace, the very rationale of life has been reduced to production for its own sakeâand consumption for its own sake.[14]
[14] It is worth noting here that the emergence of the âconsumer societyâ provides us with remarkable evidence of the difference between the industrial capitalism of Marxâs time and state capitalism today. In Marxâs view, capitalism as a system organized around âproduction for the sake of productionâ results in the economic immiseration of the proletariat. âProduction for the sake of productionâ is paralleled today by âconsumption for the sake of consumption,â in which immiseration takes a spiritual rather than an economic formâit is starvation of life.
Is there a redemptive dialectic that can guide the social development in the direction of an anarchic society where people will attain full control over their daily lives? Or does the social dialectic come to an end with capitalism, its possibilities sealed off by the use of a highly advanced technology for repressive and co-optative purposes?
We must learn here from the limits of Marxism, a project which, understandably in a period of material scarcity, anchored the social dialectic and the contradictions of capitalism in the economic realm. Marx, it has been emphasized, examined the *preconditions for* liberation, not the *conditions of* liberation. The Marxian critique is rooted in the past, in the era of material want and relatively limited technological development. Even its humanistic theory of alienation turns primarily on the issue of work and manâs alienation from the product of his labor. Today, however, capitalism is a parasite on the future, a vampire that survives on the technology and resources of freedom.
The industrial capitalism of Marxâs time organized its commodity relations around a prevailing system of material scarcity; the state capitalism of our time organizes its commodity relations around a prevailing system of material abundance. A century ago, scarcity had to be endured; today, it has to be enforcedâhence the importance of the state in the present era. It is not that modern capitalism has resolved its contradictions[15] and annulled the social dialectic, but rather that the social dialectic and the contradictions of capitalism have expanded from the economic to the hierarchical realms of society, from the abstract âhistoricâ domain to the concrete minutiae of everday experience, from the arena of survival to the arena of life.
[15] The economic contradictions of capitalism have not disappeared, but the system can plan to such a degree that they no longer have the explosive characteristics they had in the past.
The dialectic of bureaucratic state capitalism originates in the contradiction between the repressive character of commodity society and the enormous potential freedom opened by technological advance. This contradiction also opposes the exploitative organization of society to the natural worldâa world that includes not only the natural environment, but also manâs ânatureââhis Eros-derived impulses. The contradiction between the exploitative organization of society and the natural environment is beyond co-optation: the atmosphere, the waterways, the soil and the ecology required for human survival are not redeemable by reforms, concessions, or modifications of strategic policy. There is no technology that can reproduce atmospheric oxygen in sufficient quantities to sustain life on this planet. There is no substitute for the hydrological systems of the earth. There is no technique for removing massive environmental pollution by radioactive isotopes, pesticides, lead and petroleum wastes. Nor is there the faintest evidence that bourgeois society will relent at any time in the foreseeable future in its disruption of vital ecological processes, in its exploitation of natural resources, in its use of the atmosphere and waterways as dumping areas for wastes, or in its cancerous mode of urbanization and land abuse.
Even more immediate is the contradiction between the exploitative organization of society and manâs Eros-derived impulsesâa contradiction that manifests itself as the banalization and impoverishment of experience in a bureaucratically manipulated, impersonal mass society. The Eros-derived impulses in man can be repressed and sublimated, but they can never be eliminated. They are renewed with every birth of a human being and with every generation of youth. It is not surprising today that the young, more than any economic class or stratum, articulate the life-impulses in humanityâs natureâthe urgings of desire, sensuousness, and the lure of the marvelous. Thus, the biological matrix, from which hierarchical society emerged ages ago, reappears at a new level with the era that marks the end of hierarchy, only now this matrix is saturated with social phenomena. Short of manipulating humanityâs germplasm, the life-impulses can be annulled only with the annihilation of man himself.
The contradictions within bureaucratic state capitalism permeate all the hierarchical forms developed and overdeveloped by bourgeois society. The hierarchical forms which nurtured propertied society for ages and promoted its developmentâthe state, city, centralized economy, bureaucracy, patriarchal family, and marketplaceâhave reached their historic limits. They have exhausted their social functions as modes of stabilization. It is not a question of whether these hierarchical forms were ever âprogressiveâ in the Marxian sense of the term. As Raoul Vaneigem has observed: âPerhaps it isnât enough to say that hierarchical power has preserved humanity for thousands of years as alcohol preserves a fetus, by arresting either growth or decay.â{3} Today these forms constitute the target of all the revolutionary forces that are generated by modern capitalism, and whether one sees their outcome as nuclear catastrophe or ecological disaster *they now threaten the very survival of humanity*.
With the development of hierarchical forms into a threat to the very existence of humanity, the social dialectic, far from being annulled, acquires a new dimension. It poses the âsocial questionâ in an entirely new way. If man had to acquire the conditions of survival in order to live (as Marx emphasized), now he must acquire the conditions of life in order to survive. By this inversion of the relationship between survival and life, revolution acquires a new sense of urgency. No longer are we faced with Marxâs famous choice of socialism or barbarism; we are confronted with the more drastic alternatives of anarchism or annihilation. The problems of necessity and survival have become congruent with the problems of freedom and life. They cease to require any theoretical mediation, âtransitionalâ stages, or centralized organizations to bridge the gap between the existing and the possible. The possible, in fact, is all that can exist. Hence, the problems of âtransition,â which occupied the Marxists for nearly a century, are eliminated not only by the advance of technology, but by the social dialectic itself. The problems of social reconstruction have been reduced to practical tasks that can be solved spontaneously by self-liberatory acts of society.
Revolution, in fact, acquires not only a new sense of urgency, but a new sense of promise. In the hippiesâ tribalism, in the drop-out lifestyles and free sexuality of millions of youth, in the spontaneous affinity groups of the anarchists, we find forms of affirmation that follow from acts of negation. With the inversion of the âsocial questionâ there is also an inversion of the social dialectic; a âyeaâ emerges automatically and simultaneously with a ânay.â
The solutions take their point of departure from the problems. When the time has arrived in history that the state, the city, bureaucracy, the centralized economy, the patriarchal family and the marketplace have reached their historic limits, what is posed is no longer a change in form but the absolute negation of *all* hierarchical forms *as such*. The absolute negation of the state is anarchismâa situation in which men liberate not only âhistory,â but all the immediate circumstances of their everyday lives. The absolute negation of the city is communityâa community in which the social environment is decentralized into rounded, ecologically balanced communes. The absolute negation of bureaucracy is immediate as distinguished from mediated relationsâa situation in which representation is replaced by face-to-face relations in a general assembly of free individuals. The absolute negation of the centralized economy is regional ecotechnologyâa situation in which the instruments of production are molded to the resources of an ecosystem. The absolute negation of the patriarchal family is liberated sexualityâin which all forms of sexual regulation are transcended by the spontaneous, untrammeled expression of eroticism among equals. The absolute negation of the marketplace is communismâin which collective abundance and cooperation transform labor into play and need into desire.
It is not accidental that at a point in history when hierarchical power and manipulation have reached their most threatening proportions, the very concepts of hierarchy, power and manipulation are being brought into question. The challenge to these concepts comes from a rediscovery of the importance of spontaneityâa rediscovery nourished by ecology, by a heightened conception of self-development, and by a new understanding of the revolutionary process in society.
What ecology has shown is that balance in nature is achieved by organic variation and complexity, not by homogeneity and simplification. For example, the more varied the flora and fauna of an ecosystem, the more stable the population of a potential pest. The more environmental diversity is diminished, the greater will the population of a potential pest fluctuate, with the probability that it will get out of control. Left to itself, an ecosystem tends spontaneously toward organic differentiation, greater variety of flora and fauna, and diversity in the number of prey and predators. This does not mean that interference by man must be avoided. The need for a productive agricultureâitself a form of interference with natureâmust always remain in the foreground of an ecological approach to food cultivation and forest management. No less important is the fact that man can often produce changes in an ecosystem that would vastly improve its ecological quality.
But these efforts require insight and understanding, not the exercise of brute power and manipulation.
This concept of management, this new regard for the importance of spontaneity, has far-reaching applications for technology and communityâindeed, for the social image of man in a liberated society. It challenges the capitalist ideal of agriculture as a factory operation, organized around immense, centrally controlled land-holdings, highly specialized forms of monoculture, the reduction of the terrain to a factory floor, the substitution of chemical for organic processes, the use of gang-labor, etc. If food cultivation is to be a mode of cooperation with nature rather than a contest between opponents, the agriculturist must become thoroughly familiar with the ecology of the land; he must acquire a new sensitivity to its needs and possibilities. This presupposes the reduction of agriculture to a human scale, the restoration of moderate-sized agricultural units, and the diversification of the agricultural situation; in short, it presupposes a decentralized, ecological system of food cultivation.
The same reasoning applies to pollution control. The development of giant factory complexes and the use of single or dual-energy sources are responsible for atmospheric pollution. Only by developing smaller industrial units and diversifying energy sources by the extensive use of clean power (solar, wind and water power) will it be possible to reduce industrial pollution. The means for this radical technological change are now at hand. Technologists have developed miniaturized substitutes for large-scale industrial operationâsmall versatile machines and sophisticated methods for converting solar, wind and water energy into power usable in industry and the home. These substitutes are often more productive and less wasteful than the large-scale facilities that exist today.[16]
[16] For a detailed discussion of this âminiaturizedâ technology see âTowards a Liberatory Technology.â
The implications of small-scale agriculture and industry for a community are obvious: if humanity is to use the principles needed to manage an ecosystem, the basic communal unit of social life must itself become an ecosystemâan ecocommunity. It too must become diversified, balanced and well-rounded. By no means is this concept of community motivated exclusively by the need for a lasting balance between man and the natural world; it also accords with the Utopian ideal of the rounded man, the individual whose sensibilities, range of experience and lifestyle are nourished by a wide range of stimuli, by a diversity of activities, and by a social scale that always remains within the comprehension of a single human being. Thus the means and conditions of survival become the means and conditions of life; need becomes desire and desire becomes need. The point is reached where the greatest social decomposition provides the source of the highest form of social integration, bringing the most pressing ecological necessities into a common focus with the highest Utopian ideals.
If it is true, as Guy Debord observes, that âdaily life is the measure of everything: of the fulfillment or rather the non-fulfillment of human relationships, of the use we make of our time,â{4} a question arises: Who are âwe whose daily lives are to be fulfilled? And how does the liberated self emerge that is capable of turning time into life, space into community, and human relationships into the marvelous?
The liberation of the self involves, above all, a social process. In a society that has shriveled the self into a commodityâinto an object manufactured for exchangeâthere can be no fulfilled self. There can only be the beginnings of selfhood, the *emergence* of a self that seeks fulfillmentâa self that is largely defined by the obstacles it must overcome to achieve realization. In a society whose belly is distended to the bursting point with revolution, whose chronic state is an unending series of labor pains, whose real condition is a mounting emergency, only one thought and act is relevantâgiving birth. Any environment, private or social, that does not make this fact the center of human experience is a sham and diminishes whatever self remains to us after we have absorbed our daily poison of everyday life in bourgeois society.
It is plain that the goal of revolution today must be the liberation of daily life. Any revolution that fails to achieve this goal is counterrevolution. Above all, it is *we* who have to be liberated, *our* daily lives, with all their moments, hours and days, and not universals like âHistoryâ and âSociety.â[17]
The self must always be *identifiable* in the revolution, not overwhelmed by it. The self must always be *perceivable* in the revolutionary process, not submerged by it. There is no word that is more sinister in the ârevolutionaryâ vocabulary than âmasses.â Revolutionary liberation must be a self-liberation that reaches social dimensions, not âmass liberationâ or âclass liberationâ behind which lurks the rule of an elite, a hierarchy and a state. If a revolution fails to produce a new society by the self-activity and self-mobilization of revolutionaries, if it does not involve the forging of a self in the revolutionary process, the revolution will once again circumvent those whose lives are to be lived every day and leave daily life unaffected. Out of the revolution must emerge a self that takes full possession of daily life, not a daily life that once again takes full possession of the self. The most advanced form of class consciousness thus becomes self-consciousnessâthe concretization in daily life of the great liberating universals.
[17] Despite its lip service to the dialectic, the traditional left has yet to take Hegelâs âconcrete universalâ seriously and see it not merely as a philosophical concept but as a social program. This has been done only in Marxâs early writings, in the writings of the great Utopians (Fourier and William Morris) and, in our time, by the drop-out youth.
If for this reason alone, the revolutionary movement is profoundly concerned with lifestyle. It must try to *live* the revolution in all its totality, not only participate in it. It must be deeply concerned with the way the revolutionist lives, his relations with the surrounding environment, and his degree of self-emancipation. In seeking to change society, the revolutionist cannot avoid changes in himself that demand the reconquest of his own being. Like the movement in which he participates, the revolutionist must try to reflect the conditions of the society he is trying to achieveâat least to the degree that this is possible today.
The treacheries and failures of the past half century have made it axiomatic that there *can be no separation of the revolutionary process from the revolutionary goal*. A society whose fundamental aim is self-administration in all facets of life can be achieved only by self-activity. This implies a mode of administration that is always possessed by the self. The power of man over man can be destroyed only by the very process in which man acquires power over his own life and in which he not only âdiscoversâ himself but, more meaningfully, in which he formulates his selfhood in all its social dimensions.
A libertarian society can be achieved only by a libertarian revolution. Freedom cannot be âdeliveredâ to the individual as the âend-productâ of a ârevolutionâ; the assembly and community cannot be legislated or decreed into existence. A revolutionary group can seek, purposively and consciously, to promote the creation of these forms, but if assembly and community are not allowed to emerge organically, if their growth is not matured by the process of demassification, by self-activity and by self-realization, they will remain nothing but forms, like the Soviets in postrevolutionary Russia. Assembly and community must arise within the revolutionary process; indeed, the revolutionary process must be the formation of assembly and community, and also the destruction of power, property, hierarchy and exploitation.
Revolution as self-activity is not unique to our time. It is the paramount feature of all the great revolutions in modern history. It marked the *journĂ©es* of the *sans-culottes* in 1792 and 1793, the famous âFive Daysâ of February 1917 in Petrograd, the uprising of the Barcelona proletariat in 1936, the early days of the Hungarian Revolution in 1956, and the MayâJune events in Paris in 1968. Nearly every revolutionary uprising in the history of our time has been initiated spontaneously by the self-activity of âmassesââoften in flat defiance of the hesitant policies advanced by the revolutionary organizations. Every one of these revolutions has been marked by extraordinary individuation, by a joyousness and solidarity that turned everyday life into a festival. This surreal dimension of the revolutionary process, with its explosion of deep-seated libidinal forces, grins irascibly through the pages of history like the face of a satyr on shimmering water. It is not without reason that the Bolshevik commissars smashed the wine bottles in the Winter Palace on the night of November 7, 1917.
The puritanism and work ethic of the traditional left stem from one of the most powerful forces opposing revolution todayâthe capacity of the bourgeois environment to infiltrate the revolutionary framework. The origins of this power lie in the commodity nature of man under capitalism, a quality that is almost automatically transferred to the organized groupâand which the group, in turn, reinforces in its members. As the late Josef Weber emphasized, all organized groups âhave the tendency to render themselves autonomous, i.e., to alienate themselves from their original aim and to become an end in themselves in the hands of those administering them.â{5} This phenomenon is as true of revolutionary organizations as it is of state and semi-state institutions, official parties and trade unions.
The problem of alienation can never be completely resolved apart from the revolutionary process itself, but it can be guarded against by an acute awareness that the problem exists, and partly solved by a voluntary but drastic remaking of the revolutionary and his group. This remaking can only begin when the revolutionary group recognizes that it is a catalyst in the revolutionary process, not a âvanguard.â The revolutionary group must clearly see that its goal is not the seizure of power but the dissolution of powerâindeed, it must see that the entire problem of power, of control from below and control from above, can be solved only if there is no above or below.
Above all, the revolutionary group must divest itself of the forms of powerâstatutes, hierarchies, property, prescribed opinions, fetishes, paraphernalia, official etiquetteâand of the subtlest as well as the most obvious of bureaucratic and bourgeois traits that consciously and unconsciously reinforce authority and hierarchy. The group must remain open to public scrutiny not only in its formulated decisions but also in their very formulation. It must be coherent in the profound sense that its theory is its practice and its practice its theory. It must do away with all commodity relations in its day-to-day existence and constitute itself along the decentralizing organizational principles of the very society it seeks to achieveâcommunity, assembly, spontaneity. It must, in Josef Weberâs superb words, be âmarked always by simplicity and clarity, always thousands of unprepared people can enter and direct it, always it remains transparent to and controlled by all.â{6} Only then, when the revolutionary movement is congruent with the decentralized community it seeks to achieve, can it avoid becoming another elitist obstacle to the social development and dissolve into the revolution like surgical thread into a healing wound.
The most important process going on in America today is the sweeping de-institutionalization of the bourgeois social structure. A basic, far-reaching disrespect and a profound disloyalty are developing toward the values, the forms, the aspirations and, above all, the institutions of the established order. On a scale unprecedented in American history, millions of people are shedding their commitment to the society in which they live. They no longer believe in its claims. They no longer respect its symbols. They no longer accept its goals, and, most significantly, they refuse almost intuitively to live by its institutional and social codes.
This growing refusal runs very deep. It extends from an opposition to war into a hatred of political manipulation in all its forms. Starting from a rejection of racism, it brings into question the very existence of hierarchical power as such. In its detestation of middle-class values and lifestyles it rapidly evolves into a rejection of the commodity system; from an irritation with environmental pollution, it passes into a rejection of the American city and modern urbanism. In short, it tends to transcend every particularistic critique of the society and to evolve into a generalized opposition to the bourgeois order on an ever broadening scale.
In this respect, the period in which we live closely resembles the revolutionary Enlightenment that swept through France in the eighteenth centuryâa period that completely reworked French consciousness and prepared the conditions for the Great Revolution of 1789. Then as now, the old institutions were slowly pulverized by molecular action from below long before they were toppled by mass revolutionary action. This molecular movement creates an atmosphere of general lawlessness: a growing personal day-to-day disobedience, a tendency not to âgo alongâ with the existing system, a seemingly âpettyâ but nevertheless critical attempt to circumvent restriction in every facet of daily life. The society, in effect, becomes disorderly, undisciplined, Dionysianâa condition that reveals itself most dramatically in an increasing rate of official crimes. A vast critique of the system developsâthe actual Enlightenment itself, two centuries ago, and the sweeping critique that exists todayâwhich seeps downward and accelerates the molecular movement at the base. Be it an angry gesture, a âriotâ or a conscious change in lifestyle, an ever-increasing number of peopleâwho have no more of a commitment to an organized revolutionary movement than they have to society itselfâbegin spontaneously to engage in their own defiant propaganda of the deed.
In its concrete details, the disintegrating social process is nourished by many sources. The process develops with all the unevenness, indeed with all the contradictions, that mark every revolutionary trend. In eighteenth century France, radical ideology oscillated between a rigid scientism and a sloppy romanticism. Notions of freedom were anchored in a precise, logical ideal of self-control, and also a vague, instinctive norm of spontaneity. Rousseau stood at odds with dâHolbach, Diderot at odds with Voltaire, yet in retrospect we can see that one not only transcended but also presupposed the other in a *cumulative* development toward revolution.
The same uneven, contradictory and cumulative development exists today, and in many cases it follows a remarkably direct course. The âbeatâ movement created the most important breach in the solid, middle-class values of the 1950s, a breach that was widened enormously by the illegalities of pacifists, civil-rights workers, draft resisters and longhairs. Moreover, the merely reactive response of rebellious American youth has produced invaluable forms of libertarian and Utopian affirmationâthe right to make love without restriction, the goal of community, the disavowal of money and commodities, the belief in mutual aid, and a new respect for spontaneity. Easy as it is for revolutionaries to criticize certain pitfalls within this orientation of personal and social values, the fact remains that it has played a preparatory role of decisive importance in forming the present atmosphere of indiscipline, spontaneity, radicalism and freedom.
A second parallel between the revolutionary Enlightenment and our own period is the emergence of the crowd, the so-called âmob,â as a major vehicle of social protest. The typical institutionalized forms of public dissatisfactionâin our own day, they are orderly elections, demonstration and mass meetingsâtend to give way to direct action by crowds. This shift from predictable, highly organized protests within the institutionalized framework of the existing society to sporadic, spontaneous, near-insurrectionary assaults from outside (and even against) socially acceptable forms reflects a profound change in popular psychology. The ârioterâ has begun to break, however partially and intuitively, with those deep-seated norms of behavior which traditionally weld the âmassesâ to the established order. He actively sheds the internalized structure of authority, the long-cultivated body of conditioned reflexes, and the pattern of submission sustained by guilt that tie one to the system even more effectively than any fear of police violence and juridical reprisal. Contrary to the views of social psychologists, who see in these modes of direct action the submission of the individual to a terrifying collective entity called the âmob,â the truth is that âriotsâ and crowd actions represent the first gropings of the mass toward individuation. The mass tends to become demassified in the sense that it begins to assert itself against the really massifying automatic responses produced by the bourgeois family, the school and the mass media. By the same token, crowd actions involve the rediscovery of the streets and the effort to liberate them. Ultimately, it is in the streets that power must be dissolved: for the streets, where daily life is endured, suffered and eroded, and where power is confronted and fought, must be turned into the domain where daily life is enjoyed, created and nourished. The rebellious crowd marked the beginning not only of a spontaneous transmutation of private into social revolt, but also of a return from the abstractions of social revolt to the issues of everyday life.
Finally, as in the Enlightenment, we are seeing the emergence of an immense and ever-growing stratum of **dĂ©classĂ©s,** a body of lumpenized individuals drawn from every stratum of society. The chronically indebted and socially insecure middle classes of our period compare loosely with the chronically insolvent and flighty nobility of prerevolutionary France. A vast flotsam of educated people emerged then as now, living at loose ends, without fixed careers or established social roots. At the bottom of both structures we find a large number of chronic poorâvagabonds, drifters, people with part-time jobs or no jobs at all, threatening, unruly *sans-culottes*âsurviving on public aid and on the garbage thrown off by society, the poor of the Parisian slums, the blacks of the American ghettoes. But here all the parallels end. The French Enlightenment belongs to a period of revolutionary transition from feudalism to capitalismâboth societies based on economic scarcity, class rule, exploitation, social hierarchy and state power. The day-to-day popular resistance which marked the eighteenth century and culminated in open revolution was soon disciplined by the newly emerging industrial orderâas well as by naked force. The vast mass of **dĂ©classĂ©s** and *sans-culottes* was largely absorbed into the factory system and tamed by industrial discipline. Formerly rootless intellectuals and footloose nobles found secure places in the economic, political, social and cultural hierarchy of the new bourgeois order. From a socially and culturally fluid condition, highly generalized in its structure and relations, society hardened again into rigid, particularized class and institutional formsâthe classical Victorian era appeared not only in England but, to one degree or another, in all of Western Europe and America. Critique was consolidated into apologia, revolt into reform, **dĂ©classĂ©s** into clearly defined classes and âmobsâ into political constituencies. âRiotsâ became the well-behaved processionals we call âdemonstrations,â and spontaneous direct action turned into electoral rituals.
Our own era is also a transitional one, but with a profound and new difference. In the last of their great insurrections, the *sans-culottes* of the French Revolution rose under the fiery cry: âBread and the Constitution of â93!â The black *sans-culottes* of the American ghettoes rise under the slogan: âBlack is beautiful!â Between these two slogans lies a development of unprecedented importance. The **dĂ©classĂ©s** of the eighteenth century were formed during a slow transition from an agricultural to an industrial era; they were created out of a pause in the historical transition from one regime of toil to another. The demand for bread could have been heard at any time in the evolution of propertied society. The new **dĂ©classĂ©s** of the twentieth century are being created as a result of the bankruptcy of all social forms based on toil. They are the end products of the process of propertied society itself and of the social problems of material survival. In the era when technological advances and cybernation have brought into question the exploitation of man by man, toil, and material want in any form whatever, the cry âBlack is beautifulâ or âMake love, not warâ marks the transformation of the traditional demand for survival into a historically new demand for life.[18]
What underpins every social conflict in the United States today is the demand for the realization of all human potentialities in a fully rounded, balanced, totalistic way of life. In short, the potentialities for revolution in America are now anchored in the potentialities of man himself.
[18] The above lines were written in 1966. Since then, we have seen the graffiti on the walls of Paris, during the MayâJune revolution: âAll power to the imaginationâ; âI take my desires to be reality, because I believe in the reality of my desiresâ; âNever workâ; âThe more I make love, the more I want to make revolutionâ; âLife without dead timesâ; âThe more you consume, the less you liveâ; âCulture is the inversion of lifeâ; âOne does not buy happiness, one steals itâ; âSociety is a carnivorous flower.â These are not graffiti, they are a program for life and desire.
What we are witnessing is the breakdown of a century and a half of embourgeoisement and a pulverization of all bourgeois institutions **at a point in history when the boldest concepts of Utopia are realizable.** And there is nothing that the present bourgeois order can substitute for the destruction of its traditional institutions but bureaucratic manipulation and state capitalism. This process is unfolding most dramatically in the United States. Within a period of little more than two decades, we have seen the collapse of the âAmerican Dream,â or what amounts to the same thing, the steady destruction in the United States of the myth that material abundance, based on commodity relations between men, can conceal the inherent poverty of bourgeois life. Whether this process will culminate in revolution or in annihilation will depend in great part on the ability of revolutionists to extend social consciousness and defend the spontaneity of the revolutionary development from authoritarian ideologies, both of the âleftâ and of the right.
New York
Oct. 1967âDec. 1968
In almost every period since the Renaissance the development of revolutionary thought has been heavily influenced
by a branch of science, often in conjunction with a school
of philosophy.
Astronomy in the time of Copernicus and Galileo
helped to change a sweeping movement of ideas from the
medieval world, riddled by superstition, into one pervaded
by a critical rationalism and openly naturalistic and
humanistic in outlook. During the Enlightenmentâthe era
that culminated in the French Revolutionâthis liberatory
movement of ideas was reinforced by advances in mechanics and mathematics. The Victorian era was shaken to its
very foundations by evolutionary theories in biology and
anthropology, by Marxâs contributions to political economy, and by Freudian psychology.
In our own time, we have seen the assimilation of
these once-liberatory sciences by the established social
order. Indeed, we have begun to regard science itself as
an instrument of control over the thought processes and
physical being of man. This distrust of science and of the
scientific method is not without justification. âMany
sensitive people, especially artists,â observes Abraham
Maslow, âare afraid that science besmirches and depresses, that it tears things apart rather than integrating
them, thereby killing rather than creating.â{7} What is perhaps equally important, modern science has lost its critical
edge. Largely functional or instrumental in intent, the
branches of science that once tore at the chains of man are
now used to perpetuate and gild them. Even philosophy
has yielded to instrumentalism and tends to be little more
than a body of logical contrivances; it is the handmaiden
of the computer rather than of the revolutionary.
There is one science, however, that may yet restore and
even transcend the liberatory estate of the traditional
sciences and philosophies. It passes rather loosely under
the name âecologyââa term coined by Haeckel a century
ago to denote âthe investigation of the total relations of
the animal both to its inorganic and to its organic environment.â{8} At first glance, Haeckelâs definition is innocuous
enough; and ecology narrowly conceived of as one of
the biological sciences, is often reduced to a variety
of biometrics in which field workers focus on food chains
and statistical studies of animal populations. There is an
ecology of health that would hardly offend the sensibilities
of the American Medical Association and a concept of
social ecology that would conform to the most
well-engineered notions of the New York City Planning
Commission.
Broadly conceived of, however, ecology deals with the
balance of nature. Inasmuch as nature includes man, the
science basically deals with the harmonization of nature
and man. The explosive implications of an ecological approach arise not only because ecology is intrinsically a
critical scienceâcritical on a scale that the most radical
systems of political economy have failed to attainâbut
also because it is an integrative and reconstructive science.
This integrative, reconstructive aspect of ecology, carried
through to all its implications, leads directly into anarchic
areas of social thought. For, in the final analysis, it is
impossible to achieve a harmonization of man and nature
without creating a human community that lives in a lasting
balance with its natural environment.
The critical edge of ecology, a unique feature of the
science in a period of general scientific docility, derives
from its subject matterâfrom its very domain. The issues
with which ecology deals are imperishable in the sense that
they cannot be ignored without bringing into question the
survival of man and the survival of the planet itself. The
critical edge of ecology is due not so much to the power of
human reasonâa power which science hallowed during its
most revolutionary periodsâbut to a still higher power, the
sovereignty of nature. It may be that man is manipulable,
as the owners of the mass media argue, or that elements of
nature are manipulable, as the engineers demonstrate, but
ecology clearly shows that the *totality* of the natural
worldânature viewed in all its aspects, cycles and interrelationshipsâcancels out all human pretensions to mastery
over the planet. The great wastelands of the Mediterranean
basin, once areas of a thriving agriculture or a rich natural
flora, are historic evidence of natureâs revenge against human parasitism.
No historic examples compare in weight and scope with
the effects of manâs despoliationâand natureâs revengeâsince the days of the Industrial Revolution, and especially
since the end of the Second World War. Ancient examples
of human parasitism were essentially local in scope; they
were precisely *examples* of manâs potential for destruction,
and nothing more. Often, they were compensated by remarkable improvements in the natural ecology of a region,
such as the European peasantryâs superb reworking of the
soil during centuries of cultivation and the achievements of
Inca agriculturists in terracing the Andes Mountains during
the pre-Columbian times.
Modern manâs despoliation of the environment is global
in scope, like his imperialisms. It is even extraterrestrial, as
witness the disturbances of the Van Alien Belt a few years
ago. Today human parasitism disrupts more than the atmosphere, climate, water resources, soil, flora and fauna of
a region: it upsets virtually all the basic cycles of nature
and threatens to undermine the stability of the environment on a worldwide scale.
As an example of the scope of modern manâs disruptive
role, it has been estimated that the burning of fossil fuels
(coal and oil) adds 600 million tons of carbon dioxide to
the air annually, about .03 percent of the total atmospheric massâthis, I may add, aside from an incalculable
quantity of toxicants. Since the Industrial Revolution, the
overall atmospheric mass of carbon dioxide has increased
by 25 percent over earlier, more stable, levels. It can be
argued on very sound theoretical grounds that this growing
blanket of carbon dioxide, by intercepting heat radiated
from the earth, will lead to more destructive storm patterns and eventually to melting of the polar ice caps, rising
sea levels, and the inundation of vast land areas. Far removed as such a deluge may be, the changing proportion
of carbon dioxide to other atmospheric gases is a warning
about the impact man is having on the balance of nature.
A more immediate ecological issue is manâs extensive
pollution of the earthâs waterways. What counts here is not
the fact that man befouls a given stream, river or lakeâa
thing he has done for agesâbut rather the magnitude water
pollution has reached in the past two generations. Nearly
all the surface waters of the United States are now polluted. Many American waterways are open cesspools that
properly qualify as extensions of urban sewage systems. It
is a euphemism to describe them as rivers or lakes. More
significantly, large amounts of ground water are sufficiently polluted to be undrinkable, and a number of local
hepatitis epidemics have been traced to polluted wells in
suburban areas. In contrast to surface-water pollution, the
pollution of ground or subsurface water is immensely difficult to eliminate and tends to linger on for decades after
the sources of pollution have been removed.
An article in a mass-circulation magazine appropriately
describes the polluted waterways of the United States as
âOur Dying Waters.â This despairing, apocalyptic description of the water pollution problem in the United States
really applies to the world at large. The waters of the earth
are literally dying. Massive pollution is destroying the
rivers and lakes of Africa, Asia and Latin America, as well
as the long-abused waterways of highly industrialized continents, as media of life. (I speak here not only of radioactive pollutants from nuclear bomb tests and power reactors, which apparently reach all the flora and fauna of the
sea; the oil spills and the discharge of diesel oil have also
become massive pollution problems, claiming marine life in
enormous quantities every year.)
Accounts of this kind can be repeated for virtually every
part of the biosphere. Pages could be written on the immense losses of productive soil that occur annually in almost every continent of the earth; on lethal air pollution
episodes in major urban areas; on the worldwide distribution of toxic agents, such as radioactive isotopes and lead;
on the chemicalization of manâs immediate environmentâone might say his very dinner tableâwith pesticide residues
and food additives. Pieced together like bits of a jigsaw
puzzle, these affronts to the environment form a pattern
of destruction that has no precedent in manâs long history
on earth.
Obviously, man could be described as a highly destructive parasite who threatens to destroy his hostâthe natural
worldâand eventually himself. In ecology, however, the
word âparasiteâ is not an answer to a question, but raises a
question itself. Ecologists know that a destructive parasitism of this kind usually reflects the disruption of an ecological situation; indeed, many species that seem highly
destructive under one set of conditions are eminently useful under another set of conditions. What imparts a profoundly critical function to ecology is the question raised
by manâs destructive abilities: What is the disruption that
has turned man into a destructive parasite? What produces a form of parasitism that results not only in vast natural
imbalances but also threatens the existence of humanity
itself?
Man has produced imbalances not only in nature, but,
more fundamentally, in his relations with his fellow man
and in the very structure of his society. The imbalances
man has produced in the natural world are caused by the
imbalances he has produced in the social world. A century
ago it would have been possible to regard air pollution and
water contamination as the result of the self-seeking activities of industrial barons and bureaucrats. Today, this moral
explanation would be a gross oversimplification. It is
doubtless true that most bourgeois enterprises are still
guided by a public-be-damned attitude, as witness the reactions of power utilities, automobile concerns and steel corporations to pollution problems. But a more serious
problem than the attitude of the owners is the size of the
firms themselvesâtheir enormous proportions, their location in a particular region, their density with respect to a
community or waterway, their requirements for raw materials and water, and their role in the national division of
labor.
What we are seeing today is a crisis in social ecology.
Modern society, especially as we know it in the United
States and Europe, is being organized around immense urban belts, a highly industrialized agriculture and, capping
both, a swollen, bureaucratized, anonymous state apparatus. If we put all moral considerations aside for the moment and examine the physical structure of this society,
what must necessarily impress us is the incredible logistical
problems it is obliged to solveâproblems of transportation,
of density, of supply (of raw materials, manufactured commodities and foodstuffs), of economic and political organization, of industrial location, and so forth. The burden
this type of urbanized and centralized society places on
any continental area is enormous.
The problem runs even deeper. The notion that man must
dominate nature emerges directly from the domination of
man by man. The patriarchal family planted the seed of
domination in the nuclear relations of humanity; the classical split in the ancient world between spirit and realityâindeed, between mind and laborânourished it; the antinaturalist bias of Christianity tended to its growth. But it
was not until organic community relations, feudal or peasant in form, dissolved into market relationships that the
planet itself was reduced to a resource for exploitation.
This centuries-long tendency finds its most exacerbating
development in modern capitalism. Owing to its inherently
competitive nature, bourgeois society not only pits humans against each other, it also pits the mass of humanity
against the natural world. Just as men are converted into
commodities, so every aspect of nature is converted into a
commodity, a resource to be manufactured and merchandised wantonly. The liberal euphemisms for the
processes involved are âgrowth,â âindustrial societyâ and
âurban blight.â By whatever language they are described,
the phenomena have their roots in the domination of man
by man.
The phrase âconsumer societyâ complements the description of the present social order as an âindustrial society.â Needs are tailored by the mass media to create a
public demand for utterly useless commodities, each carefully engineered to deteriorate after a predetermined
period of time. The plundering of the human spirit by the
marketplace is paralleled by the plundering of the earth by
capital. (The liberal identification is a metaphor that neutralizes the social thrust of the ecological crisis.)
Despite the current clamor about population growth,
the strategic ratios in the ecological crisis are not the population growth rates of India but the production rates of the
United States, a country that produces more than half of
the worldâs goods. Here, too, liberal euphemisms like âaffluenceâ conceal the critical thrust of a blunt word like
âwaste.â With a ninth of its industrial capacity committed
to war production, the U.S. is literally trampling upon the
earth and shredding ecological links that are vital to human
survival. If current industrial projections prove to be accurate, the remaining thirty years of the century will witness a fivefold increase in electric power production, based
mostly on nuclear fuels and coal. The colossal burden in
radioactive wastes and other effluents that this increase
will place on the natural ecology of the earth hardly needs
description.
In shorter perspective, the problem is no less disquieting. Within the next five years, lumber production may
increase an overall twenty percent; the output of paper,
five percent annually; folding boxes, three percent annually; plastics (which currently form one to two percent
of municipal wastes), seven percent annually. Collectively,
these industries account for the most serious pollutants in
the environment. The utterly senseless nature of modern
industrial activity is perhaps best illustrated by the decline
in returnable (and reusable) beer bottles from 54 billion
bottles in 1960 to 26 billion today. Their place has been
taken over by âone-wayâ bottles (a rise from 8 to 21
billion in the same period) and cans (an increase from 38
to 53 billion). The âone-wayâ bottles and the cans, of
course, pose tremendous problems in solid waste disposal.
The planet, conceived of as a lump of minerals, can
support these mindless increases in the output of trash.
The earth, conceived of as a complex web of life, certainly
cannot. The only question is whether the earth can survive
its looting long enough for man to replace the current
destructive social system with a humanistic, ecologically
oriented society.
Ecologists are often asked, rather tauntingly, to locate
with scientific exactness the ecological breaking point of
natureâthe point at which the natural world will cave in
on man. This is equivalent to asking a psychiatrist for the
precise moment when a neurotic will become a nonfunctional psychotic. No such answer is ever likely to be available. But the ecologist can supply a strategic insight into
the directions man seems to be following as a result of his
split with the natural world.
From the standpoint of ecology, man is dangerously
oversimplifying his environment. The modern city represents a regressive encroachment of the synthetic on the
natural, of the inorganic (concrete, metals, and glass) on
the organic, of crude, elemental stimuli on variegated,
wide-ranging ones. The vast urban belts now developing in
industrialized areas of the world are not only grossly offensive to the eye and the ear, they are chronically smog-ridden, noisy, and virtually immobilized by congestion.
The process of simplifying manâs environment and rendering it increasingly elemental and crude has a cultural as
well as a physical dimension. The need to manipulate immense urban populationsâto transport, feed, employ, educate and somehow entertain millions of densely concentrated peopleâleads to a crucial decline in civic and social
standards. A mass concept of human relationsâtotalitarian, centralistic and regimented in orientationâtends to
dominate the more individuated concepts of the past.
Bureaucratic techniques of social management tend to replace humanistic approaches. All that is spontaneous,
creative and individuated is circumscribed by the standardized, the regulated and the massified. The space of the
individual is steadily narrowed by restrictions imposed
upon him by a faceless, impersonal social apparatus. Any
recognition of unique personal qualities is increasingly surrendered to the manipulation of the lowest common
denominator of the mass. A quantitative, statistical approach, a beehive manner of dealing with man, tends to
triumph over the precious individualized and qualitative
approach which places the strongest emphasis on personal
uniqueness, free expression and cultural complexity.
The same regressive simplification of the environment
occurs in modern agriculture.[19] The manipulated people in
modern cities must be fed, and to feed them involves an
extension of industrial farming. Food plants must be cultivated in a manner that allows for a high degree of mechanizationânot to reduce human toil but to increase productivity and efficiency, to maximize investments, and to
exploit the biosphere. Accordingly, the terrain must be
reduced to a flat plainâto a factory floor, if you willâand
natural variations in topography must be diminished as
much as possible. Plant growth must be closely regulated
to meet the tight schedules of food-processing factories.
Plowing, soil fertilization, sowing and harvesting must be
handled on a mass scale, often in total disregard of the
natural ecology of an area. Large areas of the land must be
used to cultivate a single cropâa form of plantation agriculture that not only lends itself to mechanization but also
to pest infestation. A single crop is the ideal environment
for the proliferation of pest species. Finally, chemical
agents must be used lavishly to deal with the problems
created by insects, weeds, and plant diseases, to regulate
crop production, and to maximize soil exploitation. The
real symbol of modern agriculture is not the sickle (or, for
that matter, the tractor), but the airplane. The modern
food cultivator is represented not by the peasant, the yeoman, or even the agronomistâmen who could be expected
to have an intimate relationship with the unique qualities
of the land on which they grow cropsâbut the pilot or
chemist, for whom soil is a mere resource, an inorganic raw
material.
[19] For insight into this problem the reader may consult *The Ecology of Invasions* by Charles S. Elton (Wiley; New York, 1958), *Soil and Civilisation* by Edward Hyams (Thames and Hudson; London,
1952), *Our Synthetic Environment* by Murray Bookchin [pseud.
Lewis Herber] (Knopf; New York, 1962), and *Silent Spring* by
Rachel Carson (Houghton Mifflin; Boston, 1962). The last should be
read not as a diatribe against pesticides but as a plea for ecological
diversification.
The simplification process is carried still further by an
exaggerated regional (indeed, national) division of labor.
Immense areas of the planet are increasingly reserved for
specific industrial tasks or reduced to depots for raw materials. Others are turned into centers of urban population,
largely occupied with commerce and trade. Cities and
regions (in fact, countries and continents) are specifically
identified with special productsâPittsburgh, Cleveland and
Youngstown with steel, New York with finance, Bolivia
with tin, Arabia with oil, Europe and the U.S. with industrial goods, and the rest of the world with raw materials of
one kind or another. The complex ecosystems which make
up the regions of a continent are submerged by an organization of entire nations into economically rationalized
entities, each a way station in a vast industrial belt-system,
global in its dimensions. It is only a matter of time before
the most attractive areas of the countryside succumb to
the concrete mixer, just as most of the Eastern seashore
areas of the United States have already succumbed to subdivisions and bungalows. What will remain in the way of
natural beauty will be debased by trailer lots, canvas slums,
âscenicâ highways, motels, food stalls and the oil slicks of
motor boats.
The point is that man is undoing the work of organic
evolution. By creating vast urban agglomerations of concrete, metal and glass, by overriding and undermining the
complex, subtly organized ecosystems that constitute local
differences in the natural worldâin short, by replacing a
highly complex, organic environment with a simplified, inorganic oneâman is disassembling the biotic pyramid that
supported humanity for countless millennia. In the course
of replacing the complex ecological relationships, on which
all advanced living things depend, for more elementary
relationships, man is steadily restoring the biosphere to a
stage which will be able to support only simpler forms of
life. If this great reversal of the evolutionary process continues, it is by no means fanciful to suppose that the preconditions for higher forms of life will be irreparably destroyed and the earth will become incapable of supporting
man himself.
Ecology derives its critical edge not only from the fact
that it alone, among all the sciences, presents this awesome
message to humanity, but also because it presents this message in a new social dimension. From an ecological viewpoint, the reversal of organic evolution is the result of
appalling contradictions between town and country, state
and community, industry and husbandry, mass manufacture and craftsmanship, centralism and regionalism, the
bureaucratic scale and the human scale.
Until recently, attempts to resolve the contradictions created by urbanization, centralization, bureaucratic growth
and statification were viewed as a vain counterdrift to
âprogressââa counterdrift that could be dismissed as chimerical and reactionary. The anarchist was regarded as a
forlorn visionary, a social outcast, filled with nostalgia for
the peasant village or the medieval commune. His yearnings for a decentralized society and for a humanistic
community at one with nature and the needs of the individualâthe spontaneous individual, unfettered by authorityâwere viewed as the reactions of a romantic, of a
declassed craftsman or an intellectual âmisfit.â His protest
against centralization and statification seemed all the less
persuasive because it was supported primarily by ethical
considerationsâby Utopian, ostensibly âunrealistic,â notions of what man could be, not by what he was. In response to this protest, opponents of anarchist thoughtâliberals, rightists and authoritarian âleftistsââargued that
they were the voices of historic reality, that their statist
and centralist notions were rooted in the objective, practical world.
Time is not very kind to the conflict of ideas. Whatever
may have been the validity of libertarian and non-libertarian views a few years ago, historical development has
rendered virtually all objections to anarchist thought
meaningless today. The modern city and state, the massive
coal-steel technology of the Industrial Revolution, the
later, more rationalized, systems of mass production and
assembly-line systems of labor organization, the centralized nation, the state and its bureaucratic apparatusâall
have reached their limits. Whatever progressive or liberatory role they may have possessed, they have now become
entirely regressive and oppressive. They are regressive not
only because they erode the human spirit and drain the
community of all its cohesiveness, solidarity and
ethico-cultural standards; they are regressive from an
objective standpoint, from an ecological standpoint. For
they undermine not only the human spirit and the human
community but also the viability of the planet and all
living things on it.
It cannot be emphasized too strongly that the anarchist
concepts of a balanced community, a face-to-face democracy, a humanistic technology and a decentralized societyâthese rich libertarian conceptsâare not only desirable,
they are also necessary. They belong not only to the great
visions of manâs future, they now constitute the preconditions for human survival. The process of social development has carried them out of the ethical, subjective dimension into a practical, objective dimension. What was once
regarded as impractical and visionary has become eminently practical. And what was once regarded as practical
and objective has become eminently impractical and irrelevant in terms of manâs development towards a fuller, unfettered existence. If we conceive of demands for community, face-to-face democracy, a humanistic liberatory
technology and decentralization merely as reactions to the
prevailing state of affairsâa vigorous ânayâ to the âyeaâ
of what exists todayâa compelling, objective case can now
be made for the practicality of an anarchist society.
A rejection of the prevailing state of affairs accounts, I
think, for the explosive growth of intuitive anarchism
among young people today. Their love of nature is a reaction against the highly synthetic qualities of our urban
environment and its shabby products. Their informality of
dress and manners is a reaction against the formalized,
standardized nature of modern institutionalized living.
Their predisposition for direct action is a reaction against
the bureaucratization and centralization of society. Their
tendency to drop out, to avoid toil and the rat race, reflects a growing anger towards the mindless industrial routine bred by modern mass manufacture in the factory, the
office or the university. Their intense individualism is, in
its own elemental way, a *de facto* decentralization of social
lifeâa personal withdrawal from mass society.
What is most significant about ecology is its ability to
convert this often nihilistic rejection of the status quo into
an emphatic affirmation of lifeâindeed, into a reconstructive credo for a humanistic society. The essence of ecologyâs reconstructive message can be summed up in the
word âdiversity.â From an ecological viewpoint, balance
and harmony in nature, in society and, by inference, in
behavior, are achieved not by mechanical standardization
but by its opposite, organic differentiation. This message
can be understood clearly only by examining its practical
meaning.
Let us consider the ecological principle of diversityâwhat Charles Elton calls the âconservation of varietyââas
it applies to biology, specifically to agriculture. A number
of studiesâLotkaâs and Volterraâs mathematical models,
Bauseâs experiments with protozoa and mites in controlled
environments, and extensive field researchâclearly demonstrate that fluctuations in animal and plant populations,
ranging from mild to pestlike proportions, depend heavily
upon the number of species in an ecosystem and on the
degree of variety in the environment. The greater the variety of prey and predators, the more stable the population;
the more diversified the environment in terms of flora and
fauna, the less likely there is to be ecological instability.
Stability is a function of variety and diversity: if the environment is simplified and the variety of animal and plant
species is reduced, fluctuations in population become
marked and tend to get out of control. They tend to reach
pest proportions.
In the case of pest control, many ecologists now conclude that we can avoid the repetitive use of toxic chemicals such as insecticides and herbicides by allowing for a
greater interplay between living things. We must leave
more room for natural spontaneity, for the diverse biological forces that make up an ecological situation. âEuropean entomologists now speak of managing the entire
plant-insect community,â observes Robert L. Rudd. âIt is
called manipulation of the biocenose[20] The biocenetic environment is varied, complex and dynamic. Although numbers of individuals will constantly change, no one species
will normally reach pest proportions. The special conditions which allow high populations of a single species in a
complex ecosystem are rare events. Management of the
biocenose or ecosystem should become our goal, challenging as it is.â{9}
[20] Ruddâs use of the word âmanipulationâ is likely to create the
erroneous impression that an ecological situation can be described
by simple mechanical terms. Lest this impression arise, I would like
to emphasize that our knowledge of an ecological situation and the
practical use of this knowledge are matters of insight rather than
power. Charles Elton states the case for the management of an ecological situation when he writes: âThe worldâs future has to be
managed, but this management would not be like a game of chess
... [but] more like steering a boat.â
The âmanipulationâ of the biocenose in a meaningful
way, however, presupposes a far-reaching decentralization
of agriculture. Wherever feasible, industrial agriculture
must give way to soil and agricultural husbandry; the factory floor must yield to gardening and horticulture. I do
not wish to imply that we must surrender the gains acquired by large-scale agriculture and mechanization. What I
do contend, however, is that the land must be cultivated as
though it were a garden; its flora must be diversified and
carefully tended, balanced by fauna and tree shelter appropriate to the region. Decentralization is important, moreover, for the development of the agriculturist as well as for
the development of agriculture. Food cultivation, practiced in a truly ecological sense, presupposes that the agriculturist is familiar with all the features and subtleties of
the terrain on which the crops are grown. He must have a
thorough knowledge of the physiography of the land, its
variegated soilsâcrop land, forest land, pasture landâits
mineral and organic content and its micro-climate, and he
must be engaged in a continuing study of the effects produced by new flora and fauna. He must develop his sensitivity to the landâs possibilities and needs while he becomes
an organic part of the agricultural situation. We can hardly
hope to achieve this high degree of sensitivity and integration in the food cultivator without reducing agriculture
to a human scale, without bringing agriculture within the
scope of the individual. To meet the demands of an ecological approach to food cultivation, agriculture must be
re-scaled from huge industrial farms to moderate-sized
units.
The same reasoning applies to a rational development of
energy resources. The Industrial Revolution increased the
true that pre-industrial societies relied primarily on animal
power and human muscles, complex energy patterns developed in many regions of Europe, involving a subtle integration of resources such as wind and water power, and a
variety of fuels (wood, peat, coal, vegetable starches and
animal fats).
The Industrial Revolution overwhelmed and largely destroyed these regional energy patterns, replacing them first
by a single energy system (coal) and later by a dual system
(coal and petroleum). Regions disappeared as models of
integrated energy patternsâindeed, the very concept of *integration through diversity* was obliterated. As I indicated
earlier, many regions became predominantly mining areas,
devoted to the extraction of a single resource, while others
were turned into immense industrial areas, often devoted
to the production of a few commodities. We need not
review the role this breakdown in true regionalism has
played in producing air and water pollution, the damage it
has inflicted on large areas of the countryside, and the
prospect we face in the depletion of our precious hydrocarbon fuels.
We can, of course, turn to nuclear fuels, but it is chilling
to think of the lethal radioactive wastes that would require
disposal if power reactors were our sole energy source.
Eventually, an energy system based on radioactive materials would lead to the widespread contamination of the
environmentâat first in a subtle form, but later on a massive and palpably destructive scale. Or we could apply ecological principles to the solution of our energy problems.
We could try to re-establish earlier regional energy patterns, using a combined system of energy provided by
wind, water and solar power. We would be aided by devices more sophisticated than any known in the past.
Solar devices, wind turbines and hydro-electric resources, taken singly, do not provide a solution for our
energy problems and the ecological disruption created by
conventional fuels. Pieced together as a *mosaic*, as an
organic energy pattern developed from the potentialities of
a region, they could amply meet the needs of a decentralized society. In sunny latitudes, we could rely more
heavily on solar energy than on combustible fuels. In areas
marked by atmospheric turbulence, we could rely more
heavily on wind devices; and in suitable coastal areas or
inland regions with a good network of rivers, the greater
part of our energy would come from hydro-electric installations. In all cases, we would use a mosaic of non-combustible, combustible, and nuclear fuels. The point I wish to
make is that by diversifying our use of energy resources,
by organizing them into an ecologically balanced pattern,
we could combine wind, solar and water power in a given
region to meet the industrial and domestic needs of a given
community with only a minimal use of harmful fuels. And,
eventually, we might sophisticate our non-combustion
energy devices to a point where all harmful sources of
energy could be eliminated.
As in the case of agriculture, however, the application of
ecological principles to energy resources presupposes a far-reaching decentralization of society and a truly regional
concept of social organization. To maintain a large city
requires immense quantities of coal and petroleum. By
contrast, solar, wind and tidal energy reach us mainly in
small packets; except for spectacular tidal dams, the new
devices seldom provide more than a few thousand kilowatt-hours of electricity. It is difficult to believe that we
will ever be able to design solar collectors that can furnish
us with the immense blocks of electric power produced by
a giant steam plant; it is equally difficult to conceive of a
battery of wind turbines that will provide us with enough
electricity to illuminate Manhattan Island. If homes and
factories are heavily concentrated, devices for using clean
sources of energy will probably remain mere playthings;
but if urban communities are reduced in size and widely
dispersed over the land, there is no reason why these devices cannot be combined to provide us with all the amenities of an industrialized civilization. To use solar, wind and
tidal power effectively, the megalopolis must be decentralized. A new type of community, carefully tailored to
the characteristics and resources of a region, must replace
the sprawling urban belts that are emerging today.
To be sure, an objective case for decentralization does
not end with a discussion of agriculture and the problems
created by combustible energy resources. The validity of
the decentralist case can be demonstrated for nearly all the
âlogisticalâ problems of our time. Let me cite an example
from the problematical area of transportation. A great deal
has been written about the harmful effects of gasoline-driven motor vehiclesâtheir wastefulness, their role in urban air pollution, the noise they contribute to the city
environment, the enormous death toll they claim annually
in the large cities of the world and on highways. In a
highly urbanized civilization it would be useless to replace
these noxious vehicles by clean, efficient, virtually noiseless, and certainly safer, battery-powered vehicles. The best
of our electric cars must be recharged about every hundred
milesâa feature which limits their usefulness for transportation in large cities. In a small, decentralized community,
however, it would be feasible to use these electric vehicles
for urban or regional transportation and establish monorail
networks for long-distance transportation.
It is fairly well known that gasoline-powered vehicles
contribute enormously to urban air pollution, and there is
a strong sentiment to âengineerâ the more noxious features of the automobile into oblivion. Our age characteristically tries to solve all its irrationalities with a gimmickâafterburners for toxic gasoline fumes, antibiotics for ill
health, tranquilizers for psychic disturbances. But the
problem of urban air pollution is too intractable for gimmicks; perhaps it is more intractable than we care to believe. Basically, air pollution is caused by high population
densitiesâby an excessive concentration of people in a
small area. Millions of people, densely concentrated in a
large city, necessarily produce serious local air pollution
merely by their day-to-day activities. They must burn fuels
for domestic and industrial reasons; they must construct or
tear down buildings (the aerial debris produced by these
activities is a major source of urban air pollution); they
must dispose of immense quantities of rubbish; they must
travel on roads with rubber tires (the particles produced by
the erosion of tires and roadway materials add significantly
to air pollution). Whatever pollution-control devices we
add to automobiles and power plants, the improvements
these devices will produce in the quality of urban air will
be more than canceled out by future megalopolitan
growth.
There is more to anarchism than decentralized communities. If I have examined this possibility in some detail, it
has been to demonstrate that an anarchist society, far from
being a remote ideal, has become a precondition for the
practice of ecological principles. To sum up the critical
message of ecology: if we diminish variety in the natural
world, we debase its unity and wholeness; we destroy the
forces making for natural harmony and for a lasting equilibrium; and, what is even more significant, we introduce an
absolute retrogression in the development of the natural
world which may eventually render the environment unfit
for advanced forms of life. To sum up the reconstructive
message of ecology: if we wish to advance the unity and
stability of the natural world, if we wish to harmonize it,
we must conserve and promote variety. To be sure, mere
variety for its own sake is a vacuous goal. In nature, variety
emerges spontaneously. The capacities of a new species are
tested by the rigors of climate, by its ability to deal with
predators and by its capacity to establish and enlarge its
niche. <em>Yet the species that succeeds in enlarging its niche
in the environment also enlarges the ecological situation as
a whole.</em> To borrow E. A. Gutkindâs phrase, it âexpands
the environment,â{10} both for itself and for the species
with which it enters into a balanced relationship.
How do these concepts apply to social theory? To many
readers, I suppose, it should suffice to say that, inasmuch
as man is part of nature, an expanding natural environment
enlarges the basis for social development. But the answer
to the question goes much deeper than many ecologists
and libertarians suspect. Again, allow me to return to the
ecological principle of wholeness and balance as a product
of diversity. Keeping this principle in mind, the first step
towards an answer is provided by a passage in Herbert
Readâs âThe Philosophy of Anarchism.â In presenting his
âmeasure of progress,â Read observes: âProgress is measured by the degree of differentiation within a society. If
the individual is a unit in a corporate mass, his life will be
limited, dull, and mechanical. If the individual is a unit on
his own, with space and potentiality for separate action,
then he may be more subject to accident or chance, but at
least he can expand and express himself. He can developâdevelop in the only real meaning of the wordâdevelop in
consciousness of strength, vitality, and joy.â
Readâs thought, unfortunately, is not fully developed,
but it provides an interesting point of departure. What first
strikes us is that both the ecologist and the anarchist place
a strong emphasis on spontaneity. The ecologist, insofar as
he is more than a technician, tends to reject the notion of
âpower over nature.â He speaks, instead, of âsteeringâ his
way through an ecological situation, of *managing* rather
than *recreating* an ecosystem. The anarchist, in turn,
speaks in terms of social spontaneity, of releasing the
potentialities of society and humanity, of giving free and
unfettered rein to the creativity of people. Both, in their
own way, regard authority as inhibitory, as a weight limiting the creative potential of a natural and social situation.
Their object is not to *rule* a domain, but to *release* it. They
regard insight, reason and knowledge as means for fulfilling
the potentialities of a situation, as facilitating the working
out of the logic of a situation, not as replacing its potentialities with preconceived notions or distorting their development with dogmas.
Turning to Readâs words, what strikes us is that both the
ecologist and the anarchist view differentiation as a measure of progress. The ecologist uses the term âbiotic pyramidâ in speaking of biological advances; the anarchist, the
word âindividuationâ to denote social advances. If we go
beyond Read we will observe that, to both the ecologist
and the anarchist, an ever-increasing unity is achieved by
growing differentiation. <em>An expanding whole is created by
the diversification and enrichment of its parts.</em>
Just as the ecologist seeks to expand the range of an
ecosystem and promote a free interplay between species,
so the anarchist seeks to expand the range of social experience and remove all fetters to its development. Anarchism
is not only a stateless society but also a harmonized society which exposes man to the stimuli provided by both
agrarian and urban life, to physical activity and mental
activity, to unrepressed sensuality and self-directed spirituality, to communal solidarity and individual development,
to regional uniqueness and worldwide brotherhood, to
spontaneity and self-discipline, to the elimination of toil
and the promotion of craftsmanship. In our schizoid society, these goals are regarded as mutually exclusive, indeed
as sharply opposed. They appear as dualities because of the
very logistics of present-day societyâthe separation of
town and country, the specialization of labor, the atomization of manâand it would be preposterous to believe that
these dualities could be resolved without a general idea of
the *physical* structure of an anarchist society. We can gain
some idea of what such a society would be like by reading
William Morrisâs *News From Nowhere* and the writings of
Peter Kropotkin. But these works provide us with mere
glimpses. They do not take into account the post-World
War II developments of technology and the contributions
made by the development of ecology. This is not the place
to embark on âutopian writing,â but certain guidelines can
be presented even in a general discussion. And in presenting these guidelines, I am eager to emphasize not only the
more obvious ecological premises that support them, but
also the humanistic ones.
An anarchist society should be a decentralized society,
not only to establish a lasting basis for the harmonization
of man and nature, <em>but also to add new dimensions to the
harmonization of man and man</em>. The Greeks, we are often
reminded, would have been horrified by a city whose size
and population precluded a face-to-face, often familiar,
relationship between citizens. There is plainly a need to
reduce the dimensions of the human communityâpartly to
solve our pollution and transportation problems, partly
also to create *real* communities. In a sense, we must
telegraphs, radios and television receivers should be used
as little as possible to mediate the relations between
people. In making collective decisionsâthe ancient Athenian ecclesia was, in some ways, a model for making social
decisionsâall members of the community should have an
opportunity to acquire in full the measure of anyone who
addresses the assembly. They should be in a position to
absorb his attitudes, study his expressions, and weigh his
motives as well as his ideas in a direct personal encounter
and through face-to-face discussion.
Our small communities should be economically balanced and well rounded, partly so that they can make full
use of local raw materials and energy resources, partly also
to enlarge the agricultural and industrial stimuli to which
individuals are exposed. The member of a community who
has a predilection for engineering, for instance, should be
encouraged to steep his hands in humus; the man of ideas
should be encouraged to employ his musculature; the âinbornâ farmer should gain a familiarity with the workings
of a rolling mill. To separate the engineer from the soil, the
thinker from the spade, and the farmer from the industrial
plant promotes a degree of vocational overspecialization
that leads to a dangerous measure of social control by
specialists. What is equally important, professional and vocational specialization prevents society from achieving a
vital goal: the humanization of nature by the technician
and the naturalization of society by the biologist.
I submit that an anarchist community would approximate a clearly definable ecosystem; it would be diversified,
balanced and harmonious. It is arguable whether such an
ecosystem would acquire the configuration of an urban
entity with a distinct center, such as we find in the Greek
proposes, society would consist of widely dispersed communities without a distinct center. I n any case, the ecological scale for any of these communities would be determined by the smallest ecosystem capable of supporting a
population of moderate size.
A relatively self-sufficient community, visibly dependent on its environment for the means of life, would gain a
new respect for the organic interrelationships that sustain
it. In the long run, the attempt to approximate self-sufficiency would, I think, prove more efficient than the
exaggerated national division of labor that prevails today.
Although there would doubtless be many duplications of
small industrial facilities from community to community,
the familiarity of each group with its local environment
and its ecological roots would make for a more intelligent
and more loving use of its environment. I submit that, far
from producing provincialism, relative self-sufficiency
would create a new matrix for individual and communal
developmentâa oneness with the surroundings that would
vitalize the community.
The rotation of civic, vocational and professional responsibilities would stimulate the senses in the being of the
individual, creating and rounding out new dimensions in
self-development. In a complete society we could hope to
create complete men; in a rounded society, rounded men.
In the Western world, the Athenians, for all their shortcomings and limitations, were the first to give us a notion
of this completeness. âThe *polis* was made for the amateur,â H. D. F. Kitto tells us. âIts ideal was that every
citizen (more or less, according as the *polis* was democratic
or oligarchic) should play his part in all of its many activities-an ideal that is recognizably descended from the generous Homeric conception of *arete* as an all-round excellence and an all-round activity. It implies a respect for the
wholeness or the oneness of life, and a consequent dislike
of specialization. It implies a contempt for efficiencyâor
rather a much higher ideal of efficiency; and efficiency
which exists not in one department of life, but in life
itself.â{11} An anarchist society, although it would surely
aspire to more, could hardly hope to achieve less than this
state of mind.
If the ecological community is ever achieved in practice,
social life will yield a sensitive development of human and
natural diversity, falling together into a well balanced, harmonious whole. Ranging from community through region
to entire continents, we will see a colorful differentiation
of human groups and ecosystems, each developing its
unique potentialities and exposing members of the community to a wide spectrum of economic, cultural and behavioral stimuli. Falling within our purview will be an exciting, often dramatic, variety of communal formsâhere
marked by architectural and industrial adaptations to
semi-arid ecosystems, there to grasslands, elsewhere by
adaptation to forested areas. We will witness a creative
interplay between individual and group, community and
environment, humanity and nature. The cast of mind that
today organizes differences among humans and other life-forms along hierarchical lines, defining the external in
terms of its âsuperiorityâ or âinferiority,â will give way to
an outlook that deals with diversity in an ecological manner. Differences among people will be respected, indeed
fostered, as elements that enrich the unity of experience
and phenomena. The traditional relationship which pits
subject against object will be altered qualitatively; the âexternal,â the âdifferent,â the âotherâ will be conceived of
as individual parts of a whole all the richer because of its
complexity. This sense of unity will reflect the harmonization of interests between individuals and between
society and nature. Freed from an oppressive routine, from
paralyzing repressions and insecurities, from the burdens
of toil and false needs, from the trammels of authority and
irrational compulsion, individuals will finally, for the first
time in history, be in a position to realize their potentialities as members of the human community and the
natural world.
New York
February 1965
Not since the days of the Industrial Revolution have
popular attitudes toward technology fluctuated as sharply
as in the past few decades. During most of the twenties,
and even well into the thirties, public opinion generally
welcomed technological innovation and identified manâs
welfare with the industrial advances of the time. This was a
period when Soviet apologists could justify Stalinâs most
brutal methods and worst crimes merely by describing him
as the âindustrializerâ of modern Russia. It was also a
period when the most effective critique of capitalist society could rest on the brute facts of economic and technological stagnation in the United States and Western
Europe. To many people there seemed to be a direct, one-to-one relationship between technological advances and
social progress; a fetishism of the word âindustrializationâ
excused the most abusive of economic plans and programs.
Today, we would regard these attitudes as naive. Except
perhaps for the technicians and scientists who design the
âhardware,â the feeling of most people toward technological innovation could be described as schizoid, divided
into a gnawing fear of nuclear extinction on the one hand,
and a yearning for material abundance, leisure and security
on the other. Technology, too, seems to be at odds with
itself. The bomb is pitted against the power reactor, the
intercontinental missile against the communications satellite. The same technological discipline tends to appear
both as a foe and a friend of humanity, and even traditionally human-oriented sciences, such as medicine, occupy an ambivalent positionâas witness the promise of
advances in chemotherapy and the threat created by
research in biological warfare.
It is not surprising to find that the tension between
promise and threat is increasingly being resolved in favor
of threat by a blanket rejection of technology. To an evergrowing extent, technology is viewed as a demon, imbued
with a sinister life of its own, that is likely to mechanize
man if it fails to exterminate him. The deep pessimism this
view produces is often as simplistic as the optimism that
prevailed in earlier decades. There is a very real danger that
we will lose our perspective toward technology, that we
will neglect its liberatory tendencies, and, worse, submit
fatalistically to its use for destructive ends. If we are not to
be paralyzed by this new form of social fatalism, a balance
must be struck.
The purpose of this article is to explore three questions.
What is the liberatory potential of modern technology,
both materially and spiritually? What tendencies, if any,
are reshaping the machine for use in an organic, human-oriented society? And finally, how can the new technology
and resources be used in an ecological mannerâthat is, to
promote the balance of nature, the full development of
natural regions, and the creation of organic, humanistic
communities?
The emphasis in the above remarks should be placed on
the word âpotential.â I make no claim that technology is
necessarily liberatory or consistently beneficial to manâs
development. But I surely do not believe that man is destined to be enslaved by technology and technological
modes of thought (as Juenger and Elul imply in their
books on the subject[21]). On the contrary, I shall try to
show that an organic mode of life deprived of its technological component would be as nonfunctional as a man
deprived of his skeleton. Technology must be viewed as
the basic structural support of a society; it is literally the
framework of an economy and of many social institutions.
[21] Both Juenger and Elul believe that the debasement of man by the
machine is intrinsic to the development of technology, and their
works conclude on a grim note of resignation. This viewpoint reflects the social fatalism I have in mindâespecially as expressed by
Elul, whose ideas are more symptomatic of the contemporary human condition. See Friedrich George Juenger, *The Failure of Technology* (Regnery; Chicago, 1956) and Jacques Elul, *The Technological Society* (Knopf; New York, 1968).
The year 1848 stands out as a turning point in the history
of modern revolutions. This was the year when Marxism
made its debut as a distinct ideology in the pages of the
political force on the barricades of June. It could also be
said that 1848, a year close to the halfway mark of the
nineteenth century, represents the culmination of the traditional steam-powered technology initiated by the
Newcomen engine a century and a half earlier.
What strikes us about the convergence of these ideological, political and technological milestones is the extent to
which the *Communist Manifesto* and the June barricades
were in advance of their time. In the 1840s, the Industrial
Revolution centered around three areas of the economy:
textile production, iron-making and transportation. The
invention of Arkwrightâs spinning machine, Wattâs steam
engine and Cartwrightâs power loom had finally brought
the factory system to the textile industry; meanwhile, a
number of striking innovations in iron-making technology
assured the supply of high-quality, inexpensive metals
needed to sustain factory and railway expansion. But these
innovations, important as they were, were not accompanied by commensurate changes in other areas of industrial technology. For one thing, few steam engines were
rated at more than fifteen horsepower, and the best blast
furnaces provided little more than a hundred tons of iron a
weekâa fraction of the thousands of tons produced daily
by modern furnaces. More important, the remaining areas
of the economy were not yet significantly affected by
technological innovation. Mining techniques, for example,
had changed little since the days of the Renaissance. The
miner still worked the ore face with a hand pick and a
crowbar, and drainage pumps, ventilation systems and
hauling techniques were not greatly improved over the
descriptions we find in Agricolaâs classic on mining written
three centuries earlier. Agriculture was only emerging from
its centuries-old sleep. Although a great deal of land had
been cleared for food cultivation, soil studies were still a
novelty. So heavy, in fact, was the weight of tradition and
conservatism that most harvesting was still done by hand,
despite the fact that a mechanical reaper had been perfected as early as 1822. Buildings, despite their massiveness
and ornateness, were erected primarily by sheer muscle
power; the hand crane and windlass still occupied the
mechanical center of the construction site. Steel was a
relatively rare metal: as late as 1850 it was priced at $250
a ton and, until the discovery of the Bessemer converter,
steel-making techniques had stagnated for centuries. Finally, although precision tools had made great forward
strides, it is worth noting that Charles Babbageâs efforts to
build a sophisticated mechanical computer were thwarted
by the inadequate machining techniques of the time.
I have reviewed these technological developments because both their promise and their limitations exercised a
profound influence on nineteenth century revolutionary
thought. The innovations in textile and iron-making technology provided a new sense of promise, indeed a new
stimulus, to socialist and Utopian thought. It seemed to the
revolutionary theorist that for the first time in history he
could anchor his dream of a liberatory society in the
visible prospect of material abundance and increased leisure for the mass of humanity. Socialism, the theorists
argued, could be based on self-interest rather than on
manâs dubious nobility of mind and spirit. Technological
innovation had transmuted the socialist ideal from a vague
humanitarian hope into a practical program.
The newly acquired practicality compelled many socialist theorists, particularly Marx and Engels, to grapple with
the technological limitations of their time. They were
faced with a strategic issue: in all previous revolutions,
technology had not yet developed to a level where men
could be freed from material want, toil and the struggle
over the necessities of life. However glowing and lofty
were the revolutionary ideals of the past, the vast majority
of the people, burdened by material want, had to leave the
stage of history after the revolution, return to work, and
deliver the management of society to a new leisured class
of exploiters. Indeed, any attempt to equalize the wealth
of society at a low level of technological development
would not have eliminated want, but would have merely
made it into a general feature of society as a whole, thereby recreating all the conditions for a new struggle over the
material things of life, for new forms of property, and
eventually for a new system of class domination. A development of the productive forces is the âabsolutely
necessary practical premise [of communism],â wrote Marx
and Engels in 1846, âbecause without it *want* is generalized, and with want the struggle for necessities and all the
old filthy business would necessarily be reproduced.â{12}
Virtually all the Utopias, theories and revolutionary programs of the early nineteenth century were faced with
problems of necessityâof how to allocate labor and material goods at a relatively low level of technological development. These problems permeated revolutionary thought in
a way comparable only to the impact of original sin on
Christian theology. The fact that men would have to devote a substantial portion of their time to toil, for which
they would get scant returns, formed a major premise of
all socialist ideologyâauthoritarian and libertarian, Utopian
and scientific, Marxist and anarchist. Implicit in the Marxist notion of a planned economy was the fact, incontestably clear in Marxâs day, that socialism would still be
burdened by relatively scarce resources. Men would have
to planâin effect, to restrictâthe distribution of goods and
would have to rationalizeâin effect, to intensifyâthe use
of labor. Toil, under socialism, would be a duty, a responsibility which every able-bodied individual would have to
undertake. Even Proudhon advanced this dour view when
he wrote: âYes, life is a struggle. But this struggle is not
between man and manâit is between man and Nature;
and it is each oneâs duty to share it.â{13} This austere,
almost biblical, emphasis on struggle and duty reflects the
harsh quality of socialist thought during the Industrial
Revolution.
The problem of dealing with want and workâan age-old
problem perpetuated by the early Industrial Revolutionâproduced the great divergence in revolutionary ideas
between socialism and anarchism. Freedom would still be
circumscribed by necessity in the event of a revolution.
How was this world of necessity to be âadministeredâ?
How could the allocation of goods and duties be decided?
Marx left this decision to a state power, a transitional
âproletarianâ state power, to be sure, but nevertheless a
coercive body, established above society. According to
Marx, the state would âwither awayâ as technology developed and enlarged the domain of freedom, granting
humanity material plenty and the leisure to control its
affairs directly. This strange calculus, in which necessity
and freedom were mediated by the state, differed very
little politically from the common run of bourgeoisâdemocratic radical opinion in the last century. The anarchist hope for the abolition of the state, on the other
hand, rested largely on a belief in the viability of manâs
social instincts. Bakunin, for example, thought custom
would compel any individuals with antisocial proclivities
to abide by collectivist values and needs without
obliging society to use coercion. Kropotkin, who exercised
more influence among anarchists in this area of speculation, invoked manâs propensity for mutual aidâessentially
a social instinctâas the guarantor of solidarity in an anarchist community (a concept which he derived from his
study of animal and social evolution).
The fact remains, however, that in both casesâthe Marxist and the anarchistâthe answer to the problem of want
and work was shot through with ambiguity. The realm of
necessity was brutally present; it could not be conjured
away by mere theory and speculation. The Marxists could
hope to administer necessity by means of a state, and the
anarchists, to deal with it through free communities, but
given the limited technological development of the last
century, in the last analysis both schools depended on an
act of faith to cope with the problem of want and work.
Anarchists could argue against the Marxists that any transitional state, however revolutionary its rhetoric and democratic its structure, would be self-perpetuating; it would
tend to become an end in itself and to preserve the very
material and social conditions it had been created to remove. For such a state to âwither awayâ (that is, promote
its own dissolution) would require its leaders and bureaucracy to be people of superhuman moral qualities. The
Marxists, in turn, could invoke history to show that custom and mutualistic propensities were never effective
barriers to the pressures of material need, or to the onslaught of property, or to the development of exploitation
and class domination. Accordingly, they dismissed anarchism as an ethical doctrine which revived the mystique of
the natural man and his inborn social virtues.
The problem of want and workâof the realm of necessityâwas never satisfactorily resolved by either body of
doctrine in the last century. It is to the lasting credit of
anarchism that it uncompromisingly retained its high ideal
of freedomâthe ideal of spontaneous organization, community, and the abolition of all authorityâalthough this
ideal remained only a vision of manâs future, of the time
when technology would eliminate the realm of necessity
entirely. Marxism increasingly compromised its ideal of
freedom, painfully qualifying it with transitional stages
and political expediencies, until today it is an ideology of
naked power, pragmatic efficiency and social centralization almost indistinguishable from the ideologies of modern state capitalism.[22]
[22] It is my own belief that the development of the âworkersâ stateâ
in Russia thoroughly supports the anarchist critique of Marxist statism. Indeed, modern Marxists would do well to consult Marxâs own
discussion of commodity fetishism in *Capital* to understand how
everything (including the state) tends to become an end in itself
under conditions of commodity exchange.
In retrospect, it is astonishing to consider how long the
problem of want and work cast its shadow over revolutionary theory. In a span of only nine decadesâthe years
between 1850 and 1940âWestern society created, passed
through and evolved beyond two major epochs of technological historyâthe paleotechnic age of coal and steel, and
the neotechnic age of electric power, synthetic chemicals,
electricity and internal combustion engines. Ironically,
both ages of technology seemed to enhance the importance of toil in society. As the number of industrial workers increased in proportion to other social classes, laborâmore precisely, toil[23]âacquired an increasingly high status
in revolutionary thought. During this period, the propaganda of the socialists often sounded like a paean to toil;
not only was toil âennobling,â but the workers were extolled as the only useful individuals in the social fabric.
They were endowed with a supposedly superior instinctive
ability that made them the arbiters of philosophy, art, and
social organization. This puritanical work ethic of the left
did not diminish with the passage of time and in fact acquired a certain urgency in the 1930s. Mass unemployment
made the job and the social organization of labor the central themes of socialist propaganda in the 1930s. Instead of
focusing their message on the emancipation of man from
toil, socialists tended to depict socialism as a beehive of
industrial activity, humming with work for all. The Communists pointed to Russia as a land where every able-bodied individual was employed and where labor was continually in demand. Surprising as it may seem today, little
more than a generation ago socialism was equated with a
work-oriented society and liberty with the material security provided by full employment. The world of necessity
had subtly invaded and corrupted the ideal of freedom.
[23] The distinction between pleasurable work and onerous toil should
always be kept in mind.
That the socialist notions of the last generation now
seem to be anachronisms is not due to any superior insights that prevail today. The last three decades, particularly the years of the late 1950s, mark a turning point in
technological development, a technological revolution that
negates all the values, political schemes and social perspectives held by mankind throughout all previous recorded
history. After thousands of years of torturous development, the countries of the Western world (and potentially
all countries) are confronted by the possibility of a materially abundant, almost workless era in which most of the
means of life can be provided by machines. As we shall see,
a new technology has developed that could largely replace
the realm of necessity by the realm of freedom. So obvious
is this fact to millions of people in the United States and
Europe that it no longer requires elaborate explanations or
theoretical exegesis. This technological revolution and the
prospects it holds for society as a whole form the premises
of radically new lifestyles among todayâs young people, a
generation that is rapidly divesting itself of the values and
the age-old work-oriented traditions of its elders. Even
recent demands for a guaranteed annual income sound like
faint echoes of the new reality that currently permeates
the thinking of the young. Owing to the development of a
cybernetic technology, the notion of a toil-less mode of
life has become an article of faith to an ever-increasing
number of young people.
In fact, the real issue we face today is not whether this
new technology can provide us with the means of life in a
toil-less society, but whether it can help to *humanize* society, whether it can contribute to the creation of entirely
new relationships between man and man. The demand for
a guaranteed annual income is still anchored in the *quantitative* promise of technologyâin the possibility of satisfying material needs without toil. This quantitative approach
is already lagging behind technological developments that
carry a new qualitative promiseâthe promise of decentralized, communitarian lifestyles, or what I prefer to call
ecological forms of human association.[24]
[24] An exclusively quantitative approach to the new technology, I
may add, is not only economically archaic, but morally regressive.
This approach partakes of the old principle of justice, as distinguished from the new principle of freedom. Historically, justice is
derived from the world of material necessity and toil; it implies
relatively scarce resources which are apportioned by a moral principle which is either âjustâ or âunjust.â Justice, even âequalâ justice, is a concept of limitation, involving the denial of goods and the
sacrifice of time and energy to production. Once we transcend the
concept of justiceâindeed, once we pass from the quantitative to the
qualitative potentialities of modern technologyâwe enter the unexplored domain of freedom, based on spontaneous organization
and full access to the means of life.
I am asking a question that is quite different from what
is ordinarily posed with respect to modern technology. Is
this technology staking out a new dimension in human
freedom, in the liberation of man? Can it not only liberate
man from want and work, but also lead him to a free,
harmonious, balanced human communityâan ecocommunity that would promote the unrestricted development of
his potentialities? Finally, can it carry man beyond the
realm of freedom into the realm of life and desire?
Let me try to answer these questions by pointing to a new
feature of modern technology. For the first time in history, technology has reached an open end. The potential
for technological development, for providing machines as
substitutes for labor is virtually unlimited. Technology has
finally passed from the realm of *invention* to that of
systematic innovations.
The meaning of this qualitative advance has been stated
in a rather freewheeling way by Vannevar Bush, the former
director of the Office of Scientific Research and
Development:
Suppose, fifty years ago, that someone had proposed making a device which would cause an
automobile to follow a white line down the middle
of the road, automatically and even if the driver
fell asleep.... He would have been laughed at,
and his idea would have been called preposterous.
So it would have been then. But suppose someone
called for such a device today, and was willing to
pay for it, leaving aside the question of whether it
would actually be of any genuine use whatever.
Any number of concerns would stand ready to
contract and build it. No real invention would be
required. There are thousands of young men in the
country to whom the design of such a device
would be a pleasure. They would simply take off
the shelf some photocells, thermionic tubes, servomechanisms, relays and, if urged, they would build
what they call a breadboard model, and it would
work. The point is that the presence of a host of
versatile, cheap, reliable gadgets, and the presence
of men who understand fully all their queer ways,
has rendered the building of automatic devices
almost straightforward and routine. It is no longer
a question of whether they can be built, it is rather
a question of whether they are worth building.{14}
Bush focuses here on the two most important features
of the new, so-called âsecond,â industrial revolution,
namely the enormous potentialities of modern technology
and the cost-oriented, nonhuman limitations that are
imposed upon it. I shall not belabor the fact that the cost
factorâthe profit motive, to state it bluntlyâinhibits the
use of technological innovations. It is fairly well established that in many areas of the economy it is cheaper to
use labor than machines.[25] Instead, I would like to review
several developments which have brought us to an open
end in technology and deal with a number of practical
applications that have profoundly affected the role of
labor in industry and agriculture.
Perhaps the most obvious development leading to the
new technology has been the increasing interpenetration of
scientific abstraction, mathematics and analytic methods
with the concrete, pragmatic and rather mundane tasks of
industry. This order of relationships is relatively new.
Traditionally, speculation, generalization and rational
activity were sharply divorced from technology. This
chasm reflected the sharp split between the leisured and
working classes in ancient and medieval society. If one
leaves aside the inspired works of a few rare men, applied
science did not come into its own until the Renaissance,
and it only began to flourish in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
[25] For example, in cotton plantations in the Deep South, in automobile assembly plants, and in the garment industry.
The men who personify the application of science to
technological innovation are not the inventive tinkerers
like Edison, but the systematic investigators with catholic
interests like Faraday, who add simultaneously to manâs
knowledge of scientific principles and to engineering. In
our own day this synthesis, once embodied by the work of
a single, inspired genius, is the work of anonymous teams.
Although these teams have obvious advantages, they often
have all the traits of bureaucratic agenciesâwhich leads to
a mediocre, unimaginative treatment of problems.
Less obvious is the impact produced by industrial
growth. This impact is not always technological; it is more
than the substitution of machines for human labor. One of
the most effective means of increasing output, in fact, has
been the continual reorganization of the labor process,
extending and sophisticating the division of labor. Ironically, the steady breakdown of tasks to ever more inhuman
dimensionsâto an intolerably minute, fragmented series of
operations and to a cruel simplification of the work
processâsuggests the machine that will recombine all the
separate tasks of many workers into a single mechanized
operation. Historically, it would be difficult to understand
how mechanized mass manufacture emerged, how the
machine increasingly displaced labor, without tracing the
development of the work process from craftsmanship,
where an independent, highly skilled worker engages in
many diverse operations, through the purgatory of the
factory, where these diverse tasks are parceled out among a
multitude of unskilled or semiskilled employees, to the
highly mechanized mill, where the tasks of many are
largely taken over by machines manipulated by a few
operatives, and finally to the automated and cybernated
plant, where operatives are replaced by supervisory technicians and highly skilled maintenance men.
Looking further into the matter, we find still another
new development: the machine has evolved from an extension of human muscles into an extension of the human
nervous system. In the past, both tools and machines enhanced manâs muscular power over raw materials and
natural forces. The mechanical devices and engines developed during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries did
not replace human muscles but rather enlarged their effectiveness. Although the machines increased output enormously, the workerâs muscles and brain were still required
to operate them, even for fairly routine tasks. The calculus
of technological advance could be formulated in strict
terms of labor productivity: one man, using a given machine, produced as many commodities as five, ten, fifty, or
a hundred before the machine was employed. Nasmythâs
steam hammer, exhibited in 1851, could shape iron beams
with only a few blows, an effort that would have required
many manhours of labor without the machine. But the
hammer required the muscles and judgment of half a
dozen able-bodied men to pull, hold and remove the casting. In time, much of this work was diminished by the
invention of handling devices, but the labor and judgment
involved in operating the machines formed an indispensable part of the productive process.
The development of fully automatic machines for complex mass-manufacturing operations requires the successful
application of at least three technological principles: such
machines must have a built-in ability to correct their own
errors; they must have sensory devices for replacing the
visual, auditory and tactile senses of the worker; and,
finally, they must have devices that substitute for the
workerâs judgment, skill and memory. The effective use of
these three principles presupposes that we have also developed the technological means (the effectors, if you will)
for applying the sensory, control and mind-like devices in
everyday industrial operation; further, effective use presupposes that we can adapt existing machines or develop
new ones for handling, shaping, assembling, packaging and
transporting semi-finished and finished products.
The use of automatic, self-correcting control devices in
industrial operations is not new. James Wattâs fly ball
governor, invented in 1788, provides an early mechanical
example of how steam engines were self-regulated. The
governor, which is attached by metal arms to the engine
valve, consists of two freely mounted metal balls supported by a thin, rotating rod. If the engine begins to
operate too rapidly, the increased rotation of the rod
impels the balls outward by centrifugal force, closing the
valve; conversely, if the valve does not admit sufficient
steam to operate the engine at the desired rate, the balls
collapse inward, opening the valve further. A similar principle is involved in the operation of thermostatically controlled heating equipment. The thermostat, manually
preset by a dial to a desired temperature level, automatically starts up heating equipment when the temperature
falls and turns off the equipment when the temperature
rises.
Both control devices illustrate what is now called the
âfeedback principle.â In modern electronic equipment, the
deviation of a machine from a desired level of operation
produces electrical signals which are then used by the control device to correct the deviation or error. The electrical
signals induced by the error are amplified and fed back by
the control system to other devices which adjust the
machine. A control system in which a departure from the
norm is actually used to adjust a machine is called a *closed*
system. This may be contrasted with an *open* systemâa
manually operated wall switch or the arms that automatically rotate an electrical fanâin which the control operates
without regard to the function of the device. Thus, if the
wall switch is flicked, electric lights go on or off whether it
is night or day; similarly the electric fan will rotate at the
same speed whether a room is warm or cool. The fan may
be automatic in the popular sense of the term, but it is not
self-regulating like the flyball governor and the thermostat.
An important step toward developing self-regulating
control mechanisms was the discovery of sensory devices.
Today these include thermocouples, photoelectric cells,
X-ray machines, television cameras and radar transmitters.
Used together or singly they provide machines with an
amazing degree of autonomy. Even without computers,
these sensory devices make it possible for workers to engage in extremely hazardous operations by remote control.
They can also be used to turn many traditional open systems into closed ones, thereby expanding the scope of
automatic operations. For example, an electric light controlled by a clock represents a fairly simple open system;
its effectiveness depends entirely upon mechanical factors.
Regulated by a photoelectric cell that turns it off when
daylight approaches, the light responds to daily variations
in sunrise and sunset. Its operation is now meshed with its
function.
With the advent of the computer we enter an entirely
new dimension of industrial control systems. The computer is capable of performing all the routine tasks that
ordinarily burdened the mind of the worker a generation
or so ago. Basically, the modern digital computer is an
electronic calculator capable of performing arithmetical
operations enormously faster than the human brain.[26] This
element of speed is a crucial factor: the enormous rapidity
of computer operationsâa quantitative superiority of
computer over human calculationsâhas profound qualitative significance. By virtue of its speed, the computer can
perform highly sophisticated mathematical and logical
operations. Supported by memory units that store millions
of bits of information, and using binary arithmetic (the
substitution of the digits 0 and 1 for the digits 0 through
9), a properly programmed digital computer can perform
operations that approximate many highly developed logical activities of the mind. It is arguable whether computer
âintelligenceâ is, or ever will be, creative or innovative
(although every few years bring sweeping changes in computer technology), but there is no doubt that the digital
computer is capable of taking over all the onerous and
distinctly uncreative mental tasks of man in industry,
science, engineering, information retrieval and transportation. Modern man, in effect, has produced an electronic
âmindâ for coordinating, building and evaluating most of
his routine industrial operations. Properly used within the
sphere of competence for which they are designed, computers are faster and more efficient than man himself.
[26] There are two broad classes of computers in use today: analogue
and digital computers. The analogue computer has a fairly limited
use in industrial operations. My discussion on computers in this
article will deal entirely with digital computers.
What is the concrete significance of this new industrial
revolution? What are its immediate and foreseeable implications for work? Let us trace the impact of the new technology on the work process by examining its application
to the manufacture of automobile engines at the Ford
plant in Cleveland. This single instance of technological
sophistication will help us assess the liberatory potential of
the new technology in all manufacturing industries.
Until the advent of cybernation in the automobile
industry, the Ford plant required about three hundred
workers, using a large variety of tools and machines, to
turn an engine block into an engine. The process from
foundry casting to a fully machined engine took many
manhours to perform. With the development of what we
commonly call an âautomatedâ machine system, the time
required to transform the casting into an engine was reduced to less than fifteen minutes. Aside from a few monitors to watch the automatic control panels, the original
three-hundred-man labor force was eliminated. Later a
computer was added to the machining system, turning it
into a truly closed, cybernated system. The computer regulates the entire machining process, operating on an electronic pulse that cycles at a rate of three-tenths of a millionth of a second.
But even this system is obsolete. âThe next generation
of computing machines operates a thousand times as fastâat a pulse rate of one in every three-tenths of a billionth of
a second,â observes Alice Mary Hilton. âSpeeds of millionths and billionths of a second are not really intelligible
to our finite minds. But we can certainly understand that
the advance has been a thousand-fold within a year or two.
A thousand times as much information can be handled or
the same amount of information can be handled a thousand times as fast. A job that takes more than sixteen
hours can be done in one minute! And without any human
intervention! Such a system does not control merely an
assembly line but a complete manufacturing and industrial
process!â{15}
There is no reason why the basic technological principles involved in cybernating the manufacture of automobile engines cannot be applied to virtually every area of
mass manufactureâfrom the metallurgical industry to the
food processing industry, from the electronics industry to
the toymaking industry, from the manufacture of prefabricated bridges to the manufacture of prefabricated houses.
Many phases of steel production, tool-and-die making,
electronic equipment manufacture and industrial chemical
production are now partly or largely automated. What
tends to delay the advance of complete automation to
every phase of modern industry is the enormous cost involved in replacing existing industrial facilities by new,
more sophisticated ones and also the innate conservatism
of many major corporations. Finally, as I mentioned before, it is still cheaper to use labor instead of machines in
many industries.
To be sure, every industry has its own particular problems, and the application of a toil-less technology to a
specific plant would doubtless reveal a multitude of kinks
that would require painstaking solutions. In many industries it would be necessary to alter the shape of the product and the layout of the plants so that the manufacturing
process would lend itself to automated techniques. But to
argue from these problems that the application of a fully
automated technology to a specific industry is impossible
would be as preposterous as to have argued eighty years
ago that flight was impossible because the propeller of an
experimental airplane did not revolve fast enough or the
frame was too fragile to withstand buffeting by the wind.
There is practically no industry that cannot be fully automated if we are willing to redesign the product, the plant,
the manufacturing procedures and the handling methods.
In fact, any difficulty in describing how, where or when a
given industry will be automated arises not from the
unique problems we can expect to encounter but rather
from the enormous leaps that occur every few years in
modern technology. Almost every account of applied automation today must be regarded as provisional: as soon as
one describes a partially automated industry, technological
advances make the description obsolete.
There is one area of the economy, however, in which
any form of technological advance is worth describingâthe
area of work that is most brutalizing and degrading for
man. If it is true that the moral level of a society can be
gauged by the way it treats women, its sensitivity to
human suffering can be gauged by the working conditions
it provides for people in raw materials industries, particularly in mines and quarries. In the ancient world, mining
was often a form of penal servitude, reserved primarily for
the most hardened criminals, the most intractable slaves,
and the most hated prisoners of war. The mine is the day-to-day actualization of manâs image of hell; it is a deadening, dismal, inorganic world that demands pure mindless
toil.
Field and forest and stream and ocean are the
environment of life: the mine is the environment
alone of ores, minerals, metals [writes Lewis
Mumford].... In hacking and digging the contents
of the earth, the miner has no eye for the forms of
things: what he sees is sheer matter and until he
gets to his vein it is only an obstacle which he
breaks through stubbornly and sends up to the
surface. If the miner sees shapes on the walls of his
cavern, as the candle flickers, they are only the
monstrous distortions of his pick or his arm:
shapes of fear. Day has been abolished and the
rhythm of nature broken: continuous day-and-night production first came into existence here.
The miner must work by artificial light even
though the sun be shining outside; still further
down in the seams, he must work by artificial
ventilation, too: a triumph of the âmanufactured
environment.â{16}
The abolition of mining as a sphere of human activity
would symbolize, in its own way, the triumph of a liberatory technology. That we can point to this achievement
already, even in a single case at this writing, presages the
freedom from toil implicit in the technology of our time.
The first major step in this direction was the continuous
miner, a giant cutting machine with nine-foot blades that
slices up eight tons of coal a minute from the coal face. It
was this machine, together with mobile loading machines,
power drills and roof bolting, that reduced mine employment in areas like West Virginia to about a third of the
1948 levels, at the same time nearly doubling individual
output. The coal mine still required miners to place and
operate the machines. The most recent technological
advances, however, replace the operators by radar sensing
devices and eliminate the miner completely.
By adding sensing devices to automatic machinery we
could easily remove the worker not only from the large,
productive mines needed by the economy, but also from
forms of agricultural activity patterned on modern industry. Although the wisdom of industrializing and mechanizing agriculture is highly questionable (I shall return to this
subject at a later point), the fact remains that if society so
chooses, it can automate large areas of industrial agriculture, ranging from cotton picking to rice harvesting. We
could operate almost any machine, from a giant shovel in
an open-strip mine to a grain harvester in the Great Plains,
either by cybernated sensing devices or by remote control
with television cameras. The effort needed to operate these
devices and machines at a safe distance, in comfortable
quarters, would be minimal, assuming that a human operator were required at all.
It is easy to foresee a time, by no means remote, when a
rationally organized economy could automatically manufacture small âpackagedâ factories without human labor;
parts could be produced with so little effort that most
maintenance tasks would be reduced to the simple act of
removing a defective unit from a machine and replacing it
by anotherâa job no more difficult than pulling out and
putting in a tray. Machines would make and repair most of
the machines required to maintain such a highly industrialized economy. Such a technology, oriented entirely toward human needs and freed from all consideration of
profit and loss, would eliminate the pain of want and
toilâthe penalty, inflicted in the form of denial, suffering
and inhumanity, exacted by a society based on scarcity
and labor.
The possibilities created by a cybernated technology
would no longer be limited merely to the satisfaction of
manâs material needs. We would be free to ask how the
machine, the factory and the mine could be used to foster
human solidarity and to create a balanced relationship
with nature and a truly organic ecocommunity. Would our
new technology be based on the same national division of
labor that exists today? The current type of industrial
organizationâan extension, in effect, of the industrial
forms created by the Industrial Revolutionâfosters industrial centralization (although a system of workersâ management based on the individual factory and local community
would go far toward eliminating this feature).
Or does the new technology lend itself to a system of
small-scale production, based on a regional economy and
structured physically on a human scale? This type of industrial organization places *all* economic decisions in the
hands of the local community. To the degree that material
production is decentralized and localized, the primacy of
the community is asserted over national institutionsâassuming that any such national institutions develop to a
significant extent. In these circumstances, the popular
assembly of the local community, convened in a face-to-face democracy, takes over the *full* management of social
life. The question is whether a future society will be organized around technology or whether technology is now
sufficiently malleable so that it can be organized around
society. To answer this question, we must further examine
certain features of the new technology.
In 1945, J. Presper Eckert, Jr. and John W. Mauchly of
the University of Pennsylvania unveiled ENIAC, the first
digital computer to be designed entirely along electronic
principles. Commissioned for use in solving ballistic problems, ENIAC required nearly three years of work to design
and build. The computer was enormous. It weighed more
than thirty tons, contained 18,800 vacuum tubes with half
a million connections (these connections took Eckert and
Mauchly two and a half years to solder), a vast network of
resistors, and miles of wiring. The computer required a
large air-conditioning unit to cool its electronic components. It often broke down or behaved erratically, requiring time-consuming repairs and maintenance. Yet by all
previous standards of computer development, ENIAC was
an electronic marvel. It could perform five thousand computations a second, generating electrical pulse signals that
cycled at 100,000 a second. None of the mechanical or
electro-mechanical computers in use at the time could
approach this rate of computational speed.
Some twenty years later, the Computer Control Company of Framingham, Massachusetts, offered the DDP-124
for public sale. The DDP-124 is a small, compact computer
that closely resembles a bedside AM-radio receiver. The
entire ensemble, together with a typewriter and memory
unit, occupies a typical office desk. The DDP-124 performs over 285,000 computations a second. It has a true
stored-program memory that can be expanded to retain
nearly 33,000 words (the âmemoryâ of ENIAC, based on
preset plug wires, lacked anything like the flexibility of
present-day computers); its pulses cycle at 1.75 billion per
second. The DDP-124 does not require any air-conditioning unit; it is completely reliable, and it creates very few
maintenance problems. It can be built at a minute fraction
of the cost required to construct ENIAC.
The difference between ENIAC and DDP-124 is one of
degree rather than kind. Leaving aside their memory units,
both digital computers operate according to the same electronic principles. ENIAC, however, was composed primarily of traditional electronic components (vacuum
tubes, resistors, etc.) and thousands of feet of wire; the
DDP-124, on the other hand, relies primarily on micro-circuits. These microcircuits are very small electronic units
that pack the equivalent of ENIACâs key electronic components into squares a mere fraction of an inch in size.
Paralleling the miniaturization of computer components
is the remarkable sophistication of traditional forms of
technology. Ever-smaller machines are beginning to replace
large ones. For example, a fascinating breakthrough has
been achieved in reducing the size of continuous hot-strip
steel rolling mills. This kind of mill is one of the largest
and costliest facilities in modern industry. It may be regarded as a single machine, nearly a half mile in length,
capable of reducing a ten-ton slab of steel about six inches
thick and fifty inches wide to a thin strip of sheet metal a
tenth or a twelfth of an inch thick. This installation alone,
including heating furnaces, coilers, long roller tables, scale-breaker stands and buildings, may cost tens of millions of
dollars and occupy fifty acres or more. It produces three
hundred tons of steel sheet an hour. To be used efficiently,
such a continuous hot-strip mill must be operated together
with large batteries of coke ovens, open-hearth furnaces,
blooming mills, etc. These facilities, in conjunction with
hot and cold rolling mills, may cover several square miles.
Such a steel complex is geared to a national division of
labor, to highly concentrated sources of raw materials
(generally located at a great distance from the complex),
and to large national and international markets. Even if it
is totally automated, its operating and management needs
far transcend the capabilities of a small, decentralized
community. The type of administration it requires tends
to foster centralized social forms.
Fortunately, we now have a number of alternativesâmore efficient alternatives in many respectsâto the modern steel complex. We can replace blast furnaces and open-hearth furnaces by a variety of electric furnaces which are
generally quite small and produce excellent pig iron and
steel; they can operate not only with coke but also with
anthracite coal, charcoal, and even lignite. Or we can
choose the HyL process, a batch process in which natural
gas is used to turn high-grade ores or concentrates into
sponge iron. Or we can turn to the Wiberg process, which
involves the use of charcoal, carbon monoxide and hydrogen. I n any case, we can reduce the need for coke ovens,
blast furnaces, open hearth furnaces, and possibly even
solid reducing agents.
One of the most important steps towards scaling a steel
complex to community dimensions isâthe development of
the planetary mill by T. Sendzimir. The planetary mill
reduces the typical continuous hot-strip mill to a single
planetary stand and a light finishing stand. Hot steel slabs,
two and a quarter inches thick, pass through two small
pairs of heated feed rolls and a set of work rolls mounted
in two circular cages which also contain two backup rolls.
By operating the cages and backup rolls at different rotational speeds, the work rolls are made to turn in two directions. This gives the steel slab a terrific mauling and
reduces it to a thickness of only one-tenth of an inch.
Sendzimirâs planetary mill is a stroke of engineering genius;
the small work rolls, turning on the two circular cages,
replace the need for the four huge roughing stands and six
finishing stands in a continuous hot-strip mill.
The rolling of hot steel slabs by the Sendzimir process
requires a much smaller operational area than a continuous
hot-strip mill. With continuous casting, moreover, we can
produce steel slabs without the need for large, costly slabbing mills. A future steel complex based on electric furnaces, continuous casting, a planetary mill and a small
continuous cold-reducing mill would require a fraction of
the acreage occupied by a conventional installation. It
would be fully capable of meeting the steel needs of several moderate-sized communities with low quantities of
fuel.
The complex I have described is not designed to meet
the needs of a national market. On the contrary, it is
suited only for meeting the steel requirements of small or
moderate-sized communities and industrially undeveloped
countries. Most electric furnaces for pig-iron production
produce about a hundred to two hundred and fifty tons a
day, while large blast furnaces produce three thousand
tons daily. A planetary mill can roll only a hundred tons of
steel strip an hour, roughly a third of the output of a
continuous hot-strip mill. Yet the very scale of our hypothetical steel complex constitutes one of its most attractive
features. Also, the steel produced by our complex is more
durable, so the communityâs rate of replenishing its steel
products would be appreciably reduced. Since the smaller
complex requires ore, fuel and reducing agents in relatively
small quantities, many communities could rely on local
resources for their raw materials, thereby conserving the
more concentrated resources of centrally located sources
of supply, strengthening the independence of the community itself vis-a-vis the traditional centralized economy,
and reducing the expense of transportation. What would at
first glance seem to be a costly, inefficient duplication of
effort that could be avoided by building a few centralized
steel complexes would prove, in the long run, to be more
efficient as well as socially more desirable.
The new technology has produced not only miniaturized electronic components and smaller production facilities but also highly versatile, multi-purpose machines. For
more than a century, the trend in machine design moved
increasingly toward technological specialization and single
purpose devices, underpinning the intensive division of
labor required by the new factory system. Industrial operations were subordinated entirely to the product. In time,
this narrow pragmatic approach has âled industry far from
the rational line of development in production machinery,â observe Eric W. Leaver and John J. Brown. âIt has
led to increasingly uneconomic specialization.... Specialization of machines in terms of end product requires that
the machine be thrown away when the product is no
longer needed. Yet the work the production machine does
can be reduced to a set of basic functionsâforming, holding, cutting, and so onâand these functions, if correctly
analyzed, can be packaged and applied to operate on a part
as needed.â{17}
Ideally, a drilling machine of the kind envisioned by
Leaver and Brown would be able to produce a hole small
enough to hold a thin wire or large enough to admit a
pipe. Machines with this operational range were once
regarded as economically prohibitive. By the mid-1950s,
however, a number of such machines were actually designed and put to use. In 1954, for example, a horizontal
boring mill was built in Switzerland for the Ford Motor
Companyâs River Rouge Plant at Dearborn, Michigan. This
boring mill would qualify beautifully as a Leaver and
Brown machine. Equipped with five optical microscope-type illuminated control gauges, the mill drills holes
smaller than a needleâs eye or larger than a manâs fist. The
holes are accurate to a ten-thousandth of an inch.
The importance of machines with this kind of operational range can hardly be overestimated. They make it
possible to produce a large variety of products in a single
plant. A small or moderate-sized community using multipurpose machines could satisfy many of its limited industrial needs without being burdened with underused industrial facilities. There would be less loss in scrapping tools
and less need for single-purpose plants. The communityâs
economy would be more compact and versatile, more
rounded and self-contained, than anything we find in the
communities of industrially advanced countries. The effort
that goes into retooling machines for new products would
be enormously reduced. Retooling would generally consist
of changes in dimensioning rather than in design. Finally,
multipurpose machines with a wide operational range are
relatively easy to automate. The changes required to use
these machines in a cybernated industrial facility would
generally be in circuitry and programming rather than in
machine form and structure.
Single purpose machines, of course, would continue to
exist, and they would still be used for the mass manufacture of a large variety of goods. At present many highly
automatic, single-purpose machines could be employed
with very little modification by decentralized communities. Bottling and canning machines, for example, are
compact, automatic and highly rationalized installations.
We could expect to see smaller automatic textile, chemical
processing and food processing machines. A major shift
from conventional automobiles, buses and trucks to electric vehicles would undoubtedly lead to industrial facilities
much smaller in size than existing automobile plants. Many
of the remaining centralized facilities could be effectively
decentralized simply by making them as small as possible
and sharing their use among several communities.
I do not claim that all of manâs economic activities can
be completely decentralized, but the majority can surely
be scaled to human and communitarian dimensions. This
much is certain: we can shift the center of economic
power from national to local scale and from centralized
bureaucratic forms to local, popular assemblies. This shift
would be a revolutionary change of vast proportions, for it
would create powerful economic foundations for the
sovereignty and autonomy of the local community.
I have tried, thus far, to deal with the possibility of eliminating toil, material insecurity, and centralized economic
controlâissues which, if âutopian,â are at least tangible. In
the present section I would like to deal with a problem
that may seem highly subjective but which is nonetheless
of compelling importanceâthe need to make manâs dependence upon the natural world a visible and living part of
his culture.
Actually, this problem is peculiar only to a highly
urbanized and industrialized society. In nearly all preindustrial cultures, manâs relationship to his natural environment was well defined, viable, and sanctified by the full
weight of tradition. Changes in season, variations in rainfall, the life cycles of the plants and animals on which
humans depended for food and clothing, the distinctive
features of the area occupied by the communityâall were
familiar and comprehensible, and evoked in men a sense of
religious awe, of oneness with nature, and, more pragmatically, a sense of respectful dependence. Looking back to
the earliest civilizations of the Western world, we rarely
find evidence of a system of social tyranny so overbearing
and ruthless that it ignored this relationship. Barbarian
invasions and, more insidiously, the development of
commercial civilizations may have destroyed the reverential attitude of agrarian cultures toward nature, but the
normal development of agricultural systems, however exploitative they were of men, rarely led to the destruction
of the soil and terrain. During the most oppressive periods
in the history of ancient Egypt and Mesopotamia, the
ruling classes kept the irrigation dikes in good repair and
tried to promote rational methods of food cultivation.
Even the ancient Greeks, heirs to a thin, mountainous
forest soil that suffered heavily from erosion, shrewdly
reclaimed much of their arable land by turning to orchardry and viticulture. It was not until commercial agricultural systems and highly urbanized societies developed
that the natural environment was unsparingly exploited.
Some of the worst cases of soil destruction in the ancient
world were provided by the giant, slave-worked commercial farms of North Africa and the Italian peninsula.
In our own time, the development of technology and
the growth of cities has brought manâs alienation from
nature to the breaking point. Western man finds himself
confined to a largely synthetic urban environment, far
removed physically from the land, and his relationship to
the natural world is mediated entirely by machines. He
lacks familiarity with how most of his goods are produced,
and his foods bear only the faintest resemblance to the
animals and plants from which they were derived. Boxed
into a sanitized urban milieu (almost institutional in form
and appearance), modern man is denied even a spectatorâs
role in the agricultural and industrial systems that satisfy
his material needs. He is a pure consumer, an insensate
receptacle. It would be unfair, perhaps, to say that he is
disrespectful toward the natural environment; the fact is,
he scarcely knows what ecology means or what his environment requires to remain in balance.
The balance between man and nature must be restored.
I have tried to show elsewhere that unless we establish
some kind of equilibrium between man and the natural
world, the viability of the human species will be placed in
grave jeopardy.[27] Here I shall try to show how the new
technology can be used ecologically to reawaken manâs
sense of dependence upon the environment; I shall try to
show how, by reintroducing the natural world into the
human experience, we can contribute to the achievement
of human wholeness.
[27] See âEcology and Revolutionary Thought.â
The classical Utopians fully realized that the first step
towards wholeness must be to remove the contradiction
between town and country. âIt is impossible,â wrote
Fourier nearly a century and a half ago, âto organize a
regular and well balanced association without bringing into
play the labors of the field, or at least gardens, orchards,
flocks and herds, poultry yards, and a great variety of
species, animal and vegetable.â Shocked by the social
effects of the Industrial Revolution, Fourier added: âThey
are ignorant of this principle in England, where they experiment with artisans, with manufacturing labor alone,
which cannot by itself suffice to sustain social union.â{18}
To argue that the modern urban dweller should once
again enjoy âthe labors of the fieldâ might well seem like
gallows humor. A restoration of peasant agriculture prevalent in Fourierâs day is neither possible nor desirable.
Charles Gide was surely correct when he observed that
agricultural labor âis not necessarily more attractive than
industrial labor; to till the earth has always been regarded
... as the type of painful toil, of toil which is done with
âthe sweat of oneâs brow.â{19} Fourier does not answer this
objection by suggesting that his phalansteries will mainly
cultivate fruits and vegetables instead of grains. If our
vision were to extend no further than prevailing techniques
of land management, the only alternative to peasant agriculture would seem to be a highly specialized and centralized form of farming, its techniques paralleling the
methods used in present-day industry. Far from achieving
a balance between town and country, we would be faced
with a synthetic environment that had totally assimilated
the natural world.
If we grant that the land and the community must be
reintegrated physically, that the community must exist in
an agricultural matrix which renders manâs dependence
upon nature explicit, the problem we face is how to
achieve this transformation without imposing âpainful
toilâ on the community. How, in short, can husbandry,
ecological forms of food cultivation and farming on a human scale be practiced without sacrificing mechanization?
Some of the most promising technological advances in
agriculture made since World War II are as suitable for
small-scale, ecological forms of land management as they
are for the immense, industrial-type commercial units that
have become prevalent over the past few decades. Let us
consider an example. The augermatic feeding of livestock
illustrates a cardinal principle of rational farm mechanizationâthe deployment of conventional machines and devices in a way that virtually eliminates arduous farm labor.
By linking a battery of silos with augers, different nutrients can be mixed and transported to feed pens merely by
pushing some buttons and pulling a few switches. A job
that may have required the labor of five or six men working half a day with pitchforks and buckets can now be
performed by one man in a few minutes. This type of
mechanization is intrinsically neutral: it can be used to
feed immense herds or just a few hundred head of cattle;
the silos may contain natural feed or synthetic, hormonized nutrients; the feeder can be employed on relatively
small farms with mixed livestock or on large beef-raising
ranches, or on dairy farms of all sizes. In short, augermatic
feeding can be placed in the service of the most abusive
kind of commercial exploitation or of the most sensitive
applications of ecological principles.
This holds true for most of the farm machines that have
been designed (in many cases simply redesigned to achieve
greater versatility) in recent years. The modern tractor, for
example, is a work of superb mechanical ingenuity. Garden-type models can be used with extraordinary flexibility
for a large variety of tasks; they are light and extremely
manageable, and they can follow the contour of the most
exacting terrain without damaging the land. Large tractors,
especially those used in hot climates, are likely to have
air-conditioned cabs; in addition to pulling equipment,
they may have attachments for digging postholes, for
doing the work of forklift trucks, or even for providing
power units for grain elevators. Plows have been developed
to meet every contingency in tillage. Advanced models are
even regulated hydraulically to rise and fall with the lay of
the land. Mechanical planters are available for virtually
every kind of crop. âMinimum tillageâ is achieved by
planters which apply seed, fertilizer and pesticides (of
course!) simultaneously, a technique that telescopes several different operations into a single one and reduces the
soil compaction often produced by the recurrent use of
heavy machines.
The variety of mechanical harvesters has reached dazzling proportions. Harvesters have been developed for
many different kinds of orchards, berries, vines, vegetables
and field crops. Barns, feed pens and storage units have
been totally revolutionized by augers, conveyor belts, airtight silos, automatic manure removers, climate-control
devices, etc. Crops are mechanically shelled, washed,
counted, preserved by freezing or canning, packaged and
crated. The construction of concrete-lined irrigation
ditches has become a simple mechanical operation that can
be performed by one or two excavating machines. Terrain
with poor drainage or subsoil can be improved by earth-moving equipment and by tillage devices that penetrate
beyond the true soil.
Although a great deal of agricultural research is devoted
to the development of harmful chemical agents and nutritionally dubious crops, there have been extraordinary
advances in the genetic improvement of food plants. Many
new grain and vegetable varieties are resistant to insect
predators, plant diseases, and cold weather. In many cases,
these varieties are a definite improvement over natural
ancestral types and they have been used to open large areas
of intractable land to food cultivation.
Let us pause at this point to envision how our free
community might be integrated with its natural environment. We suppose the community to have been established
after a careful study has been made of its natural ecologyâits air and water resources, its climate, its geological
formations, its raw materials, its soils, and its natural flora
and fauna. Land management by the community is guided
entirely by ecological principles, so that an equilibrium is
maintained between the environment and its human inhabitants. Industrially rounded, the community forms a
distinct unit within a natural matrix; it is socially and
aesthetically in balance with the area it occupies.
Agriculture is highly mechanized in the community, but
as mixed as possible with respect to crops, livestock and
timber. Variety of flora and fauna is promoted as a means
of controlling pest infestations and enhancing scenic
beauty. Large-scale farming is practiced only where it does
not conflict with the ecology of the region. Owing to the
generally mixed character of food cultivation, agriculture
is pursued by small farming units, each demarcated from
the others by tree belts, shrubs, pastures and meadows. In
rolling, hilly or mountainous country, land with sharp
gradients is covered by timber to prevent erosion and
conserve water. The soil on each acre is studied carefully
and committed only to those crops for which it is most
suited. Every effort is made to blend town and country
without sacrificing the distinctive contribution that each
has to offer to the human experience. The ecological region forms the living social, cultural and biotic boundaries
of the community or of the several communities that share
its resources. Each community contains many vegetable
and flower gardens, attractive arbors, park land, even
streams and ponds which support fish and aquatic birds.
The countryside, from which food and raw materials are
acquired, not only constitutes the immediate environs of
the community, accessible to all by foot, but also invades
the community. Although town and country retain their
identity and the uniqueness of each is highly prized and
fostered, nature appears everywhere in the town, and the
town seems to have caressed and left a gentle, human imprint on nature.
I believe that a free community will regard agriculture as
husbandry, an activity as expressive and enjoyable as
crafts. Relieved of toil by agricultural machines, communitarians will approach food cultivation with the same
playful and creative attitude that men so often bring to
gardening. Agriculture will become a living part of human
society, a source of pleasant physical activity and, by virtue of its ecological demands, an intellectual, scientific and
artistic challenge. Communitarians will blend with the
world of life around them as organically as the community
blends with its region. They will regain the sense of oneness with nature that existed in humans from primordial
times. Nature and the organic modes of thought it always
fosters will become an integral part of human culture; it
will reappear with a fresh spirit in manâs paintings, literature, philosophy, dances, architecture, domestic furnishings, and in his very gestures and day-to-day activities.
Culture and the human psyche will be thoroughly suffused
by a new animism. The region will never be exploited, but
it will be used as fully as possible. Every attempt will be
made by the community to satisfy its requirements locallyâto use the regionâs energy resources, minerals, timber, soil, water, animals and plants as rationally and
humanistically as possible and without violating ecological
principles. In this connection, we can foresee that the
community will employ new techniques that are still being
developed today, many of which lend themselves superbly
to a regionally based economy. I refer hereto methods for
extracting trace and diluted resources from the earth,
water and air; to solar, wind, hydroelectric and geothermal
energy; to the use of heat pumps, vegetable fuels, solar
ponds, thermoelectric converters and, eventually, controlled thermonuclear reactions.
There is a kind of industrial archeology that reveals in
many areas the evidence of a once-burgeoning economic
activity long abandoned by our predecessors. In the Hudson Valley, the Rhine Valley, the Appalachians and the
Pyrenees, we find the relics of mines and once highly-developed metallurgical crafts, the fragmentary remains of
local industries, and the outlines of long-deserted farmsâall vestiges of flourishing communities based on local raw
materials and resources. These communities declined because the products they once furnished were elbowed out
by large-scale, national industries based on mass production techniques and concentrated sources of raw materials.
The old resources are often still available for use by each
locality; âvaluelessâ in a highly urbanized society, they are
eminently suitable for use by decentralized communities
and they await the application of industrial techniques
that are adapted for small-scale quality production. If we
were to take a careful inventory of the resources available
in many depopulated regions of the world, the possibility
that communities could satisfy many of their material
needs locally is likely to be much greater than we suspect.
Technology, by its continual development, tends to expand local possibilities. As an example, let us consider how
seemingly inferior and highly intractable resources are
made available by technological advances. Throughout the
late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, the Mesabi
range in Minnesota provided the American steel industry
with extremely rich ores, an advantage which promoted
the rapid expansion of the domestic metal industry. As
these reserves declined, the country was faced with the
problem of mining taconite, a low-grade ore that is about
forty percent iron. Conventional mining methods are virtually impossible; it takes a churn drill an hour to bite
through only one foot of taconite. Recently, however, the
mining of taconite became feasible; a jet-flame drill was
developed which cuts through the ore at the rate of twenty
to thirty feet an hour. After holes are burned by the flame,
the ore is blasted and processed for the steel industry by
newly perfected grinding, separating and agglomerating
operations.
Soon it may be possible to extract highly diffused or
diluted materials from the earth, from a wide variety of
gaseous waste products, and from the sea. Some of our
most valuable metals are actually fairly common, but they
exist in highly diffused or trace amounts. Hardly a patch
of soil or a common rock exists that does not contain
traces of gold, larger quantities of uranium, and even larger
amounts of other industrially useful elements such as
magnesium, zinc, copper and sulphur. About five percent
of the earthâs crust is made of iron. How can we extract
these resources? The problem has been solved, in principle
at least, by the analytical techniques chemists use to detect
these elements. As the chemist Jacob Rosin argues, if an
element can be detected in the laboratory, there is reason
to hope that it can be extracted on a sufficiently large
scale to be used by industry.
For more than half a century, most of the worldâs
commercial nitrogen has been extracted from the atmosphere. Magnesium, chlorine, bromine and caustic soda are
acquired from sea water and sulphur from calcium sulphate and industrial wastes. Large amounts of industrially
useful hydrogen could be collected as a byproduct of the
electrolysis of brine, but normally it is burned or released
in the air by chlorine-producing plants. Carbon could be
rescued in enormous quantities from smoke and used economically (carbon is comparatively rare in nature) but is
dissipated together with other gaseous compounds in the
atmosphere.
The problem industrial chemists face in extracting valuable elements and compounds from the sea and ordinary
rock is the cost of the energy needed. Two methods
existâion exchange and chromatographyâand, if further
perfected for industrial uses, they could be used to select
or separate the desired substances from solutions, but the
amount of energy needed to use these methods would be
very costly in terms of real wealth. Unless there is an unexpected breakthrough in extractive techniques, there is
little likelihood that conventional sources of energyâfossil
fuels like coal and oilâwill be used to solve the problem.
It is not that we lack energy *per se*, but we are just
beginning to learn how to use sources that are available in
almost limitless quantity. The gross radiant energy striking
the earthâs surface from the sun is estimated to be more
than three thousand times the annual energy consumption
of mankind today. Although a portion of this energy is
converted into wind or used for photosynthesis by vegetation, a staggering quantity is available for other uses. The
problem is how to collect it to satisfy a portion of our
energy needs. If solar energy could be collected for house
heating, for example, twenty to thirty percent of the conventional energy resources we normally employ could be
redirected to other purposes. If we could collect solar
energy for all or most of our cooking, water heating, smelting and power production, we would have relatively little
need for fossil fuels. Solar devices have been designed for
nearly all of these functions. We can heat houses, cook
food, boil water, melt metals and produce electricity with
devices that use the sunâs energy exclusively, but we canât
do it efficiently in every latitude of the earth, and we are
still confronted with a number of technical problems that
can be solved only by crash research programs.
At this writing, quite a few houses have been built that
are effectively heated by solar energy. In the United
States, the best known of these are the MIT experimental
buildings in Massachusetts, the Lof house in Denver, and
the Thomason homes in Washington, D.C. Thomason,
whose fuel cost for a solar-heated house barely reaches $5
a year, seems to have developed one of the most practical
systems at hand. Solar heat in a Thomason home is collected from the roof and transferred by circulating water
to a storage tank in the basement. (The water, incidentally,
can also be used for cooling the house and as an emergency
supply for fire and drinking.) The system is simple and
fairly cheap. Located in Washington near the fortieth
parallel of latitude, the Thomason houses stand at the edge
of the âsolar beltââthe latitudes from zero to forty degrees north and south. This belt is the geographic area
where the sunâs rays can be used most effectively for
domestic and industrial energy. With efficient solar heating, Thomason requires a miniscule amount of supple
mental conventional fuel to heat his Washington homes.
Two approaches to solar house-heating are possible in
cooler areas: heating systems could be more elaborate,
which would reduce the consumption of conventional fuel
to levels approximating those of the Thomason homes; or
simple conventional fuel systems could be used to satisfy
anywhere from ten to fifty percent of the heating needs.
As Hans Thirring observes (with an eye toward cost and
effort):
The decisive advantage of solar heating lies in the
fact that no running costs arise, except the electricity bill for driving the fans, which is very small.
Thus the one single investment for the installation
pays once and for all the heating costs for the lifetime of the house. In addition, the system works
automatically without smoke, soot, and fume
production, and saves all trouble in stoking, refuelling, cleaning, repair and other work. Adding solar
heat to the energy system of a country helps to
increase the wealth of the nation, and if all houses
in areas with favorable conditions were equipped
with solar heating systems, fuel saving worth millions of pounds yearly could be achieved. The
work of Telkes, Hottel, Lof, Bliss, and other scientists who are paving the way for solar heating is
real pioneer work, the full significance of which
will emerge more clearly in the future.{20}
The most widespread applications of solar energy devices
are in cooking and water heating. Many thousands of solar
stoves are used in underdeveloped countries, in Japan, and
in the warm latitudes of the United States. A solar stove is
simply an umbrella-like reflector equipped with a grill that
can broil meat or boil a quart of water within fifteen
minutes in bright sunlight. Such a stove is safe, portable
and clean; it requires no fuel or matches, nor does it
produce any annoying smoke. A portable solar oven delivers temperatures as high as four hundred fifty degrees
and is even more compact and easier to handle than a solar
stove. Solar water-heaters are used widely in private
homes, apartment buildings, laundries and swimming
pools. Some twenty-five thousand of these units are
employed in Florida and they are gradually coming into
vogue in California.
Some of the most impressive advances in the use of solar
energy have occurred in industry, although the majority of
these applications are marginal at best and largely experimental in nature. The simplest is the solar furnace. The
collector is usually a single large parabolic mirror, or, more
likely, a huge array of many parabolic mirrors mounted in
a large housing. A heliostatâa smaller, horizontally
mounted mirror that follows the movement of the sunâreflects the rays into the collector. Several hundred of
these furnaces are currently in use. One of the largest, Dr.
Felix Trombeâs Mont Louis furnace, develops seventy-five
kilowatts of electric power and is used primarily in high-temperature research. Since the sunâs rays do not contain
any impurities, the furnace will melt a hundred pounds of
metal without the contamination produced by conventional techniques. A solar furnace built by the U.S.
Quartermaster Corps at Nattick, Massachusetts, develops
five thousand degrees Centigradeâa temperature high
enough to melt steel I-beams.
Solar furnaces have many limitations, but these are not
insurmountable. The efficiency of the furnaces can be
appreciably reduced by haze, fog, clouds and atmospheric
dust, and also by heavy wind loadings which deflect equipment and interfere with the accurate focusing of the sunâs
rays. Attempts are being made to resolve some of these
problems by sliding roofs, covering material for the mirrors, and firm, protective housings. On the other hand,
solar furnaces are clean, they are efficient when they are in
good working order, and they produce extremely high-grade metals which none of the conventional furnaces currently in use can match.
Equally promising as an area of research are current
attempts to convert solar energy into electricity. Theoretically, an area roughly a square yard in size placed
perpendicular to the sunâs rays receives energy equivalent
to one kilowatt. âConsidering that in the arid zones of the
world many millions of square meters of desert land are
free for power production,â observes Thirring, âwe find
that by utilizing only one percent of the available ground
for solar plants a capacity could be reached far higher than
the present installed capacity of all fuel-operated and
hydroelectric power plants in the world.â{21} In practice,
work along the lines suggested by Thirring has been inhibited by cost considerations, by market factors (there is no
large demand for electricity in those underdeveloped, hot
areas of the world where the project is most feasible) and
by essentially the conservatism of designers in the power
field. Research emphasis has been placed on the development of solar batteriesâa result largely of work on the
âspace program.â
Solar batteries are based on the thermoelectric effect. If
strips of antimony and bismuth are joined in a loop, for
example, a temperature differential made, say, by producing heat in onejunction, yields electric power. Research on
solar batteries over the past decade or so resulted in devices that have a power-converting efficiency as high as
fifteen percent, and twenty to twenty-five percent is quite
attainable in the not too distant future[28] Grouped in large
panels, solar batteries have been used to power electric
cars, small boats, telephone lines, radios, phonographs,
clocks, sewing machines and other appliances. Eventually,
the cost of producing solar batteries is expected to diminish to a point where they will provide electric power for
homes and even small industrial facilities.
[28] The efficiency of the gasoline engine is rated at around eleven
percent, to cite a comparison.
Finally, the sunâs energy can be used in still another
wayâby collecting heat in a body of water. For some time
now, engineers have been studying ways of acquiring electric power from the temperature differences produced by
the sunâs heat in the sea. Theoretically, a solar pond
occupying a square kilometer could yield thirty million
kilowatt-hours of electricity annuallyâenough to match
the output of a sizeable power station operating more than
twelve hours every day of the year. The power, as Henry
Tabor observes, can be acquired without any fuel costs,
âmerely by the pond lying in the sun.â{22} Heat can be
extracted from the bottom of the pond by passing the hot
water over a heat exchanger and then returning the water
to the pond. In warm latitudes, ten thousand square miles
committed to this method of power production would
provide enough electricity to satisfy the needs of four
hundred million people!
The oceanâs tides are still another untapped resource to
which we could turn for electric power. We could trap the
oceanâs waters at high tide in a natural basinâsay a bay or
the mouth of a riverâand release them through turbines at
low tide. A number of places exist where the tides are high
enough to produce electric power in large quantities. The
French have already built an immense tidal-power installation near the mouth of the Ranee River at St. Malo with
an expected net yield of 544 million kilowatt-hours
annually. They also plan to build another dam in the bay
of Mont-Saint-Michel. In England, highly suitable conditions for a tidal dam exist above the confluence of the
Severn and Wye rivers. A dam here could provide the
electric power produced by a million tons of coal annually.
A superb location for producing tide-generated electricity
exists at Passamaquoddy Bay on the border between Maine
and New Brunswick, and good locales exist on the Mezen
Gulf, a Russian coastal area in the Arctic. Argentina has
plans for building a tidal dam across the estuary of the
Deseado River near Puerto Desire on the Atlantic coast.
Many other coastal areas could be used to generate electricity from tidal power, but except for France no country
has started work on this resource.
We could use temperature differences in the sea or in
the earth to generate electric power in sizeable quantities.
A temperature differential as high as seventeen degrees
Centigrade is not uncommon in the surface layers of tropical waters; along coastal areas of Siberia, winter differences of thirty degrees exist between water below the ice
crust and the air. The interior of the earth becomes progressively warmer as we descend, providing selective
temperature differentials with respect to the surface. Heat
pumps could be used to avail ourselves of these differentials for industrial purposes or to heat homes. The heat
pump works like a mechanical refrigerator: a circulating
refrigerant draws off heat from a medium, dissipates it,
and returns to repeat the process. During winter months,
the pumps, circulating a refrigerant in a shallow well, could
be used to absorb subsurface heat and release it in a house.
In the summer the process could be reversed: heat withdrawn from the house could be dissipated in the earth. The
pumps do not require costly chimneys, they do not pollute
the atmosphere, and they eliminate the nuisance of stoking
furnaces and carrying out ashes. If we could acquire electricity or direct heat from solar energy, wind power or
temperature differentials, the heating system of a home or
factory would be completely self-sustaining; it would not
drain valuable hydrocarbon resources or require external
sources of supply.
Winds could also be used to provide electric power in
many areas of the world. About one-fortieth of the solar
energy reaching the earthâs surface is converted into wind.
Although much of this goes into making the jet stream, a
great deal of wind energy is available a few hundred feet
above the ground. A UN report, using monetary terms to
gauge the feasibility of wind power, finds that efficient
wind plants in many areas could produce electricity at an
overall cost of five mills per kilowatt-hour, a figure that
approximates the price of commercially generated electric
power. Several wind generators have already been used
with success. The famous 1,250 kilowatt generator at
Grandpaâs Knob near Rutland, Vermont, successfully fed
alternating current into the lines of the Central Vermont
Public Service Co. until a parts shortage during World War
II made it difficult to keep the installation in good repair.
Since then, larger, more efficient generators have been
designed. P. H. Thomas, working for the Federal Power
Commission, has designed a 7,500 kilowatt windmill that
would provide electricity at a capital investment of $68
per kilowatt. Eugene Ayres notes that if the construction
costs of Thomasâs windmill were double the amount
estimated by its designer, âwind turbines would seem
nevertheless to compare favorably with hydroelectric installations which cost around $300 per kilowatt.â{23} An
enormous potential for generating electricity by means of
wind power exists in many regions of the world. In
England, for example, where a careful three-year survey
was made of possible wind-power sites, it was found that
the newer wind turbines could generate several million
kilowatts, saving from two to four million tons of coal
annually.
There should be no illusions about the extraction of
trace minerals from rocks, about solar and wind power, or
about the use of heat pumps. Except perhaps for tidal
power and the extraction of raw materials from the sea,
these sources cannot supply man with the bulky quantities
of raw materials and the large blocks of energy needed to
sustain densely concentrated populations and highly centralized industries. Solar devices, wind turbines, and heat
pumps will produce relatively small quantities of power.
Used locally and in conjunction with each other, they
could probably meet all the power needs of small communities, but we cannot foresee a time when they will be
able to furnish the electricity currently used by cities the
size of New York, London or Paris.
Limitation of scope, however, could represent a profound advantage from an ecological point of view. The
sun, the wind and the earth are experiential realities to
which men have responded sensuously and reverently from
time immemorial. Out of these primal elements man developed his sense of dependence onâand respect forâthe
natural environment, a dependence that kept his destructive activities in check. The Industrial Revolution and the
urbanized world that followed obscured natureâs role in
human experienceâhiding the sun with a pall of smoke,
blocking the winds with massive buildings, desecrating the
earth with sprawling cities. Manâs dependence on the
natural world became invisible; it became theoretical and
intellectual in character, the subject matter of textbooks,
monographs and lectures. True, this theoretical dependence supplied us with insights (partial ones at best) into
the natural world, but its onesidedness robbed us of all
sensuous dependence on and all visible contact and unity
with nature. In losing these, we lost a part of ourselves as
feeling beings. We became alienated from nature. Our technology and environment became totally inanimate, totally
syntheticâa purely inorganic physical milieu that promoted the deanimization of man and his thought.
To bring the sun, the wind, the earth, indeed the world
of life, back into technology, into the means of human
survival, would be a revolutionary renewal of manâs ties to
nature. To restore this dependence in away that evoked a
sense of regional uniqueness in each communityâa sense
not only of generalized dependence but of dependence on
a specific region with distinct qualities of its ownâwould
give this renewal a truly ecological character. A real ecological system would emerge, a delicately interlaced pattern of local resources, honored by continual study and
artful modification. With the growth of a true sense of
regionalism every resource would find its place in a natural, stable balance, an organic unity of social, technological and natural elements. Art would assimilate technology by becoming social art, the art of the community
as a whole. The free community would be able to rescale
the tempo of life, the work patterns of man, its own
architecture and its systems of transportation and communication to human dimensions. The electric car, quiet,
slow-moving and clean, would become the preferred mode
of urban transportation, replacing the noisy, filthy, highspeed automobile. Monorails would link community to
community, reducing the number of highways that scar
the countryside. Crafts would regain their honored position as supplements to mass manufacture; they would become a form of domestic, day-to-day artistry. A high standard of excellence, I believe, would replace the strictly
quantitative criteria of production that prevail today; a
respect for the durability of goods and the conservation of
raw materials would replace the shabby, huckster-oriented
criteria that result in built-in obsolescence and an insensate
consumer society. The community would become a beautifully molded arena of life, a vitalizing source of culture
and a deeply personal, ever-nourishing source of human
solidarity.
In a future revolution, the most pressing task of technology will be to produce a surfeit of goods with a minimum of toil. The immediate purpose of this task will be to
open the social arena permanently to the revolutionary
people, *to keep the revolution in permanence*. Thus far
every social revolution has foundered because the peal of
the tocsin could not be heard over the din of the workshop. Dreams of freedom and plenty were polluted by the
mundane, workaday responsibility of producing the means
of survival. Looking back at the brute facts of history, we
find that as long as revolution meant continual sacrifice
and denial for the people, the reins of power fell into the
hands of the political âprofessionals,â the mediocrities of
Thermidor. How well the liberal Girondins of the French
Convention understood this reality can be judged by their
effort to reduce the revolutionary fervor of the Parisian
popular assembliesâthe great sections of 1793âby decreeing that the meetings should close âat ten in the evening,â
or, as Carlyle tells us, âbefore the working people
come...â from their jobs.{24} The decree proved ineffective, but it was well aimed. Essentially, the tragedy of past
revolutions has been that, sooner or later, their doors
closed, âat ten in the evening.â <em>The most critical function
of modern technology must be to keep the doors of the
revolution open forever!</em>
Nearly a half century ago, while Social-Democratic and
Communist theoreticians babbled about a society with
âwork for all,â the Dadaists, those magnificent madmen,
demanded unemployment for everybody. The decades
have detracted nothing from the significance of this demand, and they have added to its content. From the
moment toil is reduced to the barest possible minimum or
disappears entirely, the problems of survival pass into the
problems of life, and technology itself passes from being
the servant of manâs immediate needs to being the partner
of his creativity.
Let us look at this matter closely. Much has been written about technology as an âextension of man.â The
phrase is misleading if it is meant to apply to technology as
a whole. It has validity primarily for the traditional handicraft shop and, perhaps, for the early stages of machine
development. The craftsman dominates his tool; his labor,
artistic inclinations, and personality are the sovereign factors in the productive process. Labor is not merely an
expenditure of energy; it is also the personalized work of a
man whose activities are sensuously directed toward preparing his product, fashioning it, and finally decorating it
for human use. The craftsman guides the tool, not the tool
the craftsman. Whatever alienation may exist between the
craftsman and his product is immediately overcome, as
Friedrich Wilhelmsen emphasized, âby an artistic judgmentâa judgment bearing on a thing to be made.â{25} The
tool amplifies the powers of the craftsman as a *human*; it
amplifies his power to exercise his artistry and impart his
identity as a creative being to raw materials.
The development of the machine tends to rupture the
intimate relationship between man and the means of production. It assimilates the worker to preset industrial tasks,
tasks over which he exercises no control. The machine now
appears as an alien forceâapart from and yet wedded to
the production of the means of survival. Although initially
an âextension of man,â technology is transformed into a
force above man, orchestrating his life according to a score
contrived by an industrial bureaucracy; not *men*, I repeat,
but a *bureaucracy, a social machine*. With the arrival of
mass production as the predominant mode of production,
man became an extension of the machine, and not only of
mechanical devices in the productive process but also of
social devices in the social process. When he becomes an
extension of a machine, man ceases to exist for his own
sake. Society is ruled by the harsh maxim: âproduction for
the sake of production.â The decline from craftsman to
worker, from an active to an increasingly passive personality, is completed by man *qua* consumerâan economic entity whose tastes, values, thoughts and sensibilities are
engineered by bureaucratic âteamsâ in âthink tanks.â
Man, standardized by machines, is reduced to a machine.
Man-the-machine is the bureaucratic ideal.[29] It is an ideal
that is continually defied by the rebirth of life, by the
reappearance of the young, and by the contradictions that
unsettle the bureaucracy. Every generation has to be assimilated again, and each time with explosive resistance.
The bureaucracy, in turn, never lives up to its own technical ideal. Congested with mediocrities, it errs continually. Its judgment lags behind new situations; insensate, it
suffers from social inertia and is always buffeted by
chance. Any crack that opens in the social machine is
widened by the forces of life.
[29] The âideal manâ of the police bureaucracy is a being whose innermost thoughts can be invaded by lie detectors, electronic listening
devices, and âtruthâ drugs. The âideal manâ of the political bureaucracy is a being whose innermost life can be shaped by mutagenic
chemicals and socially assimilated by the mass media. The âideal
manâ of the industrial bureaucracy is a being whose innermost life
can be invaded by subliminal and predictively reliable advertising.
The âideal manâ of the military bureaucracy is a being whose innermost life can be invaded by regimentation for genocide.
How can we heal the fracture that separates living men
from dead machines without sacrificing either men or
machines? How can we transform a technology for survival
into a technology for life? To answer any of these questions with Olympian assurance would be idiotic. The future liberated men will choose from a large variety of
mutually exclusive or combinable work styles, all of which
will be based on unforeseeable technological innovations.
Or these humans of the future may simply choose to step
over the body of technology. They may submerge the
cybernated machine in a technological underworld, divorcing it entirely from social life, the community and creativity. All but hidden from society, the machines would
work for man. Free communities would stand at the end
of a cybernated assembly line with baskets to cart the
goods home. Industry, like the autonomic nervous system,
would work on its own, subject to the repairs that our own
bodies require in occasional bouts of illness. The fracture
separating man from machine would not be healed. It
would simply be ignored.
Ignoring technology, of course, is no solution. Man
would be closing off a vital human experienceâthe stimulus of productive activity, the stimulus of the machine.
Technology can play a vital role informing the personality
of man. Every art, as Lewis Mumford has argued, has its
technical side, requiring the self-mobilization of spontaneity into expressed order and providing contact with the
objective world during the most ecstatic moments of experience.
A liberated society, I believe, will not want to negate
technology precisely because it is liberated and can strike a
balance. It may well want to assimilate the machine to
artistic craftsmanship. By this I mean the machine will
remove the toil from the productive process, leaving its
artistic completion to man. The machine, in effect, will
participate in human creativity. There is no reason why
automatic, cybernated machinery cannot be used so that
the finishing of products, especially those destined for
personal use, is left to the community. The machine can
absorb the toil involved in mining, smelting, transporting
and shaping raw materials, leaving the final stages of artistry and craftsmanship to the individual. Most of the
stones that make up a medieval cathedral were carefully
squared and standardized to facilitate their laying and
bondingâa thankless, repetitive and boring task that can
now be done rapidly and effortlessly by modern machines.
Once the stone blocks were set in place, the craftsmen
made their appearance; toil was replaced by creative human work. In a liberated community the combination of
industrial machines and the craftsmanâs tools could reach a
degree of sophistication and of creative interdependence
unparalleled in any period in human history. William Morrisâs vision of a return to craftsmanship would be freed of
its nostalgic nuances. We could truly speak of a qualitatively new advance in technicsâa technology for life.
Having acquired a vitalizing respect for the natural environment and its resources, the free decentralized community would give a new interpretation to the word âneed.â
Marxâs ârealm of necessity,â instead of expanding indefinitely, would tend to contract; needs would be humanized
and scaled by a higher valuation of life and creativity.
Quality and artistry would supplant the current emphasis
on quantity and standardization; durability would replace
the current emphasis on expendability; an economy of
cherished things, sanctified by a sense of tradition and by a
sense of wonder for the personality and artistry of dead
generations, would replace the mindless seasonal restyling
of commodities; innovations would be made with a sensitivity for the natural inclinations of man as distinguished
from the engineered pollution of taste by the mass media.
Conservation would replace waste in all things. Freed of
bureaucratic manipulation, men would rediscover the
beauty of a simpler, uncluttered material life. Clothing,
diet, furnishings and homes would become more artistic,
more personalized and more Spartan. Man would recover a
sense of the things that are *for* man, as against the things
that have been imposed upon man. The repulsive ritual of
bargaining and hoarding would be replaced by the sensitive
acts of making and giving. Things would cease to be the
crutches for an impoverished ego and the mediators between aborted personalities; they would become the
products of rounded, creative individuals and the gifts of
integrated, developing selves.
A technology for life could play the vital role of integrating one community with another. Rescaled to a revival
of crafts and a new conception of material needs, technology could also function as the sinews of confederation.
A national division of labor and industrial centralization
are dangerous because technology begins to transcend the
human scale; it becomes increasingly incomprehensible and
lends itself to bureaucratic manipulation. To the extent
that a shift away from community control occurs in real
material terms (technologically and economically), centralized institutions acquire real power over the lives of men
and threaten to become sources of coercion. A technology
for life must be based on the community; it must be tailored to the community and the regional level. On this
level, however, the sharing of factories and resources could
actually promote solidarity between community groups; it
could serve to confederate them on the basis not only of
common spiritual and cultural interests but also of common material needs. Depending upon the resources and
uniqueness of regions, a rational, humanistic balance could
be struck between autarky, industrial confederation, and a
national division of labor.
Is society so âcomplexâ that an advanced industrial
civilization stands in contradiction to a decentralized technology for life? My answer to this question is a categorical
constant wastefulness of capitalist enterprise. The petty
bourgeois stands in awe of the bourgeois filing systemâthe
rows of cabinets filled with invoices, accounting books,
insurance records, tax forms and the inevitable dossiers. He
is spellbound by the âexpertiseâ of industrial managers,
engineers, stylemongers, financial manipulators, and the
architects of market consent. He is totally mystified by the
stateâthe police, courts, jails, federal offices, secretariats,
the whole stinking, sick body of coercion, control and
domination. Modern society is incredibly complex, complex even beyond human comprehension, if we grant its
premisesâproperty, âproduction for the sake of production,â competition, capital accumulation, exploitation,
finance, centralization, coercion, bureaucracy and the
domination of man by man. Linked to every one of these
premises are the institutions that actualize itâoffices, millions of âpersonnel,â forms, immense tons of paper, desks,
typewriters, telephones, and, of course, rows upon rows of
filing cabinets. As in Kafkaâs novels, these things are real
but strangely dreamlike, indefinable shadows on the social
landscape. The economy has a greater reality to it and is
easily mastered by the mind and senses, but it too is highly
intricateâif we grant that buttons must be styled in a
thousand different forms, textiles varied endlessly in kind
and pattern to create the illusion of innovation and novelty, bathrooms filled to overflowing with a dazzling
variety of pharmaceuticals and lotions, and kitchens cluttered with an endless number of imbecile appliances. If we
single out of this odious garbage one or two goods of high
quality in the more useful categories and if we eliminate
the money economy, the state power, the credit system,
the paperwork and the policework required to hold society
in an enforced state of want, insecurity and domination,
society would not only become reasonably human but also
fairly simple.
I do not wish to belittle the fact that behind a single
yard of high quality electric wiring lies a copper mine, the
machinery needed to operate it, a plant for producing insulating material, a copper smelting and shaping complex,
a transportation system for distributing the wiringâand
behind each of these complexes other mines, plants,
machine shops and so forth. Copper mines, certainly of a
kind that can be exploited by existing machinery, are not
to be found everywhere, although enough copper and
other useful metals can be recovered as scrap from the
debris of our present society to provide future generations
with all they need. But let us grant that copper will fall
within the sizeable category of material that can be furnished only by a nationwide system of distribution. In
what sense need there be a division of labor in the current
sense of the term? There need be none at all. First, copper
can be distributed, together with other goods, among free,
autonomous communities, be they those that mine it or
those that require it. This distribution system need not
require the mediation of centralized bureaucratic institutions. Second, and perhaps more significant, a community
that lives in a region with ample copper resources would
not be a mere mining community. Copper mining would
be one of the many economic activities in which it was
engagedâa part of a larger, rounded, organic economic
arena. The same would hold for communities whose climate was most suitable for growing specialized foods or
whose resources were rare and uniquely valuable to society
as a whole. Every community would approximate local
or regional autarky. It would seek to achieve wholeness,
because wholeness produces complete, rounded men who
live in symbiotic relationship with their environment. Even
if a substantial portion of the economy fell within the
sphere of a national division of labor, the overall economic
weight of society would still rest with the community. If
there is no distortion of communities, there will be no
sacrifice of any portion of humanity to the interests of
humanity as a whole.
A basic sense of decency, sympathy and mutual aid lies
at the core of human behavior. Even in this lousy bourgeois society we do not find it unusual that adults will
rescue children from danger although the act may imperil
their lives; we do not find it strange that miners, for example, will risk death to save their fellow workers in cave-ins or that soldiers will crawl under heavy fire to carry a
wounded comrade to safety. What tends to shock us are
those occasions when aid is refusedâwhen the cries of a
girl who has been stabbed and is being murdered are ignored in a middle-class neighborhood.
Yet there is nothing in this society that would seem to
warrant a molecule of solidarity. What solidarity we do
find exists despite the society, against all its realities, as an
unending struggle between the innate decency of man and
the innate indecency of society. Can we imagine how men
would behave if this decency could find full release, if
society earned the respect, even the love, of the individual?
We are still the offspring of a violent, blood-soaked, ignoble historyâthe end products of manâs domination of
man. We may never end this condition of domination. The
future may bring us and our shoddy civilization down in a
Wagnerian *GĂŒtterdĂ€mmerung*. How idiotic it would all be!
But we may also end the domination of man by man. We
may finally succeed in breaking the chain to the past and
gain a humanistic, anarchist society. Would it not be the
height of absurdity, indeed of impudence, to gauge the
behavior of future generations by the very criteria we despise in our own time? Free men will not be greedy, one
liberated community will not try to dominate another because it has a potential monopoly of copper, computer
âexpertsâ will not try to enslave grease monkeys, and sentimental novels about pining, tubercular virgins will not be
written. We can ask only one thing of the free men and
women of the future: to forgive us that it took so long and
that it was such a hard pull. Like Brecht, we can ask that
they try not to think of us too harshly, that they give us
their sympathy and understand that we lived in the depths
of a social hell.
But then, they will surely know what to think without
our telling them.
New York
May 1965
Freedom has its forms. However personalized, individuated or dadaesque may be the attack upon prevailing
institutions, a liberatory revolution always poses the question of what social forms will replace existing ones. At one
point or another, a revolutionary people must deal with
how it will manage the land and the factories from which
it acquires the means of life. It must deal with the manner
in which it will arrive at decisions that affect the community as a whole. Thus if revolutionary thought is to be
taken at all seriously, it must speak directly to the problems and forms of social management. It must open to
public discussion the problems that are involved in a creative development of liberatory social forms. Although
there is no theory of liberation that can replace experience, there is sufficient historial experience, and a sufficient theoretical formulation of the issues involved, to
indicate what social forms are consistent with the fullest
realization of personal and social freedom.
What social forms will replace existing ones depends on
what relations free people decide to establish between
themselves. Every personal relationship has a social dimension; every social relationship has a deeply personal side to
it. Ordinarily, these two aspects and their relationship to
each other are mystified and difficult to see clearly. The
institutions created by hierarchical society, especially the
state institutions, produce the illusion that social relations
exist in a universe of their own, in specialized political or
bureaucratic compartments. In reality, there exists no
strictly âimpersonalâ political or social dimension; all the
social institutions of the past and present depend on the
relations between people in daily life, especially in those
aspects of daily life which are necessary for survivalâthe
production and distribution of the means of life, the rearing of the young, the maintenance and reproduction of
life. The liberation of manânot in some vague âhistorical,â
moral, or philosophical sense, but in the intimate details of
day-to-day lifeâis a profoundly social act and raises the
problem of social forms as modes of relations between
individuals.
The relationship between the social and the individual
requires special emphasis in our own time, for never before
have personal relations become so impersonal and never
before have social relations become so asocial. Bourgeois
society has brought all relations between people to the
highest point of abstraction by divesting them of their
objectâthe commodityâtakes on roles that formerly
belonged to the community; exchange relationships
(actualized in most cases as money relationships) supplant
nearly all other modes of human relationships. In this
respect, the bourgeois commodity system becomes the historical culmination of all societies, precapitalist as well as
capitalist, in which human relationships are *mediated*
rather than direct or face-to-face.
To place this development in clearer perspective, let us
briefly look back in time and establish what the mediation
of social relations has come to mean.
The earliest social âspecialistsâ who interposed themselves between peopleâthe priests and tribal chiefs who
permanently mediated their relationsâestablished the
formal conditions were consolidated and deepened by
technological advancesâadvances which provided only
enough material surplus for the few to live at the expense
of the many. The tribal assembly, in which all members of
the community had decided and directly managed their
common affairs, dissolved into chieftainship, and the community dissolved into social classes.
Despite the increasing investiture of social control in a
handful of men and even one man, the fact remains that
men in precapitalist societies mediated the relations of
other peopleâcouncil supplanting assembly, and chieftainship supplanted council. In bourgeois society, on the other
hand, the mediation of social relations by men is
replaced by the mediation of social relations by *things*, by
commodities. Having brought social mediation to the
highest point of impersonality, commodity society turns
attention to mediation as such; it brings into question *all*
forms of social organization based on indirect representation, on the management of public affairs by the few, on
the distinctive existence of concepts and practices such as
âelection,â âlegislation,â âadministration.â
The most striking evidence of this social refocusing are
the demands voiced almost intuitively by increasing
numbers of American youth for tribalism and community.
These demands are âregressiveâ only in the sense that they
go back *temporally* to pre-hierarchical forms of freedom.
They are profoundly progressive in the sense that they go
back *structurally* to **non**-hierarchical forms of freedom.
By contrast, the traditional revolutionary demand for
completely with the terrain of hierarchical society.
<em>Workersâ</em> councils originate as *class* councils. Unless one
assumes that workers are driven by their interests
society (an assumption I flatly deny), then these councils
can be used just as much to perpetuate class society as to
destroy it.[30] We shall see, in fact, that the council form
contains many structural limitations which favor the development of hierarchy. For the present, it suffices to say
that most advocates of workersâ councils tend to conceive
of people primarily as economic entities, either as workers
or nonworkers. This conception leaves the onesidedness of
the self completely intact. Man is viewed as a bifurcated
being, the product of a social development that divides
man from man and each man from himself.
[30] For a discussion on the myth of the working class see âListen,
Marxist!â
Nor is this one-sided view completely corrected by
demands for workersâ management of production and the
shortening of the work week, for these demands leave the
free time completely untouched. If workersâ councils and
workersâ management of production do not transform the
work into a joyful activity, free time into a marvelous experience, and the workplace into a community, then they
remain merely formal structures, in fact, *class* structures.
They perpetuate the limitations of the proletariat as a
product of bourgeois social conditions. Indeed, no movement that raises the demand for workersâ councils can be
regarded as revolutionary unless it tries to promote sweeping transformations in the environment of the work place.
Finally, council organizations are forms of mediated
relationships rather than face-to-face relationships. Unless
these mediated relationships are limited by direct relationships, leaving policy decisions to the latter and mere
administration to the former, the councils tend to become
focuses of power. Indeed, unless the councils are finally
assimilated by a popular assembly, and factories are integrated into new types of community, both the councils
and the factories perpetuate the alienation between man
and man and between man and work. Fundamentally, the
degree of freedom in a society can be gauged by the kind
of relationships that unite the people in it. If these relationships are open, unalienated and creative, the society
will be free. If structures exist that inhibit open relationships, either by coercion or mediation, then freedom will
not exist, whether there is workersâ management of production or not. For *all* the workers will manage will be
productionâthe preconditions of life, not the conditions
of life. No mode of social organization can be isolated
from the social conditions it is organizing. Both councils
and assemblies have furthered the interests of hierarchical
society as well as those of revolution. To assume that the
forms of freedom can be treated merely as forms would be
as absurd as to assume that legal concepts can be treated
merely as questions of jurisprudence. The form and content of freedom, like law and society, are mutually determined. By the same token, there are forms of organization
that promote and forms that vitiate the goal of freedom,
and social conditions favor sometimes the one and sometimes the other. To one degree or another, these forms
either alter the individual who uses them or inhibit his
further development.
This article does not dispute the need for workersâ
councilsâmore properly, *factory committees*âas a revolutionary means of appropriating the bourgeois economy.
On the contrary, experience has shown repeatedly that the
factory committee is vitally important as an initial form of
economic administration. But no revolution can settle for
councils and committees as its final, or even its exemplary,
mode of social organization, any more than âworkersâ
management of productionâ can be regarded as a final
mode of economic administration. Neither of these two
relationships is broad enough to revolutionize work, free
time, needs, and the structure of society as a whole. In this
article I take the revolutionary aspect of the council and
committee forms for granted; my purpose is to examine
the conservative traits in them which vitiate the revolutionary project.
It has always been fashionable to look for models of social
institutions in the so-called âproletarianâ revolutions of
the past hundred years. The Paris Commune of 1871, the
Russian Soviets of 1905 and 1917, the Spanish revolutionary syndicates of the 1930s, and the Hungarian councils of 1956 have all been raked over for examples of
future social organization. What, it is worth asking, do
these models of organization have in common? The answer
is, very little, other than their limitations as mediated
forms. Spain, as we shall see, provides a welcome exception: the others were either too short-lived or simply too
distorted to supply us with more than the material for
myths.
The Paris Commune may be revered for many different
reasonsâfor its intoxicating sense of libidinal release, for
its radical populism, for its deeply revolutionary impact on
the oppressed, or for its defiant heroism in defeat. But the
Commune itself, viewed as a *structural* entity, was little
more than a popular municipal council. More democratic
and plebeian than other such bodies, the council was
nevertheless structured along parliamentary lines. It was
elected by âcitizens,â grouped according to geographic
constituencies. In combining legislation with administration, the Commune was hardly more advanced than the
municipal bodies in the U.S. today.
Fortunately, revolutionary Paris largely ignored the
Commune after it was installed. The insurrection, the
actual management of the cityâs affairs, and finally the
fighting against the Versaillese, were undertaken mainly by
the popular clubs, the neighborhood vigilance committees,
and the battalions of the National Guard. Had the Paris
Commune (the Municipal Council) survived, it is extremely
doubtful that it could have avoided conflict with these
loosely formed street and militia formations. Indeed, by
the end of April, some six weeks after the insurrection, the
Commune constituted an âall-powerfulâ Committee of
Public Safety, a body redolent with memories of the
Jacobin dictatorship and the Terror, which suppressed not
only the right in the Great Revolution of a century earlier,
but also the left. In any case, history left the Commune a
mere three weeks of life, two of which were consumed in
the death throes of barricade fighting against Thiers and
the Versaillese.
It does not malign the Paris Commune to divest it of
âhistoricalâ burdens it never actually carried. The Commune was a festival of the streets, its partisans primarily
handicraftsmen, itinerant intellectuals, the social debris of
a precapitalist era, and lumpens. To regard these strata as
âproletarianâ is to caricature the word to the point of
absurdity. The industrial proletariat constituted a minority
of the Communards.[31]
[31] If we are to regard the bulk of the Communards as âproletarians,â
or describe any social stratum as âproletarianâ (as the French
Situationists do) simply because it has no control over the
conditions of its life, we might just as well call slaves, serfs, peasants
and large sections of the middle class âproletarians.â To create such
sweeping antitheses between âproletarianâ and bourgeois, however,
eliminates all the determinations that characterize these classes as
specific, historically limited strata. This giddy approach to social
analysis divests the industrial proletariat and the bourgeoisie of all
the historically unique features which Marx believed he had
discovered (a theoretical project that proved inadequate, although
by no means false); it slithers away from the responsibilities of a
serious critique of Marxism and the development of âlaissez-faireâ
capitalism toward state capitalism, while pretending to retain continuity with the Marxian project.
The Commune was the last great rebellion of the French
after the Great Revolution. Ultimately, this highly mixed
stratum was destroyed not by the guns of the Versaillese
but by the advance of industrialism.
The Paris Commune of 1871 was largely a city council,
established to coordinate municipal administration under
conditions of revolutionary unrest. The Russian Soviets of
1905 were largely fighting organizations, established to
coordinate near-insurrectionary strikes in St. Petersburg.
These councils were based almost entirely on factories and
trade unions: there was a delegate for every five hundred
workers (where individual factories and shops contained a
smaller number, they were grouped together for voting
purposes), and additionally, delegates from trade unions
and political parties. The soviet mode of organization took
on its clearest and most stable form in St. Petersburg,
where the soviet contained about four hundred delegates
at its high point, including representatives of the newly
organized professional unions. The St. Petersburg soviet
rapidly developed from a large strike committee into a
parliament of all oppressed classes, broadening its representation, demands and responsibilities. Delegates were
admitted from cities outside St. Petersburg, political
demands began to dominate economic ones, and links were
established with peasant organizations and their delegates
admitted into the deliberations of the body. Inspired by
St. Petersburg, Soviets sprang up in all the major cities and
towns of Russia and developed into an incipient revolutionary power counterposed to all the governmental institutions of the autocracy.
The St. Petersburg soviet lasted less than two months.
Most of its members were arrested in December 1905. To a
large extent, the soviet was deserted by the St. Petersburg
proletariat, which never rose in armed insurrection and
whose strikes diminished in size and militancy as trade
revived in the late autumn. Ironically, the last stratum to
advance beyond the early militancy of the soviet were the
Moscow students, who rose in insurrection on December
22 and during five days of brilliantly conceived urban
guerrilla warfare reduced local police and military forces to
near impotence. The students received very little aid from
the workers in the city. Their street battles might have
continued indefinitely, even in the face of massive proletarian apathy, had the czarâs guard not been transported to
Moscow by the railway workers on one of the few operating lines to the city.
The Soviets of 1917 were the true heirs of the Soviets of
1905, and to distinguish the two from each other, as some
writers occasionally do, is spurious. Like their predecessors
of twelve years earlier, the 1917 Soviets were based largely
on factories, trade unions and party organizations, but
they were expanded to include delegates from army groups
and a sizeable number of stray radical intellectuals. The
Soviets of 1917 reveal all the limitations of âsovietism.â
Though the Soviets were invaluable as *local* fighting organizations, their *national* congresses proved to be increasingly
unrepresentative bodies. The congresses were organized
along very hierarchical lines. Local Soviets in cities, towns
and villages elected delegates to district and regional
bodies; these elected delegates to the actual nationwide
congresses. In larger cities, representation to the congresses
was less indirect, but it was indirect nonethelessâfrom
the voter in a large city to the municipal soviet and from
the municipal soviet to the congress. In either case the
congress was separated from the mass of voters by one or
more representative levels.
The soviet congresses were scheduled to meet every
three months. This permitted far too long a time span to
exist between sessions. The first congress, held in June
1917, had some eight hundred delegates; later congresses
were even larger, numbering a thousand or more delegates.
To âexpediteâ the work of the congresses and to provide
continuity of function between the tri-monthly sessions,
the congresses elected an executive committee, fixed at
not more than two hundred in 1918 and expanded to a
maximum of three hundred in 1920. This body was to
remain more or less in permanent session, but it too was
regarded as unwieldy and most of its responsibilities after
the October revolution were turned over to a small Council
of Peopleâs Commissars. Having once acquired control of
the Second Congress of Soviets (in October 1917), the
Bolsheviks found it easy to centralize power in the Council
of Commissars and later in the Political Bureau of the
Communist Party. Opposition groups in the Soviets either
left the Second Congress or were later expelled from all
soviet organs. The tri-monthly meetings of the congresses
were permitted to lapse: the completely Bolshevik Executive Committee and Council of Peopleâs Commissars simply did not summon them. Finally, the congresses were
held only once a year. Similarly, the intervals between the
meetings of district and regional Soviets grew increasingly
longer and even the meetings of the Executive Committee,
created by the congresses as a body in permanent session,
became increasingly infrequent until finally they were held
only three times a year. The power of the local Soviets
passed into the hands of the Executive Committee, the
power of the Executive Committee passed into the hands
of the Council of Peopleâs Commissars, and finally, the
power of the Council of Peopleâs Commissars passed into
the hands of the Political Bureau of the Communist Party.
That the Russian Soviets were incapable of providing the
anatomy for a truly popular democracy is to be ascribed
not only to their hierarchical structure, but also to their
limited social roots. The insurgent military battalions,
from which the Soviets drew their original striking power,
were highly unstable, especially after the final collapse of
the czarist armies. The newly formed Red Army was recruited, disciplined, centralized and tightly controlled by
the Bolsheviks. Except for partisan bands and naval forces,
soviet military bodies remained politically inert throughout the civil war. The peasant villages turned inward
toward their local concerns, and were apathetic about
national problems. This left the factories as the most
important political base of the Soviets. Here we encounter
a basic contradiction in *class* concepts of revolutionary
power: proletarian socialism, precisely because it emphasizes that power must be based exclusively on the factory,
creates the conditions for a centralized, hierarchical political structure.
However much its social position is strengthened by a
system of âself-management,â the factory is not an autonomous social organism. The amount of social control the
factory can exercise is fairly limited, for every factory is
highly dependent for its operation and its very existence
upon other factories and sources of raw materials. Ironically, the Soviets, by basing themselves primarily in the
factory and isolating the factory from its local environment, shifted power from the community and the region
to the nation, and eventually from the base of society to
its summit. The soviet system consisted of an elaborate
skein of mediated social relationships, knitted along
nationwide class lines.
Perhaps the only instance where a system of working-class self-management succeeded as a mode of *class* organization was in Spain, where anarcho-syndicalism attracted a
large number of workers and peasants to its banner. The
Spanish anarcho-syndicalists *consciously* sought to limit
the tendency toward centralization. The CNT (Confederacy Nacional del Trabajo), the large anarcho-syndicalist
union in Spain, created a dual organization with an elected
committee system to act as a control on local bodies and
national congresses. The assemblies had the power to
revoke their delegates to the council and countermand
council decisions. For all practical purposes the âhigherâ
bodies of the CNT functioned as coordinating bodies. Let
there be no mistake about the effectiveness of this scheme
of organization: it imparted to each member of the CNT a
weighty sense of responsibility, a sense of direct,
immediate and personal influence in the activities and
policies of the union. This responsibility was exercised
with a highmindedness that made the CNT the most militant as well as the largest revolutionary movement in
Europe during the interwar decades.
The Spanish Revolution of 1936 put the CNT system to
a practical test, and it worked fairly well. In Barcelona,
CNT workers seized the factories, transportation facilities
and utilities, and managed them along anarcho-syndicalist
lines. It remains a matter of record, attested to by visitors
of almost every political persuasion, that the cityâs
economy operated with remarkable success and
efficiencyâdespite the systematic sabotage practiced by
the bourgeois Republican government and the Spanish
Communist Party. The experiment finally collapsed in
shambles when the central governmentâs assault troops
occupied Barcelona in May 1937, following an uprising of
the proletariat.
Despite their considerable influence, the Spanish
anarchists had virtually no roots outside certain sections of
the working class and peasantry. The movement was
limited primarily to industrial Catalonia, the coastal
Mediterranean areas, rural Aragon, and Andalusia. What
destroyed the experiment was its isolation within Spain
itself and the overwhelming forcesâRepublican as well as
fascist, and Stalinist as well as bourgeoisâthat were
mobilized against it.[32]
[32] This is not to ignore the disastrous political errors made by many
âleadingâ Spanish anarchists. Although the leading anarchists were
faced with the alternative of establishing a dictatorship in Catalonia,
which they were not prepared to do (and rightly so!), this was no
excuse for practicing opportunistic tactics all along the way.
It would be fruitless to examine in detail the council
modes of organization that emerged in Germany in 1918,
in the Asturias in 1934, and in Hungary in 1956. The
German councils were hopelessly perverted: the so-called
âmajorityâ (reformist) social democrats succeeded in gaining control of the newly formed councils and using them
for counterrevolutionary ends. In Hungary and Asturias
the councils were quickly destroyed by counterrevolution,
but there is no reason to believe that, had they developed
further, they would have avoided the fate of the Russian
Soviets. History shows that the Bolsheviks were not the
only ones to distort the council mode of operation. Even
in anarcho-syndicalist Spain there is evidence that by 1937
the committee system of the CNT was beginning to clash
with the assembly system; whatever the outcome might
have been, the whole experiment was ended by the assault
of the Communists and the Republican government against
Barcelona.
The fact remains that council modes of organization are
not immune to centralization, manipulation and perversion. These councils are still particularistic, one-sided and
mediated forms of social management. At best, they can
be the stepping stones to a decentralized societyâat worst,
they can easily be integrated into hierarchical forms of
social organization.
Let us turn to the popular assembly for an insight into
unmediated forms of social relations. The assembly probably formed the structural basis of early clan and tribal
society until its functions were pre-empted by chiefs and
councils. It appeared as the ecclesia in classical Athens;
later, in a mixed and often perverted form, it reappeared in
the medieval and Renaissance towns of Europe. Finally, as
the âsections,â assemblies emerged as the insurgent bodies
in Paris during the Great Revolution. The ecclesia and the
Parisian sections warrant the closest study. Both developed
in the most complex cities of their time and both assumed
a highly sophisticated form, often welding individuals of
different social origins into a remarkable, albeit temporary,
community of interests. It does not minimize their limitations to say that they developed methods of functioning so
successfully libertarian in character that even the most
imaginative Utopias have failed to match in speculation
what they achieved in practice.
The Athenian ecclesia was probably rooted in the early
assemblies of the Greek tribes. With the development of
property and social classes, it was replaced by a feudal
social structure, lingering only in the social memory of the
people. For a time, Athenian society seemed to be charting
the disastrous course toward internal decay that Rome was
to follow several centuries later. A large class of heavily
mortgaged peasants, a growing number of serf-like
sharecroppers, and a large body of urban laborers and
slaves were polarized against a small number of powerful
land magnates and a parvenu commercial middle class. By
the sixth century B.C., all the conditions in Athens and
Attica (the surrounding agricultural region) had ripened
for a devastating social war.
The course of Athenian history was reversed by the
reforms of Solon. In a series of drastic measures, the
peasantry was restored to an economically viable
condition, the landowners were shorn of most of their
power, the ecclesia was revived, and a reasonably equitable
system of justice was established. The trend toward a
popular democracy continued to unfold for nearly a
century and a half, until it achieved a form that has never
quite been equaled elsewhere. By Periclean times the
Athenians had perfected their polis to a point where it
represented a triumph of rationality within the material
limitations of the ancient world.
Structurally, the basis of the Athenian polis was the
ecclesia. Shortly after sunrise at each prytany (the tenth
day of the year), thousands of male citizens from all over
Attica began to gather on the Pnyx, a hill directly outside
Athens, for a meeting of the assembly. Here, in the open
air, they leisurely disported themselves among groups of
friends until the solemn intonation of prayers announced
the opening of the meeting. The agenda, arranged under
the three headings of âsacred,â âprofaneâ and âforeign
affairs,â had been distributed days earlier with the
announcement of the assembly. Although the ecclesia
could not add or bring forward anything that the agenda
did not contain, its subject matter could be rearranged at
the will of the assembly. No quorum was necessary, except
for proposed decrees affecting individual citizens.
The ecclesia enjoyed complete sovereignty over all institutions and offices in Athenian society. It decided questions of war and peace, elected and removed generals,
reviewed military campaigns, debated and voted upon
domestic and foreign policy, redressed grievances, examined and passed upon the operations of administrative
boards, and banished undesirable citizens. Roughly one
man out of six in the citizen body was occupied at any
given time with the administration of the communityâs
affairs. Some fifteen hundred men, chosen mainly by lot,
staffed the boards responsible for the collection of taxes,
the management of shipping, food supply and public facilities, and the preparation of plans for public construction.
The army, composed entirely of conscripts from each
of the ten tribes of Attica, was led by elected officers;
Athens was policed by citizen-bowmen and Scythian state
slaves.
The agenda of the ecclesia was prepared by a body
called the Council of 500. Lest the council gain any
authority over the ecclesia, the Athenians carefully
circumscribed its composition and functions. Chosen by
lot from rosters of citizens who, in turn, were elected
annually by the tribes, the Council was divided into ten
subcommittees, each of which was on duty for a tenth of
the year. Every day a president was selected by lot from
among the fifty members of the subcommittee that was on
duty to the polis. During his twenty-four hours of office,
the Councilâs president held the state seal and the keys to
the citadel and public archives and functioned as acting
head of the country. Once he had been chosen, he could
not occupy the position again.
Each of the ten tribes annually elected six hundred
citizens to serve as âjudgesââwhat we would call
jurymenâin the Athenian courts. Every morning, they
trudged up to the temple of Theseus, where lots were
drawn for the trials of the day. Each court consisted of at
least 201 jurymen and the trials were fair by any historical
standard of juridical practice.
Taken as a whole, this was a remarkable system of social
management; run almost entirely by amateurs, the
Athenian polis reduced the formulation and administration
of public policy to a completely public affair. âHere is no
privileged class, no class of skilled politicians, no
bureaucracy; no body of men, like the Roman Senate, who
alone understood the secrets of State, and were looked up
to and trusted as the gathered wisdom of the whole
community,â observes W. Warde Fowler. âAt Athens there
was no disposition, and in fact no need, to trust the
experience of any one; each man entered intelligently into
the details of his own temporary duties, and discharged
them, as far as we can tell, with industry and integrity.â{26}
Overdrawn as this view may be for a class society that
required slaves and denied women any role in the polis, the
fact remains that Fowlerâs account is *essentially* accurate.
Indeed, the greatness of the achievement lies in the fact
that Athens, despite the slave, patriarchal and class features it shared with classical society, as a whole developed
into a working democracy in the literal sense of the term.
No less significant, and perhaps consoling for our own
time, is the fact that this achievement occurred when it
seemed that the polis had charted a headlong course
toward social decay. At its best, Athenian democracy
greatly modified the more abusive and inhuman features of
ancient society. The burdens of slavery were small by comparison with other historical periods, except when slaves
were employed in capitalist enterprises. Generally, slaves
were allowed to accumulate their own funds; on the
yeoman farmsteads of Attica they generally worked under
the same conditions and shared the same food as their
masters; in Athens, they were indistinguishable in dress,
manner and bearing from citizensâa source of ironical
comment by foreign visitors. In many crafts, slaves not
only worked side by side with freemen, but occupied
supervisory positions over free workers as well as other
slaves.
On balance, the image of Athens as a slave economy
which built its civilization and generous humanistic outlook on the backs of human chattels is falseââfalse in its
interpretation of the past and in its confident pessimism as
to the future, willfully false, above all, in its cynical estimate of human nature,â observes Edward Zimmerman.
âSocieties, like men, cannot live in compartments. They
cannot hope to achieve greatness by making amends in
their use of leisure for the lives they have brutalized in
acquiring it. Art, literature, philosophy, and all other great
products of a nationâs genius, are no mere delicate growths
of a sequestered hothouse culture; they must be sturdily
rooted, and find continual nourishment, in the broad common soil of national life. That, if we are looking for lessons, is one we might learn from ancient Greece.â{27}
In Athens, the popular assembly emerged as the final
product of a sweeping social transition. In Paris, more than
two millennia later, it emerged as the lever of social transition itself, as a revolutionary form and an insurrectionary
force.
The Parisian sections of the early 1790s played the
same role as organs of struggle as the Soviets of 1905 and
1917, with the decisive difference that relations within the
sections were not mediated by a hierarchical structure.
Sovereignty rested with the revolutionary assemblies themselves, not above them.
The Parisian sections emerged directly from the voting
system established for elections to the Estates General. In
1789 the monarchy had divided the capital into sixty electoral districts, each of which formed an assembly of so-called âactiveâ or taxpaying citizens, the eligible voters of
the city. These primary assemblies were expected to elect a
body of electors which, in turn, was to choose the sixty
representatives of the capital. After performing their electoral functions, the assemblies were required to disappear,
but they remained on in defiance of the monarchy and
constituted themselves into permanent municipal bodies.
By degrees they turned into neighborhood assemblies of all
âactiveâ citizens, varying in form, scope and power from
one district to another.
The municipal law of May 1790 reorganized the sixty
districts into forty-eight sections. The law was intended to
circumscribe the popular assemblies, but the sections
simply ignored it. They continued to broaden their base
and extend their control over Paris. On July 30, 1792, the
ThĂ©Ăątre-Francais section swept aside the distinction between âactiveâ and âpassiveâ citizens, inviting the poorest
and most destitute of the *sans-culottes* to participate in the
assembly. Other sections followed the Theatre-Francais,
and from this period the sections became authentic popular organsâindeed the very soul of the Great Revolution. It
was the sections which constituted the new revolutionary
Commune of August 10, which organized the attack on
the Tuileries and finally eliminated the Bourbon monarchy; it was the sections which decisively blocked the
efforts of the Girondins to rouse the provinces against revolutionary Paris; it was the sections which, by ceaseless
prodding, by their unending delegations and by armed
demonstrations, provided the revolution with its remarkable leftward momentum after 1791.
The sections, however, were not merely fighting organizations; they represented genuine forms of self-management. At the high point of their development, they took
over the complete administration of the city. Individual
sections policed their own neighborhoods, elected their
own judges, were responsible for the distribution of food,
provided public aid to the poor, and contributed to the
maintenance of the National Guard. With the declaration
of war in April 1792 the sections took on the added tasks
of enrolling volunteers for the revolutionary army and caring for their families, collecting donations for the war
effort, and equipping and provisioning entire battalions.
During the period of the âmaximum,â when controls were
established over prices and wages to prevent a runaway
inflation, the sections took responsibility for the maintenance of government-fixed prices. To provision Paris, the
sections sent their representatives to the countryside to
buy and transport food and see to its distribution at fair
prices.
It must be borne in mind that this complex of
extremely important activities was undertaken not by
professional bureaucrats but, for the most part, by ordinary shopkeepers and craftsmen. The bulk of the sectional
responsibilities were discharged after working hours, during the free time of the section members. The popular
assemblies of the sections usually met during the evenings
in neighborhood churches. Assemblies were ordinarily
open to all the adults of the neighborhood. In periods of
emergency, assembly meetings were held daily; special
meetings could be called at the request of fifty members.
Most administrative responsibilities were discharged by
committees, but the popular assemblies established all the
policies of the sections, reviewed and passed upon the
work of all the committees, and replaced officers at will.
The forty-eight sections were coordinated through the
Paris Commune, the municipal council of the capital.
When emergencies arose, sections often cooperated with
each other directly, through ad hoc delegates. This form of
cooperation from below never crystalized into a permanent relationship. The Paris Commune of the Great Revolution never became an overbearing, ossified institution; it
changed with almost every important political emergency,
and its stability, form and functions depended largely
upon the wishes of the sections. In the days preceding the
uprising of August 10, 1792, for example, the sections
simply suspended the old municipal council, confined Petion, the mayor of Paris, and, in the persons of their insurrectionary commissioners, took over all the authority of
the Commune and the command of the National Guard.
Almost the same procedure was followed nine months
later when the Girondin deputies were expelled from the
Convention, with the difference that the Commune, and
Pache, the mayor of Paris, gave their consent (after some
persuasive âgesturesâ) to the uprising of the radical sections.
Having relied on the sections to fasten their hold on the
Convention, the Jacobins began to rely on the Convention
to destroy the sections. In September 1793 the Convention limited section assemblies to two a week; three
months later the sections were deprived of the right to
elect justices of the peace and divested of their role in
organizing relief work. The sweeping centralization of
France, which the Jacobins undertook between 1793 and
1794, completed the destruction of the sections*[33]The sections were denied control over the police and their administrative responsibilities were placed in the hands of
salaried bureaucrats. By January 1794 the vitality of the
sections had been thoroughly sapped. As Michelet observes: âThe general assemblies of the sections were dead,
and all their power had passed to their revolutionary committees, which, themselves being no longer elected bodies,
but simply groups of officials nominated by the authorities, had not much life in them either.â The sections had
been subverted by the very revolutionary leaders they had
raised to power in the Convention. When the time came
for Robespierre, Saint-Just and Lebas to appeal to the sections against the Convention, the majority did virtually
nothing in their behalf. Indeed, the revolutionary Gravilliers sectionâthe men who had so earnestly supported
Jacques Roux and the *enragĂ©s* in 1793âvindictively
placed their arms at the service of the Thermidorians and
marched against the Robespierristsâthe Jacobin leaders,
who, a few months earlier, had driven Roux to suicide and
guillotined the spokesmen of the left.
[33] Marx, it may be noted, greatly admired the Jacobins for
âcentralizingâ France and in the famous âAddress of the Central
Councilâ (1850) modeled his tactics for Germany on their policies.
This was short-sightedness of incredible proportionsâand institutional emphasis that revealed a gross insensitivity to the self-activity
and the self-remaking of a people in revolutionary motion. See
âListen, Marxist!â
The factors which undermined the assemblies of classical Athens and revolutionary Paris require very little discussion. In both cases the assembly mode of organization
was broken up not only from without, but also from
withinâby the development of class antagonisms. There
are no forms, however cleverly contrived, that can overcome the content of a given society. Lacking the material
resources, the technology and the level of economic
development to overcome class antagonisms as such,
Athens and Paris could achieve an approximation of the
forms of freedom only temporarilyâand only to deal with
the more serious threat of complete social decay. Athens
held on to the ecclesia for several centuries, mainly because the polis still retained a living contact with tribal
forms of organization; Paris developed its sectional mode
of organization for a period of several years, largely because the
head of the revolution by a rare combination of fortunate
circumstances. Both the ecclesia and the sections were undermined by the very conditions they were intended to
checkâproperty, class antagonisms and exploitationâbut
which they were incapable of eliminating. What is remarkable about them is that they worked at all, considering the
enormous problems they faced and the formidable obstacles they had to overcome.
It must be borne in mind that Athens and Paris were
large cities, not peasant villages; indeed, they were complex, highly sophisticated urban centers by the standards
of their time. Athens supported a population of more than
a quarter of a million, Paris over seven hundred thousand.
Both cities were engaged in worldwide trade; both were
burdened by complex logistical problems; both had a multitude of needs that could be satisfied only by a fairly
elaborate system of public administration. Although each
had only a fraction of the population of present-day New
York or London, their advantages on this score were more
than canceled out by their extremely crude systems of
communication and transportation, and by the need, in
Paris at least, for members of the assembly to devote the
greater part of the day to brute toil. Yet Paris, no less than
Athens, was administered by amateurs: by men who, for
several years and in their spare time, saw to the administration of a city in revolutionary ferment. The principal
means by which they made their revolution, organized its
conquests, and finally sustained it against counterrevolution at home and invasion abroad, was the neighborhood
public assembly. There is no evidence that these assemblies
and the committees they produced were inefficient or
technically incompetent. On the contrary, they awakened
a popular initiative, a resoluteness in action, and a sense of
revolutionary purpose that no professional bureaucracy,
however radical its pretensions, could ever hope to achieve.
Indeed, it is worth emphasizing that Athens founded
Western philosophy, mathematics, drama, historiography
and art, and that revolutionary Paris contributed more
than its share to the culture of the time and the political
thought of the Western world. The arena for these achievements was not the traditional state, structured around a
bureaucratic apparatus, but a system of unmediated relations, a face-to-face democracy organized into public assemblies.
The sections provide us with a rough model of assembly
organization in a large city and during a period of revolutionary transition from a centralized political state to a
potentially decentralized society. The ecclesia provides us
with a rough model of assembly organization in a decentralized society. The word âmodelâ is used deliberately.
The ecclesia and the sections were lived experiences, not
theoretical visions. But precisely because of this they
validate in practice many anarchic theoretical speculations
that have often been dismissed as âvisionaryâ and âunrealistic.â
The goal of dissolving propertied society, class rule, centralization and the state is as old as the historical emergence of property, classes and states. In the beginning, the
rebels could look backward to clans, tribes and federations; it was still a time when the past was closer at hand
than the future. Then the past receded completely from
manâs vision and memory, except perhaps as a lingering
dream of the âgolden ageâ or the âGarden of Eden.â[34] At
this point the very notion of liberation becomes speculative and theoretical, and like all strictly theoretical visions its content was permeated with the social material of
the present. Hence the fact that Utopia, from More to
Bellamy, is an image not of a hypothetical future, but of a
present drawn to the logical conclusion of rationalityâor
absurdity. Utopia has slaves, kings, princes, oligarchs, technocrats, elites, suburbanites and a substantial petty bourgeoisie. Even on the left, it became customary to define
the goal of a propertyless, stateless society as a series of
approximations, of stages in which the end in view was
attained by the use of the state. Mediated power entered
into the vision of the future; worse, as the development of
Russia indicates, it was strengthened to the point where
the state today is not merely the âexecutive committeeâ
of a specific class but a human condition. Life itself has
become bureaucratized.
[34] It was not until the 1860s, with the work of Bachofen and
Morgan, that humanity rediscovered its communal past. By that time
the discovery had become a purely critical weapon directed against
the bourgeois family and property.
In envisioning the complete dissolution of the existing
society, we cannot get away from the question of **power**âbe it power over our own lives, the âseizure of power,â or
the dissolution of power. In going from the present to the
future, from âhereâ to âthere,â we must ask: what is
power? Under what conditions is it dissolved? And what
does its dissolution mean? How do the forms of freedom,
the unmediated relations of social life, emerge from a statified society, a society in which the state of unfreedom is
carried to the point of absurdityâto domination for its
own sake?
We begin with the historical fact that nearly all the
major revolutionary upheavals began spontaneously:[35] witness the three days of âdisorderâ that preceded the takeover of the Bastille in July 1789, the defense of the artillery in Montmartre that led to the Paris Commune of 1871,
the famous âfive daysâ of February 1917 in Petrograd, the
uprising of Barcelona in July 1936, the takeover of Budapest and the expulsion of the Russian army in 1956.
Nearly all the great revolutions came from below, from the
molecular movement of the âmasses,â their progressive
individuation and their explosionâan explosion which
invariably took the authoritarian ârevolutionistsâ completely by surprise.
[35] Here, indeed, âhistoryâ has something to teach usâprecisely
because these spontaneous uprisings are not history but various
manifestations of the same phenomenon: revolution. Whosoever
calls himself a revolutionist and does not study these events on their
own terms, thoroughly and without theoretical preconceptions, is a
dilettante who is playing at revolution.
There can be no separation of the revolutionary process
from the revolutionary goal. **A society based on self-administration must be achieved by means of self-administration.** This implies the forging of a self (yes, literally a
forging in the revolutionary process) and a mode of
administration which the self can possess.[36] If we define
âpowerâ as the power of man over man, power can only
be destroyed by the very process in which man acquires
power over his own life and in which he not only âdiscoversâ himself but, more meaningfully, formulates his
selfhood in all its social dimensions.
[36] What Wilhelm Reich and, later, Herbert Marcuse have made clear
is that âselfhoodâ is not only a personal dimension but also a social
one. The self that finds expression in the assembly and community
is, literally, the assembly and community that has found
self-expressionâa complete congruence of form and content.
Freedom, so conceived, cannot be âdeliveredâ to the
individual as the âend productâ of a ârevolutionââmuch
less as a ârevolutionâ achieved by social-philistines who are
hypnotized by the trappings of authority and power. The
assembly and community cannot be legislated or decreed
into existence. To be sure, a revolutionary group can purposively and consciously seek to promote the creation of
these forms; but if assembly and community are not allowed to emerge organically, if their growth is not instigated, developed and matured by the social processes at
work, they will not be really popular forms. Assembly and
community must arise from within the revolutionary process itself; indeed, the revolutionary process must *be* the
formation of assembly and community, and with it, the
destruction of power. Assembly and community must become âfighting words,â not distant panaceas. They must
be created as *modes of struggle* against the existing society,
not as theoretical or programmatic abstractions.
It is hardly possible to stress this point strongly enough.
The future assemblies of people in the block, the neighborhood or the districtâthe revolutionary sections to comeâwill stand on a higher social level than all the present-day
committees, syndicates, parties and clubs adorned by the
most resounding ârevolutionaryâ titles. They will be the
living nuclei of Utopia in the decomposing body of bourgeois society. Meeting in auditoriums, theaters, courtyards,
halls, parks andâlike their forerunners, the sections of
1793âin churches, they will be the arenas of demassification, for the very *essence* of the revolutionary process is
people acting as individuals.
At this point the assembly may be faced not only with
the power of the bourgeois stateâthe famous problem of
âdual powerââbut with the danger of the incipient state.
Like the Paris sections, it will have to fight not only
against the Convention, but also against the tendency to
create mediated social forms.[37] The factory committees,
which will almost certainly be the forms that will take over
industry, must be managed directly by workersâ assemblies
in the factories. By the same token, neighborhood committees, councils and boards must be rooted completely in
the neighborhood assembly. They must be answerable at
every point to the assembly; they and their work must be
under continual review by the assembly; and finally, their
members must be subject to immediate recall by the assembly. The specific gravity of society, in short, must be
shifted to its baseâthe armed people in permanent assembly.
[37] Together with disseminating ideas, the most important job of the
anarchists will be to defend the spontaneity of the popular
movement by continually engaging the authoritarians in a theoretical
and organizational duel.
As long as the arena of the assembly is the modern
bourgeois city, the revolution is faced with a recalcitrant
environment. The bourgeois city, by its very nature and
structure, fosters centralization, massification and manipulation. Inorganic, gargantuan, and organized like a factory,
the city tends to inhibit the development of an organic,
rounded community. In its role as the universal solvent,
the assembly must try to dissolve the city itself.
We can envision young people renewing social life just as
they renew the human species. Leaving the city, they begin
to found the nuclear ecological communities to which
older people repair in increasing numbers. Large resource
pools are mobilized for their use; careful ecological surveys
and suggestions are placed at their disposal by the most
competent and imaginative people available. The modern
city begins to shrivel, to contract and to disappear, as did
its ancient progenitors millennia earlier. In the new,
rounded ecological community, the assembly finds its
authentic environment and true shelter. Form and content
now correspond completely. The journey from âhereâ to
âthere,â from sections to ecclesia, from cities to communities, is completed. No longer is the factory a particularized
phenomenon; it now becomes an organic part of the community. In this sense, it is no longer a factory. The dissolution of the factory into the community completes the dissolution of the last vestiges of propertied, of class, and,
above all, of mediated society into the new polis. And now
the real drama of human life can unfold, in all its beauty,
harmony, creativity and joy.
New York
January 1968
All the old crap of the thirties is coming back againâthe shit about the âclass line,â the ârole of the working class,â the âtrained cadres,â the âvanguard party,â and the âproletarian dictatorship.â Itâs all back again, and in a more vulgarized form than ever. The Progressive Labor Party is not the only example, it is merely the worst. One smells the same shit in various offshoots of SDS, and in the Marxist and Socialist clubs on campuses, not to speak of the Trotskyist groups, the International Socialist Clubs and the Youth Against War and Fascism.
In the thirties, at least it was understandable. The United States was paralyzed by a chronic economic crisis, the deepest and the longest in its history. The only living forces that seemed to be battering at the walls of capitalism were the great organizing drives of the CIO, with their dramatic sitdown strikes, their radical militancy, and their bloody clashes with the police. The political atmosphere through the entire world was charged by the electricity of the Spanish Civil War, the last of the classical workerâs revolutions, when every radical sect in the American left could identify with its own militia columns in Madrid and Barcelona. That was thirty years ago. It was a time when anyone who cried out âMake love, not warâ would have been regarded as a freak; the cry then was âMake jobs, not warââthe cry of an age burdened by scarcity, when the achievement of socialism entailed âsacrificesâ and a âtransition periodâ to an economy of material abundance. To an eighteen-year old kid in 1937 the very concept of cybernation would have seemed like the wildest science fiction, a fantasy comparable to visions of space travel. That eighteen-year-old kid has now reached fifty years of age, and his roots are planted in an era so remote as to differ **qualitatively** from the realities of the present period in the United States. Capitalism itself has changed since then, taking on increasingly statified forms that could be anticipated only dimly thirty years ago. And now we are being asked to go back to the âclass line,â the âstrategies,â the âcadresâ and the organizational forms of that distant period in almost blatant disregard of the new issues and possibilities that have emerged.
When the hell are we finally going to create a movement that looks to the future instead of the past? When will we begin to learn from what is being born instead of what is dying? Marx, to his lasting credit, tried to do that in his own day; he tried to evoke a futuristic spirit in the revolutionary movement of the 1840âs and 1850âs. âThe tradition of all the dead generations weighs like a nightmare on the brain of the living,â he wrote in **The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte**. âAnd when they seem to be engaged in revolutionizing themselves and things, in creating something entirely new, precisely in such epochs of revolutionary crisis they anxiously conjure up the spirits of the past to their service and borrow from them names, battle slogans and costumes in order to present the new scene of world history in this time-honored disguise and borrowed language. Thus Luther donned the mask of the Apostle Paul, the revolution of 1789 to 1814 draped itself alternately as the Roman Republic and the Roman Empire, and the revolution of 1848 knew nothing better than to parody, in turn, 1789 and the tradition of 1793 to 1795. ⊠The social revolution of the nineteenth century cannot draw its poetry from the past, but only from the future. It cannot begin with itself before it has stripped off all superstition in regard to the past. ⊠In order to arrive at its content, the revolution of the nineteenth century must let the dead bury their dead. There the phrase went beyond the content, here the content goes beyond the phrase.â{28}
Is the problem any different today, as we approach the twenty-first century? Once again the dead are walking in our midstâironically, draped in the name of Marx, the man who tried to bury the dead of the nineteenth century. So the revolution of our own day can do nothing better than parody, in turn, the October Revolution of 1917 and the civil war of 1918â1920, with its âclass line,â its Bolshevik Party, its âproletarian dictatorship,â its puritanical morality, and even its slogan, âsoviet power.â The complete, all-sided revolution of our own day that can finally resolve the historic âsocial question,â born of scarcity, domination and hierarchy, follows the tradition of the partial, the incomplete, the one-sided revolutions of the past, which merely changed the form of the âsocial question,â replacing one system of domination and hierarchy by another. At a time when bourgeois society itself is in the process of disintegrating all the social classes that once gave it stability, we hear the hollow demands for a âclass line.â At a time when all the political institutions of hierarchical society are entering a period of profound decay, we hear the hollow demands for a âpolitical partyâ and a âworkerâs state.â At a time when hierarchy as such is being brought into question, we hear the hollow demands for âcadres,â âvanguardsâ and âleaders.â At a time when centralization and the state have been brought to the most explosive point of historical negativity, we hear the hollow demands for a âcentralized movementâ and a âproletarian dictatorship.â
This pursuit of security in the past, this attempt to find a haven in a fixed dogma and an organizational hierarchy as substitutes for creative thought and praxis is bitter evidence of how little many revolutionaries are capable of ârevolutionizing themselves and things,â much less of revolutionizing society as a whole. The deep-rooted conservatism of the PLP[38] ârevolutionariesâ is almost painfully evident; the authoritarian leader and hierarchy replace the patriarch and the school bureaucracy; the discipline of the Movement replaces the discipline of bourgeois society; the authoritarian code of political obedience replaces the state; the credo of âproletarian moralityâ replaces the mores of puritanism and the work ethic. The old substance of exploitative society reappears in new forms, draped in a red flag, decorated by portraits of Mao (or Castro or Che) and adorned with the little âRed Bookâ and other sacred litanies.
The majority of the people who remain in the PLP today deserve it. If they can live with a movement that cynically dubs its own slogans into photographs of DRUM pickets;[39] if they can read a magazine that asks whether Marcuse is a âcopout or copâ; if they can accept a âdisciplineâ that reduces them to poker-faced, programmed automata; if they can use the most disgusting techniques (techniques borrowed from the cesspool of bourgeois business operations and parliamentarianism) to manipulate other organizations; if they can parasitize virtually every action and situation merely to promote the growth of their partyâeven if this means defeat for the action itselfâthen they are beneath contempt. For these people to call themselves reds and describe attacks upon them as redbaiting is a form of McCarthyism in reverse. To rephrase Trotskyâs juicy description of Stalinism, they are the syphilis of the radical youth movement today. And for syphilis there is only one treatmentâan antibiotic, not an argument.
Our concern here is with those honest revolutionaries who have turned to Marxism, Leninism or Trotskyism because they earnestly seek a coherent social outlook and an effective strategy of revolution. We are also concerned with those who are awed by the theoretical repertory of Marxist ideology and are disposed to flirt with it in the absence of more systematic alternatives. To these people we address ourselves as brothers and sisters and ask for a serious discussion and a comprehensive re-evaluation. We believe that Marxism has ceased to be applicable to our time not because it is too visionary or revolutionary, but because it is not visionary or revolutionary enough. We believe it was born of an era of scarcity and presented as a brilliant critique of that era, specifically of industrial capitalism, and that a new era is in birth which Marxism does not adequately encompass and whose outlines it only partially and onesidedly anticipated. We argue that the problem is not to âabandonâ Marxism, or to âannulâ it, but to transcend it dialectically, just as Marx transcended Hegelian philosophy, Ricardian economics, and Blanquist tactics and modes of organization. We shall argue that in a more advanced stage of capitalism than Marx dealt with a century ago, and in a more advanced stage of technological development than Marx could have clearly anticipated, a new critique is necessary, which in turn yields new modes of struggle, or organization, of propaganda and of lifestyle. Call these new modes whatever you wish. We have chosen to call this new approach post-scarcity anarchism, for a number of compelling reasons which will become evident in the pages that follow.
The idea that a man whose greatest theoretical contributions were made between 1840 and 1880 could âforeseeâ the entire dialectic of capitalism is, on the face of it, utterly preposterous. If we can still learn much from Marxâs insights, we can learn even more from the unavoidable errors of a man who was limited by an era of material scarcity and a technology that barely involved the use of electric power. We can learn how different our own era is from that of **all** past history, how qualitatively new are the potentialities that confront us, how unique are the issues, analyses and praxis that stand before us if we are to make a revolution and not another historical abortion.
The problem is not that Marxism is a âmethodâ which must be reapplied to ânew situationsâ or that âneo-Marxismâ has to be developed to overcome the limitations of âclassical Marxism.â The attempt to rescue the Marxism pedigree by emphasizing the method over the system or by adding âneoâ to a sacred word is sheer mystification if all the **practical** conclusions of the system flatly contradict these efforts.[40] Yet this is precisely the state of affairs in Marxian exegesis today. Marxists lean on the fact that the system provides a brilliant interpretation of the past while willfully ignoring its utterly misleading features in dealing with the present and future. They cite the coherence that historical materialism and the class analysis give to the interpretation of history, the economic insights of **Capital** provides into the development of industrial capitalism, and the brilliance of Marxâs analysis of earlier revolutions and the tactical conclusions he established, without once recognizing that qualitatively new problems have arisen which never existed in his day. Is it conceivable that historical problems and methods of class analysis based entirely on unavoidable scarcity can be transplanted into a new era of potential abundance? Is it conceivable that an economic analysis focused primarily on a âfreely competitiveâ system of industrial capitalism can be transferred to a managed system of capitalism, where state and monopolies combine to manipulate economic life? Is it conceivable that a strategic and tactical repertory formulated in a period when steel and coal constituted the basis of industrial technology can be transferred to an age based on radically new sources of energy, on electronics, on cybernation?
As a result of this transfer, a theoretical corpus which was liberating a century ago is turned into a straitjacket today. We are asked to focus on the working class as the âagentâ of revolutionary change at a time when capitalism visibly antagonizes and produces revolutionaries among virtually all strata of society, particularly the young. We are asked to guide our tactical methods by the vision of a âchronic economic crisisâ despite the fact that no such crisis has been in the offing for thirty years,[41] We are asked to accept a âproletarian dictatorshipââa long âtransitional periodâ whose function is not merely the suppression of counter-revolutionaries but above all the development of a technology of abundanceâat a time when a technology of abundance is at hand. We are asked to orient our âstrategiesâ and âtacticsâ around poverty and material immiseration at a time when revolutionary sentiment is being generated by the banality of life under conditions of material abundance. We are asked to establish political parties, centralized organizations, ârevolutionaryâ hierarchies and elites, and a new state at a time when political institutions as such are decaying and when centralizing, elitism and the state are being brought into question on a scale that has never occurred before in the history of hierarchical society.
We are asked, in short, to return to the past, to diminish instead of grow, to force the throbbing reality of our times, with its hopes and promises, into the deadening preconceptions of an outlived age. We are asked to operate with principles that have been transcended not only theoretically but by the very development of society itself. History has not stood still since Marx, Engels, Lenin and Trotsky died, nor has it followed the simplistic direction which was charted out by thinkersâhowever brilliantâwhose minds were still rooted in the nineteenth century or in the opening years of the twentieth. We have seen capitalism itself perform many of the tasks (including the development of a technology of abundance) which were regarded as socialist; we have seen it ânationalizeâ property, merging the economy with the state wherever necessary. We have seen the working class neutralized as the âagent of revolutionary change,â albeit still struggling with a **bourgeois** framework for more wages, shorter hours and âfringeâ benefits. The class struggle in the **classical** sense has not disappeared; it has suffered a more deadening fate by being co-opted into capitalism. The revolutionary struggle within the advanced capitalist countries has shifted into a historically new terrain: it has become a struggle between a generation of youth that has known no chronic economic crisis and the culture, values, and institutions of an older, conservative generation whose perspective on life has been shaped by scarcity, guilt, renunciation, the work ethic and the pursuit of material security. Our enemies are not only the visibly entrenched bourgeoisie and the state apparatus but also an outlook which finds its support among liberals, social democrats, the minions of a corrupt mass media, the ârevolutionaryâ parties of the past, and, painful as it may be to the acolytes of Marxism, the worker dominated by the factory hierarchy, by the industrial routine, and by the work ethic. The point is that the divisions now cut across virtually all the traditional class lines and they raise a spectrum of problems that none of the Marxists, leaning on analogies with scarcity societies, could foresee.
Let us cast aside all the ideological debris of the past and cut to the theoretical roots of the problem. For our age, Marxâs greatest contribution to revolutionary thought is his dialectic of social development. Marx laid bare the great movement from primitive communism through private property to communism in its highest formâa communal society resting on a liberatory technology. In this movement, according to Marx, man passes on from the domination of man by nature, to the domination of man by man, and finally to the domination of nature by man[42] and from social domination of such. Within this larger dialectic, Marx examines the dialectic of capitalism itselfâa social system which constitutes the last historical âstageâ in the domination of man by man. Here, Marx makes not only profound contributions to contemporary revolutionary thought (particularly in his brilliant analysis of the commodity relationship) but also exhibits those limitations of time and place that play so confining a role in our own time.
The most serious of these limitations emerges from Marxâs attempt to explain the transition from capitalism to socialism, from a class society to a classless society. It is vitally important to emphasize that this explanation was reasoned out almost entirely by analogy with the transition of feudalism to capitalismâthat is, **from one class society to another class society,** from one system of property to another. Accordingly, Marx points out that just as the bourgeoisie developed within feudalism as a result of the split between town and country (more precisely, between crafts and agriculture), so the modern proletariat developed within capitalism as a result of the advance of industrial technology. Both classes, we are told, develop social interests of their ownâindeed, revolutionary social interests that throw them against the old society in which they were spawned. If the bourgeoisie gained control over economic life long before it overthrew feudal society, the proletariat, in turn, gains its own revolutionary power by the fact that it is âdisciplined, united, organizedâ by the factory system.[43] In both cases, the development of the productive forces becomes incompatible with the traditional system of social relations. âThe integument is burst asunder.â The old society is replaced by the new.
The critical question we face is this: can we explain the transition from a class society to a classless society by means of the same dialectic that accounts for the transition of one class society to another? This is not a textbook problem that involves the judging of logical abstractions but a very real and concrete issue for our time. There are profound differences between the development of the bourgeoisie under feudalism and the development of the proletariat under capitalism which Marx either failed to anticipate or never faced clearly. The bourgeoisie controlled economic life long before it took state power; it had become the dominant class materially, culturally and ideologically before it asserted its dominance politically. The proletariat does not control economic life. Despite its indispensable role in the industrial process, the industrial working class is not even a majority of the population, and its strategic economic position is being eroded by cybernation and other technological advances.[44] Hence it requires an act of high consciousness for the proletariat to use its power to achieve a social revolution. Until now, the achievement of this consciousness has been blocked by the fact that the factory milieu is one of the most well entrenched arenas of the work ethic, of hierarchical systems of management, of obedience to leaders, and in recent times of production committed to superfluous commodities and armaments. The factory serves not only to âdiscipline,â âunite,â and âorganizeâ the workers, but also to do so in a thoroughly bourgeois fashion. In the factory, capitalistic production not only renews the social relations of capitalism with each working day, as Marx observed, it also renews the psyche, values and ideologies of capitalism.
Marx sensed this fact sufficiently to look for reasons more compelling than the mere fact of exploitation or conflicts over wages and hours to propel the proletariat into revolutionary action. In his general theory of capitalist accumulation he tried to delineate the harsh, objective laws that force the proletariat to assume a revolutionary role. Accordingly, he developed his famous theory of immiseration: competition between capitalists compels them to undercut each otherâs prices, which in turn leads to a continual reduction of wages and the absolute impoverishment of the workers. The proletariat is compelled to revolt because with the process of competition and the centralization of capital there âgrows the mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation.â[45]
But capitalism has not stood still since Marxâs day. Writing in the middle years of the nineteenth century, Marx could not be expected to grasp the full consequences of his insights into the centralization of capital and the development of technology. He could not be expected to foresee that capitalism would develop not only from mercantilism into the dominant industrial form of his dayâfrom state-aided trading monopolies into highly competitive industrial unitsâbut further, that with the centralization of capital, capitalism returns to its mercantilist origins on a higher level of development and reassumes the state-aided monopolistic form. The economy tends to merge with the state and capitalism begins to âplanâ its development instead of leaving it exclusively to the interplay of competition and market forces. To be sure, the system does not abolish the traditional class struggle, but manages to contain it, using its immense technological resources to assimilate the most strategic sections of the working class.
Thus the full thrust of the immiseration theory is blunted and in the United States the traditional class struggle fails to develop into the class war. It remains entirely within bourgeois dimensions. Marxism, in fact, becomes ideology. It is assimilated by the most advanced forms of state capitalist movementânotably Russia. By an incredible irony of history, Marxian âsocialismâ turns out to be in large part the very state capitalism that Marx failed to anticipate in the dialectic of capitalism.[46] The proletariat, instead of developing into a revolutionary class within the womb of capitalism, turns out to be an organ within the body of bourgeois society.
[38] These lines were written when the Progressive Labor Party (PLP) exercised a great deal of influence in SDS. Although the PLP has now lost most of its influence in the student movement, the organization still provides a good example of the mentality and values prevalent in the Old Left. The above characterization is equally valid for most Marxist-Leninist groups, hence this passage and other references to the PLP have not been substantially altered.
[39] The Dodge Revolutionary Union Movement, part of the Detroit-based League of Revolutionary Black Workers.
[40] Marxism is above all a theory of praxis, or to place this relationship in its correct perspective, a praxis of theory. This is the very meaning of Marxâs transformation of dialectics, which took it from the subjective dimension (to which the Young Hegelians still tried to confine Hegelâs outlook) into the objective, from philosophical critique into social action. If theory and praxis become divorced, Marxism is not killed, it commits suicide. This is its most admirable and noble feature. The attempts of the cretins who follow in Marxâs wake to keep the system alive with a patchwork of emendations, exegesis, and half-assed âscholarshipâ Ă la Maurice Dobb and George Novack are degrading insults to Marxâs name and a disgusting pollution of everything he stood for.
[41] In fact Marxists do very little talking about the âchronic [economic] crisis of capitalismâ these daysâdespite the fact that this concept forms the focal point of Marxâs economic theories.
[42] For ecological reasons, we do not accept the notion of the âdomination of nature by manâ in the simplistic sense that was passed on by Marx a century ago. For a discussion of this problem, see âEcology and Revolutionary Thought.â
[43] It is ironic that Marxists who talk about the âeconomic powerâ of the proletariat are actually echoing the position of the anarcho-syndicalists, a position that Marx bitterly opposed. Marx was not concerned with the âeconomic powerâ of the proletariat but with its **political** power; notably the fact that it would become the majority of the population. He was convinced that the industrial workers would be driven to revolution primarily by material destitution which would follow from the tendency of capitalist accumulation; that, **organized** by the factory system and **disciplined** by an industrial routine, they would be able to constitute trade unions and, above all, political parties, which in some countries would be obliged to use insurrectionary methods and in others (England, the United States, and in later years Engels added France) might well come to power in elections and legislate socialism into existence. Characteristically, many Marxists have been as dishonest with their Marx and Engels as the Progressive Labor Party has been with the readers of **Challenge**, leaving important observations untranslated or grossly distorting Marxâs
meaning.
[44] This is as good a place as any to dispose of the notion that anyone is a âproletarianâ who has nothing to sell but his labor power. It is true that Marx defined the proletariat in these terms, but he also worked out a historical dialectic in the development of the proletariat. The proletariat develop out of a propertyless exploited class, reaching its most advanced form in the industrial proletariat, which corresponded to the most advanced form of capital. In the later years of his life, Marx came to despise the Parisian workers, who were engaged preponderantly in the production of luxury goods, citing âour German workersââthe most robot-like in Europeâas the âmodelâ proletariat of the world.
[45] The attempt to describe Marxâs immiseration theory in international terms instead of national (as Marx did) is sheer subterfuge. In the first place, this theoretical legerdemain simply tries to sidestep the question of why immiseration has not occurred within the industrial
strongholds of capitalism, the **only areas which form a technologically adequate point of departure for a classless society.** If we are to pin our hopes on the colonial world as âthe proletariat,â this position conceals a very real danger: genocide. America and her recent ally Russia have all the technical means to bomb the underdeveloped world into submission. A threat lurks on the historical horizonâthe development of the United States into a truly fascist imperium of the nazi type. It is sheer rubbish to say that this country is a âpaper tiger.â It is a thermonuclear tiger and the American ruling class, lacking any cultural restraints, is capable of being even more vicious than the German.
[46] Lenin sensed this and described âsocialismâ as ânothing but state capitalist monopoly **made to benefit the whole people.**â{29} This is an extraordinary statement if one thinks out its implications, and a mouthful of contradictions.
The question we must ask at this late date in history is whether a social revolution that seeks to achieve a classless society can emerge from a conflict between traditional classes in a class society, or whether such a social revolution can only emerge from the decomposition of the traditional classes, indeed from the emergence of an entirely new âclassâ **whose very essence is that it is a non-class,** a growing stratum of revolutionaries. In trying to answer this question, we can learn more by returning to the broader dialectic which Marx developed for human society as a whole than from the model he borrowed from the passage of feudal into capitalist society. Just as primitive kinship clans began to differentiate into classes, so in our own day there is a tendency for classes to decompose into entirely new subcultures which bear a resemblance to non-capitalist forms of relationships. These are not strictly economic groups anymore; in fact, they reflect the tendency of the social development to transcend the economic categories of scarcity society. They constitute, in effect, a crude, ambiguous **cultural** preformation of the movement of scarcity into post-scarcity society.
The process of class decomposition must be understood in all its dimensions. The word âprocessâ must be emphasized here: the traditional classes do not disappear, nor for that matter does class struggle. Only a social revolution could remove the prevailing class structure and the conflict it engenders. The point is the traditional class struggle ceases to have revolutionary implications; it reveals itself as the physiology of the prevailing society, not as the labor pains of birth. In fact the traditional class struggle stabilizes capitalist society by âcorrectingâ its abuses (in wages, hours, inflation, employment, etc.). The unions in capitalist society constitute themselves into a counter-âmonopolyâ to the industrial monopolies and are incorporated into the neomercantile statified economy as an estate. Within this estate there are lesser or greater conflicts, but taken as a whole the unions strengthen the system and serve to perpetuate it.
To reinforce this class structure by babbling about the ârole of the working class,â to reinforce the traditional class struggle by imputing a ârevolutionaryâ content to it, to infect the new revolutionary movement of our time with âworkeritisâ is **reactionary to the core.** How often do the Marxian doctrinaires have to be reminded that the history of the class struggle is the history of a disease, of the wounds opened by the famous âsocial question,â of manâs one-sided development in trying to gain control over nature by dominating his fellow man? If the byproduct of this disease has been technological advance, the main products have been repression, a horrible shedding of human blood and a terrifying distortion of the human psyche.
As the disease approaches its end, as the wounds begin to heal in their deepest recesses, the process now unfolds toward wholeness; the **revolutionary** implications of the traditional class struggle lose their meaning as theoretical constructs and as social reality. The process of decomposition embraces not only the traditional class structure but also the patriarchal family, authoritarian modes of upbringing, the influence of religion, the institutions of the state, and the mores built around toil, renunciation, guilt and repressed sexuality. **The process of disintegration, in short, now becomes generalized and cuts across virtually all the traditional classes, values and institutions. It creates entirely new issues, modes of struggle and forms of organization and calls for an entirely new approach to theory and praxis.**
What does this mean concretely? Let us contrast two approaches, the Marxian and the revolutionary. The Marxian doctrinaire would have us approach the workerâor better, âenterâ the factoryâand proselytize him in âpreferenceâ to anyone else. The purpose?âto make the worker âclass conscious.â To cite the most neanderthal examples from the old left, one cuts oneâs hair, grooms oneself in conventional sports clothing, abandons pot for cigarettes and beer, dances conventionally, affects âroughâ mannerisms, and develops a humorless, deadpan and pompous mien.[47]
One becomes, in short, what the worker is at his most caricaturized worst: not a âpetty bourgeois degenerate,â to be sure, but a bourgeois degenerate. One becomes an imitation of the worker insofar as the worker is an imitation of his masters. Beneath the metamorphosis of the student into the âworkerâ lies a vicious cynicism. One tries to use the discipline inculcated by the factory milieu to discipline the worker to the party milieu. One tries to use the workerâs respect for the industrial hierarchy to wed to worker to the party hierarchy. This disgusting process, which if successful could lead only to the substitution of one hierarchy for another, is achieved by pretending to be concerned with the workerâs economic day-to-day demands. Even Marxian theory is degraded to accord with this debased image of the worker. (See almost any copy of **Challenge**âthe **National Enquirer** of the left. Nothing bores the worker more than this kind of literature.) In the end, the worker is shrewd enough to know that he will get better results in the day-to-day class struggle through his union bureaucracy than through a Marxian party bureaucracy. The forties revealed this so dramatically that within a year or two, with hardly any protest from the rank-and-file, unions succeeded in kicking out by the thousands âMarxiansâ who had done spade-work in the labor movement for more than a decade, even rising to the top leadership of the old CIO internationals.
The worker becomes a **revolutionary** not by becoming more of a worker but by undoing his âworkerness.â And in this he is not alone; the same applies to the farmer, the student, the clerk, the soldier, the bureaucrat, the professionalâand the Marxist. The worker is no less a âbourgeoisâ than the farmer, student, clerk, soldier, bureaucrat, professionalâand Marxist. His âworkernessâ is the **disease** he is suffering from, the social affliction telescoped to individual dimensions. Lenin understood this in **What Is to Be Done?** but he smuggled in the old hierarchy under a red flag and some revolutionary verbiage. The worker begins to become a revolutionary when he undoes his âworkerness,â when he comes to detest his class status here and now, when he begins to shed exactly those features which the Marxists most prize in himâhis work ethic, his character-structure derived from industrial discipline, his respect for hierarchy, his obedience to leaders, his consumerism, his vestiges of puritanism. In this sense, the worker becomes a revolutionary to the degree that he sheds his class status and achieves an **un-**class consciousness. He degeneratesâand he degenerates magnificently. What he is shedding are precisely those **class** shackles that bind him to **all** systems of domination. He abandons those **class** interests that enslave him to consumerism, suburbia, and a bookkeeping conception of life.[48]
The most promising development in the factories today is the emergence of young workers who smoke pot, fuck off on their jobs, drift into and out of factories, grow long or longish hair, demand more leisure time rather than more pay, steal, harass all authority figures, go on wildcats, and turn on their fellow workers. Even more promising is the emergence of this human type in trade schools and high schools, the reservoir of the industrial working class to come. To the degree that workers, vocational students and high school students link their lifestyles to various aspects of the anarchic youth culture, to that degree will the proletariat be transformed from a force for the conservation of the established order into a force for revolution.
A qualitatively new situation emerges when man is faced with a transformation from a repressive class society, based on material scarcity, into a liberatory classless society, based on material abundance. From the decomposing traditional class structure a new human type is created in ever-increasing numbers: the revolutionary. This revolutionary begins to challenge not only the economic and political premises of hierarchical society, but hierarchy as such. He not only raises the need for social revolution but also tries to live in a revolutionary manner to the degree that this is possible in the existing society.[49] He not only attacks the forms created by the legacy of domination, but also improvises new forms of liberation which take their poetry from the future.
This preparation for the future, this experimentation with liberatory post-scarcity forms of social relations, may be illusory if the future involves a substitution of one class society by another; it is indispensable, however, if the future involves a classless society built on the ruins of a class society. What, then, will be the âagentâ of revolutionary change? It will be literally the great majority of society, drawn from all the different traditional classes and fused into a common revolutionary force by the decomposition of the institutions, social forms, values and lifestyles of the prevailing class structure. Typically, its most advanced elements are the youthâa generation that has known no chronic economic crisis and that is becoming less and less oriented toward the myth of material security so widespread among the generation of the thirties.
If it is true that a social revolution cannot be achieved without the active or passive support of the workers, it is no less true that it cannot be achieved without the active or passive support of the farmers, technicians and professionals. Above all, a social revolution cannot be achieved without the support of the youth, from which the ruling class recruits its armed forces. If the ruling class retains its armed might, the revolution is lost no matter how many workers rally to its support. This has been vividly demonstrated not only by Spain in the thirties but by Hungary in the fifties and Czechoslovakia in the sixties. The revolution of todayâby its very nature, indeed, by its pursuit of wholenessâwins not only the soldier and the worker, but the very generation from which soldiers, workers, technicians, farmers, scientists, professionals and even bureaucrats have been recruited. Discarding the tactical handbooks of the past, the revolution of the future follows the path of least resistance, eating its way into the most susceptible areas of the population irrespective of their âclass position.â It is nourished by all the contradictions in bourgeois society, not simply by the contradictions of the 1860s and 1917. Hence it attracts all those who feel the burdens of exploitation, poverty, racism, imperialism and, yes, those whose lives are frustrated by consumerism, suburbia, the mass media, the family, school, the supermarket and the prevailing system of repressed sexuality. Here the form of the revolution becomes as total as its contentâclassless, propertyless, hierarchyless, and wholly liberating.
To barge into this revolutionary development with the worn recipes of Marxism, to babble about a âclass lineâ and the ârole of the working class,â amounts to a subversion of the present and the future by the past. To elaborate this deadening ideology by babbling about âcadres,â a âvanguard party,â âdemocratic centralismâ and the âproletarian dictatorshipâ is sheer counterrevolution. It is to this matter of the âorganizational question ââthis vital contribution of Leninism to Marxismâthat we must now direct some attention.
Social revolutions are not made by parties, groups or cadres, they occur as a result of deep-seated historic forces and contradictions that activate large sections of the population. They occur not merely because the âmassesâ find the existing society intolerable (as Trotsky argued) but also because of the tension between the actual and the possible, between what-is and what-could-be. Abject misery alone does not produce revolutions; more often than not, it produces an aimless demoralization, or worse, a private, personalized struggle to survive.
The Russian Revolution of 1917 weighs on the brain of the living like a nightmare because it was largely the product of âintolerable conditions,â of a devastating imperialistic war. Whatever dreams it had were virtually destroyed, by an even bloodier civil war, by famine, and by treachery. What emerged from the revolution were the ruins not of an old society but of whatever hopes existed to achieve a new one. The Russian Revolution failed miserably; it replaced czarism by state capitalism.[50] The Bolsheviks were the tragic victims of their own ideology and paid with their lives in great numbers during the purges of the thirties. To attempt to acquire any unique wisdom from this scarcity revolution is ridiculous. What we can learn from the revolutions of the past is what all revolutions have in common and their profound limitations compared with the enormous possibilities that are now open to us.
The most striking feature of the past revolutions is that they began spontaneously. Whether one chooses to examine the opening phases of the French Revolution of 1789, the revolutions of 1848, the Paris Commune, the 1905 revolution in Russia, the overthrow of the Czar in 1917, the Hungarian revolution of 1956, or the French general strike of 1968, the opening stages are generally the same: a period of ferment explodes spontaneously into a mass upsurge. Whether the upsurge is successful or not depends on its resoluteness and on whether the troops go over to the people.
The âglorious party,â when there is one, almost invariably lags behind the events. In February 1917 the Petrograd organization of the Bolsheviks opposed the calling of strikes precisely on the eve of the revolution which was destined to overthrow the Czar. Fortunately, the workers ignored the Bolshevik âdirectivesâ and went on strike anyway. In the events which followed, no one was more surprised by the revolution than the ârevolutionaryâ parties, including the Bolsheviks. As the Bolshevik leader Kayurov recalled:
âAbsolutely no guiding initiatives from the party were felt ⊠the Petrograd committee had been arrested and the representative from the Central Committee, Comrade Shliapnikov, was unable to give any directives for the coming day.â{30}
Perhaps this was fortunate. Before the Petrograd committee was arrested, its evaluation of the situation and its own role had been so dismal that, had the workers followed its guidance, it is doubtful that the revolution would have occurred when it did.
The same kind of story could be told of the upsurges which preceded 1917 and those which followedâto cite only the most recent, the student uprising and general strike in France during MayâJune 1968. There is a convenient tendency to forget that close to a dozen âtightly centralizedâ Bolshevik-type organizations existed in Paris at this time. It is rarely mentioned that virtually every one of these âvanguardâ groups disdained the student uprising up to May 7, when the street fighting broke out in earnest. The Trotskyist Jeunesse Communiste RĂ©volutionnaire was a notable exceptionâand it merely coasted along, essentially following the initiatives of the March 22nd Movement.[51] Up to May 7 all the Maoist groups criticized the student uprising as peripheral and unimportant; the Trotskyist FĂ©dĂ©ration des Ătudiants RĂ©volutionnaires regarded it as âadventuristicâ and tried to get the students to leave the barricades on May 10; the Communist Party, of course, played a completely treacherous role. Far from leading the popular movement, the Maoists and Trotskyists were its captives throughout. Ironically, most of these Bolshevik groups used manipulative techniques shamelessly in the Sorbonne student assembly in an effort to âcontrolâ it, introducing a disruptive atmosphere that demoralized the entire body. Finally, to complete the irony, all of these Bolshevik groups were to babble about the need for âcentralized leadershipâ when the popular movement collapsedâa movement that occurred despite their âdirectivesâ and often in opposition to them.
Revolutions and uprisings worthy of any note not only have an initial phase that is magnificently anarchic but also tend spontaneously to create their own forms of revolutionary self-management. The Parisian sections of 1793â94 were the most remarkable forms of self-management to be created by any of the social revolutions in history.[52] More familiar in form were the councils or âsovietsâ which the Petrograd workers established in 1905. Although less democratic than the sections, the councils were to reappear in a number of later revolutions. Still another form of revolutionary self-management were the factory committees which the anarchists established in the Spanish Revolution of 1936. Finally, the sections reappeared as student assemblies and action committees in the MayâJune uprising and general strike in Paris in 1968.[53]
At this point we must ask what role the ârevolutionaryâ party plays in all these developments. In the beginning, as we have seen, it tends to have an emancipatory function, not a âvanguardâ role. Where it exercises influence, it tends to slow down the flow of events, not âcoordinateâ the revolutionary forces. This is not accidental. The party is structured along hierarchical lines that reflect the very society it professes to oppose. Despite its theoretical pretensions, it is a bourgeois organism, a miniature state, with an apparatus and a cadre whose function it is to seize power, not dissolve power. Rooted in the prerevolutionary period, it assimilates all the forms, techniques and mentality of bureaucracy. Its membership is schooled in obedience and in the preconceptions of a rigid dogma and is taught to revere the leadership. The partyâs leadership, in turn, is schooled in habits born of command, authority, manipulation and egomania. This situation is worsened when the party participates in parliamentary elections. In election campaigns, the vanguard party models itself completely on existing bourgeois forms and even acquires the paraphernalia of the electoral party. The situation assumes truly critical proportions when the party acquires large presses, costly headquarters and a large inventory of centrally controlled periodicals, and develops a paid âapparatusââin short, a bureaucracy with vested material interests.
As the party expands, the distance between the leadership and the ranks invariably increases. Its leaders not only become âpersonages,â they lose contact with the living situation below. The local groups, which know their own immediate situation better than any remote leader, are obliged to subordinate their insights to directives from above. The leadership, lacking any direct knowledge of local problems, responds sluggishly and prudently. Although it stakes out a claim to the âlarger view,â to greater âtheoretical competence,â the competence of the leadership tends to diminish as one ascends the hierarchy of command. The more one approaches the level where the real decisions are made, the more conservative is the nature of the decision-making process, the more bureaucratic and extraneous are the factors which come into play, the more considerations of prestige and retrenchment supplant creativity, imagination, and a disinterested dedication to revolutionary goals.
The party becomes less efficient from a revolutionary point of view the more it seeks efficiency by means of hierarchy, cadres and centralization. Although everyone marches in step, the orders are usually wrong, especially when events begin to move rapidly and take unexpected turnsâas they do in all revolutions. The party is efficient in only one respectâin molding society in its own hierarchical image if the revolution is successful. It recreates bureaucracy, centralization and the state. It fosters the bureaucracy, centralization and the state. It fosters the very social conditions which justify this kind of society. Hence, instead of âwithering away,â the state controlled by the âglorious partyâ preserves the very conditions which ânecessitateâ the existence of a stateâand a party to âguardâ it.
On the other hand, this kind of party is extremely vulnerable in periods of repression. The bourgeoisie has only to grab its leadership to destroy virtually the entire movement. With its leaders in prison or in hiding, the party becomes paralyzed; the obedient membership has no one to obey and tends to flounder. Demoralization sets in rapidly. The party decomposes not only because of the repressive atmosphere but also because of its poverty of inner resources.
The foregoing account is not a series of hypothetical inferences, it is a composite sketch of all the mass Marxian parties of the past centuryâthe Social Democrats, the Communists, and the Trotskyist party of Ceylon (the only mass party of its kind). To claim that these parties failed to take their Marxian principles seriously merely conceals another question: why did this failure happen in the first place? The fact is, these parties were co-opted into bourgeois society because they were structured along bourgeois lines. The germ of treachery existed in them from birth.
The Bolshevik Party was spared this fate between 1904 and 1917 for only one reason: it was an illegal organization during most of the years leading up to the revolution. The party was continually being shattered and reconstituted, with the result that until it took power it never really hardened into a fully centralized, bureaucratic, hierarchical machine. Moreover, it was riddled by factions; the intensely factional atmosphere persisted throughout 1917 into the civil war. Nevertheless, the Bolshevik leadership was ordinarily extremely conservative, a trait that Lenin had to fight throughout 1917âfirst in his efforts to reorient the Central Committee against the provisional government (the famous conflict over the âApril Thesesâ), later in driving the Central Committee toward insurrection in October. In both cases he threatened to resign from the Central Committee and bring his views to âthe lower ranks of the party.â
In 1918, factional disputes over the issue of the Brest-Litovsk treaty became so serious that the Bolsheviks nearly split into two warring communist parties. Oppositional Bolshevik groups like the Democratic Centralists and the Workersâ Opposition waged bitter struggles within the party throughout 1919 and 1920, not to speak of oppositional movements that developed within the Red Army over Trotskyâs propensity for centralization. The complete centralization of the Bolshevik Partyâthe achievement of âLeninist unity,â as it was to be called laterâdid not occur until 1921, when Lenin succeeded in persuading the Tenth Party Congress to ban factions. By this time, most of the White Guards had been crushed and the foreign interventionists had withdrawn their troops from Russia.
It cannot be stressed too strongly that the Bolsheviks tended to centralize their party to the degree that they became isolated from the working class. This relationship has rarely been investigated in latter-day Leninist circles, although Lenin was honest enough to admit it. The story of the Russian Revolution is not merely the story of the Bolshevik Party and its supporters. Beneath the veneer of official events described by Soviet historians there was another, more basic, developmentâthe spontaneous movement of the workers and revolutionary peasants, which later clashed sharply with the bureaucratic policies of the Bolsheviks. With the overthrow of the Czar in February 1917, workers in virtually all the factories of Russia spontaneously established factory committees, staking out an increasing claim on industrial operations. In June 1917 an all-Russian conference of factory committees was held in Petrograd which called for the âorganization of thorough control by labor over production and distribution.â The demands of this conference are rarely mentioned in Leninist accounts of the Russian Revolution, despite the fact that the conference aligned itself with the Bolsheviks. Trotsky, who describes the factory committees as âthe most direct and indubitable representation of the proletariat in the whole country,â deals with them peripherally in his massive three-volume history of the revolution. Yet so important were these spontaneous organisms of self-management that Lenin, despairing of winning the soviets in the summer of 1917, was prepared to jettison the slogan âAll Power to the Sovietsâ for âAll Power to the Factory Committees.â This demand would have catapulted the Bolsheviks into a completely anarcho-syndicalist position, although it is doubtful that they would have remained there very long.
With the October Revolution, all the factory committees seized control of the plants, ousting the bourgeoisie and completely taking control of industry. In accepting the concept of workersâ control, Leninâs famous decree of November 14, 1917, merely acknowledged an accomplished fact; the Bolsheviks dared not oppose the workers at this early date. But they began to whittle down the power of the factory committees. In January 1918, a scant two months after âdecreeingâ workersâ control, Lenin began to advocate that the administration of the factories be placed under trade union control. The story that the Bolsheviks âpatientlyâ experimented with workersâ control, only to find it âinefficientâ and âchaotic,â is a myth. Their âpatienceâ did not last more than a few weeks. Not only did Lenin oppose direct workersâ control within a matter of weeks after the decree of November 14, even union control came to an end shortly after it had been established. By the summer of 1918, almost all of Russian industry had been placed under bourgeois forms of management. As Lenin put it, the ârevolution demands ⊠precisely in the interests of socialism that the masses unquestionably obey the single will of the leaders of the labor process.[54] Thereafter, workersâ control was denounced not only as âinefficient,â âchaoticâ and âimpractical,â but also as âpetty bourgeoisâ!
The Left Communist Osinsky bitterly attacked all of these spurious claims and warned the party: âSocialism and socialist organization must be set up by the proletariat itself, or they will not be set up at all; something else will be set upâstate capitalism.â{31} In the âinterests of socialismâ the Bolshevik party elbowed the proletariat out of every domain it had conquered by its own efforts and initiative. The party did not coordinate the revolution or even lead it; it dominated it. First workersâ control and later union control were replaced by an elaborate hierarchy as monstrous as any structure that existed in pre-revolutionary times. As later years were to demonstrate, Osinskyâs prophecy became reality.
The problem of âwho is to prevailââthe Bolsheviks or the Russian âmassesââwas by no means limited to the factories. The issue reappeared in the countryside as well as the cities. A sweeping peasant war had buoyed up the movement of the workers. Contrary to official Leninist accounts, the agrarian upsurge was by no means limited to a redistribution of the land into private plots. In the Ukraine, peasants influenced by the anarchist militias of Nestor Makhno and guided by the communist maxim âFrom each according to his ability; to each according to his needs,â established a multitude of rural communes. Elsewhere, in the north and in Soviet Asia, several thousand of these organisms were established, partly on the initiative of the Left Social Revolutionaries and in large measure as a result of traditional collectivist impulses which stemmed from the Russian village, the mir. It matters little whether these communes were numerous or embraced large numbers of peasants; the point is that they were authentic popular organisms, the nuclei of a moral and social spirit that ranged far above the dehumanizing values of bourgeois society.
The Bolsheviks frowned upon these organisms from the very beginning and eventually condemned them. To Lenin, the preferred, the more âsocialist,â form of agricultural enterprise was represented by the state farmâan agricultural factory in which the state owned the land and farming equipment, appointing managers who hired peasants on a wage basis. One sees in these attitudes toward workersâ control and agricultural communes the essentially bourgeois spirit and mentality that permeated the Bolshevik Partyâa spirit and mentality that emanated not only from its theories, but also from its corporate mode of organization. In December 1918 Lenin launched an attack against the communes on the pretext that peasants were being âforcedâ to enter them. Actually, little if any coercion was used to organize these communistic forms of self-management. As Robert G. Wesson, who studied the Soviet communes in detail, concludes: âThose who went into communes must have done so largely of their own volition.â{32} The communes were not suppressed but their growth was discouraged until Stalin merged the entire development into the forced collectivization drives of the late twenties and early thirties.
By 1920 the Bolsheviks had isolated themselves from the Russian working class and peasantry. Taken together, the elimination of workersâ control, the suppression of the Makhnovtsy, the restrictive political atmosphere in the country, the inflated bureaucracy and the crushing material poverty inherited from the civil war years generated a deep hostility toward Bolshevik rule. With the end of hostilities, a movement surged up from the depths of Russian society for a âthird revolutionâânot to restore the past, as the Bolsheviks claimed, but to realize the very goals of freedom, economic as well as political, that had rallied the masses around the Bolshevik program of 1917. The new movement found its most conscious form in the Petrograd proletariat and among the Kronstadt sailors. It also found expression in the party: the growth of anticentralist and anarcho-syndicalist tendencies among the Bolsheviks reached a point where a bloc of oppositional groups, oriented toward these issues, gained 124 seats at a Moscow provincial conference as against 154 for supporters of the Central Committee.
On March 2, 1921, the âred sailorsâ of Kronstadt rose in open rebellion, raising the banner of a âThird Revolution of the Toilers.â The Kronstadt program centered around demands for free elections to the soviets, freedom of speech and press for the anarchists and the left socialist parties, free trade unions, and the liberation of all prisoners who belonged to socialist parties. The most shameless stories were fabricated by the Bolsheviks to account for this uprising, acknowledged in later years as brazen lies. The revolt was characterized as a âWhite Guard plotâ despite the fact that the great majority of Communist Party members in Kronstadt joined the sailorsâprecisely as Communistsâin denouncing the party leaders as betrayers of the October Revolution. As Robert Vincent Daniels observes in his study of Bolshevik oppositional movements:
âOrdinary Communists were indeed so unreliable ⊠that the government did not depend upon them either in the assault on Kronstadt itself or in keeping order in Petrograd, where Kronstadtâs hopes for support chiefly rested. The main body of troops employed were Chekists and officer cadets from Red Army training schools. The final assault on Kronstadt was led by the top officialdom of the Communist Partyâa large group of delegates to the Tenth Party Congress was rushed from Moscow for this purpose.â{33}
So weak was the regime internally that the elite had to do its own dirty work.
Even more significant than the Kronstadt revolt was the strike movement that developed among the Petrograd workers, a movement that sparked the uprising of the sailors. Leninist histories do not recount this critically important development. The first strikes broke out in the Troubotchny factory on February 23, 1921. Within a matter of days the movement swept one factory after another, until by February 28 the famous Putilov worksâthe âcrucible of the Revolutionââwent on strike. Not only were economic demands raised, the workers raised distinctly political ones, anticipating all the demands that were to be raised by the Kronstadt sailors a few days later. On February 24, the Bolsheviks declared a âstate of siegeâ in Petrograd and arrested the strike leaders, suppressing the workersâ demonstrations with officer cadets. The fact is, the Bolsheviks did not merely suppress a âsailorsâ mutinyâ; they crushed the working class itself. It was at this point that Lenin demanded the banning of factions in the Russian Communist Party. Centralization of the party was now completeâand the way was paved for Stalin.
We have discussed these events in detail because they lead to a conclusion that the latest crop of Marxist-Leninists tend to avoid: the Bolshevik Party reached its maximum degree of centralization in Leninâs day not to achieve a revolution or suppress a White Guard counterrevolution, but to effect a counterrevolution of its own against the very social forces it professed to represent. Factions were prohibited and a monolithic party created not to prevent a âcapitalist restorationâ but to contain a mass movement of workers for soviet democracy and social freedom. The Lenin of 1921 stood opposed to the Lenin of 1917.
Thereafter, Lenin simply floundered. This man who above all sought to anchor the problems of his party in social contradictions found himself literally playing an organizational ânumbers gameâ in a last-ditch attempt to arrest the very bureaucratization he had himself created. There is nothing more pathetic and tragic than Leninâs last years. Paralyzed by a simplistic body of Marxist formulas, he can think of no better countermeasures than organizational ones. He proposes the formation of the Workersâ and Peasantsâ Inspection to correct bureaucratic reformations in the party and stateâand this body falls under Stalinâs control and becomes highly bureaucratic in its own right. Lenin then suggests that the size of the Workersâ and Peasantsâ Inspection be reduced and that it be merged with the Control Commission. He advocates enlarging the Central Committee. Thus it rolls along: this body to be enlarged, that one to be merged with another, still a third to be modified or abolished. The strange ballet of organizational forms continues up to his very death, as though the
problem could be resolved by organizational means. As Mosche Lewin, an obvious admirer of Lenin, admits, the Bolshevik leader âapproached the problems of government more like a chief executive of a strictly âelitistâ turn of mind. He did not apply methods of social analysis to the government and was content to consider it purely in terms of organizational methods.â{34}
If it is true that in the bourgeois revolutions the âphrase went beyond the content,â in the Bolshevik revolution the forms replaced the content. The soviets replaced the workers and their factory committees, the party replaced the soviets, the Central Committee replaced the Party, and the Political Bureau replaced the Central Committee. In short, means replaced ends. This incredible substitution of form for content is one of the most characteristic traits of Marxism-Leninism. In France during the MayâJune events, all the Bolshevik organizations were prepared to destroy the Sorbonne student assembly in order to increase their influence and membership. Their principal concern was not the revolution or the authentic social forms created by the students, but the growth of their own parties.
Only one force could have arrested the growth of bureaucracy in Russia: a social force. Had the Russian proletariat and peasantry succeeded in increasing the domain of self-management through the development of viable factory committees, rural communes and free soviets, the history of the country might have taken a dramatically different turn. There can be no question that the failure of socialist revolutions in Europe after the First World War led to the isolation of the revolution in Russia. The material poverty of Russia, coupled with the pressure of the surrounding capitalist world, clearly militated against the development of a socialist or a consistently libertarian society. But by no means was it ordained that Russia had to develop along state capitalist lines; contrary to Leninâs and Trotskyâs initial expectations, the revolution was defeated by internal forces, not by invasion of armies from abroad. Had the movement from below restored the initial achievements of the revolution in 1917, a multifaceted social structure might have developed, based on workersâ control of industry, on a freely developing peasant economy in agriculture, and on a living interplay of ideas, programs and political movements. At the very least, Russia would not have been imprisoned in totalitarian chains and Stalinism would not have poisoned the world revolutionary movement, paving the way for fascism and the Second World War. The development of the Bolshevik Party, however, precluded this developmentâLeninâs or Trotskyâs âgood intentionsâ notwithstanding. By destroying the power of the factory committees in industry and by crushing the Makhnovtsy, the Petrograd workers and the Kronstadt sailors, the Bolsheviks virtually guaranteed the triumph of the Russian bureaucracy over Russian society. The centralized partyâa completely bourgeois institutionâbecame the refuge of counterrevolution in its most sinister form. This was covert counterrevolution that draped itself in the red flag and the terminology of Marx. Ultimately, what the Bolsheviks suppressed in 1921 was not an âideologyâ or a âWhite Guard conspiracy,â but an **elemental struggle of the Russian people** to free themselves of their shackles and take control of their own destiny.[55] For Russia, this meant the nightmare of Stalinist dictatorship; for the generation of the thirties it meant the horror of fascism and the treachery of the Communist parties in Europe and the United States.
It would be incredibly naive to suppose that Leninism was the product of a single man. The disease lies much deeper, not only in the limitations of Marxian theory but in the limitations of the social era that produced Marxism. If this is not clearly understood, we will remain as blind to the dialectic of events today as Marx, Engels, Lenin and Trotsky were in their own day. For us this blindness will be all the more reprehensible because behind us lies a wealth of experience that these men lacked in developing their theories.
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels were centralistsânot only politically, but socially and economically. They never denied this fact and their writings are studded with glowing encomiums to political, organizational and economic centralization. As early as March 1850, in the famous âAddress of the Central Council to the Communist League,â they call upon the workers to strive not only for âthe single and indivisible German republic, but also strive in it for the most decisive centralization of power in the hands of the state authority.â Lest the demand be taken lightly, it is repeated continually in the same paragraph, which concludes: âAs in France in 1793, so today in Germany the carrying through of the strictest centralization is the task of the really revolutionary party.â
The same theme reappears continually in later years. With the outbreak of the Franco-Prussian War, for example, Marx writes to Engels: âThe French need a thrashing. If the Prussians win, the centralization of state power will be useful for the centralization of the German working class.â{35}
Marx and Engels, however, were not centralists because they believed in the virtues of centralism per se. Quite the contrary: both Marxism and anarchism have always agreed that a liberated, communist society entails sweeping decentralization, the dissolution of bureaucracy, the abolition of the state, and the breakup of the large cities. âAbolition of the antithesis between town and country is not merely possible,â notes Engels in Anti-DĂŒhring. âIt has become a direct necessity ⊠the present poisoning of the air, water and land can be put to an end only by the fusion of town and country. âŠâ To Engels this involves a âuniform distribution of the population over the whole countryâ{36}âin short, the physical decentralization of the cities.
The origins of Marxian centralism are in problems arising from the formation of the national state. Until well into the latter half of the nineteenth century, Germany and Italy were divided into a multitude of independent duchies, principalities and kingdoms. The consolidation of these geographic units into unified nations, Marx and Engels believed, was a sine qua non for the development of modern industry and capitalism. Their praise of centralism was engendered not by any centralistic mystique but by the events of the period in which they livedâthe development of technology, trade, a unified working class, and the national state. Their concern on this score, in short, is with the emergence of capitalism, with the tasks of the bourgeois revolution in an era of unavoidable material scarcity. Marxâs approach to a âproletarian revolution,â on the other hand, is markedly different. He enthusiastically praises the Paris Commune as a âmodel to all the industrial centers of France.â âThis regime,â he writes, âonce established in Paris and the secondary centers, the old centralized government would in the provinces, too, have to give way to the **self-government of the producers**.â (Emphasis added.) The unity of the nation, to be sure, would not disappear, and a central government would exist during the transition to communism, but its functions would be limited.
Our object is not to bandy about quotations from Marx and Engels but to emphasize how key tenets of Marxismâwhich are accepted so uncritically todayâwere in fact the product of an era that has long been transcended by the development of capitalism in the United States and Western Europe. In his day Marx was occupied not only with the problems of the âproletarian revolutionâ but also with the problems of the bourgeois revolution, particularly in Germany, Spain, Italy and Eastern Europe. He dealt with the problems of transition from capitalism to socialism in capitalist countries which had not advanced much beyond the coal-steel technology of the Industrial Revolution, and with the problems of transition from feudalism to capitalism in countries which had scarcely advanced much beyond handicrafts and the guild system. To state these concerns broadly, Marx was occupied above all with the preconditions of freedom (technological development, national unification, material abundance) rather than with the conditions of freedom (decentralization, the formation of
communities, the human scale, direct democracy). His theories were still anchored in the realm of survival, not the realm of life.
Once this is grasped it is possible to place Marxâs theoretical legacy in meaningful perspectiveâto separate its rich contributions from its historically limited, indeed paralyzing, shackles on our own time. The Marxian dialectic, the many seminal insights provided by historical materialism, the superb critique of the commodity relationship, many elements of the economic theories, the theory of alienation, and above all the notion that freedom has material preconditionsâthese are lasting contributions to revolutionary thought.
By the same token, Marxâs emphasis on the industrial proletariat as the âagentâ of revolutionary change, his âclass analysisâ in explaining the transition from a class to a classless society, his concept of the proletarian dictatorship, his emphasis on centralism, his theory of capitalist development (which tends to jumble state capitalism with socialism), his advocacy of political action through electoral partiesâthese and many related concepts are false in the context of our time and were misleading, as we shall see, even in his own day. They emerge from the limitations of his visionâmore properly, from the limitations of his time. They make sense only if one remembers that Marx regarded capitalism as historically progressive, as an indispensable stage to the development of socialism, and they have practical applicability only to a time when Germany in particular was confronted by bourgeoisâdemocratic tasks and national unification. (We are not trying to say that Marx was correct in holding this approach, merely that the approach makes sense when viewed in its time and place.)
Just as the Russian Revolution included a subterranean movement of the âmassesâ which conflicted with Bolshevism, so there is a subterranean movement in history which conflicts with all systems of authority. This movement has entered into our time under the name of âanarchism,â although it has never been encompassed by a single ideology or body of sacred texts. Anarchism is a libidinal movement of humanity against coercion in any form, reaching back in time to the very emergence of propertied society, class rule and the state. From this period onward, the oppressed have resisted all forms that seek to imprison the spontaneous development of social order. Anarchism has surged to the foreground of the social arena in periods of major transition from one historical era to another. The decline of the ancient and feudal world witnessed the upsurge of mass movements, in some cases wildly Dionysian in character, that demanded an end to all systems of authority, privilege and coercion.
The anarchic movements of the past failed largely because material scarcity, a function of the low level of technology, vitiated an organic harmonization of human interests. Any society that could promise little more materially than equality of poverty invariably engendered deep-seated tendencies to restore a new system of privilege. In the absence of a technology that could appreciably reduce the working day, the need to work vitiated social institutions based on self-management. The Girondins of the French Revolution shrewdly recognized that they could use the working day against revolutionary Paris. To exclude radical elements from the sections, they tried to enact legislation which would end all assembly meetings before 10 p.m., the hour when Parisian workers returned from their jobs. Indeed, it was not only the manipulative techniques and the treachery of the âvanguardâ organizations that brought the anarchic phases of past revolutions to an end, it was also the material limits of past eras. The âmassesâ were always compelled to return to a lifetime of toil and rarely were they free to establish organs of self-management that could last beyond the revolution.
Anarchists such as Bakunin and Kropotkin, however, were by no means wrong in criticizing Marx for his emphasis on centralism and his elitist notions of organization. Was centralism absolutely necessary for technological advances in the past? Was the nation-state indispensable to the expansion of commerce? Did the workersâ movement benefit by the emergence of highly centralized economic enterprises and the âindivisibleâ state? We tend to accept these tenets of Marxism too uncritically, largely because capitalism developed within a centralized political arena. The anarchists of the last century warned that Marxâs centralistic approach, insofar as it affected the events of the time, would so strengthen the bourgeoisie and the state apparatus that the overthrow of capitalism would be extremely difficult. The revolutionary party, by duplicating these centralistic, hierarchical features, would reproduce hierarchy and centralism in the postrevolutionary society.
Bakunin, Kropotkin and Malatesta were not so naive as to believe that anarchism could be established overnight. In imputing this notion to Bakunin, Marx and Engels willfully distorted the Russian anarchistâs views. Nor did the anarchists of the last century believe that the abolition of the state involved âlaying down armsâ immediately after the revolution, to use Marxâs obscurantist choice of terms, thoughtlessly repeated by Lenin in State and Revolution. Indeed, much that passes for âMarxismâ in State and Revolution is pure anarchismâfor example, the substitution of revolutionary militias for professional armed bodies and the substitution of organs of self-management for parliamentary bodies. What is authentically Marxist in Leninâs pamphlet is the demand for âstrict centralism,â the acceptance of a ânewâ bureaucracy, and the identification of soviets with a state.
The anarchists of the last century were deeply preoccupied with the question of achieving industrialization without crushing the revolutionary spirit of the âmassesâ and rearing new obstacles to emancipation. They feared that centralization would reinforce the ability of the bourgeoisie to resist the revolution and instill in the workers a sense of obedience. They tried to rescue all those precapitalist communal forms (such as the Russian **mir** and the Spanish **pueblo**) which might provide a springboard to a free society, not only in a structural sense but also a spiritual one. Hence they emphasized the need for decentralization even under capitalism. In contrast to the Marxian parties, their organizations gave considerable attention to what they called âIntegral educationââthe development of the whole manâto counteract the debasing and banalizing influence of bourgeois society. The anarchists tried to live by the values of the future to the extent that this was possible under capitalism. They believed in direct action to foster the initiative of the âmasses,â to preserve the spirit of revolt, to encourage spontaneity. They tried to develop organizations based on mutual aid and brotherhood, in which control would be exercised from below upward, not downward from above.
We must pause here to examine the nature of anarchist organizational forms in some detail, if only because the subject has been obscured by an appalling amount of rubbish. Anarchists, or at least anarcho-communists, accept the need for organization.[56] It should be as absurd to have to repeat this point as to argue over whether Marx accepted the need for social revolution.
The real question at issue here is not organization versus non-organization, but rather what **kind** of organization the anarcho-communists try to establish. What the different kinds of anarcho-communist organizations have in common is organic developments from below, not bodies engineered into existence from above. They are social movements, combining a creative revolutionary lifestyle with a creative revolutionary theory, not political parties whose mode of life is indistinguishable from the surrounding bourgeois environment and whose ideology is reduced to rigid âtried and tested programs.â As much as is humanly possible, they try to reflect the liberated society they seek to achieve, not slavishly duplicate the prevailing system of hierarchy, class and authority. They are built around intimate groups of brothers and sistersâaffinity groupsâwhose ability to act in common is based on initiative, on convictions freely arrived at, and on a deep personal involvement, not around a bureaucratic apparatus fleshed out by a docile membership and manipulated from above by a handful of all-knowing leaders.
The anarcho-communists do not deny the need for coordination between groups, for discipline, for meticulous planning, and for unity in action. But they believe that coordination, discipline, planning, and unity in action must be achieved **voluntarily,** by means of a self-discipline nourished by conviction and understanding, not by coercion and a mindless, unquestioning obedience to orders from above. They seek to achieve the effectiveness imputed to centralism by means of voluntarism and insight, not by establishing a hierarchical, centralized structure. Depending upon needs or circumstances, affinity groups can achieve this effectiveness through assemblies, action committees, and local, regional or national conferences. But they vigorously oppose the establishment of an organizational structure that becomes an end in itself, of committees that linger on after their practical tasks have been completed, of a âleadershipâ that reduces the ârevolutionaryâ to a mindless robot.
These conclusions are not the result of flighty âindividualistâ impulses; quite to the contrary, they emerge from an exacting study of past revolutions, of the impact centralized parties have had on the revolutionary process, and of the nature of social change in an era of potential material abundance. Anarcho-communists **seek to preserve and extend the anarchic phase that opens all the great social revolutions.** Even more than Marxists, they recognize that revolutions are produced by deep historical processes. No central committee âmakesâ a social revolution; at best it can stage a **coup dâĂ©tat**, replacing one hierarchy by anotherâor worse, arrest a revolutionary process if it exercises any widespread influence. A central committee is an organ for acquiring power, for **recreating** power, for gathering to itself what the âmassesâ have achieved by their own revolutionary efforts. One must be blind to all that has happened over the past two centuries not to recognize these essential facts.
In the past, Marxists could make an intelligible (although invalid) claim for the need for a centralized party, because the anarchic phase of the revolution was nullified by material scarcity. Economically, the âmassesâ were always compelled to return to a daily life of toil. The revolution closed at ten oâclock, quite aside from the reactionary intentions of the Girondins of 1793; it was arrested by the low level of technology. Today even this excuse has been removed by the development of a post-scarcity technology, notably in the U.S. and Western Europe. A point has now been reached where the âmassesâ can begin, almost overnight, to expand drastically the ârealm of freedomâ in the Marxian senseâto acquire the leisure time needed to achieve the highest degree of self-management.
What the MayâJune events in France demonstrated was not the need for a Bolshevik-type party but the need for greater consciousness among the âmasses.â Paris demonstrated that an organization is needed to propagate ideas systematicallyâand not ideas alone, but ideas which promote the concept of self-management. What the French âmassesâ lacked was not a central committee or a Lenin to âorganizeâ or âcommandâ them, but the conviction that they could have operated the factories instead of merely occupying them. It is noteworthy that not a single Bolshevik-type party in France raised the demand of self management. The demand was raised only by the anarchists and the Situationists.
There is a need for a revolutionary organizationâbut its function must always be kept clearly in mind. Its first task is propaganda, to âpatiently explain,â as Lenin put it. In a revolutionary situation, the revolutionary organization presents the most advanced demands: it is prepared at every turn of events to formulateâin the most concrete fashionâthe immediate task that should be performed to advance the revolutionary process. It provides the boldest elements in action and in the decision-making organs of the revolution.
In what way, then, do anarcho-communist groups differ from the Bolshevik type of party? Certainly not on such issues as the need for organization, planning, coordination, propaganda in all its forms or the need for a social program. Fundamentally, they differ from the Bolshevik type of party in their belief that genuine revolutionaries must function **within the framework of the forms created by the revolution**, not within the forms created by the party. What this means is that their commitment is to the revolutionary organs of self-management, not to the revolutionary âorganizationâ; to the social forms, not the political forms. Anarcho-communists seek to persuade the factory committees, assemblies or soviets to make themselves into **genuine organs of popular self-management**, not to dominate them, manipulate them, or hitch them to an all-knowing political party. Anarcho-communists do not seek to rear a state structure over these popular revolutionary organs but, on the contrary, to dissolve all the organizational forms developed in the prerevolutionary period (including their own) into these genuine revolutionary organs.
These differences are decisive. Despite their rhetoric and slogans, the Russian Bolsheviks never believed in the soviets; they regarded them as instruments of the Bolshevik Party, an attitude which the French Trotskyists faithfully duplicated in their relations with the Sorbonne studentsâ assembly, the French Maoists with the French labor unions, and the Old Left groups with SDS. By 1921, the soviets were virtually dead, and all decisions were made by the Bolshevik Central Committee and Political Bureau. Not only do anarcho-communists seek to prevent Marxist parties from repeating this; they also wish to prevent their own organization from playing a similar role. Accordingly, they try to prevent bureaucracy, hierarchy and elites from emerging in their midst. No less important, they attempt to remake themselves; to root out from their own personalities those authoritarian traits and elitist propensities that are assimilated in hierarchical society almost from birth. The concern of the anarchist movement with lifestyle is not merely a preoccupation with its own integrity, but with the integrity of the revolution itself.[57]
In the midst of all the confusing ideological crosscurrents of our time, one question must always remain in the foreground: what the hell are we trying to make a revolution for? Are we trying to make a revolution to recreate hierarchy, dangling a shadowy dream of future freedom before the eyes of humanity? Is it to promote further technological advance, to create an even greater abundance of goods than exists today? It is to âget evenâ with the bourgeoisie? Is it to bring PL to power? Or the Communist Party? Or the Socialist Workers Party? Is it to emancipate abstractions such as âThe Proletariat,â âThe People,â âHistory,â âSocietyâ?
Or is it finally to dissolve hierarchy, class rule and coercionâ**to make it possible for each individual to gain control of his everyday life?** Is it to make each moment as marvelous as it could be and the life span of each individual an utterly fulfilling experience? If the true purpose of revolution is to bring the neanderthal men of PL to power, it is not worth making. We need hardly argue the inane questions of whether individual development can be severed from social and communal development; obviously the two go together. The basis for a whole human being is a rounded society; the basis for a free human being is a free society.
These issues aside, we are still faced with the question that Marx raised in 1850: when will we begin to take our poetry from the future instead of the past? The dead must be permitted to bury the dead. Marxism is dead because it was rooted in an era of material scarcity, limited in its possibilities by material want. The most important social message of Marxism is that freedom has material preconditionsâwe must survive in order to live. With the development of a technology that could not have been conceived by the wildest science fiction of Marxâs day, the possibility of a post-scarcity society now lies before us. All the institutions of propertied societyâclass rule, hierarchy, the patriarchal family, bureaucracy, the city, the stateâhave been exhausted. Today, decentralization is not only desirable as a means of restoring the human scale, it is necessary to recreate a viable ecology, to preserve life on this planet from destructive pollutants and soil erosion, to preserve a breathable atmosphere and the balance of nature. The promotion of spontaneity is necessary if the social revolution is to place each individual in control of his everyday life.
The old forms of struggle do not totally disappear with the decomposition of class society, but they are being transcended by the issues of a classless society. There can be no social revolution without winning the workers, hence they must have our active solidarity in every struggle they wage against exploitation. We fight against social crimes wherever they appearâand industrial exploitation is a profound social crime. But so are racism, the denial of the right to self-determination, imperialism and poverty profound social crimesâand for that matter so are pollution, rampant urbanization, the malignant socialization of the young, and sexual repression. As for the problem of winning the working class to the revolution, we must bear in mind that a precondition for the existence of the bourgeoisie is the development of the proletariat. Capitalism as a social system presupposes the existence of both classes and is perpetuated by the development of both classes. We begin to undermine the premises of class rule to the degree that we foster the declassifying of the non-bourgeois classes, at least institutionally, psychologically and culturally.
For the first time in history, the anarchic phase that opened all the great revolutions of the past can be preserved as a permanent condition by the advanced technology of our time. The anarchic institutions of that phaseâthe assemblies, the factory committees, the action committeesâcan be stabilized as the elements of a liberated society, as the elements of a new system of self-management. Will we build a movement that can defend them? Can we create an organization of affinity groups that is capable of dissolving into these revolutionary institutions? Or will we build a hierarchical, centralized, bureaucratic party that will try to dominate them, supplant them, and finally destroy them?
Listen, Marxist: The organization we try to build is the kind of society our revolution will create. Either we will shed the pastâin ourselves as well as in our groupsâor there will simply be no future to win.
New York
May 1969
[47] On this score, the Old Left projects its own neanderthal image on the American worker. Actually this image more closely approximates the character of the union bureaucrat or the Stalinist commissar.
[48] The worker, in this sense, begins to approximate the socially transitional human types who have provided history with its most revolutionary elements. Generally, the âproletariatâ has been most revolutionary in transitional periods, when it was least âproletarianizedâ psychically by the industrial system. The great focuses of the classical workersâ revolutions were Petrograd and Barcelona, where the workers had been directly uprooted from a peasant background, and Paris, where they were still anchored in crafts or came directly from a craft background. These workers had the greatest difficulty in acclimating themselves to industrial domination and became a continual source of social and revolutionary unrest. By contrast, the stable hereditary working class tended to be surprisingly non-revolutionary. Even in the case of the German workers who were cited by Marx and Engels as models for the European proletariat, the majority did not support the Spartacists of 1919. They return large majorities of official Social Democrats to the Congress of Workersâ Councils, and to the Reichstag in later years, and rallied consistently behind the Social Democratic Party right up to 1933.
[49] This revolutionary lifestyle may develop in the factories as well as on the streets, in schools as well as in crash pads, in the suburbs as well as on the Bay AreaâEast Side axis. Its essence is defiance, and a personal âpropaganda of the deedâ that erodes all the mores, institutions and shibboleths of domination. As society begins to approach the threshold of the revolutionary period, the factories, schools and neighborhoods become the actual arena of revolutionary âplayââa âplayâ that has a very serious core. Strikes become a chronic condition and are called for their own sake to break the veneer of routine, to defy the society on an almost hourly basis, to shatter the mood of bourgeois normality. This new mood of the workers, students and neighborhood people is a vital precursor to the actual moment of revolutionary transformation. Its most conscious expression is the demand for âself-managementâ; the worker refuses to be a âmanagedâ being, a class being. This process was most evident in Spain, on the eve of the 1936 revolution, when workers in almost every city and town called strikes âfor the hell of itââto express their independence, their sense of awakening, their break with the social order and with bourgeois conditions of life. It was also an essential feature of the 1968 general strike in France.
[50] A fact which Trotsky never understood. He never followed through the consequences of his own concept of âcombined developmentâ to its logical conclusions. He saw (quite correctly) that czarist Russia, the latecomer in the European bourgeois development, necessarily acquired the most advanced industrial and class forms instead of recapitulating the entire bourgeois development from its beginnings. He neglected to consider that Russia, torn by tremendous internal upheaval, might even run ahead of the capitalist development elsewhere in Europe. Hypnotized by the formula ânationalized property equals socialism,â he failed to recognize that monopoly capitalism itself tends to amalgamate with the state by its own inner dialectic. The Bolsheviks, having cleared away the traditional forms of bourgeois social organization (which still act as a rein on the state capitalist development in Europe and America), inadvertently prepared the ground for a âpureâ state capitalist development in which the state finally becomes the ruling class. Lacking support from a technologically advanced Europe, the Russian Revolution became an internal counterrevolution; Soviet Russia became a form of state capitalism that does not âbenefit the whole people.â Leninâs analogy between âsocialismâ and state capitalism became a terrifying reality under Stalin. Despite its humanistic core, Marxism failed to comprehend how much its concept of âsocialismâ approximates a later stage of capitalism itselfâthe return to mercantile forms on a higher industrial level. The failure to understand this development led to devastating theoretical confusion in the contemporary revolutionary movement, as witness the splits among the Trotskyists over this question.
[51] The March 22nd Movement functioned as a catalytic agent in the events, not as a leadership. It did not command; it instigated, leaving a free play to the events. This free play, which allowed the students to push ahead on their own momentum, was indispensable to the dialectic of the uprising, for without it there would have been no barricades on May 10, which in turn triggered off the general strike of the workers.
[52] See âThe Forms of Freedomâ.
[53] With a sublime arrogance that is attributable partly to ignorance, a number of Marxist groups were to dub virtually all of the above forms of self-management as âsoviets.â The attempt to bring all of these different forms under a single rubric is not only misleading but willfully obscurantist. The actual soviets were the least democratic of the revolutionary forms and the Bolsheviks shrewdly used them to transfer the power to their own party. The soviets were not based on face-to-face democracy, like the Parisian sections or the student assemblies of 1968. Nor were they based on economic self-management, like the Spanish anarchist factory committees. The soviets actually formed a workersâ parliament, hierarchically organized, which drew its representation from factories and later from military units and peasant villages.
[54] V. I. Lenin, âThe Immediate Tasks of the Soviet Government,â in **Selected Works**, vol. 7 (International Publishers; New York, 1943), p. 342. In this harsh article, published in April 1918, Lenin completely abandoned the liberatarian perspective he had advanced the year before in **State and Revolution**. The main themes of the article are the needs for âdiscipline,â for authoritarian control over the factories, and for the institution of the Taylor system (a system Lenin had denounced before the revolution as enslaving men to the machine). The article was written during a comparatively peaceful period of Bolshevik rule some two months after the signing of the Brest-Litovsk Treaty and a month before the revolt of the Czech Legion in the Uralsâthe revolt that started the civil war on a wide scale and opened the period of direct Allied intervention in Russia. Finally, the article was written nearly a year before the defeat of the German revolution. It would be difficult to account for the âImmediate Tasksâ merely in terms of the Russian civil war and the failure of the European revolution.
[55] In interpreting this elemental movement of the Russian workers and peasants as a series of âWhite Guard conspiracies,â âacts of kulak resistance,â and âplots of international capital,â the Bolsheviks reached an incredible theoretical low and deceived no one but themselves. A spiritual erosion developed within the party that paved the way for the politics of the secret police, for character assassination, and finally for the Moscow trials and the annihilation of the Old Bolshevik cadre. One sees the return of this odious mentality in PL articles like âMarcuse: Cop-out or Cop?ââthe theme of which is to establish Marcuse as an agent of the CIA. (See **Progressive Labor**, February 1969.) The article has a caption under a photograph of demonstrating Parisians which reads: âMarcuse got to Paris too late to stop the May action.â Opponents of the PLP are invariably described by this rag as âredbaitersâ and as âanti-worker.â If the American left does not repudiate this police approach and character assassination it will pay bitterly in the years to come.
[56] The term âanarchistâ is a generic word like the term âsocialist,â and there are probably as many different kinds of anarchists as there are socialists. In both cases, the spectrum ranges from individuals whose views derive from an extension of liberalism (the âindividualist anarchists,â the social-democrats) to revolutionary communists (the anarcho-communists, the revolutionary Marxists, Leninists and Trotskyists).
[57] It is this goal, we may add, that motivates anarchist dadaism, the anrchist flipout that produces the creases of consternation on the wooden faces of PLP types. The anarchist flipout attempts to shatter the internal values inherited from hierarchical society, to explode the rigidities instilled by the bourgeois socialization process. In short, it is an attempt to break down the superego that exercises such a paralyzing effect upon spontaneity, imagination and sensibility and to restore a sense of desire, possibility and the marvelousâof revolution as a liberating, joyous festival.
The term âaffinity groupâ is the English translation of the Spanish **grupo de afinidad**, which was the name of an organizational form devised in pre-Franco days as the basis of the redoubtable FederaciĂłn Anarquista IbĂ©rica, the Iberian Anarchist Federation. (The FAI consisted of the most idealistic militants in the CNT, the immense anarcho-syndicalist labor union.) A slavish imitation of the FAIâs forms of organization and methods would be neither possible nor desirable. The Spanish anarchists of the thirties were faced with entirely different social problems from those which confront American anarchists today. The affinity group form, however, has features that apply to any social situation, and these have often been intuitively adopted by American radicals, who call the resulting organizations collectives,â âcommunesâ or âfamilies.â
The affinity group could easily be regarded as a new type of extended family, in which kinship ties are replaced by deeply empathetic human relationshipsârelationships nourished by common revolutionary ideas and practice. Long before the word âtribeâ gained popularity in the American counterculture, the Spanish anarchists called their congresses **asambleas de las tribus**âassemblies of the tribes. Each affinity group is deliberately kept small to allow for the greatest degree of intimacy between those who compose it. Autonomous, communal and directly democratic, the group combines revolutionary theory with revolutionary lifestyle in its everyday behavior. It creates a free space in which revolutionaries can remake themselves individually, and also as social beings.
Affinity groups are intended to function as catalysts within the popular movement, not as âvanguardsâ; they provide initiative and consciousness, not a âgeneral staffâ and a source of âcommand.â The groups proliferate on a molecular level and they have their own âBrownian movement.â Whether they link together or separate is determined by living situations, not by bureaucratic fiat from a distant center. Under conditions of political repression, affinity groups are highly resistant to police infiltration. Owing to the intimacy of the relationships between the participants, the groups are often difficult to penetrate and, even if penetration occurs, there is no centralized apparatus to provide the infiltrator with an overview of the movement as a whole. Even under such demanding conditions, affinity groups can still retain contact with each other through their periodicals and literature.
During periods of heightened activity, on the other hand, nothing prevents affinity groups from working together closely on any scale required by a living situation. They can easily federate by means of local, regional or national assemblies to formulate common policies and they can create temporary action committees (like those of the French students and workers in 1968) to coordinate specific tasks. Affinity groups, however, are always rooted in the popular movement. Their loyalties belong to the social forms created by the revolutionary people, not to an impersonal bureaucracy. As a result of their autonomy and localism, the groups can retain a sensitive appreciation of new possibilities. Intensely experimental and variegated in lifestyles, they act as a stimulus on each other as well as on the popular movement. Each group tries to acquire the resources needed to function largely on its own. Each group seeks a rounded body of knowledge and experience in order to overcome the social and psychological limitations imposed by bourgeois society on individual development. Each group, as a nucleus of consciousness and experience, tries to advance the spontaneous revolutionary movement of the people to a point where the group can finally disappear into the organic social forms created by the revolution.
<em>Robert B. Carson, in an article published in the April 1970 issue of </em>Monthly Review<em>, writes that the âmajor thrustâ of âListen, Marxist!â is to âdestroy a class-based analysis of society and revolutionary activity.â This criticism has been made by many Marxists who read the article.</em>[58]
[58] This is an edited summary of several discussions on âListen, Marxist!,â most of which occurred at my anarcho-communism class at Alternate U, New Yorkâs liberation school. I have selected the most representative and recurrent questions raised by readers of the pamphlet.
Carsonâs accusation is quite absurd. I seriously doubt if he did more than skim the article. Carson goes on to say that my approach is âahistoricalâ and that I try to promote a âcrude kind of individualistic anarchismââthis despite the fact that a large portion of the article attempts to draw important historical lessons from earlier revolutions and despite the fact that the article is unequivocally committed to anarcho-communism.
The most interesting thing about Carsonâs criticism is what it reveals about the theoretical level of many Marxists. Apparently Carson regards a **futuristic** approach as âahistorical.â He also seems to regard my belief that freedom exists only when each individual controls his daily life as âa crude kind of individualistic anarchism.â Here we get to the nub of the problem. Futurism and individual freedom are indeed the âmain thrustâ of the pamphlet. Carsonâs reply confirms **precisely** what the pamphlet set out to prove about Marxism today, namely that Marxism (I do not speak of Marx here) is **not** futuristic and that its perspectives are oriented not toward concrete, existential freedom, but toward an abstract freedomâfreedom for âSociety,â for the âProletariat,â for **categories** rather than for people. Carsonâs first charge, I might emphasize, should be leveled not only at me but at Marxâat his futurism in the **Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon**.
As to the charge that I am opposed to a âclass-based analysis of society and revolutionary activity,â need I say that a âclass analysisâ permeates the pamphlet? Is it conceivable that I could have terms like âcapitalistâ and âbourgeoisâ without working with a âclass-based analysisâ? Originally I thought there could have been no doubt about the matter. I have since changed the expression âclass analysisâ in the text to âclass line,â and perhaps I had better explain the difference this change is meant to convey.
What Carson is **really** saying is that I do not have a **Marxist** âclass analysisââa âclass analysisâ in which the industrial proletariat is driven to revolution by destitution and immiseration. Carson apparently assumes that Marxâs traditional âclass **line**â exhausts all there is to say about the class struggle. And in this respect, he assumes far too much. One need only turn to Bakunin, for example, to find a class analysis that was quite different from Marxâsâand more relevant today. Bakunin believed that the industrial proletariat by no means constitutes the most revolutionary class in society. He never received the credit due him for predicting the **embourgeoisement** of the industrial working class with the development of capitalist industry. In Bakuninâs view, the most revolutionary class was not the industrial proletariatââa class always increasing in numbers, and disciplined, united, organized by the very mechanisms of capitalist production itselfâ (Marx)âbut the uprooted peasantry and urban **dĂ©classĂ©s**, the rural and urban lumpen elements Marx so heartily despised. We need go no further than the urban centers of Americaânot to speak of the rice paddies of Asiaâto find how accurate Bakunin was by comparison with Marx.
As it turned out, the development of capitalist industry not only âdisciplined,â âunitedâ and âorganizedâ the working class but, **by these very measures**, denatured the proletariat for generations. By contrast, the transitional and lumpenized classes of society today (such as blacks, dropout youth, people like students, intellectuals and artists who are not rooted in the factory system, and young workers whose allegiance to the work ethic has been shaken by cultural factors) are the most radical elements in the world today.
A âclass analysisâ does not necessarily begin and end with Marxâs nineteenth-century version, a version I regard as grossly inaccurate. The class struggle, moreover, does not begin and end at the point of production. It may emerge from the poverty of the unemployed and unemployables, many of whom have never done a dayâs work in industry; it may emerge from a new sense of possibility that slowly pervades societyâthe tension between âwhat isâ and âwhat could beââwhich percolates through virtually all traditional classes; it may emerge from the cultural and physical decomposition of the traditional class structure on which the social stability of capitalism was based. Finally, every class struggle is not necessarily revolutionary. The class struggle between the original Roman **proletarius** and **patricius** was decidedly reactionary and eventually ended, as Marx observed in the opening lines of the **Communist Manifesto**, âin the common ruin of the contending classes.â{37}
Today, not only poverty but also a relative degree of affluence is causing revolutionary unrestâa factor Marx never anticipated. Capitalism, having started out by proletarianizing the urban **dĂ©classĂ©s**, is now ending its life-cycle by creating new urban **dĂ©classĂ©s**, including âshiftlessâ young industrial workers who no longer take the jobs, the factory discipline or the work ethic seriously. This stratum of **dĂ©classĂ©s** rests on a new economic baseâa post-scarcity technology, automation, a relative degree of material abundanceâand it prefigures culturally the classless society the Marxists so devoutly envision as humanityâs future. One would have thought that this remarkable dialectic, this ânegation of the negation,â would have stirred a flicker of understanding in the heavy thinkers of the Marxist movement.
<em>It would be difficult to conceive of a revolution in any industrially advanced capitalist country without the support of the industrial proletariat</em>.
Of course. And âListen, Marxist!â makes no claim that a social revolution is possible without the participation of the industrial proletariat. The article, in fact, tries to show how the proletariat can be won to the revolutionary movement by stressing issues that concern the quality of life and work. I agree, of course, with the libertarian Marxists and anarcho-syndicalists, who raise the slogan âworkersâ management of production.â I wonder, however, if this slogan goes far enough now. My suspicion is that the workers, when they get into revolutionary motion, will demand even more than control of the factories. I think they will demand the elimination of toil, or, what amounts to the same thing, freedom from work. Certainly a dropout outlook is growing among kids from working-class familiesâhigh school kids who are being influenced by the youth culture.
Although many other factors may contribute to the situation, it remains true that the workers will develop revolutionary views to the degree that they shed their traditional working-class traits. Young workers, I think, will increasingly demand leisure and the abolition of alienated labor. The young Marx, I might add, was not indifferent to the development of unconventional values in the proletariat. In **The Holy Family**, he cites with obvious favor a Parisian working-class girl in Eugene Sueâs **The Wandering Jew** who gives of her love and loyalty spontaneously, disdaining marriage and bourgeois conventions. He notes, âshe constitutes a really human contrast to the hypocritical, narrow-hearted, self-seeking wife of the bourgeois, to the whole circle of the bourgeoisie, that is, to the official circle.â{38} The working class, in the young Marxâs view, is the negation of capitalism not only in that it suffers total alienation, abasement and dehumanization, but also in that it affirms life forces and human values. Unfortunately, observations of this kind tend to fade away as Marxâs socialism becomes increasingly âobjectivistâ and âscientificâ (the admirers of Marxâs famousâbut untranslated and little-readâ**Grundrisse** notwithstanding). The later Marx begins to prize the bourgeois traits of the workerâthe workerâs âdiscipline,â âpracticality,â and ârealismââas the characteristics necessary for a revolutionary class.
The approach which Marx followed in **The Holy Family** was, I think, the correct one. Trapped by the notion that the working class, **qua** class, implied the liquidation of class society, Marx failed to see that this class was the alter ego of the bourgeoisie. Only a new cultural movement could rework the outlook of the proletariatâand deproletarianize it. Ironically, the Parisian working-class girls of Marxâs youth were not industrial workers, but rather people of transitional classes who straddled small- and large-scale production. They were largely lumpenized elements, like the *sans-culottes* of the French Revolution.
<em>If the analysis in</em> â<em>Listen, Marxist!</em>â <em>is</em> â<em>class-based</em>,â <em>what is the nature of the class struggle</em>?
The class struggle does not center around material exploitation alone but also around spiritual exploitation. In addition, entirely new issues emerge: coercive attitudes, the quality of work, ecology (or, stated in more general terms, psychological and environmental oppression). Moreover, the alienated and oppressed sectors of society are now the **majority of** the people, not a single class defined by its relationship to the means of production; the more radical as well as more liberatory sensibilities appear in the younger, not in the more âmature,â age groups. Terms like âclassesâ and âclass struggle,â conceived of almost entirely as economic categories and relations, are too one-sided to express the **universalization** of the struggle. Use these limited expressions if you like (the target is still a ruling class and a class society), but this terminology, with its traditional connotations, does not reflect the sweep and the multi-dimensional nature of the struggle. Words like âclass struggleâ fail to encompass the cultural and spiritual revolt that is taking place along with the economic struggle.
â**Listen, Marxist!**â **speaks a great deal about the potentialities of a post-scarcity society**, **but what of the actualities**? **There is still a great deal of poverty and hunger in the U.S. Inflation is a growing problem**, **not to speak of unemployment**, **bad housing**, **racial discrimination**, **work speed-ups**, **trade union bureaucracy**, **and the danger of fascism**, **imperialism and war**.
âListen, Marxist!â was written to deal with the simplifications of social problems (the economic and Third World-oriented âeither/orâ notions) that were developing in the âNew Left.â The post-scarcity viewpoint advanced in the pamphlet was not designed to replace one simplification (class struggle) by another (utopia). Yes, these economic, racial and bureaucratic actualities exist for millions of people in the U.S. and abroad. Any revolutionary movement that fails to deal energetically and militantly with them will be as distorted as a movement that deals with them, singly or severally, to the exclusion of all others. My writings on post-scarcity possibilities, ecology, utopia, the youth culture and alienation are intended to help fill a major gap in radical theory and praxis, not to create another gap.
The really important problem we face is how the actualities of the present scarcity society are related toâand conditioned byâthe potentialities for a future post-scarcity society. So far as this really dialectical problem is concerned, the heavy thinkers of the âleftâ show themselves to be incredibly light-minded and narrowly empirical. In the industrialized Western world, scarcity has to be enforced, so great is the productive potential of technology. Today economic planning has one basic purpose: to confine a highly advanced technology within a commodity framework. Many of the social problems which were endured almost passively a generation ago are now regarded as intolerable because the tension between âwhat isâ and âwhat could beâ has reached a point where âwhat isâ seems utterly irrational. This tension adds an explosive character to many actualities that evoked only a flicker of protest a quarter of a century ago. Moreover, the tension between âwhat isâ and âwhat could beâ conditions all the traditional economic and social issues that have occupied radical movements for generations. We can no longer deal with these issues adequately unless we view them in the light of the economic, social and cultural possibilities of post-scarcity.
Let me present a concrete example. Assume there is a struggle by welfare mothers to increase their allotments. In the past, the mothers were organized by liberal groups or Stalinists; petitions were drawn up, demonstrations were organized, and **perhaps** a welfare center or two was occupied. Almost invariably, one of the groups or parties trotted out a âreform candidateâ who promised that, if elected, he would fight âunflinchinglyâ for higher welfare expenditures. The entire struggle was contained within the organizational forms and institutions of the system: formal meetings of the mothers (with the patronizing âorganizersâ pulling the strings), formal modes of actions (petitions, demonstrations, elections for public office), and maybe a modest amount of direct action. The issue pretty much came to an end with a compromise on allotment increases and perhaps a lingering formal organization to oversee (and later sell out) future struggles around welfare issues.
Here actuality triumphed completely over potentiality. At best, a few mothers might be âradicalized,â which meant that they joined (or were shamelessly used by) organizations such as the Communist Party to promote their political influence. For the rest, most of the welfare mothers returned to the shabbiness of their daily lives and to varying degrees of passivity as human beings. Nothing was really changed for those who did not ego trip as âleaders,â âpoliticalsâ and âorganizers.â
To revolutionaries with a âpost-scarcity consciousnessâ (to use Todd Gitlinâs phrase), this kind of situation would be intolerable. Without losing sight of the concrete issues that initially motivated the struggle, revolutionaries would try to catalyze an order of relationships between the mothers entirely different from relationships the usual organizational format imposes. They would try to foster a deep sense of community, a rounded human relationship that would transform the very subjectivity of the people involved. Groups would be small, in order to achieve the full participation of everyone involved. Personal relationships would be intimate, not merely issue-oriented. People would get to **know** each other, to **confront** each other; they would **explore** each other with a view toward achieving the most complete, unalienated relationships. Women would discuss sexism as well as their welfare allotments, child-rearing as well as harassment by landlords, their dreams and hopes as human beings as well as the cost of living.
From this intimacy there would grow, hopefully, a supportive system of kinship, mutual aid, sympathy and solidarity in daily life. The women might collaborate to establish a rotating system of baby sitters and child-care attendants, the cooperative buying of good food at greatly reduced prices, the common cooking and partaking of meals, the mutual learning of survival skills and new social ideas, the fostering of creative talents, and many other shared experiences. Every aspect of life that could be explored and changed would be one part of the new kinds of relationships. This âextended familyââbased on explored affinities and collective activitiesâwould replace relationships mediated by âorganizers,â âchairmen,â an âexecutive committee,â **Robertâs Rules of Order**, elites, and political manipulators.
The struggle for increased allotments would expand beyond the welfare system to the schools, the hospitals, the police, the physical, cultural, aesthetic and recreational resources of the neighborhood, the stores, the houses, the doctors and lawyers in the area, and so onâinto the very ecology of the district.
What I have said on this issue could be applied to every issueâunemployment, bad housing, racism, work conditionsâin which an insidious assimilation of bourgeois modes of functioning is masked as ârealismâ and âactuality.â The new order of relationships that could be developed from a welfare struggle is Utopian only in the sense that actuality is informed and conditioned by post-scarcity consciousness. The future penetrates the present; it recasts the way people âorganizeâ and the goals for which they strive.
<em>Perhaps a post-scarcity perspective is possible in the U.S. and Europe</em>, <em>but it is hard to see how a post-scarcity approach has any relevance for the Third World</em>, <em>where technological development is grossly inadequate to meet the most elementary needs of the people</em>. <em>It would seem that the libertarian revolution and the non-coercive</em>, <em>unmediated social forms that are possible for the U.S. and Europe would have to be supplanted by the rigorous planning of highly centralized</em>, <em>coercive institutions in Asia</em>, <em>Africa and Latin America</em>. <em>Carl Oglesby has even argued that to help these continents catch up with the U.S.</em>, <em>it will be necessary for Americans to work ten or twelve hours daily to produce the goods needed</em>.
I think we must dispel the confusion that exists about the Third World. This confusion, due partly to the superficiality of knowledge about the Third World, has done enormous harm to radical movements in the First World. âThird Worldâ ideology in the U.S., by promoting a mindless imitation of movements in Asia and Latin America, leads to a bypassing of the social tasks in the First World. The result is that American radicals have often eased the tasks of American imperialism by creating an alien movement that does not speak to issues at home. The âMovementâ (whatever **that** is) is isolated and the American people are fair game for every tendency, reactionary as well as liberal, that speaks to their problems.
I think we should begin with some essentials. The Third World is **not** engaged in a âsocialist revolution.â One must be grossly ignorant of Marxismâthe favored ideology of the Third World fetishistsâin order to overlook the **real** nature of the struggle in Asia, Africa and Latin America. These areas are still taking up the tasks that capitalism resolved for the U.S. and Europe more than a century agoânational unification, national independence and industrial development. The Third World takes up these tasks in an era when state capitalism is becoming predominant in the U.S. and Europe, with the result that its own social forces have a highly statified character. Socialism and advanced forms of state capitalism are not easy to distinguish from each other, especially if oneâs conception of âsocialismâ is highly schematic. Drape hierarchy with a red flag, submerge the crudest system of primitive accumulation and forced collectivization in rhetoric about the interests of âthe Peopleâ or âthe âProletariat,â cover up hierarchy, elitism and a police state with huge portraits of Marx, Engels and Lenin, print little âRed Booksâ that invite the most authoritarian adulation and preach the most inane banalities in the name of âdialecticsâ and âsocialismââand any gullible liberal who is becoming disenchanted with his ideology, yet is totally unconscious of the bourgeois conditioning he has acquired from the patriarchal family and authoritarian school, can suddenly become a flaming ârevolutionaryâ socialist.
The whole process is disgustingâall the more so because it stands at odds with every aspect of reality. One is tempted to scream: âLook, motherfucker! Help the Third World by fighting capitalism at home! Donât cop out by hiding under Hoâs and Maoâs skirts when your real job is to overthrow domestic capitalism by dealing with the real possibilities of an American revolution! Develop a revolutionary project at home because every revolutionary project here is **necessarily** internationalist and anti-imperialist, no matter how much its goals and language are limited to the American condition.â Oglesbyâs hostility to a post-scarcity approach on the grounds that we will have to work ten or twelve hours daily to meet the Third Worldâs needs is simply preposterous. To assume that the working day will be increased by an American revolution is to invite its defeat before the first blow is struck. If, in some miraculous way, Oglesbyâs ârevolutionâ were to be victorious, surely he doesnât think that the American people would accept an increased working day without a strong, centralized state apparatus cracking its whip over the entire population. In which case, one wonders what kind of âaidâ such a regime would âofferâ to the Third World?
Like many of the âThird Worldâ zealots, Oglesby seems to have an incomplete knowledge of Americaâs industrial capacity and the real needs of the Third World. Roughly seventy percent of the American labor force does absolutely no productive work that could be translated into terms of real output or the maintenance of a rational system of distribution. Their work is largely limited to servicing the commodity economyâfiling, billing, bookkeeping for a profit and loss statement, sales promotion, advertising, retailing, finance, the stock market, government work, military work, police work, etc., **ad nauseam**. Roughly the same percentage of the goods produced is such pure garbage that people would voluntarily stop consuming it in a rational society. Working hours could be reduced enormously after a revolution without losing high productive output, provided that the available labor supply and raw materials were used rationally. The quality of the productive output, moreover, could be so improved that its durability and usefulness would more than cancel out any reduction in productive capacity.
On the other side, let us look more closely at the material needs of the Third World. As Westerners, âweâ tend to assume out of hand that âtheyâ want or need the same kind of technologies and commodities that capitalism produced in America and Europe. This crude assumption is bolstered by the fear consciously generated by imperialist ideology, that millions of black, brown, and yellow people are hungrily eyeing âourâ vast resources and standard of living. This ideology reminds us how lucky âweâ are to be Americans or Europeans, enjoying the blessings of âfree enterprise,â and how menacing âtheyâ are, festering in poverty, misery and the ills of overpopulation. Ironically, the âThird Worldâ zealots share this ideology in the sense that they, too, conceive of Asian, African and Latin American needs in Western termsâan approach that might be called the Nkrumah mentality of technological gigantism. Whatever is living and vital in the pre-capitalist society of the Third World is sacrificed to industrial **machismo**, oozing with the egomaniacal elitism of the newly converted male radical.
Perhaps no area of the world is more suitable for an eco-technology than the Third World.[59] Most of Asia, Africa and Latin America lie in the âsolar belt,â between latitudes 40 degrees north and south, where solar energy can be used with the greatest effectiveness for industrial and domestic purposes. New, small-scale technologies are more easily adapted for use in the underdeveloped areas than elsewhere. The small-scale gardening technologies, in fact, are indispensable for the productive use of the soil types that are prevalent in semi-tropical, tropical, and highland biomes. The peasantry in these areas have a long tradition of technological know-how in terracing and horticulture, for which small machines are already available or easily designable. Great strides have been made in developing an irrigation technology to provide year-round water resources for agriculture and industry. A unique combination could be made of machine and handcrafts, crafts in which these areas still excel. With advances in the standard of living and in education, the population of these areas could be expected to stabilize sufficiently to remove pressure on the land. What the Third World needs above all is a rational, sophisticated communications network to redistribute food and manufactures from areas of plentiful supply to those in need.
[59] The alternatives to a âWesternâ-type technology for the Third World and the resolution of the âpopulation problemâ in this area will be discussed in some detail in my forthcoming book, *The Ecology of Freedom*, to be published by Alfred A. Knopf and as a Vintage paperback.
A technology of this kind could be developed for the Third World fairly rapidly by American and European industry without placing undue strain on the resources of the West. The rational use of such a technology presupposes a sweeping social revolution in the Third World itselfâa revolution, I believe, that would almost immediately follow a social revolution in the U.S. With the removal of imperialismâs mailed fist, a new perspective could open for the Third World. The village would acquire a new sense of unity with the elimination of the local hierarchies appointed by the central governments which have so heavily parasitized the regions. An exchange economy would continue to exist in the Third World, although its base would probably be collectivist. In any case, the exploitation of labor and the domination of women by men would be eliminated, thus imposing severe restrictions on the use of income differentials for exploitative purposes.[60] The resources of the First World could be used to promote the most revolutionary social alternativesâa peopleâs movement as against an authoritarian one, decentralized, immediate relations as against centralized mediated institutions.
[60] More can be learned, I think, from the impact the Spanish anarchist movement had on the village economy than from Mao or Ho and the movements they spoke for. Unfortunately, very little information on this development is available in English. The spontaneous takeover and collectivization of the land by Spanish *pueblos* during the early weeks of Francoâs rebellion provides us with one of the most remarkable accounts of how the peasantry can respond to libertarian influence.
It would be difficult to say what kind of institutional structure would emerge from revolutionary changes in the Third World following a complete social revolution in the First World. Until now, the Third World has been obliged to fight imperialism largely on its own. Although there has been a great deal of international solidarity from millions of people in Europe and the U.S. for Third World struggles, there has been no real, disinterested material support from these key industrial areas. One wonders what will happen when a revolutionary United States and Europe begin to aid the Third World fully and disinterestedly, with nothing but the well being of the African, Asian and Latin American peoples at issue. I believe that the social development in the Third World will take a more benign and libertarian form than we suspect; and that surprisingly little coercion will be needed to deal with material scarcity in these areas.
In any case, there is no reason to fear that a quasi-statist development in the Third World would be more than temporary or that it would affect the world development. If the U.S. and Europe took a libertarian direction, their strategic industrial position in the world economy would, I think, favor a libertarian alternative for the world as a whole. Revolution is contagious, even when it occurs in a relatively small and economically insignificant country. I cannot imagine that Eastern Europe could withstand the effects of a libertarian revolution in Western Europe and the U.S. The revolution would almost certainly engulf the Soviet Union, where massive dissatisfaction exists, and finally the entire Asian continent. If one doubts the fulfillment of this possibility, let him consider the impact of the French Revolution on Europe at a time when the world economy was far less interdependent than it is today.
After the revolution the planet would be dealt with as a whole. The relocation of populations in areas of high density, the development of rational, humanistic birth control programs oriented toward improving the quality of life, and the modification of technology along ecological linesâall of these programs would be on the agenda of history. Aside from suggesting some basic guidelines drawn from ecology, I can do no more than speculate about how the resources and land areas of the world could be used to improve life in a post-revolutionary period. These programs will be solved in practice and by human communities that stand on a far higher level, culturally, psychologically and materially, than any community that exists today.
â**Listen, Marxist!**â **seems to be quite relevant as a critique of the vulgar MarxistsâProgressive Labor**, **the Trotskyists**, **and other** â**Old Left**â **movements**. **But what of the more sophisticated Marxistsâpeople such as Marcuse**, **Gorz and the admirers of Gramsci**? **Surely** â**Listen, Marxist!**â **imputes too much to the** â**Old Left**â **in taking it as the point of departure for a critique of Marxism**.
Marcuse is the most original of the thinkers who still call themselves Marxists, and I must confess that even on those points where I may have disagreements with him, I am stimulated by what he has to say.
With this exception, I would differ with the claim that âListen, Marxist!â is relevant only as a critique of the âOld Left.â The article is relevant to all types of Marxist ideology. Two things trouble me about Marxâs mature writings: their pseudo-objectivity and the obstacles they raise to Utopian thinking. The Marxian project, as it was formulated by Marx himself, deepened the early socialist tradition but also narrowed it, and in the long run this has produced a net setback rather than a net gain.
By Marxâs pseudo-objectivity I mean the astonishing extent to which Marx identified âscientific socialismâ with the scientism of the nineteenth century. Although there is a tendency today for the more sophisticated âneo-Marxistsâ to cast the Marxian project in terms of alienation, the project (as it developed in Marxâs hands) was above all an attempt to make socialism âscientific,â to provide it with the authority of a scientific critique. This led to an emphasis on âobjectivityâ that increasingly subverted the humanistic goals of socialism. Freedom and Eros (where the latter was taken up at all) were anchored so completely in the material preconditions for freedom that even the loss of freedom, if it promoted the material development, was viewed as an âadvanceâ of freedom. Marx, for example, welcomed state centralization as a step in the development of the productive forces without once considering how this process enhanced the capacity of the bourgeoisie to resist revolution. He disclaimed any moral evaluation of society and in his later years became increasingly captive to scientism and to mathematical criteria of truth.
The result of this development has been a major loss for the humanistic and imaginative elements of socialism. Marxism has damaged the left enormously by anchoring it in a pseudo-objectivity that is almost indistinguishable from the juridical mentality. Whenever I hear âNew Leftâ Marxists denounce a position as âobjectively counter-revolutionary,â âobjectively racist,â or âobjectively sexist,â my flesh crawls. The charge, flung randomly against all opponents, circumvents the need for an analytic or a dialectical critique. One simply traces âcounterrevolution,â âracismâ or âsexismâ to be the preconceived âobjective effects.â Marx rarely exhibited the crudity of the âOld Leftâ and âNew Leftâ in his use of this approach, but he used the approach often enoughâand often as a substitute for a multidimensional analysis of phenomena.
You must see how consequential this is. Freedom is divested of its autonomy, of its sovereignty over the human condition. It is turned into a means instead of an end. Whether freedom is desirable or not depends upon whether it furthers the âobjectiveâ development. Accordingly, any authoritarian organization, any system of repression, any manipulatory tactic can become acceptable, indeed admirable, if it favors the âbuilding of socialismâ or âresistance to imperialismââas though âsocialismâ or âanti-imperialismâ is meaningful when it is poisoned by manipulation, repression, and authoritarian forms of organization. Categories replace realities; abstract goals replace real goals; âHistoryâ replaces everyday life. The universal, which requires a complex, many-sided analysis to be grasped, is replaced by the particular; the total, by the one-sided.
No less serious is the rejection of Utopian thoughtâthe imaginative forays of Charles Fourier and William Morris. What Martin Buber called the âutopian element in socialismâ is rejected for a âhardheadedâ and âobjectiveâ treatment of âreality.â But, in fact, this approach shrivels reality by limiting oneâs purview of social experience and data. The hidden potential of a given reality is either subverted by an emphasis on the âobjectiveâ actualities or, at least, diminished by a one-sided treatment. The revolutionary becomes a captive to experience not as it exists dialectically, in **all** its actualities and potentialities, but as it is defined in advance by âscientific socialism.â Not surprisingly, the New Left, like the Old Left, has never grasped the revolutionary potential of the ecology issue, nor has it used ecology as a basis for understanding the problems of communist reconstruction and Utopia. At best the issue is given lip service, with some drivel about how âpollution is profitableâ; at worst it is denounced as spurious, diversionary and âobjectively counterrevolutionary.â Most of the sophisticated Marxists are as captive to these limiting features of Marxism as their New Left brethren. The difference is that they are simply more sophisticated.
<em>In contrast to most radical works</em>, â<em>Listen, Marxist!</em>â <em>continually speaks of</em> â<em>hierarchical society</em>â <em>instead of</em> â<em>class society</em>,â <em>of</em> â<em>domination</em>â <em>instead of</em>â<em>exploitation</em>.â <em>What significance do these differences in language have</em>?
A difference is definitely intended. Pre-Marxian socialism was, in many ways, much broader than the Marxian variety. Not only was it more utopian, it was also occupied more with the general than the particular. Varlet, the last of the great **enrages**, who survived the death of his comrade Jacques Roux and Robespierreâs purge of the left, concluded that government and revolution are utterly âincompatible.â What a splendid insight! In this one observation revolutionary consciousness expanded from a critique of a specific class society to a critique of hierarchical society as such. The pre-Marxian socialist and radical theorists began to occupy themselves with domination, not only exploitation; with hierarchy, not only class rule. With Fourier, consciousness advanced to the point where the goal of society was viewed as pleasure, not simply happiness.
You must see what an enormous gain this was. Exploitation, class rule and happiness are the **particular** within the more **generalized** concepts of domination, hierarchy and pleasure. It is theoreticallyâand, in great part, actuallyâpossible to eliminate exploitation and class rule or to achieve happiness, as these concepts are defined by Marxism, without achieving a life of pleasure or eliminating domination and hierarchy. Marx, by âscientificallyâ anchoring exploitation, classes, and happiness in the economic domain, actually provided the rationale for a theoretical regression from the original socialist values. Marxian economic solutions, such as nationalization of property, may even create the illusion that hierarchy has disappeared. One has only to study the torment of the Trotskyist movement over the nature of the Russian state to see how obfuscating Marxian theory can be.
This particularization of the general is precisely what Marxism achieved. As I noted in reply to the previous question, socialism was given greater theoretical depth by the acquisition of dialectical philosophy, but it was narrowed disastrously by Marxâs economic emphasis. Even Marxâs writings shrivel in content as the man âmatures.â They increasingly center on the âobjectiveâ economic elements of society, until Marx sinks into a grotesque fetishization of economic theory of the kind we find in volume two of **Capital**. With Marxâs death, an immense exegetical literature emerges on capitalist circulation, accumulation and ârealization theory.â Even Rosa Luxemburg was caught in this swamp, not to speak of the Keynesian Marxists who churn out their papers for the **American Economic Review** and **Science and Society**.
Marxism created a stupendous intellectual furniture that one must clear away to make contact with reality. The field abounds with âexpertsâ and heavies, with academics and authorities whose bullshit makes original, indeed dialectical, thought virtually impossible. Once we rescue the essentials, this theoretical garbage must be junked. It is vitally necessary that we return to the generalized terrain that pre-Marxian socialism established, and then go forward again.
The youth culture has already posed the âsocial questionâ in its richest and most meaningful termsââLife versus death.â I would say, with an eye towards the insights of Marxism, âLife versus survival.â In any case, we have to get away from the one-sided, repressive jargon of Marxism, which defines our perspective in a limiting manner. I am reminded of a fine passage from Paul Avrichâs recent book, **Kronstadt 1921**, in which the language of the revolutionary Kronstadt sailors is contrasted with that of the Bolsheviks. âRebel agitators,â Avrich notes, speaking of the sailors, âwrote and spoke (as an interviewer later noted) in a homespun language free of Marxist jargon and foreign-sounding expressions. Eschewing the word âproletariat,â they called, in true populist fashion, for a society in which all the âtoilersââpeasants, workers and the âtoiling intelligentsiaââwould play a dominant role. They were inclined to speak of a âsocialâ rather than a âsocialistâ revolution, viewing class conflict not in the narrow sense of industrial workers versus bourgeoisie, but in the traditional **narodnik** sense of the laboring masses as a whole pitted against all who throve on their misery and exploitation, including politicians and bureaucrats as well as landlords and capitalists. Western ideologiesâMarxism and liberalism alikeâhad little place in their mental outlook.â{39}
The point, of course, is not Western ideologies versus Russian, or âhomespunâ versus âforeign-soundingâ language. The real point is the **broader** concepts with which the âmassesâ worked almost intuitivelyâconcepts drawn from the experience of their own oppression. Note how the sailors had a broader view of the âlaboring massesâ and their âoppressorsâ than the Bolsheviks, a view that included the elitist Bolsheviks among the oppressors. Note well, too, how Marxist jargon made it possible for the Bolsheviks to exclude themselves as oppressors in flat denial of the real situation. For my part, I am delighted that the New Left in America has replaced the words âworkers and âproletariatâ by âpeople.â Indeed, it is significant that even professedly Marxian groups like the Panthers and Weathermen have been obliged to use a populist language, for this language reflects the changed reality and problems of our times.
To sum up: what I am talking about is a human condition reflected by the word âpower.â We must finally resolve the historic and everyday dichotomies: manâs power over woman, manâs power over man, and manâs power over nature. For inherent in the issue of powerâof dominationâare the contradictory, destructive effects of power: the corruption of life-giving sexuality, of a life-nourishing society, of a life-orienting ego, and of a life-sustaining ecology. The statement âpower corruptsâ is not a truism because it has never been fully understood. It may yet become understood because power now **destroys**. No amount of theoretical exegesis can place power in the service of history or of a revolutionary organization. The only act of power that is excusable any longer is that one actâ**popular** revolutionâthat will finally dissolve power as such by giving each individual power over his or her everyday life.
New York
August 1970
The 1968 MayâJune uprising was one of the most important events to occur in France since the Paris Commune of 1871. Not only did it shake the foundations of bourgeois society in France, it raised issues and posed solutions of unprecedented importance for modern industrial society. It deserves the closest study and the most thoroughgoing discussion by revolutionaries everywhere.
The MayâJune uprising occurred in an industrialized, consumption-oriented countryâless developed than the United States, but essentially in the same economic category. The uprising exploded the myth that the wealth and resources of modern industrial society can be used to absorb all revolutionary opposition. The MayâJune events showed that contradictions and antagonisms in capitalism are not eliminated by statification and advanced forms of industrialism, but changed in form and character.
The fact that the uprising took everyone by surprise, including the most sophisticated theoreticians in the Marxist, Situationist and anarchist movements, underscores the importance of the MayâJune events and raises the need to re-examine the sources of revolutionary unrest in modern society. The graffiti on the walls of ParisââPower to the Imagination,â âIt is forbidden to forbid,â âLife without dead times,â âNever workâârepresent a more probing analysis of these sources than all the theoretical tomes inherited from the past. The uprising revealed that we are at the end of an old era and well into the beginning of a new one. The motive forces of revolution today, at least in the industrialized world, are not simply scarcity and material need, but also **the quality of everyday life, the demand for the liberation of experience, the attempt to gain control over oneâs own destiny**. It matters little that the graffiti on the walls of Paris were initially scrawled by a small minority. From everything I have seen, it is clear that the graffiti (which now form the content of several books) have captured the imagination of many thousands in Paris. They have touched the revolutionary nerve of the city.
The revolt was a majority movement in the sense that it cut across nearly
all the class lines in France. It involved not only students and workers, but technicians, engineers and clerical people in nearly every stratum of the state, industrial and commercial bureaucracy. It swept in professionals and laborers, intellectuals and football players, television broadcasters and subway workers. It even touched the gendarmerie of Paris, and almost certainly affected the great mass of conscript soldiers in the French army.
The revolt was initiated primarily by the young. It was begun by university students, then it was taken up by young industrial workers, unemployed youth, and the âleather jacketsââthe so-called âdelinquent youthâ of the cities. Special emphasis must be given to high school students and adolescents, who often showed more courage and determination than the university students. But the revolt swept in older people as wellâblue and white-collar workers, technicians and professionals. Although it was catalyzed by conscious revolutionaries, especially by anarchist affinity groups whose existence no one had even faintly supposed, the flow, the movement of the uprising was spontaneous. No one had âsummoned it forthâ; no one had âorganizedâ it; no one succeeded in âcontrollingâ it.
A festive atmosphere prevailed throughout most of the MayâJune days, an awakening of solidarity, of mutual aid, indeed of a selfhood and self-expression that had not been seen in Paris since the Commune. People literally discovered themselves and their fellow human beings anew or remade themselves. In many industrial towns, workers clogged the squares, hung out red flags, read avidly and discussed every leaflet that fell into their hands. A fever for life gripped millions, a reawakening of senses that people never thought they possessed, a joy and elation they never thought they could feel. Tongues were loosened, ears and eyes acquired a new acuity. There was singing with new, and often ribald, verses added to old tunes. Many factory floors were turned into dance floors. The sexual inhibitions that had frozen the lives of so many young people in France were shattered in a matter of days. This was not a solemn revolt, a **coup dâĂ©tat** bureaucratically plotted and manipulated by a âvanguardâ party; it was witty, satirical, inventive and creativeâand therein lay its strength, its capacity for immense self-mobilization, its infectiousness.
Many people transcended the narrow limitations that had impeded their social vision. For thousands of students, the revolution destroyed the prissy, tight-assed sense of âstudenthoodââthat privileged, pompous state that is expressed in America by the âposition paperâ and by the stuffy
sociologese of the âanalyticalâ document. The individual workers who came to the action committees at Censier[61] ceased to be âworkersâ as such. They became revolutionaries. And it is precisely on the basis of this new identity that people whose lives had been spent in universities, factories and offices could meet freely, exchange experiences and engage in common actions without any self-consciousness about their social âoriginsâ or âbackground.â
The revolt had created the beginnings of its own classless, nonhierarchical society. Its primary task was to extend this qualitatively new realm to the country at largeâto every corner of French society. Its hope lay in the extension of self-management in all its formsâthe general assemblies and their administrative forms, the action committees, the factory strike committeesâto all areas of the economy, indeed to all areas of life itself. The most advanced consciousness of this task seems to have appeared not so much among the workers in the more traditional industries, where the Communist-controlled CGT exercises great power, as among those in newer, more technically advanced industries, such as electronics. (Let me emphasize that this is a tentative conclusion, drawn from a number of scattered but impressive episodes that were related to me by young militants in the student-worker action committees.)
[61] The new building of the Sorbonne Faculty of Letters.
Of paramount importance is the light that the MayâJune revolt cast on the problem of authority and hierarchy. In this respect it challenged not only the conscious processes of individuals, but also their most important unconscious, socially conditioned habits. (It does not have to be argued at any great length that the habits of authority and hierarchy are instilled in the individual at the very outset of life in the family milieu of infancy, in childhood educationâ at home and in school, in the organization of work, âleisureâ and everyday life. This shaping of the character structure of the individual by what seem like âarchetypalâ norms of obedience and command constitutes the very essence of what we call the âsocializationâ of the young.)
The mystique of bureaucratic âorganization,â of imposed, formalized hierarchies and structures, pervades the most radical movements in
nonrevolutionary periods. The remarkable susceptibility of the left to authoritarian and hierarchical impulses reveals the deep roots of the radical movement in the very society it professedly seeks to overthrow. In this respect, nearly every revolutionary organization is a potential source of counterrevolution. Only if the revolutionary organization is so âstructuredâ that its forms reflect the direct, decentralized forms of freedom initiated by the revolution, only if the revolutionary organization fosters in the revolutionist the lifestyles and personalities of freedom, can this potential for counterrevolution be diminished. Only then is it possible for the revolutionary movement to dissolve into the revolution, to disappear into its new, directly democratic social forms like surgical thread into a healing wound.
The act of revolution rips apart all the tendons that hold authority and hierarchy together in the established order. The direct entry of the people into the social arena is the very **essence** of revolution. Revolution is the most advanced form of direct action. By the same token, direct action in ânormalâ times is the indispensable preparation for revolutionary action. In both cases, there is a substitution of social action from below for political action within the established, hierarchical framework. In both cases, there are molecular changes of âmasses,â classes and social strata into revolutionary individuals. This condition must become, permanent if the revolution is to be successful if it is not to be transformed into a counterrevolution masked by revolutionary ideology. Every formula, every organization, every âtried-and-testedâ program, must give way to the demands of the revolution. There is no theory, program or party that has greater significance than the revolution itself.
Among the most serious obstacles to the MayâJune uprising were not only de Gaulle and the police, but also the hardened organizations of the leftâthe Communist Party that suffocated initiative in many factories and the Leninist and Trotskyist groups that created such a bad odor in the general assembly of the Sorbonne. I speak here not of the many individuals who romantically identified themselves with Che, Mao, Lenin or Trotsky (often with all four at once), but of those who surrendered their entire identity, initiative and volition to tightly disciplined, hierarchical organizations. However well-intentioned these people may have been, it became their task to âdisciplineâ the revolt, more precisely, to de-revolutionize it by imbuing it with the habits of obedience and authority that their
organizations have assimilated from the established order. These habits, fostered by participation in highly structured organizations organizations modeled, in fact, on the very society the ârevolutionariesâ profess to opposeâled to parliamentary maneuvering, secret caucusing, and attempts to âcontrolâ the revolutionary forms of freedom created by the revolution. They produced in the Sorbonne assembly a poisonous vapor of manipulation. Many students to whom I spoke were absolutely convinced that these groups were prepared to destroy the Sorbonne assembly if they could not âcontrolâ it. The groups were concerned not with the vitality of the revolutionary forms but with the growth of their own organizations. Having created authentic forms of freedom in which everyone could freely express his viewpoint, the assembly would have been perfectly justified to have banned all bureaucratically organized groups from its midst.
It remains to the lasting credit of the March 22nd Movement that it merged into the revolutionary assemblies and virtually disappeared as an organization, except in name. In its own assemblies, March 22nd arrived at all its decisions by the âsense of the assembly,â and it permitted all tendencies within its midst to freely test their views in practice. Such tolerance did not impair its âeffectivenessâ; this anarchic movement, by the common agreement of nearly all observers, did more to catalyze the revolt than any other student group. What distinguishes March 22nd and groups such as the anarchists and Situationists from all others is that they worked not for the âseizure of powerâ but for its dissolution.
The French events of May and June reveal, vividly and dramatically, the remarkable dialectic of revolution. The everyday misery of a society is highlighted by the possibilities for the realization of desire and freedom. The greater these possibilities, the more intolerable the everyday misery. For this reason, it matters little that French society has become more affluent in recent years than at any time in its history. Affluence in its highly distorted bourgeois form merely indicates that the material conditions for freedom have developed, that the technical possibilities for a new, liberated life are overripe.
It is plain, now, that these possibilities have haunted French society for a long time, even if unperceived by most people. The insensate
consumption of goods graphs, in its own warped way, the tension between the shabby reality of French society and the liberatory possibilities of a revolution today, just as a sedating diet and extravagant obesity reveal the tension in an individual. A time is finally reached when the diet of goods becomes tasteless, when the social obesity becomes intolerable. The breaking point is unpredictable. In the case of France, it was the barricades of May 10, a day which shook the conscience of the entire country and posed a question to the workers: âIf the students, âthose children of the bourgeoisieâ, can do it, why canât we?â It is clear that a molecular process was going on in France, completely invisible to the most conscious revolutionaries, a process that the barricades precipitated into revolutionary action. After May 10, the tension between the mediocrity of everyday life and the possibilities of a liberatory society exploded into the most massive general strike in history.
The scope of the strike shows that nearly all strata of French society were profoundly disaffected and that the revolution was anchored not in a particular class but in everyone who felt dispossessed, denied, and cheated of life. The revolutionary thrust came from a stratum which, more than any other, should have âaccommodatedâ itself to the existing orderâthe young. It was the young who had been nourished on the pap of Gaullist âcivilization,â who had not experienced the contrasts between the relatively attractive features of the prewar civilization and the shabbiness of the new one. But the pap didnât work. Its power to co-opt and absorb, in fact, is weaker than was suspected by most critics of French society. The pap-fed society could not withstand the drive for life, particularly in the young.
No less important; the lives of young people in France, as in America, had never been burdened by the Depression years and the quest for material security that shaped the lives of their elders. The prevailing reality of French life was taken by the young people for what it isâshabby, ugly, egotistical, hypocritical and spiritually annihilating. This single factâthe revolt of the young is the most damning evidence of the systemâs inability to prevail on its own terms.
The tremendous internal decay of Gaullist society, a decay long ante dating the revolt itself, took forms that do not fit into any of the traditional, economically oriented formulas of ârevolution.â Much had been written about âconsumerismâ in French society to the effect that it was a polluting form of social stabilization. The fact that objects,** commodities,**
were replacing the traditional subjective loyalties fostered by the church, the school, the mass media and the family, should have been seen as evidence of greater social decomposition than was suspected. The fact that traditional class consciousness was declining in the working class should have been evidence that conditions were maturing for a majority **social** revolution, not a minority **class** revolution. The fact that âlumpenâ values in dress, music, art and lifestyle were spreading among French youth should have been evidence that the potential for âdisorderâ and direct action was ripening behind the facade of conventional political protest.
By a remarkable twist of dialectic irony, a process of âdebourgeoisificationâ was going on precisely when France had attained unprecendented heights of material affluence. Whatever may have been the personal popularity of de Gaulle, a process of deinstitutionalization was going on precisely when state capitalism seemed more entrenched in the social structure than at any time in the recent past. The tension between drab reality and the liberatory possibilities was increasing precisely when French society seemed more quiescent than at any time since the 1920s. A process of alienation was going on precisely when it seemed that the verities of bourgeois society were more secure than at any time in the history of the republic.
The point is that the issues that make for social unrest had changed qualitatively. The problems of survival, scarcity and renunciation had changed into those of life, abundance and desire. The âFrench dream,â like the âAmerican dreamâ was eroding and becoming demystified. Bourgeois society had given all it could give on the only terms it was capable of âgivingâ anythingâa plethora of shabby material goods acquired by meaningless, deadening work. Experience itself (not âvanguard partiesâ and âtried-and-tested programsâ) became the mobilizing agent and source of creativity for the MayâJune uprising. And this is as it should be. Not only is it natural that an uprising **breaks out spontaneously**âa feature of all the great revolutions in historyâbut it is also natural that it **unfolds **spontaneously. This hardly means that revolutionary groups stand mute before the events. If they have ideas and suggestions, it is their responsibility to present them. But to use the social forms created by the revolution for manipulatory purposes, to operate secretly behind the back of the revolution, to distrust it and try to replace it by the âglorious party,â is wantonly criminal and unforgivable. Either the revolution
eventually absorbs **all** political organisms, or the political organisms become ends in themselvesâthe inevitable sources of bureaucracy, hierarchy and human enslavement.
To diminish the spontaneity of a revolution, to break the continuum between **self-**mobilization and **self-**emancipation, to remove the **self** from the process in order to mediate it with political organizations and institutions borrowed from the past, is to vitiate the revolutionâs liberatory goals. If the revolution does not start from below, if it does not enlarge the âbaseâ of society until it becomes the society itself, then it is a mere** coup dâĂ©tat.** If it does not produce a society in which each individual controls his daily life, instead of daily life controlling each individual, then it is a counterrevolution. Social liberation can only occur if it is simultaneously self-liberationâif the massâ movement is a self-activity that involves the highest degree of individuation and self-awakening.
In the molecular movement below that prepares the condition for revolution, in the self-mobilization that carries the revolution forward, in the joyous atmosphere that consolidates the revolutionâin **all **of these successive steps, we have a **continuum **of individuation, a process in which power is dissolved, an expansion of personal experience and freedom almost aesthetically congruent with the possibilities of our time. To see this process and articulate it, to catalyze the process and pose the next practical tasks, to deal unequivocally with the ideological movements that seek to âcontrolâ the revolutionary processâthese, as the French events have shown, are the primary responsibilities of the revolutionary today.
Paris
July 1968
What Happened...
What Could Have Happened...
You ask how the MayâJune revolt could have developed into a successful social revolution.[62] I shall try to give you my own views as clearly as possible. My answer applies not only to France, but to any industrialized country in the world. For what happened in France could be regarded as a model of social revolution in any advanced bourgeois country today. It astonishes me that there is so little discussion about France in the United States. The MayâJune events are the first really clear illustration of how a revolution can unfold in an industrially developed country in the present historical period, and they should be studied with the greatest care.
[62] This is an excerpt from a letter written shortly after the MayâJune events.
The general strike, let me point out, occurred not only because of the wage grievances that were piling up in France, but alsoâand mainly, in my opinionâbecause the people were fed up. Intuitively, unconsciously, and often quite consciously, the strikers were disgusted with the whole system, and they showed it in countless ways. A cartoon published in France after the MayâJune events shows a CGT official addressing the strikers: âWhat do you want?â he shouts. âBetter pay? Shorter hours? Longer vacations?â Each time this Stalinist hack asks one of these questions, the strikers respond with silence. Finally, the CGT official cries out in anger; âTell me, damn it! I am your representative!â And the strikers answer with a huge cry. âWe want the revolution!â
To a very large extent, this response is accurate. The cartoon expressed a sentiment which was still very diffuse, of course, but was nevertheless quite real. That is why the cartoon was so popular in France when it came out. it expressed what many workers (especially young workers) felt in a vague wayâand perhaps not so vaguely.
The student barricades of May 10 precipitated the general strike, the largest general strike in history. The workers (mainly the young workers) said to themselves, âif the students can do it, so can we.â And out of the Sud-Aviation plant in Nantes, a city with the strongest anarcho-syndicalist tendencies in France, came the general strike. The strike swept into Paris and brought out almost everybody, not only industrial workers. Insurance
employees went out, as well as postal workers, department store clerks, professionals, teachers, scientific researchers. Yes, even the football players took over the building of their professional association and put out a banner that proclaimed, âFootball belongs to the people!â It was not only a workersâ strike; it was a **peopleâs** strike that cut across almost all class lines. You must understand this, for it is a very important fact about the possibilities of our time. At Nantes, peasants brought their tractors into the city to help the movement and longshoremen emptied the holds of the ships to feed the strikers. The most advanced demands, I should emphasize, were raised in the **newer** industriesâfor example, in the electronics plants. In one such plant, a firm composed largely of highly skilled technicians, the employees declared publicly, âWe have everything we want. We won large wage increases and longer vacations in negotiations we conducted last month [April]. We are now striking for only one demand: workersâ control of industryâand not only in our plant, but for all the plants in France.â
What an astonishing development! And this demand was precisely the key to the whole situation. The workers had occupied the plants. The economy was in their hands. Whether this sweeping movement would become a complete social revolution depended upon one thingâwould the workers not only occupy the plants, but **work** them? This was the barrier that had to be surmounted. Had the workers begun to work the plants under workersâ management, the revolt would have advanced into a full-scale social revolution.
Let us now try to imagine what would have happened if the workers had actually surmounted this barrier. Each plant would elect its own factory committee from among its own workers to **administer** the plant. (Here the workers could have counted on a great deal of cooperation from the technical staff, most of whom would have gone over to the revolution.) I emphasize âadministerâ because policy would be made by the workers in the plant, by an assembly of the workers on the factory floor. The factory committee would merely execute and coordinate these policies. Here you have true revolutionary democracy, and in the arena of production, where the means of life are made.
Let us go further (and what I shall describe was absolutely possible). The factory committees of all the local plants could now link together to form an area administrative council, whose function would be to deal with
whatever supply problems exist. Each member of this council would be rigorously controlled by the workers in the plant from which he or she came and would be fully accountable to the factory assembly. The tasks of the council, I must emphasize, would be entirely administrative; many of its technical functions could be taken over by computers, and membership on the council would be rotated as often as possible.
Together with these industrial forms of organization, there would also be neighborhood organizationsâassemblies corresponding to the French revolutionary sections of 1793, as well as action committees to perform the administrative tasks of the neighborhood assemblies. They too would form an administrative council, which would work with the factory committee council, the two meeting together periodically to deal with common problems. One of the most important functions of the neighborhood assembliesâthe new âsectionsââwould be to recycle employment from nonproductive areas of the economy (sales, insurance, advertising, âgovernment,â and other socially useless areas) into productive areas. The goal here would be to shorten the work week as rapidly as possible. In this way, everyone would benefit almost immediately from the new arrangement of societyâboth the industrial worker and, say, the ex-salesman whom the worker trains in the factory. All would get the means of life for a fraction of the time they devote to work under bourgeois conditions. The revolution would thus undercut the position of many counterrevolutionary elements who, from time immemorial, have argued that the old conditions of life were better than the new.
What is essential here is not the fine detail of this structure, which could be worked out in practice, but the dissolution of power into the assemblies, both factory and neighborhood. In the past, very little attention has been given to the role and importance of unmediated relations and popular assemblies. So strongly was the notion of ârepresentationâ fixed in the thinking of revolutionary groups and the people that the assemblies, where they existed, arose almost accidentally. Apart from the Greek ecclesia, they emerged, in most cases, not as a result of conscious design, but rather of fortuitous circumstances. Ordinarily, the various councils and committees in earlier revolutions were given enormous powers in formulating policy; the demarcation between administrative work and policy decisions was murky at best, or simply nonexistent. As a result, the committees and councils became social agencies exercising enormous
political powers **over** society; they became a nascent state apparatus that rapidly acquired control over society as a whole. This can now be avoided, partly by making all committees and councils **directly** answerable to assemblies, partly by using the new technology to shorten the work week radically, thereby freeing the whole people for active participation in the management of society.
At first the various committees, councils and assemblies would use the existing mechanism of supply and distribution to meet the material needs of society. Steel would come to Paris the way it always has: by means of the same ordering methods and the same railways and trucks, probably operated by the same engineers and truck drivers. The postal, cable and telephone networks that were used before the revolution to request materials would be used again after the revolution. Finally, finished goods would be distributed by the same warehouses and retail outlets except that the cash registers would be removed. The principal functions of the new factory committee councils and neighborhood councils would be to deal with any bottlenecks and obstructive practices that might emerge and to propose changes that would lead to a more rational use of existing resources.
Capitalism has already established the physical mechanism of circulationâof distribution and transportation that is needed to maintain society without any state apparatus. This physical mechanism of circulation can be vastly improved upon, to be sure, but it would still be as workable the day after the revolution as it was the day before the revolution. It needs no police, jails, armies or courts to maintain it. The state is superimposed on this technical system of distribution and actually serves to distort it by maintaining an artificial system of scarcity. (This, today, is the real meaning of the âsanctity of property.â)
I must emphasize again that since we are concerned with human needs, not with profit, a vast number of people who are needed to operate the profit system could be freed from their idiotic work. So could many people who are occupied with working for the state. These people could join their brothers and sisters in productive jobs, thus drastically shortening everyoneâs work week. In this new system, the producers and the community could jointly manage the economy from below, coordinating their administrative operations through factory committees, councils of factory committee representatives, and neighborhood action committeesâall directly accountable to the plant and neighborhood
assemblies, all recallable for their actions. At this point, society takes direct control of its affairs. The state, its bureaucracy, its armies, police, judges and jails, can disappear.
You may object that the old system of production and distribution is still centralized structurally and based on a national division of labor. Agreed; you are perfectly correct. But does its **control** have to be centralized? As long as policy is made from below and everyone who executes that policy is controlled locally, administration is socially decentralized although the means of production are structurally fairly centralized as yet. A computer used to coordinate the operations of a vast plant, for example, is an instrument for structural centralization. However, if the people who program and operate the computer are completely answerable to the workers in the plant, their operations are socially decentralized.
To pass from a narrow analogy to the broader problems of administration, let us suppose that a board of highly qualified technicians is established to propose changes in the steel industry. This board, we may suppose, advances proposals to rationalize the industry by closing some plants and expanding the operations of others in different parts of the country. Is this a âcentralizedâ body or not? The answer is both yes and no. Yes, only in the sense that the board is dealing with problems that concern the country as a whole; no, because it can make no decisions that **must** be executed for the country as a whole. The boardâs plan must be examined by all the workers in the plants that are to be closed down, and those whose operations are to be expanded. The plan itself may be accepted, modified, or simply rejected. The board has no power to enforce âdecisionsâ; it merely offers recommendations. Additionally, its personnel are controlled by the plant in which they work and the locality in which they live.
Similar boards, I may add, could be established to plan the physical decentralization of the societyâboards composed of ecologists as well as technologists. They could develop plans for entirely new patterns of land use in different areas of the country. Like the technicians who are dealing with the existing steel industry, they would have no decision-making powers. The adoption, modification or rejection of their plans would rest entirely with the communities involved.
But Iâve already traveled too much into the âfuture.â Let us return to the MayâJune events of 1968. What of de Gaulle, the generals, the army,
the police? Here we come to another crucial problem that faced the MayâJune revolt. Had the armament workers not merely occupied the arms factories but worked them to arm the revolutionary people, had the railroad workers transported these arms to the revolutionary people in the cities, towns and villages, had the action committees organized armed militiasâthen the situation in France would have changed drastically. An armed people, organized into militias by its own action committees (and there are plenty of reservists among the young people to train them), would have confronted the state. Most of the militants I spoke to do not believe that the bulk of the army, composed overwhelmingly of conscripts, would have fired on the people. If the people were armed, every street could have been turned into a bastion and every factory into a fortress. Whether de Gaulleâs most reliable troops would have marched upon them in these circumstances is very questionable. Alas, the situation was never brought to that point-the point that every revolution has to risk.
Let me emphasize again that all I have sketched out for you was perfectly possible. I write here of a reality that started the French revolution aries in the face. All that was necessary was for the workers to work the factories and turn their strike committees into factory committees. This decisive step was not taken; hence the people were not armed and the bourgeois system of property relations was not shattered. The Stalinists shrewdly deflected the revolutionary movement into political lines by calling for a Communist-Socialist coalition cabinet. Thus the struggle was channeled into an election campaign on strictly bourgeois grounds. For these reasons and others, the revolt receded and in so doing produced a âbacklashâ from the mass of people who were watching and waiting. These people might have been won to the revolution had it succeeded. They seemed to be standing by and saying; âLetâs see what you can do.â Once the revolt failed, however, they voted for de Gaulle. De Gaulle at least had reality; the revolution, on the other hand, had been vaporized by failure.
How did the Maoists and Trotskyists, the âvanguardâ Bolshevik parties and groupuscules, behave? The Maoists opposed every demand for workersâ control. (Some of them, after the revolt receded, began to revise their views and are now called âanarcho-Maoistsâ!) Chairman Mao had opined that workersâ control is anarcho-syndicalismâhence a âpetty bourgeois deviation.â The job of the workers, cried the Maoists, was to âseize state power.â Thus, in the name of âBolshevik realism,â the only basis for a social
revolutionâthe occupation of the factoriesâwas subordinated to abstract political slogans that had no reality in the living situation. Let me give you an example: marching to the Billancourt plant of Renault, the Maoists carried a big banner which read âVive the CGT!ââthis at a time when the most revolutionary workers were carrying on a bitter struggle with the CGT and were trying to shed the bureaucratic apparatus with which the labor federation had saddled the workers. What the Maoists were saying was âput us in control of the CGT.â But who the hell wanted **them**?
The Trotskyists? Which onesâthe FER? The JCR? The other two or three splits? The FER played an overtly **counterrevolutionary** role at almost every decisive point, condemning all the street actions that led to the general strike as âadventuristic.â The students had their hands full with them in the street-fighting before the Sorbonne, where they tried to get the students to go home, and in the barricade fighting on the night of May 10, when they denounced the students as âromantics.â Instead of joining the students, they held a âmass meeting at the MutualitĂ©. All of this did not prevent the FER from politicking like mad in the corridors and assembly meetings of the Sorbonneâafter the students had succeeded. As to the JCR, more often than not they dragged their feet and created a great deal of confusion in the Sorbonne assembly with their politicking. Toward the end of the MayâJune events, they held back the movement and accommodated themselves to the non-Stalinist electoral left.
What was âmissingâ in the MayâJune events? Certainly not âvanguardâ Bolshevik parties. The revolt was afflicted with these parties like lice. What was needed in France was an awareness among the workers that the factories had to be **worked,** not merely occupied or struck. Or to put it differently, what the revolt lacked was a movement that could develop this **consciousness** in the workers. Such a movement would have had to be anarchic, similar either to the March 22nd Movement or the action committees that took over Censier and tried to help the workers, not dominate them. Had these movements developed before the revolt, or had the revolt lasted long enough for them to develop an impressive propaganda and action force, events might have taken a different turn. Anyway, the Communists combined with de Gaulle to deflect the revolt and finally destroy it.
In my opinion, these are the real lessons of the MayâJune events. In reading what I have written, it becomes very clear why Marxist-Leninists
in America devote little discussion to the MayâJune events in France: the events, even the memory of them, challenge all their tenets, programs, and strategies.
Paris
July 1968
Most of the articles that have been written thus far about the Marat/Sade play have been drivel and the tritest remarks have come from its author, Peter Weiss. A good idea can slip from the hands of its creator and follow its own dialectic. This kept happening with Balzac, so there is no reason why it shouldnât happen with Weiss.
The play is mainly a dialogue between Desire and Needâa dialogue set up under conditions where history froze them into antipodes and opposed them violently to each other in the Great Revolution of 1789. In those days, Desire clashed with Need: the one aristocratic, the other plebeian; the one as the pleasures of the individual, the other as the agony of the masses; the one as the satisfaction of the particular, the other as the want of the general; the one as private reaction, the other as social revolution. In our day, Marat and de Sade have not been rediscovered; they have been reinterpreted. The dialogue goes on, but now on a different level of possibility and toward a final resolution of the problem. It is an old dialogue, but in a new context.
In Weissâs play, the context is an asylum. The dialogue can only be pursued by madmen among madmen. Sane men would have resolved the issues raised by the dialogue years ago. They would have resolved them in practice. But we talk about them endlessly and we refract them through a thousand mystical prisms. Why? Because we are insane; we have been turned into pathological cases. Weiss, on this score, is only just; he places the dialogue where it belongs, in an asylum policed by guards, nuns and an administrator. We are insane not only because of what we have done, but also because of what we havenât done. We âtolerateâ too much. We tremble and cower with âtolerance.â
How, then, are we to act? How, following the credo imputed to Marat, are we to pull ourselves up by the hair, turn ourselves inside out, and see the world with fresh eyes? âWeiss refuses to tell us,â says Peter Brook in an introduction to the script, and then Brook trails off into talk about facing contradictions. But this doesnât carry any conviction. The dialogue, launched by its literary creator and by its stage director, has its own inner movement, its own dialectic. At Cordayâs third visit, de Sade lasciviously displays her before Marat and asks: â...whatâs the point of a revolution without general copulation?â De Sadeâs words are taken up by the mimes and then by all the âlunaticsâ in the play. Even Brook cannot leave the answer alone. The ending of the play, equivocal in the script version, turns into a riotous bacchanal in the movie version. The âlunaticsâ overpower the guards, nuns, visitors and administrator; they grab all the women on the stage and everybody fucks like mad. The answer begins to emerge almost instinctively: the revolution that seeks to annul Need must enthrone Desire for everybody. Desire must become Need!
Needâthe need to survive, to secure the bare means of existenceâcould never have produced a public credo of Desire. It could have produced a religious credo of renunciation, to be sure, or a republican credo of virtue, but not a public credo of sensuousness and sensibility. The enthronement of Desire as Need, of the pleasure principle as the reality principle, is nourished as a **public **issue by the productivity of modern industry and by the possibility of a society without toil. Even the widely touted recoil of the flower children from the verities of consumption, drudgery and suburbia has its origin in the irrationalities of modern affluence. Without the affluence, no recoil. To state the matter bluntly, the revolutionary growth of modern technology has brought into question every historical precept that promoted renunciation, denial and toil. It vitiates every concept of Desire as a privileged, aristocratic domain of life.
This technology creates a new dimension of Desire, one that completely transcends the notions of de Sade, or for that matter of the French symbolists, from whom we still derive our credo of sensibility. De Sadeâs unique one, Baudelaireâs dandy, Rimbaudâs visionary, each is an isolated ego, a rare individual who takes flight from the mediocrity and unreality of bourgeois life into hallucinated reveries. In spite of its high, anti-bourgeois spirit of negation, this ego remains distinctly privileged. Baudelaire, one of the most unequivocal of the symbolist writers, expresses its aristocratic nature with bluntness in his notion of Dandyism. The Dandy, the man of true sensibility, he tells us, enjoys leisure and is untroubled by Need. This leisure is defined by the opposition of the Dandy to the crowd, of the particular to the general. It is anchored in the very social conditions that breed Marats and the **enragĂ©s** of 1793âthe world of Need.
Dandyism, to be sure, asserts itself against the existing elites, but not against elitism; against the prevailing privileges, but not against privilege. âDandyism flourishes especially in periods of transition,â Baudelaire notes with acuity, âwhen democracy is not yet all-powerful and the aristocracy is just beginning to totter and decay. Amidst the turmoil of these times, a small group of men,** dĂ©classĂ©s,** at loose ends, fed up-but all of them rich in determinationâwill conceive the idea of founding a new sort of aristocracy, stronger than the old, for it shall be based on only the most precious, the most indestructible factors, on those heaven-sent gifts that neither money nor ambition can confer.â The truth, however, is that its gifts are not heaven-sent. This aesthetic elite floats on the surface of the social war, a richly ornamented debris that presupposes, objectively, the very aristocracy and bourgeoisie it repudiates in spirit.
What, then, of the revolutionary movementâthe movement that seeks to reach below the surface of the social war into its very depths? For the most part it dispenses almost completely with a concrete credo of sensuousness. Marxism, the dominant project within the revolutionary movement, offers itself to the proletariat as a harsh, sobering doctrine, oriented toward the labor process, political activity, and the conquest of state power. To sever all the ties between poetry and revolution, it calls its socialism scientific and casts its goals in the hard prose of economic theory. Where the French symbolists formed a concrete image of man, defined by the specifics of play, sexuality and sensuousness, the two great exiles in England formed an abstract image of man, defined by the universals of class, commodity and property. The whole personâconcrete **and** abstract, sensuous **and** rational, personal **and **socialânever finds adequate representation in either credo.[63] This is tragedy in the Hegelian sense that both sides are right. In retrospect, it is only fair to add that the social situation of their time was inadequate for the complete fulfillment of humanity. Ordinarily the social period admits neither of the liberated personality nor of the liberated society; its doors are closed to the free expression of sensuousness and to the unfettered exercise of reason.
[63] A sense of incompleteness haunts Western philosophy after Hegelâs death and explains much of the work of Kierkegaard, Schopenhauer, Stirner, Nietzsche, the surrealists and the contemporary existentialists. For the Marxians merely to dismiss this post Hegelian development as âbourgeois ideologyâ is to dismiss the problem itself.
But the doors are never solid. There are moments when they, and indeed the entire house, are shaken to the foundations by elemental events.
In such moments of crisis, when the senses of everyone are strained to extraordinary acuity by social emergencies, the doors break down and the people surge past the hanging portals, no longer as masses but as awakened personalities. These people cannot be crucified on theoretical formulas. They acquire their human reality in revolutionary action. The Paris Commune of 1871 represents precisely such a moment when neither aesthetic nor social theory adequately encompasses the over-all social situation. The Communards of the Belleville district in Paris, who fought the battles of the barricades and died by the tens of thousands under the guns of the Versaillese, refused to confine their insurrection to the private world described by symbolist poems or the public world described by Marxist economics. They demanded the eating and the moral, the filled belly and the heightened sensibility. The Commune floated on a sea of alcoholâfor weeks everyone in the Belleville district was magnificently drunk. Lacking the middle-class proprieties of their instructors, the Belleville Communards turned their insurrection into a festival of public joy, play and solidarity. Perhaps it was foredoomed that the prose of bourgeois society would eventually digest the songs of the Communeâif not in an orgy of slaughter, then in the day-to-day compromises and retreats required by work, material security and social administration. Faced with a bloody conflict and nearly certain defeat, the Communards flung life away with the abandon of individuals who, having tasted of experience in the open, can no longer return to the coffins of daily routine, drudgery and denial. They burned down half of Paris, fighting suicidally to the very last on the heights of their district.
In the Paris Commune of 1871, we have the expression not merely of social interest, but of social libido.[64] It is hard to believe that the repression following the fall of the Communeâthe mass shootings, the ruthless trials, the exile of thousands to penal coloniesâowed its savagery strictly to class vengeance. A review of the memoirs, newspapers and letters of the time shows that the bourgeois directed his vengeance against his own subterranean humanity. In the spontaneous outburst of social libido which we call the Paris Commune the bourgeois saw the breakdown of all the repressive mechanisms that maintain hierarchical society. He recoiled with the horror and ferocity of a man who suddenly comes face to face with his unconscious drives.
[64] Is it any different in other great revolutions? Can we resolve the anarchic, intoxicating phase that opens all the great revolutions of history merely into an expression of class interest and the opportunity to redistribute social wealth?
No one really learned from the Communards of the Belleville district, with the result that Desire and the revolutionary credo developed away from each other. In separating, both were divested of their human content. The credo of Desire evaporated into a misty subjectivism, far removed from all social concerns; the credo of revolution hardened into a dense objectivism, almost completely absorbed in the techniques of social manipulation. The need to round out the revolutionary credo with Desire, or Desire with the revolutionary credo, remains a pressing, perhaps the most pressing, problem of our times. Serious attempts to achieve this totality were made in the 1920s, when the surrealists and Wilhelm Reich tried to resynthesize Marxism and transcend it with a larger conception of the revolutionary project. Although this project did not succeed, it did not fail. All the issues were passed on to us, transformed by new dimensions of thought and by a new sense of immediacy produced by the technological advances of our time.
Ironically, the greatest single obstacle to fulfilling this project is the revolutionary credo itself. Leninism, and its various offshoots have refocused the revolutionistâs attention from social goals to political means, from utopia to strategy and tactics. Lacking any clear definition of its human goals, the revolutionary movement, at least in its currently organized forms, has assimilated the hierarchical institutions, puritanism, work ethic and general characterology of the very society it professes to oppose. The goals of Marxism are largely contained in the demand for the **seizure** of power rather than the **dissolution** of power; the former implies the existence of hierarchy and the power of an elite over society as a whole.
Almost equally important as an obstacle to the project envisioned by the surrealists and Reich is the emergence of a crude, undifferentiated subjectivism that casts the rediscovery of man exclusively in terms of self-discoveryâin the journey inward. What is basically wrong with this form of subjectivism is not its emphasis on the subject, on the concrete individual. Indeed, as Kierkegaard has emphasized, we have been overfed with the universals of science, philosophy and sociology. The error that vitiates this subjectivism is its operating principle that the self can be divorced completely from society, subjectivity from objectivity, consciousness from
action. Ironically, this inner, isolated self turns out to be one of the most fictitious of universals, one of the most treacherous abstractions, a metaphysical concept in which consciousness, far from expanding, contracts into banalities and trivia. Philosophically, its ultimate state is pure being, a purity of experience and inner repose that adds up to nothing.[65] Its ultimate state, in short, is the dissolution of Desire into contemplation.
[65] My concern with this philosophical aspect of subjectivism stems from the fact that it is advanced not only by a salad of Hindu Cagliostros but also by serious thinkers such as Norman 0. Brown.
The fact is, the self cannot be resolved into an inherent âit,â a cryptic âsoulâ covered and obscured by layers of reality. In this abstract form, the self remains an undifferentiated potentiality, a mere bundle of individual proclivities, until it interacts with the real world. Without dealing with the world it simply cannot be **created** in any human sense. Nietzsche reveals this feature of the Self when he declares â...your true nature lies not concealed deep in you, but immeasurably high above you, or at least what you call your self.â Valid introspection turns out to be the conscious appropriation of a self formed largely by the world, and thus a judgment of the world and of the actions needed to reconstitute it along new lines. This order of self-consciousness reaches its height during our time in revolutionary action. To revolt, to **live **revolt, is the complete reconstitution of the individual revolutionary, a change as far-reaching and as radical as the remaking of society. In the process of discarding accumulated experiences, of integrating and re-integrating new experience, a self grows out of the old. For this reason it is idiotic to predict the behavior of people after a revolution in terms of their behavior before it. They will not be the same people.
If it is true that valid introspection must culminate in action, in a reworking of the self by experience with the real world, this reworking achieves a sense of direction only insofar as it moves from the **existent** to the **possible,** from the âwhat isâ to the âwhat could be.â Precisely this dialectic is what we mean by psychic growth. Desire itself is the sensuous apprehension of possibility, a complete psychic synthesis achieved by a âyearning for...â Without the pain of this dialectic, without the struggle that yields the achievement of the possible, growth and Desire are divested of all differentiation and content. The very** issues** which provide a concept of the possible are never formulated. The real responsibility we face is to eliminate not the psychic pain of growth but rather the psychic suffering
of dehumanization, the torment that accompanies the frustrated and aborted life.
The goal of crude subjectivism is stasisâthe absence of pain, the achievement of undisturbed repose. This stasis yields an all-embracing placidity that dissolves anger into love, action into contemplation, willfulness into passivity. The absence of emotional differentiation means the end of real emotion. Confronted with the goal of insensate stasis, dialectical growth could justly demand any right to emotionâincluding the right to hateâto reclaim a real state of sensibility, including the ability to love selectively. The apostle of the undifferentiated type of sensibility (more precisely, sensation) is Marshall McLuhan, whose fantasies of integral communication consist entirely of kicks and highs. Technique, here, is degraded into ends, the message into the media.
The fact remains, nonetheless, that there can be no meaningful revolutionary credo that fails to include the subject in its point of departure. We have passed beyond a time when the real world can be discussed without taking up in depth the basic problems and needs of the psycheâa psyche that is neither strictly concrete nor strictly universal, but both newly integrated and transcended. The rediscovery of the concrete psyche is the most valid contribution of modern subjectivism and existentialist philosophy to the revolutionary credo, albeit the rediscovered psyche is partial and incomplete, and often tends to become abstracted. In an era of relative affluence, when material immiseration is not the exclusive source of social restiveness, the revolution tends to acquire intensely subjective and personal qualities. Revolutionary opposition centers increasingly around the disintegration of the quality of life, around the anti-life perspectives and methods of bourgeois society.
To put this matter differently, the revolutionist is created and nourished by the breakdown of all the great bourgeois universalsâproperty, class, hierarchy, free enterprise, the work ethic, patriarchalism, the nuclear family and so on, **ad nauseam.** From all of this wreckage, the self begins to achieve self-consciousness and Desire begins to recover its integrity. When the entire institutional fabric becomes unstable, when everyone lacks a sense of destiny, be it in job or social affiliations, the lumpen periphery of
society tends to become its center and the **déclassé**s begin to chart out the most advanced forms of social and personal consciousness. It is for this reason that any work of art can be meaningful today only if it is lumpenized.
The lumpenâs self is permeated by negativity, a reflection of the overall social negativity. Its consciousness is satyr-like and its mockery is acquired by its distance from the verities of bourgeois society. But this very mockery constitutes the selfâs transcendance of the repressive ideologies of toil and renunciation. The lumpenâs acts of disorder become the nuclei of a new order and his spontaneity implies the means by which it can be achieved.
Hegel understood this fact beautifully. In a brilliant review of Diderotâs **Rameauâs Nephew,** he writes: âThe mocking laughter at existence, at the confusion of the whole and at itself, is the disintegrated consciousness, aware of itself and expressing itself, and is at the same time the last audible echo of all this confusion... It is the self-disintegrating nature of all relations and their conscious disintegration... In this aspect of the return to self, the vanity of all things is the selfâs own vanity, or the self is itself vanity...but as the indignant consciousness it is aware of its own disintegration and by that knowledge has immediately transcended it... Every part of this world either gets its mind expressed here or is spoken of intellectually and declared for what it is. The honest consciousness (the role that Diderot allots to himself in the dialogue[66]) takes each element for a permanent entity and does not realize in its uneducated thoughtfulness that it is doing just the opposite. But the disintegrated consciousness is the consciousness of reversal and indeed of absolute reversal; its dominating element is the concept, which draws together the thoughts that to the honest consciousness lie so wide apart; hence the brilliance of its own language. Thus the contents of the mindâs speech about itself consist in the reversal of all conceptions and realities; the universal deception of oneself and others and the shamelessness of declaring this conception is therefore the greatest truth... To the quiet consciousness which in its honest way goes on singing the melody of the True and the Good in even tones, i.e., on one note, this speech appears as âa farrago of wisdom and madness...?â{40}
[66] Diderot takes the role of the virtuous man, the petty bourgeois, engaged in a dialogue with Rameauâs nephew, a Figaro-like scamp and pimp.
Hegelâs analysis, written more than a century and a half ago, anticipates and contains all the elements of the âabsolute refusalâ advanced so poignantly at the present time. Today, the spirit of negativity must extend
to all areas of life if it is to have any content; it must demand a complete frankness which, in Maurice Blanchotâs words, âno longer tolerates complicity.â To lessen this spirit of negativity is to place the very integrity of the self in the balance. The established order tends to be totalistic: it stakes out its sovereignty not only over surface facets of the self but also over its innermost recesses. It seeks complicity not only in appearances but also from the most guarded depths of the human spirit. It tries to mobilize the very dream-life of the individualâas witness the proliferation of techniques and art forms for manipulating the unconscious. It attempts, in short, to gain command over the selfâs sense of possibility, over its capacity for Desire.
Out of the disintegrating consciousness must come the recovery, the reintegration and the advance of Desire a new sensuousness based on possibility. If this sense of possibility lacks a humanistic social content, if it remains crudely egoistic, then it will simply follow the logic of the irrational social order and slip into a vicious nihilism.[67] In the long run, the choices confronting the modern bohemianâhip or freakâare not between a socially passive subjectivism and a politically active reformism (the prevailing society, as it moves from crisis to crisis, will eliminate these traditional luxuries), but between the reactionary extremism of the SS man and the revolutionary extremism of the anarchist.
Bluntly, to drop out is to drop in. There is no facet of human life that is not infiltrated by social phenomena and there is no imaginative experience that does not float on the data of social reality. Unless the sense of the **merveilleux,** so earnestly fostered by the surrealists, is to culminate in a credo of death (a credo advanced with consistency by Villiers de lâIsle Adam in **Axel),** honesty requires that we acknowledge the social roots of our dreams, our imagination and our poetry. The real question we face is **where** we drop in, **where** we stand in relation to the whole.
[67] This is perhaps as good a place as any to emphasize that capitalism promotes egotism, not individuality or âindividualism.â Although bourgeois society loosened the hold of precapitalist unitary societies on the ego, the ego it created was as shriveled as the one it replaced. The tendency in modern state capitalism is to homogenize and massify the ego on a scale that can be compared only with the totalitarian societies of the archaic Oriental world. The term âbourgeois individualism,â an epithet widely used by the left today against libertarian elements, reflects the extent to which bourgeois ideology permeates the socialist project; indeed, the extent to which the âsocialistâ project (as distinguished from the libertarian communist project) is a mode of state capitalism.
By the same token, there is nothing in the prevailing reality that is not polluted by the degeneration of the whole. Until the child is discharged from the diseased womb, liberation must take its point of departure from a diagnosis of the illness, an awareness of the problem, and a striving to be born. Introspection must be corrected by social analysis. Our freedom is anchored in **revolutionary** consciousness and culminates in **revolutionary** action.
But the revolution can no longer be imprisoned in the realm of Need. It can no longer be satisfied merely with the prose of political economy. The task of the Marxian critique has been completed and must be transcended. The subject has entered the revolutionary project with entirely new demands for experience, for re-integration, for fulfillment, for the **merveilleux.** The very character structure promoted by the revolutionary project in the past is now at issue in its most nuclear forms. Any hierarchical organization of human differences sexual, ethnic, generational or physicalâmust now give way to the dialectical principle of unity in diversity. In ecology, this principle is already taken for granted: the conservation, indeed elaboration, of variety is regarded as a precondition for natural stability. All species are equally important in maintaining the unity and balance of an ecosystem. There are no hierarchies in nature other than those imposed by hierarchical modes of human thought, but rather differences merely in function between and within living things. The revolutionary project will always remain incomplete and one-sided until it recognizes the need to remove all hierarchical modes of thought, indeed all conceptions of âothernessâ based on domination, from its own midst. Social hierarchy is undeniably real today in the sense that it stems from a clash of **objectively **conflicting interests, a clash that up to now has been validated by unavoidable material scarcity. But precisely because this hierarchical organization of appearances exists in bourgeois society at a time when the problem of scarcity can be solved, it must be eliminated completely from the revolutionary community. And it must be eliminated not only in the revolutionary organization, but in the outlook and character structure of the individual revolutionary.
To rephrase Pierre Reverdyâs words, the poet now stands on the rampartsânot only as dreamer, but also as fighter. Stalking through the dream, permeating the surreal experience, stirring the imagination to entirely new evocative heights are the liberatory possibilities of the
objective world. For the first time in history, object and subject can be joined in the revolutionary affinity groupâthe anarchic, revolutionary collectivity of sisters and brothers. Theory and praxis can be united in the purposive revolutionary deed. Thought and intuition can be merged in the new revolutionary vision. Conscious and unconscious can be integrated in the revolutionary revel. Liberation may not be completeâfor us, at leastâbut it can be totalistic, involving every facet of life and experience. Its fulfillment may be beyond our wildest visions, but we can move toward what we can see and imagine. Our Being is Becoming, not stasis. Our Science is Utopia, our Reality is Eros, our Desire is Revolution.
New York June
1967
{1} G. W. F. Hegel, **The Phenomenology of Mind**, trans. J. B. Baillie, 2nd ed. rev. (Humanities Press; New York, 1949), p. 654.
{2} Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, âThe Communist Manifesto,â in **Selected Works** (International Publishers; New York, n.d.), vol. 1, p. 227.
{3} Raoul Vaneigem, âThe Totality for Kidsâ (International Situationist pamphlet; London, n.d.), p. 1.
{4} Guy Debord, âPerspectives for Conscious Modification of Daily
Life,â mimeographed translation from **Internationale Situationiste,** no. 6 (n.p., n.d.), p. 2.
{5} Josef Weber, âThe Great Utopia,â **Contemporary Issues,** vol. 2, no. 5 (1950), p. 12.
{6} Ibid., p. 19 (my emphasis).
{7} Abraham H. Maslow**, Toward a Psychology of Being** (Van Nostrand; New York, 1962), p. viii.
{8} Quoted in Angus M. Woodbury, **Principles of General Ecology** (Blakiston; New York, 1954), p. 4.
{9} Robert L. Rudd, âPesticides: The **Real** Peril,â **The Nation,** vol. 189 (1959), p. 401.
{10} E. A. Gutkind**, The Twilight of Cities** (Free Press; Glencoe, N.Y., 1962), pp. 55â144.
{11} H. D. F. Kitto**, The Greeks** (Aldine; Chicago, 1951), p. 16.
{12} Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, **The German Ideology** (International Publishers; New York, 1947), p. 24.
{13} Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, *What Is Property?* (Bellamy Library; London, I n.d.), vol. 1, p. 135.
{14} U.S. Congress, Joint Committee on the Economic Report,
<em>Automation and Technological Change: Hearings Before the Subcommittee on Economic Stabilization, 84<sup>th</sup> Cong., Ist session (U.S. Govt. Printing Office; Washington, 1955), p. 81.</em>
{15} Alice Mary Hilton, âCyberculture,â Fellowship for Reconciliation paper (Berkeley, 1964), p. 8.
{16} Lewis Mumford, *Technics and Civilization* (Harcourt, Brace and Co.;
New York, 1934), pp. 69â70.
{17} Eric W. Leaver and John J. Brown, âMachines without Men,â
{18} F. M. C. Fourier, *Selections from the Works of Fourier*, (S.
Sonnenschein and Co.; London, 1901), p. 93.
{19} Charles Gide, introduction to Fourier, op. cit., p. 14.
{20} Hans Thirring, Energy for Man (Harper & Row; New York, 1958),
p. 266
{21} Ibid., p. 269. 22 Henry Tabor, âSolar Energy,â in Science and the New Nations, ed.
{22} Ruth Gruber (Basic Books; New York, 1961), p. 109.
{23} Eugene Ayres, âMajor Sources of Energy,â *American Petroleum Institute Proceedings*, section 3, Division of Refining, vol. 28 III. (1948), p. 117.
{24} Thomas Carlyle, *The French Revolution* (Modern Library; New York,
n.d.), p. 593.
{25} Friedrich Wilhelmsen, preface to Friedrich G. Juenger, *The Failure of Technology* (Regnery; Chicago, 1956), p. vii.
{26} W. Warde Fowler, **The City State of the Greeks and Romans**
(Macmillan & Co.; London, 1952), p. 168.
{27} Edward Zimmerman, The Greek Commonwealth, 5th ed. (Modern
Library; New York, 1931), pp. 408â9.
{28} Karl Marx, âThe Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte,â in Marx
and Engels, Selected Works, Vol. 2, p. 318.
{29} V.I. Lenin, <em>The Threatening Catastrophe and How to Fight It, The
Little Lenin Library, vol, II</em> (International Publishers; New York, 1932), p. 37.
{30} Quoted in Leon Trotsky, **The History of the Russian Revolution **(Simon
& Schuster; New York, 1932), vol. 1, p. 144.
{31} V. V. Osinsky, âOn the Building of Socialism,â Kommunist, no. 2,
April 1918, quoted in R. V. Daniels, *The Conscience of the Revolution* (Harvard University Press; Cambridge, 1960), pp. 85â86,
{32} Robert G. Wesson, *Soviet Communes* (Rutgers University Press; New
Brunswick, N.J., 1963), p. 110.
{33} R. V. Daniels, op. cit., p. 145.
{34} Mosche Lewin, *Leninâs Last Struggle* (Pantheon; New York, 1968),
p. 122.
{35} Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, **Selected Correspondence**
(International Publishers; New York, 1942), p. 292.
{36} Frederick Engels, **Herr Eugen DĂŒhringâs Revolution in Science (Anti-DĂŒhring)** (International Publishers; New York, 1939),p. 323.
{37} Marx and Engels, âThe Communist Manifesto.â
{38} Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, **The Holy Family** (Foreign
Languages Publishing House; Moscow, 1956), p. 102.
{39} Paul Avrich, **Kronstadt 1921** (Princeton University Press; Princeton,
N.J., 1970), pp. 172â73. For a different interpretation of the Kronstadt events see my introduction to Ida Mett, **The Kronstadt Uprising** (Black Rose Books; Montreal, 1971).
{40} Hegel, op. cit. The passage cited here is quoted in Marx and Engels,
<em>Selected Correspondence,</em> pp. 542â43.