đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș document â€ș murray-bookchin-urbanization-without-cities captured on 2023-07-22 at 20:04:26. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âŹ…ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Urbanization Without Cities
Subtitle: The Rise and Decline of Citizenship
Date: 1992
Source: [[https://libcom.org/library/urbanization-without-cities-rise-decline-citizenship][libcom.org]]
Notes: This is the 1992 edition published by Black Rose Books
Authors: Murray Bookchin
Topics: History, Anarchist history, Social ecology, Civilization, Cities, Citizenism, Libertarian municipalism, Urbanization, Black rose books

Dedication

<em>For **Jane Coleman** and **Dan Chodorkoff**—<br><br>

and in memory of **Zeitel Kaluskaya** (1860–1930),

my grandmother, who raised me

and showed me a world long gone by.</em>

Preface

The city at its best is an ecocommunity. To ignore this compelling fact is to ignore the destruction it faces by one of the most

serious phenomena of the modern era, the massive urbanization

that is sweeping it away together with so many natural features of

our planet. Urbanization is not only a social and cultural fact of

historic proportions; it is a tremendous ecological fact as well. At

a time when the overwhelming majority of people in North America and Western Europe regard themselves as city dwellers, we

are obliged, if only for ecological reasons, to explore modern urbanization. We must explore not only its impact on the natural

environment, a subject that has already been discussed in considerable detail by many writers, but, more significantly these days,

the changes urbanization has produced in our sensibility toward

society and toward the natural world. A social ecology of the city

is needed today if ecological thinking is to be relevant to the

modern human condition.

This book attempts to lay the groundwork for such a social

ecology. It tries to develop a concept of the city in those participatory terms that are uniquely characteristic of all “ecosystems” (or,

as I prefer to call them, ecocommunities). It relates ecology’s participatory sensibility to the city in all its forms over the course of

history, partly to show that the city was a social ecocommunity at

various times insofar as it fostered diversity, mutualism, and connectedness. In applying a participatory sensibility to the city, I

have been obliged to take the reader on a voyage into the evolution of the city, just as any serious natural ecologist would be

obliged to deal with the biological development of an organism to

better understand its life-cycle. To think about the city as an ecocommunity is to try to understand how it evolved, what forms it

assumed over time, how it functioned as more than a mere market

or center of production, and, in the last analysis, how member

this urban ecocommunity called the city interacted with each

other to produce a form of “second nature”—a humanly made

“nature”—that existed in balance with the “first nature” we

usually call the natural environment. Hence the citizens of a city

of no less concern to me than the city itself, for the city at its best

eventually became an ethical union of people, an ethical as

as social ecocommunity, not simply a dense collection of structures

designed for no other purpose than to provide goods and services

for its anonymous residents.

What I wish to do is redeem the city, to visualize it not;

threat to the environment but as a uniquely human, ethical, and

ecological community that often lived in balance with nature and

created institutional forms that sharpened human awareness of

their sense of natural place as well as social place. My repeated

references to the agrarian world could easily be regarded as references to the natural world as well. My emphasis on civic participation can be taken as the social counterpart of biological mutualism

citizenship, as the social counterpart of biotic involvement if

shaping the form of a natural ecocommunity; civic history, as the

social counterpart of natural history. My goal, in effect, has been

to redefine the city and the citizen in the language of social ecol

ogy in the hope that environmentally as well as socially oriented

people today will understand what the city and citizenship *used*

to be in order to better understand what they *should* be in an

ecological society.

The real urban crisis of our time, I shall emphasize, has resulted

not from the emergence of the city as such; rather it results from

the emergence of a relatively new and cancerous phenomenon

that poses a deadly threat to the city and countryside alike: urbanization. The nature of this threat—not merely as geographic sprawl

but a devastating dehumanizing of city life, a destructing of community, and a denaturing of agrarian life—is the underlying

theme of this book. I must leave it to the pages which follow for

a more complete description and elucidation of the vast problems

urbanization is creating. My argument runs counter to the conventional wisdom that city and countryside, like society and nature, are necessarily in conflict with each other, a theme that

pervades so much of the writing on urbanity of western society.

Quite to the contrary: however much city life marks a departure

in many social respects from the more natural forms of human

sociation such as tribal and kinship groups, the city has often been

as much a gift to the ecology of a landscape as it has been a harm.

To recover a feeling for the participatory civic institutions that

Once marked city life and citizenship is to recover those ideals of

Civic life and a civic sensibility that could countervail the massive

destruction that urbanization inflicts on city and countryside alike.

This book advances several reflections on how an ecological

politics can be developed. In so doing, it redefines the word politics itself along ecological lines, much as Green groups in North

America and Europe have been doing over the past years. Finally,

this book makes a plea for a confederal and institutional politics,

this is, for enlarging the democratic, grass-roots institutions that

countervail the growing centralization of the nation-state, not the

conventional electoral politics based on single issues and parliamentary tournaments.

Much that motivated my writing of this book stems from my

conviction as a social ecologist and environmental activist that

there is a pressing need to view the city—more generally, the

municipality, if we are to include towns as well as metropolitican

areas—as an ecological enterprise, not merely a logistical or structural one. Hence, the largest chapter in this book advances a

programmatic agenda for recovering not only an ecological image

of the city and an active citizenry but a way of looking at politics

that combines the high ideal of a participatory citizenship—in

short, ecological values based on participation as a mutualistic

phenomena in society as well as in nature.

In any case, the city is here to stay. Indeed, it has been a crucial

part of human history and a factor in the making of the human

mind for some seven thousand years. Can we afford to ignore it?

Must we accept it as it is—as an entity that faces obliteration by

a sprawling urbanization that threatens the countryside as well?

Or can we give the city a new meaning, a new politics, a new sense

of direction—and, also, provide new ideals of citizenship, many of

which were in fact attained in great part during past times? By

ignoring the city and citizenship, we do so at the peril of becoming

isolated from the great mass of humanity which is threatened by

the anonymity and powerless created by urbanization. This is a

issue which all socially and environmentally oriented people must

face and answer in their own way: My goal, here, is to pose the

question of urbanization and citizenship as clearly as I can and

advance some modest solutions based on my own concerns as a

social ecologist

Murray Bookchin

Burlington, Vermont

<br><br>

Director Emeritus,

Institute for Social Ecology,

Marshfield, Vermont

<br><br>

Professor Emeritus,

School of Environmental Studies,

Ramapo College of New Jersey

Introduction

The city has been a favorite target of hostility from biblical

times onward—and it is no less so today. Viewed as a festering

source of moral depravity by many people, it has been

variously assailed as an ugly blight on a seemingly pristine

natural landscape, as the sinful embodiment of a human nature

that is aggressive, domineering, or even as “male” in its

“rape” of a caring Mother Earth and “her” gentle aboriginal

folk and animal offspring. I will leave the metaphoric, often

terribly fuzzy ruminations of this genre of anti-city sentiment

aside. A far stronger case can be made for an anti-city sentiment

that regards modern, generally sprawling and formless

urban agglomerations as sources of anomie, fear, self-interest,

and a host of environmental problems. Urbanization, as I call

this ever-encroaching and ever-growing phenomenon that

we so often facilely identify with cities as such, can indeed be

as toxic to the human spirit as it can be to a region’s natural

integrity.

But what, then, is a city? And are the people trapped in

modern-day urban agglomerations really citizens?

reflective and hopeful way. Far from joining the chorus of

city-denouncers, I wish to explore the enormous value of

cities—and towns—as remarkable human creations. In

responding to the above questions, I have tried to examine

from a historical viewpoint the origins of cities, their role in

shaping humanity as a highly unique and creative species,

and the promise they offer as arenas for a new political and

social dispensation. I have tried to examine how the city

evolved, what forms it assumed over time, how it functioned

as more than a mere market or center of production, and how

citizens of a city interacted with one another to produce a

form of what the great Roman thinker Cicero called “second

nature”—that is, a *humanly* made “nature”—that existed in

balance with the “first nature” we usually call the natural

environment. Hence the citizens of a city are of no less concern

to me than the city itself, for the city at its best ultimately

became an ethical union of people, a moral as well as a

socioeconomic community—not simply a dense collection of

structures designed merely to provide goods and services for

its anonymous residents.

What I wish to do is to redeem the city, to explore it hot as

a corrosive phenomenon but as a uniquely human, ethical,

and ecological community whose members often lived in

balance with nature and created institutional forms that

sharpened human self-awareness, fostered rationality, created a

secularized culture, enhanced individuality, and established

institutional forms of freedom. My repeated references to the

agrarian world can easily be regarded as references to the

natural world as well. My emphasis on civic participation can

be taken as the social counterpart of biological mutualism;

citizenship, as the social counterpart of biotic involvement in

shaping the forms of natural ecocommunities; and civic history,

as the social counterpart of natural history. In using the

word *counterpart* here, however, I do not mean that civic

participation, citizenship, and civic history are reducible to

natural mutualism, ecocommunities, and biological

evolution; they differ in far too many ways to be congruent. But

this is a philosophical question I have dealt with in a broad

discussion of first and second nature in my

(Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1990). Suffice it to

say here that my goal in this book has been to redefine the

city and the citizen in the language of social ecology. It is my

hope that thoughtful people today will attempt to understand

what the city and citizenship *used* to be in order to better

understand what they *could* be in a free, rational, and ecological

society.

----

The usual kinds of answers given to the question of what

constitutes a city are often spatial and demographic in character,

viewing the the city as an area occupied by a closely interlocked,

densely populated human community. This definition,

cast in largely quantitative terms, has been advanced for a

long time. In fact, it is the popular criterion for the prestige

enjoyed by some cities over other ones, and of cities generally

over towns and villages. Tradition has it that the larger a city

is, the *better* it is culturally and economically, by comparison

with smaller communities. It is worth noting that years ago,

American census-takers regarded communities of five

thousand people or more as urban and those with smaller

populations as rural. More recent criteria of what constitutes

a city have changed only quantitatively. The word *city*, in fact,

has turned into something of a social euphemism, the

product of a time long past. Today, statisticians and many

urbanologists favor the use of such categories as the Standard

Metropolitan Statistical Area (SMSA)-sprawling, densely

occupied regions that ordinarily embrace milllions of people. In

reality, cities are being supplanted by areas so immense in size

that they are losing their contours, specificity, and uniqueness.

Many urban agglomerations today have larger populations

than many countries had a century ago and are in many

respects hardly different from small nation-states.

My own definition of a *city* cannot be reduced to a single

proposition. Like rationality, science, and technology, which I

regard as defined by their own histories, I view the city as the

cumulative development—or dialectic—of certain important social

potentialities and of their phases of development, traditions,

culture, and community features. Least of all do I see

citification—a processual noun for the city in history—as a mere

“system of space,” to use Henri Lefebvre’s phrase, in which

the geometrical term *space* becomes a quasi-mystical category

for social, economic, and cultural relationships-relation-

ships that I feel should be explored quite directly, without the

convoluted “decoding” that enters into the work of certain

postmodernists and neo-Marxists today. Neither from simple

propositional definitions nor from somewhat mystical

postmodernist gymnastics would I have any way of knowing

how cities and their village, temple, and town progenitors

came into being, how they developed, or what they ought to

be if their potentialities were to be fulfilled in a free and

rational society.

Defining the early city, I maintain, begins with the

recognition of the city as a *creative* breach with humanity’s

essentially biological heritage, indeed the “metamorphosis” of that

heritage into a new *social* form of evolution. The city was

initially the arena par excellence for the transformation of

human relationships from associations based on biological

facts, such as kinship, to distinctly social facts, such as

residential propinquity; for the emergence of increasingly

secular forms of institutionalization; for often rapidly

innovative cultural relations; and for universalizing economic

activities that had been previously associated with age, gender,

and ethnic divisions. In short, the city was the historic arena

in which—and as a result of which—biological affinities were

transformed into social affinities. It constituted the single

most important factor that changed an ethnic folk into a body

of secular citizens, and a parochial tribe into a universal

become a member of the community without having to satisfy

any requirement of real or mythic blood ties to a common

ancestor. Not only did political relationships replace kinship

relationships; the notion of a shared *humanitas* replaced the

exclusivity of the clan and tribe, whose biosocial claims to be

“the People” had often excluded the “outsider” as an

inorganic, exogenous, or even threatening “other.”

Hence the city was historically the arena for the

emergence of such universalistic concepts as “humanity”—and is

potentially the arena for the reemergence of concepts of politi-

cal self-regulation and citizenship, for the elaboration of social

relations, and for the rise of a new civic culture. The steps from

a consanguineous clan, tribe, and village to a *polis*, or political

city; from blood brothers and sisters who were *born* into their

social responsibilities to citizens who in the best of circumstances

could freely decide on their civic responsibilities and determine their own affinities based on reason and secular

interests—these steps constitute a meaningful definition of

the city. Cities, to be sure, can rise and fall. They can enjoy

good fortune for a time or, owing to conflicts, totally disappear.

But once the city established firm roots in the history of social

development, it acquired a conceptual reality that still persists,

and it can still undergo many metamorphoses despite the

disappearance or stagnation of individual cities. The city, in effect,

has become a historic tradition—often a highly moral one—that

tends to expand uniquely human traits and notions of

freedom, and an idea of civic commonality that corrodes the

parochial bonds of blood ties, gender distinctions, age status-groups,

and ethnic exclusivity.

We can thus legitimately speak of the history of the city

without focusing on the rise, development, and decline of any

one city in particular. And we can speak of this history as

cumulative. The late medieval city, for example, united civic

and ideological traditions that had originated in Athens,

Jerusalem, and Rome, and that persisted long after those

cities had declined as innovative civic entities. Later, the cities

of the Renaissance, the Baroque era, and the Enlightenment

arose as reworked arenas of ancient and medieval cities,

borrowing from them their architecture, literature, art, religions,

and philosophies, yet transforming them to meet the needs of

a new time.

----

The ways in which actual cities provide US with processual

definitions of the city form much of the content of this book.

Insofar as I am guided by the Greek notion that a city or *polis*

is an *ethical* union of citizens, I am committed to an

overarching vision of what the city *ought* to be, not merely what it *is* at

any given time. The term *ought* is the stuff out of which ethics

is usually made—with the difference that in my view the

“ought” is not a formal or arbitrary regulative credo but the

product of reasoning, of an unfolding rational process elicited

or derived eductively from the potentialities of humanity to

develop, however falteringly, mature, self-conscious, free,

and ecological communities. I call this integration of the best

in first or “biological” nature and second or “social” nature an

emergently new “third” or *free* nature—that is, an ethical,

humanly scaled community that establishes a creative

interaction with its natural environment. From a processual

standpoint, I refuse to bifurcate that continuum we call

“Nature” into a biological world and a social world that stand in

flat opposition to each other. Both are in a very real sense

realization in those remarkable primates called human beings who,

consciously responding to a sense of obligation to the

ecological integrity of the planet, bring their rational,

communicative, richly social, imaginative, and aesthetic capacities to the

service of the nonhuman world as well as the human.

This ethics of complementarity, as I called it years ago,

would not only be a culminating point of aeons of natural

evolution, once it guided human behavior in the cities of an

ecological society; it would eminently be a culminating point

of reason itself—a condition in which rational goals could be

established for citizenship not only in new, ecologically

oriented networks of cities but in truly rational beings called

citizens. For citizenship, too, is a process—as the Greeks so

brilliantly saw—a process involving the social and self-formation

of people into active participants in the management of

their communities. As this book stresses, citizens today no

longer even approximate the high and eminently human

standard of citizenship that was established in the Hellenic

world—a meaning that must be recovered, as well as the personal

and social training, or *paideia*, for producing citizens.

----

To this high civic and ethical calling, so to speak, we are

summoned by reason: to networks of new, humanly scaled cities,

to citizenship, to directly democratic political institutions, and

to a vastly expanded ideal of freedom. The cities I have discussed

in this book approximate the fulfillment of this calling—some

more than others, a few more highly conscious of

free civic ideals than the rest—in civic cultures that held to

such intituitive, often naive notions of citizenship that they

were highly vulnerable to destructive forces; and in thinkers

who projected (often in revolutionary situations,) in thought

what they believed should have been achieved in actuality

but, alas, was not.

When I use the word *networks* in this book, I am alluding

not to ad hoc interactions, tentative agreements, contracts, or

transient associations among cities-although these were

common enough, if usually very short-lived, in the past.

Rather, I am referring to what has long been a theoretical

ideal and at times an impressive municipal reality: namely,

association of cities and towns is part of the development of a

free, ecologically oriented society. Localism, in the narrow

sense of a virtually autarchical locality that aspires to

“self-sufficiency”—in the sense so popular in the ecology movement today—could easily produce a parochialism notable for

such evils as racism, cultural insularity, and a stagnant

traditionalism. Conceived localistically, municipalities would

be as regressive as authoritarian nation-states.

Confederalism is explicitly *not* “localist” but is rather

the mutual obligations of confederated municipalities to

systematically adjudicate conflicting claims, coordinate common

efforts, and see to the administration of municipal policies

without infringing on the right of the majority of its

participants. That consensual forms of agreement where possible

would be the most desirable decision-making procedure does

not mean that majority decision-making should not be

adopted if a confederation risks the prospect of being

tyrannized by the few at the expense of the many. Moreover,

confederation, if it is to be successful, must not only function in

accordance with majoritarian forms of decision-making; it

must diminish the authority of confederal councils, the

higher they are, in coordinating the policies formulated at the

basic level of decision-making—the citizen assembly of a

municipality.

A clear distinction must be drawn between *administration*

and *policy-making*: the former would fall within the province

of the confederal councils, while the latter would fall within

the province of the municipal assemblies. The traditional

hierarchial pyramid of authority would thus be literally

inverted in confederal municipalism; the “apex” of all authority

would lie with the municipal assemblies, guided by majority

rule both in the assembly and among the assemblies of a confederal region; the “base” would lie with the broadest confederal councils whose work is simply administrative and adjudicatory, and whose deputies, drawn from smaller confederal bodies, would be easily recallable and subject to

careful popular oversight.

Is this a chimerical scheme? History has shown that the

very contrary is true. Although confederations in the past

often fell apart, each for very specific reasons that would require a full volume to explore, they were often shattered or

confined to limited areas by imperial states and, more recently, the nation-state. Confederations, in fact, have a long and

impressive history. They were the principal political

weapons for resisting—and, for a time, diminishing—state

power. The struggles of confederated Rhenish cities in the

late Middle Ages against the Holy Roman Empire and of the

confederated Spanish cities against Charles V during the

Reformation era can be cited as partially successful attempts

to abort or restrict imperial and national power. In Spain,

confederal movements had an impact on public life that was

felt well into the 1930s.

In many respects, this contest between confederalism

and the nation-state is reemerging today, although very little

consciousness guides intuitive opponents of the nation-state,

a shortcoming that has more to do with the atrophied consciousness of so-called “Left”-wing movements than with

any other single factor. Indeed, if the closing decade of this

century is permitted to pass without the emergence of a

strong, self-conscious, and well-organized movement that is

committed to municipal confederation, radical theory and

practice will deserve the ignominious oblivion into which

Marxist and individualistic “anarchist” tendencies have been

drifting for some time now. Today’s dogmatic or subcultural

radical movements may one day be viewed with contempt if

they reject the last—and in my view their **only**—prospect of

functioning as popular movements, and if they fail to cross

the line from academic or personalistic subcultures into the

public sphere where they could still reach millions of eager

but confused people. Popular albeit inchoate impulses toward

these same ideas—local control, confederation, and a new

politics—may well be used, in altered form, and manipulated

by reactionary forces in the service of racist, parochial, and ultimately authoritarian ends.

----

the last that can be made in this period—not only for a new

theoretical framework in which to develop a new politics (in

this term’s Hellenic meaning rather than in the parliamentary

meaning imparted to it by the nation-state). It also advances

an appeal for a self-conscious *practice* in which

confederal municipalists engage in local electoral activity to

alter city and town charters, restructure civic institutions to

provide the public sphere for direct democracy, and bring the

means of production under *citizen* control—not under the

particu1aristic forms of “workers’ control” that tend to

degenerate into a form of collectivistic capitalism, or under

forms of nationalized production, which enhance the state’s

authority with greater economic power.

This practice is not a mere “strategy,” to use the language

of the traditional Left—indeed, the language of all statist

movements. It is not a “means” to an end, least of all a very

unclear and muddled end. Rather, it is the *unfolding* of an end:

the famous “Commune of communes,” to which socialists

and anarchists alike long aspired, especially after the legendary Paris Commune of 1871, which explicitly used this term.

In this process or dialectic of unfolding, the achievement of a

Commune of communes—or in less colorful terms, a confederation of municipalities—requires a completely

uncompromising politics. It rests on the notion of a fundamental

confederated municipalities emerge in flat *opposition* to the

centralized nation-state. Indeed, whatever power confederated municipalities gain can be acquired only at the expense of the

nation-state, and whatever power the

nation-state gains can be acquired only at the expense of

municipal independence.

In the force-field that exists between the two, either the

municipalities and their confederations will increase their

power by diminishing the the power of the ration-state, or

the nation-state will increase its power by diminishing the

authority of the municipalities and their confederations.

Thus, for a municipalist movement to run candidates for

state, provincial, or national office would be an absurd, in

fact, oxymoronic subversion of its very claim to seek a

“grassroots” or “participatory democracy,” if only because

a form of representation rather than participation. Even

more significantly, it would ignore the crucial fact that as

they run candidates *for* local offices, confederal municipalists

are also running them *against* state, provincial, and national

offices and institutions. The demand for municipal confederations is simultaneously a demand for opposition to the

nation-state in **all** its forms, and to the illusion that the

control of state, provincial, or national legislative bodies on the

“top” is a precondition for the attainment of local power at

the “bottom.”

Not only would campaigns for state, provincial, and

national office relax the tension between the “top,” which is the

realm of statecraft, and the “bottom,” which is the realm of an

authentic politics; they would diminish the *educational* function of politics at the “bottom,” which alone can become the

realm of a new politics. Far from reaching greater numbers of

people by running candidates for the summits of state power,

such campaigns would confuse the distinction between

politics and statecraft, between the participatory and the representative, between the confederal and the national. Not

only would the tension between these two utterly opposing

spheres of activity be relaxed and its dialectic aborted; and not

only would the truly democratic nature of political education,

which is based on face-to-face discourse between neighbors

and citizens, be replaced by the media; but the very moral and

educational thrust of a libertarian or confederal municipalist

approach would be lost as a heavy mist beclouded the distinction between politics and statecraft. A “Commune of communes” is not a “Republic of communes” or a “Commonwealth of communes”; indeed, as a confederation of municipalities, it stands uncompromisingly opposed to any specious attempts to reduce a confederation or commune to a

republic or a commonwealth.

Radicals, social-democrats, and liberals—not to speak of

that hybridized phenomenon known as “the Greens”—have

never learned how to deal with the problem of state power. If

history from earliest recorded times to the present has

demonstrated anything, it is the implacable fact that state

power is corruptive. None of the most idealistic and principled revolutionary leaders of the past lived comfortably

with the corruptive effects of state power. Either they succumbed to it, or they consciously tried to diffuse it. The retention of state power destroyed the moral integrity not only of

the most radical Puritans of the seventeenth century, who

were eager to gain it, but that of the most dedicated socialists,

communists, and anarchists who actually held it for a time.

The English, French, Russian, and Spanish revolutions provide compelling evidence of the capacity of state power to

corrupt—a capacity that can no longer be regarded as a moral

truism but, given its unrelenting nature, must be seen as an

existential fact. To pursue state power—or to “seize” it, to use

the language of traditional radicalism—is to guarantee that it

will persist as a form of elitist manipulation, expand, and be

brutally exercised as an instrument against a popular

democracy.

A libertarian or confederal municipalist politics advances

the best approach against “seizures” of state power and its

retention by an elite, by slowly trying to *accrete* power for

municipalities—initially, by acquiring *moral* power for

municipal assemblies, as I have indicated in the closing chapter of this book. Libertarian or confederal municipalism seeks

to expand the democratic institutions that still linger on in

any modern republican system by opening them to the

widest public participation possible at any given time. Hence

the slogan that I have advanced: “Democratize the Republic!

Radicalize the Democracy!” It is not that state power is to be

“seized”—and then never relinquished—but that popular

power is to be expanded until all power belongs to the institutions of a participatory democracy.

From this standpoint, the distinction between politics

and statecraft must be maintained in a clear and uncompromising manner, all the more to assure that no “pragmatic” exigencies or parliamentary” strategies”—even if they

are used only to propagandize one’s views or challenge the

“top” from the “top”—are invoked for seemingly confederal-municipalist ends. Indeed, the most effective impact of

municipalist propaganda comes precisely from the fact that

it is **municipalist**—that is to say, that it can be conducted only

by person-to-person contact and its scope hopefully extended by a movement that tries to reach every municipality

in a region or nation. It is this kind of propaganda that makes

for trust, personal interaction, and face-to-face education

and that fosters the development of a face-to-face

democracy. Its authentic starting point is the small study

group, the local lecture hall, the neighborhood press, and

personal discourse-not the electronic media of statecraft

that hypnotized the countercultural “media freaks” of the

1960s.

----

Most of the ideas that appear in this introduction are

elaborated in the body of this book. They are developed

against the larger background of a historic moment in the

evolution—and I should add, the decline—of city life, namely

the emergence of a major threat to city and countryside alike:

urbanization. The existence of this threat—not merely as

geographic sprawl but as a devastating dehumanization of

city life, a destructuring of community and a denaturing of

agrarian life—informs the views that follow. My argument

runs counter to the conventional wisdom that city and

countryside, like society and nature, are necessarily in conflict

with each other, a theme that pervades so much of the writing

on urbanity in Western society. Quite to the contrary:

whatever may be the ways in which city life marks a departure from the more “natural” forms of human association

such as tribal and kinship groups, the city has been more of a

gift to social life and the ecological landscape than it has been

harmful. To recover a feeling for the participatory civic institutions that once marked city life and citizenship is to

recover those ideals of civic life and civic sensibility that could

countervail the massive destruction that urbanization and

the nation-state inflict on city and countryside alike.

My writing of this book stemmed from my conviction as

a social ecologist and eco-anarchist that there is a pressing

need to view the city—more generally, the municipality, if we

are to include towns as well—as an ecological enterprise, not

merely as a logistical or structural one. The word *ecological*

means a good deal more here than it does in the conventional

environmentalism of the single-issue movements that are

concerned with pollution, the retention of relatively untouched forests, the perpetuation of wildlife, and the like.

Ecology, in my view, is more a societal project than a biological one. It should be conceived in terms that explore how notions of domination and the historical development of

hierarchy have led to the social as well as natural problems

we face today. For a clearer understanding of my ecological

perspective—social ecology—the reader is advised to consult

my many books on the subject, particularly

with what are loosely called “urban problems,” or if you like,

“urban ecology.” Its goal is practical as well as theoretical.

Hence, the largest chapter in the book (“The New Municipal

Agenda”) advances a programmatic agenda for recovering

not only an ecological concept of the city and an active

citizenry but the creation of a new politics that combines the

high ideal of a participatory citizenship with a recognition of

what the city or town can be in a rational, free, and ecological

society.

In any case, the city, however much more distorted it

may become in the future, will remain a problem. At its best, it

has been a crucial part of human history and a force in the

making of the human mind for some seven thousand years.

Can we afford to ignore it? Must we accept it as it is—as an

entity that sprawling urbanization threatens to obliterate, as

it threatens to devour the countryside as well? Or can we

give the city a new meaning, a new politics, a new sense of

direction-as well as provide new ideals of citizenship, many

of which were in fact once attained in previous times? We ignore the city and citizenship at the peril of becoming isolated

from the great mass of humanity, which is threatened by the

anonymity and powerlessness created by urbanization. This

is an issue that all socially and enviromentally concerned

people must face. My goal here is to pose the question of the

future of cities and citizenship as clearly as I can and to advance solutions based on the principles of social ecology.

Murray Bookchin

Institute for Social Ecology

Plainfield, Vermont

January, 1992

Chapter One: Urbanization Against Cities

The title of this chapter has been deliberately worded to create a

paradox in the reader’s mind. How, it may be fair to ask, can, we

speak of urbanization against cities? The two words, “urbanity”

and “city,” are usually taken to be synonyms. Indeed, as conventional wisdom would have it, a city is by definition an urban entity,

and an urban entity, in turn, is certainly regarded as a city.

Yet I shall take great pains to show that they are in sharp

contrast to each other—in fact, that they are bitter antagonists. My

reasons for making such an unorthodox distinction between urbanization and citification are not intended to be semantic word

juggling. The contradiction forms the very rationale for writing

this book. “Urbanization against cities” is meant to focus as sharply

as possible on a human and ecological crisis so deep-sfeated we are

hardly aware of its existence, much less its grave impact on social

freedom and personal autonomy. I refer to the historic decline of

the city as an authentic arena of political life (that once lived in

some balance with the natural world) and, perhaps no less significantly, the decline of the very notion of citizenship.

So sweeping a statement obviously requires some clarification

at the outset of our discussion. According to most social theorists,

the traditional “contradiction” created by the rise of urbanism has

been the city’s ages-old “conflict” with the countryside. History,

we are commonly told, is filled with innumerable examples of the

city’s efforts to free itself from the trammels of agrarian parochialism. The city, it is emphasized, has always tried to assert its cosmopolitan culture and secular civic institutions over the narrow provincialism and constrictive kinship ties of the rural town and

village. We take it for granted that from ancient to modern times

the city and countryside have been at “war” with each other.

Historically, this “war” is supposed to be embodied in the conflicting interests between the feudal lord and the urban merchant, the

peasant food-cultivator and town-dwelling craftsperson, the landbased aristocrat and the citified capitalist, the farmer and the industrial worker.

That such conflicts have existed over the course of history and

echo in modern society is true enough. We still retain ingrained

visions of a cleansing and virtuous pastoral life that stands in moral

contrast with the tainted and sinful world of the city. The contrast

has been the subject of Biblical invectives, the theme of some of

our most outstanding novels, and a centerpiece in the writings of

many distinguished sociologists.

Taken as a whole, however, this Manichean drama can be a

gross simplification of reality. It is certainly true that city and

countryside have commonly viewed each other antagonistically in

the past. And there have been long stretches of history when each

tried to assert economic and political dominance over the other.

But there have also been times when they existed in an almost

exquisitely sensitive, creative, and ecological balance with each

other. Some of the most admirable human adventures m culture,

technics, and social freedom have occurred precisely in those periods when a complementary relationship between city and country, indeed between society and nature, successfully replaced the

mutual rivalry for supremacy.

Today, it would seem that the city has finally achieved complete

dominance over the countryside. Indeed, with the extension of

suburbs into nearby open land on an unprecedented scale, the city

seems to be literally engulfing the agrarian and natural worlds,

absorbing adjacent towns and villages into sprawling metropolitan

entities—a form of social cannibalism that could easily serve for

our very definition of urbanization. All talk of metropolitan Babylon and Rome to the contrary, we have no comparable parallels

in the past to urbanization on our present-day scale. Worse, the

city seems to be replacing rural culture and all its rich traditional

forms with the mass media and technocratic values we tend to

associate with “city life.” If all of this is true—as I frankly believe

it is—I plan to introduce in this book a very discordant qualification. Contrary to most views on the subject, I plan to show that if

we use words such as “city” and “country” meaningfully to describe this process of physical, cultural, and ecological urban cannibalism, the image of an all-devouring “city” that is engulfing a

supine and helpless “country” is a sheer myth.

The truth is that the city **and** the country are under siege today—a siege that threatens humanity’s very place in the natural environment. Both are being subverted by urbanization, a process that

threatens to destroy their identities and their vast wealth of tradition and variety. Urbanization is engulfing not only the countryside; it is also engulfing the city. It is devouring not only town and

village life based on the values, culture, and institutions nourished

by agrarian relationships. It is devouring city life based on the

values, culture, and institutions nourished by civic relationships.

City space with its human propinquity, distinctive neighborhoods,

and humanly scaled politics—like rural space, with its closeness to

nature, its high sense of mutual aid, and its strong family relationships—is being absorbed by urbanization, with its smothering

traits of anonymity, homogenization, and institutional gigantism.

Whether or not the urbanization of both the city and the country

is desirable is an issue that I shall earnestly explore, But I cannot

emphasize too strongly that even if we think in the old terms of

city versus country and the unique political contrasts such a time-honored imagery has nurtured, the conflict between city and

country has largely become obsolete, Urbanization threatens to

replace both contestants in this seemingly historic antagonism. It

threatens to absorb them into a faceless urban world in which the

words “city” and “country” will essentially become social, cultural, and political archaisms.

----

Perhaps our greatest difficulty in understanding urbanization and

its grave impact on social and personal life today stems from our

tendency to link it with our very naive idea, of the city. We are

often satisfied to call any urban entity a city if it is demographically congested, structurally sizable, and, most significantly, populated by individuals whose work no longer deals directly with food cultivation. Urbanization, like citification, seems to meet these

criteria so completely that we commonly identify the two, and

distinguish them more as a matter of degree than of kind. Thus,

we tend to regard a sprawling metropolitan area merely as an

oversized city, or it may be an agglomeration of closely packed

“cities” that Americans call “urban belts” and the British call

“conurbations.”

Granted that we are finding it increasingly difficult, on careful

reflection, to regard urban belts and conurbations merely as cities.

We uneasily sense that they are something more—if not something newer—than what previous generations called cities. What

confuses us about such perplexing issues is that the people who

live in such new urban entities are plainly engaged in city-type

occupations and seem to follow citified lifeways. Increasingly

removed from the natural world, metropolitan dwellers rarely, if

ever, earn their livelihood as farmers, however fashionable urban

and suburban gardening has become in recent years. They are

employed in urban jobs, be they professional, managerial, service-oriented, craft-oriented, or the like. They five highly paced and

culturally urbane lifeways-that lock into mechanically fixed time

slots—notably, the “nine-to-five” pattern—rather than follow

agrarian cycles guided by seasonal change and dawn-to-dusk personal rhythms. Urban environments are highly synthetic rather

than natural. Food is normally bought rather than grown. Dwellings tend to be concentrated rather than dispersed. Personal life

is not open to the considerable public scrutiny we find in small

towns or rooted in the strong kinship systems we find in the country. Urban culture is produced, packaged, and marketed as a segment of the city dweller’s leisure time, not infused into the totality

of daily life and hallowed by tradition as it is in the agrarian world.

That country life is growing more and more like city life and losing

its simplest natural attributes is a point that will become highly

salient for the purposes of our discussion. For the present, what

counts is,that the aforementioned distinction still exists’ in the

image of what we call urbanization (conceived as citification) as

distinguished from ruralization.

Superficial as these continuities and contrasts may be, they

begin to dissolve completely when we start to explore history for

richer, fuller standards of what we mean by the word cities. I use

the plural, cities, advisedly: Despite certain similarities, the differences between cities of the past also have considerable importance. History presents us with a wide range of unique and distinctive cities—the earliest in Sumer centering around temples;

later ones, such as Babylon, around palaces; the more dynamic

Greek democracies around civic squares that fostered citizen interaction; medieval and more recent ones, around a variety of

different marketplaces. However diversified cities may have

been in the past, our language gives them considerable prestige.

The term civilization has its origin in *civitas*—a Latin word occasionally used for city—and denotes the cultural sophistication the

western world has traditionally imparted to some kind of urbanism. Most of our utopian visions, whether heavenly or earthly,

take the form of a pity, a “New Jerusalem’’ to. speak in sacred

terms, or an idealized version of the Hellenic “city-state” to use

Secular language.

----

But here we abruptly encounter the limits of the term urbanization as a synonym for citification. Urbanization does not comfortably fit into an imagery of the city drawn from theocratic, monarchic, democratic, and economic communities peopled by

craftsfolk and small merchants who were engaged in a natural

economy. Our urban belts and conurbations are vast engines for

operating huge corporate enterprises, industrial networks, distribution systems, and administrative mechanisms. Their facilities,

like their towering buildings, stretch almost endlessly over the

landscape until they begin to lack all definition and centrality. It

is difficult to root them in a temple, palace, public square, or the

small, intimate marketplace of craftsfolk and merchants. To say

that they have any specific center that gives them civic identity

is often so ill-fitting as to be absurd, even if one allows for centers

that linger on from past eras when cities were still clearly delineable areas for human association.

What, then, do our premodern cities with their rich diversity of

forms and functions have in common? We arrive at a basic characteristic of city life that is the result not only of human propinquity,

structural size, occupations, and an urbane culture. What major

cities of the past share—whatever their differences are largely

moral, often spiritual, attributes with deep roots in a natural environment that sharply distinguish them from the physical attributes we associate with urbanization. Cities of the past from their

very beginnings were ultimately what I would call communities

of the heart”—moral associations that were nourished by a shared

sense of ideological commitment and public concern. Civic ideology and concern centered around a strong belief in the good life

for which the city provided the arena and catalytic agent. The

good life by no means meant the affluent life, the life of personal

pleasures and material security. More often than not, it meant a

life of **goodness**, of virtue and probity. This sense of civic calling

could assume a highly spiritual form such as we find in the Jews’

reverence for Jerusalem or a highly ethical form as in the Greeks’

admiration for Athens. Between these emotive and intellectual

extremes, city dwellers of the past tended to form social compacts” that were guided not only by material and defensive considerations but by loyalties to their cities that were shaped by

richly textured ideological commitments.

Love of one’s city, a deep and abiding sense of loyalty to its

welfare, and an attempt to place these sentiments within a rich

moral and ecological context, whether God-given or intellectual,

clearly distinguishes the majority of cities of past eras from those

of present ones. We have virtually no equivalent in the modern

city of the Near Eastern sense of civic spirituality, the Greek feeling of political affiliation, the medieval endearment to communal

fraternity, and the Renaissance love of urban pageantry that infused the otherwise disparate citizenry of the past. Such loyalties,

with their moral underpinnings, may linger on in the residents of

modern cities, but more as a fevered appetite for the material,

cultural, and nervous stimulation of what we today designate as

the good life than as a product of the ethical sturdiness, spiritual

commitment, and sense of civic virtue that marked the citizenry

of earlier eras. It also meant a love of the land, of place and natural

setting that gave rise to a rich ecological sensibility and respect for

the countryside.

To speak truthfully, our present-day relationship to the city

usually takes the form of very pragmatic material requirements.

A modern city, suburb, town, or, for that matter, a village is often

evaluated in terms of the “municipal services” it offers to its residents. The traditional religious, cultural, ethical, and ecological

features that once endeared citizens to their city, and its natural

surroundings have dissolved into quantitative, often ethically neutral, criteria. The city is the first fund into which we make a series

of social investments for the express purpose of receiving a number of distinctly material returns. We expect our persons and

property to be protected, our shelters to be safeguarded, our garbage to be removed, our roads to be repaired, our environment

to be physically and socially tidy—which is to say, spared from the

invasion of “undesirable elements.”

Doubtless we want our cities to be culturally stimulating,

economically viable, and attractive in reputation. But such attainments are not necessarily a function of the city as such. They often

depend upon the results of personal enterprise, the presence of

individual types who reside in it by virtue of birth or choice. For

a city to claim a famous son—and, more recently, a famous daughter—does not necessarily reflect well upon the city’s reputation for

producing gifted or renowned people but rather on the individual

gifts of one or more of its residents. It does not provide us with

evidence of the city’s cultural milieu but of a specific person’s gifts

and biography that often involve a valiant effort to transcend a

community’s oppressive environment. Such was the case, for example, with James Joyce’s relationship with Dublin, Oscar Wilde’s

relationship with London, or Cezanne’s relationship with Paris.

Hence, urban “civilization” as we know it today is the erratic

byproduct of a particular city, not its main and distinguishing

consequence. Such a “civilization” emerges from the wayward

activities of fairly privatized individuals or corporations rather

than the innate traits of the municipality itself. A civic culture does

not stem from the collective efforts of a unique and cohesive

public, however unusual the city may be in terms of its regional

location and its historic traditions. It stems from the personal activities of certain individuals wKo happen to occupy a residence

within the city’s confines, staff its shops and offices, work its industries, and, of course, produce its artistic artifacts. Urban “civilization,” today, is not a characteristic civic phenomenon that

emerges from a distinctive public and body politic; it is simply the

exudate of free enterprise with its patina of “public service” and

cultural charity. That mayors, corporate leaders, and philanthropists may vie with each other in celebrating the projects they

initiate—projects that may range from concert halls and museums

to airports and industrial parks—is simply evidence of the shallowness of what today is called “civic-mindedness.” Rarely do these

projects, which in any case are seldom free of vulgarity, nourish

the city as a collectivity and arena for public activity. Like iridescent bubbles that rise, glisten, and burst, they form the surface of

the city’s often stagnant cultural life and social malaise.

In fact, like any marketplace, the modern city is the hectic

center of a largely privatized interaction between anonymous

buyers and sellers who are more involved in exchanging their

wares than in forming socially and ethically meaningful associations. Cities today are typically measured more by their success as

business enterprises than cultural foci. The ability of an urban

entity to “balance its budget,” to operate “efficiently,” to “maximize” its service with minimal cost, all of these are regarded as the

hallmark of municipal success. Corporate models form the ideal

examples of urban models, and civic leaders take greater pride in

their managerial skills than in their intellectual abilities.

----

This dominant entrepreneurial concept of the city has its precise

counterpart in the dominant contemporary notion of citizenship.

If we tend to view the city as our most immediate social “investment,” we expect the city to give us adequate material “returns.”

We pay our taxes with a distinct expectation of the services they

will buy. The greater the services for the money we pay, the more

profitable it is to reside in a given city. Civic amenities are clearly

measurable in terms of the number of schools, class sizes, parks,

firehouses, transportation facilities, police, crime rates, parking

spaces—indeed, in terms too numerous to inventory. When we

“buy” into a residential area, we reconnoiter it primarily for these

material and logistical amenities and secondarily, if at all, for the

cultural stimulation and sense of community it provides.

Not surprisingly, the resident of most cities today tends to develop a very distinctive self-image. It is not the image of a citizen—a historically remarkable term that I have yet to describe—but

that of a taxpayer. He or she does not have a sense of self appropriate to what we might call a public figure but rather that of a

free-wheeling investor. Doubtless, taxpayers and investors often

form many associations, but they ally with each other to advance

or protect very specific interests. Like all sensible entrepreneurs

who are involved in the business of residing in a city, they want

a favorable return for what they pay, and, as the saying goes, “in

numbers there is strength.” Accordingly, all common adages to

the contrary, they **can** fight City Hall—presumably, the place

where the corporate board meets—and, depending as much upon

their wealth as upon their numbers, they may succeed.

But beyorid this economically secure interplay of conflicting

interests and demands, the citizen **qua** taxpayer is not expected

to get deeply involved in municipal affairs. Nor does the contemporary urban environment encourage him or her to do so. A “good

citizen” is one who obeys the laws, pays taxes, votes ritualistically

for preselected candidates, and “minds his or her own business.”

This notion of appropriate civic behavior is no t merely a mutually

shared, quietistic vision of modern-day citizenship; it is a political

desideratum that, if violated, exposes—more active taxpayers to

charges of “meddling” at best and “vigilantism” at worst. Both

taxpayers and municipal officials prudently acknowledge that the

people of a city should be properly represented by efficient, specialized, and professional surrogates of “the public.” Day-to-day

power, however, resides’ precisely in the hands of these

managerial surrogates, not in their “constituencies” who increasingly acquire the anonymity and’ facelessness that the word “constituency” denotes. Like the traditional liberal concept that government is best when it governs least, so the contemporary liberal

Concept of citizenship seems to be that a “constituent” is best

when he or she acts the least.

----

Such a concept of citizenship is fraught with grave psychological as

well as political consequences. Individuals whose public lives

barely transcend the social level of mere taxpayers tend to form

very passive images of their personalities and of the natural environment around them. An increasingly disempowered citizen

may well become a quietistic and highly retiring self. A major loss

of social power tends to render a person less than human and

thereby yields a loss of individuation itself. Such constituents live

in a painfully contradictory world. On the one hand, society

becomes an intensely problematic presence in their lives. The

social realm is a potential source of war, of economic instability,

of contending factions and ideologies that may reach directly into

the most guarded niches of private life. These problems become

particularly intimate when issues such as abortion, military conscription, sexual freedom, and earning capacity invade the individual’s domestic realm.

On the other hand, while such issues rage around the “constituent,” he or she is steadily divested of the power to act upon them.

Indeed, the “constituent’s” intellectual equipment to form an assured opinion is eroded by an ever-deepening sense of personal

incompetence and public detachment. A preoccupation with

trivia—the problems of shopping, fashion, personal appearance,

career advancement, and entertainment in a thoroughly boring

milieu—replaces the more heroic stance of a socially and environmentally involved body politic. We thus encounter a twofold development: a world in which growing social power preempts concerns that were once largely within the purview of the individual

and the community, and the steady erosion of personal power and

the individual’s capacity for action. Within this paralyzing forcefield, the individual’s self-identity begins to suffer a crucial decline.

Self-recognition dissolves steadily into a grim lack of selfhood.

Inaction becomes the only form of action with the result that the

“constituent” retreats into an inwardness that lacks the substance

to render one individually functional.

A world in which personality itself resembles the **tabula rasa** of

an aimless society and a meaningless way of personal fife would

seem to raise more universal issues than the fate of the city and

the citizen. But in many respects this universality expresses itself

as a need for a larger perspective toward civic issues. The city is

not only the individual’s first social “investment”; it is his or her

most intimate social environment. Owing to its vital immediacy,

the city remains (as it has throughout history) the most direct

arena in which the individual can act as a truly social being and

from which he or she can attain the most immediate social solutions to the broader problems that beleaguer the privatized self.

Insofar as the individual’s self-definition as an empowered person

and citizen is even possible today, the civic terrain on all its levels

must be regained by its constituents and reconstituted in new

ways to render people socially operational. Civic reempowerment

of the citizen thus becomes a personal issue as well as a social one.

It Is equivalent to regaining one’s private selfhood as well as one’s

public selfhood, one’s personality as well as one’s citizenship.

----

To attain such reempowerment and self-reconstitution has its presuppositions. So much of civic participation and civic-mindedness

has been lost in this century, particularly its latter half, that we will

have to probe deeply into the buried history of the city and of

Citizenship for reference points by which to understand where we

Stand in the swirl of urbanization that surrounds us.

We will want to know what the concepts of “city” and “citizenship” really mean—not simply as ideal definitions but as fecund

ecological processes that reveal the growth of communities and

the individuals who people them—indeed, that turn them into a

genuine public sphere and a vital body politic. It is painfully characteristic of our present-day myopia that these very words, public

Nphere and body politic, have simply dropped out of our social

vocabulary. When we use them at all, we rarely seem to understand what they mean or at least meant to earlier civilizations in

which we claim to have our civic and social roots. They have been

supplanted by such terms as “electorate” and, of course, “taxpayers” and “constituents”—administrative terms that denature the

concepts of politics and community by definition.

It also behooves us to examine the kind of institutions cities

have created to foster citizenship and public empowerment. A

romarkable number of conflicting institutional issues clustered

around the city as it meandered its way through different historical forms: decentralization versus centralization, direct democracy versus representative republicanism, assemblies of the people versus councils of deputies, recall and rotation of public

officials versus lengthy tenure in office and professional fixidity.

popular management of social affairs versus bureaucratic control

and manipulation. These issues have exploded repeatedly, from

ancient times to the present, into bitter civic conflicts. They persist

in our very midst under the rubric of “reform” movement to alter

city charters and most recently as neighborhood movements to

establish “grass-roots” democracy.

We will want to know how the high ideals of a free citizenry

with a sense of place in a cherished natural environment were

variously realized and lost, often to be regained for limited periods

of time in the same area or in other parts of the world. We will

have to ask how “communal liberty” (to use Benjamin Barber s

phrase) has fared with the fortunes of the citizenry and how each

interacted with the other, for neither the city’s forms of freedom

nor the citizen can be isolated from each other without doing

violence to the meaning of both. That urbanization eventually

separated from citification to take on a life of its own and ravage

the city and countryside, ecological as well as agricultural alike

will be an abiding theme in all we shall have to explore. This

separation begins with the massive institutional, technological,

and social changes that eventually dispossessed the citizen of his

or her place in the city’s decision-making processes. Urbanization,

in effect, both presupposes and later promotes the reduction of the.

citizen to a “taxpayer,” “constituent,” or part of an “electorate.”

We shall see that urbanization yields not only a drastic colonization of the countryside but also of the city’s and the citizen s very

self-identity. Like the modern market, which has invaded every

sphere of personal life, we shall find that urbanization has swept

before it all the civic as well as agrarian institutions that provided

even a modicum of autonomy to the individual. Born of the city,

urbanization has been its parent’s most effective assailant, not to

speak of the agrarian world that it has almost completely undone.

It will be important to see the extent to which presumably

nonurban institutions, often remotely tribal in origin and rooted

in a more naturalistic society, became integral features of the

democratic city in the form of popular assemblies, neighborhood

councils, and the town meetings so redolent of an active municipalism and citizenship in our own day. Ironically, the same can be

said for feudal, theocratic, and monarchical institutions, with the

castle, temple, and palace as their centers. Indeed, we need go no

further, if we choose, than the American and French revolutions

to find that popular assemblies under different names have been

the principal means by which ordinary people fought out the

issues of justice and freedom with nobles, monarchs, and centralized nation-states. Each opposing camp has fought with the other

for civic and ultimately social sovereignty. The current legalistic

image of the city as a “creature” of the state is not an expression

of contempt. It is an expression of fear, of careful deliberation in

a purposive effort to subdue popular, democracy. That the term

has been codified into laws, even in self-professed “democracies,”

expresses a dread of a menacing civic or municipal incubus in

every centralized social system, one that has always threatened to

dismember centralized power as such and restore the control of

society to a public that has been cruelly dispossessed of its very

identity..

History is an all-important vehicle in our enterprise, the counterpart of evolution in an ecological approach. The “powers-that-be” live in a compulsive fear of remembrance, a fear of humanity’s

social memory of past institutions, cultures, and the search for

origins. An essential theme of George Orwell’s **1984** is the effort

by a highly totalitarian state to eliminate the sense of contrast

earlier lifeways imposed as a challenge to existing ones. Thinking

itself had to be restructured to exclude this challenge by using

words—Orwell’s famous “Newspeak”—that attenuated their previous wealth of meaning and the disquieting alternatives that the

past posed to a fixed, eternalized, and ahistorical “now” or commitment to “nowness.” Previously, authority had rested on tradition, often in a highly distorted form; today, it rests oil conditioning, with no regard to a troubling past.

The purpose of Orwell’s “Newspeak” Was to change thinking by

“the invention of new words and by stripping such words as remained of unorthodox meanings, and insofar as possible of all

meanings whatever,” Words such, as “free,” Orwell tells us, still

existed in “Newspeak” but not “in its old sense of‘politically free’

or ‘intellectually free,’ since political and intellectual freedom no

longer existed even as concepts and were therefore of necessity

nameless.”{1} One could only use the word “free” in a strictly functional, amoral, and technical sense, such as in the statement “This

dog is free from lice” or “This field is free from weeds.” “Newspeak was designed not to extend but diminish the range of

thought” by a process of abbreviation—by rendering concepts

more functional than moral in nature and by dememorizing

thought (if I may coin a phrase) that was designed to uproot the

mind from a sense of continuity and contrast with a challenging

past.

compromises with an emphasis on “nowness” and the cybernetic

language of electronic circuitry that is so fashionable today. The

pages that follow are thoroughly infused with history and its moral

meaning, and with language that is rich in secondary meanings.

The reader will find no words like “feedback,” “input,” “output,”

and “bottom lines,” which are currently used as substitutes for

processual and thought-laden terms such as dialogue, origins,

“explanations,” “judgements,” and “conclusions.” I have been at

pains to emphasize my use of history and traditional language for

a very distinct reason. This book deals with cities and citizenship—traditionally, the shared fate that confronts “town and country”

in the modern era—and the impact of urbanization upon personality, freedom, and humanity’s sensitivity to nature. But it is also

a book about morality and ethics. My concern with the way people

commune—that is, actively associate with each other, not merely

form communities—is an ethical concern of the highest priority in

this work. I am concerned with the “social compacts” people form

as ethical beings and the institutions they create to embody their

ethical goals.

To a great extent, this is the Greek, more precisely, the

Athenian, ideal of civicism, citizenship, and politics, an ideal, that

has surfaced repeatedly throughout history. I believe this ideal

forms a crucial challenge—despite its many limitations for the

modern era. I propose to explore not only the ills of urbanization

insofar as they have subverted town and country (including the

natural environment), alike, but to explore the social and cultural

conditions that gave rise to communities, citizens, and a politics

whose high regard for personal activism has always made community the richest and most fulfilling expression of our humanity.

Chapter Two: From Tribe to City

Conventional accounts of the city’s origins tend today to be stridently technological: they anchor the emergence of the city in the

discovery of food cultivation, particularly its highly productive

form of animal-powered agriculture. The city, it is assumed, appeared because of the large food surpluses farming folk could

provide with the Neolithic technological innovations that marked

the cultivation of the land. With this new material plentitude at

their disposal, we are told, people began to detach themselves

from agricultural pursuits and develop their skills as potters, weavers, metallurgists, carpenters, jewelers, and masons, not to speak

of administrators, priests, soldiers, and artists. As agrarian villages

increased in size and density, they are said to have reached a

“critical mass”—often of undefinable size—that apparently qualified them to be called “cities.” Generally, we tend to regard the

city itself as a sharp economic breach with the countryside,

marked by a typically urban development of crafts, administration, and, to use a grossly denatured word, “politics.” This new,

largely nonagrarian ensemble of activities produced what we like

to call “civilization”: a literate world, culturally “enlightened,”

presumably more rational institutionally and technologically than

the agrarian, society on which, it relied—in short, what the distinguished Marxian archaeologist, V. Gordon Childe, called the

“urban revolution/’

This conventional image of the city’s origins projects a highly

modern view, largely ecbnomistic and progressivistic, onto the

past. It assumes that because we are primarily, economic beings

whose civic activities are deeply rboted in industrial, commercial,

and service occupations, our urban “forebearers” gathered in

towns and cities to follow similar pursuits. They, too, we tend to

believe, conceived of the city as an economic enterprise, massively committed to nonagrarian tasks. We are prepared to concede that in a more “barbarous” era early city dwellers were also

preoccupied with their safety or defense from rival cities or pastoral nomads. Hence, they congregated in great numbers behind

defensive palisades and fortified walls. While defensive concerns

might account in part for early urban density, they too were a

function of economic concerns in modern eyes, just as we, today,

assign economic motivations to what we also call defense by

nation-states and imperialistic blocs. Thus we assume that our

urban “forebearers” were very much like us. They were economic

beings who were busily engaged in the pursuit of their material

interests within the fixed confines of a structural and territorial

entity called the “city.”

With equal alacrity we assume that just as they shared our

economic lifeways (albeit in a more rudimentary fashion), they

also shared our civic attitudes. Although we are likely to concede

that their sense of communal loyalties was stronger than ours, we

often believe that they judged their cities with a shared viewpoint

like ours. However exotic many of their civic institutions seem in

the light of our own, we tend to believe that their notion of citizenship was essentially as self-serving and self-interested as our own.

They participated in civic affairs to the degree that their material

interests were involved, and essentially their interests were no less

economic than our own. Unwittingly, we subject their civic-mindedness as well as their “civilization to the very economistic class

analyses we profess to reject in the name of our “higher ideals”

and “morals,” however much these are honored in the breach.

This view is greatly reinforced by the historical literature at our

disposal. Athens, we are reminded, had its *demos*; Home, its **plebs**;

the medieval commune, its *popolo*, just as we have our proletariat

and lower middle classes who live in gnawing envy or hatred of

their aristocratic and bourgeois elites. We are reminded that such

Lorms as “ancient,” “medieval,” and “modern” should not impel

118 to greatly distinguish the unalterable content of human nature,

that human beings will seek to satisfy their egoistic impulses despite all their ideological avowals to the contrary. This excursion

Into an unvarying psyche that lies at the core of human behavior

defines the city dweller—particularly the citizen—with the same

modern attributes that define our contemporary metropolitan

dwellers. Hence, we comfortably sit back before the vast tableau

of urban historical development with a sense of self-assurance that

Our contemporary ills are as ancestral and incorrigibly “human”

as our biological attributes and pathologies. They belong to us as

assuredly as the human brain, human fingers, and ingrained

human psychological traits that our species shares with its ancestors and with its heirs.

----

If the city provides any evidence of human association and the immutability of human behavior, a serious account of its rise and

development in no way supports this simplistic and conventional

Imagery. It would be difficult to find one all-embracing reason that

oxplains the emergence of a settled human collectivity such as a

village, much less a population of thousands that we would expect

to find in a city. The earliest cities archaeologists have unearthed

do not seem to have been based on advanced forms of food cultivation, notably animal r powered plow agriculture, a point that Jane

Jacobs has so ably highlighted in her book **The Economy of Cities.**

Although it is doubtful that an “urban revolution” gave rise to an

“agricultural revolution,” as Jacobs seems to contend, strong evidence exists that such very early cities as Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk in Anatolia

and Jericho of Biblical fame may have consisted of sizable communities that acquired much, perhaps most, of their food from the

hunting of game and the harvesting of undomesticated plants.

Much plants as were domesticated seem to have been recent

achievements of people who were harvesters of wild wheat varieties rather than experienced food cultivators. Bones of aurochs—the extinct ancestors of modern cattle—as well as those of wild

deer, boars, asses, geese, and the skeletal remains of such predators as wolves, foxes, and leopards, suggest a “citified population

of hunters and gatherers whose arts of gardening were of recent

origin. By conventional standards, this economic tableau does not

comfortably explain why a city such as Çatal, with an estimated

population of at least 6,000 people occupying some 30 acres,

should have been able to flourish on two nearby sites 9,000 years

ago, many millennia before Mesopotamia became the region for

Childe’s celebrated “urban revolution.”

If Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk is to be accorded a major place m the origins o

the city, the reason for its existence—indeed, for its persistence for

centuries—seems primarily to have been religious. Although the

city was close to a rich source of obsidian that was almost certain y

bartered for a wide variety of nonindigenous foods it is most

conspicuous for its large number of religious shrines. James Melaart, who has provided us with detailed and richly interpretive

studies of the city, found no less than 40 shrines among the 139

buildings he examined. These shrines were generally larger than

the surrounding houses and decorated with elaborate religious

artwork, paintings on opposing walls that symbolized death in one

case and life in another...

Mellaart found no pottery in Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk—one of the principal

hallmarks of Neolithic culture that, together with plow agriculture

and domesticated animals, would normally be associated with a

compact city of thousands. The thick walls of Çatal, its pueblolike

houses, its small plazas, and its ornate artwork so visible to the

public suggest an intensely vivid religious fife that is equally suggestive of an intensely active civic life. Its tool kit and higly

naturalistic artistry suggest an ecologically oriented community of

late Paleolithic hunters and gatherers rather than an early neolithic community of food cultivators. The culture is marked by a

very sophisticated stone and bone technics, by markedly collective dwellings adorned with images of animals and shamanlike

figures amidst paintings of reindeer, leopards, and bow-carrying

hunters. If we are to judge by the considerable amount of comment Çatal has elicited—owing partly to Mellaart’s own interpretations—the occupants of the city were strikingly matricentric in

their orientation. Women figure highly in the symbolism of the

city’s cults. The Mother Goddess is the most conspicuous figurine

that we find among the city’s statuettes, and careful attention

seems to have been given to the internment of women and infants

in joint graves, presumably mothers and their children, a feature

that is absent in male burials. Nor do hierarchy and warfare seem

to be features of the city’s social life. Judging from the size of

Çatal’s dwellings and the implements found in burial remains, the

city was fairly egalitarian despite minor differences that are observable. There are no “obvious signs of violence or deliberate

signs of destruction,” Mellaart observes for the original city and its

nearby successor, both of which were simply abandoned for no

apparent reason after centuries of occupancy.{2} Cases of violent

death among the hundreds of skeletons examined on the sites are

notable for their absence.

If the emergence of a city as large as Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk cannot be

explained by a high degree of technical development or by warfare, it is interesting to note that an unknown people, already

familiar with the arts of planting, harvesting, and milling grains,

did not form any kind of permanent settlements on fertile soil as

early as 18,000 years ago, when ice sheets still covered vast portions of the European continent. Evidence of food cultivators has

been found quite recently adjacent to the Nile River at Wadi

Kubbaniya in upper Egypt. They were planting wheat, barley,

lentils, and chickpeas at a time when Magdelenian hunters were

still wandering over the European tundra of Spain and France,

leaving behind their celebrated wall paintings of animals in remote cave sites. The Wadi Kubbaniya people were not Neolithic

farmers, although by every precept of technological or economic

determinism they should have been. Their “diversified agriculture did not lead directly to the beginnings of village life,” observed Fred Wendrof, Romauld Schild, and Angela E. Chase, who

unearthed the remains of these early food cultivators. “Probably

people continued their wandering ways as hunters and gatherers

for thousands of years more. Farming was just one more resource

in a broad-based way of life. These conclusions raise anew the

question of why civilization emerged.”{3}

In fact, it is fair to say that both the Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk and Wadi

Kubbaniya peoples, who may not have been particularly exceptional, raise the question, Why did “civilization” (more precisely,

the drastic change from hunting and gathering to food cultivation

and civic social relationships) emerge at all? This question seems

shrouded in mystery because the changeover from one cultural

form to another seems to be more drastic than it actually was.

What Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk and the earliest food cultivators tell us is that

the transition from tribe to village and city was not the predictable

result, as archaeological orthodoxy would have it, of technological

change or, as more recent theories would claim, of population

pressure, war, or other drastic environmental pressures that might

have produced hunger on a large scale. In short, the transition

from tribe to city was not the necessary result of economists

relationships that our Euro-American minds foist upon prehistory

and history; nor was the transition, when it occurred, as deliciously

complete and sharply delineated with polarities of a war between town and country as theoretical orthodoxy would have us

believe.

Conversely, hunting and food-gathering peoples, who by all

conventional standards of archaeology seem to have lacked the

“economic base” for an urban society, actually formed sizable

cities and initially used a technics more akin to late Paleolithic

lifeways than Neolithic. As the anthropologists who studied the

Wadi Kubbaniya sites conclude, “There does not, in fact, seem to

be any single ‘cause’ for the beginnings of agriculture [and we may

reasonably add, the city]. It may well have begun as a natural

interaction between early peoples and the plant species they

came to exploit regularly. It probably happened many times in the

past, whenever Paleolithic peoples made extensive and sustained

use of plant resources. It is important in this instance because the

plants used [by the Wadi Kubbaniya people] were cereals, and

these cereals provided the economic base for the development of

our civilization. The rise of agriculture, however, did not lead

rapidly or inevitably to identifiable social or economic change. It

simply provided another resource in a broadly based hunting,

fishing, and gathering economy.”{4} I find this conclusion, with its

wayward suggestions and its shades of heterodoxy, all the more

tantalizing because its authors do, in fact, use the conceptual

framework and terminology of traditional archaeology with its

recourse to such words as economic base, resource, and exploit.

----

Which is not to say that cities congeal out of mere mist. Clearly a

city requires a tangible food supply, one that is sufficiently plentiful to support such nonagrarian strata as artisans, administrators,

and shamanlike priests to perform their specialties. If the remains

of Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk and the Wadi Kubbaniya cereal farmers suggest

anything, however, it is that early cities formed to meet cultural

rather than strictly economic or defensive needs. The shrines so

evident at Çatal suggest that the population of the city was committed to the performance of religious rituals, that cultic and

priestly functions do more to explain why this city arose in Anatolia many millennia ago than do economic or military functions.

Paleolithic lifeways; richly elaborated by time and environmental

changes, may have been more tenacious than we have supposed

them to be. They may have been more attractive to tribal peoples,

even many self-anointed “civilized” ones, or, at least, more deeply

rooted in the long evolution of human culture.

If this conclusion is sound, the urban and agricultural “revolutions” so closely associated in the archaeological literature with

the rise of urban culture do not form an elegant fit by modern

standards. The rise of cities may have had more to do with shrines,

cultic practices, and temples rich in naturalistic symbols than with

the “discovery” of cereal cultivation, plows, and domesticated

animals. Not that the city gave rise to these agrarian basics, as Jane

Jacobs seems to suggest. Apparently, agriculture in a simple form

was known to hunters and food gatherers long before villages

began to dot the landscape that phased from the Paleolithic into

the Neolithic. But the shrine, later enclosed by a temple, may have

been more authentically a harbinger of the city than the plow, and

a quasireligious figure such as the shaman or priest may have been

an earlier civic leader than the politically astute chief. By the same

tokeri, the earliest “citizen” may have assumed his or her civic

functions as a member of a congregation rather than, as a “resident” of an urban district. The earliest civic center, in effect, may

have been a ceremonial area rather than a marketplace, a center

for the worship of natural deities and forces.

----

If this background accurately portrays the factors that gave rise to

the city and the functions of its residents, it highlights many features of early city life that contradict modern economistic biases

about urbanism, notably contemporary ones that visualize the city

as a business enterprise and its concerns as primarily fiscal or

commercial. Despite the highly sophisticated crafts that appear in

cities as differently situated in time from our own cities as Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk, there is no evidence of the existence of an internal market

within the community itself, and certainly very little beyond local

barter. A considerable amount of trade may have developed between cities or between a city and an essentially tribal community.

But trade inside the city itself was minimal or, at least, marginal.

To summarily repeat Karl Polanyi’s rich probing into what he was

to call “the anonymity of the economy in early society” and his

compelling demolition of the view that the market was necessarily

the decisive element in the founding of the city would exhibit a

lack of appreciation for the thoroughness and elegance of his analysis.{5} Indeed, according to Polanyi, no domestic marketplace appears in early cities until Hellenic times, when the Athenian *agora*

became a modest center for exchanges of goods as well as intense

civic activity. Even so, Aristotle was to regard moneymaking as an

“unnatural” urge that required public control and self-restraint.

What early city dwellers actually exchanged with each other were

services. More precisely, men and women cojointly contributed

their share to the common fund of material goods. It was this

shared pool of the means of life that constituted the economic

life” of tribal communities and early cities. People contributed, in

effect, their skills in growing food, in working wool and flax, in

crafting metals and stone, and, by no means of least importance,

their artistic and decorative talents in bejeweling and designing

artifacts for deities, priests, and members of their own community.

“Postulates” of “self-sufficiency” and the distinction between

“natural and unnatural trade” are not strictly archaic. We find

them most self-consciously and philosophically stated in Greece.

But prior to the full flowering of the Hellenic *polis*, material life

in cities was deeply embedded in the blood ties, religious obligations, mutual loyalties, magical techniques, and the intensely naturalistic sensibilities of the tribal world. Guided more by custom

than rationally vdiced strictures, these form the psychological setting and institutional carryovers for the more rationalistic civilization we later find in the Greek archipelago. This unconscious tribal

and mutualistic substrate of obligation and association was, in fact,

more forceful as a guide for human behavior than its formulation

into a sophisticated civic and political philosophy or social theory.

In the so-called “primitive” or archaic worlds, more than food

entered the “common pool,” Possibly, all things short of one’s

closest possessions, including aspects of one’s very identity, had a

highly collective aura that destined them to be shared or to be

used communally. Initially, if the city had a pronounced function

at all, it was a religious one. The strong emphasis that many anthropologists now place on political and centralized governmental

forms as institutions for efficiently redistributing produce from

ecologically different areas may be overstated. That great imperial

systems, such as those of the Incas, Aztecs, Babylonians, Egyptians,

Persians, and Chinese, were centers for collecting and redistributing a great variety of goods from highly diverse and distant ecological regions can hardly be faulted as a reality. Indeed, by imperial

times many ancient cities were as conspicuous for their warehouses as they were for their temples and palaces.

But such an emphasis on material function, like the highly deterministic strategies to explain the existence of every community

within our purview, betrays a very modern bias. It reveals a proclivity, almost an unthinking compulsion, to assign a “material

role” to every phenomenon, particularly every institution and

form of association, that exists in the past as well as the present.

Worse, it crudely downgrades the richly associative role played by

material things such as gifts, which serve to foster a much deeper

human attribute: the need to be grounded in community, to enjoy

shared sensibilities that are spiritually supportive and without

which authentic individuality is chimerical. Human personality,

which is nurtured by parental care, kinship ties, friendship, and

the assurance or security provided by personal support systems,

becomes a material thing—a manipulatable object among many

other objects and commodities—precisely when its immaterial

support systems are subverted and its traits reified. Quite an opposite case can be made for the belief, so widely promoted by contemporary “cultural materialists,” that chiefdoms, monarchies,

bureaucracies, armies, clerical hierarchies, and the unlimited investment they required were distributive agencies and processes

that served humanity’s “needs,” mythic or real. It could be more

validly shown that they reflected a mania for domination that

created mythic “needs” and systems of control on a scale so harmful to the communities they were pledged to service that they and

their legacy of waste, destruction, and cruelty now threaten the

very : existence of society and its natural fundament, Indeed the

domination of nature was to have its roots in the domination of

human by human such that a credo of domination was to embrace

the planet.

But an important caveat must be voiced here when we speak

of a mania for domination that can so facilely be used to color our

image of the early, essentially temple, cities at the dawn of civic

life. By no means is it clear that the sacerdotal hierarchies that

emerged in these cities from Erech in Mesopotamia to Teobhuacan in Mexico immediately led to a hierarchical restructuring of

the fairly egalitarian tribal or village peoples on whom they depended—peoples who built their monuments, often massive in

size; who created their plazas, dwellings, and altars; who filled

their temple storehouses, erected their walls, and shaped the

sculptures that dazzle the modern eye. That such vast efforts with

their enormous mobilizations of labor could have been made for

purposes that seem so “profitless” and “useless” by present-day

urban standards without coercion of the most authoritarian kind

seems unthinkable at first glance—so much, in fact, that all early

temples and mortuaries are normally regarded as the work of

savagely coercive rulers and brutal tyrants.

But if this imagery is certainly true well into history, we have

no reason to believe that it reflects the social relationships that

gave us our earliest cities and their cultic structures at the dawn

of history. I have described elsewhere, in great detail, how an

egalitarian society may have slowly phased into an increasingly

hierarchical one-initially theocratic, ultimately feudal, and

finally monarchical.[1] Here, I would like to emphasize that the

earliest cities were largely ideological creations of highly complex, strongly affiliated, and intensely mutualstic communities of

kin groups, ecological in outlook and essentially egalitarian and

nondomineering in character. We do not know if a sizable city

like Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk, which dates back 9,000 years, or a hugely

monumental city like Teotihuacan, which was slowly erected

around 300 B.c. and ceased to be occupied around 800 A.D.,

were originally constructed by forcibly “mobilizing” large numbers of “oppressed” villagers in surrounding communities or, surprising as it may seem, whether they were voluntary enterprises

undertaken by devout “parishioners” who viewed their civic responsibilities as a sort of “calling.” We assume that a coercive

strategy was followed by oppressive elites at the inception of city

life because we read our literary accounts of Mesopotamian and

Egyptian forced labor back into city lifeways in a misty preliterate era. It is easy to. overlook the fact that any literary tradition

of urban, life, even the very early Gilgamesh epic that dates back

to the beginnings of Mesopotamian city life, is already evidence

of a technically advanced, often coercive, society. Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk,

Jericho, Erech, Teotihuacan, Monte Alban, and Tikal, to cite cities far-removed from modern urban development in the cultured areas of the Near East and the Americas, are mysteries to

us that we try to dispel with our own motivations and social interests. Yet their archaeological remains are rich with the evidence of ideological aspirations and human relationships that

were fundamentally different from our own secular ones—cultic

and communal sensibilities that viewed “the city” (if such a word

can be used indiscriminately to encompass all sizable human settlements) as a monument to lifeways and sentiments that were

basically different from our own. Possibly, the ordinary people

who reared the monuments in the earliest of these cities were

closer in their outlook to the medieval artisans who often willingly gave of their time and skills to slowly erect over generations the great cathedrals of Europe. In either case, they speak to

a dedication that stands in marked contrast to the mentality of

the engineers and construction crews who are seeding the modern world with high-rise residential and office structures in urban areas of every continent.

[1] See Murray Bookchin: *The Ecology of Freedom* (Palo Alto: Cheshire Books,

1982), pp. 62–88

----

We are confronted, too, with the differences between early and

modern conceptions of “citizenship.” How did ancestral “citizens” of the first cities view themselves? In what sense were they

different from us—or similar to us? By asking these questions, we

encounter a problem that lacks the degree of completeness and

fixity that we find in a physical structure such as the remains of a

temple or palace. Citizenship, as we shall see, is a process, not a

reality that is reducible to a concise, single-line definition. It does

not leap into being from a vacuum, surrounded by streets for

personal display, buildings into which the sovereign individual can

retreat, and dense populations that foster personal intercourse.

Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk, in fact, had no streets at all, to cite an intriguing

feature of the city. A pueblolike city, it had small squares but no

open byways. It lacked the streets that such modernists as Marshall

Berman and Richard Sennett regard as the structural essence of

urbanism, particularly in the form of wide boulevards in which the

monadic ego of our time can display itself in dandylike fashion and

assert its “individuality.” One moved from one part of Çatal to

another over rooftops, ascending or descending ladders, entering

into the recesses of dwellings and crossing small squares.

This is a significant personal fact, not merely a structural eccentricity. Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk must have been a highly collective community. It was intensely peopled—more like a tribe than what we,

today, would call a city. Yet even by modern standards of urbanism such as size and density, it was a town, not a village. From a

historical perspective, given time and place, it was even an immense city if archaeological calculations of its populations are

remotely correct. What does this tableau mean? In what sense

were its men and women “urban”? We can surmise that they were

not mere “residents” of the city or the ancestral members of

modern-day “constituencies.” They were not burdened by the

anonymity and awesome sense of personal isolation that is the

most characteristic trait of the modern urban dweller. In some

sense, they were “protocitizens” of a highly articulated and richly

textured community in which a high sense of collectivity, nourished by such organic facts as kinship ties and a sexual division of

labor, was integrated with the civic facts of politically defined

rights and duties. They were communities in transition between

the biological realities of the tribal world, rooted in blood ties,

gender, and age groups, and the political realities of the urban

world, rooted in residential propinquity, vocational mobility, and

legal prerogatives. Early cities probably did not contain citizens in

the sense of self-empowered individuals ethically united by ideals

of civic virtue, rational in their social policies, and completely free

to participate through discourse and practice in the management

of their cities—in short, those attributes that Greek social thinkers

were to call *phronesis*, the practical reason involved in creating

and managing a community. All the evidence we have of these

protocitizens suggests that their power for social action was

largely controlled by obligations to kin groups and theocrats, their

ideals guided more by faith than reason, their sense of virtue more

pragmatic than ethical, and their social institutions more biologically derivative than cultural in character.

Yet these seemingly uncivic features provided a crucially important matrix for what was to grow into the highly sophisticated

classical notion of the “citizen.” If social empowerment seemed to

derive more from such group attributes as the family or the clan

than from personal attributes, the individual living in these cities

enjoyed a real sense of power as such, not a body of conferred

rights that were more formal and juridical than substantive. Tribal

societies are known that exhibit a high degree of respect for individual uniqueness and free will, however much custom and public

opinion seem to place limits on personal behavior. One cannot

simultaneously deny the existence of primitive individuality while

acknowledging the existence of a fairly spontaneous ego and considerable self-assertion among, say, certain hunting and gathering

communities such as the pygmies of the Ituri Forest who include

outrageously boastful men and extremely shrewd women. By

their marked presence, such personal traits as boastfulness and

shrewdness, indeed humor, gaeity, and reflectiveness, frankly contradict the conventional image of preliterate peoples as divested

of ego and personality, the modern claim to individuality. The

contemporary neurotic notion of personality may not have been

as common among so-called primitives as it is today in the metropolitan areas of Europe and America, although by no means is it

absent. But individuality certainly exists among remaining preliterate communities, albeit in a different form and faced by more

overt constraints than our own, notably where the rules of the

game are fairly explicit and mutualistic in contrast to our modern,

highly engineered society, which bombastically celebrates its formal “freedoms” and tries to ignore its lack of social concern.

----

Surprisingly, citizenship and the political forms that foster it would

be difficult to explain without looking precisely at those primal

organic institutions—particularly clanlike relationships, popular

assemblies or the various councils that spin off from them, and the

egalitarian outlook, in sum, the tribalism—that the city, in the

conventional wisdom of the recent past, was supposedly designed

to overcome. Rousseau was to pithily observe that “houses make

a town but citizens make a city.”{6} Yet he would have been no less

surprised than all the major social theorists of his day to learn that

the most important attributes, of citizenship derive more directly

from the tribal world than the village world, from rude shelters

rather than houses. Houses may make towns, even huge urban

belts that subvert the conditions for an active, participatory body

politic, but simple huts and tents—the “primitive” dwellings of

hunting, gathering, and pastoral peoples^—provided the homes for

institutions and social types that often embodied the civic ideals

we associate with citizenship.

Notions of human scale—of communities that are modest in size

and comprehensible politically and logistically to their residents

are distinctly tribalistic in character and origin. They are formed

from the idiom of a civic mentality that is rooted in familial loyalties and’extended kinship relationships. Not surprisingly, many

early cities, insofar as they leave any written account that is open

to us, are. “founded” entities. Their “ancestry” originates in a

shared deity or a delineative progenitor with some kind of personal embodiment. The Sons of Aeneas, the Trojan hero who

“founded” Rome in the city’s urban mythology, are no different

in principle than the Children of Israel and the Biblical Jacob who

was the patriarchal ancestor of the Hebrew tribes. The word “citizen,” in fact, appears sporadically, or late in the history of cities.

Quite commonly, the “citizens” of a community denoted themselves as “brothers,” a term in widespread use throughout the

Middle Ages and early Renaissance. Men and women in the towns

and cities of the past visualized their relationships in terms of

familial connections. As “strangers” began to form the majority of

urban dwellers in late classical and medieval cities, this familial

imagery with its emphasis on smallness of scale, accessibility of

person, and close-knit support systems of the kind we associate

With “humanly scaled” communities became the outlook and prerogative of urban elites, notably the municipal aristocrats and!

nobles who staked out a real or legendary claim to the city’s “founder.” Ultimately, the newer, dwellers of the city, too, formed their

own “brotherhoods” in which ties, rights, arid duties were solemnized by blood oaths and kinshiplike rituals. In time, the word

“brother” became an ecumenical form of civic address and affiliation, spanning class ties and interests.

The civic institutions that we most commonly associate with a

“participatory democracy” often reach back in almost unbroken

continuity to tribal assembles. It is fairly certain that face-to-face

assemblies of the people in ancient cities were often the keystone

of the civic institutional arch and extensions of tribal assemblages

with their remote origins in primitive egalitarian relationships. So,

100, the notions of consensus where it existed, prolonged discourse

with its goal of arriving at a commonality of views, and a sense of

agreement were pronounced features of such a radical political

(lomocracy. By contrast, councils, the representative organs of

assemblies, patently originate in the smaller assemblies of elders,

chiefs, and warriors. As contractions of the popular assembly—the

“voice of the people” as distinguished from the people themselves—they are ubiquitous features of a tribalistic view of the reduced

assembly projected into republican concepts of self-governance.

----

Yet here, too, I must add a caveat that initially seems to break the

continuity of the development from tribe to city. The city may

continue the traditions of the tribe institutionally into a rich skein

of participatory, indeed ecological relationships, but it also constitutes its antithesis biologically. The city is the perpetuator of the

kin group insofar as the latter is a parochial expression of blood ties

I hut exclude the stranger—the outsider—who cannot claim a common ancestry with the brothers and sisters. Tribalism is equatable

with familial exclusivity, not only familial solidarity. The distinction between exclusivity and solidarity is crucial here. Whether

He live or real, tribalism has its universal solvent in blood, the

medium that accords equality or *isonomia* (to use the Hellenic

term) to its members. Theoretically, one does not join a tribe; one

is born into it or, at most, adopted by it because of the services it

requires. Adoption involves elaborate rituals that transform the

outsider into an insider—an “inorganic” being, to use Marx’s formulation, into an “organic” part of the community.

The city breaks this biological spell, with its ecological aura,

however fictive it may be in reality. It exorcises the blood oath

from the family with its parochial myths and its chauvinistic exclusivity, while retaining or reworking its concept of socialization.

Paternity is given a high place in the civic firmament of values, but

the fathers are slowly divested of their absolute powers over the

sons—sons who are needed by the city to perform administrative

and military services. The stranger is denied formal legal status in

the city’s system of governance but is admitted into the magic

circle of civic protection and solicitude, especially if bearing skills,

wealth, and material resources.

But the ecological aura remains as legend by hypostasizing the

city’s founders, the ethnic continuity of its citizens, the status of

its rulers, although reality enhances the hidden powers of the

newer residents who can claim no tie to the civic progenitors.

Hence, the city creates a special kind of social space. A projection

of familial and tribal forms, the city subverts the authentic substance of the parochialism that flavors kinship ties with a mysterious inwardness and rescues tribal institutions as ecumenical forms

of civic administration. The Greek democrat, Kleisthenes, is almost a symbol of these shrewed maneuvers, maneuvers by no

means unique to the Athenian *polis*. To break the hold of family

ties that obstructed the power of civic institutions, the citizenry

was organized into territorial “wards,” but each “ward’ was felicitously called a “tribe.” The municipal space of Athens, in effect,

was expanded to create a largely civic citizenry, unencumbered

by the mindless tribal obligations and blood oaths that impeded

the rights of the stranger but in a form that wore the symbols and

enjoyed the prestige of tribal tradition. Indeed, one of the great

tasks of ecological thinking will be to develop an ecological civicism that restores the organic bonds of community without reverting to the archaic blood-tie at one extreme or the totalitarian “folk

philosophy” of fascism at the other.

Chapter Three: The Creation of Politics

Politics has acquired a fairly odious reputation among the great

majority of people today. The word seems to denote techniques

for the unsavory end of exercising power over human beings. We

“play politics” not only on an international national, and local

scale; we do so in domestic relations, in schools and places of

learning, in ordinary jobs or extraordinary careers. Politics, in

effect, is seen to have invaded the most private recesses of our

lives. At worst, it is viewed as oppressive, manipulative, cunningly

seductive, and basically degrading. Few words more readily evoke

a contemptuous sneer than the term “politician.” Conceived instrumentally as a means to control people, politics is regarded as

inherently corruptive of both its user, the politician, and the public on whom it is used. The ideal of a political life earns few acolytes

among people with any degree of moral probity. Traditional conservatives and anarchists alike identify it with the state and preach

a message of the attenuation or outright abolition of “political

power.” Liberals and socialists rarely celebrate politics as a

desideratum, but they wed it so closely to the state—a necessity

in modern liberal and socialist theory—that its practice is seen as

unavoidable in a highly imperfect world.

Modern social ideologies tend to blend politics with the state

almost unthinkingly—and often throw society into the brew for

good measure. The confusion on this score is massive. Just as there

are many people who, by virtue of the all-pervasive role the state

plays in their private lives, draw no distinction between “government” and “society,” so an incalculable number are incapable of

distinguishing between the state and “politics. These attitudes

and they are often, little more—are justified today by ordinary

experience, as we shall see. That the social, political, and “statified” are not synonymous, indeed, that they are broadly demarcatable arenas with histories and identities of their own, is so far

removed from the public’s mind that to distinguish them seems

paradoxical.[2] The equatability of political with state activities is

taken as a given. The penetration of the two, normally conceived

as one common phenomenon, into private affairs still encounters

considerable resistance, although in the form of a psychological

tension that finds expression in existential resistance such as petty

violations of the law rather than ideological clarity.

[2] How paradoxical can be judged by the fact that “statified” is a word I have had

to create for my own needs to denote the extent of the state’s penetration into

social and political life. It does not exist in the English language. This term, which

I used extensively in my *Post-Scarcity Anarchism*, produced numerous tiffs with

a dedicated editor and repeated misprints with a knowledgeable printer.

In recent years, however, serious attempts have been made to

probe the distinction between “society” and politics, which has

traditional roots in theoretical distinctions between, society and

the state. The anarchists have been saying for years what everyone

either knows or feels: the state is not the same kind of phenomenon as the family, workplace, fraternal and sororal groups, religious congregations, unions and professional societies, in short, the

“private” world that individuals create or inherit to meet their

personal and spiritual needs. This personal world can be designated as “social,” however much “government” penetrates, regulates, or, in totalitarian states, absorbs its forms. It is a world that

has deep roots in what Marx and later Hannah Arendt were to

designate as the “realm of necessity,” a world where the individual satisfies the conditions for his or her personal survival. Here,

biology provides the soil for a system of self-maintenance such that

people have a culturally conditioned but systematic way of reproducing their kind, feeding and clothing themselves, satisfying

their needs for shelter and the support systems for resisting an

inclement, presumably “cruel, mute, and blind natural world.”

----

To have sharpened the distinction between the social and the state

is one of the major contributions of traditional anarchist theory.

That there could be a political arena independent of the state and

the social, however, was to elude most radical social thinkers, even

so intense a political ‘thinker as Marx who allowed for “democratic” states that could “evolve” toward socialism and “Bonapartist” states that stood above and balanced off conflicting class interests. The reformist wing of Marxian socialism was by no means

alone when it envisioned a pliable state that could be used for

socialist interests. Its own “founding fathers’:’ were no less riddled

with uncertainties about the nature of the state than the reformists

are today.

The emergence of the political realm as unique has a complex

background in the history of ideas,. Politics as a phenomenon distinguishable from the state and from social life initially appears in

the extant writings of Aristotle, perhaps the most Hellenic of the

Greek social theorists and philosophers. With Aristotle we are still

dealing in terms of human association on the level of the city, or

to be more precise, the *polis*, which is commonly mistranslated as

the “city-state!”. [3]

[3] Quite often, in fact, the word *polis*, for which there is no comparable term in

English, is translated as *state*.

By the middle of the fifth century B.C., when the Athenian

democracy was approaching its high point of development, the

concept of a state—of a professionalized bureaucratic apparatus

for social control—was notable for its absence; Attic Greek

contains no word for state. The term is Latin in origin, and its

etymological roots are highly ambiguous. It more properly

denotes a person’s condition in life—his or her status or way

of life and “standing”—than a commonwealth or a state in the

modern sense of the term. Not until the early sixteenth century,

when we witness the rise of authentic nation-states and highly

centralized monarchies, does the word come to mean a professional civil authority with the power to govern a “body politic.”

There is a very real sense in which the evolution of the word

broadly reflects the evolution of the state itself. Not that state

powers were rarities in the ancient and medieval worlds. Eric

Vogelin’s “cosmological” empires—Mesopotamian, Egyptian,

Persian—and the more “ecumenical” Roman empire were certainly states in the sense that they controlled vast resources, dominated millions of people, and were structured along highly professional, rationalized, and bureaucratic lines. State institutions

emerged very early in human history, although in varying degrees

of development and stability, often in “bits and pieces,” as it were,

with highly tribalistic features. The Pharaonic state in the Nile

valley already reached back thousands of years, perhaps beyond

the unification of northern and southern Egypt, long before the

Roman empire had begun its long decline.

Athens had a “state” in a very limited and piecemeal sense.

Despite its governmental system for dealing with a sizable slave

population, the “state” as we know it in modern times could

hardly be said to exist among the Greeks, unless we are so reductionist as to view any system of authority and rule as statist. Such

a view would grossly simplify the actual conditions under which

humanity lived in the “civilized world.[4] Until recent times, professional systems of governance and violence coexisted with richly

articulated community forms at the base of society—city neighborhoods in the world’s few large urban areas, self-contained

towns and villages, a network of extended kinship ties, a great

variety of vocational, mutual-aid, and fraternal groups—which

were largely beyond the reach of centralized state authorities. In

fact, these distinctly social formations were necessary to the maintenance of the state. They were sources of its revenues, its military

personnel, and, in many cases, the source of many labor services

for a great variety of public and religious tasks.

[4] I use the word “civilized” throughout this book to mean literally the world of

the *civitas* or city in the broad Latin sense this term was used, not in any culturally

pejorative sense. Readers of my book, *The Ecology of Freedom*, will know that the

word denotes no monumental advance in the human condition over so-called

“primitive” societies—apart from certain technical and scientific amenities that

may have lightened humanity’s material burdens.

The Athenian democracy, if anything, was the opposite of a

professionalized system of governance organized strictly for social

control. If we choose to translate the word for the Athenian *polis*

as “state,” which is done with appalling promiscuity, we would

have to assume that the notion of a state is consistent with a body

politic of some forty thousand male citizens, admittedly an elite

when placed against a still larger population of adult males possibly three times that number who were slaves and disenfranchised

resident aliens. Yet the citizens of Athens could hardly be called

a “class” in any meaningful sense of the term. Indeed, within this

body politic, we encounter economic distinctions that run the

entire gamut of material resources from the wealthy to the impoverished.

We would also have to assume that the notion of a state is

consistent with a consciously amateur system of governance,

based on almost weekly popular assemblies, a judicial system

structured around huge juries that represent the assemblies on an

attenuated scale, the selection and rotation of civic officials by

sortition, that is, the use of the lot, and the absence of any political

professionalism or bureaucratism, including military forces that

are authentic militias of armed citizens rather than professional

soldiers.

----

These few remarks do not do full justice to the Athenian system of

democracy, notably its high level of consciousness, civicism, commitment, and esthetics. They must suffice for the present to understand how politics was created on the rare occasions when it appeared in history with a reasonable degree of authenticity, and

how it was conceived by its most renowed theorist, Aristotle. It is

to Aristotle that we must turn for the earliest known distinctions

between the social and political realms, the household and the

public arena. The state was not alien to Aristotle; it existed as

monarchy and tyranny, as everyone could see among the states

that surrounded the Athens of Pericles’s day. And they were as

easily confused with the *polis* by Aristotle and his students, just as

we, today, confuse *politikos*, the administration of the *polis*’s

affairs, with the state. What was central to Aristotle’s thought,

however, was the *polis*, not that ambiguous phenomenon, the

state. What is central to modern thought, by contrast, is the state

not politics or, strictly speaking, the affairs of administering an

entity that could pass for a *polis*. Hence, although politics and the

state intermesh in both cases, they do so in very different ways and

from remarkably different perspectives.

This distinction should not be reduced to a simple difference of

vantage points toward a shared phenomenon. Aristotle and the

modern social theorists are, in fact, looking at two very dissimilar

worlds. The difference becomes very evident in Book Seven of

Aristotle’s Politics where the proper size of the “ideal” *polis* is

discussed. Both Aristotle and most modern social theorists would

agree that a community that is very small risks the possibility, if

it relies primarily on its own resources, of inadequately furnishing

its inhabitants with the means of existence, much less providing

for the “good life,” however one chooses to interpret this highly

problematical phrase. Almost presciently, Aristotle derides, the

view that a community’s greatness is to be judged by its demographic and territorial size. Important as numbers and resources

may be, a *polis* with too large a population and area cannot have

a “good legal government.... Law [*nomos*] is a form of order, and

good law must necessarily mean good order; but an excessively

large number cannot participate in order: to give it order would

surely be a task for divine power, which holds the universe together. Hence the *polis* also must necessarily be the most beautiful with whose magnitude it combines the above-mentioned limiting principle; for certainly beauty is usually found in number and

magnitude, but there is a due magnitude for a *polis* as there is for

all things—animals, plants, tools,” otherwise it will lose “its true

nature’’ as well as workability. Summing up this remarkable body

of notions, Aristotle concludes “that the best limiting principle for

a *polis* is the largest expansion of the population with a view to

self-sufficiency that can be taken in at one view.”{7}

Probably no modern social theorist would reason out this case

for “beauty” *qua* “magnitude” and “limit” *qua* “true nature” as

the essence of a community. The ease for human scale has been

argued by heterodox urbanologists on logistical, democratic, and

esthetic grounds; but rarely, if ever, has it been argued on ethical, indeed metaphysical, grounds. A community “that can be

taken in at one view”—that is, decentralized, comprehensible,

and attractive—which Aristotle and his modern counterparts regard as a desideratum, is rooted in many, similar but also many

different premises. Aristotle speaks to us from an age that found

In magnitude and harmony the essence and, in the “true nature”

of a human community, the limit to a *polis*. An ethical pragmatism pervades Aristotle’s remarks that qualitatively differs from

the instrumental pragmatism of the modern urbanologist, however much the two share a common practical view of human consociation.

Politics, in turn, is also inseparable in Aristotle’s mind from its

ethical context. Men are “animals,” a fact that greets us early on

In the *Politics*, but they are animals of a very special kind. It is

man’s destiny or *telos*, if he is to fulfill his “true nature,” to live in

the *polis*. A *polis*, however, is more than a community or *koinonia*.

It is a *koinonia* that has reached the ideal form of a shared commonality of purpose among men whose self-realization is the “good life.”

The “good life,” in turn, includes a degree of material self-sufficiency that goes beyond mere survival. But it does not consist

in on appetite for goods, with all its attendant excesses, that clouds

man’s ethical and intellectual clarity. Man transcends his animality

insofar as he has reason and speech, or *logos*, which combines both

lit tributes in the ability to symbolize verbally and generalize logically. But these abilities do not guarantee that man has reached or

oven approximates the fulfillment of his potentialities. Institutions

must exist that constitute the means for achieving human self-fulfillment; a body of ethics must exist that gives the required

Institutions substance as well as form; a wealth of social activities

must be cultivated in the civic center or *agora* of the *polis*, the

gymnasium, and in the theater as well as the popular assembly and

courts to nourish, interactions and discourse; a mode of character

development and education, both of which are combined in the

(Ireek word *paideia*, must be at work to enrich the interactions

among men and thereby foster the growth of ethical and intellectual insight.

Underlying these various “means” is Aristotle’s emphasis on

human solidarity or *philia*, which includes friendship (the common English translation for the Greek term) but which is a word

more far-reaching in its connotation of civic commonality. The

Intimacies of friendship may be reserved for a limited few, but

which is to say that he is destined not only to live in a community

but also to communize. In criticizing Lylcophron the Sophist, who

contends that the *polis* is a “mere alliance” among men to prevent

them from inflicting harm on each other (Hobbes’s later view of

the “social contract”) and promote the exchange of goods to satisfy

their individual needs, Aristotle argues that the *polis* is an end in

itself, the realization of man’s need for consociation apart from its

material benefits. “If men formed the community and came together for the sake of wealth,” he declared, “their share in the

that the argument of the champions of oligarchy would appear to

be valid... ; but if on the other hand the *polis* was formed not

for the sake of fife only but rather for the good life... and if its

object is not military alliance for defence against injury by anybody, [and] it does not exist for the sake of trade and of business

relations,” the *polis* would be more than a community and its

citizens would “take civic virtue and vice into their purview.”

Indeed, lacking a concern for “civic virtue and vice,” men would

form communities no different from those of animals or slaves,

who are simply concerned with survival. Communities united by

mere economic and military alliances—and, here, Aristotle has the

Etruscans and Carthaginians in mind—would be no different from

the associations other people establish who, for all “agreements

about imports and covenants [to abstain] from dishonesty and

treaties... for mutual defence,” have no “officials in common” and

take no “concern as to the moral character of the other.”{8}

By contrast, the household is the sphere of mere survival, the

place to which our *zoon politiken* repairs to satisfy his biological

need for food, clothing, shelter—in sum, the “realm of necessity”

to cite Marx’s commonly used phrase. It is the domain of the man’s

wife, children, kin, and slaves where an apolitical “kingship” (patriarchy) prevails. Here, the man’s relationship between his own

person and the members of his domestic group is determined not

by *logos* but by need, and the social tie is strictly one of “ruler”

and “ruled.” “The family,” we are bluntly told by Aristotle, “is the

association established by nature for the supply of men’s everyday

wants...”{9}

But men aspire for more and accordingly group their families

together to form villages. To the extent that villages are transformed by man’s potential for the good life into ethical and cultural communities, the *polis* begins to appear. The family still exists

to satisfy man’s animal wants. Hence the two worlds of the social

and political emerge, the latter from the former. Aristotle’s approach to the rise of the *polis* is emphatically developmental and,

in this way, resembles Plato’s account of the rise of the “ideal

whole from the growth of a social and biological part, a realm of

the latent and the possible. Family and village do not disappear in

Aristotle’s treatment of the subject, but they are encompassed by

the fuller and more complete domain of the *polis*.

[5] Literally, *politea*. The word *republic*—the Latin for *res publica*, literally *public things*—has no meaning or analogue in Greek, and, in this writer’s view, no

place in the title of Plato’s famous dialogue.

The distinction between the social and political in Aristotle’s

thinking is strikingly processual: the difference is explained by the

growth and development of the social into the political, not by

their polarization and mere succession. The state has not yet

emerged in a form that gives it a uniqueness apart from the other

two domains. “Buie” properly belongs to the family. Where it does

appear in the *koinonia*, it is simply a brute extension of the patriarchal family to the civic world (*monarchia*) or it takes the form

of a despotism ruled by a tyrant (*tyrannos*). And Aristotle views

monarchies and tyrannies as warped or unfinished forms of civic

administration that are unbecoming to a *polis*, although rule by

a monarch with its traditional constraints on the ruler is to be

preferred to rule by a tyrant, which is the arbitrary supremacy of

one man.

Nor does he prefer the rule of the few over the many—an

aristocracy at best and an oligarchy at worst. By the same token,

democracy that Aristotle understands to be the rule of the many

over the few—specifically, a condition where the “poor” rule over

the “wealthy”—is by no means desirable, although he does not

seem to find it as abhorrent as arbitrary one-man rule.

The best-ordered *polis* is structured around a system of governance where the most ethically and materially meritorious stratum

of the population manages the *polis*’s affairs in the interests of all.

This “polity” or “meritocracy,” as it has been called, is an ethical

union that simultaneously yields the “good life” in a moral and

material sense. Politics consists of the practical reason (*phronesis*)

and action (*praxis*) that enters into such a felicitous *koinonia*.

----

Athenian politics was nothing if it was not vital, indeed voluble, and

popular in every sense of the term. Within a span of some three

centuries, the Athenian people and their renegade aristocratic

surrogates such as Solon, Kleisthenes, and Perikles were to dismember the traditional feudal system of Homeric times, wage a

steady war against privilege within the citizen body, and turn the

popular assembly from a lifeless, rarely convened mass meeting

into a vital on-going forum for making major decisions, thereby

opening public life to every Athenian adult male. Power ceased to

be the prerogative of a small, well-born stratum of the population.

It became a citizen activity. Athens’s historic calendar is marked

by seething upsurges of the people, startling fluctuations between

aristocratic rule, tyranny, limited popular government, until, by

the latter half of the fifth century B.C., Athenian political life stabilized around a face-to-face democracy of the most radical kind. We

may assume that similar developments occurred: in many Hellenic

In any case, in recorded history we have no structure comparable to the Athenian democracy. Popular assemblies such as the

New England town meeting and the Parisian revolutionary sections of 1793–94 were to appear elsewhere over time. The Swiss

Confederation is one of the few among many aborted or incomplete examples where popular control formed the underpinnings

of an on-going political system. Athens, however, is unique historically in that the *polis* fostered a degree of citizen participation not

only in the decision-making activities of the assembly but in the

everyday politics of the *agora* that impelled its admirers over the

ages to regard it with uncritical adulation as evidence of a “pure”

democracy—and its opponents as evidence of a horrendous

“mobocracy.”

If politics is taken to be a form of popular activity in administering public life that, strictly speaking, is neither a, state, conceived

as a highly professionalized system of governance, nor a “society,”

conceived as forms of personal association for promoting survival

and well-being, the Athenians’ could be said to have literally

created politics. It was a parochial politics by modern “global”

definitions of the term: civic rather than regional in,scale, limited

to a minority of the population, Hellenic in its purview of the

“civilized” world, contemptuous of slaves, women, the “barbarians” beyond the confines of the Greek *ethnos*, and resident aliens

who performed much of skilled work and engaged in most of its

trading activities.

Qualitatively, however, Athens made up in depth what it lost

In scope. It may well be, as the Jewish Zealots were to believe, that

a special insight of a spiritual or moral nature is the privilege not

Of great empires but of small communities on the margins of the

great classical ecumenes. Both peoples, the Hellenes and the Israelites, provide visible evidence of the truth that may be hidden

In this seemingly self-serving conviction. Yet a “creation” had

Certainly emerged that opened a new dispensation in human

affairs. A new realm of life had appeared, the political realm,

winch was to acquire many different meanings but whose origins

in classical Greece still keep faith with the pristine values and

practices that impart meaning to those ill-used words, the “public

sphere.”

The Roman Republic, which looms high in its impact on the

Euro-American political tradition, stands in marked, contrast to

the Athenian notion of a public sphere., Polybius, the Greek

chronicler of Rome’s rise to world hegemony, offers us the classical

theory of republican, government, a theory that was to deeply

affect the thinking of American and French constitutionalists in

the eighteenth century.

According to Polybius, the virtues of monarchy were embodied

III the consuls, the two chief magistrates of the Republic. The

Sonate provided the Republic with the advantages of aristocracy,

with its gradations in descending order of consular, praetorian,

aedilitian, tribunitial, and quaestorial ranks. The image of the

Roman Senate freely debating public issues is essentially a myth:

no senator could voice his views on an issue unless the presiding

consul solicited his opinion, and these requests were directed in

a strict hierarchical sequence that often left little time for oratory

by the body’s lower orders. Finally, democracy was represented

by several assemblies of the people. These assemblies (some four

have been identified) reflected, in their variety and ascendancy,

the fortunes of the plebeians and other lowly orders in their conflicts with the ruling patriciate. Whatever their origins, Roman

popular assemblies elected all the magistrates of Rome, some of

whom, such as the tribunes and praetors, had enormous control

over other branches of the government during their heyday.

Assemblies could be used by ambitious politicians to bypass the

Senate and enact laws that the ruling oligarchies opposed. Hence,

two political strategies existed during the more fervent periods of

the republican era: an oligarchical one and a popular one. The

of republican times. A complex mix of weighted voting groups

sorted out according to military status and, later, according to

classes based on property and age, the assembly was highly structured along hierarchical lines. It elected Rome’s consuls, praetors,

and censors—each successively forming the most important or

prestigious magistrates of the republic. The elective functions of

the *comitia centuriata* were to be slowly supplanted by the Roman

tribal assembly, the *comitia tributa*, largely based on territorial

divisions in which 35 tribes were classified into 31 rural tribes and

4 urban ones. Coexisting with both of these ranked assemblies, the

<em>plebs</em> had their own exclusive *concilium plebis* from which all

patricians were excluded. The *concilium* chose its own tribunes

and aediles, the latter constituting officials who administered public works and police and took charge of the grain supply and games

that gave the city such ill-famed distinction.

We owe the word “plebiscite” (*plebiscitia*) to the right of the

plebeian tribunes to submit laws for the approval of the *concilium*.

Either the *Campus Martius* along the westward bend of the Tiber

or the Forum constituted the principal meeting places for these

assemblies, and discussion, if it occurred at all, was minimal. Laws,

edicts, declarations of war were presented to the people by officials such as consuls, praetors, and tribunes; elections and confirmations were voted upon methodically. We cannot say with certainty that Roman popular assemblies were simply mute. Before

the assemblies divided into their specific units, the highly structured *comitia* was preceded by a loosely organized *contio* where

discussion may have been possible. “The *contio* may be a survival

of an early form of assembly,” opined the late Lilly Ross Taylor,

“like that of the Homeric warriors or the Spartans of later times,

in which men expressed their opinion by shouting.”{10} If so, the

highly talkative Athenian assembly. Indeed, Greek observers of

Roman procedures found the difference between the *contio* and

“Greek writers on Roman institutions have difficulty with the

word *contio*.”{11} Polybius and Dio Cassius were to call the assemblies by one word, *demos*, or, simply, the people. Appian, an Alexandrian Greek, and Plutarch, who was born in Boeotia, seem to

have been removed sufficiently from the traditional *polis* to designate the Roman assembly form as an *ekklesia*, the Greek word for

the popular assembly that, as Ross emphasizes, “combined speaking and voting.”{12} If the *contio* was anything like the Homeric and

Spartan assemblies, it did more listening than speaking, voicing its

approval by acclamation and shouts rather than by oratory.

Polybius’s association of the Roman assemblies with democracy

Is specious. The republic had no democratic component in the

Hellenic sense of the term, and speech, while relatively free, was

more an affair of delivering elitist rhetoric to manipulable audiences in the Forum than the verbal interchange of political equals.

A face-to-face relationship, between active citizens for the purpose

of arriving at a consensus is alien to republican systems of government. A democracy is participatory; a republic, representative.

The first involves the exercise of power directly by the people; the

Second, its delegation to selected surrogates, who then *reconstitute* the political realm that initially existed at the base of the

at its summit. Republics are beyond the immediate reach of popular control; democracies are not even confronted by the issue of the displacement of power.

Rousseau, with barely concealed irony for the French *philosophes* who were so endeared to English constitutionalism, was to

draw these distinctions sharply. “Sovereignty, for the same reason

as it makes it inalienable, cannot be represented. It lies essentially

in the general will, and will does not admit of representation: it is

either the same, or other; there is no intermediate possibility. The

deputies of the people, therefore, are not and cannot be its representatives: they are merely its stewards, and can carry through no

definitive acts. Every law the people has not ratified in person is

null and void—is, in fact, not a law. The people of England regards

itself as free: but it is grossly mistaken: it is free only during the

election of members of parliament. As soon as they are elected,

slavery overtakes it, and it is nothing.”{13}

The Roman cult of *libertas* is structured around personal freedom/not political. An individual can exercise a wide range of

choices in vocations, responsibilities, and the satisfaction of tastes.

Roman license during the Empire, with its almost psychotic appetite for ‘extremes, merely expanded this cult into a way of life.

Credo was warped into extravagant practice with the result that

the state soon found it ceased to enjoy the support of its citizenry.

Its citizens fled from military service, public obligations, tax levies,

and the most minimal communal responsibilities. Accordingly,

every aspect of government had to be professionalized, Under the

Empire, Rome’s troops were mercenaries, increasingly of alien

birth and culture; its bureaucracy became an elaborate apparatus,

staffed by numerous ex-slaves who had acquired the skills for political affairs that their former masters lost and that Roman citizens generally neglected.

This extraordinary erosion of personal competence blemishes

every aspect of the imperial era. But even the republic prepared

the way for Rome’s decline, In the political sphere, Roman *libertas*

never became freedom, the Greek vision of *eleutheria* based on

equality. One searches Latin for a term other than *libertas* or

collective and weighted units of the *comitia* and councilium. The

search is a vain one. The Roman concept of political life is corporatist, even statist, to the core, and there is no reciprocal interaction between the personal and the political.

To find an individual who has room for a political fife, we turn

to the Roman noble or well-born for examples. Here, political life

is obligatory—indeed, apart from war, the authentic calling of an

aristocrat. Hence it is to be conceived as a profession and suffers

from the very professionalization of politics that Greek democrats

tried so assiduously to avoid. Young men of patrician lineage were

trained from birth in diction and rhetoric, physical fitness and

military skills, amiability and the. arts of influence. Overly mannered and self-conscious, they were taught to gain favor with the

powerful and befriend the potentially influential. By degrees, they

were initiated into legal skills and affairs together with martial arts

and the> postures of command. Polybius advises us that ten years

of military service are necessary before a man can aspire to a

political career—a prerequisite that was mercifully abbreviated in

the later years of the Republic. One then went into the service of

a provincial governor and moved onward, at home, to a minor

magistrate or a military tribune.

To become a praetor was the “next obligatory office,” as Taylor

puts it, followed by the consulship, if at all possible. Between

times, one held important offices in the provinces where the opportunities for enrichment and plunder were immense. These

broad outlines of the nobleman’s training and career could be

painted with details that more appropriately describe politicking,

rather than politics. The right friends, devoted clients, and suitable personal connections were critically important in achieving public office and political renown.

Even more significant than the Roman cult of *libertas* was the

Roman cult of *amicitia*, the Latin word for “friendship.” Career

success depended not only upon lineage and wealth but also on

the elaborate system of friends and shared obligations a rising

patrician developed. I use the word “system” advisedly to single

out the complex machinery of personal ties and interactions on

which the whole structure of rule was based. Roman “politics”

must be seen as a network of clients and associates rather than

dubs and parties. The fierce differences between factions in the

Republic, that finally brought it to ruin were more personal in

nature than political. Cicero’s allusions to the *partes* of the *populores* and the *optimates* (the “parties” of the “people” and “aristocrats,” to use these terms in a modern sense) are evidence of

differences in methods of manipulation rather than programs.

None of the nobles, with the exception of the brothers Gracchi,

over tried to really shift political power from the patrician elite to

the populace. Indeed, Roman politicians were rarely burdened by

Nontimentality for the oppressed or the plight of the commoners.

To use the people for personal ends and career ambitions, however, was a widespread technique, not only during republican

times but also during the imperial era. Nor were the Roman people the worse For the use of such demagogic tactics. Nobles gave

immense quantities of their wealth to gain popular support against

their rivals. A steady flow of emoluments, gifts, festivals, and

games came to be expected by the Roman people as a characteristic feature of politics. Roman client and gift politics, in turn, accelerated the degradation of the citizenry, fostering an appetite

for sensationalism and brutality that emerged in marked contrast

with its traditional republican spirit and virtues. “Public things” or

“thing” to be sold, bought, and pilfered. In this respect, the Empire changed very little in Roman “politics.” It merely made the

process of demoralization, vulgarization, and pilfering more systematic and orderly.

Early Rome did not produce a breed of kindly men—nor, for

that matter, did Athens and other Greek *poleis*, Kindness and

sentimentality are not classical traits. Obligation and duty are the

preferred personal attributes of the ancient world. But these attributes did create an ideal of a highly committed, morally certain,

and fiercely independent yeomanry. The landholdings of these

yeomen provided the material competence for a solid independence of mind and a sense of community rootedness. Behind the

more distinguished names of early republican Rome, such as Cincinnatus, who left his farmstead for vigorous public service, were

the stern traditions of family cults, civic deities, and an unblemished ancestry—a lineage to be cherished because it exhibited

soldierly simplicity and agrarian virtues. *Dignatas* and *honorare*

were to be prized over wealth, social status, and public esteem,

although invariably such rewards came with family probity.

These stern and dutiful farmers were to fill the legions commanded by Scipio in the brutal wars with Carthage. They were the

fodder of costly, long-term, and debilitating conflicts that brought

ruin to their farms and the destruction of their social moorings.

Thereafter, an unyielding patriciate, too urbane to value the innocent simplicity of its own rural ancestors, effaced what the Punic

Wars had largely undone—the ideals of republican virtue and the

agrarian material conditions in which this sense of virtue and duty

was rooted. Cincinnatus belonged to a social world rather than a

political one. Governance in his day was seen as a domestic responsibility in which a public servant tended to the needs of the people

more as a father than an administrator. Such men became short-lived *dictatori* without ever establishing dictatorships; they

promptly went back to their farms after answering the call to

public service. They did not thirst for power, much less professionalize it.

But Rome could not strike the balance between aristocratic

values and public rights achieved by Athens. More precisely,

Rome failed to turn the governance of the *civitas* into a genuinely

political community. Men like Cincinnatus were to lose not only

the landholdings that gave them independence of mind and spirit;

they were to lose the social base for public commitment without

developing a politics that could control and contain the new civic

dispensation that was forming around them. Like Athens, Rome

was to grow—and, like Athens, it was to be brought into a broad

regional theater of power relationships and responsibilities. But

where Athens drastically reworked its yeoman society into a vital

public realm that fostered active citizenship among all its social

elements, Rome permitted its yeomanry to dissolve into rootless

constituencies and its public fife to languish. A republic rather

than a democracy came into existence with a degree of administrative ingenuity unprecedented in the history of jurisprudence,

efficiency, and military prowess. But for this achievement it paid

a penalty that ultimately spelled its death. The late Roman Republic was not a world that could nourish a Cincinnatus or even a

Marcus Portius Cato, whose writings are filled with denunciations

of Rome’s moral debasement, lasciviousness, and extravagance.

Politics was claimed almost exclusively by the patriciate and jealously guarded from any serious invasion by the people. In this

sonse, republican Rome was true to itself: like all elitist regimes,

it would have been exceptional if it failed to turn from an increasingly oligarchical republic into a completely despotic empire.

----

Athens and Rome ultimately became legendary models for two types

of “popular” government: a democracy and a republic. And later

social theorists and political practitioners who had lost any monarchic proclivities were to clearly favor a republican system of governance over a democratic one.

But democratic notions of a body politic did not disappear.

They were to surface from the depths of a popular “underground”

of deviant Christian sects throughout ‘the Middle Ages, such as the

Brethren of the Free Spirit, Anabaptist movements, and blatantly

anarchic conventicles during the Reformation Era. Like Athens,

they were not without their flaws: elites are to be found within

elites, saints within larger communities of believers, and the like.

Nevertheless, village democracies kept alive strong traditions of

popular assemblies that may have been inherited from distant

Neolithic and similar institutions’and that also emerged in many

medieval towns. The notion of the “people” or *demos* did not

disappear. The ideals of “popular rule” were to linger on from

classical antiquity well into modern times.

More commonly, however, republican theories of governance

were hybridized with democratic notions, and they were to produce rising demands of self-governance with institutions that were

redolent of democratic Athens. Machiavelli’s **Prince** and **Discourses** glitter with a fascinating mixture of republican and democratic ideas, largely translated into the virtues of his beloved

Roman Republic, His aversion for the idle nobility is pronounced.

Politics, in Machiavelli’s eyes, is not the fare for the slothful, ignorant, and crested boors who are the fatuous heirs of titles and

aristocratic pedigrees. It is a highly skilled craft that must be exercised as gently by the prince in his relationship with the people

as it must be exercised ruthlessly by him in his relationship with

his rivals. Machiavelli’s demand for a total commitment by his

chosen sovereign to politics reflects the emergence of a new kind

of man, the Renaissance prince: secular, keenly intelligent, skillful,

and cunning. He is a man of reason rather than faith, of judgement

rather than belief, and self-reliance rather than dependency, A

new political dispensation is in the air, a modern one, that draws

its precedents from the senatorial party of the early Roman Republic rather than the sacerdotal party of the medieval church.

Machiavelli’s references are to Scipio, not to Augustine; to Livy,

not Aquinas.

But within this republican idea of a meritocracy, Machiavelli

advances for sixteenth-century Italian concepts that could be

found in Perikles and the Athenian commitment to amateurism.

Comparable only to his, hatred of the nobility is his hatred of

mercenaries who were plaguing and plundering Italy in his day—professional soldiers. The most commanding need of a well-ordered state, he tells us, is a citizen-army. Mercenaries are as

unreliable as they are unscrupulous. They are born plunderers

who have no allegiances other than those that money can buy.

“Mercenary captains are either very capable men or not,” he

declares; “if they are, you cannot rely on them, for they will always

aspire to their own greatness, either by oppressing you, their master, or by oppressing others against your intentions; but if the

captain is not an able man, he will generally ruin you. And if it is

replied to this, that whoever has armed forces will do the same,

whether these are mercenaries or not, I would reply that as armies

are to be used either by a prince or by a republic, the prince must

go in person to take the position of captain, and the republic must

send its own citizens. If the man sent turns out to be incompetent,

it must change him; and if capable, keep him by law from going

beyond the proper limits. And it is seen by experience that only

princes and armed republics make very great progress, whereas

mercenary forces do nothing but harm, and also an armed republic submits less easily to the rule of one of its citizens than a republic armed by foreign forces.”{14}

Machiavelli’s argument clearly tips toward a republic and an

armed citizenry rather than a prince and a professional army.

Clearly, if princely government was central to his concerns, the

prince’s competence would normally be beyond any legal assessment. There would be nothing that could prevent him from

“going beyond the proper limits,” indeed, to tolerate any limits at

all. Nor could Machiavelli, whose mind was steeped in the Greek

and Roman classics, have been unmindful that the Athenian military forces, in contrast to the Roman imperial ones, were structured around clearly accountable captains who were strictly regulated by law, indeed by the *ekklesia* or popular citizen-assembly.

Amateurism takes high priority over professionalism and political

Institutions, visibly peopled by a free, and an armed, citizenry,

over a state power with its mercenary bureaucrats and soldiers.

Machiavelli undoubtedly had his eyes sharply focused on Italy and

the cause of national independence, but his feet were firmly

planted in his beloved Florence and the cause of freedom. The sap

flowed, as it were, from the roots upward—from city to nation—with the result that a republican, even princely, state was nourished by and mixed with civic democratic notions.

----

Ideologically, the hybridization of two very distinct and potentially

conflicting classical ideas of public governance arises from a serious confusion over what we mean by politics and statecraft.

The rise of the nation-state from the sixteenth century onward

greatly altered the entire framework of political discourse. The

basic unit of public governance was the city, not larger entities

such as the province, nation, or empire. A citizen’s allegiances to

gover nin g institutions could be comfortably enumerated as a very

distinct hierarchy of loyalties. He was first and foremost a townsman. The town was the authentic and most meaningful locus of his

personal and public life. Only secondarily did he identify himself

with a province or a region. The idea of “nationality” was at best

vague, that is when it existed at all. Romans in the most far-flung

reaches of the empire consistently visualized themselves as citizens of the imperial city. Among the Greeks, civic loyalty was

virtually all-consuming: Athenians, for example, sharply and disdainfully distinguished themselves from Spartans or Corinthians,

a sentiment that was freely reciprocated by all citizens of other

who were to pave the way for Christianity insisted well into

Roman times that civic loyalty defiled the novel notion that all

men were brothers. But the Stoic notion and its very novelty has

the ring of an ideological protest against the more popular view

that citizenship implies a primary loyalty to one’s town, not to a

vagary called “humanity.”

The rise of the nation-state altered this hierarchy of loyalties—and, with this change, the way in which politics was conceived.

Not that ancient and medieval civic parochialism was an unblemished desideratum. Parochialism had a very harmful, often dehumanizing, effect on urban life generally. The tendency to set one

city against another fostered local chauvinism with such pathologies as ethnic antagonisms, wars, and cultural introversion. In a

world where the city produced a deep sense of ethnic and cultural

identity that compares with the modern world’s most strident

forms of nationalism, the conquest of one city by another often

terminated in the sheer annihilation of a people as a distinct community. Rome’s total destruction of Carthage in the last of the

Punic wars was not merely the dismantling of a major ancient city;

it was the enslavement and total effacement of a people—of their

identity, culture, traditions, uniqueness, indeed their very claim to

exist. Jericho, Troy, and Jerusalem were to suffer similar fates, to

cite only the most well-known examples of what urban destruction

often meant in the early and classical worlds—an act of devastation comparable only to genocide in the modern world.

With the rise of nationalism and the nation-state, the state

began to assume ideological preeminence over the city, and even

radical social thinkers began to formulate their political ideologies

in broad territorial or national terms. Puritan revolutionaries

thought of their “rights” not as citizens of London, which formed

the real center of parliamentary unrest against the court, but as

“Englishmen.” Puritan theory, based on a doctrine of natural

rights, formulated these “rights” not in the characteristically civic

forms of popular assemblies and politics based on personal intimacy; a nation, “England,” was conceived as the legendary victim

of invading “barbarous” Normans who had crossed the channel

from France some five hundred years earlier and imposed a royal

tyranny on a representative system of Saxon self-governance. The

Combatants in the revolution expressed their loyalties in terms of

their adherence to “parliament” or the “court.” Larger-than-life

Institutions, far beyond the reach of the ordinary citizen, began to

Supplant the civic institutions within which some kind of face-to-face democracy was feasible. Republicanism, in effect, was a radical ideology of nations rather than cities and statecraft became the

“politics” of highly centralistic state structures.

It is hard to overstate the amount of intellectual mischief the

extension of the word politics, basically rooted in the civic life of

the *polis*, produced when it was permitted to encompass statecraft. Classical politics always implied the existence of a body

politic—in its own way, a kind of ecological community in the

social sense even in Rome, when the words **<em>populus** Romanus</em>

came to mean little more than an aristocratic oligarchy. The classical notion of a body politic was not a euphemism for an “electorate” or a “constituency,” as it is today; it was a real, physical, and

clearly observable entity. It could be seen daily in public squares

where heated discussions over political issues intermingled with

the chitchat of personal and business problems; it assembled with

almost weekly regularity on a hillside of Athens, the Pnyx, where

meetings of the *ekklesia* were convened, or it gathered in open

spaces of the Roman Forum where the **comitia tributa** often held

its sessions. It could be heard quite audibly, whether by acclamation in Sparta, arguments in Athens, or even in the most despotic

of Rome’s imperial periods when the hoots and shouts of commoners at the Coliseum reminded the emperors that they were not

beyond the reach of public criticism. In more militant times, this

body politic rioted in Rome’s St. Peter’s Square during the Middle

Ages and stormed into Florentine churches to hear the sermons

of Savonarola during the Renaissance. In short, the body politic

existed in the literal sense that it was a tangible, protoplasmic

entity that expressed its concerns in the eye-to-eye contact of

personal confrontation and fervent discourse.

This eye-to-eye contact of active citizens was an organic politics

in its most meaningful, protoplasmic, and self-fulfilling sense. Political assemblies were not mere audiences on which public officials practiced their arts of statecraft; they were legislative communities united by a reasonable commonality of shared, public

interests and ethical precepts. That political life had worked its

way out of social life to acquire a distinct identity of its own and

presupposed social forms as its underpinnings is evident enough

from any account of the *polis* or its near-equivalent in the medieval city-state or “commune.” But even so conservative a thinker

as Aristotle never confused a family or a workshop with the *agora*,

where public affairs were normally discussed, and the *ekklesia*.

Where the body politic physically assembled to make public decisions. Hence, the Greek *polis* was never a state in any modern

sense of the term with professional surrogates for an assembled

body politic, nor was it a social entity such as a “family” that united

the people into an authentic kin group. Aristotle’s notion of *philia*

or solidarity as a crucial precondition for a political life expressed

the unique identity politics possessed as a form of governance, one

That transcended mere kinship obligations. If kinsmen were obligated to each other by virtue of blood ties and tribal custom,

citizens were obligated to each other by virtue of civic ties and

ethical precepts.

If politics can be said to have emerged from society in the strict

sense that I use the latter word to denote familial, vocational, and

sociable relationships, so statecraft can be said to have emerged

from politics conceived as the activities of a directly involved body

politic. Aristocracies, monarchies, and republics ultimately dissolve the body politic as a participatory entity, an essentially ecological phenomenou into an amorphous mass of privatized “social” beings we so aptly call an electorate or a constituency. The

“deputies of the people” replace the people, to use Rousseau’s

pithy formulation, and bureaucratic institutions replace popular

assemblies. The identity of politics as a unique phenomenon to be

distinguished from other, presumably “social” activities, is not a

concept that was confined to classical thinkers such as Aristotle. It

is a recurring and often perplexing problem that appears in the

writings of Rousseau, in constitutional documents of the past that

distinguish between “active” (propertied) citizens and “passive”

(propertyless) citizens, and today, most strikingly, in the writings

of a highly gifted political philosopher, Hannah Arendt.

What is so curious about this literature and its attempt to single

Out politics as a clearly identifiable area of public activity is the

extent to which it is burdened by the institutional weight of the

nation-state. Arendt’s distinction between a “political realm” and

one that is “social” allows for very little difference between political activity and statecraft. The state has so thoroughly merged

with the political—institutionally and functionally—that the two

almost seem identical. What is remarkable is that modern social

theory does not find this congruence of very different arenas of

public governance problematical. Clear as the old Aristotelian

distinction between the social and political may be, the equally

crucial distinction between the political and the statist tends to be

lost in the modern literature on politics. Political activity and

statecraft have become so thoroughly intermixed in theory and

l’Oality that the present-day usage of the word “politics” is taken

to be the “art” of the politician, who, for all practical purposes,

replaces the body politic. That the state historically depoliticized

tills body politic and essentially disbanded it institutionally seems

like a meaningless ideological curiosity in a world where political

activity” takes the form of an on-going battle of political gladiators

in a strangely muted, almost empty arena.

Perhaps the main reason why the confusion between politics

and statecraft persists so strongly today is that we have lost sight

of the historic source and principal arena of any authentic politics—the city. We not only confuse urbanization with citification, but

we have literally dropped the city out of the history of ideas—both

in terms of the way it explains the present human condition and

the systems of public governance it creates. Not that we lack any

valuable histories of the city or attempts to evaluate it sociologically. But our urban literature generally neglects the relationship

between the city and the remarkable phenomenon of citizenship

it produces. Urban historians tend to fixate on largely narrative

accounts of the city’s development from village to megalopolis—accounts that are riddled by nostalgia for the past or a brute acceptance of existing urban conditions and the future they portend.

The notion that the city is the source of immensely provocative

political, ethical, and economic theories—indeed, that its institutions and structures embody them—is generally alien to the modern social theorist.

An ethical interpretation of historical urban standards must

highlight one central issue: the need to recover civic forms and

values that foster an active citizenry. This amounts to saying that

we must recover politics again—not only the social forms of personal intercourse that underpin every kind of human activity. The

city, conceived as a new kind of ethical union, a humanly scaled

form of personal empowerment, a participatory, even ecological

system of decision making, and a distinctive source of civic culture—this civic notion of community must be brought back again into

the history of human ideas and practical wisdom. It must be critically reexamined as a realm of thought and activity that gives rise—as it did in various periods of history—to political consociation,

a politics that places family, work, friendship, art, and values

within the larger context of a rounded civic world. Politics, in

effect, must be recreated again if we are to reclaim any degree of

personal and collective sovereignty over our destiny. The nuclear

unit of this politics is not the impersonal bureaucrat, the professional politician, the party functionary, or even the urban resident

in all the splendor of his or her civic anonymity. It is the citizen—a term that embodies the classical ideals of *philia*, autonomy,

rationality, and, above all, civic commitment, The elusive citizen

who surfaced historically in the assemblies of Greece, in the communes of medieval Europe, in the town meetings of New England,

and in the revolutionary sections of Paris must be brought to the

foreground of political theory. For without his or her presence and

without a clear understanding of his or her genesis, development,

and potentialities, any discussion of the city is likely to become

anemically institutional and formal. A city would almost certainly

become a shapeless blob, a mere chaos of structures, streets, and

squares if it lacked the institutions and forms appropriate to the

development of an active citizenry. But without the citizens to

occupy these institutions and fill these forms, we may create an

endless variety of civic entities—but like the great urban belts that

threaten to devour them, they would be completely socially lifeless and ecologically denatured.

Chapter Four: The Ideal of Citizenship

If the city makes it possible for us to single out politics as a unique

sphere of self-governance that is neither social nor statist, the

citizen as the viable substance of this unique sphere makes it

possible’to undo the confusion that blends these very distinct

spheres into a collage of overlapping terms and blurred meanings,

For it is in the citizen—in his or her activity as a self-governing

being—that! the political sphere becomes a living reality with the

flesh and blood of a palpable body politic.

The Greeks may have been the first people to give us a clear

image of the citizen in any politically intelligible sense of the term.

Tribal peoples form social groups—families, clans, personal and

community alliances, sororal and fraternal clubs, vocational and

totemic societies, and the like; They may assemble regularly to

examine and decide communal affairs—certainly a nascent form

of politics—but the issues that confront them rarely deal with ways

and means of governing themselves. Custom plays a paramount

role in establishing their norms for community management; discourse, beyond, direct argumentation, occupies a place secondary

to the enormous authority of precedence and long-established

administrative procedures. Nor is this approach to be disdained as

trivial or “primitive/’ Group safety and stability require that the

community preserve the old, well-tested ways of life, of expeditiously applying and modifying time-honored and secure structures of group management. The kin relationship forms the social

tissue of this governing body, whether the blood tie be real or

fictitious. Religious belief, too, may play a very important role, as

Fustel de Coulanges has argued.

But politics as a creative and rational arena of discourse with its

vastly innovative possibilities for shaping and bonding widely disparate individuals is only latent in tribal assemblies. It still has a

domestic character with powerful familial biases that exclude the

stranger. Tribal assemblies of preliterate peoples invoke the past

political assemblies of free citizens create a future. The former

tends to be highly conservative; the latter, highly innovative. If

the two were juxtaposed with each other, we would be obliged to

contrast custom to reason, precedent to a sense of futurity, kinship ties to civic ties, mythopoeia to ethics. In waxing enthusiastically over the popular assemblies that existed very early in

Mesopotamian cities, Henri Frankfort declared that the assembly

form “is a man-made institution overriding the natural and primordial division of society into families and clans. It asserts that

habitat, not kinship, determines one’s affinities. The city, moreover, does not recognize outside authority. It may be subjected by

a neighbour or a ruler, but its loyalty cannot be won by force, for

its sovereignty rests with the assembly of its citizens.”{15}

Which is not to say that these contrasts are so absolute that they

polarize the tribal assembly against its civic counterpart. Athenian

citizenship, based on a civic myth that all citizens shared a common ancestry, became highly parochial by Perikles’s time. For a

well-established resident alien or *metoikos* (metics) to become a

citizen of the *polis* was virtually impossible. Doubtless, Athenians

knew that Solon, a century earlier, offered the lure of Athenian

citizenship to all skilled craftsmen who were willing to migrate

from various parts of the Mediterranean to Athens. And Kleisthenes, a generation removed from Perikles, permitted many

metics to become citizens in his day. Athenian citizenship, conceived as a form of status based on blood ties, was a shaky affair

at best. But under Perikles, the body politic behaved like an oversized medieval guild. For patently self-serving reasons, it simply

closed its doors to outsiders who might stake a reasonable claim to

the privileges afforded by the corporate community. In principle,

the impediments Athenians raised to citizenship in the middle of

the fifth century B.C. were not different from those that modern

nation states place in the way of immigrants and alien residents.

The Greek citizen ideal, however, differed very profoundly

from the modern. It was not simply some specious myth of shared

heredity that united citizens of the *polis* with each other but a

profoundly cultural conception of personal development—the

Greek notion of *paideia*. *Paideia* is normally translated into English as education, a term that is notable for its sparseness and

limitations. To the Greeks, particularly the Athenians, the word

meant considerably more. The education of a young man involved

a deeply formative and life-long process whose end result made

him an asset to the *polis*, to his friends and family, and induced

him to five up to the community’s highest ethical ideals. The

German word, *bildung*, with its combined meanings of character

development, growth, enculturation, and an well-rounded education in knowledge and skills, more appropriately denotes what the

Greeks meant by *paideia* than any word we have in English. It

expresses a creative integration of the individual into his environment, a balance that demands a critical mind with a wide-ranging

sense of duty. The Greek word, *areté*, which in Homeric times

denoted the warrior attributes of prowess and valor, was extended

by the classical era to mean goodness, virtue, and excellence in all

aspects of life. *Paideia* and *aretĂ©* are indissolubly linked—not as

means and ends but as a unified process of civic- and self-development. Excellence in public life was as crucial to an Athenian’s

character development as excellence in his personal life. The *polis*

was not only a treasured end in itself; it was the “school” in which

the citizen’s highest virtues were formed and found expression.

Politics, in turn, was not only concerned with administering the

affairs of the *polis* but also with educating the citizen as a public

boing who developed the competence to act in the public interest.

training. It rooted civic commitment in independence of mind,

The modern notion of “politics” as a form of managerial “efficiency” or of education as the mere acquisition of knowledge and

skills would have seemed pitiful to an Athenian citizen of classical

times. Athenians assembled as an *ekklesia* not only to formulate

policies and make judgments; they came together to mutually

educate each other in the ability to act justly and expand their

civic ideals of right and wrong. The “political process,” to use a

modern cliche, was not strictly institutional and administrative; it

was intensely processual in the sense that politics was an inexhaustible, everyday “curriculum” for intellectual, ethical, and personal, growth—*paideia* that fostered thjs ability of citizens to creatively participate in public affairs, to bring their best abilities to the

service of the *polis* and its needs, to intelligently manage their

private affairs in Accordance with the highest ethical standards of

the community.

This “calling” to civic and personal excellence was more than

a family responsibility’or an institutionalized form of personal

training. By classical times, Athenians who could afford them had

tutors aplenty—rhetoricians to teach them the arts of persuasion;

philosophers and logicians to instruct them in wisdom and consistency of thought; elders to provide them with the inherited lore of

their families, civic traditions, and models of behavior; gymnasia

in which to train and control their bodies or learn martial arts;

courts to shape their faculties for judgment; and, in time, the

and debate. But every *polis*, be it a garrison-state such as Sparta

or a democracy such as Athens, provided a variety of public spaces

in which citizens could gather on more intimate terms, often daily,

to discuss public and practical affairs. Perhaps the most important

of these spaces, the *agora*, which M. I. Finley calls the “town

square,” was an informal meeting ground in the people could be

assembled when needed.{16} By Perikles’ time, the Athenians were

to shift the formal assembly of the people—the *ekklesia*—to a

hillside (the Pnyx), but, as Finley notes, the *agora* originally meant

a “gathering place,” long before it was invaded by shops, stalls,

and temples.

The *agora* provided the indispensible physical space for turnÂŹing citizens hip from a periodic institutional ritual into a living,

everyday practice. Home was the place in which one ate, slept,

and tended to the details of private life. But the Greeks generally

held this private world in small esteem. Life was authentically

lived in the open public space of the *agora*, where the citizens

discussed business affairs, gossiped, met friends—new and old—occasionally philosophized, and almost certainly engaged in vigorous political discussion. Perikles could be waylaid there by badgering critics as surely as Sokrates could be drawn into lengthy discussions by the intellectually earnest young nobles of the *polis*.

Jugglers, acrobats, poets, and play-actors mixed with tradesmen,

yeomen, philosophers, and public officials, a crowd spiced by

strangely costumed visiting foreigners who gawked at the looming

acropolis above and the superbly adorned public buildings nearby.

During inclement weather, this colorful and eminently vocal

crowd could take refuge in the colonnaded arcades or **stoa** that

lined part of the twenty-six-acre square. There, they encountered

artisans working at their trade and merchants who displayed their

wares, often women who sold much of the farm produce that fed

the community. In its emphasis on-direct, almost protoplasmic

contact, full participatory involvement and its delight in variety

and diversity, there is a sense in which the *agora* formed the space

for a genuine ecological community within the *polis* itself. Thus

politics, which found its most ordered and institutionalized expression in the *ekklesia*, originated in the daily ferment of ordinary life

In the *agora*. Its informal genesis reveals the organic way in which

Important policies slowly developed into popular ideas before

they were formulated as verdicts and laws in the courts and official

assemblages of the *polis*. The democratic institutions of Athens,

for all the ritualistic panoply that surrounded them, were merely

the structural forms in which everyday debate and gossip were

hardened into the legislated expression of an easy-going, unstructured, and popular politics—one that was embodied by an earnest,

Spontaneous, and an extraordinarily active citizenry. The “tyranny of structurelessness” that so many contemporary liberals and

socialists fling so reprovingly at their libertarian critics as an “ultrademocratic” vice would have been incomprehensible to the

Athenian citizen. The teeming “anarchy” of the *agora* was, in fact,

an indispensible and fecund grounding for “libertarian” structures

(to use Jaeger’s term) that, given time and neglect, would have

Otherwise turned into oligarchic institutions with a democratic

veneer.

Citizenship, in effect, involved an on-going process of educational, ethical, and political gestation for which such words as

“constituent” and “voter” are modern parodies of a politics that

was more existential than formal. This gestative process occurred

in the *agora* days before it found expression in the *ekklesia*. It is

a cliche to say that Americans are a “practical people,” Italians an

“emotional people,” Germans a “methodical people.” In any case,

there can be no doubt that the Athenians were a “political people”

and citizenship was their destiny, not merely the avocation it has

become in the modern world. Behind their ideal of citizenship,

nonperishable as long as there is a meaningful literature on democracy, is the way that citizenship was formed. It was a citizenship formed by the moral fortitude of a mountain people—in Athens’s case, tempered by the wide cultural contacts afforded by a

major seaport—and a delicate balancing of social conflicts that

pitted opposing classes against each other without obliterating the

virtues each possessed in its own right. Greece was to inherit not

only the aristocratic epics of Homer and their high standard of

courage but the mundane litanies of Hesiod with their workaday

sense of practicality. Her long journey from a tribal to a political

world, from a society of peasants to one of citizens, is a fascinating

narrative in its own right. But it is also an exemplary biography of

the citizen as such, at least insofar as this remarkable individual

was to approximate an ideal that Athens more closely attained

than any community that followed her—and one that the modern

world may well lose at the peril of its freedom.

----

The first phase of this journey into a political world begins with the

way the Athenians managed to shed the narrow features of the

kinship bond based on blood ties, religion, and familial loyalties,

while simultaneously developing an almost ecological **sensibility**

based on a Active kinship, territorial commonality, rationality, and

a healthy secular humanism.

Greek society was not immune to a general historical trend that

raised humanity out of a dismal archaic era, one which reworked

an egalitarian tribal world into a hierarchical feudal one. By Homeric times, commanding patriarchal clans had already imposed

their will on loosely structured and highly vulnerable peasant

communities. Ironically, the very tribal features of kin and blood

that once had produced egalitarian norms of mutual aid and material reciprocity were used to achieve their very opposite: a hierarchical system of rule focused on domination and acquisition. This

new reordering of traditional clans or phratries from tribal into

aristocratic families fostered exclusivity and privilege rather than

sharing and communal responsibility. The “bribe-devouring

judges” whom Hesiod, the Boeotian peasant, had denounced in

the eighth century B.c. had become land-devouring nobles by the

seventh. Gross inequalities in the ownership of land that mark the

Greek world in that period of transition seem like forerunners of

the Roman agrarian crisis that followed the Punic Wars. That

Greece, especially Athens, did not become a mere historical preface to Rome, indeed that the *polis* developed a political life so

markedly different from any republican system of governance,

can be explained only in terms of a remarkable constellation of

factors from which the modern world can learn much.

What aristocratic Greece and democratic Greece were to share

as a common legacy is a vigorous ideal of independence—an ideal

oven stronger than its widely touted ideal of justice. To the Greek

mind, clientage in any form verged on slavery, indeed a denial of

the individual’s humanness and personality. This notion, which

many Greek scholars were to regard as an aristocratic disdain for

Work as such, actually expressed a concern for the citizen’s capacity to form independent judgements insulated from external or

personal interests. “To build one’s own house, one’s own ship, or

to spin and weave the material which is used to clothe the members of one’s own household is in no way shameful,” observes

Claude Mosse in her insightful study on work in the ancient world.

“But to work for another man, in return for a wage of any kind,

is degrading. It is this which distinguishes the ancient mentality

from a modern which would have no hesitation in placing the

independent artisan above the wage-earner. But, for the ancients,

there is really no difference between the artisan who sells his own

products and the workman who hires out his services. Both work

to satisfy the needs of others, not their own. They depend on

Others for their livelihood. For that reason they are no longer free.

This perhaps above all is what distinguishes the artisan from the

poasant. The peasant is so much closer to the ideal of self-sufficiency (*autarkeia*) which was the essential basis for man’s freedom

in the ancient world. Needless to say,fin the classical age, in both

Greece and Rome, this ideal of self-sufficiency had long since given

way to a system of organized trade. However, the archaic mentality endured, and this explains not only the scorn felt for the artisan,

labouring in his smithy, or beneath the scorching sun on building

sites, but also the scarcely veiled disdain felt for merchants or for

rich entrepreneurs who live off the labor of their slaves.”{17}

As befitted free men, farmers enjoyed the economic independence and material security that were needed to form decisions

untainted by self or class interests. In fact many Greeks would

have seen even wealthy tradesmen as clients of their buyers and

highly skilled craftsmen, artists, and poets as dependents of a fickle

market for their products. To be free in Athens meant very little

if one’s basic needs were not satisfied within a mutualistic group

of self-sufficient producers. The word *autarkeia*, strictly translated, has the double meaning of the rarely used definition of

“selfirule,” as weil as. the. more familiar notion of “self-sufficiency.”

In its latter meaning, *autarkeia* has long been replaced by *autonomos*, literally the conditipn of living by one’s own laws. This

concept of independence is more juridical than political. The English translation of these words, notably the use of “autarchy” to

mean economic self-sufficiency and autonomy to denote personal freedom or self-government, creates a disjunction between

the material and political that would have been alien to the Greek

ideal of independence. We would be hard put to understand Artistotie’s belief that all tradesmen, artisans, merchants, and servants

should be denied the franchise if we failed to recognize that it is

not simply labor and trade he despised but, more importantly,

material clientage in any form that could affect the citizen s independence of judgement. Independence without the substance of

material self-sufficiency and personal autonomy would have been

formal at best and hollow at worst to the Greek mind. No client,

however well-off, could render a judgement or reason freely without deferring to exogenous authorities and interests on whom his welfare depended.

It is worth noting that these Hellenic precepts have entered

into modern ecological thinking with little knowledge of their

remote origins and political orientation. But such a demanding

notion of independence could not have emerged solely from ideological considerations. Here, the mountainous terrain of the Greek

archipelago comes verymuch to our aid. “Nature gave to Greece,

as to her neighbors, the tendency to equality together with abundant opportunities for the growth of public opinion, and then

intensified these forces by strictly limiting the areas in which they

could operate,” observes Alfred Zimmern. “Each little plain, rigidly sealed within its mountain-barriers and with its population

concentrated upon its small portion of good soil, seems formed to

be a complete world of its own. Make your way up the pasture-land, over the pass and down on to the fields and orchards on the

other side, and you will find new traditions and customs, new laws

and new gods, and most probably a new dialect.... The Greeks

were not painfully taught to value local independence. They grew

up unable to conceive of any other state of government. It was a

legacy slowly deposited through the long period of isolation which

intervened between the first settlement of the Hellenic invaders

and their emergence centuries later as a civilized race. They

never themselves realized, even their greatest writers did not

realize, how unique and remarkable their political institutions

were.”{18}

Colorful and truthful as these lines may be, Zimmern understates the extent to which Greek thinkers were conscious of their

heritage and political uniqueness. Indeed, as we shall see, it was

the extraordinary acuity of this consciousness that imbued Athens

with a high sense of mission and clear sense of direction. No political sphere was more carefully, thoughtfully, and artistically

crafted than the Athenian. Equality or *isonomia* followed from an

even more basic; influence than Greece’s mountainous terrain exercised on its pocket-sized communities of free villagers. To five

in such isolation and forced independence required that every

family and family-sized community had to fend for itself. The

Greek farmer had to be a well-rounded man in a more tangible

sense than we use this cliche today. He was obliged to know how

to fight for his land,as well as cultivate it, build his shelters as well

as repair them, methodically tend to his wounds as well as cunningly avoid needless conflicts, plan his long-range needs as well

as satisfy his immediate ones, function as a caring father, loyal

spouse, dutiful son, supportive brother, a wary buyer of things that

his co mm unity could not produce—in short, he needed to combine a working knowledge of all the techniques needed for his

survival with soldiering and “politicking.” Together with his

spouse, who presided over all the domestic affairs of the family, the

Greek farmer gained in practical competence and personal fortitude what isolation denied him in acculturation. In the Latin sense

of competere—to be fit, proper, or qualified—he had no equal in

the ancient world. Hence, he could be “unequalled” by self-anointed superiors who tried to subordinate him and assert their

authority over his destiny. A magnificent amateur, he embodied

the nascent citizenship in which all his peers acknowledged the

need for a self-possessed individual who could be entrusted as

much with the affairs of his community as with the satisfaction of

his private needs.

The flow of ideas from the independence of a mountain-dwelling villager to the egalitarianism of a *polis*-dwelling citizen must

be seen as an unbroken continuum. The Greek language itself is

magnificently processual and organic. A crucially important word

such as *arche*, from which an entire political vocabulary has been

constructed, denotes the originating principle as well as the ordering principle of any *kosmos*, the Greek word for “order” in the

broadest sense of the term. To think of an “order” without deriving it from its origin and, hence, the latent possibilities that it could

fulfill is linguistically built into the Greek mind—and also provides

us with an important clue to the language’s ethical thrust. Origin,

history, f ulfillm ent, and possibility—all form a unified whole in

Greek, so that whether we choose to speak of the universe,

humankind, the *polis*, or the citizen, these concepts, charged with

ethical meaning, denote the unity of civic, natural, and social life

or what we call “connectedness” today. Accordingly, autarchies or

self-sufficient communities lead us organically—deductively, if

you will—to independence, competence, and *isonomia*. The

Greek *polis* has its *arche* in this germinal phasing of a highly

competent farmer who, by an immanent process of sociopolitical

development, found his fulfillment as a highly competent citizen.

The old Greek aristocracy was no mere anachronism in this

process. The Athenian democracy did not shed it; rather, it tried,

with qualified success, to absorb it. Its epic culture, gospel of valor,

high sense of *philia*, and code of honor, marked by a disdain for

material thin gs, were incorporated into the puritanical virtues of

the democracy, which abjured luxury, ornateness of dress, culinary delights, and self-indulgence. The democratic hero was not

only valorous but sternly self-willed and emotionally controlled.

Warrior manliness did not die; it was reworked into civic loyalty,

personal dignity, and a high regard for virtuous behavior. The

comradeship of the military camp became the *isonomia* of the

competent equals. Hence, all could participate in the governance

of the *polis* on the same footing, a practice which, as we shall see,

was translated into the widespread use of sortition and attempts

to arrive at decisions by consensus as well as by voting.

It is worth emphasizing that nearly all the men who turned

Athens from an aristocratic oligarchy into a democratic polity

were of noble lineage, Solon, Kleisthenes, and Perikles, to cite the

most well-known figures in forming the democracy, were members of the most elite clans, the *genos*, of Attica, the territorial

domain of Athens. In contrast to their Roman counterparts, however, they did not become the leaders of an unruly *partes populares*, nor did they try to rise in an oppressive hierarchy by throwing away their fortunes in gifts to a debased urban mob. They were

commonly men of exceptional distinction who could be as heroically selfless in political causes as their ancestors were heroically

valorous in military ones. As Werner Jaeger was to point out,

Athens did not destroy its aristocracy but rather tried to turn its

entire citizen body into one.

----

This pithy formulation has several levels of meaning. Politically, it

sums up the slow but sweeping way in which Attica’s “bribe-devouring” nobles were shorn of their power. By the seventh

century B.C., Athens and its environs were on the brink of revolution. Plutarch tells us that the “common people were weighed

down with debts they owed to a few rich men. They either cultivated their lands for them and paid them a sixth of the produce

and were hence called *Hectemorioi* and *Thetes*, or else they

pledged their own persons to raise money and could be seized by

their creditors, some of them being enslaved at home, and others

being sold to foreigners abroad. Many parents were even forced

to sell their own children (for there was no law to prevent this) or

to go into exile because of the harshness of their creditors. However, the majority, which included the men of most spirit, began

to make common cause together and encourage one another not

to resign themselves to these injustices, but to choose a man they

co,uld trust to lead them. Having done this, they proposed to set

all enslaved debtors free, redistribute the land and make a complete reform of the constitution.”{19}

At this point, Athens might have easily gone the way of Rome.

Five centuries later; the Gracchi brothers, who faced a nearly

identical crisis between bitterly polarized classes of landless peasants and bloated patricians, raised such sweeping demands for

political change and agrarian reform that they opened irreparable

wounds in the Roman body politic. It remains to the credit of the

Athenians that the crisis was handled very gingerly. The moderation that Hellenic society turned into a deeply personal as well as

civic ethos was to find its embodiment in Solon, a noble of considerable prestige who had earned the respect of the Athenians as a

whole. No one could have contained the crisis that faced his people with greater prudence.

Elected archon of the *polis*—its chief magistrate—and invested

with sweeping powers to resolve the, conflict, Solon followed the

middle course that eluded the Gracchi and the more sincere populates in the closing years of the Republic. For the poorest of the

pressing economic burden by cancelling all outstanding debts and

making debt slavery illegal. To strengthen their political status, he

revived and expanded the functions of the *ekklesia*, which had

virtually ceased to exist since tribal days. The assembly was authorized not only to enact the community’s laws and elect its magistrates; it convened as a court of justice to deal with all cases other

than homicide, a crucial advance in empowering the *demos*, The

upper crust of the nobility—the *Eupatridai*—were obliged to relinquish their hereditary claim to, furnish Athens with its archons,

a powerful, annually elected magistracy whose number Solon increased to nine. The office, to be sure, could only be filled by

landowners, but the door to executive power, which later generations were to open, was now unlocked for the *demos*.

Solon never pretended that he desired the political and economic supremacy of *demos*, nor did he try to divest the nobility

of power. As his verses indicated, he shrewdly steered a middle

course through a crisis that would have exploded in social chaos

had any of the contending orders gained absolute supremacy over

the others:

To the mass of people I gave the power they needed,
Neither degrading them, nor giving them too much rein;
For those who already possessed great power and wealth
I saw to it that their interests were not harmed.
I stood guard with a broad shield before both parties
And prevented either from triumphing unjustly.{20}

The land magnates were not deprived of their holdings, nor

were the *Hectemorioi* permitted to reclaim the sixth of their produce that was taken by their landlords. Usury still plagued the

Attic peasantry, although the lender and borrower were more

evenly squared off by the controls that the *ekklesia* exercised over

legal disputes. Solon also created a Council of Four Hundred—the

famous Athenian *boule*—to which only propertied men could be

elected annually. However, the *boule* served to check not only the

popular *ekklesia* by rigorously determining its agenda and supervising its deliberations; it also checked the behavior of the aristocratic Council of the Areopagus (formerly the powerful Council of

the Eupatridai), whose functions over the years were to, become

more ceremonial than political. A number of reforms, unique for

their time, were made to expand individual rights and alter popular etiquette. An heiress, burdened by an impotent husband, was

free to marry his next of kin, and relatively poor women were

spared the need to collect dowries. Individuals could will their

property as they ‘chose, not according to familial dictates—a law

that struck an important blow at the collective solidity of the

aristocratic *genos* and its concentration of sizable wealth. A number of lesser laws restricted displays of excessive luxury and riches.

But perhaps the most strikingly Hellenic law imputed to Solon was

one that disenfranchised any citizen who, to use Plutarch’s words,

“in the event of revolution, does not take one side or the other.”

It was Solon’s intention, Plutarch emphasized, not to reward citizens who seek the safety of neutrality, apathy, or indifference at

the expense of the public interest. Athenians were expected to be

politically involved, irrespective of the causes to which they adhered, or else they were not worthy of citizenship. It was an

affront to the Hellenic concept of citizenship for a man to prudently and selfishly “sit back in safety waiting to see which side

would win.”

Characteristically, Solon refused to linger on as a tyrant by no

means a pejorative term or a despised status in those days despite pleas that he become one, and went into voluntary exile for

ten years. His work did not resolve all the political and economic

problems that brought him to the archonship, nor did it prevent

a tyrant from ultimately replacing him. But it provided Athens

with the opportunity to absorb his reforms and the time needed

for its citizenry to mature politically—to use and accustom itself

to the *ekklesia*, to learn the arts of compromise, and to develop a

political etiquette that fostered a sense of civic commonality

rather than social conflict. The rather mild tyranny of Peisistratus

and his son Hippias, which followed Solon s departure, greatly

reduced the power of the Attic nobility and initiated the economic

and political changes that were to lead to the democracy. Recalcitrant nobles were forced into exile and their estates divided

among the poor. The needy were given livestock and seed, exports

were promoted, and a vigorous foreign policy opened new markets to Athenian commerce. Peisistratus, despite the personal control he exercised over Attica’s affairs and his blatant nepotism,

adhered to the Solonic constitution so meticulously that even

Solon was induced to support him after his return to Athens. The

political level of the Athenian citizen was raised enormously by

the tyranny, and the commoners—farmers, shepherds, artisans,

and merchants—benefited so considerably from the archonships

of Peisistratus and Hippias that the tyranny became self-vitiating.

Three generations had passed since Solon had been given the

archonship, and Athens was now ready for a democracy. In terms

of the mere flow of events, the efforts to initiate authentic popular

rule seemed to come almost as a reaction to attempts by the

aristocracy to restore their old clannish oligarchy, and many of the

democracy’s features must be seen as institutionalized efforts to

prevent the emergence of entrenched power by elites of any kind.

But the Athenian people, too, seem to have become more certain

of themselves and their capacity to govern their own affairs. The

aristocracy, in turn, appears to have suffered a genuine lack of

nerve. After a feeble attempt to eliminate the reforms of Solon

and the Peisistradae, the nobles broke ranks. One of their own

kind, Kleisthenes, the head of the aristocratic Alcmaenodae, became archon in 506 B.C., and the democraticization of Athens was

launched in earnest.

Kleisthenes struck decisively at the societal basis of aristocratic

power—the traditional kinship network that gave the Attic nobility its very sense of identity. The ancient Greek phratries and clans

were simply divested of any political power and gradually declined in importance for want of any significant functions. The old

Ionian system of four ancestral tribes was converted into ten

Strictly territorial “tribes” based exclusively on residence. The

villages and towns of Attica, in turn, became outlying sections of

Athens and were designated as “*demes*” instead of *genoi*. Politics

now became inseparable from territorialism: the *demes*, with their

own popular assemblies, were grouped together in varying numbers into thirds or *trittyes*, and three *trittyes*, in turn, constituted

a tribe, hence Attica was composed of thirty *trittyes*. Ten of the

thirty *demoi* were composed of residents in or around Athens;

another ten, from the maritime districts; and the remainder from

the interior.

Kleisthenes shrewdly placed one urban trittys in each of the ten

tribes, so that the Attic agrarians from whom the nobles garnered

whatever popular support they had were politically buffered by

City citizens—the men who were to form the backbone of the

democracy. This switch in the governance system of the *polis* was

Strategic: it fostered the power of a citizenry that was distinctly

urbane, cosmopolitan, and forward looking, vitiating the strongly

hierarchical structure of a once-entrenched, highly parochial, feudal class system. At the same time, tradition was kept alive by

using the language of the tribal world (even the word *gene* had a

special clannish origin), retaining a number of local religious associations, chieftainlike figures such as **demarchs** (the deme’s version of the Athenian archons), and by making membership in a

dome hereditary even though a citizen might choose to reside at

some later time in another part of Attica. Kleisthenes, in effect,

“revolutionized” Athenian political life in the literal sense of the

term: he replaced a once-egalitarian tribal system that had been

perverted into a harsh feudal hierarchy by a tribalistic structure

that actually restored the old freedoms of the people on an entirely new political and societal level. Athens had revolved in a

full circle—more precisely, a spiral—to the **isonomia** of its tribal

past, but without the innocence that made the early Greeks vulnerable to hierarchy and domination.

The *boule* was increased from a council of four hundred to five

hundred and restructured so that fifty men from each of the ten

tribes rotated every tenth of the year as an administrative “executive committee” between sessions of the *ekklesia*. Each tribe selected its fifty *bouleutes* by lot, a practice that became so widespread that even archons were so chosen from members of the *boule*, as were members of Athenian juries (*dikastoi*) and lesser

functionaries. Apart from the *polis*’s magistrates, no property qualifications debarred Athenian citizens from participating in the

governance system, and under Perikles the last restrictions that

lingered on from Kleisthenes’s reforms disappeared completely.

In time, members of the *boule*, the *ekklesia*, and the *heliaea* or

courts were compensated for participating in these institutions,

generally on a *per diem* basis and in the case of the *boule*, annually. No public office could be held for more than a year, and with

certain exceptions (jurymen and generals) none could be held

more than twice in a lifetime.

This extraordinary opening of public life to the Athenian citizenry was completed during the sixty years that saw Kleisthenes

assume the archonship in: 492 B.C. and the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War in 431. An analytic account of the democracy, its

possibilities and its limitations, properly belongs to the discussion

of civic freedom that follows in the next chapter. For the present,

what counts is the way the democracy formed the citizenry and,

in turn, was formed by it. Democratic leaders such as Kleisthenes

and Perikles did not foist a remarkably open system of participatory governance on a passive people; the institutional structure

and the body politic interacted closely with each other against a

haunting background of quasitribal social forms and relationships.

This is politics at its best—in a lived sense, not a formal one. The

Athenian notion of *areté*, the daily practice of *paideia*, and the

institutional structure of the *polis* were synthesized into an ideal

of citizenship that the individual tried to realize as a form of

self-expression, not an obligatory burden of self-denial. Citizenship became an ethos, a creative art, indeed, a civic cult rather

than a demanding body of duties and a palliative body of rights.

At his best, the Athenian citizen tried not only to participate as

fully as possible in a far-reaching network of institutions that elicited his presence as an active being; the democracy turned his

participation into a drama that found visible and emotional expression in rituals, games, artwork, a civic religion—in short, a

collective sense of feeling and solidarity that underpinned a collective sense of responsibility and. duty. This drama extended beyond

life itself. The Athenian citizen had little hope of any certain

immortality other than the memory he left behind in the *polis*.

Afterlife became a form of political life and eternahty existed only

insofar as noble political actions were memorable enough to become part of the *polis*’s history and destiny.

----

The *polis* shrewdly availed itself of aristocratic attributes to bring

the individual Athenian into the full light of citizenship, with its

high standards of civic responsibility. We have seen how the *agora*

prepared the way for the *ekklesia*. By the same token, the gymnasium, presided over by a **paidotribes,** extended the all-consuming

fascination of the Greeks for athletics into martial arts, thereby

preparing the young for military training. Troubling as this may

be in modern eyes, war was a fact of life in antiquity. Apart from

certain cults and religions, pacifism found no following among the

ancients. One either fought unquestioningly for one’s city or faced

clientage and slavery in the event of defeat. The citizen-soldier

was much more than: a pillar of Athenian military strategy. He was

a guardian not only of the *polis* but also of the democracy, as we

shall see later, just as the citizen-farmer became the embodiment

of its ideal of *autarkeia*.

But the *polis*, particularly the democracy, gave the family’s

aristocratic attributes a uniquely public character. And it is in this

non-elitist sense that the democracy elevated its citizens into an

“aristocracy”—not only as a result of the participatory nature of

Its courts, assemblies, and councils, but also the familial mood of

essentially religious character, rituals and festivals became a form

of politics. The *ekklesia* opened with prayers, and its agenda was

composed of sacred as well as secular topics. Problems of constructing temples or planning festivals occupied the assembly as

earnestly as matters such as ostracism or the ratification of treaties.

In famous funeral oration, which so vividly captures the spirit of

the democracy, Perikles cites among its attributes “the contests

and sacrifices throughout the year, which provide us with more

relaxation from work than exists in any other city.”{21} Webster’s

observation that the Athenians tended to turn their holy days into

holidays suffers from a certain degree of misunderstanding.{22}

Athenian life struck a remarkable balance between religiosity and

secularity: the camaraderie of participating in a spectacle or sharing fully in the excitement of the games imparted a quasireligious

sense of communion to civic life. This sense of communion more

accurately conveys the intense meaning of *koinonia* than do such

commonplace words as “community.” At the risk of repitition, we

could say that such shared experiences unravel the Athenian notion of “community” as an on-going activity of communizing, not

simply an institutionalized form of participation. Like the *agora*,

the “contests and games” of Athens often created a shared sense

of preternatural civic enchantment.

The democrats knew this very well and these “contests and

games” occurred with considerable frequency. To discuss them in

detail would require a volume in itself. Let it suffice to say that

every year, many days were devoted to the Lesser Mysteries in

February and the Greater Mysteries in September, rituals that

centered around Persephone’s descent into Hades and Demeter’s

mourning, the mythical explanation for the occurrence of winter

and its lean months. Every July, Athenians participated in the

Lesser Panathenaia, which culminated quadrennially in the

Greater Panathenaia, an extraordinary parade of Athenians and

Athenian life in full array, if we are to judge from the bas relief

that girdles the Parthenon. Almost every month, Athenians witnessed or participated in a variety of rituals, contests (athletic,

musical, poetic, and choral), or celebrations to honor deities, historic events, great personages, victors in Panhellenic festivals such

as the Olympics or the fallen of past and recent battles. Religion

and civic loyalty blended the great variety of personal and social

interests within the body politic into an underlying commonality

of outlook that, if it did not remove serious conflicts, rarely

reached such desperate levels that they could efface the democracy from within. Ultimately, it was to be Macedonian rule that

brought the democracy to its definitive end, not the Athenians.

For all its shortcomings, the democracy in various forms persisted

through nearly two of the most stormy centuries of the ancient

world and, at its height, exhibited a degree of cultural and intellectual creativity that has no peer in western history.

Perhaps the most important of the Athenian festivals was a

comparatively new one: the City Dionysia. Even more than the

Greater Panathenaia, when all of Athens went on display with a

large tapestry (the *pelops*) that depicted the triumph of Olympian

“reason” over the chthonic rule of “force,” the City Dionysia was

strongly democratic in its focus. It was then, for three out of a span

of six days that overlapped March and April, that Athenians could

witness the great dramatic tragedies that gave the democracy its

ideological meaning. By the thousands, Athenians flocked to the

Theater of Dionysos on the southeast slope of the Acropolis to see

the plays of Aeskylos, Sophokles, Euripides, and others who literally created serious drama in western culture. Under the clear

skies of a high Mediterranean spring, they watched with absorption the Aeskylean drama of their own *polis* and its human antecedents unfold with a majesty that may have verged on reverence—certainly a thrilling sense of exaltation that compels a modern

historian of the democracy, W. G. Forrest, to cite Aeskylos “as the

greatest of the three Athenian tragedians,” and for many, including myself, the greatest of the world’s dramatists.{23} Aeskylos’s

trilogy, the *Oresteia*, advanced a powerful validation of the democracy that, in its emotional and declaratory power, may even

exceed the funeral oration of Perikles—a trilogy that was constantly replayed and kept winning prizes at the City Dionysos long after the author’s death.

Its story has been told and interpreted repeatedly, and to explore it at length would be a tiresome redundancy. Let it suffice

to say that the murder of Agamemnon, the returning chief of the

besiegers of Troy, by his wife, Klytemnestra, followed by her own

death at the hands of her vengeful son, Orestes, opens the whole

drama of Athens’s transformation from a quasitribal society,

rooted in kinship rules, custom, and chthonic deities, into a political community—a *polis*—based on residence, reason, and the anthropomorphic Olympians. It is Athene who, in a challenging

statement against the Erinyes (the three female guardians of “matriarchal” blood ties and tribal retribution for the murder of one’s kin), solemnly declares:

It is my task to render final judgement here.
This is a ballot for Orestes I shall cast.
There is no mother anywhere who gave me birth,
and, but for marriage, I am always for the male
with all my heart, and strongly on my father’s side.
So; in a case where the wife has killed her husband, lord of the
house, her death shall not mean most to me. And if the other votes
are even, then Orestes wins.{24}

After being pursued by the Erinyes for committing a blood

crime more damning than a marital one—and particularly against

his mother from whom early tribal descent may have been traced—Orestes is absolved and the Erinyes reconciled by acquiring a

civic status as Eumenides, the kindly ones who look after the

well-being of the Athenian *polis*.

The trilogy has many levels of meaning, probably all of which

had a gripping effect on the audience that knew Aeskylos personally or, in later years, by reputation. The *Eumenides*, the last

drama of the trilogy, celebrates the victory of civic law and rationality over tribal custom and unthinking mimesis. Athene, born of

Zeus’s head, embodies *logos* and justice. In a strongly patriarchal

society that saw male rationality as the sole bulwark to dark chaos

and an uncertain, untamed world, it was not difficult to identify

“fickle” woman with nature and the *polis* as the sole realm of

freedom and law. Orestes’ trial, which marks the culmination of

the trilogy, is presented as a new dispensation in the affairs of men.

The Erinyes unrelentingly pursue any homicidal perpetrator of

the blood tie. All that counts with them is the act of murder of

one’s kin, not the circumstances or motive that produced it. To the

Athenians, this behavior was evidence of unreasoning tribalism, of

an irrationality that precluded any civic union based on discourse,

logic, and orderly compromise. Recourse to trial rather than ordeal, to the weighing of circumstantial evidence, motive, and logical judgement rather than mere action and contests of fortitude, marked the first step toward a political *koinonia*—the city as a *polis*.

To the Athenian audience, which believed Athens was the first

city to establish a system of laws, the trial of Orestes was a founding

act. Athens’s decision to try homicide by a judicial process literally

created the *polis* as an ethical union based on justice. “If it please

you, men of Attica,” intoned Athene, the patroness of the *polis*,

“hear my decree now, on this first case of bloodletting I have

judged. For Aegeus’ population, this forevermore shall be the

ground [the Hill of Ares] where justices deliberate-No anarchy,

no rule of a single master.... I establish this tribunal. It shall be

untouched by moneymaking, grave but quick to wrath, watchful

to protect those who sleep, a sentry on the land.”{25} Henceforth,

justice, not tradition; reason, not custom; fact, not ordeal; motive,

not myth are to guide the men of Attica, for without this new

dispensation, the *polis* has no ethical meaning, nor does the democracy have an ethical rationale.

It is easy to see in Aeskylos not only the clearest voice of the

Athenians, who apparently revered Aeskylos, the *Oresteia* unfolds

the emergence of justice from a hazy “dark” world of tribal antiquity and its fortunes in the arbitrary domain of warriors, nobles,

and the *genoi*, into the clear light of the *polis* and its orderly

citizenry. The identification of the audience with the drama must

have been intensely personal; it was the authentic protagonist of

the play. Of Aeskylos’s remaining dramas, **Prometheus Bound** arrests us to this very day with its message of heroic defiance against

unfeeling authority and its expansive belief in humanity’s sense of

promise, indeed its capacity to advance toward an ever-wider

horizen of intellect and wisdom.

It would be easy enough to end our discussion of the Athenian

drama with Aeskylos, but Sophokles beckons us with other facets

of meaning that must have deeply affected the Athenian spirit. His

<em>Antigone</em> raises the ambiguities of justice in the form of conflicting

Individuals, indeed personalities. Antigone herself becomes the

ombodiment of tribal kinship rules in her frenzied zeal to bury the

body of her brother, Polyneikes, whom Kreon, the King of Thebes,

wishes to leave to vultures and dogs as an example for future

rebels. Kreon thus appears as the embodiment of secular authority, the civil counterpart to Antigone. The drama emerges as a

fugue, in which deeply emotive ethical themes are played against

each other and intermesh. If Aeskylos’s characters tend to appear

as forces rather than individuals, despite Klytemnestra’s awesome

personality and Athene’s majesty, Antigone wins us as a persecuted heroine who seeks the burial of her brother s body and

Kreon as the willful embodiment of civil rule, prior even to the

rise of the *polis*. For we are still in the time of the royal *oikos* or

household. In writing the drama, Sophokles may have tried to

show that after the decline of this prepolitical world of blood clans

and regal palaces the Athenian citizen no longer had to confront

the pangs of tragedy in Hegel’s sense of the term—a drama in

which both sides are right. The *polis* spares us the need to pit

divine law in the form of tribal commandment against human law

in the form of civil retribution for rebellion. We can read our

romantic sympathies for Antigone into the drama, but a Greek

audience might have viewed her differently. It would have been

obliged to place Kreon’s civil obligation on a par with Antigone s

tribal obligation, and its sympathies would have been allotted

according to political as well as personal sensibilities. Relief

emerges from the sense of delivery that a concealed theme in the

drama affords: the free air of the *polis* in which the citizen can

breathe without the presence of such exotic conflicts.

Such is also the case in one of Sophokles’s most celebrated—and

possibly one of his most misunderstood—plays, **Oedipus the King**

and **Oedipus at Colonus**. Here man, potentially the citizen, rises

to a clear and level gaze at his fate and his ability to learn from

suffering. If there is anything that impresses us about the play, it

is the fact that Oedipus emerges with greater nobility toward the

end of his life, all his misfortunes notwithstanding, than in its

portentous beginnings. No broken King Lear confronts us but

rather a hero whose passion for truth ultimately transcends the

disastrous impact of patricide and incest. The cathartic core of the

drama is unmistakable: it is the nobility of the individual, purged

of archaic curses and trammels, of man’s high promise and destiny

to achieve insight and wisdom when he acquires the status of a

free citizen.

Yet, the Greek ideal of the citizen, in contrast to ours, is not

monadic. However individuated the Greek drama became with

Sophokles and even more decidedly so with Euripides, the

Athenian citizen would have mocked the entrenched bourgeois

myth that the free man is an atomized buyer and seller whose

choices are constrained by his own psychological and physical

infirmities. He would have seen beyond the arrogance of this

self-deception into the pathos of the bourgeois citizen’s clientage

to the powerful, his aimless pursuit of wealth, his reduction of life

to the acquisition of things—in short, a **moira** or destiny governed

more by **ananke** or necessity than by the understanding that even

such a nascent personality as Oedipus brings to his own insight

into reality. Such a despised bourgeois being, he would have concluded, is no less archaic than the Erinyes, who must be freed from

their primality as mere forces and reconstructed by reason and

justice into the “kindly ones.” Only then, in synchronicity and

ethical union with the *polis*, is citizenship more than a formality

and its practice more than a ritual.

By the same token, the Athenian citizen was not a corporate

being in our usual meaning of the term. Most present-day discussions of the Athenian’s lack of individuality and the *polis*’s tendency to subserve his personality to an overbearing collectivity are

weighed down by Eurocentrically neurotic images of the individual as such. The modern identification of individuality with egotism and personality with neurosis has been overindulged under

the rubric of “modernity” with an arrogance that bears comparison only with the conceited claims of psychoanalysis and psychohistory to explain the human drama in all its aspects. That human

beings can be individuated in different ways—some as highly social and political beings, others as private and self-indulgent beings, still others as combinations and permutations of both—is as

alien to the imperialistic claims of “modernity” as it is to the

admirers of *gemeinschaft*, the stagnant folk community based on

kinship and organismic relationships. To the Hellenic citizen of a

seemed as prehuman as the folk community seemed prepolitical.

Individuality meant citizenship. And, ideally, citizenship meant

the personal wholeness that came from deep roots in tradition, a

complexity of social bonds, richly articulated civic relationships,

shared festivals, *philia*, freedom from clientage and freedom for

collective self-determination through institutions that fostered the

full participation and everyday practice of a creative body politic.

To he such a citizen, one had to live in a *polis*—a city that possessed an *agora*, a space to convene general assemblies of the

people, a theater to dramatize the reality and ideology of freedom,

and the ceremonial squares, avenues, and temples that gave it

reverential meaning. To remove any of these elements that made

up this whole was to instantly destroy it. Without every one of

them, cultivated on a daily basis by the *paideia* of citizenship and

guided by an unerring concept of *areté*, the Athenian ideal of

citizenship fell apart and its institutions became hollow forms.

But such notions, valuable as they may be, lack a processual

content that sees this whole from the standpoint of an ever-fuller

development. We can see this by looking closely at the quixotic

nature of the Greek dramatic tragedy itself—the staged experience of the *polis* and citizen. For it was through the tragedy that

the Athenian underwent self-examination, much as though he

could withdraw from his own skin and observe himself thoughtfully for what he really was. It is notable that all the tragedies we

have at our disposal are made up of mythic and epic material. As

civic experiences, they seem to function dissonantly with stuff that

is drawn from a prepolitical world, from eras that precede the

heroines are Bronze Age characters who still live under the commandments of a tribal or warrior society, by canons of right and

wrong that are archaic at best and chthonic at worst. In the transformations that the dramas recount from one world to another, we

rarely seem to rise from new foundations embedded in still older

ones to the edifice that the audience knew at hand—the *polis* of

the, fifth century B.C. and its democracy.

Yet the antiquity of the characters, material, and themes with

which all the great tragedians seem to have worked is belied by

a startling sense of innovation, by tensions from which new ideals,

institutions, and credos are born. The, *Oresteia* seems to not only

justify radically new communal dispensations, indeed most of

which already existed when the trilogy was presented; its radicalism consists in the fact that Athene’s decrees are fraught with the

promise of change, with motives that are likely to yield ever-wider

ethical and political horizons. One senses that a community

guided by justice has just begun to emerge, that the civic ideal of

freedom is still nascent, that citizenship and the *polis* are still

experiencing birth pangs and their future still lies before them.

Few Athenians, I suspect, could have left such dramas without

feeling an intense sense of futurity and a serene commitment to

growth. **Prometheus Bound** is even more challenging in its thirst

for heroic innovation and its passion for a fuller arid richer experiential life, as are the Oedipus dramas for truth at all costs.

Hence, seemingly conservative material is played, replayed,

and ultimately transmuted into searingly progressive hopes and

possibilities. When we bear witness to these dramas by viewing

them in all their starkness as idealized “archetypes” of an immutable human nature, we do violence to the tensions they probably

produced in the Athenian audiences of their day. These plays

were no mere spectacles or cathartic outlets for pent-up civic

anxieties. Quite to the contrary: they were sources of motivation

and tension, designed to move their audiences forward to noble

deeds and great enterprises, to contrast past with present so that

meaning, continuity, and tendency could be imparted to the future. They voiced a hope in the human spirit that belies the conventional interpretation of the Athenian drama as fatalistic in its

view of life and resigned in its image of destiny. Indeed, it is with

Euripides, that most “modern,” “realistic,” and “individualistic”

of the Greek tragedians, that hopelessness, alienation, and the

insufferable burden of circumstances seem to devour the characters of the drama and exhaust the hopes of the audience. Here, the

drama with its promise of futurity and hope.

The *polis* was no less a theater for the practice of virtue than

the orchestra at the foot of the Acropolis was a home for the

performance of the plays it watched. And the citizen was no less

an actor in a great civic drama than the men who performed for

him with masks in the City Dionysos. In both cases, the plot we

call the history of Athens incorporated the layered traditions that

formed its cultural biography and ideology. So central was the

citizen to this plot with his “freedom for” as well as his “freedom

from,” that the histories of the time, when they refer to Attica,

speak more commonly of “the Athenians” than they do of “Athens.” Unerringly, they reveal that Athens was no mere collection

of structures, no simple geographic locale, that any aggregate of

people could occupy without the *polis* losing its authenticity. Admittedly, the city outlived the *polis*, and the democracy in a formal sense outlived the citizens. Democratic institutions persisted

in a truncated form long after Athens s final defeat by the

Macedonians at Krannon in 322 B.C. No city was a *polis*, in Aristotle’s view, unless it had an *agora*; but, needless, to say, no *agora*

could have produced a democracy unless it had the kind of citizen

the historians of that day called “the Athenians.”

----

There is a myth that the classical Athenian *polis* was the spontaneous product of custom and tradition. Hence, its integrity rested

largely on hidden presuppositions of which it was largely unconscious, indeed, to which it was sublimely oblivious. This notion of

an unreflective Athenian morality, imputed to Hegel and held by

many romantics in the last century, is belied by almost everything

we know about the democracy. The Aeskylean tragedies and Perikles’s funeral oration, to cite two highly important and widely

separated examples, completely refute the image of the democracy as a phenomenon based on mere habit and convention. One

must totally ignore Kleisthenes’s reforms and the subtle melding

of religious tradition with clearly formulated political goals not to

recognize that the democracy was a consciously crafted structure,

the product of purposeful, insightful, and thoughtful efforts to

achieve clearly perceived goals—and, let me add, guided by a

philosophy and practice of its own. The introduction of the lot, the

rotation and limitation of tenure in public office, the development

of the assembly and the *boule*—all reveal a degree of intentionality and clarity of purpose that has few equals in any later constitutional developments. That Sokrates was executed for questioning

this order on charges that were archaic even by conservative

standards of fifth-century Athens has more to do with the politics

of the trial, particularly Sokrates’ arrogance and his desire for

martyrdom, than the challenge his philosophy posed to the *polis*’s

“ethical order.” No political community was more aware of its

uniqueness and wondrous of its achievement than the Athenian

democracy. And no one was more consciously committed to this

humanly wrought body of institutions than the Athenian citizen.

By contrast, later ideals of citizenship, even insofar as they were

modeled on the Athenian, seem more unfinished and immature

than the original—hence, the very considerable discussion I have

given to the Athenian citizen and his context. As we shall see

shortly, there were impressive attempts to create patterns of civic

freedom that approximated the democratic *polis* in medieval city-states and in the American and French revolutions. These attempts were usually intuitive. The Americans who attended town

meetings in New England after 1760 and the French **sans-culottes**

who filled the radical sections of Paris in 1793–94 were hardly

aware of the political drama that unfolded in Athens some two

millennia earlier, although their more knowledgeable spokesmen

fingered Plutarch throughout their lives and occasionally adopted

heroic names during fervent moments of the two revolutions.

What was lacking in their attempts to achieve a living approximation of civic democracy was not merely ideology. Greece, commonly Athens (although Sparta’s garrison-state was a close runner-up for some utopian writers and for Rousseau), was held up as a

fascinating experiment in popular self-governance and, as usual,

compromised with the republican ideals generated by the emerging nation-state,

For this reason, the Athenian ideal of citizenship, like its parallel creation, politics, demands careful exploration today even

more than at any time in the past. If moderns find democratic

politics and citizenship a desideratum, they will never achieve

them without a supreme act of consciousness. They must not only

want it but know it. Athenian civic goals, for all their shortcomings

(notably Athens’s treatment of women, alien residents, and its

widespread use of slave labor), must be rooted in an everyday

notion of what we mean by politics. Is it statecraft? Or does it

center around social entities such as cooperative, vocational societies or tribes in the countercultural sense of this much-abused term? Or some broad concept of grass-roots organization that

passes under words such as “localism,” “decentralism,” and “bioregionalism”? Is it an educational activity—a civic *paideia*—that

fosters the citizen’s empowerment, both spiritually as well as institutionally? Or is it primarily a form of “management” whose goal

is administrative efficiency and fiscal shrewdness?

No modern body of ideas, to my knowledge, has wrestled with

the answers to these questions adequately enough to draw clear

distinctions among the social, the political, and the statist so that

a meaningful outlook can be formulated—one that will seek the

delicate balance of ingredients (traditional, familial, ethical, and

institutional) and the *paideia* that articulates an authentically

democratic politics with a concept of citizenship that gives this

outlook reality. Nor do we have a clear idea of the extent to which

the city, properly conceived as a humanly scaled ethical community, differs from urbanization and the inhuman scale produced by

the nation-state. We rarely understand’how integrally an ethical

politics is wedded to a comprehensible civic scale, to the city itself,

conceived as a thoroughly manageable and participatory union of

citizens, richly articulated by tradition and by social, cultural, and

political forms. We live so contemporaneously within the given

state of affairs, the overbearing “now” that eternalizes the status

quo, that no society is more prey to the workings of mindless forces

than bur own. Bereft of a serious regard for history, indeed for the

experiences of our own century, we find ourselves in the airless

vacuum of an immutable “present/ a time warp that precludes

any sense of futurity and ability to reason innovatively.

Accordingly, where thinking of a crude kind does exist, lines of

thought fecklessly crisscross each other like the scrawlings of an

infant that can barely grasp a pencil. Oligarchies are accepted as

democracies; virtual monarchies as republics; state institutions as

social forms; social forms as political ones. One, can hardly speak,

here, of a kind of shallow eclecticism that afflicts every age; rather

one encounters a potpourri of unfinished notions, barely worthy

of being called “ideas,” that are mingled together in the viscera

rather than the head. To think out ideas to their logical conclusion,

to be consistent and complete in thought, is viewed as a form of

intellectual aggression that stimulates reticence or withdrawal

rather than dialogue or response. The modern “ego” is now so

fragile that the mere presence of passion, particularly in the form

of argumentation, is a stimulus to flight or, worse, cause for a

yielding quietism. The emphasis that the Athenians placed on

speaking, which was identified with democracy, spells out the

extent to which a qualitative breach separates our pitiful image of

public activity from the classical one of two millennia ago.

What should be stressed, for the present, is that the Athenian

ideal of citizenship did not die in the formal sense, even after

Macedonia had eviscerated the democracy. The *ekklesia* and

Mediterranean-wide belief in Athens’s uniqueness, all the more to

cloak a growing despotism that finally caused the last institutional

vestiges of the democracy to wither completely. And here lies a

lesson that later institutionally oriented democrats were to learn

at great cost. An *agora* does not in itself produce a *polis*, nor does

an *ekklesia* in itself produce citizens. All of them must exist, to be

sure, if a democracy is to be established; but they remain mere

formalities if they fail to interact in the proper way to form a

unified whole. It was this largely formal sense of democracy and

citizenship that served, in part at least, to abort the only attempt

to rescue the Roman republic in the guise of the Athenian *polis*.

It would be difficult to tell from Plutarch’s biographies of Tiberius

and Gaius Gracchus that the brothers were no mere agrarian

reformers; indeed that their laws to supplant the Senate’s powers

by the authority of the *comitia tributa* came as close to a fundamental political revolution as Rome ever experienced. The brothers, in M. I. Rostovtzeff’s view, were clearly out to “set up at Rome

a democracy of the Greek type,” a “dream or farce,” as he calls

It, that was designed “to transfer from the Senate to the popular

assembly the decision of all important business, or, in other words,

to set up at Rome a democracy after the Athenian model.”{27} Nor

Was this goal entirely impractical, at least institutionally. “To secure this point no special law was required: according to the constitution all important business was, in theory, settled by the popular assembly; the innovation was this, that business which by

custom had hitherto been decided by the Senate was now laid by

[Gaius] Gracchus, as tribune, before the popular assembly, for

their consideration and decision.”{28}

The effort ultimately foundered not for want of institutional mechanisms but for lack of a genuine citizenry. Despite

Rostovtzeff’s aristocratic biases, he is on solid ground when he

emphasizes that “to allow land even to every member of the

proletariat could never bring back a time when the state rested

NOCurely upon a strong peasant population.”{29} The culture that

produced men such as Cincinnatus or the elder Cato was waning

and had to be recovered or a new one developed in its place if

mere institutional changes were to be viable and lasting. The

Gracchi would have had to deal with still another change that

would ultimately undermine the entire republican edifice. Rome

was no longer a city in any Hellenic sense of the term. It was the

center of an emerging empire, an *urbs*, to use the conventional

Latin word for “city,” that had ceased to be a *civitas*, the word

Romans commonly used to denote a “union of citizens.” The terminological distinction is apt: the Roman *urbs* was growing uncontrollably by the second century B.C., at the expense of the Roman

scope, especially after the spoils of the Punic Wars began to fill its

coffers. Conceivably, the yeoman-citizens who founded the republic could have turned it into a democracy. But once they “came

down from the Seven Hills” on which Rome was founded, they

became “small,” to use Heine’s words. The “idea of Rome” as a

spiritual heritage diminished in direct proportion to the growth of

the city. “The greater Rome grew,” Heine wrote, “the more this

idea dilated; the individual lost himself in it: the great men who

remain eminent are borne up by this idea, and it makes the littleness of the little men even more pronounced.”{30}

The decline of the ancient world did not efface the ideals that

Athens and Rome inspired. Later eras were to blur them so that

we now speak of two kinds of “democracy,” “direct” and “representative,” as though they derive from a common heritage. During inspired moments, medieval and modern cities were to fluctuate between the two and, at times, come closer to a Hellenic

democracy and citizenry than the Gracchi could have achieved in

Rome. What these cities achieved in fact, however, they rarely

achieved in ideology; hence their patterns of civic freedom were

basically intuitive creations. They did not last long. But in an era

of chilling discontinuities, when our knowledge of western culture

is in grave peril of disappearing, we can no more ignore the legacy

of their example than we can ignore the sprawling urbanization

that threatens our civic identity and political freedom.

Chapter Five: Patterns of Civic Freedom

Although the city was the cultural center of the ancient world, its

material base was extremely fragile. Hence the remarkable rise

and fall of cities throughout antiquity. City life depended to a

remarkable degree on the viability and the economy of agrarian

communities and labor so that cities appear more as islands in a

vast rural ocean than self-sustaining economic entities. Indeed,

prudent estimates of the number of rural workers needed to sustain a single city dweller have been placed at a ratio of ten to one.

Hence any serious agricultural catastrophe like a drought, floods,

or pest infestation, not to speak of wars that devastated agriculture, could lead to the breakdown, indeed the complete disappearance, of a major city as so many civic ruins from antiquity

attest to this very day.

The fragile dependence of the city on the countryside’s economy placed a high.premium on the stability of urban institutions.

The Hellenic emphasis on the *polis* as a realm of reason that had

to vigilantly guard itself against a surrounding world of chaotic

uncertainty and mindless barbarism—a sensibility so important to

understanding its attitude toward women, slaves, and aliens—is

not without its roots in the compelling realities of ancient urban

life. A nature tamed by man, specifically by well-established and

reliable farmers, forms the matrix of Hellenic philosophy and the

great cultural monuments of the Athenian *polis*. Civic democracy

was largely an agrarian democracy, and its ideal of the farmer-citizen, however dubious it became in the later history of the *polis*,

was the product of a very viable agrarian heritage. Rome, too,

developed these ideals and did ndt require Greek culture to produce them.

Correspondingly, the ancient city was not only a center for

country life whose standards were formed by farmers, later by

nobles and “country gentlemen,” but it was “seafaring” in a very

loose sense of the term. Owing to the insecurity that the city felt

as an “atoll... on an ocean of rural primitivism,” it direly needed

access to the sea to cope with any dislocations between town and

country. The all-important factor that could correct any imbalances caused by drought, flood, plague, arid other such disasters

was imports or, put more bluntly, the tribute that a city-state could

exact from a league of captive “allies” or the victims of outright

conquest. The Delian League,i which Athens established to assert

its supremacy over the eastern Mediterranean, quickly turned

into a relatively modest looting enterprise to feed and provide the

“good fife” for its citizens. The Roman Empire is a lasting historical example of parasitism run riot to the point of moral, cultural, and societal suicide.

Hence, ancient cities were located within a hundred miles or

so of the Mediterranean Sea or close to navigable rivers that led

to major bodies-of water. Ancient Lugdunum (modern Lyons)

provides us, with an example of a city that Rome founded in 43

B.C., deeply inland in Gaul, that was. felicitously located at the

confluence of the Rhone and Saone rivers. Beyond the coasts and

rivers, cities dwindled to towns and, not much farther, to villages

and hamlets that then phased into a little known wilderness where

military forts kept a guarded eye on restless barbarian tribes. Ancient cities were never autonomous urban centers. Fragile in the

extreme, they depended upon local agricultural communities for

the most important essentials of fife, a very simple technology, and

a considerable amount of human muscle power to work it, If they

expanded beyond the capacity of their agricultural base, they

direly needed tribute from other city-states to sustain themselves

unless they enjoyed natural blessings such as the Nile, whose annual overflow in September provided Egypt with endless quantities of fertile soil from the highlands of Ethiopia.

Modern urban dwellers tend to feel uneasy about so tentative

and qualified an image of the city., We like to think of cities as

“eternal” and urban cultural fife as free of rural social influences.

We are willing to grant that cities do change with architectural

innovations, technology, and societal advances but that basically

they are immune to the ravages of time and the vicissitudes of

history. The tombs of buried cities in Anatolia, Mesopotamia,

North Africa, and the ruins of Central America and Mexico are

grim reminders that cities can die forever without successors to

overlay them, indeed that historically they have been terribly

Vulnerable to social and ecological changes. Nor do we like to

think that, cities have any significant roots in agrarian societies,

Indeed that they did not always “dominate” the countryside in the

(ill-encompassing sense that they do today. The enormous power

modern cities exercise over rural fife—not only economically and

technologically but culturally—seems to be a historic destiny in

Our eyes that is structured into citification or “civilization” from

its very origins, a *telos* that predestines urban fife to achieve lasting supremacy over all other fife ways. The great urban belts that

sprawl across the land, ugly as they may be, appear to us as the

culmination, perhaps the fulfillment, of a drama in which early

temple cities or Greek *poleis* were merely archetypal characters

ill a larger and more sweeping civic story that reaches its climax

In what we call “modernity” and all its citified amenities. That

contemporary urbanization does not represent the culmination or

fulfillment of citification, that the history of the city cannot be

properly understood with the hindsight and Eurocentricity of a

New Yorker, Parisian, Berliner, or Londoner reveals a modern

conceit that under critical examination tells us how skewed and

misleading are popular ideas of how cities actually developed and

the special identities they acquired.

This conceit, to be sure, is not entirely modern. Ancient empires such as the Babylonian and Persian built cities to last and

earnestly believed in their immortality. The Greek image of the

fame that would survive his own mortality. The words “eternal

Rome” are proverbial. Even before the rise of Christianity, they

entered deeply into the consciousness of the city’s citizens. As it

turned out, the closing years of the empire, a span of two centuries

before it finally fell apart, were riddled by deep civic pessimism.

The Romans of that time were filled with a fatalistic despair about

the future of their city and eventually transferred their allegiance

from the “eternal city” to the “City of God.”

What distinguished their civic optimism from our civic arrogance, however, is our preening belief in the autonomy of the city,

our conviction that city life and its traditions have always enjoyed

a supremacy over rural lifeways and cultures, indeed that the

former stands in innovative and exciting contrast to the latter.

This conceit is very different from the ancient commitment to the

city and has its origins in the highly introverted civic development

of Europe during the late Middle Ages. Judging from the comedies

of antiquity, Greeks and Romans had their “country bumpkins”

who were the naive foils for “city slickers. But the ancients never

doubted that these “bumpkins” were their “country cousins” in a

very real cultural and material sense. The ancestral farm, if an

urban citizen owned one, or the family village where the bones of

his ancestors lay, was a place to which he repaired from the demands and stresses of city living. It was there that he found his

“roots” and from there that he carried his household deities into

the very confines of the city. It was from the country, too, that he

acquired his bread, cheese, figs, and precious olives so characteristic of Mediterranean fare, for no doubt existed in his mind that,

all its cultural amenities aside, the city was materially dependent

upon the immediate countryside and the farmers who trundled its

produce into his squares.

His political fife, such as it was after the decline of the *polis*, had

a distinct rural imprint: it centered around assemblies even in

Rome and other cities outside Latium, on such councils of “elders”

as the Senate, and, in republican times, on a citizen-militia, all of

which were institutions formed by early village and town democracies. It is in this sense, by no means a strictly exploitative one,

that we can agree with Chester G. Starr’s observation that nearly

all ancient cities “controlled a wide expanse of countryside, which

extended in more recently urbanized areas as far as fifty miles or

more from the city walls; they thus resembled an American or

English county more than our purely urban units of government.

Commerce and industry might have some significance within this

complex but did not need to do so, for its unity rested primarily

on administrative, agricultural, and psychological bonds.”{31} A

brisk walk of an hour or so could bring a Roman within clear sight

of farmland and within two or three additional hours to villages

that seemed largely untouched by urban culture.

That the ancient city also carried enormous political weight in

Mediterranean life and was a source of considerable ferment, indeed, potentially, of serious rebellions against its imperial sovereigns, is a fact that never left the minds of the Roman emperors.

Not that the peasantry was totally passive and free of strong resentments—not only toward the imperial city but also its own

urban centers. Attica’s “party of the Plain,” as historians call it,

enviously regarded the Athenian town-dweller as a parasite and

periodically aligned itself against him, hence Kleisthenes’ shrewd

admixture of urban with rural *trittyes* to neutralize these conflicts.

In Roman times a rural police was created by the city, particularly

In the Near East, to maintain “order” among the agricultural poor.

But the emperors kept an especially tight rein on the cities

under their control, for it was here that internecine conflicts

against urban oligarchies and civic chauvinism could reach acute

proportions. “The ancient city was an institution which swallowed

up much of its citizens’ hearts,” Starr tells us, and Roman emperors “were undoubtedly right in feeling that the Roman world

could not endure outright war among its constituent units but the

necessary alternative was deplorable: the race for titles was miserable stuff to fire civic loyalty and to promote urban thinking.”{32}

Ultimately, through imperial paternalism, legal constraints, and

the use of oligarchies to control or deflect the anger of lower

orders in their own cities, “the vigor of local politics waned; the

cities were not granted, as a substitute, a really significant, inspiriting influence on the imperial government. In all this the Empire

was wiping out not merely freedom of thought in the political

Sphere but the very possibility of serious political action for the

bulk of its subjects. So it was destroying a very important focus for

the forces which had led to the expansion and remarkable vitality

of Mediterranean civilization up to this point. The upper classes

and the Caesars both delivered devastating blows at the sense of

local attachment, the solidarity of the city, from which the thinkers of the past had drawn their strength.” Whatever Roman civilization seemed to produce in the way of order and uniformity of

laws, it more than destroyed in the way of creativity and political

commitment. By the latter part of the fifth century A.D., the Mediterranean basin had ceased to be either orderly or innovative. In

balance, the cost of imperial and bureaucratic control from above

with its loss of local control and participation outweighed, by far,

the dubious benefits it professed to confer and the entire basin

suffered a collapse that was to haunt civilization throughout future

centuries.[6]

[6] For a more detailed discussion of the decline of Rome and the problems the

empire created, the reader should read my book, *The Limits of the City* (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1973, pp. 32–35).

----

By contrast to the Mediterranean basin, Europe through the Middle Ages and well into modern times followed a very different

development. Although European patterns of civic freedom

never equalled the institutional and political creativity of the

the Greek cities, and it is from this world that modern images of

urban supremacy really derive. From the thirteenth century onward, particularly in Italy and the lowlands of modern Belgium

and Holland, city-states began to emerge that were structured

around uniquely urban tasks—artisan oriented, financial, commercial, and industrial—that slowly loosened urban fife from its traditional agrarian matrix and provided the town with an authentic

civic fife and momentum of its own.

Which is not to say that medieval towns and cities ceased to be

dependent upon their rural environs for food and raw materials.

But as time passed, in different parts of western Europe, it was to

be the city that gradually remade the countryside in its own image

and entangled the landed nobility in its own economic and political concerns. And ultimately it was to be the city that imposed its

technics, economic relationships, culture, and values on agrarian

communities.

Traditional agrarian attitudes did not place a high premium on

artisans, merchants, and financiers; these were not orders that

were respected in ancient society. A Greek or Roman “bourgeois”

who made a profitable income from trade and workshops tried to

accumulate enough wealth in order to retire on landed property

of his own and five in rural gentility with the airs of a noble.

Capital migrated from town to country, not the reverse. The

medieval world radically altered this movement. For the first time

on a large scale, urban entrepreneurs began, to view their vocations as honorable and invest their earnings from generation to generation in their own enterprises.

As family fortunes increased, they remained in the city and

were not invested into estates. Quite to the contrary, it was the

Italian and Flemish noble who often moved to town and began to

enchance his own fortunes by involving himself in industry, trade,

and foreign promise. The “merchant prince” of the Middle Ages

was not simply a euphemism for men of ignoble lineages who

managed to, acquire “princely” fortunes from trade. The words

often included noblemen of highly prestigious families who regarded the city as a center of a very lucrative commerce and began to participate in it with the avidity of the most pedestrian

burgher.

How this reversal of traditional trends occurred can only be

noted summarily here, The breakup of the top-heavy, highly parasitic, and costly Roman Empire led to a general retreat of the Latin

cities and their European affines in Iberia, Gaul, and Britain to

their authentic ecological *chora*: the land base that could properly

support a modest urban population. As sources of tribute began to

break away from the empire and its provinces were assailed by

repeated invasions of semitribal German, Slav, and Magyar peoples, the fragile ancient city dwindled to little more than a village

scale, at least in western Europe where urban fife had a, very

limited land base and abutted the vast forest that still covered

most of the continent. Rome’s population alone declined from its

highpoint of a million to less than 50,000 in the “Dark Ages” that

followed and never fully recovered demographically through the

medieval period, despite its enormous importance as the center of

western Christianity. Already, as early as the third century, the

European provinces such as Iberia, Gaul, and Britain began to

detach themselves from the empire in everything but name and

move toward a localist economy that produced only for their own

particular needs. As John Mundy and Peter Reisenberg point out,

the foundations for a decentralized medieval society were not

created by German invaders, the “barbarians at the gates” who

sounded the death knell of a terminally ill empire; they were

established by Rome itself when the late Caesars, faced with a

completely unwieldly imperial structure, set each order in Roman

society adrift with the necessary “duties, privileges and special

jurisdictions [it needed] to implement its work.” Each group, in

effect, was obliged to make “its own law” in order to survive.

“Moreover, the old classical conception of liberty was replaced by

something less grand but more socially exact. Gildsmen, or **collegiati,** were privileged, for example, even to the equestrian

grade. But privilege depended upon obligatory service. This perception of an inmixture of liberty and servitude pervaded late

Roman and much of medieval social thought.”{33}

The veering of the former Roman provinces toward a highly

localist society, one in which each component was internally held

together by an elaborate hierarchy of clearly defined rights and

duties, laid the foundations for European feudalism. Autarchy,

now based on hierarchy, surfaced with a vengeance in the form

of minutely segmented and self-sufficient communities, all supported by agriculture and a rude form of manorial artisanship.

Cities that were once the islands in a rural world largely disappeared while the rural society seemed to solidify into minute congeries of simple manors, each surrounded by small dependent

villages. The serfs who peopled these villages were not attached

permanently to the land. Both manor and village, in turn, seemed

to be haunted by the nearby debris of ruined cities, some partly

occupied, which were testimony to an exotic world clouded by

legends of past greatness and the misty traditions of imperial

power. Within this setting, we do not have to go too far to understand the origins of the Arthurian legends of Britain and the dreams of grandeur that clustered around the name of Charlemagne.

These ruins came to fife very slowly, often as the building

materials of churches, modest villas, and town halls. The medieval

towns and the few cities that we find in the eleventh century after

the great tides of “barbarian” invaders and the fractured empires

of Charlemagne receded into history were very unusual

phenomena. Although they were never independent materially,

there is a very real sense in which they were to become quite

autonomous economically, to an extent, in fact, that was quite rare

in the ancient city. To begin with, they were not simply religious

or administrative centers as were so many of their classical predecessors, although such centers were fairly common in medieval

Europe. What is significant about them is that they were largely

structured around the tasks that most markedly distinguish the

city from the agrarian village: crafts, trade, a nascent form of

mechanized industry, and a culture—moral, artistic, architectural,

and even religious—that is peculiar to such a citified constellation

of activities. No longer was nonagricultural work demeaning, nor

for that matter was work generally, as ultimately became the case

during the imperial period of Rome and the old Mediterranean

slavocracy. Quite to the contrary, nonagricultural work was to be

celebrated over all other forms as authentic evidence of “civilization,” so that, etymologically speaking, the word now came into its

own. The artisan and tradesman, normally metics whom the ancient city dweller viewed with condescension as the urban counterparts of the rural “primitives” (the view that the imperial age

created toward its once idealized yeomanry), now found themselves the center of a new concept of urbanity, indeed, the city’s

most prized and productive member. Trade itself, which aristocrats at all times slyly exploited to their own advantage, was

openly acknowledged as an honorable enterprise, and wealthy

merchants began to give lavishly of their fortunes to adorn this

new civic temple to their interests. However much the Church

viewed profit making as intrinsically evil, it soon learned to accommodate itself to this new civic reality despite its pious denunciations of gain from the pulpit.

This new kind of city appeared not only because of the extraordinary energy Europe brought to a world drained by imperial

tribute; it also emerged because of the inherent weakness that

marked a highly decentralized and parochial system of agriculture. Whatever may be the image Roman nobles developed of

their servile farming orders, the aristocrats of the ancient world

still prized their status and traditions as landed gentry. To own a

large estate, worked by gangs of slaves and tenants, was as much

a calling as it was a lucrative enterprise. The nobles, moreover,

had used the Empire to wrest all political power from the artisan

and merchant orders, and thus gave their imprimature to the

ancient city: its odium of parasitism, display, indolence, luxury,

and class arrogance. The cities they now controlled became monuments to their power as lords of a basically agrarian economy and

culture. Under the Caesars, this economy and culture did not

disappear; quite to the contrary, it was greatly strengthened by a

huge bureaucracy and enriched by an immense flow of tribute.

The ancient city never transcended these economic and cultural

limits. The *polis*, to be sure, gave it a creativity that made civic

life seem like a work of art. Rome, particularly under the Empire,

gave it a highly elaborate state apparatus that made it a self-destructive engine for exploiting Mediterranean society.

The medieval city was more fortunate and found itself surprisingly free of these limits. Agrarian society in the Middle Ages was

much too fragmented to establish lasting obstacles to urban development:, and its culture was much too introverted to challenge the

new “civilization” nurtured by the towns. The famous medieval

maxim, “Urban air makes for freedom/’ could be, said to include

freedom of thought and an openness to innovation as well as personal and political liberty. Like a calculating observer who can

patiently stand by while his opponents exhaust themselves in mutual combat, the medieval towns played for time and waited for

the temporal lords to drain their strength in the ceaseless rivalries

that marked the era. When the local nobles were weak enough or

drained of their wealth, the cities stepped in to assert their own

autonomy, either by buying their freedom or by force of arms, and

ultimately were to assert their supremacy over the countryside.

This drama, to be sure, did not unfold with the elegant consistency we often expect from a good story. Many cities and towns

failed to gain their freedom for generations, despite bitter struggles with their territorial lords. And when they did so, their liberties were often fragile and highly vulnerable to internal as well as

external challenges. In retrospect, however, we can see a fairly

distinct pattern of civic freedom emerge, not only from territorial

lords but also structurally, within the medieval *civitas* itself. The

Italian city-states, in particular, provide the **dramatis personae**

and almost exemplary “plot lines” for an overall story of European

civic development. Not that other cities—Flemish, German,

French, and Swiss—are not good examples in their own right, or,

in some cases, more lasting patterns of civic freedom. But what

Lauro Martines calls the “power and, imagination” of the Italian

city-states is so vibrant, so artistically creative and institutionally

stimulating, that one senses a degree of organicity and roundedness rarely matched for that period by other European regions.{34}

And if we rise above the national chauvinism that afflicted medievalists of the recent past, it would be hard to disagree with Mundy

that the “distinction between the northern European and Italian

town” drawn by Belgium’s great historian, Henri Pirenne, a distinction that so greatly biased a whole generation of medieval

scholars toward the northern city-states, “seems to have no basis

in fact, at least through the ages of urban renewal up to the twelfth

century,” a time when urban freedom reached its peak internally.{35}

We also know that the movement for civic freedom really

began in Italy and only later did it move up to Flanders, northern

France, and southern, Germany. Thereafter it became a contagion

in the cities of western and central Europe. To discuss so mixed

and uneven a development in civic freedom’ we would be obliged

to leap almost dervishly from one region to another to uncover the

underlying sequence of events that makes medieval urban development reasonably intelligible. If most of this account focuses on

the Italian experience, it is because the peninsula’s city-states encapsulate in a clearly definable area the basic cycle that marked

the rise and decline of civic democracy in Europe as a whole.

Indeed, it was in Italy that the city-state of the High Middle Ages

was to come into its own, and it is from the rich accounts of that

civic world—its extraordinary art and architecture, its changing

political relationships, and its cycle of birth, maturation, and decay—that the European municipality was to play out its most authentic internal development and lead, almost unerringly, to the urban

drama that is unfolding before our eyes today.

----

The origins of these city-states need not concern us. After at least

a millennium of urban development, from the legendary founding

of Rome in 753 B.C. to the last of the emperors in 476 A.D., probably no area in ancient Europe was more citified than Italy and few

municipalities exhibited more staying power than those that the

German invaders engulfed as they rolled over the peninsula. Thus,

Italian cities never really disappeared. However much they declined demographically, they recovered fairly early and by the

tenth century began to grow with exceptional verve and energy.

Nor need we trouble ourselves too much about the factors that

led to this recovery. So far as the northern Mediterranean was

concerned, the Saracen floodtide that swept over the basin began

to recede by the eleventh century: even Sicily was reclaimed for

Christianity by 1091, after two centuries of Muslim occupation. By

this time, a lively trade existed between Italian and Arab merchants until the Mediterranean between the twelfth and fourteenth centuries was largely controlled by the Italian city-states

lake from 1150 to 1350. These city-states were soon the major

entrepot agents that brought Christian and Muslim into commercial contact with each other, and the economic foundations for a

flourishing municipal fife were securely established.

The locale of the Italian city-state, or **communa** to use its medieval Latin name, covered most of the northern and central areas of

the peninsula and embraced the great Renaissance cities of Florence, Venice, Verona, Pisa, Sienna, and Cremona, to cite only a

few, and those great political nodal points of Italy’s history, Milan,

Genoa, and Bologna. It is not the Renaissance that will concern us

here, except insofar as the Dominican Fra Savonarola represented

a popular reaction to the aristocratic and simoniacal world that

fostered it, and it is not the **communa** as a “city republic,” words

so easily interchangeable with “city-state” that will be our main

focus of interest. What is insufficiently known about the Italian

commune is the extent to which it became a stage for a working

democracy and its actors a new expression for an active citizenry.

Dazzling as its cultural treasures and adventurous as its stories

may be, we must put aside the pure glamour of the commune and

examine those brief periods when it seemed more like a *polis* than

a republic.

Democracy clearly emerged in the early Italian cities, not only

representative forms of governance and oligarchies of various

kinds, only to submerge and then reappear again for a short time

in richly articulated forms. Its principal institution took the.form

of a popular assembly and we hear of it almost from the inception

of the commune itself. The Italian commune, it should be clear,

was not simply a community or even a town in the customary civic

sense of the term, although it was this as well. It was above all an

association of burghers who were solemnly united by an oath or

we might simply designate as a town into a vibrant fraternity.

Although motivated by shared practical concerns, the burghers

who took this oath were presumably foreswearing their personal

self-interest on behalf of a common one, a conscious act of mutual

fealty not to a local noble, cleric, military chieftain, or distant

monarch. Despite its strongly religious terms, it was an act of

citizenship, unique in an age of religious congregations, that

pledged members of the commune to respect each others’ civic

rights and extend them untampered to newcomers and future

generations.

The *conjuratio*, in fact, did considerably more: it committed the

citizens of the commune to orderly and broadly consensual ways

of governing themselves with a decent respect for individual liberty and a pledge to their mutual defense. The stormy conflicts

between the monarchs of the Holy Roman Empire and their Italian vassals, and more disruptively between local bishops, nobles,

and military captains over landed domains and control over the

cities, were resolved by a delineable and, at times, a logical course

of urban development to which the *conjuratio* forms a point of

ethical entry. Once the cities replaced arbitrary rule with some

kind of elective rule, coordinates emerged for gauging its political

evolution. Men then swore to aid and defend each other, to pledge

their prestige and bring their personal jurisdictions to the service

of a shared community, and to respectfully invest the chosen

heads of this civic association with executive and judicial powers.

A consulate, composed of all the consuls in formal assembly, constituted the highest executive and judicial magistracy of this remarkable association. We know that its members were chosen at

a general assembly of the commune itself, a popular assembly that

“was quite likely convened with some regularity, and in times of

trouble even more often,” Lauro Martines tells us. “Here the

views of leading men were heard and important decisions taken,

usually by acclamation.” We know, too, that this general assembly

of “all the members of the commune” was the “oldest communal

institution” of these Italian cities, and further, that the, consuls

usually “sounded out the general assembly” before they made any

major decisions about such issues as war and peace, taxes, and

laws.{36} What is so vexing is that we know so little about this revival

of a highly democratic, face-to-face form of political control and

of the citizens who created it. Whether age endowed it with the

legitimacy of an unbroken tradition back to ancient times, we do

not know—only that it was the oldest of the commune’s structures.

This much is clear: whatever authority the assembly enjoyed prior

to the consulate—that is, if it existed at all before the *conjuratio*—is clouded by the furious infighting between clerics, nobles,

opportunists of all kinds who managed to grasp and lose control

of the cities for nearly two centuries before these civic entities

freed themselves of arbitrary rule and disruptive rivalries.

Considering the volatility of the Italian city-states, the assembly

soon lost ground to the consulate and the consuls, who began to

elect their own successors. The Italian city was never to be restrained by such Hellenic mores as “nothing in excess” or the

Pythagorean ideal of **harmonia**. One could almost say that seldom

did anything but excess and explosive political theatrics, mark

these fervent and creative urban entities. In any case, civic leadership fell into the hands of large, wealthy families who were to

establish the parameters of civic ‘politics for centuries to come,

even after they were temporarily removed from power or replaced by newcomers from within or outside the city. The assembly, in turn, never totally disappeared. It lingered on in a highly

atrophied form and haunted the oligarchs and despots who

usurped its powers. We know that in Bergamo, for example, as

elsewhere, outgoing consuls were obliged to hold elections for

new ones in popular assemblies, although the nomination of candidates was the privilege of only a few. Such practices persisted well

into the twelfth century when cities such as Genoa and Pistoia

tried to eliminate prearranged nominations of consuls between

electors that favored one of the parties at the expense of another.

In time, this early popular democracy gave way to republican

forms of governance, and the powers of the city were invested in

a large legislature dominated by influential urban families. In

some places, the assembly continued on as a vestige to be manipulated by oligarchs. Elsewhere, it was replaced by “assemblies” that

were simply republican legislatures. “Emulating all princely

courts and the general assemblies in Italian towns, some of these

[representative] assemblies hoped to meet four times a year,”

observes John H. Mundy. “This was impracticable for general

assemblies, but smaller select councils often did meet three or four

times yearly....”{37} Although Mundy is referring here specifically

to England, the drift from popular assemblies to oligarchical councils was as true of Italy as it was for Europe generally. The “conciliarism,” as this parliamentary trend was called, essentially replaced civic democracies, such as they were, with authentic city

republics, and the great towns of Italy looked more, institutionally

speaking, like preimperial Rome than classical Athens.

We must not suppose, however, that Italy became a centralized

State at this time, even on a municipal base. Whether as a democracy or a republic, the Italian city rested to an astonishing extent

on little neighborhood “communes” that existed within the larger

urban commune. We have no parallel for this development in

ancient Athens or Rome. Irrespective of the kind of consulate it

had, the city’s neighborhoods acquired an autonomy of their own

that is truly spectacular by any standards of civic governance.

Fortified towers rose everywhere—in Milan, Florence, Pisa,

Verona, Pavia, Parma, and the like—held by noble families in

the commune as a whole. Oaths were sworn everywhere in the

tradition of the *conjuratio* but so localist in their commitments

that we can only describe a commune as a loose confederation of

neighborhood communes, indeed, a confederation of neighborhoods within the commune. “When a union of this sort brought

peace to a neighborhood,” observes Martines, “that part of the city

became nearly impregnable, because the linking of towers and the

easy blocking of the narrow streets made for an effective domination of the adjoining area.”{38}

Let there be no mistake about the fact that these *consortia*

were anything but neighborhood democracies. The towers were

built by leading wealthy families who were much too powerful in

Home respects, and much too weak in others, to seize complete

control of the commune. They were highly localist oligarchies that

kept Italian cities in continual turmoil until they were supplanted

by despotic **signori**, family dynasties ruled by one man who replaced a multitude of oligarchies, often to be unseated again and

his sons restored in reckless shifts of aristocratic and military

power. Italian civic history is not notable for any even or linear

development from democracy through republican systems to oligarchy, monarchy, and despotism. All five of these institutional

forms bubbled up in an unpredictable assortment of patterns,

predominantly as one at certain times or in combination with each

other on many other occasions. Ultimately, the Renaissance cities

settled down as oligarchies and princely courts where an electrifying but aristocratic humanism gave us the priceless artistic treasures of that era.

But the *consortia* created “bad” and lasting habits that fostered

a highly democratic atmosphere at the base of city fife. It produced neighborhood loyalty and citizen empowerment with a

vengeance. “Propertied urban inhabitants were attached tenaciously not merely to a city but to a street, a parish, an ambience—to a radius of perhaps 150 meters,” declares Martines. “And

though a citizen might frequent an estate in the country, he lived

in the city and there, if fortunate, he died. More likely than not,

he married someone from that vicinage, and all his main blood

ties, as well as his closest friendships, were there. The character of

the neighborhood could be so distinctive, could’ leave so deep an

imprint on its inhabitants, as to make for different linguistic expressions and even for different intonations or accents. Dante detected neighborhood differences in speech at Bologna.”[7]{39}

[7] This is a feature that existed even in New York during the 1930s, which I

distinctly recall as a young man. This great city, at one time an agglomeration of

a thousand ethnically unique neighborhoods, seemed to have been stopped in

time, for a generation or two, and created much the same degree of neighborhood

loyalties and distinctive accents. I have encountered such differences in New

Orleans today, although they are rapidly disappearing. The emergence of civic

variety, loyalty, and cultural diversity even in modern American cities is an important theme to which we shall return later in this book, and the consequences of

its loss will be fully explored as a consequence of contemporary urbanization.

These loyalties gave the commune a political vitality it never

fully lost until recent times. Conciliar governance did not abolish

major democratic features of the city such as the selection of

consuls by sortition at Lucca, for example, where the neighborhoods or **contrada** convened in their own assemblies and “lots

were drawn,” notes Daniel Waley, whereupon “each of the 550

men who drew slips inscribed **elector consiliari** then had the duty

of naming one man from his own **contrada** as a councillor.”{40}

When the **podesta** system of government or **podesteria** was established in Italian communes that vested all executive power in a

single man, he too was often chosen this way. In Vicenza during

the mid-thirteenth century, twenty city electors “were chosen by

lot, and of these twelve were eliminated by voting; the eight

remaining electors then proposed three names, from which the

final choice was made by a further vote of the council.”{41} The

councils, in turn, often required a quorum of two-thirds to arrive

at a decision, and in some cities councillors were fined for failing

to attend. Nor is it unusual to learn that a majority of two-thirds

was needed to make major decisions, at which time even larger

quorums and majorities as high as 10/11 or 16/17 were required—proportions that could almost be regarded as consensual.

The **podesteria**, for all its majesty and seeming absolutism, was

by no means the authoritarian ogre it initially appears to be. A

<em>podesta</em> was not selected from any members of the community.

He had to be an outsider who could distance himself from the

internecine familial and factional conflicts that often brought the

city to the brink of chaos, hence too the elaborate electoral system

that was meant to buffer the influence of particularly powerful

groups. Nor could he come from a neighboring commune, which

obviously was privy to the city’s infighting. He was selected for his

impartiality, for his legal training, and ordinarily held his office for

no more than a year, often as little as six months. The consulate,

like the assembly, did not disappear; indeed, in Treviso as late as

1283, general assemblies of virtually all resident citizens who enjoyed rights to public office were convened to deal with emergencies, even if only to bestow almost despotic powers of control on

a military captain.

A detailed account of the **podesteria**, **signori**, the later courts of

the Sforza and Medici, and the republican oligarchies that overturned these various forms of one-man control, would require a

volume in itself. Here we must focus on the conflict between the

“People” and the “nobility,” the *popolo* and *nobilta* as they were

called respectively. Equivalently, we could have called the “people” the “foot soldiers” or **pedites** and the “nobility” the “knights”

or **milites**, the military characterizations so redolent of the rise of

Greece’s **hoplites** and the supremacy they achieved over the aristocratic cavalry. The parallel, limited as it may be, is quite instructive. What the Italian citizens of the twelfth and early thirteenth

centuries called the *popolo* was in no sense the urban poor, the

inchoate stratum of journeymen, relatively unskilled craftsmen

who verged on being proletarians, laborers, servants, itinerant

tradesmen, runaway serfs, and that vast **déclassé** of beggars and

thieves who plagued the medieval cities almost from their inception. Many of these elements could be expected to follow any

standard that filled their empty pockets. In a feudal world where

a feeling of social place was crucial to one’s sense of self-regard,

they were outside the pale of the commune’s life and its broader

political concerns.

^yhat the commune meant by the *popolo* were men with a

certain amount of material substance, such as master craftsmen,

professionals, notaries, well-off tradesmen, even financiers and an

emerging commercial bourgeoisie that owned sizable fortunes

from foreign trade. Although there was a close interlinking of the

draw precise class lines in the conflicts that brought the two into

opposition with each other, many of the *popolo* were’ virtually

excluded from the city’s political life and were treated like resident aliens, the **metics** of ancient Athens. They paid its taxes,

served in its militia, and were subject to all its laws without any

right to hold public office or enter into its civic councils. In cities

of 40,000 or more, active citizenship was restricted by property

qualifications, social status, and length of residence to a thousand

or less. Although the Milanese *popolo* provided the city with the

greatest part of its revenues, for example, they held only one-fifth

of the consulate’s offices. Later, on the intervention of the Holy

Roman Emperor, Otto IV, they were given half of the conciliar

seats. This reform and others like it were enough to whet appetites

without providing enough sustenance to keep them satisfied. In

the first half of the thirteenth century, the *popolo* began to take

over the reins of power in one commune after another—Bologna

by 1231, Pistoiain 1237, Florence in 1250—and to acquire a growing voice in the governance of Piacenza, Lodi, Bergamo, Siena,

Parma, and Qenoa. “The *popolo*’s breakthrough into politics was

the result of revolutionary organization,” declares Martines with

a decisiveness that is not easy to encounter among many historians

of the era.{42} In a very real sense, perhaps more sweeping than we

realize, he is correct.

In retrospect, what makes the *popolo*’s ways of organizing so

revolutionary was its highly localist and organic fashion of acting

politically, a form of organizing that is utterly antithetical to modern concepts of party politics. The *popolo* had turned themselves

into a neighborhood movement, not unlike the **contrada** in structure and the **consorterie** in their ‘confederal way of interlinking

with each other. The noble families of two centuries earlier had

taught its more servile orders well in the arts of political organization and power, The tradition of organizing a movement on a

block-to-block, square-to-square basis had not died out in Italian

cities after the *podestarie* subdued the interfamilial squabbles

within the nobility. It was still very much alive, and the *popolo*

used it well. However varied the specific structures this organization produced, certain forms clearly emerged from this neighborhood base.

The rise of vocational gilds provided one very important pattern for linking men of the same occupation from different neighborhoods into a common organization. Gilds were established not

only for merchants, physicians, apothecaries, jurists, and notaries,

but also for smiths, cloth finishers, butchers, bakers, furriers, tanners, leather makers and the like, generally reflecting the *popolo*’s

social composition as a whole. These vocational groups, composed

almost exclusively of well-to-do tradesmen and master craftsmen

in their fields, were the earliest popular organizations of which we

have any record, and they tried not only to control the operations

of their crafts and its produce but also constituted themselves into

armed societies with the very distinct goal of controlling the commune. Before long, open clashes exploded between the *popolo*

and the *nobilta* at Brescia in 1192, Piacenza in 1198, Milan in

1201, and in year-by-year sequence, Cremona, Assisi, Lucca, and

onward to Pistoia in 1234.

Neighborhoods were now convulsed by strife between poorly

trained and the more highly skilled fighters of the noble **consorterie**, Rarely had the armed citizen moved so much to the forefront

of civic political life. By now, armed popular societies based on

neighborhood ties began to supplant the gilds in order to deal with

the endemic warfare that erupted in the city’s streets. These societies were better trained than the vocational organizations. More

closely cemented by their ties as neighbors, they had a better

knowledge of the quarters in which they functioned and they

could muster their forces more rapidly and on shorter notice as

emergencies arose. If Bologna can be taken as an example of the

enhanced ways of dealing with the *nobilta*, it demonstrated the

need for the armed neighborhood societies to extend beyond the

gild framework into a more cohesive, area-oriented, well-synchronized, and highly cooperative form of military organization. By

the middle of the twelfth century, the city could boast of twentyfour armed neighborhood companies in comparison to Florence’s

twenty and still smaller numbers elsewhere. Moreover, the Bolognese societies were consolidated across adjacent urban parishes

into what looked very much like a citywide militia. The *popolo*, to

be sure, had not created the idea of a neighborhood militia out of

thin air; such companies of men living in the same parts of the city

had been the backbone of the communal military system for years.

What the *popolo* did, however, was to change the militia’s function from a mere civic guard, designed exclusively to defend the

commune from external enemies, into a politically insurrectionary

force designed to change the commune’s internal structure and

power relationships.

Florence’s armed societies can be taken as a general example

of the structure that the *popolo* established in the popular communes of Italy after their victory over the *nobilta*, The twenty

neighborhood companies it had created earlier now became the

commune’s exclusive fighting force, absorbing the remains of the

old one where it could. In districts where the *popolo* was weak,

a larger number of militia units were assigned to guard its interests. The rest were equally distributed throughout the city. Each

company adopted its own banner and insignia—a “dragon, a whip,

a serpent, a bull, a bounding horse, a Hon,” even a ladder, “were

emblazoned on individual shields and helmets,” Martines notes.

“Rigorous requirements required guildsmen to keep their arms

near at hand, above all in troubled times. The call to arms for the

twenty companies was the ringing of a special bell, posted near the

main public square. A standard-bearer, flanked by four lieutenants, was in command of each company. These men were elected

by a council of twenty-four members of the company and served

one year. The Captain of the People was the commander of the

twenty companies. Being an outsider, he was expected to stand

above the temptations of local partisanship. His oath of office

obliged him to call the companies to action whenever there was

a threat to the *popolo*.... The *popolo* had no trouble finding only

the most committed and reliable men for its armed companies.

The success of this was seen in moments of crisis, when the ardor

of the companies won many victories for the *popolo*,” a fact that

was not lost on Machiavelli some two centuries later when he

voiced his compelling argument for a citizen-militia as opposed to

the use of mercenaries in *The Prince*.{43}

Once it came to power, the *popolo* did not completely eliminate

the podestal constitution. A large Council of the People was formed

to counterbalance the power of the old communal legislature and a

powerful council of “elders” functioned as the commune’s executive. The Captain of the People was elevated to a status that, for all

practical purposes, matched that of the **podesta**, and he was fully

regaled with a court system that paralleled that of the podestal one.

The *popolo*, in effect, had structured a dual power into the older

constitution, matching the communal council with a popular one,

the **podesta** with the militia chieftain, and courts of both men as

counterweights to each other. Overarching this entire structure

was the popular militia itself, which could easily intervene in the

If this was a democracy, it was one of merchants, notaries,

professionals, and master craftsmen, not of journeymen, weavers, dyers, and laborers who formed the only “proletariat” the

thirteenth-century world knew. By the same token, however, it

was not a democracy of blooded idlers and aristocratic bullies.

The popular democracy was composed of men who worked with

their hands at crafts or devoted long hours of the day to the

chores of administration, business, and legal affairs. Whether

they were wealthy entrepreneurs or men of modest means, they

saw themselves as self-made individuals, not the heirs of family

wealth and unearned status; they believed; with good reason,

that, they lived highly productive, sober,‘and socially useful lives

and were far more capable than the nobles of bearing serious

responsibilities on, their shoulders. They were no one’s clients

and no one’s masters, except where they trained their own

successors in the skills of their crafts. Although the new manufacturers who operated with hired labor could hardly make this last

claim for themselves, they were far from constituting a majority

of the typical ltalian *popolo*. Italy in the thirteenth century was

not an industrial society with modern capitalists and workers. It

was a largely artisan and highly paternalistic world, and the men

who fathered its workshops as well as its families were not, disposed to grant the least modicum of: power to anyone who was a

subordinate. These men knew only too well that, without them,

the commune would quickly atrophy and disappear, but without

the nobles and, to a considerable extent, their own subordinates,

it could survive and ultimately flourish.

For limits of space, it is impossible to explore the vast cultural

impact the popular commune had on its age, be it the painting of

Giotto, the sensual realism of Boccaccio, the shift of literature from

Latin to the vernacular, the laicization. of education, the huge

increase in popular literacy, or a political tradition that trounced

any attempt at institutionalized despotism. For all his aristocratic

inclinations, Dante was a *popolani*, no less than the chronicler

Giovanni Villani whose history of Florence is one of the best to be

written of his era. The popular commune created new men who

breathed a fresher urban air than any of their medieval contemporaries: one relatively free of superstition, turgid scholasticism, and

social status; Above all, it produced a new kind of citizen who, with

his Weapons by his side and craft tools in his hands, felt boldly

empowered arid politically confident. Alert to any threat to his

liberties; he was prepared to fight for his rights with the same

energy with which he fashioned his produce. This alertness extended beyond a defensive stance against an aggressive nobility

into a mili tant interest in public affairs and a readiness to occupy

public responsibility. Not since Hellenic times did men of relatively modest means feel so close an identification between their

own interests and those of the city in which they lived. Deeply

individuated, indeed animated by a vivacious love of public debate and political discussion, such as Italians are to this very day,

this new citizen seemed all the more motivated to shape his city’s

destiny as well as his own. The ancient *civitas* as an association of

active citizens had been reborn, and its spirit was to live in its

citizen body long after its institutions were to atrophy and pass

into history.

That the popular commune did not last as long as the Athenian

problems could not be resolved by replacing a small oligarchy

with a bigger one. The popular commune, was not a “leveler” of

social orders and economic classes. Quite to the contrary, it gave

a new impetus to trade, the accumulation of wealth, and increasing economic and political differentiation, setting the *popolo grosso* or “fat people” against the *popolo magro* or “thin people.”

In time, the commune developed a siege mentality, fearful of the

gathering their forces outside them. To live with one’s weapons by

one’s side with an ear open to the requests of a buyer and another

to the peals of an alarm bell is not conducive to trade and is

exhausting to the spirit of a nascent bourgeois. After a few generations—and the time span varied from city to city—signorial rule

began to overtake republican virtue. The process was as insidious

then as it is today: popular assemblies began to vote increased

emergency powers to their **podesta** and captain; the same men

were repeatedly confirmed in executive office, and their tenure

was extended from one year to five, from five to ten, and ultimately to lifetime office. Soon the leader’s son supplanted his father after death and dynasties began to turn elective offices into

mere charades. However much they lingered on ceremoniously in

form, the republics began to die in fact, and the Italian cities,

unevenly and with trepidation, entered the age of the **signori**.

That the republican era never ceased to haunt the Italian mind is

attested to by sporadic attempts to revive it. The most notable, to

be sure, were Cola di Rienzi’s assumption of power as the tribune

of a new Roman republic in the mid-fourteenth century and Fra

Savonarola’s theocratic republic in Florence toward the end of the

fifteenth. Rienzi, however, had his eyes focused more on a unified

Italy than an emancipated Rome, a project that was woefully advanced for its time, and Savonarola turned Florence into a hysterical battleground for an apocalyptic battle between Christ and

Satan. If Rienzi was too early for the fourteenth century,

Savonarola was too late for the fifteenth. Both men challenged

entrenched attitudes that stood as insuperable obstacles to their

projects: Rienzi, a predominantly feudal sensibility; Savonarola, a

vivacious Renaissance sensibility that increasingly made his monkish mentality an anachronism. And both men went down in tragic

defeat: Rienzi as a hero of Italian nationalism, Savonarola as a

fanatic of Italian medievalism.

----

There can be no doubt that all of Europe watched the career of the

Italian city-state with keen interest and borrowed heavily from its

pioneering civicism. If Europe had any capital during the High

Middle Ages, it was papal Rome, also an Italian city-state. Pilgrims

and invaders, kings and beggars, knights and merchant-adventurers, all crisscrossed the peninsula for reasons of their own, and

Italian merchants were to be seen everywhere: at fairs in France,

city gates in Germany, on London’s docks, and in Flemish city

squares. Hence, if civic freedom needed a stimulus it could not

generate on its own, the Italian city-state was a ubiquitous presence that could provide one. In any case, and in almost every way,

the cities of western Europe went through all the phases that the

Italian cities had pioneered and added certain adornments of their

own.

Generally, European towns north of the Alps lagged behind the

Italians by a half-century or so, and at some point in time they

branched off from this shared development into institutional stagnation. Various kinds of republican structures can be found at one

time or another in almost every town of Europe, often preceded

by consulates and followed by oligarchies with a wide variety of

names. Elective systems of governance, which Roman traditions

inspired in Italy, were reinforced north of the Alps by German

tribal traditions. Not until well into the High Middle Ages did

hereditary kingships come into fashion; until then, monarchs were

elected to the throne and by no means did they occupy it with

complete regal confidence. Moreover, they were surrounded by

councils that spawned the parliamentary structures of later times,

essentially oligarchic in character but in some measure reflective

of the aristocratic, clerical, and commoner estates that made up

the sovereign’s realm. As in Italy, the word “people” was defined

in a highly restricted manner. “Note that there is a difference

between the people (**populus**) and **plebs** which is the same as that

between an animal and a man or between a genus and a species,”

declared a thirteenth-century canonist in the Aristotelian language of the day. “For nobles and non-nobles collected together

constitute the **populus**, The **plebs** is where there are no senators

or men of consular dignity.”{44} The inferences we can draw from

these remarks are that the “people” include everyone of all orders

and degree; the **plebs** consist of that segment of the “people” who

are not equipped to govern. The governing councils of European

towns generally reflected this distinction: an urban patriciate

monopolized most of the civic offices. Rich merchants took over

Bruges in the mid-thirteenth century; Rouen in the late twelfth;

Freiburg, which established a lifetime consulate, in 1218; and

many large cities of Germany such as Cologne. The conciliar system and the early assemblies were reworked into oligarchies.

Needless to say, there were also exceptions. At Nimes, the constitution provided for the election of five consuls from the “whole

people of the city or its larger part,” typically indirectly, such as

existed in the Italian city-states. Arles locked its carefully controlled general assemblies into an oligarchy by placing virtually all changes of law and imposition of taxes in the hands of its consuls

and their council.

“Democratization” of the European cities occurred slowly and

generally followed on the heels of the popular communes in Italy,

often in exacting detail. Basel established a captain of the people

in 1280; Freiburg turned its oligarchy into an annually elected

board of twenty-four consuls following a “popular” revolt very

similar to Bologna’s; Liege created what can best be called a gild-type city republic, headed by sixty governors of its craft gilds and

two burgomasters. The city went even further than most when,

from 1313 onward, it made the issuance of new laws contingent

upon the approval of a popular assembly composed of all the city’s

citizens, irrespective of their status. Even broader extensions of

civic liberties were to mark the stormy popular movement of

Flanders when civic government was shaped by the despised

weavers and fullers of cloth-manufacturing towns such as Ghent

and Ypres where the “fat” and “thin” people were to clash in

brutal conflicts. This chronic struggle is too complex to narrate

here; it involved not only battles between well-to-do oligarchies

and virtual proletarians who manufactured wool products as mere

hired help but also the intervention of the Count of Flanders, Guy

de Dampierre, and the French monarch, Philip the Fair. Patriotism intermingled with class conflicts to a point where democratic

demands were repeatedly diluted by the hatred of the Flemish

people toward France. As a result, lowly artisans and their lordly

masters fought side-by-side when they were not fighting face-to-face. Ultimately, the “thin” people, organized into “lesser gilds”

triumphed over their patriciates, and established a civic structure

that gave adequate representation to the weavers, fullers, and

gildsmen of “low degree” in a tripartate magistracy that excluded

all or most of the patricians.

What the European communes could not resist was the steady

rise of the nation-state, indeed one that the rich merchants favored to restrain their unruly local barons who interfered with the

free movement of trade and their unruly laboring classes who

posed a continual threat to civic oligarchies. Perhaps the earliest

harbinger of this new drift toward territorial centralism occurred

when the Flemish communes, led by Philip van Artavelde, the son

of the great champion of Flemish liberty, Jacques van Artavelde,

were thoroughly routed by Count Louis in the Battle of Roosebeeke in 1382. “Henceforth, Flanders was to give up the dream

of government by a league of independent towns and submit to

the ever more and more centralized rule of powerful territorial

lords, whose model was naturally the aggressive monarchy of

France,” concludes Ephraim Emerton in his wistful account of this

tragic history. “At the death of Count Louis in 1383 the county

passed by inheritance to his son-in-law, Philip the Bold of Burgundy, the first in the fine of princes through whom the Low

Countries were drawn into the politics of France, the Empire, and

Spain. The cities, still great and powerful, enjoying very wide

privileges, were to be only incidents in the larger relations of the

country.”{45}

----

Emerton’s closing remarks on the struggle of Flemish towns for

civic freedom and autonomy might well seem like a touching

epitaph for the commune as the nation-state began to emerge. Not

only did it survive as little more than a haunting dream in Flanders, but also in Italy, where the triumph of the **signori** by the

fifteenth century was virtually completed. Savonarola’s brief restoration of a Florentine republic in the closing years of that century reads more like a parody of the city’s glorious republican: past

than an authentic revival. It would seem that Daniel Waley’s verdict on the nature of Italian civic republicanism could be applied

to European communes as a whole. “The existence of republican

forms of government in the Italian city-states was intensely precarious,” Waley writes in an assessment that can only be regarded

as an understatement. “These institutions were so constantly

under pressure or even in full crisis that there is little reason to be

puzzled at their failure to survive in most of the cities.”{46} Internal

factionalism, which often reached insurrectionary proportions,

“suffices on its own to explain why, in most cities, the regime of

a single individual was able to secure acceptance before the end

of the fourteenth century. Clearly the occasional survival of

republicanism as an exception needs more explaining than do the

triumphs of the **signori**. Republicanism in decline is seen as a

puzzling historical problem only if the republic is regarded as the

body politic in health, the ‘tyranny’ (**signoria**) as a pathological

form.”{47}

Perhaps, as Waley seems to suggest, we should reverse the

judgement modern liberal historians have of what constitutes the

health arid pathology of a body politic. But it is fair to ask, as I have

throughout this book, whether any kind of politics, much less one

that can be “embodied” in an active citizenry, is possible under

a tyranny or, for that matter, a “representative democracy” (republic). Waley seems to surrender the need for an ethical judgement of the commune, of the *conjuratio*’s radical implications and

its sense of promise, if he asks us to surrender to the “facts” of the

historical record rather than cherish the possibilities civic freedom

holds for a humanity that has yet to fulfill its unfinished potentialities for a rational way of life. We can never let this commitment

to an ethical judgement give way to the evidence of a grossly

irrational reality merely because the record of the human enterprise speaks faultingly against it. Truth rarely lies in the center of

experienced facts. If it did so, we would still believe the earth is

flat and justice is merely the authority of the strong. These are the

irrefragable facts as they are experienced in everyday life. Historians, in turn, would merely be turgid chroniclers of anecdotes,

storytellers of things past whose accounts can never be free of

their own hidden biases and proclivities. Until very recent times,

philosophy for more than two millennia has warned us that “brute

facts” do not really exist and are never free of interpretation, even

as we deny humanity any sense of possibility, the hope of going

beyond the “facts” and achieving its most worthy ideals. “Brute

facts” will become real only when we become brutish and deal

with the existing reality on its own terms, no different in principle

from the adaptive ways we impute to other living beings.

Actually, the history of civic freedom does not end with the

fourteenth century or the rise of the nation-state. The ideal of

popular assemblies as a form of self-governance, and the city as the

nuclear arena for politics and an active citizenry, seems to have

enjoyed a remarkable degree of persistence, especially if we bear

in mind that there were so many factors—statist, economic, logistical, and demographic—to work against. That it exists even today

in the form of the New England town meeting, however vestigial

it appears by comparison with its past, is testimony to the need

people have felt in fairly politicized regions to retain forms of

face-to-face decision making and direct democracy. In fact, the

town meeting is much too close to our discussion of the city’s

future to be examined in any detail here. It may be regarded as

a legacy, but it is still a living legacy that should not be consigned

to the past. Suffice it to say, for the present, that from 1760 to the

closing years of the American Revolution, it spread out of New

England and reached as far south as Charleston. During this period, it fueled the revolution as surely as the more well-known

Committees of Correspondence and such popular societies as the

Sons of Liberty. Considerable effort was needed to eliminate the

town-meeting form in many communities of the new United

States and to nibble away at its powers in New England itself. We

shall see that as recently as the 1960s, Vermont townships and

their popular meetings essentially controlled the state government because the House of Representatives was elected by towns, not along geographic and demographic lines.

Nor can we deal with the challenging problems raised by the

Swiss Confederation, a piece of contemporary history that seems

to have been shunted away from “mainstream” accounts of civic

freedom. To assign a few paragraphs to a living illustration of

confederalism, participatory democracy, and active citizenship,

despite the philistine smugness of Swiss life and the conservatism

of Swiss politics, would be doing violence to the extraordinary

example of freedom that is also with us. It will require a section

of a later chapter on civic confederal forms to even remotely

approximate the insights Benjamin Barber brings to this issue in

his discussion of direct democracy in the Swiss cantons. What

Barber asks us to recognize is that democratic forms in themselves, however radical they may seem to be, “are inherently

neither conservative nor progressive; they can be employed to

bring about rapid and even radical change under conditions of

consensus and unity of governing and people. They can obstruct

reform and paralyze effective government altogether where the

people are no longer one with their governors or synonymous with

their government.... Democracy in Switzerland appears reactionary because the conditions that justify it have eroded; democracy in the villages of GraubĂŒnden is failing because the village

communities are themselves moribund. Neither the institutions

themselves nor a putative peasant mentality is to blame.”{48} Democracy, in sum, has its own prerequisites, and it will be no small

part of the coming chapters to examine them in the light of modern societal problems—American, European, GraubĂŒnden, no less

than those that exist for a New England town-meeting democracy.

The most dazzling, almost meteoric example of civic liberty and

direct democracy in modern times is the rise and brief ascendancy

of the sectional assemblies in the Great French Revolution, a

movement that addresses the typical question of whether or not

a face-to-face democracy is possible in a large city, indeed by the

standards of two centuries ago a world city. It should be kept in

mind that eighteenth-century Paris, where the sectional assemblies flourished, was the capital of continental Europe’s most absolute monarchies, a city that, more so than any other aside from

London, seemed to have been a creature of the nation-state.

Under the Bourbons, Paris had very little self-government of its

own. Ruled more or less directly by the monarchy, it groaned

under the imposition of an inept regal administration and a corrupt nobility that reduced its lower orders to sheer destitution. Yet

within a span of only four years, Paris acquired not only complete

control over its own civic afFairs but created a system of control

that was built around face-to-face neighborhood assemblies, coordinated by a commune that, at its revolutionary highpoint, called

for the complete restructuring of France into a confederation of

free communes. This demand was to survive for nearly a century

after the revolution, when it became the insurrectionary program

of the more famous Paris Commune of 1791.

Ironically, the sectional assemblies have their origin in the sixty

district assemblies Louis XVI convened in Paris to elect the city’s

middle-class deputies to the Estates General. These assemblies

were directed to select the 147 electors who, in turn, were to

choose Paris’s twenty deputies to the Third Estate. The French

Revolution, although spurred into action by the power plays between the Third Estate and the monarchy, really began from

below and, most typically, as a result of Parisian militancy. Despite

the highly discriminatory franchise that the Xing imposed on his

own capital—nearly a quarter of the city’s population was disenfranchised in contrast to a sixth in the rest of France—the district

assemblies were highly spirited and acted in flat defiance of the

throne. They rejected the presiding officers with whom they were

saddled by the municipality and chose presiding officers of their

own; the 147 electors to whom they were entitled were unabashedly raised to four hundred; and what is perhaps most damning, they refused to go home as the monarchy directed them to do.

They defiantly established themselves as permanent fixtures of

Paris’s municipal government. The four hundred electors, in turn,

began to meet almost daily at the museum and shortly afterward

at the Town Hall, where they simply edged out the royal appointees to the municipal government. The electors, in effect, became

a provisional Paris, “Commune”’ until an authentic Commune was

constitutionally elected. By September 1790, the Paris Commune

numbered three hundred and coexisted uneasily with the sixty

district assemblies from which it drew its representatives.

The tension between the Commune and its district assemblies

and within the assemblies themselves mounted as the revolutionary fever of the’ city rose. The distinction between propertied

“active citizens” who had franchise rights and propertyless “passive” ones who were expected tp be little more than political

bystanders ultimately made any exclusion of the disenfranchised

people, the *sans culottes*, increasingly awkward. By this time, the

“districts” had been renamed “sections” and their number reduced from sixty to forty-eight by the National Assembly in order

to diminish their power. Despite such attempts to suppress the

“districts” and later the “sections” as deliberative bodies, the assemblies largely ignored the National Assembly’s decrees. In May

1790, the Assembly tried to limit the concerns of the sectional

assemblies to purely municipal issues, a ploy typipal to this day of

conservative elements in New England town meetings, but the

restriction ultimately proved to be ineffectual. With the outbreak

of war, the revolution moved markedly leftward. In July 1792, the

Theatre-Français sectipn decreed the elimination of all distinctions between “active” anil “passive” citizens, a decree that was

quickly adopted by all the forty-eight sections of Paris. The sectional assemblies were now thrown open to all the underprivileged orders of Paris: the laboring classes, relatively unskilled

artisans, carpenters, construction workers, nascent proletarians of

the textile and luxury goods workshops, and the like. A year later,

on Danton’s request, the newly elected revolutionary Convention

that replaced the National Assembly dbcreed that poor citizens

could receive a stipend of forty sous for, attending sectional assemblies, which were reduced to two a week, presumably so that the

attempt by the liberal Girondins to close all sectional assemblies

by nine in the evening so that working *sans culottes* would be

unable to attend the assemblies after they returned home contributed greatly to the popular insurrection that removed them

from the Convention and brought the Jacobins to power.

Although the details of how these local assemblies functioned

leaves much to be desired, partly because the minutes of the

sections were lost in the flames of the Paris Commune of 1871,

partly, too, because their history has yet to be written by historians

sympathetic to their decentralistic outlook, we know enough to

describe them in broad terms. Sectional assemblies met at least

twice weekly in the summer and autumn of 1793, the high tide of

the **sans culotte** movement and often went into “permanent session” during hectic periods of the revolution. Attendance fluctuated widely from a hundred or less when the agenda was routine

to overflowing halls (usually in state-commandeered churches and

chapels) when serious issues confronted the revolutionary people.

Structurally, each section had a president with a committee to

assist him, a recording secretary, tellers for counting votes, and

ushers to maintain order. Although it is not very clear how fixed

these positions were, the President’s committee was renewed

monthly by an assembly vote, and very few presidents seem to

have held office for more than a year. Each section, it must be

stressed, made its own rules and probably varied in form and the

frequency of its meetings.

A multitude of revolutionary commissars and committees surfaced from these assemblies and dealt with a large number of

important economic, political, and military problems. We have

only to enumerate the names of the sectional committees to gain

some idea of the functions this neighborhood democracy undertook. Aside from its *assemblee generale* of the local citizen body,

each section’s “most important function, that of police, was entrusted to a **commissaire de police**, aided by sixteen **commissaires de section**. To meet the needs of local administration the sections

formed almost as many committees as a modern American town

or city. There were **comites civile** and **comites revolutionaires**

(Vigilance Committees); there were **comites de bienfaisance** (Relief Committees), *comites militaires*, *comites d’agriculture*, and

had its own revolutionary court system and justices of the peace

as well as special committees to organize work for the unemployed (*ateliers de charite*), or tenth-day festivities (*fetes decadaires*), or open-air suppers for the poor (*banquets populaires*).[8]

[8] France, it is worth noting, had extended its newly adopted decadenal metric

system from weights, measures, lengths, and areas directly into the calendar with

the result that a week was measured in ten days. This did not displease the French

bourgeoisie, which was only too glad to have a longer work week than existed

under the older religious calendar.

The forty-eight sectional assemblies, in turn, were coordinated

by the Paris Commune to which each section elected three deputies at an *assemblee primaire*. Also at this special assembly, usually

quite heavily attended, the sections elected the *Bureau* of the

Commune: the city’s mayor, its *procureur*, and his two deputies,

who essentially constituted a communal executive committee to

which sixteen *administrateurs* were chosen from the Commune’s

normal complement of 144 sectional representatives. To buffer

this rather manipulative executive from popular pressure, an additional thirty-two members were added to the *Bureau* to form a

<em>Corps Municipal.</em> When this majestic group of forty-eight sectional notables convened with the remaining ninety-two deputies

that formed the Commune, it bore the solemn title of the *Conseil General de la Commune* or, as it came to be known in the historical literature, the Commune’s General Council.

The more radical sections of Paris were not unmindful that

these concentric rings of authority surrounding the commune’s

Bureau were meant to camouflage an inner circle of executives

who were as disquieted by the irascibility of the sections as the

Convention was of the Commune, a body that it really saw as a

dangerous challenge to the nation-state. Although the Commune

eventually became more radical under sectional pressure as time

went by, the sections were always more radical than the Commune and began to act very much on their own. When necessary,

as was frequently the case, **sans culotte** sections did not hesitate

to bypass the Commune completely and form their own interlocking committees and networks. Delegations from one section often

visited the assemblies of another, where they were usually greeted

with fervent embraces, hortatory speeches of welcome, and characteristic “kisses of fraternity,” which often culminated with banquets topped by endless toasts to liberty and the brotherhood of

man. As F. Furet *et al*. tell us: “From the angle of political solidarity, the participants in activities of the sections saw themselves as

forming a whole, a ‘family’ of ‘brothers and friends,’ where the use

of the familiar form *tu* broke down all the barriers of social and

cultural origin. Outside the section this fraternal solidarity was

further expressed by ‘fraternization,’ a sort of pact for mutual aid

between the popular sections to resist the pressure of the aristocrats and the moderates, and then to eliminate them from the

committees which they controlled. Thus on May 14, 1793, the

Social Contract section, under the direction of its president, went

in a body to the Lombard section to chase out the ‘aristocracy.’ In

this way the sections were regenerated in the bourgeois quarters

dominated by the moderates before the fall of the Girondins, and

by the ‘new moderates’ after the month of September 1793.”{49}

It is difficult to fully convey the enormous powers the sections

accrued by 1793 before they were subverted by the Convention.

The titles of their various *comites* and *commissions* do not’ tell us

how intensely active the sections had become in the administration of their neighborhoods and finally in running the entire city

of Paris. They were sources of information on local counterrevolutionaries and grain speculators, both of whom existed by the nestful in the city. They became the dispensers of a rough-and-ready

popular justice, the guardians of the “maximum” that regulated

the price of staples, the dispensers of food for the poor and sustenance for the widowed and orphaned, the caretakers of refugees

from the provinces and the homeless who all but lived on the

streets. They were the authentic organizers of the great *journées*,

the insurrectionary “days” that pushed the revolution in an increasingly egalitarian direction much to the dismay of the Jacobins, whom they mistakenly worshipped with almost unthinking

reverence before they were betrayed by the Robespierres, Dantons, and Saint-Justs. They forged the “holy pike” that armed the

revolutionary populace and made it possible for it to intervene

directly in the Convention’s proceedings and alter the course of

its decrees and laws. Going even further, the sections began to

intervene significantly in the economy of the city. Their *comites d’agriculture* scoured the countryside to feed the city, their committees to establish *ateliers de charite* freely appropriated workshops abandoned by wealthy emigres and used them to provide

jobs for the unemployed who made uniforms, weapons, and gunpowder fpr the embattled revolutionary armies at the front. Not

unlike the Athenian festivals of an earlier age that did so much to

cement the *polis* together, the sections not only called periodic

fetes decadaires and neighborhood *banquets populaires* but

helped to stage the fervent citywide celebrations that occurred

throughout the revolution, fostering a sense of civic fraternity that

Paris was to rarely see again after 1793, when the “year of the *sans culottes*” passed into history. And it was these *canaille*, or “rabble” as they were also called, who were to be pushed from tho

stage of history and shot down by the thousands in the reaction

that followed the tenth of Thermidor (July 28,1794), when Robespierre and his followers were guillotined.

Finally, “From the principle of popular sovereignty,” observe

Furet and his colleagues, “the *sans culottes* went as far as the

notion of direct government. With the same verve which made

them rise against the Girondins, in the summer of 1793 certain

sections demanded to keep their own civil records, to levy their

own taxes, and to render justice without appeal. No limitations

should be imposed upon the assembly of citizens, which decided

everything. A decision by the Convention (September 9, 1793)

having limited section meetings to two days a week, the **sans culottes** got around the decree by holding a daily meeting of the

‘Society of the section.’ This assembly claimed to supervise the

civil servants and magistrates, who in their eyes were merely their

subordinates. Members of the *comites civiles*, revolutionary commissions, police commissioners, or commissioners for supplies

were subjected to constant surveillance by the sections, at least as

long as the latter maintained their independence from the revolutionary government. Censure, ‘purifying’ votes, and revocability

of elected persons were the principal means by which this popular

sovereignty was exercised, according to the Rousseauean principle of a sovereign and indivisible popular opinion.”{50}

The well-to-do classes of France had everything to fear from

these sectional assemblies and a radical Commune of Paris. Although it was highly unlikely that the largely bourgeois districts

of 1789 ever envisioned a France governed by a completely popular direct democracy, the rise and growing influence of the sectional assemblies clearly evoked images of a confederal France

structured around sections similar to the Parisian in all the cities

and towns of the country—a nationwide commune of communes.

The extent to which this vision of an entire European country

began to take hold of the popular imagination as early as November, 1792, is suggested by a statement that the **Section de la Cité**

circulated for the approval of other sectional assemblies. “The

citizens of Paris declare ... that they recognize no sovereignty

except a majority of the communes of the republic ..the statement provocatively declares, “that they only recognize deputies

In the Convention as composers of a draft constitution and provisional administration of the republic.” By the spring of 1793, such

views ceased to be isolated. On April 29 of the following year, the

the concentric groups within that body, took practical steps toward implementing the idea of a federation of communes by establishing a corresponding committee to communicate with the

44,000 municipalities of France. In a printed circular to the

municipalities, the committee’s secretary boldly declared: “That

is the only kind of federalism the people of Paris want.... All the

communes in France should be sisters.”{51}

For all his biases and preconceptions, Daniel Guerin is on solid

ground when he resolutely concludes, “The bourgeois philosophers who had pronounced direct democracy unworkable in large

countries [no less Rousseau than other social theorists of his day],

on the grounds that it would be materially impossible to bring all

the citizens together in one meeting, were thus proved wrong.

The Commune had spontaneously discovered a new form of representation more direct and more flexible than the parliamentary

system and which while not perfect, for all forms of representation

have their faults, reduced the disadvantages to a minimum.” Indeed, it is doubtful if the Commune and the sectional assemblies

could be regarded as a system of “representation.” The *sans culottes* had gone much further than any assembly form of which we

know in establishing a direct democracy, this in the very heart of

a nation-state that the Jacobins had centralized to a degree that

would have been the envy of France’s most absolutist monarchs.

Chapter Six: From Politics to Statecraft

It remains one of history’s great ironies that the city, which reworked stagnant archaic systems of corporate life based on status

and kinship into the innovative, free realm of politics and citizenship, was to produce the very factors that led to its own undoing.

European cities, I have pointed out, were different from their

ancient counterparts because of their inherent autonomy as civic

entities. The increasing separation of the medieval town from the

city’s traditional agrarian matrix produced not only a new kind of

city with an identity of its own; it also produced a new type of

economy, culture, and political structure that profoundly altered

the countryside and slowly remade it into the city’s image. Today,

we have no difficulty in recognizing this profound change—the

“urbanization” of the land—as a logical step in a mythic ascent of

societal life from what Marx lamely called “rural idiocy” to what

we like to call “civilization.” Modern agribusiness is the patent

“conquest” of agriculture by industry, a city-born enterprise and

technics; so, too, is mass culture, which has urbanized as well as

homogenized agrarian lifeways. What we do not fully sense is the

extent to which early city dwellers would have regarded such a

sweeping urbanization of the countryside as peculiar, nor could

they have anticipated the extent to which it would have undermined civic life and citizenship. We have simply lost contact with

the problem of urbanization as antithetical to citification—and to

the extent that we are oblivious to the very existence of the issue

itself, we have become its mute and unknowing victims.

How, then, did this remarkable change from civic autonomy to

civic supremacy come about? And in what sense, institutionally

and economically, did it begin to challenge the city s integrity,

ultimately to raise the very real problem of its subversion as a

realm of genuine politics and meaningful citizenship? Gur answers to these questions, so crucial to an understanding of modern

urbanization arid the threat it poses to the city, oblige us to examine the new kind of economy and values that became preponderant in the communes of the late Middle Ages and the role they

played in replacing civic life with the nation-state or, more precisely, politics with statecraft.

We must first look at the new economic relationships that began

to link European cities and regions together—and I say “first” not

because they are the sole, the “definitive,” cause that produced

this new economic and political dispensation. Whether the European continent “necessarily” would have been changed from a

loose association of towns, cities, baronies, duchies, and the allpresiding, if ineffectual, Holy Roman Empire into a clearly articulated group of nation-states is a problem in divination, not in

social analysis. How Europe could have developed—whether toward confederal communities or toward highly centralized nation-states—is an open question. One can single out many reasonable alternatives European towns and cities might have followed

that were, no less possible than the one that became prevalent in

fairly recent times. No single course of development was “inevitable” or “predetermined” by the economic, social, and political

forces at work. Indeed, that Italy did not become a nation-state

until the nineteenth century must remain an utter mystery if a

constellation of cultural, social, and political factors, particularly

the role of its cities, is not invoked against strictly economic explanations. Seemingly, no area of Europe was more “modern,” “capitalistic,” or entangled in a market economy some 500 years ago

than the Italian peninsula, and yet Italy was to lag behind western

Europe’s trend toward nation-state building for centuries. Nor can

we understand why it was only in England that a market economy

virtually absorbed all other economic forms of life such that the

British Isles became the “model” for a capitalistic society in the

nineteenth century while Spain, which entered so early on in the

development of nation-states, lagged behind Europe as a whole

and remained a predominantly agrarian society until well into the

1930s.

This much is clear: from the thirteenth or fourteenth centuries

onward, Europe—and, most notably, Italy—was the scene for an

entirely new economic and social dispensation. The Italian city-states began to break with-traditional economic relationships that

had been ingrained in ancient and early medieval civic life ways.

From Italian ports and inland commercial cities—and in northern

Europe from Flemish industrial centers—foreign trade began to

bring a growing number of parochial communes into a new kind

of commercial network, one that resembled what we would now

regard as capitalistic. Trade, accumulation, and the reinvestment

of profits into expanding and competitive business enterprises

now became ends in themselves, not simply means to achieve

personal wealth, land holdings, and aristocratic status. Not that

this development was totally universal, as we shall see very

shortly. But it occurred on a sufficiently wide scale to make it

unique and to subvert the traditional agrarian lifeways that

marked European society, merchant as well as noble, in past historical eras.

Yet new as this development was, I do not wish to overstate it.

Our own society, a society that celebrates the ascendancy of “free

trade” and a competitive capitalist economy, is ideologically imperialistic: it tends to cast the past too much in its own image. All

the roads of European history do not lead to the triumph of the

twentieth-century market economy. The fact is that feudal values,

rooted in an elaborate system of rank and a strong orientation

toward the ownership of land, were no less a part of received

wisdom of the new, rising urban “bourgeoisie” than of the old

agrarian nobility. Trade did not alter this received wisdom of

feudal society for centuries to come. Indeed, like the merchants

of antiquity, whose goal consisted of amassing enough wealth from

the “sordid” operations of commerce in order to retire to a

manorial life in the countryside, many Italian and Flemish merchants had very similar ambitions. Prestige gained by titles

through intermarriage and by the ownership of landed property

was still a desideratum among these early “bourgeois”—and such

goals were to remain widespread in Europe well into the eighteenth century. On this score, the merchants of antiquity and their

descendants in the Middle Ages were very much alike in outlook,

particularly the most wealthy ones. In their psychology and sense

of cultural self-definition, the city rich were similar to all the upper

rural strata of the time. And we shall also see that these ambitions

and this mentality exercised less of a hold among the more middling sort of city dwellers, such as artisans, ordinary merchants,

and aspiring members of the plebeian orders. Differences in attitudes and wealth were to profoundly divide the medieval towns

and cities internally, greatly complicating their relationships with the emerging monarchies.

For the present, it is important to emphasize that the wealthy

merchants of the late Middle Ages differed from their ancient

counterparts in the **way** in which they were committed to commercial operations. Although their outlook closely resembled a

feudal one, their practice was very akin to a modern one. The

tension between the old and new, between precept and practice,

introduced ways of functioning that deeply altered European life.

Ancient trade, generally speaking, was surprisingly simple in comparison to later medieval business transactions despite its Mediterranean-wide scope. Ordinarily it was local and more like barter

than modern forms of exchange; the ancient economy was not as

highly monetized as it is today. Money was conspicuous more by

its absence than by its presence, and the extent to which ancient

trade was a regulated affair would have chilled modern acolytes

of **laissez-faire** doctrines.

Like the cities, which were usually religious and administrative

centers, often as parasitic in their need for tribute from the surrounding countryside as in the exactations they placed on distant

subject peoples, Mediterranean commerce found itself physically

and culturally hemmed in by a distinctly agrarian world and a

largely subsistence economy. Beyond the ancient cities that clustered along the shores of the Mediterranean or were planted

strategically at intersections of inland waterways, the early trader

faced a semifeudal world of crude manors and impoverished peasant villages, a world that dissolved into a forested, semitribal communal world. Both of these worlds, the manorial and the tribal, in

antiquity constituted a very precarious, indeed hazardous, terrain

for the merchant, for his caravans on the land and his ships in

remote waterways.

The ancient merchant responded to these barriers accordingly.

Trade was distinguished by its highly personalized and somewhat

tentative character. The merchant and his sea captain or caravan

leader were united by a specific enterprise rather than a highly

organized business, although there were always many notable exceptions to this rule. Ships often went to sea and caravans with

pack animals went inland to make a “killing” just as a wayfaring

stock-market speculator today seeks his “lucky break.” In this

sense, merchants were literally “merchant-adventurers,” and

their “companies” had quasimilitary characteristics. They commonly went abroad as armed expeditions. Loans were often no less

personal than the expeditionary techniques that brought a fleet of

ships or a caravan of pack animals together. Although credit was

fairly well developed by Roman times when the empire was already quite secure, in foreign trade to fairly remote parts, at least,

credit was often seen more as a gamble than a safe investment.

Such profits were high, and went into hoards or were invested in

land rather than the expansion of on-going businesses. I speak here

of foreign trade, not local trade; of the ancient world’s “merchant-adventurers,” not its home-based business enterprises, artisans,

and commercial farmers.

----

What the Italian merchants introduced in the Middle Ages was as

close to a “revolution” as anything that goes by that name. A broad

network of business houses, credit institutions, trading depots,

warehouses, and affiliates began to interlink Italian city-states with

numerous medieval European towns, and the movement of goods

was gradually secured by treaties, tribute, and hired mercenaries

from the predations of robber barons and bandits. The Venetian

navy virtually swept the city’s Mediterranean trade routes of pirates, attaining a sea supremacy that rivalled the naval power of

the more formidable empires around the basin. Business became

systematic, safe, a predictable enterprise. Money was invested not

only in the expansion and acquisition of landed property; it was

also invested in larger commercial operations whose profits not

only attracted ordinary people but also the local, nobility. The lure

of this fairly safe source of wealth, still disdained culturally but

crassly attractive to an increasingly practical and secularized

world, was enormous. It opened new doors everywhere in late

medieval society. Indeed, the social mobility of the fourteenth and

fifteenth centuries sharply contrasts with the social stagnation of

the classical world. Well-to-do commoners were closely interlinked with nobles by marriage as well as by trade. Aristocrats

offered titles and pedigree in exchange for the wealth and material security offered by merchants. Alliances were forged not only

with families of the same social order but between families of

different social orders. This melding of “classes,” largely feudal

and “bourgeois,” has only recently received the attention it deserves and was to have a profound effect on the so-called “bourgeois revolutions” that marked the eighteenth century.

Finally, where elite orders were not interlinked by marriage,

merchants and even professionals acquired aristocratic status by

buying it outright, especially from the fifteenth century onward.

A considerable portion of the revenue acquired by the French

Bourbon kings, for example, came from the sale of titles, a sale that

united the higher orders of society by a shared sense of titular

nobility—even as it divided them by a sense of shared disdain

between the purchased “nobility of the robe" and the hereditary

“nobility of the sword.” In time, alliances and differences were to

become as tentative and precarious as distinctions formed by

wealth, when the rich of one day could easily suffer the pangs of

penury after the misfortunes of another day.

What did last and expand, however, were the trade networks

established between communities, particularly the larger towns of

medieval Europe. But the enormous growth, continuity, and increased stability of this foreign trade—the nearest thing to a capitalistic enterprise the continent developed—should not cause us

to overlook the rich elaboration of the local market that occurred

within the medieval communes and their immediate environs.

The decline of the Roman Empire and the eclipse of the administrative cities that held it together brought the European continent

face-to-face with itself and threw it back on its own mainsprings.

No longer could the continent be sustained’and civilized, much

less managed and exploited, by the Mediterranean basin with its

rich granaries and sources of tribbte. Beyond the highly cultivated

Roman-controlled territories of Europe lay great forests and bogs,

a huge continent within the continent itself that was fairly pristine

and open to new forms of social development. Communes began

to appear in this virginal terrain that were now structured not only

around religious and governmental institutions but, significantly,

around the markets qf craftsmen and artisans. These artisan towns,

to be sure, were crude and unpolished; they were more villagelike

than urban. The work and the markets that emerged from this

highly decentralized, localistic society were still mainly organized

around religious and feudal values. Often collecting around

churches and cathedrals—indeed, commonly under the sovereignty of a bishop—they nevertheless became productive towns

with small markets arid family-operated workshops, living off the

agricultural produce in their environs and providing rural folk

with the more skillfully crafted commodities they could not make

in the countryside.

Here we encounter something remarkably new: communes

marked by a rich social fife, and with it a popular politics rooted

in gilds, systems of mutual aid, a civic riiilitia, and a strong sense

of community loyalty. The gild, the most important institutional

center of a new kind of artisan society, should not be confused with

the ancient collegia that it resembled structurally or with such

strictly economic associations as modern trade unions, which it

seems to resemble functionally. The Roman Empire exhibited a

very low tolerance for nonstatist bodies that could challenge the

authority of the monarchy and its bureaucracy. Hence ancient

collegial associations of craftspeople were rarely permitted to extend their activities beyond those of burial societies and festive

fraternities. They were allowed to have no economically regulative or protective functions. Essentially, they were cultural and

quasireligious institutions. Modern labor unions, in turn, are primarily economic organizations and’ assume few cultural, much less religious; undertakings.

The medieval gild, by contrast, assumed the responsibilities of

the ancient collegium, the modern labor union, and a great deal

more. Possibly religious in origin, it became highly secular in many

of its activities, fostering material as well as moral commitments.

It was a sworn, covenanted brotherhood that punished its members for lowering the quality of goods or seeking higher than

prescribed prices. It regulated personal, moral, and religious behavior as well as the output of goods. Not only did it care for

widows and orphans, the ill and infirm of its own members, but it

gave alms to the poor, performed charitable works of all kinds,

celebrated feast days, punished its members for usury, blasphemy,

gambling, and other presumably “immoral” infractions of good

behavior.

What made medieval gilds particularly significant in ways that

mark a sharp departure from towns of the past is that they attained

a degree of legislative and governing authority that made them

the principal municipal institution of many communes. However

parochial they seem to us today, European towns by the thousands

achieved a degree of autonomy that few municipal entities had

acquired in times past or were to acquire later. This autonomy was

pieced together corporately from a localized world of small artisans, craftsmen, and merchants—a feudal world, in fact, not a

capitalistic one, however much it was centered around the marketplace—before European communes were to be networked together by foreign trade. The commune’s growth and elaboration

took place organically, not artificially, within a highly decentralized agrarian society. In contrast to the Roman-controlled town,

the European town was a unique phenomenon insofar as local

autonomy became the rule rather than the exception. Control

from below thrived at the expense of an institutionally weak feudal society that was beleaguered by overlapping and conflicting

jurisdictions between landed nobles, urban bishoprics, papal legates, and insecure monarchs. The unending series of conflicts

that these jurisdictions generated was exacerbated by an undeveloped system of communications and by a crude armamentorium, one that made civic militias a powerful military force in

social life.

Foreign trade—more precisely the capitalistic carrying trade

that emanated from the Italian city-states and the Flemish communes—definitely worked against this communal autonomy as

surely as it played a role in interlocking Europe’s towns and cities.

And in so doing, it posed a historic problem: would the commercial

network created by intercity trade yield the formation of nation-states, centralized by monarchical and later republican systems of

power, or would it give rise to confederal institutions, united in a

shared continental system based on local community control?

That the nation-state was to gain ascendancy over confederal systems of self-governance does not mean that its victory was predetermined by Europe’s history—nor does it mean that its victory

cannot be undone. How that nation-state’s ascendancy was

achieved is a story worth telling because it also brings to fight an

achievement that was often very tenuous, owing to the resistance

of the towns to centralism, a struggle that has not been definitively

foreclosed by urban issues that are emerging today.

For the present, we shall confine our account of the nation-state

to the way it was achieved, with the clear reservation that other

alternatives continually existed, indeed dramatic alternatives that

we will explore later. Initially, the intercity carrying trade that

began to unite Europe economically from the twelfth century

onward not only tore into a complex web of mutual personal and

communal dependencies in which trade as well as behavior was

carefully regulated; it also became the infrastructure for a new

body of societal institutions—initially regional rather than local,

later overwhelmingly national—that cut across the grain of a time-hallowed and intensely communal and decentralized mode of social fife. It eventually introduced nationalism, a distinctly European phenomenon that was to spread beyond the continent itself

and acquire global dimensions.

The ancients, like the early Europeans, had very little experience with the notion of nationhood. Largely tribalistic or locafistic

in outlook, they tended to look inward toward their traditional

fifeways, to elaborate them rather than innovate new institutions

and values. Even the Greeks and Romans, who were comparatively “forward looking” in their attitudes, were heavily guided by

tradition. Cultural as well as economic “limits to growth” were

deeply molecular: people owed their strongest allegiances to their

kin group; next, to their community or perhaps region; rarely to

a “nation.” The idea of a “nation” was alien to the ancient mind,

a tribalistic form of mind that opposed the locality to the ecumene.

Although pan-Hellenism was very much in the air among the

Greek *polei* shortly before Alexander brought the western world

and the Near Eastern together institutionally, it quickly drifted

into a cosmopolitan Hellenistic ecumene that adopted Greek for

its *lingua franca* and Greek culture for its spiritual adornment.

Hence a Greek “nation” never developed among the Greek *polei*.

Israel seems to have acquired a strong sense of nationhood after

the Maccabean Revolt, but it was smothered by foreign invaders.

Religion ultimately placed a stronger claim on the Jews than a

sense of territorial nationhood, hence a budding form of nationalism was soon supplanted by a powerful belief in a spiritual community whose strength still defies the economistic explanations advanced by crude variants of Marx’s “historical materialism.” The

great empires of the ancient world were nOt “nations” in any sense

of the term. Indeed, it is difficult to associate them with the modern, class-based nation-state. In the Near East, these empires assumed a highly patronymic form: a “property,” as it were, of a

deified, patriarchal monarch for whom the vast lands under his

control were regarded as part of his *oikos* or household. Lands

annexed to the monarch’s original inheritance became the tributaries of a centralized household rather than the territory of an

institutionalized body politic. The Roman Empire, particularly in

its imperial rather than republican form, inherited this Near Eastern tradition-bound state form, however much it was secularized

and regulated by laws. Indeed it should be kept in mind always

that the Roman state was managed primarily by patricians, a

group of “fathers,” by definition, rather than by citizens. The

emperors, in turn, were the “fathers” of their people, not simply their sovereigns,

European nations, by contrast, were pieced together by sterner

stuff. However muph monarchical nation building, so redolent of

ancient statecraft, went hand in hand with the market’s expansion,

the infrastructure created by commerce laid a stronger foundation for nationalism than anything we encounter in the ancient

i world. This new, continentwide commercial nexus, formed out of

the interlinking of towns, produced material dependencies for

goods that cut across the moral relationships fostered by traditional society. Even before the monarchs of Spain, France, and

England asserted their authority over their respective nations,

they shrewdly exploited the divided loyalties and value systems

created by a growing commercial dependence on far-flung markets on the one hand and a powerful psychological dependence

produced by a richly elaborated localist community on the other.

Between the material wealth offered by the former and the

spiritual security offered by the latter, many towns were to divide

internally as sharply as they divided against the countryside.

Hence the European commune was pulled in two opposing directions: between the desirability of the nation-state and an ideal of

communal confederation. France ;was to provide an existential

example of the first, the Swiss Confederation, in its early days, of

the second.

Such alternatives did not really exist in the ancient world apart

from Greece. The administrative cities of antiquity easily dissolved in the West into virtual villages with the decline of the

empire, villages that formed the real community base of that society. Indeed, once sources, of tribute disappeared, the resources for

maintaining the Roman imperial state disappeared as well and the

West devolved into decentralized feudal society. Europe fell back

on its own resources and its own authentic forms of social and

economic organization.

The long history of Europe’s medieval development, a development that brings us to the opening of the modern era, totally

changed the setting for urban evolution. European-wide trade,

centered entirely around a new kind of self-sustaining municipality, opened sharply contrasting opportunities for development.

The wealthy elites of the towns were riddled by the divided loyalties and interests to which I have already alluded. Among the rich

merchants and their noble urban allies, a growing trend surfaced

for unfettered trade, free of gild, restrictions and traditional moral

constraints. On the other hand, the great majority of artisans,

journeymen, small retailers, and professionals were to demand the

perpetuation of traditional controls, their time-honored source of

security and stability. What complicates this fairly conventional

account of the “class struggle” within the medieval city is the very

disconcerting fact that the medieval patricians and plebeians

often united as readily as they fought with each other, notably

against assaults from outside the city itself. Although by no means

consistently, both “classes” commonly joined together to support

their municipal privileges against landed nobles and, more strikingly, even against monarchs who were bent on achieving a highly

centralized state. While the ordinary plebeian strata tended to be

more consistent in their commitment to their civic rights, the

more conflicted patrician stratum—feudal in outlook but decidedly bourgeois in its commercial practices—oscillated in its loyalties between the more popular elements in the city and the elite

elements, noble and kingly, to which it felt a groveling loyalty that

marks all parvenu elements in society. As we shall see, such alliances within the commune tended to be tentative and inconclusive, at times giving rise to serious urban revolts against the newly

emerging absolute monarchs, at other times dividing the towns so

seriously that they easily fell prey to monarchs who were to fashion the modern nation-state.

The reader who looks for an elegant and compact development

toward a modern urban society will not find one here. Between

the fourteenth and sixteenth centuries, when nation-states began

to form, the continent’s towns and cities found themselves deeply

entangled in a skein of shifting alliances and conflicts. Modern

notions of “free trade,” largely confined to merchants engaged in

the carrying trade of the Mediterranean basin and the continent,

were nevertheless permeated by feudal values rooted in land ownership and status to an extent that would have seemed curious to

the modern mind. “Capital,” in effect, was at war with itself and

had very little identity of its own. Newly emerging capitalists of

the high and late Middle Ages were often pulled in sublimely

contrary directions by a fading past and a barely emerging future.

For their part, the plebeian elements of the towns were deeply

committed to their ancient traditions, that is, to the corporative

values of the medieval world. No affinity to “free trade” or notions

of unregulated business practices were to be found among these

less privileged groups. Despite their quasifeudal notions, however,

they resolutely opposed territorial lords who sought to challenge

the liberties of their towns, ironically in contrast to the wealthy

merchant strata in their own communities who feared both camps

in this conflict and variously allied themselves with one against the

other. Finally, the newly emerging princes and monarchs who

were to eventually piece together the nations of Europe were

themselves deeply divided by this skein of tentative alliances and

conflicts. They were more than willing to use the European communes against nobles who challenged monarchical authority. But

they were equally willing to subdue the communes when they

raised the cry for their ancient municipal liberties and autonomy.

It is within this highly unstable yet very traditional world—unprecedented in the ancient Mediterranean—that a new form of

societal organization was to permeate very old ones: a centralized

state apparatus structured around a distinct national entity. The

ancient world had seen the centralized state in all its grandeur and

power. And it had even seen in a bare, rudimentary form the

outlines of the nation. But never before had the two—state and

nation—been cojoined to produce a form of statism based on nationalism with its far-reaching sequelae for the modern world and

the emergence of a highly corrosive global market economy.

----

Within this rich, highly variegated, and fluid period of history, when

societal development could have followed very different directions from the one toward which it moved, we must reexamine the

conventional wisdom about the rise of the modern state and the

formation of the nation.

That the state preceded the nation historically hardly requires

emphasis here. The previous pages of this work have operated

with this fact throughout. The professional institutionalization of

power and the monopolization of violence by distinct administrative, judicial, military, and police agencies occurred fairly early in

history. The state, so conceived, emerges as a highly compact

entity whose persistence from ancient times to the present seems

almost unchanged functionally, however much it has varied in

form.

But so functionally similar an institution, seen only in terms of

its “class character” and its coercive role, can be very tricky when

it is treated without respect for the many nuances of its development. Among many social theorists, this simplistic notion of the

state has given rise to images of various state forms as mere epiphenomenal expressions of a basic, deceptively unchanged structure—indeed, to use Marxian language, as the mere “superstructure” of an unaltered “base,” hence an institution that scarcely

deserves searching analysis. In modern politics, this simplistic approach produced considerable mischief. The careless use of words

similar to “fascist,” applied to established republican states as well

as totalitarian ones, can generate very slovenly and crude political

attitudes. States have been called fascist or, for that matter, democratic that are very far from being either one or the other; and

their opponents have often disregarded hard-won civil liberties

that deserve the most; earnest support by any ideological standards

or values.

What is no less disturbing, there has been a gross disregard of

democratic rights generally among self-styled “progressives”

whose concerns for material justice have supplanted their concerns for social justice. The primacy given to economics, an emphasis uniquely characteristic of a market-economy mentality—and most evident, ironically, in socialist and syndicalist ideologies—has led to a troubling disregard for libertarian political institutions whose preservation and expansion is of immeasurable importance to the development of a new, municipally oriented politics.

These institutions have often been contemptuously dismissed as

“bourgeois” by many socialists and anarchists alike, although we

shall have occasion to see that the “bourgeoisie” was never libertarian in outlook and rarely republican in its commitment to state

institutions. Even liberal and conservative ideologies have used

such words as “freedom” so ecumenically that both the content

and form of the term have been absorbed into a meaningless

“black hole” of sociological rhetoric.

The interchangeable use of the words “state” and “nation,” in

turn, has been even more troubling. Trite avowals of “my country

right or wrong!” imply no commitment to a republican state, even

when the cry is justified by a country’s seemingly democratic or

libertarian institutions. Patriotism today is nationalism, not democratism, although during the French revolution the two words

could have easily passed as synonyms. “Love of country” may

characterize the sentiments of a fascist, socialist, liberal, or conservative, and this love does not in itself commit any one of them

to a particular state form, much less to a free community. Hence

the development of the state and the emergence of the nation are

not matters of academic interest. Their history is deeply entangled

with the prevalent societal values of our time and profoundly

affects our visions of society’s future, especially in a discussion of

the municipality.

A close study of the state shows that there are and have been

varying *degrees* of statehood, not simply the emergence of a

finished phenomenon called “*the* state.” Indeed, the universal use

of such words as “state” can impede a clear understanding of the ;

extent to which “the state” exists at various levels of societal development—not only historically, but also today in modern society.

Conceived in a processual way with due regard to the degrees of

statism that have existed historically and functionally, I should

emphasize very decidedly that “the state” can be less pronounced

as a constellation of institutions at the municipal level, more pronounced at the provincial or regional leyel, and most pronounced

at the national level. These are not trifling distinctions. We cannot

ignore them without grossly simplifying politics. Differences in

degrees of statification can have major practical consequences for

politically concerned individuals and communities.

History, moreover, provides us with compelling evidence of

germinal states, quasistates, partially formed, often very unstable

states, and finally fully formed and all-embracing states. The

Athenian *polis* and even the Roman Republic were not fully

formed states—this in contrast, for example, to the fairly well-formed Roman imperial state and even more fully formed Egyptian state of Ptolemaic times. When applied to classical Athens, the

use of the word **“state”** has a very limited meaning, despite the

presence of slavery. Even in the modern nation-states we know

best, municipalities are often less “statified” than nations, with the

exception, to be sure, of the patently totalitarian states that have

emerged in our own time. In practical terms, a modern municipal

politics can be very different from a national parliamentary “politics,” as we shall see in the closing chapter of this book, and localist

politics can rest on ideological traditions and premises very different from those we associate with the formation of the nation-state.

The fact is that we have been much too concerned with the

origins of the state, conceived primarily as an instrument of class

domination, to give due recognition to the history of the state: its

evolution, its various unfinished forms, its varying kinds of structure, and its capacity to penetrate the social and political life of the community as well as the nation.

Living, as we do in “founded” republican states of one kind or

another—states that are clothed in a panoply of “declarations,”

“constitutions,” “charters,” and even highly personified “fathers”

and “founders”—our images of “the state” tend to acquire a highly

contractual, legalistic, and contrived form. “The state,” with its

clearly dated documents, seems more like a social contract than

a historically conditioned phenomenon. Behind the “contractual”

state lies an anthropology and history that, carefully considered,

desanctifies its rationalistic claims to authority and its mandate as

the source of an orderly society. The state, in fact, had to fight its

way into existence against claims that were no less rationalistic and

morally valid than those that it advanced on behalf of its own

legitimation. It had to emerge organically, that is to say, within the

framework of social relationships and, later, political norms that

were by no means consistent with and were, at times, highly

antithetical to the formation of a state apparatus. Hence, it is fair

to say that just as the constituted or constitutional state preceded

the formation of the nation, so an organic state, uncertain of its

pedigree and of dubious legitimacy, preceded the establishment

of a constituted or “constitutional” state. The organic origins of the

state, in turn, bring into question the extent to which the state can

be validated wholesale on strictly rationalistic terms and, above

all, its capacity to absorb the very aspects of social and community

life in which it was gestated. To demystify the authority of the

state as a rationalistic contrivance is to take the first step toward

recovering the Hellenic notion of politics as a public activity, the

domain of authentic citizenship—not as statecraft, the domain of

the professional legislatures, military, and bureaucrats.

Contrary to rationalistic and contractual images of the state,

state institutions emerged slowly, uncertainly, and precariously

out of a social milieu that was distinctly nonstatist in character. In

fact, the social and organic sources of the state had to be meticulously reworked before they could give rise to state institutions.

The ancient temple corporation, actually a religious legitimation

of tribal collectivity and public control of land, seems to have been

the most likely source of the Near Eastern state. This was a time

when priests commonly became kings or, at least, when the kingship often took on a priestly character. In either case, the temple

and palace monumentalized as well as deified the tribal community.

Despite the increasing secularization of the state, notably m

Greece and Borne, the state never completely lost its religious

trappings and its function as the custodian of the collectivistic

community. This attribute, whether as an ensemble of feudal nobles or a monarchy and ultimately as an absolutist empire, remained with it well into recent times. The traditional “head of

state,” be he a lord or king, always remained the “father of his

people,” whether by divine right or as a divinity in his own right.

Hence, prior to the rise of republican systems of governance, the

state always appeared not as a constituted phenomenon but as a

reworking of a very traditional, organic, patriarchal, indeed tribalistic body of relationships in which power was not simply conferred by the community as in the case of elected kingships but

inherited along lineage and blood lines in a manner redolent of the

ancient tribalist blood tie. The present always entailed a reworking of the past, a transmutation rather than a dissolution of traditional forms to meet new needs and imperatives.

It is notable that the rise of the centralized nation-state in

Europe also followed this archaic and highly organic process of

transmutation of old into new. Indeed, until “The Age of the

Democratic Revolutions,” to use the title of R. R. Palmer’s distinguished book, it was not through the constitution of new states but

the recovery of ancient rights that king and community were

thrown into civil war with each other, a conflict that often took the

shape of monarchy against municipality.{52} Neither one party nor

the other sought to innovate new forms of governance but rather

to restore old ones from the past. Characteristically, the earliest

form of the European nation-state appears not as the emergence

of a national economy, significant as this development proved to

be, but as the increasing sovereignty of the kingly household itself—the monarchical *oikos*—and the image of the “nation” as a kingly patrimony.

The evolution of the kingly household into an authentic state is

strikingly revealed by the evolution of the English monarchy. The

reputation of England as a uniquely centralized state from the

days of the Norman Conquest in 1066 tends to be overstated.

Admittedly, William the Conquerer took firm possession of Anglo-Saxon England shortly after the defeat of Harold in the Battle of

Hastings, but the area under Norman control was relatively small,

almost provincial in size. Wales and Ireland had yet to be conquered and Scotland to be absorbed. William’s absolutism was not

only restricted territorially; it was short-lived historically. The English state—and certainly its highly fragmented sense of nationhood—is notable not for its continuity but its discontinuity. Growing baronial strength clearly began to abridge monarchical rule in

little more than a century after the conquest: the Magna Carta, to

which John unwillingly set his seal at Runnymede in June 1215 is

testimony not to the rise of English democracy, all legends about

the charter’s intent aside, but to the power that the English barons

acquired at the expense of the monarchy. Although John’s father,

Henry II, had left his sons a state buttressed by a system of royal

law remarkable for its time—extending the “King’s peace” to

include civil and criminal cases, a rationalized system of trials,

punishments, and juries, and a professional royal judiciary to translate this system into practice—many of these jurisdictions were to

be reclaimed by the barons. Nominally centralized, England remained remarkably decentralized under the weaker monarchs

who filled the long span between Henry II and Henry VII, a period

of some three centuries. A centralized infrastructure had emerged

from the conquest, but history had yet to flesh it out with effective

royal institutions.

What makes the English state interesting is the challenge it

raises to simplistic theories of state formation and rule. I refer to

its organic roots and its evolution out of household offices. The

English state was born not out of an administrative body of autonomous departments but rather it was formed out of the personal

responsibilities of the king’s servants—his immediate household

coterie—often in opposition to the doubtful loyalties of the king’s

own feudal barons. Perhaps the foremost of these royal servants

was the king’s personal secretary, his chancellor, who carried the

royal seal and coordinated the emerging departments that comprised the administrative portion of the royal court. In time, the

chancellor became the pole around which an increasing number

of clerks, experts, and specialists in various governmental areas,

and overseers of what was to become a fairly complex executive

authority collected to form the all-important English chancery.

Almost every aspect of monarchical rule fell within its purview,

principally the king’s exchequer who saw to the collection of taxes

and Henry II’s professional judiciary.

In fact, the English state was formed largely from the king’s

bedroom, dining table, men-in-waiting, and household clergy, not

from constituted principles of government that spoke in the interests of a specific “ruling class.” Class theories of the “origins of the

state” to the contrary notwithstanding, the English state of the

Middle Ages began as the elaboration of a patrimony rather than

the institutionalization of one “class’s” authority over that of another. The English barons, who were to view the formation of this

state with suspicion and later with overt hostility, found it difficult

to claim it as their own. A continual tension; existed—occasionally

expressing itself in a violent form—between the baronial infrastructure of English medieval society and the monarchy, which

formed the originating impulse of an authentic, fairly complete

state, In its patrimonial form, the English state is no exception to

the “origins of the state” generally; this mode of state formation

is very similar to the way in which the “barbarian” chiefdoms of,

an earlier tribal society gradually extended their power from networks furnished by their personal retainers and clans. The journey

from “valet” to “prime minister,” amusing as the juxtaposition

may seem, is closer to the truth of state formation than the more

“sociological” idea that the state emerged as an agency of class

interest—whatever it was to become later in history.

I have dwelt in some detail bn the origins of the English state—in time to be regarded as the prototype of the nation-state *par*

continuity with the ancient past. The organic growth of the English monarchy parallels to a remarkable degree the rise of *oikos*

forms of statehood. Historically, these forms go back to early

Egypt, Persia, Babylonia, and even Rome before the empire became heavily bureaucratized.

Why did the English state become such a useful framework for

the modern nation and for modern capitalism? An answer to this

question lies precisely in the limits as well as the rationalistic and

centralistic forms it assumed, both territorially and institutionally.

Despite its exhausting adventures in France, the English state by

Tudor times remained focused more fixedly on its own island

territories than did its archaic antecedents. And institutionally, it

never achieved a degree of absoluteness—or at least was never

permitted to do so—such that it devoured its own bourgeois

“golden goose.” It permitted a flexibility of market development

that was rarely to be seen in the past, not only in the medieval

world. Thus, while the absolute monarchs of England (principally

Henry II and the Tudors) managed to hold a nation together, at

least in the Anglo-Saxon core areas of the island, eventually integrating the Scots as well as the Welsh within a national framework,

it provided ample space for its middle-class “commons” to flourish,

prosper, and, in time, resist the exactations and arbitary demands

Charles I imposed upon them. Throughout much of its history,

England was burdened less by a bureaucracy than her rivals in

western Europe. While the monarchy retained a well-knit bureaucratic structure, particularly in the administration of royal law and

the collection of taxes, England was largely managed by its local

squirearchy, a highly personalized system of management guided

by the rationalized standards introduced by Henry II and the

Tudor monarchs. The English Revolution of Cromwell’s time

finalized this delicate balance between the king and his “commons” in a way that imparted a fictive quality to the English state

as an ideal “bourgeois” political system. Indeed, it was England’s

“constitutional monarchy” that was to have an almost hypnotic

attraction for the progressive intelligentsia of the French and German enlightenments.

Ironically, it was France rather than England that was to create

the kind of all-pervasive bureaucratic nation-state that characterizes present-day bourgeois state forms. Given the waywardness of

history that defies attempts by historians to systematize the development of events in the name of historical materialism and

other “scientific” explanations of the nation-state s emergence,

France’s preeminence as the prototypic nation-state is explained

not by her “advanced” development as a “bourgeois” society but

rather by the lateness of that development, indeed by delays that

were to significantly initiate that development in the midnineteenth century, well after it occurred in England. To be sure,

French absolutism did not emerge in a sudden burst of centralization but quite to the contrary. Louis IX (“Saint Louis”), more than

a century after Henry II of England, still issued his decrees with

a terminology that is redolent of the early Frankish system of

collective rule in which the Germanic kings were considered

merely first among equals. The expression “We and our barons

recurs in Louis’s pronouncements, a phrase that in no way suggests a commanding authority over the feudal community. But

even more so than England, France began to enter into a phase

of state evolution that was to induce many historians to regard

French absolutism as the predecessor of all Europe—an overstatement, to be sure, but a sufficiently suggestive one to impart to the

French Revolution, which overthrew it, a particularly incendiary

challenge to absolutism as such.

By the end of the twelfth century, France had already begun

to catch up with England by creating **les officiers du roi** (officials

of the king) who shared power with the French barons in the

traditional royal council. By degrees, the French began to outpace

their English rivals. Functionaries, emerging from the royal

household, acquired expanding administrative roles so that the

kingly servants were soon to be royal bureaucrats rather than

household administrators. In contrast to the English monarchy,

the French carried this development much further: it encompassed time-honored

<em>local</em> as well as royal jurisdictions. Already a

huge hierarchy of petty officials had arisen, such that by the end

of the thirteenth century, Philippe le Bel was obliged to place the

host of **lieutenants, sergents,** and **hedeaux** who afHicted the

French people on local and provincial levels under the scrutiny of

<em>controlleurs,</em> a royal strategy that may have enhanced rather than

diminished the bureaucratization of the nation. Royal **commis·**

<em>saires</em> were to become permanent regional officials by the midsixteenth

century and a far-reaching network of **intendants,** supervised

by **surintendants,**

acquired the odious status of a financial

bureaucracy that particularly aroused popular hatred.

In time, the immense French bureaucracy of the sixteenth and

seventeenth centuries, in theory answerable only to the monarchy, acquired a life—indeed an outlook—of its own. The emergence of a bureaucratic sensibility, permeating all levels of French

society, can hardly be emphasized too strongly. A new, almost

ubiquitous “nobility of the robe,” ennobled more as functionaries

of the monarchy than by virtue of birth, began to overshadow the

hereditary “nobility of the sword.” In contrast to so much of feudal

Europe, the sons of the French middle classes began to regard the

royal bureaucracy rather than the clerical hierarchy as the avenue

toward upward mobility and power, a shift in perspective that

linked the French “bourgeoisie,” whatever that word meant some

two centuries ago, to the monarchy more tightly than historians

of “class conflict would have us believe. The French Revolution,

conceived as the “classic bourgeois revolution” of emerging capitalism, was to test this “class analysis” in the fiery crucible of

insurrection, with more dismal results than later, nineteenth-century historians suspected.

Herder’s conclusion to the contrary notwithstanding, France

was by no means the “precursor of all Europe.” It is beguiling to

think that an even more centralized and bureaucratized “nation-state” was established in Sicily in the early thirteenth century,

when Norman conquerors dispossessed the Arab rulers of their

control over the island and established what many historians have

variously called the “earliest modern state” and “absolute monarchy” in Europe’s history. Emperor Frederick II did, in fact, create

an “omnipotent royal power” that led to the, “complete destruction of the feudal state” to use Jacob Burckhardt’s words, a state

marked by a completely centralized legal system, a professional

army (which the French monarchy introduced very early in its

evolution), and an all-encompassing bureaucracy of professionally

trained officials, all indubitable traits of Norman Sicily.

But these are traits of a kind that in no way made Sicily a

“modern state,” much less a “nation-state.”{53} Such state forms, in

fact, were to appear very early in human history. The Ptolemaic

state that followed Alexander’s conquest of Egypt in ancient times

did not differ in fundamentals from the structure that Frederick

imposed’on Sicily some fifteen centuries later. Characteristically,

both Alexander’s general, Ptolemy, and the Norman monarch,

Frederick, wedded the economy of the Nile and of the island to

the state itself. In both cases, key commercial operations, particularly the grain trade, became state monopolies and economic activity was. bound to statecraft. The Norman state in Sicily was an

“Oriental despotism,” to use the language of nineteenth- and early

twentieth-century historiography, not a “modern state,” much

less a “nation-state.” Administered t>y conquerors and their

bureaucracies with highly regulated economies, the Norman state

was no more “modern” than the Inca state in Peru or the Egyptian

state in North Africa.

We are faced with the paradox that one of the earliest approximations to a centralized “nation-state” emerged in Spain, even

before the Tudors in England and the Bourbons in France fully

consolidated their rule. Yet Spanish absolutism and nationalism

did not promote the development of a “bourgeoisie” or a “bourgeois society”—developments that have been associated with the

emergence of the nation-state. In fact, Charles V and his successors were to virtually devour a flourishing Spanish burgher stratum, milking it of its wealth, preempting its power, and essentially

subverting town life in the Iberian peninsula. At the beginning of

the sixteenth century, a swath of almost meaningless royal parasitism and domestic extortion cut across Spanish history, eventually

undermining a flourishing city network that enjoyed extraordfi

nary wealth and autonomy. The extortions initiated by the Spanish

state led, as we shall see shortly, to one of the greatest urban

uprisings in western history, an uprising that decided the future

of the new nation that had emerged from the Christian reconquest of the Iberian peninsula after centuries of Moorish rule. City

life and commerce were to stagnate or decline for reasons that had

much more to do with absolutism and its efforts to forge Spain into

a nation-state than did the decentralization that marked the ensuing history of the country.

What is most intriguing is that neither absolutism nor the rise

of a nation-state provides us with an adequate explanation for the

rise of a “national economy” as Hannah Arendt suggests. Although

Spain was to remain a largely agrarian society up to the 1930s,

indeed a very traditional one, its Hapsburg kings were no less

“enlightened” than the Bourbon kings of France and, with the

exception of the two Henrys and Elizabeth, the Tudor and Stuart

kings of England. Nevertheless, Spain moved into a period of

economic decline that still weighs on her shoulders today while

England became the “factory of the world” and France its cultural

“perfumery.” Although European nation-states from the sixteenth

century onward created the arena for a national economy, they

did not necessarily create the forces that shaped it. Absolutism,

which, sculpted a sense of nationhood out of feudal parochialism,

played a very crucial role: it not only supplanted localism with,

nationalism; it also stifled a highly decentralistic, localistic, and

spontaneous society, marked by a rich diversity of cultural, economic, and communal attributes, replacing it with increasingly

homogenized lifeways, bureaucratized institutions, and centralized state forms. In some cases, this absolutist alternative favored

the later expansion of a market economy; in others, it led to state

parasitism and outright regression. In all cases, however, it turned

localist politics into nationalist statecraft, divesting citizenship of

its classical attributes and turning vital, empowered, and strongly

etched men and women into passive, disempowered, and obedient “subjects.”

This shift from a living people to deadened subjects did not

occur without furious resistance. A belief in autonomy, regional

and local identity, and citizen empowerment ran very high between the late Middle Ages and fairly recent times. The battle to

retain these distinctly political qualities and rights was to be

fought not in national political parties or by professional statesmen; rather, it was conducted on the level of village, town, neighborhood, and city life, where the ideals of confederation were to

be opposed to demands for a nation-state and the values of decentralization were to be opposed to those of centralization. What lay

in the balance was not only the future of the town and countryside

but the development of political institutions as opposed to state

institutions—and an active citizenry as opposed to a passive “constituency.”

----

It has become somewhat conventional in urban historiography to

treat “city-states” as though their relationships with each other

were normally marked by endless petty squabbles and their relationship to absolutism by an almost unqualified degree of support.

“City-states,” we are commonly told, were almost innately quarrelsome, hence the wars that were endemic on the municipal level

of politics. Ultimately, so the argument goes, they were to show a

unique commonality of interests in the support they gave to the

emerging absolute monarchies and nation-states of the late Middle

Ages. Like the monarchy, they opposed feudal lords who placed

imposts on their commercial transactions and blocked the development of their markets with a self-enclosed manorial economy.

The partial truth this conventional view conveys is outweighed

by the serious error it contains. It expresses a characteristically

liberal and Marxist prejudice that prevailed a century ago against

all decentralized societies, a prejudice that was to be placed in tho

ideological service of European nationalism and its gospel of the

centralized state. Only today do we seem willing to recognize how

reactionary and false was this imagery of ever-embattled, quarrelsome, and promonarchical cities, whose economic power was presumably placed with few if any qualms in the service of absolutism.

There is more than enough historical evidence to show that

cities were as disposed to form,leagues and confederacies with

each other as they were to fight with each other. Many of these

leagues and confederacies, in fact, were not only networks of mutual aid; they were vigorously directed against absolutism and its

threat to communal liberties. Finally, territorial lords were often

quick to abandon their traditional feudal or manorial forms of

rights and duties, to participate as vigorously in commerce as the

most avaricious merchants. Indeed, English capitalism cut its first

teeth in the countryside where many squires and nobles turned

agricultural and common lands into sheep runs to meet Flemish

demands for wool—perhaps the earliest example of agribusiness in

modern times.

Confederacies or leagues of cities go back as far as Greek times

when *poleis* entered into various associations with each other for

mutual protection, shared religious beliefs, economic interests,

even for quasitribal honorific reasons. At least fifteen of these

confederacies of one kind or another, known more generally as

marked by fascinating examples of cooperation. These confederacies can often be traced back to tribal groups that were established

as early as the Bronze Age. Tribalism never completely disappeared as a framework for the later confederations, Thus the famous Delian League that Athens developed was initially Ionian,

composed of *poleis* that generally claimed a shared ethnic ancestry. By the same token, the Peloponnesian League that opposed

it was largely Dorian, and the Achaean League claimed a shared

ancestry with the archipelago’s early Mycenean settlers although

“Achaea” itself was really composed of a mixed population of

Dorians and their precursors, the simpler Arcadians.

A troubling feature of many confederations is that one *polis*

tended to become the pole around which its confederates clustered, whether by inclination, necessity, or coercion. The Delian

League formed by Athens eventually became so overarchingly

Athenian in character that historians were to call its later phase an

“Athenian empire,” This is an overstatement. That Athens battened itself on the revenues it extracted as “protection money”

from the league and used coercion when persuasion failed to hold

its confederates in line is doubtless true; but there is an inescapable irony in the fact that it foisted its own democratic institutions

on *poleis* with limited freedoms of their own, whether they

wanted a democracy or not. The internal politics of the league’s

members stands in very sharp contrast to the despotic institutions

we encounter in virtually all ancient empires. In fact the original

confederal council of the league, formed early in the fifth century

to check Persia’s advances into Greece, was distinguished by its

high sense of fraternity. All members of the council had an equal

vote, and its treasury was kept in the Temple of Apollo on the

politically neutral island of Delos. Only later, when the Persian

threat ended, did Athens assert complete sovereignty over the

league, preventing Naxos and Thasos from seceding and bringing

the league’s treasury to the Athenian acropolis.

We also know of confederacies, however, where *poleis* were

permitted to function very much on their own. Pellene, for example, showed considerable independence in the Achaean Confederacy; conversely, Thebes was held in check by *poleis* that made

up the Boeotian Confederacy, particularly after it was reformed

toward the end of the fourth century B.C. The use of the word

<em>sympoliteia</em> to designate many confederacies, particularly those

that extended byeond traditional tribal areas, is significant. Taken

literally, the word describes a union of *poleis*, presumably of equal

status, in contrast to a *patria* or “fatherland” with its connotations

of a capital city, or an *ethnos*, with its real or fictive tribal bonds

based on blood ties. At the molecular level of the **sympoliteia**’s

life, the human bond is based on citizenship, on the *polites*, not

on some form of juridical national identity at one extreme or

kinship ties at the other. Citizenship, in effect, is not dissolved into

an impersonal national affiliation or a presumably biological or

tribal one. And, in fact, many *polites* or citizens of a confederacy

enjoyed rights in other confederal *poleis* that they normally denied to resident aliens. They could buy land, enjoy the full protection of a confederated *polis*’s laws, and, in some cases perhaps,

participate in its *ekklesia*, although normally their political rights

were linked to the institutions of their own cities. In short, the

confederacies of ancient Greece were to enlarge the whole concept of citizenship, well beyond the parochial framework of early

How were the confederacies structured? Our knowledge of

them is very limited and any extended discussion of their known

institutions is precluded by lack of space as well as facts. But

certain general outlines can be noted. Normally, a Greek *polis*

consisted of magistrates, a board of generals, a council or *boule*,

and a citizens’ assembly. This form of “government” existed in

many Greek *poleis* from the fifth to the third century, when it was

finally swept away by the Romans.

This is not an overstatement. The fact is that Greek *poleis* had

very little experience with “representative” forms of governance;

indeed it was very hard for the Greeks to think in terms of “representation” generally. They could understand the rise of an oligarchy, which they often identified with a tyranny or repressive control of some kind, and a democracy, which, in its Perikleaii form,

seemed radical or “excessive” to its opponents. And republican-type structures did surface among them from, time to time. But

these republics rarely produced stable institutional forms. Human

scale—a distinctly municipal scale—continued to be the only congenial and comprehensible level of institutional form that seemed

to satisfy Hellenic lifeways and modes of thinking. Any form larger

than the *polis* or confederacies of *poleis* cut across the grain of the

Gfeek mind and Greek social theory. The rise of the Macedonian

empire, regaled with all the trappings of royalty, generally horrified the Greeks, and the Roman empire seems more to have

fascinated them, as Polybius’s writings indicate, than attracted

them until the very memory of political democracy had faded

away, In any case, even when a republican regime did emerge

among the Greeks, notably with the ascendancy of Rome, it was

often called a **demokratia** and there was a tendency to trace its

pedigree back to the *polis* of classical times. The Macedonian and

Roman empires, in effect, constituted an annoying challenge to

the Greek image of political consociation: its ethical as distinguished from administrative ways of visualizing or defining politics: its high regard for some degree of citizen participation in

formulating policy or executing it. Just as a Roman in imperial

times might look back nostalgically to the republica, so Greeks

under foreign rule looked back endearingly to the *demokratia* and

often used the word when it no longer applied to their institutions.

Not surprisingly, the *boule* and *ekklesia* the council and the

citizens’ assembly—were to appear in many Greek confederations, not only within Greek *poleis* themselves. There is evidence

that an *ekklesia* formulated policies for the Thessalian Confederacy in the closing decades of the fifth century B.C., possibly as an

aristocratic body. But in time cities began to encroach upon the

power of the territorial nobles. Apparently, a democratic faction,

strongly influenced by the Athenians, successfully extended popular rule within the Thessalian cities and the confederacy itself,

after which the confederacy eventually became more centralized

and exclusive. The Boeotian Confederacy was, as J. A. O. Larsen

puts it, “a land of **hoplites**” because the area itself favored small-scale farming.{54} But it is surprising to find that the Confederacy

more closely approximates a republican state than any we encounter so early in Greek history. This may have been the result more

of Spartan influence than the internal development of the Thessalian *poleis*, an influence that did not go unchallenged by a pro-Athenian faction in the cities that made up the confederacy. Unfortunately, the details of its development are closed to us by the lack of adequate historical data.

The Phocian Confederacy alternated between an oligarchy

and a democracy: a strong executive made up of generals had to

answer to a popular assembly that enjoyed the power to depose

its military leaders. The Locrian Confederacy seems to have had

a citizens’ assembly; indeed, from the scant evidence we have,

democracy found a comfortable home here, often together with

shared citizenship that made it possible for citizens of one *polis*

to acquire property and to intermarry with citizens of another

Greeks generally singled them are out for their fairly humane

and decent treatment of foreigners. The Aetolian Confederacy

appears to have had an *ekklesia* in which all citizens not only

had the right to vote but followed the Athenian fashion of voting

as individuals, not as citizens of their own *poleis*. This extraordinary degree of political individuation within a confederacy—a

rarity even in decentralistic and confederal social theories—should not go unnoticed. What the Athenians did within Athens

and its environs, the Locrians did within a confederation of separate cities. Meetings of their confederal assembly were held

twice a year—once in the spring when the military campaigning

season began and again in autumn when it came to an end. We

shall have occasion to emphasize that democracy cannot be

disassociated historically from military associations when they involve the mobilization of citizens for warfare, changes in arms

and military technique, or simply a high valuation that is placed

on the image of the armed citizen.

The Achaean Confederacy, perhaps the best known of all Greek

confederacies, became so democratic that it was in advance of

Athens in some respects. Finally, in 417 B.C., Sparta was obliged

to step in to impose oligarchic rule. This intervention stirred up

a medley of reactions in which a pro-Athenian faction restored

democracy that led to further Spartan intervention. Nevertheless,

there seems to have been a persistent *ekklesia* on a local level that

certainly was in existence in Hellenistic times, the era following

Alexander’s conquests in the Near East and North Africa. Unfortunately, we know far too little about other Greek confederacies to

provide even capsule descriptions about their structure and development.

What does it mean in very concrete terms to say that a Greek

confederacy had a citizens’ assembly? It is tempting to think that

in comparatively large confederal areas, such an assembly is simply a euphemism for a representative system of government, not

a direct, face-to-face body of citizens. Actually, this is far from true.

Judging from the Achaean Confederacy, citizens from various

would mean a journey over wide distances, hence assembly meetings would tend to attract only the well-to-do who had the means

and leisure to attend them. But much the same could be said of

the Athenian *ekklesia*. Attika was more than the environs of Athens, and for communities in the more distant parts of Athenian

territory a journey to the city would have been a fairly difficult

one. Like Athens, however, the poorer elements in the host city

or ‘‘capital” of a Greek confederacy often outnumbered the well-to-do who could afford to make the journey and may have, provided it with a popular, indeed radical, ambience.

Whatever may have been the possibilities and limits of ancient

cities, municipal democracy withered and finally died under

Roman rule. The Roman Empire, a purely parasitic phenomenon,

was extremely wary of municipal autonomy. It provided cities

with only enough freedom to police themselves and extract tribute from subject populations. In the centuries following Periklean

democracy, city life as a political reality began to decline and, after

the second century of the contemporary era, shrivelled disastrously, at least in Europe and the northern rim of the Mediterranean basin. Nor was urban life to revive in this area until the

eleventh century. But with this revival came the emergence of

new confederacies, an extremely important aspect of European

history whose story has been badly neglected. Peter Kropotkin’s

work on the city confederacies and leagues of Europe, limited as

it may be, may be cited as a truly pioneering effort.{55} The period

of the French Revolution and the nineteenth century were to

.witness a depressing shift in perspective from historical studies of

localism and urban confederalism to the nation-state, a shift that

reflects a distinctly centralistic bias in radical as Well as liberal

historiography. The lacuna that exists in this field is by no means

the result of oversight: it originates from a distinct political proclivity in Marxian historiography and liberal social theory to emphasize the role of the nation-state in fashioning the modern era,

an emphasis for which we have paid dearly in evaluating the

alternatives that face this era today with its increasing bureaucratization and centralization of social life.

Despite its brevity and incompleteness, Kropotkin’s work still

provides us with a robust framework for recovering some sense of

the vitality this municipal world offered as an alternative to the

nation-state. “Already in the years 1130–1150 powerful leagues

came into existence,” Kropotkin tells us, “and a few years later,

when [Emperor] Frederick Barbarossa [of the Holy Roman Empire] invaded Italy and, supported by the nobles and some retardory cities, marched against Milan, popular enthusiasm was

roused in many towns by popular preachers. Crema, Piacenza,

Brescia, Tortona, etc., went to the rescue; the banners of the guilds

of Verona, Padua, Vicenza, and Trevisa floated side by side in the

cities’ camp against the banners of the Emperor and the nobles.”{56}

The following year saw the emergence of the first of the Lombard Leagues (1167), which numbered, sixteen cities at its height,

followed by a second in 1198 and finally a third (1226) that collectively included nearly all the major cities of northern Italy. Not

only was Milan a member of all three leagues but also Bologna,

Verona, Brescia, Ferrara, Faenza, Vercelli, and Alessandria. Even

Venice, proud and independent, joined the first of the leagues. A

league of Tuscan cities was formed shortly after Henry Vi’s death

in 1195, and still another two centuries later, guided largely by

Rome during the papacy’s quarrels with the empire. The number

of leagues that formed in Italy during this time are too numerous

to examine here. Some clustered around powerful cities such as

Florence, Venice, Milan, and the papal seat in Rome, surfacing in

the Romagna and in Umbria as well as in northern Italy. With the

passing of time, these leagues either fell apart into rival cities or

formed genuine city-states—in fact, small republics or duchies,

depending upon the internal political structure of cities that led

them. By the thirteenth century, this structure was usually oligarchical: the *popolo*, had given way to **signori**, and Italy was to

become a battleground for major’ European powers that tried to

dip into the still very considerable wealth of the peninsula. Although eminent urban historians such as Lewis Mumford are

highly disdainful of this development, particularly the continual

discord between the cities that are believed ultimately to have fed

the parcelization of the area, Kropotkin is careful to note that it

was precisely “when separate cities became little States [that] wars

broke out between them,” generally as, a “struggle for supremacy

or colonies.”{57} Whether Italy’s parcelization is quite the overall

“evil” that characterizes most historical accounts of the Italian

city-states or a desideratum that delayed the emergence of an

overly centralized nation-state has yet to be assessed.

The creation of city confederacies in central Europe followed

a development that is very similar to what we encounter in Italy,

but they were-also marked by characteristics that make them

highly distinctive. That Italy led Europe in urban development is

not surprising: the peninsula had been dotted by cities for centuries when much of the continent north of the Alps was still covered by forest. The German-speaking cities, however, were

unique. Although they were to follow their Italian counterparts in

time, they differed from them in social texture. They were

burgher cities with sturdy domestic markets based on the ordinary

staples of life to an extent we do not quite find in Italy (apart from

Florence) or encounter in France. Cities involved in the Mediterranean trade made their fortunes largely from luxury goods such

as silk, spices, gems, well-wrought armor, gold and silver ornaments, and the like, mainly transported from the Near East, North

Africa, and Asia. By contrast, German’cities tended to deal in the

making and sale of coarser cloths, tools, simple armor, food staples,

and raw materials. These commodities gave rise to a stay-at-home

artisan and merchant order that underpinned very stolid communities with a deep sense of rootedness and a strong appetite for

security. Accordingly, a localist civicism and proclivity for autonomy persisted after the Italians had become relatively jaded in

their municipal loyalties and yielded to despotic regimes. The

German word **Gemeinde** has a special meaning in civic history for

which other languages have poor equivalents. It denotes an organic community, a community that has a sense of identity and

personality, indeed one in which city hierarchies are notable for

the contribution they make to the collective good at each level

rather than the oppression they inflict on subordinates.

Genoa and Venice acquired their wealth mainly from exotic

goods and a Mediterranean-wide trade. Hamburg acquired its

wealth from brewing and Liibeck from herring and the furs of east

European forests. Merchant and artisan, trader and primary producer developed a symbiotic relationship that was relatively rare

in the Latin cities of the south. The city confederacies projected

their burgher traits onto their confederacies: cities and towns

came together not only to protect their autonomy and liberties;

they also joined to promote trade and share in a common prosperity, not simply as rivals whom circumstances forced into collusion

with each other. The persistent conflict that marked so many

Italian cities, especially when they developed into city-states that

placed lesser communities under their control, was more subdued

north of the Alps. Although bitter internal wars unravel this picture in the Flemish cities, where a nascent “proletariat” stood at

loggerheads with a nascent “capitalist class” in the wool-processing industry of the time (a problem, I may add, that afflicted

Florence no less than Bruges), the gild structures of central and

northern Europe were more entrenched than elsewhere. They

helped to create and empower a stratum of middling people,

mainly artisans and small merchants, who enjoyed relatively comfortable lives and had a stabilizing effect on the community, cushioning the conflicts that were spawned by great disparities of

wealth.

Thus, one has the sense that German cities formed more stable

confederacies than did other urban entities in Europe. Indeed the

Swiss Confederation, perhaps the most enduring and libertarian to

emerge in Europe, rested heavily on the formation of the **Graubunden** or “Gray League,” the canton that was to be dubbed *die kleine Schweiz* or “little Switzerland,” partly because of its prototypic character as the home of Swiss democracy, partly too because of

its ethnic diversity although its population is mainly German-speaking. Here, the Swiss recourse to referenda is reputed to have

been born and “Nowhere through the whole range of history,”

declared F. B. Baker exultantly, nearly a century ago, “is it possible

to find a country where the democratic principle was more

thoroughly applied ... or where the good and bad results of that

principle have been more thoroughly demonstrated.”{58}

Mumford’s churlish statements about the municipal confederacies of central Europe to the contrary notwithstanding, what the

cities of Germanic Europe lacked in durability, they tended to

make up in recuperability.{59} Some four centuries of German history are marked by a large number of municipal confederations

that continually bubbled up to the surface of political life. The

Hanseatic League, perhaps the most durable of the lot, existed

from 1241, when Liibeck and Hamburg signed a treaty of mutual

protection, to 1669, when its last diet was convened. Officially, the

league was never terminated and cities such as Hamburg and

Bremen are still designated as “Hanseatic cities.” Largely based

on the Baltic trade, the league at its height embraced between 60

and 80 cities (I have taken the most conservative figures at my

disposal), including the wool-processing center of Bruges in Flanders. Nearly all the major Baltic ports belonged to this confederacy

at one time or another, and its ships ranged widely from Novogorod in the east to London in the west and along the Atlantic coastline.

Still earlier, major confederacies appeared in parts of central

Germany,; principally the short-lived First Rhenish League in

1226, followed by the Second in 1254, which lasted until 1258.

Some eighty cities, virtually all the leading Rhineland communities, belonged to the league until its members drifted away after

supporting contending claimants to the throne of the Holy Roman

Empire. Intermixed with the politics of the empire and endemically at war with nobles who preyed on their trade, their history

weaves a story of enormous complexity and challenges. By 1384,

a Swabian League had been formed that brought German cities

to unprecedented influence. League members even advanced

proposals to join the Swiss Confederation. Had the Swiss been

responsive to these overtures, European history might have taken

a very different turn than it did, possibly replacing nationalism

with confederalism. But the union was not to be, and the cities,

ever mindful of their autonomy and liberties, failed to prevail over

the empire and the princes. Later leagues were to appear

throughout Europe, even in England and, very significantly, in

Spain. If we bear in mind the large number of municipal confederacies! that existed in Europe during the eleventh century and in

the centuries that followed it, the certainty so prevalent in present-day historiography tliat the nation-state constitutes a “logical”

development of Europe out of feudalism can only be regarded as

a bias, indeed a misuse of hindsight that verges on a mystical form

of historical predetermination.

Again, how, may we ask, were the Italian and northern European municipal confederacies structured? None of them created

the popular intercity assemblies we encounter among the Greeks,

Although citizen assemblies emerged within the cities, they did

not appear between the cities. In Italy, the ad hoc nature of the

confederacies did not create any serious problem of entrenched

representatives who could defy the will of their constituencies: the

confederacies were notable for their impermanence. They were

little more than defensive alliances and disappeared as soon as

they were not needed. The First Lombard League created a parliament of its own, but as Daniel Waley tells us, it simply assigned to its members areas of military responsibility and settled

the price contributions of each to field armies (*tallia milium*) and

garrisons.” This “parliament” never became a supracommunal

authority.” Rather it functioned more like a temporary general

staff. “To the communes,” Waley adds, “this *societas* or League

was, like the Empire, an institution to be judged by its utility

rather than by any theoretical implications: only an immediate

imperialist threat could keep it in being.”{60} To the extent that we

can speak of “capitalism” at this time, the highly aggressive entrepreneurial spirit of the Italian municipalities, fed by the enormous

wealth of the Mediterranean-wide trade, fostered a degree of rivalry that inhibited cooperation between the cities and imparted

a highly imperialistic spirit to the largest among them.

This was not entirely the case north of the Alps. German city

confederations, for example, provide us with more enduring

efforts to institutionalize intercommunal cooperation, efforts that

reflect the prudent and deeply rooted burgher spirit of the communities that composed them as distinguished from the more

reckless and venturesome features of the Italian merchants. The

Second Rhenish League, shrewdly playing off the different candidates for the imperial throne, demanded and received formal

recognition from William of Orange as a confederation—a *civitates conjuratae*—and avowed in its declaration that its citizens

“have mutually bound [themselves] by oath to observe a general

peace from St. Margaret’s Day (July 12, 1254).” This declaration

was to go well beyond peacekeeping. Each member of the : league

agreed to send four representatives to a city assembly or *StĂ€dtetag*—one at Worms for the upper Rhine, the other at Mainz for the

lower—to remove excessive river tolls, provide for the common

defense, add or expel new members, and foster the commerce and

welfare of each of the league’s members to the benefit of all civic

orders, including Jews and clergy, not only ordinary citizens. A

board of arbitration was established to settle quarrels between

confederate cities. Finally, an assembly meeting of the municipalities’ representatives was held on a quarterly basis, not on the usual annual one we encounter elsewhere.

The Swabian League followed almost naturally out of its Rhenish predecessor and functioned as a countervailing force to the

empire and the territorial lords. Its very formation without imperial sanction was an act of defiance against the efforts of Emperor

Charles IV to assert centralized control over the German cities,

hence its articles of agreement have a markedly defensive tone.

But it functioned very much like the Rhenish League. By the

1380s, the confederacy forced the princes into temporary submission and, in combination with the League of the Rhine, which it

structurally resembled, formed one of Europe’s greatest urban

confederacies.

The emergence of the celebrated Swiss Confederation or

“Switzering anarchists” as Cromwell’s supporters were to call it

centuries later, must be seen as an extension of the Rhenish and

Swabian leagues, not an anomaly that stands at odds with the

supposedly parochial traits imputed to European cities and their

leagues. Switzerland was formed out of a milieu and modelled

after examples that existed in central Europe as a whole.[9] The

Swiss confederation, far from being an almost lonely “exception”

to the confederal trends that existed in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, was actually a product of them. That the creation

of nation-states was to be so greatly delayed in Germany and Italy

is due in great measure to the obstacles that the cities, their

confederacies, and later the powerful impact of their traditions of

autonomy and freedom exercised on political life as a whole. It was

not localist “pettiness” and “parochialism” that kept central and

southern Europe from achieving nationhood until well into the

nineteenth century. Rather, the “delay” was in great measure the

product of a strong tradition of municipal autonomy and a dramatic history of resistance to centralization, however perverted

this history became in later times. The Hanseatic League’s Diet,

the *StĂ€dtetag* of the Rhenish League, and autonomous confederal’

bodies elsewhere in Europe haunt the history of the continent like

the unexorcised spirit of a more active public life and a vital civic

politics. That the nation-state eventually did unite the laggard

principalities of Germany, Italy, and, as we shall see, Spain into

centralized states was not quite the happy dispensation it seemed

to be at the turn of the present century, when nationhood was

regarded as evidence of “modernity” and “progress.” Viewed

with hindsight, the images of Mussolini, Hitler, and Franco rise up

to remind us that the ideological celebration of the nation-state,

which marked social theory during the Victorian era, was grossly

misplaced. We of a later generation have good reason to lament

the loss of the confederal alternative that appeared at an earlier

epoch in Europe, one that might have averted the terrifying turn

“national unity” took between 1914 and 1945.

[9] Hence my strong objections to the way European, particularly German, city

confederacies are treated in the mainstream historical literature of the time, particularly by Toynbee and Mumford. In this respect, Kropotkin’s writings are still

exceptional for their sympathy, although they are not given sufficient attention in

his work.

Confederalism was not merely an intuitive civic reaction to the

feudal parochialism that marked so much of the medieval world

at the time. There were theoretical not only practical considerations that were to surface almost simultaneously in two charismatic figures of western Europe. Heraldic rebels such as Cola di

Rienzi in Rome and Etienne Marcel in Paris, contemporaries during the mid-fourteenth century, were to formulate the numerous

moves toward confederal unity in very dramatic form. Rienzi’s

efforts to restore a new Roman republic evoke images of the Gracchi and their efforts to restore Rome’s traditional republican virtues. His attacks on the venal nobility of papal Rome and his efforts

to create a citizens’ militia were apparently part of a larger effort

to unite Italy into civic leagues under Rome’s suzereinty. Present-day historians tend to depict Rienzi as a forerunner of Italian

nationalism when they are not occupied with defaming him as a

“demagogue” with strictly self-serving intentions. The greater

likelihood is that he was a strident leader of Italian confederalism.

As a self-styled “Tribune of the People,” a title redolent of the

Gracchi rather than a Cincinnatus, Rienzi’s “parliament” was to

be made up of delegates from Italian cities, not peninsular “provinces” that had yet to come into being. This effort was to be

aborted when the papacy and nobility allied with each other,

ultimately leading to his murder in 1354.

Etienne Marcel emerges from this stormy era in a far more

favorable light. A “provost of the merchants” and economically

well-to-do in his own right, Marcel was clearly a popular leader of

the “Third Estate” in Paris whose efforts to enlarge the powers of

the **Estates Generale** at the expense of the monarchy and nobility

and make royal taxes more equitable developed into a wider challenge to absolutism and aristocratic power. Marcel’s own goals, in

fact, were probably more “bourgeois,” possibly even more “republican,” than his own order would have been prepared to accept. Like Rienzi, he was to enjoy immense support until a royalist

faction within the middle class itself assassinated him in 1358. The

tendency of nineteenth- and twentieth-century historians to read

a “nation-state” mentality into men who lived in an era guided

largely by feudal or confederal visions of political life is misleading.

Underlying this bias is the: myth that Europe’s “bourgeoisie” was

initially republican and basically nationalist in its convictions.

Rierizi and Marcel rose to prominence because they spoke for

artisans and the urban poor as well as merchant and professional

strata, many of whom sided with the nobility against the ordinary

people of Europe’s cities. Perez Zagorin seems to be much closer

to the truth when be observes, “Grievances born of unfavorable

<em>conjoncture</em> and wretched conditions underlay the popular upsurge, whereas Marcel himself was a revolutionary reformer who

wanted to build an alliance of towns, strengthen the Estates General, and fasten political limitations on the monarchy. His movement also established some slight ties with the Jacquerie, the big

peasant revolt that had broken out at the same time in the Ile-de-France and surrounding region.”{61} This judgement speaks to a

confederal outlook, one that was more in tune with the period

than a “nationalist” vision of a centralized France.

Zagorin’s reference to the Jacquerie reminds us that the period

faced a series of major peasant tumults—not only in France but

throughout western Europe. The English Peasant Rebellion of

1381, which followed the French *Jacquerie* by less than three

decades, formed a high point in the restive village upsurges that

finally led to the brief seizure of London by a peasant army. John

Ball, an itinerant priest who’ was to color the rebellion with powerful declamations against social and economic inequality, gave the

rising a larger-than-life image. Actually, the peasantry tended to

rise in the aftermath of wartime ravages of the countryside or

unpredictably in isolated pockets against feudal exactations, royal

taxes, excessive “tithes,” upper-class highhandedness. To detail

these uprisings would be impossible. Occasionally, they managed

to cojoin with urban unrest into full-scale rebellions and to pose

serious challenges to provincial and central authorities. Whether

this connection was well-established—as was the case in the

Hussite Wars of Bohemia during the fifteenth century—or assumed an emphemeral character, agrarian unrest became endemic throughout the centuries that followed and persists to this

day in the Third World.

Ordinarily, peasant revolts were short-lived and fragmented.

The climax of these uprisings in western Europe was to emerge

from the Lutheran Reformation of the 1520s, when the cities and

countryside of Germany were thrown into years of persistent unrest. Between 1524 and 1526, German peasants rose on a mass

scale; sweeping over large areas of the western and southern parts

of the country and entering into historical annals as the famous

“Peasants’ War.” Presumably, this was regarded as a “revolution”

by chroniclers, who were eager to distinguish it from the many

“rebellions” that exploded sporadically in the countryside from

medieval times to the Enlightenment. The medley of ideologies,

sentiments, and interests that are imputed to the German peasant

uprising has endeared it to Marxists, liberals, romantics, theologians, and nationalists alike. It has been variously’ seen as a precursor of modern communistic movements, a striking example bf

class war, an effort at moral regeneration, even as a forerunner of

the German nation-state or a force that shaped’ its development.

Most of these appraisals do not give sufficient emphasis to the

deep-seated communitarian impulses that moved the peasants to

action: their attempts to preserve the rural **Gemeinde** from fern

dal, commercial, and clerical encroachment. If there is any unifying drama to the upheaval, it is the peasantry’s effort to preserve

its organic communal ties, its traditional village universe that encompassed time-honored values, institutions, and lifeways as well

as landholdings that were challenged by princely and baronial

encroachments. It is this universe, so much of a piece with the

civic values of traditional society as such, that makes the Peasants’

War of 1524–26 so fascinating to theorists and historians of municipal development.

The fortunes of this conflict, with all their varied interpretations,

have been explored extensively enough to require no detailed

treatment here. Thomas Munzer’s legendary “communist” tenets

of the time probably articulated the peasantry’s commitment to its

traditional networks of mutual aid, its timeless visions of a “golden

age” based on equality, its precarious reality of collective management of land and goods that marked the **Gemeinde**—all village-based traditions rather than “anticipations” of socialist and communist theories that appropriately stem from a sophisticated

industrial society rather than an old agrarian one. To the romantics

who found in the peasantry the embodiment of a German *ethnos*,

the conflict offers no inspiring myths of a united people motivated

by a sense of blood and soil. The Peasants’ War was as fragmented as

the society from which it stemmed. Only once do we hear of a really

earnest effort to bring what were separate uprisings into a unified

struggle. A “peasant parliament” was convened at Memmingen to

form a “Christian Union of the Peasants” and coordinate the peasant armies of Upper Swabia. The union brought together the three

completely replicated the administration of the peasant village.

The village form, in effect, was projected onto the shared command

structure of the mili tary forces, mirroring the traditional society

that it was meant to preserve.

The Memmingen “parliament” also formulated and adopted

the famous “Twelve Articles” of the peasant revolt, a program

worded in terms of scriptural authority. The articles “humbly”

petition the secular authorities for the right of the villages to

choose and depose their own pastors, to fix their own “tithes”

according to the needs of the pastor and the poor of the community, to abolish serfdom, diminish corvee labor, reduce feudal dues

and rents, and, finally, to restore all enclosed common land to the

village and end further enclosures definitively. Allowing for many

local variations, the Memmingen Articles became the basic program of the rebellious German peasantry and was soon the most

widely circulated document of the war. Given its tone of humility,

recourse to scriptural legitimacy, and humane demands, it completely expressed the spirit and values of the **Gemeinde**, It was the

voice of a traditional village world by which the municipal life of

the era was nourished and from which it drew its vitality. Herein

lies the real continuity of the articles with German civic life: its

strong solidarity as an ethical covenant.

The German princes were to unite and crush the Peasants’ War

in a terrible bloodbath. Although city support of the peasants was

very widespread, it was often qualified and prone toward compromise. The Twelve Articles resonated with the urban poor and

lower classes, and its moral tone and appeals to scripture won it

considerable clerical support. The almost evangelical nature of the

uprising gave it the qualities of a crusade for human rights and

decency, traits that were not lost on many of the educated strata

of the cities. Despite its radical rhetoric, Frederick Engels’s appraisal of the Peasants’ War is pervaded by all the prejudices of the

last century. The war’s “chief result,” we are told, was the

“strengthening of German decentralization which, in turn, was

the “cause of [the war’s] failure.”{62} One is disposed to ask if victory

by the peasants would have yielded a “centralization” of Germany

that would have overcome the fragmentation created by the German princes. Accordingly, the Peasants’ War was either a “revolution,” as Engels claimed, or a crude anachronism as he should have

claimed by his own standards of “historical materialism,” in which

case it belonged not to the truly “revolutionary tradition” of Germany but to a “reactionary” one. His appraisal becomes all the

more entangled when he rejects confederacy as a valid solution to

Germany’s problems, a solution that the peasants intuitively seem

to have desired. This problem is not an academic one. It raises the

crucial question of whether or not seemingly “undeveloped” peoples today are to achieve what we so flippantly call “modernization”—by confederalism or nationalism, decentralism or centralism, libertarian institutions or authoritarian ones. We have not

removed these questions from the future of our civilization nor

can they be concealed from purview by the veil of history. If

anything, hindsight has made them as searing today as they were

in earlier times, when the terrifying future that now looms before

us was very far removed from the eyes of men and women in the

sixteenth century.

This much must be emphasized: the attempts to create a nation-state in western Europe four centuries ago did not occur

without considerable resistance from the free cities of the era,

rebellious villages, and aroused artisans, not only recalcitrant nobles. The sixteenth century, which was decisive in the rise of

European absolutism and ultimately nationalism, bears witness to

a veritable deluge of village, provincial, and urban uprisings. Even

England was not spared from dramatic agrarian unrest: Kett’s

Rebellion of 1549, while more of a mass protest against land enclosures than a revolutionary challenge to royal authority, required

the use of thousands of troops before it could be subdued. In

France, the rebellion was followed by the rising of the *Croquants*

between 1592 and 1595, a struggle more redolent of German

demands for village autonomy than the English one. Such revolts,

generally localized and easily subdued, were to become endemic

as France passed deeper into absolutism and ultimately revolution. Indeed, it was not until the Napoleonic Era that they came

to a definitive end, and a once rebellious peasantry was turned into

a conservative pillar of the Bonapartist monarchy.

None of these rebellions produced confederations or developed

into serious challenges to the emerging nation-states of the West.

The civic roots of the English Revolution have rarely been appraised from a municipal viewpoint, although the revolution that

began in England in the 1640s was to find a remarkably democratic fulfillment in the townships of New England. (This is a

development we must reserve for a later and fuller discussion.)

The Great French Revolution, in turn, was to evoke the ideal of

communal confederation without giving it permanent reality. Indeed, the Jacobin “dictatorship,” if such it can be called, was to

turn France into one of the most centralized nation-states in

Europe. But the ideal did not die. Later, it acquired a brief and

glowing moment of reality in the subsequent Paris Commune of

1871, a commune or “city council” that called upon all the cities

of France to join’it in a huge civic confederation—only to be

crushed in bloody fighting with troops of the Third Republic after

some two months of existence. With magnificant stubbornness,

the Paris Commune of the nineteenth century had tried to bring

to life what its predecessor of the eighteenth century had entertained in its conflict with the Jacobin-controlled Convention during the last years of the Great Revolution.

Ironically, the most serious threat to absolutism and the nationstate by a confederation of municipalities was to emerge during

the sixteenth century in a country where absolutism seemed virtually triumphant: Spain under the rule of Europe’s sternest and

politically least yielding monarch, Charles V. The period directly

preceding the final subjugation of the Moors in 1492 was marked

by a remarkable burgeoning of city life and the consolidation of

Spanish absolutism under the Catholic monarchs, Ferdinand and Isabella. Spain’s prosperity and its movement toward a nation-state seem like an almost textbook example of collaboration between a monarchy and an urban “bourgeoisie.” That monarchy

and city could have eventually entered into conflict with each

other would have seemed inconceivable at the time if it did not

actually happen. Isabella, following an active policy of fostering

city life and playing urban strata against landed magnates, promoted internal commerce, scrupulously respected municipal

rights, and worked closely with the Spanish *Cortes*, the country’s

“parliament.” This policy was intended to develop institutions and

forces countervailing the rapacious Spanish territorial lords. The

gilds, long the objects of royal hostility, were permitted to extend

their ordinances and confirmed in their Tights to control production operations. The ‘‘crusade” against the Moors was shrewdly

used to increase popular enthusiasm for the monarchy, indeed to

give it a centrality in Spanish life and religion that, it had never

enjoyed. The image of a morally regenerated Christian Spain

evoked hopes of a stable, unified, and powerful nation whose restive nobility and centrifugal regionalism had to be brought under rigorous control.

This image was translated into a certain measure of fact, especially in Castile, the Spanish heartland. Castile formed the bulwark of the newly emerging nation, the source of its prevailing

dialect, its manners, and the “prototypic” Spanish character,

which held such linguistically, ethnically, and culturally disparate

“Spains” as the Basques, Catalans, and largely Moorish Andalusians together. Here, tod, the monarchy in later years was to

choose its future capital, Madrid, and turn the city into the administrative center of the country as a whole. This state machinery

was one of the most sophisticated in Europe. At the same time, the

Catholic kings began to shore up their relationship with the cities,

deflecting urban hostility from the monarchy to the nobility and

drawing upon urban wealth to consolidate royal rule, Ferdinand

and Isabella enlarged their bureaucratic control over the independent cities of the province. The *corregidores* or town officials of the

crown were given extended powers to bring the urban noble clans

under control and protect the cities from landed magnates who

exploited them.. Municipal land that the magnates had illegally

seized were restored in some measure; tax farmers, whose actions

verged on outright plunder, were replaced by the *encabezamiento* system in which the main tax, the *alcabala*, was

collected by local officials; the Royal Council was staffed by university trained lawyers, the *letrados*, and a supervisory hierarchy of

officials to oversee the burgeoning bureaucracy from secretaries to

A centralized and professional judiciary, together with various

councils of brotherhoods, the Inquisition, and the *Cortes* itself

balanced out a bureaucracy and provided for close royal supervision of nearly all aspects of Spanish life.

This machinery, partly traditional and partly new, was destined

to have a very limited life span. Although the French monarchy

was to install a similar one that lasted for some two centuries, the

Spanish state machinery began to weaken appreciably even during the reign of the Catholic monarchs. The final struggle against

the Moors essentially brought the conflict between the monarchy

and nobility to an end. Despite her fears of the landed magnates,

Isabella was obliged to use them militarily to complete the reconquest, and the magnates claimed their full rewards for supporting

the state. Increasingly, the lost municipal lands were recovered by

the aristocracy, their taxing powers were increased, their abilities

to sidestep disagreeable court decisions were enhanced, and their

financial control of the monarchy increased immensely. When in

1519 Charles V became king of Spain as Carlos I and entered his

claim to the throne of the Holy Roman Empire, the monarchy was

largely under aristocratic control. Born and raised in Flanders,

Charles quickly earned the mistrust of his Spanish subjects as a

foreigner whose principal concerns were his own imperial ambitions and who lived mainly abroad to advance them. Virtually all

strata of Castilian society viewed the newly installed king as a man

who regarded Spain as a resource for his squabbles abroad, freely

bilking the country of its wealth.

To exacerbate matters still further, the central administrative

apparatus was all but taken over by a coterie of Flemish advisors

that was notable for its insensitivity to Spanish traditions and interests. Inept and clumsy, Charles’s Flemish surrogates turned the

monarchy into a parasitic entity in which the aristocracy was the

main beneficiary of the new dispensation. Increasing taxes, a grave

decline in the honesty and effectiveness of the *corregidores*, a

breakdown in the road system that led to higher, often unbearable

financial levies on impoverished village and town populations, a

failure by inept or corrupt supervisory officials to discharge their

responsibilities in controlling the bureaucracy and aristocracy, a

decline in the integrity of the court system, a military system that

quartered ill-paid and unruly troops with an increasingly impoverished population—all, well underway before Charles became king,

were exacerbated by alien rulers, a suspect monarch, the declining prestige of the royal power, and the growing encroachments of a self-serving aristocracy.

On May 30,1520, a crowd of woolworkers seized a hated member of Segovia’s *Cortes* delegation and hanged him, leading to a

revolt in the city that forced all its royal officials to take to their

heels. This seemingly local act of crowd violence was to unleash

one of history’s most extraordinary municipal “revolutions,” as

many historians call it, the rising of the ***Comuneros*** (literally translated as Communards). Although this *comunidad* or community

revolt was fairly short-lived, it is outstanding for its institutional

creativity. The action of the woolworkers in Segovia pales before

the more serious rebellion that developed when Toledo’s city

council, challenging an unfavorable change in royal tax policy,

wrote to all the cities represented in the *Cortes* and defiantly

called upon them to establish a common front against the royal

government. What may have appeared like one of many urban tax

revolts that marked the whole period soon turned into a full-scale

revolution. Within months, city after city in Castile began to collect and impound all taxes collected for the monarchy. Civic militias were organized, and far-reaching changes were introduced

to democratize and enhance the autonomy of municipal governments. On Toledo’s suggestion, a national junta was established

with delegates from all the *Cortes* cities. The **Comuneros**, in effect,

had established a parallel or “dual” power in opposition to the

prevailing royal administration.

Early reactions to this development ranged from the enthusiastic to the tolerant. Even the landed magnates, ever mindful of an

opportunity to gain from any diminution of the central government, placed a tactful distance between themselves and the monarchy. By mustering an impressive army of citizens with an infrastructure and added detachments of professional soldiers, the

threatened to replace the entire royal state with a municipal

confederation. The **Comuneros** had created their own military

system, an administrative apparatus that reached deeply into most

of Castile’s social order, tax resources, and a tremendous reservoir

of popular goodwill, cutting across seemingly insurmountable

“class” barriers (including clerical ones) that seemed irresistible in

the early months of the **junta**’s existence.

What brought this movement to an end in April 1521 when its

last major field detachments were defeated, near the village of

Villalar? Toledo, it should noted, held out against royalist forces

until February 1522, and other cities tried to resist after the battle

of Villalar. Perhaps the most strategic military fact was the swing

of the nobility from a generally neutral position over to the monarchy. No less important was the support that the royalists slowly

acquired from the city elites—the knights or *Caballeros* who lived

in urban areas, well-to-do merchants, the higher clergy, and generally more prosperous strata, who were alienated by the radicalization and democratization of civic life. The **Comuneros**, like their

heirs centuries later in Paris, were stridently urban in outlook and

retained a basic hostility to the peasantry (who actually were their

natural allies) as a class controlled by the nobles. Finally, the

<em>Comuneros</em> could not extend their movement beyond the center

of Spain. Viewed as Castilians by the other “Spains” that surrounded them, the movement was seen as the work of a privileged

population that had revolted against its even more privileged

overlords. The Catalans, Basques, and Andalusians, to cite the

most well-known regions hostile to Castilian hegemony, could not

be brought to identify with a Castilian cause, however much the

<em>Comuneros</em> solicited their support

It is easy in view of these reasons to see the revolt of the

<em>Comunidades</em> as a strictly “class” movement, to speak of it variously as “atavistic” because it posed a mere municipal challenge

to a seemingly “progressive” nation-state or to regard it as a conflict of interests between vague, indefinable class strata: nobles, a

“bourgeoisie,” a “nascent proletariat,” and the like. The term

“nascent” is what makes such a “class analysis” questionable. Of

all the clearly definable “classes” that were to play a major role in

later Spanish history—apart from Spain’s enduring peasantry-only the landed magnates survived the era as a cohesiye stratum

and were to carry on intact until recent times. The others are

more properly “orders” in their indefinability, that is, in their

paucity of economic roots, their wavering stability as social groups,

and the murkiness of their concerns. What we have here is a

typical, quasifeudal “Third Estate,” ranging from well-to-do, even

wealthy, strata to an amorphous mass of artisans, merchants, “intellectuals” of various sorts, clerks, and clerics, to which we may

add a considerable number of servants, laborers, and beggars. This

“Third Estate” was united by its urbanity, literally by a shared

culture as town dwellers. Despite the many material differences

that were to separate them, either they were citizens Of a particular city or they aspired to be. Their ideological unity came from

the primary loyalty that the city claimed and from the political

arena it created. It was the city, not their “class,” that evoked in

them a real feeling of place, a meaningful commitment of service,

and a clear sense of self-definition. This collective loyalty to a

dwellers during that era, is difficult to convey today when nationalism has invaded all public sentiments of local loyalty. In the sixteenth century it was intense enough to impart an alien, almost

exogenous, quality to the central power and to focus one’s devotion on the village, town, or city in which one lived rather than the still-emerging nation-state.

Nowadays, we would be inclined to believe that such varied

economic groups would be in chronic conflict with each other, a

conclusion that seems to be supported by the internal conflicts

that engulfed many cities of Europe, particularly the Flemish and

Italian ones. Actually, this is a very one-sided picture of urban fife

in the past. It is easy for historians to forget how readily disparate

strata in a city united against invaders or other city rivals, despite

their divergent economic interests. In fact, it would be hard to

understand why the **Comuneros** could unite in the first place,

given the disparities in wealth and social position that existed in

their cities, and why a strong sense of unity existed to the very last,

even after urban elites began to fall away from their movement.

Their royalist opponents did not win all the well-to-do strata of the

Castilian cities; in fact, there was resistance to the very end, especially in Toledo, which held out against royalist opponents for

nearly a year after the battle of Villalar. What the royalists succeeded in achieving was enough of a division between these strata

to tip the balance in their favor and bring the greater military

prowess of the aristocracy into an advantageous position over relatively inexperienced civic militias.

What the **Comuneros** really achieved has yet to be fully grasped

by some of its historians. The movement opened civic life on a

scale that had rarely been seen in Europe since Hellenic times. It

expanded the very meaning of the word “politics,” not only at a

confederal, city, or town level but at a neighborhood or parish

level. *Comunero* demands were strikingly radical even for our

day: a *Cortes*, composed of city delegations, which would greatly

limit royal authority, and a municipal democracy whose extent

varied from one city to another. In a group of articles formulated

in Valladolid, the **Comuneros** demanded that delegates for the

Cortes be chosen with the consent of parish assemblies instead of

city councils, the practice followed by the monarchy. These delegates in turn were to be guided by the mandate of their electors

and were to acquire the right to consult with their cities if their

instructions did not adequately cover the problems that surfaced

at the Cortes, a right that the monarchy had consistently denied

city delegates to the parliamentary body. Had these demands

been realized, Spain would have seen the emergence of a broadly

based local democracy, one deeply rooted in city neighborhoods

as well as municipalities. Such a democracy, in fact, went far beyond radical conceptions of political representation. They were an

open invitation to revitalize the entire public sphere, opening it

to all strata of the population and advanced urban concepts of

citizenship that were all-inclusive and completely grass-roots in

character. In cities such as Toledo and Valladolid, this neighborhood democracy was not merely a demand; it became a working

reality, one that was rarely to be achieved again until the rise of

the Parisian sectional movement in the Great French Revolution.

Many *Comunero* demands constituted a sixteenth-century “Bill

of Rights.” The *Cortes* was to meet regularly and all the grievances

of the **Comunidades** were to be addressed before it could terminate its proceedings. The **Comuneros**, of course, called for the

protection of property from legal confiscation except in cases of

treason; freedom from harsh punishment in criminal cases; limits

on the quartering of visiting royalty; prohibition of the sale of

public offices; reforms of judicial and appeals procedures; and the

complete “Castilianization” of the court, which Charles had filled

with aliens who knew very little about Spanish problems. The

demands contained a strong, basically egalitarian appeal for choosing officials according to their personal merit, professional qualifications, and moral probity rather than for their status and social

background.

Charles’s victory over the **Comuneros** signalled the triumph in

Spain of statecraft over politics, of the nation-state over confederalism. It was a victory that was attained primarily by the force of

arms, not by a hidden logic of history. The struggle of the **Comunidades** with the monarchy—it was never a struggle against monarchism as such although it came very close at times to a challenge

of monarchical rule in its sixteenth-century form—had been

preceded by similar conflicts between city leagues or confederacies almost everywhere on the European continent. It was to be

followed by greater or lesser struggles of a similar nature after

nation-states had been well-established. If Spain, one of Europe’s

strongest absolute monarchies in the sixteenth century, is singled

out for study, the *Comunero* movement did not establish a tradition that an “ascending” bourgeoisie could claim for itself. Quite

to the contrary: the **Comuneros** found a later, albeit highly

modified, expression in Pi y Margall’s Federalist movement of the

late nineteenth century, which distinctly resisted state centralization, and finally in the largest anarchist movement in Europe.

Charles V did nothing to foster a capitalist society. Indeed,

absolutism became a lethal cancer in a once prosperous country

that was devitalized by massive state expenditures for imperial

adventures abroad. The *Comunero* movement, by contrast, tried

to rein this monarchy and ultimately drastically diminish its power.

Its failure was followed over a period of time by an incredible

decline of Spanish economic and urban life. Cities sank into lethargy, agriculture stagnated under the rule and mismanagement of

the magnates, roads were permitted to decay, and the wealth of the

country was vastly diminished. On the other hand, the Industrial

Revolution in Europe, which presumably dates the ascendancy of

urban capitalism over traditional society, did not foster a city development in Spain that was wholesome or vital. It did not revive

community life; rather, it replaced what remained of community

with urbanization, anomie, and, under Francisco Franco, with a

ferociously terrorist regime that has variously been called “nationalist” by its admirers and “fascist” by its opponents. Whether or not

the two terms actually reveal the convergence of a development

that was to yield centralized authority in its most brutal forms is a

problem that we have yet to resolve in our own time.

That there is a logic in certain historical premises, one that

unf olds more as a tendency than a necessity, is certainly not arguable: nationalism does foster totalitarianism, and the centralized

state tends to develop into an all-embracing state. But it is certainly difficult to argue, that a suprahuman phenomenon called

“history” exists and predetermines a society’s development. The

<em>Comuneros</em> had opened a pathway to a cooperative, unified Spain

that could have yielded a very different dispensation from that

which came with a centralized nation-state. So, too, had earlier

city confederacies, whose achievements meet with so much disdain. Politics had to be structured around a community of one kind

or another, whether as a **polis, Gemeinde, burg, commune,** or city.

Lacking the flesh and blood of politically involved people and

comprehensible self-governing institutions, the human phenomenon we call “society” tends to disintegrate at its base, even as it seems to consolidate at its apex.

Centralization becomes most acute when deterioration occurs

at the base of society. Divested of its culture as a political realm,

society becomes an ensemble of bureaucratic agencies that bind

monadic individuals and family units into a strictly administrative

structure or a form of “possessive,” more properly acquisitive,

individualism that leads to privitization of the self and its disintigration into mere egoism. The city, in turn, is no longer united by

any sort of ethical bond. It becomes a marketplace, a destructured

and formless economic unit, a realm in which the Hobbesian war

of “all against all” becomes a virtual reality, ironically designated

as a “return to nature.”

Such a condition and the mentality it produces constitute a

dissolution of nature and society’s evolutionary thrust toward diversity, complexity, and community, a problem that appropriately

belongs to the newly developing field and philosophy of social

ecology rather than urban sociology. It is a social problem because

we are talking about one of the most elemental forms of human

consociation—the city—where people advance beyond the kinship bond to share, create, and develop the means of life, culturally as well as economically, as human beings. Here, **humanitas** as

distinguished from the “folk” comes into its own. And it is an

ecological problem in the sense that diversity, variety, and participation constitute not only the basis for the stability of human

consociation but also for the creativity that is imparted to us by

diversity, indeed, ultimately, the freedom that alternative forms

of development allow for the evolution of new, richer, and well-rounded social forms.

Urbanization, which I see as the dissolution of the city’s wealth

of variety and as a force that makes for municipal homogeneity

and formlessness, is a threat to the stability, fecundity, and freedom that the city added to the social landscape. A critical analysis

of how urbanization emerged, its genesis partly in the nation-state,

partly in industrialism, and generally with the onset of capitalistic

forms of production and distribution—all examined from the

viewpoint of social ecology—is a problem of crucial importance for

our time, indeed one that will help us define the future of the city,

politics, and, above all, citizenship.

Chapter Seven: The Social Ecology of Urbanization

From the sixteenth century onward, Europe was the stage for a

drama unique in history: the development of nation-states and

national cultures in which populations tended to identify with

what we, today, accept as a commonplace—a sense of personal

nationality. Even the notion of citizenship, long-rooted in loyalty

to a city and the public body that occupied it, began to shift toward

a large territorial entity, the “nation,” and to its “capital” city.

Politics, too, began to acquire a new definition. It increasingly

denoted the professionalization of power with roots in the state

and its institutions.

We would be gravely mistaken to assume that these changes

and redefinitions occurred within the span of a few centuries or

that they have been completed even in our own time. The development toward nationalism was slow, uneven, and very mixed.

Nor is it secure in its major European centers. There is a strong

human proclivity, reaching back to the socialization process itself

and familial care, that identifies “homeland” with home rather

than nationalist abstractions, hence even the most consolidated

nation-states are more divided internally than nationalist myths

would have us believe. For example, the intense domestic conflicts

that beleaguer the United States—notably between ethnic groups,

regions, and even localities, not to speak of economic classes and

interests—are testimony to the hold of specific cultural and territorial identities among populations, even those that belong to

highly nationalistic “superpowers.” These divisions are more

strongly evident in modern Russia.

Nationalism exercises its strongest power over the popular

imagination in oppositional ways when a nation is in some sense

under attack. As an internally cohesive fdrce, it has always been

fragile. The success of National Socialism in “unifying” the German people has deeper roots in German history than in a sense of

national allegiance, a history that is notable for the tragic decline

of German social life after the Reformation and the need for compensatory mechanisms to counteract the slump that marked that

bloody and ennervating period.

But how did these nation-states come into existence? What role

did European cities play in forming them? And what began to

happen to cities—and with them, politics and citizenship—when

the nation-state asserted its sovereignty over public fife?

We have seen that nationalism existed only in an incipient form

in the ancient world where, with few exceptions, people psychologically and culturally identified themselves with their villages,

towns, cities, and immediate territorial area. Classical antiquity

was mainly an era of empire building, not of nation building, and

ancient imperialism took a very special form. It was patrimonial,

not strictly political; its center was the royal household, not a

capital in any nationalist sense. If “all roads lead to Rome,” it is not

because Rome; was, a city that commanded a high degree of national loyalty but’rather because it was the hub of ancient power

and order. Its centrality was derived from its administrative significance, not, as is the case with Jerusalem, its symbolic significance. Indeed, insofar as Rome was symbolic of anything, it was

seen as a symbol of oppression. Crucifixion, a mode of punishment

normally reserved for rebels and intransigent slaves, imparted to

the cross a symbolic meaning not unlike that which was attached

to the Nazi swastika during the World War II. The adoption of this

symbol by the Church instead of the fish, which early Christians

used as an expression of plentitude and conversion, reflected the

accommodation of the heavenly city to the worldly city—Rome—and of a rebellious creed to the institutions it originally opposed.

Rome, once the whore of the world; to the early Christians became the holy city of the papacy and acquired a spiritual status in

the very act of seducing its most intransigent rebels, a lesson in

statecraft that far too many rebels have failed to learn.

Medieval Europe did, not have nations at all. Loyalties were

mainly localist in character, notably to one’s, village, parish, town,

city, barons, and rather tenuously to one’s monarch. Strong kings

such as Henry II of England and Philip Augustus of France had an

unusual amount of power for their times and, by their innovations

as well as their actions, exercised a great deal of authority over

their barons and clerics. More often than not, however, tlieir heirs

were weaklings and royal authority was easily subverted by feudal

lords until another strong monarch surfaced and managed to centralize power for a brief period of time. Personal authority and the

forcefulness of a monarch’s character created the illusion of a

nation-state, but it was still along patrimonial lines. The association

of the monarch with the “nation,” such as it was, was so close that

“nationalism” in the Middle Ages rarely survived the person of the

king. The wide swings in royal authority that we encounter in

European feudalism stem from the tenuous basis of centralized

authority as such in the ancient arid medieval worlds. Centralized

power was limited by the hard facts of a primitive communications system and a largely Neolithic technology. Armies and officials could move no faster than horses; roads were very poor, often

almost trackless; and weaponry had barely emerged from the

Bronze Age. The simple fact that obedience depended heavily

upon personal ties and a reasonable modicum of fear of a resolute

king resulted in a loosely hanging political system based on individual’ commitments and the use of brutal punitive measures. The

times were cruel rather than barbarous because of the nature of

statecraft in a world where authority was extremely fragile and

punishment took a very harsh form in order to sustain monarchical

and baronial power.

The one institution that commanded widespread allegiance beyond that which any monarch could hope to achieve was the

Roman Church and the papacy. Shaped over centuries into a vast

hierarchical bureaucracy, the Catholic Church eventually became

the most unifying and certainly the most centralized apparatus in

western Europe. It could reach into villages with an effectiveness

that was the envy of any royal authority, and its command of

resources had no precedent on the continent. I refer not only to

its enormous wealth and landholdings but also to its spiritual

power—ultimately the power of excommunication and interdiction that brought even emperors such as Frederick Barbarossa to their knees.

Yet here one encounters a paradox to which J. R. Strayer gives

deserved emphasis.{63} The papacy as early as the eleventh century,

during the time of Gregory VII, was an empire unto itself. More

important than its centralized institutional structure is the compelling fact that it was an elaborate state: a vast apparatus not only

with its black-robed bureaucracy but a system of law and a juridical machinery adequate enough to make its legal sovereignty

effective. The emergence of ecclesiastical law served to open a

crucial area for the development of secular law. In the great division of power that Gregory VII created between church and state,

the latter essentially disentangled itself from the former. Secular

law, rarely free in the past of ecclesiastical influence and priestly

functionaries, could now come completely into its own. In the

very act of charting and firming up its own authority, the Church

created an ever-growing space for the expansion of the state and

for a largely nonreligious form of statecraft that no longer required supernatural sanction and legitimation. However much

monarchs were to claim divine right to support their authority,

their rights were divine, not their origins—origins that even the

Roman Caesars claimed. Hence, like all rights, they could be challenged even on religious grounds by the church, the barons, and

later by the people. Rights are always subject to rational evaluation and legitimate defiance, a problem that monarchs such as

Charles I of England and Louis XVI of France were to face before

accusing regicides. That the Church, too, by claiming a legal domain of its own, was to pay a heavy penalty by being removed later

on from every sphere other than its spiritual authority is a part of

history that adds a dimension of irony and paradox to all assertions

of power—the paradoxical reality of history’s own dialectical process.

The great division between state and church, monarch and

pope, secular and divine can be taken as a symbolic expression for

the many divisions that riddled medieval society and made the

nation-state possible. Had medieval society been entirely unitary,

it might very well have been blanketed by large, suffocating, patrimonial empires that would have drained its resources and diverted it into a relatively stagnant dead end. Ironically, it was the

fragmentation of the European world that made its unification

into several nation-states possible. In contrast to empires, nations

are relatively self-contained; their existence, at least between the

sixteenth and eighteenth centuries, was possible only because empire building by one state was blocked by the power of another.

Nation building, in effect, occurred not only because monarchs

accumulated sufficient power to establish a central authority in

parts of western Europe but also because their ability to extend

that power beyond a region was arrested by countervailing powers external to them. Charles V’s efforts to create an empire in the

sixteenth century failed because other states acquired enough

power to successfully resist him and his son, Philip II. The successful revolt of the Netherlands and the defeat of the Spanish Armada

by England ended any serious attempt to create an empire within

Europe up to our own time, despite the Napoleonic wars and

Germany’s expansion from 1940 to 1945. Nation-states and nationalism have vitiated all efforts to create empires on the continent,

at least by direct means. Russian expansion toward the west, seemingly vigorous after 1945, has visibly begun to ebb. American

power in Europe, although rarely exercised in a direct manner,

stands at odds with its strongly republican institutions.

This external system of “checks and balances” that medieval

Europe produced on a continental level has its parallel in an internal system of “checks and balances” that existed on a domestic

level. The intercity trade that provided economic underpinnings

to the formation of nation-states repeatedly came up against

strong localist barriers—artisan gilds, relatively self-sufficient village economies, popular hostility to trade that formed the legacy

of medieval Christianity, and a very strong individual desire, particularly among craftsmen and free peasants, to live directly by

their own skills and on their own property with minimal commercial intercourse—a state of mind we would call “self-sufficiency,”

today, which has its roots in the Greek concept of *autarkeia*. Nor

can we ignore the immense hold of the **Gemeinde**, the local community, on. the minds of people during that period, a sense of

communal loyalty that was reinforced not only by cultural bonds

but by a tradition of communal land ownership and mutual aid.

The considerable attention that recent economic historians

have given to the role of foreign trade in producing a capitalistic

society and the nation-state is somewhat ingenuous. That the earliest forms of capitalism in the ancient as well as medieval worlds

were commercial and that port and riverine cities often enriched

themselves enormously, promoting a domestic market for goods

acquired abroad, does not remove the need for a balanced perspective toward the reach this economy had into the depths of

emerging European, nations. Owing to the poor condition of the

roads that existed in Europe, the cost of commodities brought

from abroad rose enormously as they moved inland. A cartload of

hay priced at 600 denari during Diocletian’s time increased by 20

denari every mile so that the cost of transporting it as little as 30

miles rendered its sale in a nearby market prohibitive. Unless a

good network of waterways existed, foreign trade had a limited

economic impact on the interior of a region. Generally, the commodities that passed from port and riverine cities to inland towns

were luxury items or direly needed goods in limited supply.

Spices, expensive cloths, skillfully crafted artifacts and weapons,

and exotic foods from abroad were the usual fare that were carried

from port cities into the interior of Europe. Within the heartland

of the newly emerging nations, trade was often local rather than

national. Intercity trade brought towns and villages together but

in regional networks and local, markets, not in national ones.

This “parochialism,” to use a term that is distinctly pejorative

today, gave inland towns a certain degree of economic strength:

their relative self-sufficiency and ingrown cultures provided them

with the material and spiritual fortitude to resist the overbearing

effects of the nation-state, particularly during the “Age of Absolutism,” when strong monarchs came to the foreground of European

political life. Decentralism remained a major obstacle—and, for

generations, an abiding civic impulse—in counteracting the extension of royal power. Hence, emerging European nation-states

were often checked internally as well as externally from successfully engaging in empire building. European empire building

found an outlet not in the “old” continent but abroad, in so-called

“new” continents such as the Americas, where indigenous peoples,

living in tribal communities were easily quelled by recently discovered firearms, and, in no small part, by dazzling European

trinkets. Needless to emphasize, European epidemics, too, played

a major role in depleting aboriginal populations and demoralizing

them..

The rise of European nation-states, so unique when compared

with the imperial systems of antiquity and the fragmented social

structures of feudalism, can thus be explained by a special conjunction of forces. A few are simply negative: the internal resistance

within emerging nations to centralism that made a highly organized patrimonial state difficult to achieve and the balance between new states that confined them to a “national” scale. Other,

factors, more positive in nature, consist of the fairly organic links

established between municipalities primarily by local and regional

trade and secondarily by the exceptionally rich rewards that port

cities acquired from foreign commerce. The royal power that built

the nation-state, virtually brick by brick as it were, used the internal intercity networks as political routes for extending its bureaucracies into the depths of the country just as the Church, centuries

earlier, sent its missionaries and holy orders into the forests and

farmlands of barbarian Europe along trails and footpaths.

Despite the enormous wealth monarchs gained from the taxes

these commercial networks provided, nation building was still

primarily a political phenomenon. Economic explanations to the

contrary notwithstanding, the absolute monarchs of the sixteenth

century who dominated the emerging era of European nationalism drained the economy as much as they fostered its development; The removal of feudal tolls on roads and riverways, the

domestic tranquility provided by the “King’s peace,” the creation

of a national currency and presumably a reliable monetary system

were vitiated by the enormity of royal taxes, the ongoing wars

between nation-states that placed Europe in a chronic state of

siege, and the monetary instability produced by royal loans and

defaults.

----

The role cities played in this development was very mixed; indeed, to understand it, we must know what kind of city we are

talking about and what phase of nation building we are examining.

Generally, the smaller, artisan-oriented towns tended to oppose

the nation-state and often gained support for their opposition from

the relatively free peasantry in their environs. Indeed, it could be

said in a very broad way that where artisans were the majority of

a free town, they elected for municipal freedom and were more

predisposed to forming town confederations than larger, commercially oriented cities. Their high sense of independence and their

striking defiance of authority was not to end with their opposition

to royal rule; whether as master craftsmen or as skilled workers,

they shared an intuitive inclination toward a vague kind of republicanism, often even democracy, that clashed with the politically

more conservative merchant, banking, and professional strata in

their own communities and in strongly commercial cities.

The radical role played by skilled artisans in precapitalist society and in periods of transition to the nation-state and capitalism

is only recently gaining the attention it deserves. This is not to say

that this on-going stratum that was not to disappear as a major

social force even after the Industrial Revolution, which virtually

destroyed it, shared a completely unified outlook. Between a master craftsman who enjoyed the privileges conferred by gild membership and a skilled worker who was barred from the status of a

master by increasing gild exclusivity, a serious gap developed that

could rend communities in violent struggles. We have seen evidence of such struggles in Flanders and Italy, where skilled as well

as unskilled workers were proletarianized and reduced to exploited wage earners. But elsewhere in Europe, the traditional

bridges between master craftsmen and skilled workers served

effectively to close the gap that had been created by status differences; indeed, in many places gild doors remained fairly open well into the Middle Ages.

What is so noticeable about this town stratum, taken as a whole,

is the fairly high educational level it attained. Artisans were often

well-read, surprisingly well-informed, and intellectually innovative. Craftsmanship sharpened not only one’s dexterity and esthetic sense; it sharpened one’s mind as well. The radical heretical

movements within medieval Christianity consisted of large numbers of well-read artisans, not simply “millenarian” peasants, as

Marxist historians such as Eric Hobsbawn would have us believe.{64}

The Brethren of the Free Spirit and many revolutionary gnostic

sects that challenged the church’s hierarchical system were filled

with artisans. Town revolts against ruling bishops, barons, and

commercially minded patricians were initiated by well-informed,

even well-read, artisans who could argue holy writ with disquieting acuteness. They often provided the ideological coherence for

these uprisings that historians often impute to professional strata,

not only mass support. This tradition did not die out with the

Middle Ages. It continued for centuries, through the Reformation,

which was by no means only a peasant war, through the era of the

democratic revolutions, and into the Industrial Revolution, indeed

for several generations afterward.

Skilled workers, particularly craftsmen, are remarkably self-contained individuals—the urban counterpart of the yeoman

farmer who formed the basis for the democratic revolutionary era.

Skill and a minimal competence, whether in the form of a personally owned shop or land holding, confers a sense of independence

and self-esteem upon a person. It is out of these traits that the

classical—and, to some extent, the modern—ideal of citizenship

was fashioned. The lack of a respected skill and the absence of

material independence makes for mobility in the pejorative sense

of the term, notably, a wayward, fickle, and free-floating mob that

is easily manipulated, no less by patrician demagogues than by

dispossessed ones. Rebellion that lacks men and women with the

moral substance produced by a sense of material independence

and self-esteem—or, at least, a sense of hope that these attributes

can be acquired by concerted action—tends to degenerate as easily into nihilistic counterrevolution as it does into constructive

revolutionary behavior. The gap that emerged between the

skilled *popolo* of Italian cities during the High Middle Ages and

the more or less lumpenized proletariat was to last for centuries

and disappear only when craftsmanship was dissolved by the factory system.

European absolutism repeatedly came up against this human

element in its endeavor to place its territorial realm under royal

authority. That many artisans were in the service of the royal court

as producers of luxury items does not tarnish the character of those

who lived outside the orbit of absolutism and opposed it. These

outsiders, in fact, were the great majority in Europe and generally

serviced local and regional markets. By contrast, the bankers,

professionals, and merchants whose incomes were derived from

loans to the upper classes, bureaucratic positions, and international trade—thej “big bourgeoisie,” as it were—were generally

royalist and more irresolute than the artisans in their localist loyalties. Absolutism provided them not only with domestic security

and a huge source of revenues; banker and merchant followed in

the wake of royal armies, garnering the spoils acquired by conquest, the need for arms, and the opening of new markets. Where

these strata were deeply entrenched in a municipal establishment,

they tended to resist but rarely rebel against royal authority. Here

they might act as an inertial force against nation building but

seldom as a major obstacle. Hence they formed opportunistic alliances with rebellious artisans that, they readily betrayed when

things threatened to get out of hand and demands for civic autonomy threw municipalities into violent and serious opposition with the centralized state.

The “bourgeoisie” that is said to have given support to absolutism against the feudal lords consisted mainly of bankers and merchants and later, to some extent, of the new industrial bourgeoisie,

Indeed, this “bourgeoisie” was strikingly conservative; it consistently supported some kind of royal power, whether absolutist in

the sixteenth century or constitutional in the eighteenth. Republicanism and democratism (a very revolutionary concept until well

into the nineteenth century) found its most steadfast recruits in

artisans and, less reliably, the “mobility” people or rootless, statusless, and homeless “mob,” whom even the English Levellers

viewed warily because of their dependence on the largesse of the

possessing classes.

Our picture is further complicated by the aspirations of the

territorial lords, who openly rose in rebellion time and again

against the monarchy—and, of course, by the peasantry that never

lived on comfortable terms with the royal power, the manorial

estates, or the towns. The story of the conflict between the monarchy and nobility, a struggle that reached its violent zenith in the

Fronde, which literally chased the young Louis XIV out of Paris,

is the stuff out of which the conventional history of European

absolutism is written. It does not require emphasis here. The peasant wars in England in the late fourteenth century and in Germany in the early sixteenth were really climactic events in a

chronic conflict that went bn for centuries from the High Middle

Ages to our own time. John Ball and Thomas Miinzer were the

ancestors of a host of later agrarian leaders such as Emilian Pugachev in Russia and Emiliano Zapata in Mexico. All of them shared

the central goal of preserving the village community, its insular

lifeways, its networks of mutual aid, its common lands and communitarian economy.

Nation building during the era of absolutism was unique precisely because it occurred within—and by the tensions it produced

and fostered—a highly diversified and creative social arena for

political development. The ancient world had been dominated by

massive, generally immobile empires that suffocated social development with their parasitism and massive bureaucratic structures.

Medieval Europe was an embryonic world—rich in promise, to be

sure, but largely unformed, lacking in cohesion, indeed more particularistic than decentralistic. Absolutism and the early era of

nation building stood somewhere in between. As Perez Zagorin

tells us: “In spite of the expansion of absolutism and its critical

collisions with rebellious subjects, royal government never became uniform or monolithic, even in the kingdoms where it suffered least limitation. Confusions of jurisdictions and rivalries and

conflicts among governmental institutions abounded under its

rule. Its actual power was more like an intricate mosaic of particular prerogatives, rights, and powers than a homogeneous, all-inclusive authority. The attributes of sovereignty that were ascribed to absolute kings by royalist lawyers and political philosophers, such

as the French thinker Jean Bodin, were more often than not

greater in theory than the powers these same kings could dispose

of in practice. The monarchies of our early modern states continued to be in many regards conservative and traditionalistic, as

befitting regimes ruling hierarchic societies and of centuries-long

growth from ancient origins. Absolutist kings did not quarrel with

social privilege, of which their own position was the supreme

manifestation. They quarreled only with the privileges that resisted their authorities or claimed immunity from their government [which, one is obliged to add, seems to mean that they

opposed all social privilege but their own]. In building their more

centralized states, they did not sweep the stage clean with a new

broom and many older and outmoded political forms and institutions survived the reign of absolutism, like scenery left standing while a new play was performed.”{65}

What Zagorin seems to reproach the absolutist monarchies for

-namely their failure to “sweep the stage clean with a new

broom” and achieve a more homogenized, efficient, and smoothly

working social order—is what gave the era its incredibly

mism and creativity. It was precisely the rich social features of the

sixteenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth centunes-the extraordinary diversity of social life and its forms, the creative tension from

whffih so much mobility in status, cultural, and intellectual fervor

emerged—that makes the era so fascinating and provocative. The

absolute monarchies, caught in a complex web of ancient priveleges and rights, thus became the reluctant conservators and the gnawing subversives of an accumulated wealth of old customs

autonomous jurisdictions, traditional liberties, and hierarchical

claims to authority.

Within this immense warehouse of historical rights and duties,

communities and individuals, institutions and interests could

move with remarkable freedom and function with exciting fecundity often invoking past precedent to defend recent innovation

in an old guise and play history against present to create amew

future Marx was to reprove the French revolutionaries of 1848 for

dressing their rhetoric, claims, and ideals in the slogans of the

French revolutionaries of 1789–94, who in turn borrowed the

language and postures of the Roman Republic to legitimate then

own ideals. Yet it was precisely this rich sense of historicity and

variety of forms, manners, and ideas-whose power and insightfulness

we will explore in the closing chapter of this book-that gave

such fecundity to both French revolutions and opened such

sense of promise in Europe two centuries ago. What an individual

“thinks of himself”—not simply the hidden economic laws or

some unknown “spirit” that ostensibly guides history—has a

very profound effect on how he or she acts as a social being

deeply influences the course of social development, Marx to the

contrary notwithstanding. The richly variegated images that people had of their own time, their rights, and themselves profoundly

taped much of the history of that time. Diversity made fo

greater choice and a more fertile social landscape, however often

precedent was invoked and reshaped to serve new ends. The

tensions created by the alternate developmental pathways that

emerged before communities, orders, classes, and, yes, individuals

fostered a highly creative practice in the achievement of their

ends.

Nor is it true, as Marx tells us, that “No social order ever

perishes before all the productive forces for which there is room

in it have developed.”{66} I leave aside the fact that this dictum begs

the very question it poses: we presuppose that the limits of a social

order are defined by their “productive forces,” notably technology and the various ways of organizing labor, indeed that they

constitute the essence of a “social order.” Actually, we have no

way of knowing how far the “productive forces” could have developed in precapitalist society, nor do there seem to be any limits

to the development of “productive forces” today, which means, by

inference, that a market society will be with us forever.

But what is most disquieting about Marx’s vision of social

change is the extent to which it denies the power of speculative

thought to envision a new society long before an old one becomes

intolerable or is bereft of any room for development. Artisans and

peasants in the era of nation building had many sound ideas about

the kind of society they wished to create. It is a mechanistic arrogance of the most extreme kind to predetermine how far communities can go—whether forward, backward, or both, m their

vision of the good society and the elements that compose it—and

literally dictate the material or productive limits of their vision, its

“preconditions,” its possibilities, and its place in a theory of history

structured around various “stages” and presuppositions.

We may say, returning to Zagorin’s description of absolutism,

that it was not in spite of a monarch’s “brutal collision with rebellious spirits” but because of this collision that the nation builders

of Bodin’s time failed to “sweep the stage clean with a new

broom...” English, French, and Spanish monarchs, like their

ancient counterparts who built huge empires, wanted very much

to achieve “homogeneous and all-inclusive authority. They did

not require the existence of local hierarchies to justify the development of a national hierarchy, nor did they need the challenges

created by local privileges to justify their own claims to national

privilege. To the extent that they tolerated local hierarchies and

privileged strata, it was because they did not have the resources

and the economic supports to replace them. Jean Bodin’s justification for the all-inclusive authority of every national government

over the rights claimed by lesser, more local jurisdictions is evidence of a prevailing vision among the monarchies of his day that

clashed with the reality of their situation and profoundly unsettled

the real world. What European monarchs did “think” of themselves—namely, all-powerful rulers of highly centralized state’s—deeply affected the development of European history. Their centralists proclivities clearly influenced the thinking of men like

Robespierre, France’s centralizer par excellence, who also struggled to overthrow royalism as such, using Rousseau-like principles

of a democracy that “forces” men to be free. Herein lies one of the

great ironies of the modern era: leaders of the popular opposition

to absolutism were to function in many ways like the monarchs

they professed to oppose and, ultimately, they were to turn against

the very popular movements that brought them to power.

It was the artisans and peasants—of the autonomous towns

whose walls centralistic royalists such as Cardinal Richelieu were

to demolish, not only self-governing and parochial feudal lords

who were to rise in rebellions against the monarchies of Europe.

I have already examined the resistance and alternative offered by

the **Comuneros** and the German peasants as examples, together

with others who typified the most important efforts to arrest centralism and statist forms of nation building. The seventeenth and

eighteenth centuries, no less than the sixteenth, exploded in numerous albeit more localized conflicts of the kind that produced

so much civil turmoil in the sixteenth. To catalogue these smaller

but highly numerous revolts, particularly those that occurred in

France, would be tedious. Their overall pattern, however, is described by Zagorin very ably:

In every case, some new exorbitancy of royal finance, a tax on
taverns, for instance, or the abolition of as exemption from certain
imposts, sparked the outbreak. Then the residential quarters of the
poor erupted, mobs of three, five, and even ten thousand took to the
streets, and the pursuit of the *gabeleurs* [tax collectors] became the
order of the day. Riot and excitation, violence coupled with aspects
of a popular festival and its drunken indulgence, dominated these
outbreaks, as the lower orders dropped their workaday routine for
the collective action that demonstrated their anger and made them
feel their strength. The militant base was always the urban **plebs**:
not made up entirely, perhaps, of what the president of the parlement of Bordeaux called “the lowest part of the people,” but com
sisting of artisans, journeymen, day laborers, small shopkeepers, and
sometimes womenfolk, too, who participated with their men! At,
Bordeaux a boatman and a tavernkeeper, at Agen a master glover,
a pack-saddle maker, and again a tavernkeeper, at Perigeau a physician, stood out as leaders and hafanguers of the crowd. Peasants
swarmed in from the outskirts to unite briefly with the revolt, as
happened in Bordeaux, At Agen, six thousand peasants who tried to
enter were kept out by the bourgeois militia and burned the property of *gabeleurs* in the vicinity.{67}

A more detailed account would include attacks upon the town

hall, the release of jailed prisoners, the killing of tax collectors and

finance officials, even of wealthy individuals who were suspected

of being in collusion with the state. Without the leadership provided by artisans, small proprietors, occasionally professionals, and

even members of the lesser nobility, it is unlikely that these uprisings would have gone very far. Apparently their extent depended

upon “the passivity, neutral or ambiguous behavior, and even

partial support [of] the notables and well-to-do. The bourgeois

militia of Bordeaux showed little will to act.. At Perigeux the

bourgeois guard was similarly slack. Only at Agen, where the

violence was particularly intense and accompanied by a definite

social antagonism, did elites and authorities take concerted steps

against the outbreak.”

The limits of these insurrections, rural as well as urban, should

be noted. Again, Zagorin comes to our aid:

Taken as a whole, French urban rebellions were devoid of programs
or ideas. In the same way as the concurrent agrarian revolts, they
seemed to reflect a stasis in French society despite its exceptional
amount of violence and insubordination, an inability by insurgent-forces to transcend the existing state of things with any informing
vision of an alternative. Although again and again the centralist
offensive led to resistance, the latter failed to give rise to demands
for political changes.... Urban rebellion was essentially a defensive
response by the whole community. To the plebeian populace, the
punishment of *gabeleurs* was a deserved act of communal justice.
If such people took the largest, most active part in these insurrections, that was because they were the most sensible of fiscal oppression. But elites usually shared responsibility in some measure. Their ‘own opposition to exactions helped to legitimize resistance, and
they encouraged revolt, whether by actual instigation, covert approval and sympathy, or inaction, when disorder broke out.... But
they were helpless to hold back the advance of absolutism and its
centralizing grip because they had no political reforms to propose
and conceived of no new institutional limits on the power of the
royal state. {68}

Actually, Zagorin’s account of the way these chronic town insurrections unfolded—ultimately leading to the French Revolution itself a century or so later—fails to explore certain important

details that help us understand the extent to which the uprisings

actually did “hold the advance of absolutism and its centralizing

grip” under control. The French monarchs such as Louis XIII and

Louis XIV were strong kings who were guided by even stronger

advisors such as the cardinals Richilieu and Mazarin, respectively.

They created the strongest armies and created the most far-reaching bureaucracies in western Europe in their day. They were

ruthless centralizers and patently hostile to their own nobility,

often encouraging trade and playing the “bourgeois” classes

against the noble classes who were as protective of their particularistic privileges as they were of their economic. Western Europe in

the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries was a status-oriented

world. It was made up more of “orders”—status groups who enriched themselves, developed extravagant patterns of conspicuous consumption, and spoke in a mannered language according to

an elaborate body of etiquette—rather than of classes who simply

and unadornedly pursued their material interests. Power and social recognition were no less important than wealth; in fact they

were major sources of material wealth. Personal enrichment, in

turn, was often pursued precisely to gain more power and greater

social recognition. Consumption in all its dazzling forms thus assumed greater significance than production, even for the bourgeoisie, which tried to elbow its way into the social hierarchies of

the era. Mary Beard’s account of the merchant’s values in the

Roman world holds as well in the era of absolutism as it does in the

era of empire, a thousand years earlier. The trader, she observes,

“had drained the wealth of the West for ‘bones and stones’ [gems

and ornaments] from the East and thereby brought on currency

troubles for which there was apparently no remedy.... Because

he had yielded much to the landed gentleman’s ideal, he tended

to draw fortunes away from the business to the land, taking wealth

out of circulation and energy out of business enterprise. His children, growing up in the country, were often lost to business entirely.”{69}

In western Europe, especially in “classical” France—the country that so many radical and liberal thinkers were to regard as the

model for “pure” feudalism and the “bourgeois-democratic” revolution—this process of moving from the status of trader to that of

nobleman was especially marked and adds considerable ambiguity

to what we mean by the word “bourgeois.” Many “bourgeois” and

noble interests coalesced. Both orders generally had a greater fear

of the “mob” than of each other—and, in moments of crisis, of the

monarchy. The two orders were united by bonds of marriage, land

ownership, cultural tastes, values, and‘ a desire for status and the

power, political as well as economic, that it conferred.

The “bourgeois militia” of Bordeaux, Perigeaux, and Agen

probably included many aspiring master craftsmen, merchants,

and a good sprinkling of “industrialists” who were eager to acquire

noble status—even if only “nobles of the robe” (nobles who had

noble status conferred upon them for service to the state or, quite

crassly, for money) rather than “nobles of the sword” (hereditary

nobility). They were more like medieval burghers, than capitalists

in the present-day sense of the term. Indeed capitalism, conceived

not simply as an economic system structured around commercial

transactions or trade but, in its truly modern sense, as an accumulative system (what Marx called “expanding reproduction”)

in which industrial expansion became an end in itself, was a feeble

thing in western Europe in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, more characteristically Dutch than either English or French.

Hence, it would be of value to discriminate between the words

“bourgeoisie” and “capitalists” rather than turn them into synonyms.

By the same token, the “lowest part of the people,” whom the

president of the Bordeaux Parlement designated as the principal

activists in the urban rebellions of the 1630s, were not simply

laborers, vagabonds, and beggars. In a status-oriented society, they

could also be said to include master craftsmen, artisans, shopkeepers, and small-property owners. The fact that tavernkeepers, master glovers, pack-saddle makers, and. even a physician “stood out

as leaders and haranguers of the crowd,” to use Zagorin’s words,

tells us something about the “crowd” they led and harangued.

That nobles, too, occasionally became such “leaders” tells us something about the transclass nature of such uprisings and the extent

to which nearly all sectors of society could be united against the

centralization of power by the monarchy. Most of the people

hated men like Richelieu, Mazarin, and members of the king’s

administrative bureaucracy, despite’their ritualistic expressions of

affection for the king. Such cries as “Long live the king without the

status as a caring father, could earn popular loyalty only if he was

shorn; of the all-important fiscal means for maintaining his commanding position in the country—a position that amounted to

very little without the money for provisioning his army, paying his

bureaucrats, and carrying on domestic wars against recalcitrant

towns and nobles.

Which raises Zagorin’s’ question of how much of a program

French insurrectionaries actually needed if French society was

indeed in a “stasis.” Zagorin’s use of the word *stasis* stands at odds

with, his notion that the insurrectionaries were “helpless to hold

back the advance of absolutism and its centralizing grip.” The

“stasis” of the time consisted precisely of a lasting balance of forces

between the central power and the regions, localities, orders, and

classes of the time, not an ever-encroaching central power. Richilieu and Mazarin, working ruthlessly on behalf of their monarchs, tried to forge a completely centralized nation-state around

the king and his bureaucracy. It is myth, in my view, to believe

that any but the most naive of the absolutist Frerich kings trusted

their nobles, although one French monarch, Louis XVI, tried to

enlist his nobles in 1788 against an ever-demanding “Third Estate.” They betrayed him without scruples and, in the most self-seeking manner, brought about his downfall as well as their own.

Thus Richelieu and Mazarin did not succeed, in fact. They carried centralization far in France, but not so far that it could prevent the French Revolution, which tried in its early phases to

reverse the power of the king and the aristocrats alike, initially

driving toward a relatively decentralized, indeed minimal, state.

If centralism is to be identified with the interests of the newly

emerging capitalist economy insofar as the “bourgeoisie” seeks a

politically unified country, the French Revolution was categorically not a “bourgeois revolution.” Nor did the French “bourgeoisie” want a “democracy” or even, necessarily, a republic. Indeed,

it tried to model France on England’s constitutional monarchy.

The supreme irony of the French Revolution is that a movement

designed to curb privilege, hierarchy, and, above all, centralized

power was twisted by liberal intellectuals, “forward-looking” lawyers, and marginal strata into the most centralized state in Europe

in order to defeat its counterrevolutionary enemies. In some respects, the Jacobin Republic that followed the collapse of these

hopes for a constitutional monarchy and a fairly decentralized

political structure was marbled by feudal concepts of government,

notably, the famous “maximum” that limited the rise of placed

prices and wages, state intervention in many parts of the economy

and society, and a moral posture that espoused “republican virtue” as a political calling. The Jacobin Republic, in effect, was a

wartime state that Napoleon was to make fairly permanent. This

quixotic turn of events etched itself, deeply into French national

fife for nearly two centuries, and centralism became a focal issue

around which popular movements were to rebel throughout the

nineteenth century. The climax of this popular movement was

reached in May 1871 when the Commune of Paris tried to establish a confederal republic based on a commune of communes, a

struggle that ended in a bloody massacre and the ebbing of decentralistic notions of socialism in France itself.

----

Robespierre and napoleon, more than Richilieu and Mazarin, were

the true forgers of the nation-state in France, and it was they who

provided the real “classical” example of centralized national authority in Europe.

What role did the towns and cities play in abetting this development from the sixteenth century onward? Towns and cities responded, as we have seen, in very mixed ways to the emergence

of a centralized authority that tried to absorb them. Some resisted

that authority with very little internal division or difference of

opinion. Others, particularly where the “bourgeoisie” and elite

orders prevailed, favored a well-coordinated society in which

trade could prosper. They thereby abetted the work of Richelieu,

Mazarin, and Napoleon, both the original article and his nephew,

Louis Bonaparte, in the 1850s and 1860s. But there is a sense in

which all the towns of Europe unwittingly abetted the formation

of nation-states, even as they opposed it for social, political, and

cultural reasons. They did this by creating the arteries and veins,

as it were, for national consolidation: the elaborate, indeed historically unprecedented, road systems and nodal market towns that

fostered the monetization, commercialization, and industrialization of nations—and with these possibilities, the effective centralization of the state along national lines.

I wish to advance the view that this was one of the most important achievements of Europe during the Middle Ages and well

into recent times. So much emphasis has been placed by historians

on Europe’s development of a market economy, its relative freedom of trade, and its openness to industrial innovation—features

that are certainly uniquely European—that we fail to recognize

how little they would have been able to affect the continent’s

development without a network of roads, canals, and rivers to

make such an economy possible. Apart from the trade that created

market towns—towns where all goods were systematically exchanged—long-distance commerce was an elitist affair and served

the well-to-do, not society at large. Local trade was necessarily

very local because of the insular nature of most European communities. So, too, was political power. Rivers, canals, and maritime

transportation served to link a fair percentage of Europe’s towns

and villages together, but by no means the majority. A European

“hinterland” existed almost everywhere on the continent, such

that towns and villages were almost entirely self-sufficient in the

staples of everyday life and culture remained highly insular. These

“hinterlands” were largely beyond the reach of the nation-state

and surprisingly impenetrable to commerce, monetization, and

the “bourgeois” incubus that was to claim Europe for itself during

the nineteenth century.

We can begin to sense the importance of road systems in economic development and political control today (perhaps even

more than during any other part of our century) because of the

effectiveness of guerrilla warfare in the Third World. The very

lack of “development” and the poor road systems that exist in

Central America, mountainous portions of Asia, and the rain forests in southeast Asia have brought even nation-states aided by

“superpowers” to their knees. All the “colonizers” of the past

recognized the need for effective road systems. The Romans were

able to hold their empire together precisely because it was networked by a highly elaborate system of roads that penetrated into

the Iberian peninsula, Gaul, and portions of Britain and Germany

as well as the hinterlands of the Mediterranean basin. Even quasi-tribal societies such as the Inca of Peru developed “empires” because roads—actually well-maintained pathways and footbridges—made central coordination possible. It matters little whether

elaborate road networks emerged because “economic forces”

created a need for them or because they made the emergence of

such “economic forces” as a market economy possible. The two,

in fact, may have interacted reciprocally with each other: road

building stimulating commerce and commerce stimulating road

building.

Judging from Rome’s network, however, good roads in themselves did not necessarily foster a high volume of commerce, although they were indispensable for commercial advances. This

great network of antiquity was not constructed primarily to transport merchandise. It was created mainly to move troops and imperial administrators to various parts of the empire. Even the transport of goods to supply the legionnaires was a secondary factor in

road design and its routes. As R. S. Lopez tells us in his absorbing

discussion of land transport, Roman troops were encouraged to

live “as far as possible on the food produced in their immediate

vicinity and the administrative centres were almost all situated

either on the sea or on internal navigable waterways.”{70} This orientation is very “un-European”: it reflects the astonishing extent

to which a world oriented toward agrarian values dominated its

merchants and morally denigrated their sources of income. Essentially, it was the “merchant, glutted, or rather contented with his

profit, [who] retires from the port to become a landed proprietor,”

Cicero tells us, “... [who] seems to me worthy of full praise,” not

the “small-scale” trader, much less, artisan, “who should be of

little account.”{71}

Accordingly, Roman roads wore built almost defensively along

mountain crests, very much like fortresses, rather than through

populous valleys. Their seemingly indestructible large blocks of

stone gave them a rigidity that increased their vulnerability to

climatic changes, opening large surface cracks that, as Lopez tells

us, “needed gangs of slaves, or continuous work by those obliged

to furnish road-services to the state, and even so they were unsuitable for heavy or broad vehicles.”{72} The Roman road system, indeed ancient road networks generally, were not designed to expand local commerce beyond its regional confines or open trade

routes to a continental exchange of ordinary staples. Long-distance trade of luxury goods and delicacies transported by sea or

along rivers was favored over a mosaic of local and regional commercial transactions that brought ordinary goods and money into remote areas of the continent.[10]

[10] Which is not to say that grain, that all-important import of the Greek cities and

Rome, was not a major staple in the Mediterranean basin and along European

water routes. But the inland transportation of grain by carts was quite secondary

to luxury objects once we look beyond a regional economy in Europe.

By contrast, Europe placed a high premium on the local artisan

and merchant. At a time when so much emphasis is placed on the

role of long-distance commerce in forming capitalism and the

modern age, it is important to recognize how local producers and

local markets slowly reworked the interior of the European continent, preparing it for a monetized economy and providing the

goods and markets for creating a market society. This slow but

historic change in the economic culture of Europe—a slow but

decisive change in attitudes toward trade, production for sale, and

the use of money—was the work in large part of small towns, not

only busy, glamorous ports.

Little by little a new network of roads was put into effective operation, different totally in structure and methods from the ancient one
and used by quite different types of transport and haulage. The
changes in transport which accompanied the commercial revolution and the outburst of economic activity in this period can themselves be described as a slow revolution, If we consider them more
closely, we find that they reveal the changed political and social face
of Europe. For in medieval Europe there was no large and powerful
state like the Roman Empire. Slavery disappeared and in many
regions, of which Italy was the first, serfdom was abolished. Finally,
the dignity of the, merchant and of trade won recognition, though
with many reservations. Hence private initiative or local associations largely took the place of coercive government action. The
routing of roads reflected the needs of commerce rather than the
convenience of soldiers and civil servants. Maximum use was made
of animal labour in transport, while human labour was safer as
possible, economized.

Lopez goes on to say that road construction “initiative came from

autonomouslocal bodies or independent private companies. Plurality of roads, which is always possible when the dogma of the

straight line is abandoned, enabled a great number of minor centres to be included in the network.”

To say, Ferdinand Braudel reminds us, that “Napoleon moved

no faster than Julius Caesar” misses a number of very important

points. Even if this statement were true, Napoleon had a greater

variety of transportation choices than Caesar and climatic factors

limited his strategic decisions far less than those of his Roman

counterpart; so, too, for the European tradesman by comparison

with the Roman. Even if we examine the regional network of

roads created by this gradual transportation revolution, new possibilities and a sharper division of labor between the artisan and

food cultivator—with its concomitant elaboration of skills, local

inter action, use of money, and growing wants—all constituted the

indispensable spadework for creating a sophisticated market economy.

What is important is that it was the proliferation of craftspeople,

of new wares and technics, of more craft organizations or gilds,

and the intensive as well as extensive development of market

interactions—generally intimate, humanly scaled, and ethical—that is most characteristic of the market economy that emerged

in Europe. Let me emphasize that this rich patchwork of commercial relationships enhanced human interaction, unlike the capitalistic type of market economy that was to replace it centuries later.

Even as it slowly advanced over the European continent, trade on

a small, local scale between closely associated communities and

individuals fostered cooperation rather than competition. It

tended to deepen and extend local ties rather than sever them. It

was more participatory than adversarial, more moral than predatory, and politically it provided the individual producer with a

stronger material base for the exercise of citizenship.[11] Finally, it

tended to dissolve barriers between local communities and adjacent regions, opening the doors to new ideas, cultures, values, and

the interchange of skills and technics. In time, the towns themselves acquired greater political and economic weight in the struggle to form nation-states. It may have entangled them in the crises

of nation building, but it also turned them into centers of revolutionary social transformation, an advance signalled by the

Comunero movement in Spain and the sectional movement in

France.

[11] I find it fascinating that so many radicals, socialists and anarchists alike, almost

intuitively rally to the support of small-scale farmers against agribusiness and small

family enterprises against giant supermarkets, this despite their hostility to private

property of any kind. Americans seem to suspect that domestic forms of society,

however propertied, are a desideratum in themselves and foster individuality in

a mass society. This Jeffersonian legacy acts as one of the most important inertial

elements against the full colonization of society by corporations and big business,

even though its historical context in the making of the free city and free citizen

has not been fully understood; so, too, for our appreciation of craftsmanship.

These markets and towns were not capitalistic. Marx has appropriately designated their economy as “simple commodity production” in which profit making and the plowing of surplus earnings

back into capital expansion are largely nonexistent. Taken in this

pure form, his account of their “mode of production” is more of

a Weberian “ideal type” than an actual reality. Capitalism almost

certainly did exist in European towns, even predominantly in

some artisan ones, and even dominated many European cities,

particularly port and riverine cities. But Europe also developed

for centuries by elaborating its artisan-oriented towns rather than

by significantly transforming them. Viewed as a whole, the continent from the fourteenth century onward until well into the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries seemed to have a mixed

economy, which was neither predominantly feudal, capitalist, nor

structured entirely around simple commodity production. Rather,

it contained and combined elements of all three forms. That one

of these elements seemed to be of greater significance than another in some communities and areas does not alter the mixed

nature of economic life as a whole. Contrary to the widely held

belief that a capitalistic economy emerged within the “womb” of

feudalism and asserted itself as a “dominant” form with the attempt to build nation-states in the sixteenth century, it seems

more accurate in my view to say that capitalism coexisted with

feudal and simple commodity relationships. This long era, perhaps

spanning more than five centuries, simply cannot be treated as

“transitional” without reading back the present into the past and

teleologically structuring European history around an Aristotelian

“final cause” called “capitalism.”

At various times and in various places, this mixed economy

assumed a very balanced form—in some respects more stable in

terms of everyday life than our own war-ridden century. Marxist

and liberal historians have been vexed to give this long era a name

that accords with the dogmatic “stages” theories of history that

abound in Marx and Engels’s writings. Its existence seems to be an

affront to the neat categories that even radical historians impose

on the rich flux of social development. Conclusions that it was

either “feudal” or “capitalist,” or what able writers like Paul

Sweezy designate as “precapitalist commodity production” (a designation that tells us we know more about what it was not than

what it really proved to be), often stand in flat contradiction to the

data at our disposal.{73}

A more open-minded reading of the data and the empirical

evidence at our disposal on the era—one that extended well beyond the sixteenth-century period of nation building—will show,

I submit, that western Europe existed within a force field in which

feudal traditions interacted with simple commodity and capitalist

forms of societal organization. Nor were feudalism, capitalism, and

simple commodity production socially rigid economic systems.

They were evolving cultures, differing in values, sensibilities, ways

of experiencing the world and organizing it artistically and intellectually, not simply “modes of production,” to use Marx’s terminology again. They constituted unique social ecologies, as it were,

that were patterned in highly diverse ways throughout the continent. They also changed with the passage of time in varying degrees and with varying accent or emphasis on their components,

often as a result of their interaction with each other.

Space does not allow me to make a closer examination of this’

seemingly “transitional era,” which in actuality forms a yery definable and long era of European history. That it fits none of the

dogmatic interpretations advanced by many moderni historians

who have an ideological ax to grind says more about academic

trends in contemporary historiography than the richly varied texture of European life over the past thousand years: The “stasis” to

which Zagorin alludes in his account of the state’s development

seems also to have occurred in town development during the

fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, possibly even later in many

parts of Europe. Although greatly increased in number, European

towns seem to have entered into a demographic slack period

where urban populations ceased to grow and in some cases diminished. Trade, too, appears to have declined and the development

of new towns generally came to an end.

A number of historians have called this period the “crisis of

feudalism,” a terminology that may very well express a typically

modern identification of “progress” with expansion. This bias

tends to overlook qualitative growth and cultural elaboration for

quantitative growth and cultural change. Apparently, “progress”

is to be defined primarily as material growth, the increasing “domination of nature.” Cultural stability and the elaboration of cultural traits, by contrast, is often conceived as evidence of stagnation,” even of “crisis” and social regression. The received wisdom

of historians to the contrary, is it not possible that Europe had

paused during these centuries and begun to live with minimal

changes in the “force field” of the era, perhaps even reaching a

fairly stable balance between the three components of the mixed

economy that began to develop centuries earlier? That violence,

was endemic at that time, as it generally was before and afterward,

does not alter the stability of everyday life, especially in the small

towns that contained the majority of Europe’s urban population.

This much is reasonably clear: by the seventeenth century, western Europe and its towns seem to haye reached a historic crossroads. The continent’s further “development,” a term that by no

means denotes “progress” in any qualitative sense, was to depend

less on the growth of a centralized state and on the expansion of

commerce than on technology—on the development of machines

and transportation techniques that were to rework all the traditional ties that had produced such an ecologically extraordinary

cultural, political, civic, and economic diversity of social and urban

forms.[12]

[12] Put bluntly: there was no “transition” from feudalism to capitalism in the simple sense presented by most Marxist and liberal historians and theorists. Nor is

it true to say that capitalism developed “within the womb” of feudalism and then

“emerged” as a dominant social order through a series of “bourgeois-democratic

revolutions” whose “paradigm” is the French Revolution of 1789–94 (in the view

of some historians, the span of the revolution is expanded to included the Napoleonic era, notably up to 1814!). The remarkably mixed, diversified, and complex

society that is often presented to us as a “transitional period” was, in fact, an era

in its own right that social ecology can describe and interpret more insightfully

than economistic interpretations. We shall see that the view of this remarkable era

as merely “transitional”leads to a host of errors, particularly its depiction of the

revolutionary era and its democratic aspirations as “bourgeois,” an imagery that

makes capitalism a system more committed to freedom, or even ordinary civil

liberties, than it was historically.

----

The market society we call “capitalism”—a society that tends to

reduce all, citizens to mere buyers and sellers and debases all the

ecologically varied social relationships produced by history to the

exchange of objects called “commodities”—did not “evolve” out

of a feudal era. It literally exploded into being in Europe, particularly England, during the eighteenth and especially nineteenth

centuries, although it existed in the ancient world, the Middle

Ages, and with, growing significance in the mixed economy of the

West from the fourteenth century up to the seventeenth. It is still

spreading around the world—intensively in, its traditional Euro-American center and extensively in the non-European world; Its

forms have varied from the largely mercantile (its earliest kind)

through the industrial (its more recent eighteenth- and nineteenth-century forms) to the statist, corporate, and multinational

forms of our own time. It has slowly penetrated from its special

spheres, such as market arenas of exchange and the production of

commodities in cottages and later in factories, into domestic life

itself, such as the family and neighborhood. This is a fairly recent

“advance” that can be dated most strikingly from the midpoint of

the twentieth century. Its invasion of the neighborhood, indeed of

villages and small towns into the recesses of the domestic or familial relationships, has subverted the social bond itself and threatens

to totally undermine any sense of community and ecological balance and diversity in social life.

Moreover, the newly gained dominance of the capitalistic market relationship over all other forms of production and consociation is a major source of what I have denoted as “urbanization”—the explosion of the city itself into vast urban agglomerations that

threaten the very integrity of city life and citizenship. What makes

the market society we call “capitalism” unique, even by contrast

to its early mercantile form, is that it is an ever-expansive, accumulative, and, in this respect, a cancerous economic system

whose “law of life” is to “grow or die.” Capitalism in its characteristically modern and “dominant” form threatens not only to undermine every “natural economy” (to use Marx’s own terms), be

it small-scale agriculture, artisanship, simple exchange relationships, and the like; it threatens to undermine every dimension of

“organic society,” be it the kinship tie, communitarian forms of

association, systems of self-governance, and localist allegiances—the sense of home and place. Owing to its metastatic invasion of

every aspect of life by means of monetization and what Immanuel

Wallerstein calls “commodification,” it threatens the integrity of

the natural world—soil, flora, fauna, and the complex ecocommunities that have made present-day life forms and relationships

possible by turning everything “natural” into an inorganic, essentially synthetic form.{74} Soil is being turned into sand, variegated

landscapes into level and simplified ones, complex relationships

into more primal forms such that the evolutionary clock is being

turned back to a biotically earlier time when life was less varied

in form and its range more limited in scope.

The effect of capitalism on the city has been nothing less than

catastrophic. The commonly used term “urban cancer” can be

taken literally to designate the extent to which the traditional *urbs*

of the ancient world have been dissolved into a primal, ever-spreading, and destructive form that threatens to devour city and

countryside alike. Growth in the special form that singles out

modern capitalism from all earlier forms of economic fife, including earlier forms of capitalism itself, has affected what we still

persist in calling the “city” by leading to the expansion of pavements, streets, houses, and industrial, commercial, and retail structures over the entire landscape just as a cancer spreads over the

body and invades its deepest recesses.

Cities, in turn, have begun to lose their form as distinctive

cultural and physical entities, as humanly scaled and manageable

political entities. Their functions have changed from ethical

arenas with a uniquely humane, civilized form of consociation,

free of all blood ties and family loyalties, into immense, overbearing, and anonymous marketplaces. They are becoming centers

primarily of mass production and mass consumption, including

culture as well as physically tangible objects. Indeed, culture has

become objectified into commodities as have human relationships,

which are increasingly being simplified and mediated by objects.

The simplification of social life and the biosphere by a growth-oriented economy in which production and consumption become

ends in themselves is yielding the simplification of the human

psyche itself. The strong sense of individuation that marked the

people of the mixed society preceding capitalism is giving way to

a receptive consumer and taxpayer, a passive observer of fife

rather than an active participant in it, lacking in economic roots

that support self-assertiveness and community roots that foster

participation in social life. Citizenship itself, conceived as a function of character formation, and politics, as part of *paideia* or the

education of a social being, tend to wane into personal indifference to social problems. The decline of the citizen, more properly

his or her dissolution into a being lost in a mass society—the

human counterpart of the mass-produced object—is furthered by

a burgeoning of structural gigantism that replaces human scale

and by a growing bureaucracy that replaces all the organic sinews

that held precapitalist society together. The counselor is the humanistic counterpart of the indifferent bureaucrat and the counseling chamber is the structural counterpart of the governmental

office.

Let it be said that this debasement of the ecological complexity

of the city, of its politics, citizens, even of the individuals who

people its streets and structures, is of very recent origin. It did not

really begin in a manorial society, with its barons and serfs, food

cultivators and artisans, and all the “orders” we denote as feudal.

Nor did it follow from those grossly misnamed revolutions, the

“bourgeois-democratic” ones of England, America, and France,

that ostensibly catapulted capital into political control of a society

it presumably “controlled” economically during earlier generations. Rather, this development began to appear with technical

innovations that made possible both the mass manufacture of

cheap commodities and, that is crucially important, their increasingly rapid transportation into the, deepest recesses of western

Europe, inexpensive and highly competitive with the products of

local artisans who serviced their localities for centuries. It need

hardly be emphasized that this development depended enormously for its success on the opening of colonial markets abroad:

the Americas, Africa, and particularly Asia, the area where the

English crown found its richest jewel, notably India.

It was the extraordinary combination of technical advances

\yith the existence of a highly variegated society, relatively free of

the cultural constraints to trade that prevailed in antiquity, that

gave economic ascendancy to the capitalistic component of the

mixed economy over all its other components. Neither wealth

from the Americans nor the large monetary resources accumulated by port cities from long-distance trade fully explains

the rise of,industrial capitalism—a form of capitalism that more

than any other penetrated into the very inner life of Europe.[13] Had

the wealth acquired from the “New World” been a decisive factor

in creating industrial capitalism, Spain rather than England should

have become its center, for it was Spanish cqnquistadores who

initially plundered the Aztec and Inca empires and brought their

precious metals to Europe. The very wealth these “empires” provided for the ascendant nation-state in Spain served to weaken

town life in the Iberian peninsula and provide the means for

absolute monarchs to embark on an archaic program of continental empire building that eventually ruined Spanish cities and the countryside alike.

[13] This I believe probably accounts for Karl Marx’s strongly productivist bias in

economic theory over the more consumptionist biases of contemporary economists. Marx, I believe, was quite correct when he pointed out that under capitalism,

at least, it was production that created demand, not demand that created production, although there is an obvious interplay between the two at a surface level of

economic life. Where he was most lacking was in his failure to recognize the

cultural constraints that limited production and profoundly influenced the vulner·

ability of a society to technological innovation. In this respect, ancient society was

always a mystery to him, and its development was often explained in surprisingly

conventional ways.

Nor did long-distance trade provide the most important sources

for capitalizing industrial development. Rather it fostered consumption more than production, the dissolute lifeway that makes

for a diet of luxuries instead of the parsimonious habits that steer

investment into new means of production. Indeed, too much state

centralization and too much commerce, despite the wealth they

initially generated, ultimately led to excessive expenditures for

territorial expansion and high living by elite groups in all the

orders of a courtly society. That nation-building, increased ceritralization, or, more properly, national consolidation prepared the

way for industrial capitalism by opening more “hinterlands” to

trade is patently clear. So, too, did increases in the population of

dispossessed, propertyless hands, whether as a result of land enclosures or normal demographic growth, hands that were available

for a factory system that had yet to appear on the economic horizon. Europe, in effect, was more open than any part of the world

to the expansion of its Capitalist’component along industrial lines.

This was especially true of England, a country in which a remarkable balance had emerged between a particularly bourgeois-minded aristocracy and monarchy on the one hand and a very

open economy on the other, peopled by a tight-fisted, god-fearing

Puritan yeomanry and structured around towns with decaying

gild systems and cottagers in the countryside who were already

engaged in a domestic form of textile mass production. Whether

the new industrial capitalists who were destined to totally reshape

the country emerged from the merchants involved in the sale of

raw wool to cottage weavers and its sale in the towns, or whether

it came from well-to-do artisans, yeomen, artistocrats who used

sheep to create a new form of pastoral agribusiness, or merchants

who were inclined to siphon their wealth into production—possibly even all of them combined at one time or another—need not

concern us here. What pushed the capitalist component of this

mixed economy into a nation that could regard itself as the “workshop of the world” in the, nineteenth century was a series of inventions that made the factory system and the distribution of its wares possible.

Nor need we be concerned with whether the needs of a “rising

bourgeoisie” produced the Industrial Revolution or the Industrial

Revolution gave rise to the “bourgeoisie,” which in any case was

always a presence in all the major cities of Europe. Factories, in

fact, had begun to appear in eighteenth- and even seventeenth-century England long before an industrial technology had

emerged. Wherever the “bourgeoisie” entered into the productive sphere rather than the commercial, it tried to bring labor

together and rationalize output even with tools, hence a strictly

technological interpretation of the *rise* of industrial capitalism

would be greatly misleading. My concern here is how industrial

capitalism managed to gain ascendancy over *other* forms of production, including commercial capitalism, and alter *all* social relationships that encountered its power. Waterwheels had preceded

the steam engine as a prime mover, and worksheds organized

around simple tools had preceded mechanized factories. But without the inventions that introduced the Industrial Revolution in the

late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, it is doubtful that

industrial capitalism could have impacted so powerfully on

Europe and ultimately on the entire world.

England, perhaps more so than other countries in the western

European orbit, seems to have been an ideal terrain for technological innovation. Its society was highly mobile socially and extremely fluid territorially. The few remaining feudal inhibitions to

change of its various elites, aristocratic as well as commercial, had

already been shattered by the civil war of the Cromwell period,

a conflict that brought armed Puritans to power and added a

strongly plebeian character to the country’s system of government. Even the English aristocracy had been readied for a gainful

capitalistic economy by the wealth it acquired from the sale of

wool. We shall have occasion to note that landed squires and industrial capitalists were not without serious differences over the distribution of manpower in the country’s economy, nor did the rural

patronal system disappear completely. But it can be said that

England, more than any other European country at the time, had

begun to acclimate itself to industrialization owing to the relative

weakness of absolutism, which might have drained the nation’s

wealth to fulfill imperial ambitions and the growth of a money-minded yeomanry and a highly avaricious merchant class.

One must consult Max Weber’s *The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism* to understand how much gain became a

quasireligious “calling” among England’s merchants and its well-to-do yeomanry and artisans; how much they were readied psychologically for the plundering of their own communities and

country. The Spanish *conquistadores* had ruthlessly sacked the

Indian “empires” of the Aztecs and Inca in order to enrich themselves, not to “save” their “souls.” They were maniacally involved

in acts of destruction that often verged on self-destruction with

only indirect effects upon the texture of Spanish society. The English Puritans, by contrast, dourly plundered their own country in

a systematic and lasting manner to accumulate capital. Their behavior seemed to be guided by a moral imperative that made

greed an end in itself, an imperative that was to transform the

lifeways of the precapitalist society from which they had derived.

Long after Puritanism had passed away as a movement, English

society had become secularized. The joyless spirit that the Puritans brought to England then lived on, largely bereft of the few

moral constraints that religion generally imposed on the acquisitive spirit engendered by the Reformation.

Within a span of some two generations, England was transformed on a scale unprecedented in the history of western

Europe. Frederick Engels’s *The Condition of the Working-Class in England*, a period piece based on personal observations in

1844, could justly call the changes introduced by the new industrial inventions—principally in textiles, metallurgy, and transportation—a historic change of unpredented proportions. The rapidity of the transformation is what makes these changes so startling

in a domain of human endeavor—technology—which had developed over centuries at a slow, piecemeal pace. The social and

cultural ramifications of this technological revolution were nothing less than monumental. “Sixty, eighty years ago, England was

a country like every other,” Engels tells us, “with small towns, few

and simple industries, and a thin but *proportionately* large agricultural population. Today {1844} it is a country like *no* other, with

a capital of two and a half million inhabitants; with vast manufacturing cities; with an industry that supplies the world, and produces almost everything by means of the most complex machinery; with an industrious, intelligent, dense population, of which

two thirds are employed in trade and commerce, and composed

of classes wholly different, forming, in fact, with other customs and

other needs, a different nation from the England of those days.”{75}

Engels’s words are meant as much to praise the “revolutionary”

work of the English industrial capitalist as they are intended to

startle the German readers, who first encountered his book. The

Enlightenment’s uncritical commitment to technical progress

completely infects the author’s generalizations, however much he

is bitterly critical of, the misery inflicted by,industrial capitalism on

the new proletariat. Accordingly, we learn that the preexisting

cottage weavers, who were to be devastated economically and

culturally by the new textile machines invented around the middle

of the eighteenth century, “vegetated throughout a passably comfortable existence, leading a righteous arid peaceful life in all piety

and probity; and their material position was far better than that of

their successors. They did not have to overwork; they did no more

than they chose to do, and yet earned what they needed: They had

leizure for healthful work in garden or field, work which, in itself,

was recreation for them, and they could take part besides in the

recreations and games of their neighbours, and all games—bowling, cricket, football, etc., contributed to their physical health and

vigour. They were, for the most part, strong, well-built people, in

whose physique little or no difference than that,of their peasant

neighbours was discernable. Their children grew up in the fresh

country air, and, if they could help their parents at work, it was only

occasionally; while of eight or twelve hours work for them [introduced, later, by the factory system] there was no question.”{76}

The mixed messages in this passage reflect the characteristic

tension created among the “progressives” of the era between the,

claims of an abstract sense of “history” and an existential sense of

humanity that was to rend apart major socialists such as Engels

and ultimately, owing to his commitment to industrial progress

as a “precondition” for a free society, justify the most horrible

barbarities of a Stalin as the “modernizer’ of Russia, The unquestioning humility” of the English cottage weavers and yeomen,

“their silent vegetation ... which, cosily romantic as it was, was

nevertheless not worthy of human beings,” to use Engels’ pejorative remarks, is doubtful on its own terms, particularly from the

standpoint of our own time when the ebullient concept of ‘ progress” that prevailed over the past two centuries is so much in

doubt.[14]{77} But placed in a broader historical context, it is hard to

square this denigration of the cottage weavers and lesser yeomanry with their vigorous role in the English Civil War of the

1640s and their resistance to the introduction of machinery—indeed, the role they played in the’ Chartist movement, the most

radical cause, culturally as well as economically, that England has

seen since the Puritan revolution.

[14] That Engels’s commitment to a harsh concept of technological progress, indeed, the whole Marxist theory of “historical materialism,” was meant to slap not

only the face of philosophical idealism but also of the high spirit of European

romanticism is an issue that has yet to be fully explored. Gray became a favorite

color of Marxian socialism as part of its deliberate endeavor to disenchant the world and relegate the past, with all its humane as well as barbarous traditions, to a

historical “junk heap.” Eventually socialism, like Puritanism, was to be deprived

of all its ethical content and turned into a doctrine very much like the egoistic

political economy of the industrial bourgeoisie itself.

The explosive nature of the Industrial Revolution and the emergence of industrial capitalism can best be understood by rioting

the limited time span in which the new technology surfaced and

swept over England—a period so brief that it is almost difficult to

call it an “era,” as so many historians do. James Watt’s steam

engine, which freed the factory system from its reliance on waterpower, was invented by 1769; James Hargreaves’ spinning jenny,

which enormously increased the output of yarn, by 1764; Richard

Arkwright’s throstle, a sophistication of the spinning machine calculated for the use of a mechanical prime mover, by 1767; Samuel

Crompton’s mule, by 1785, followed around the same time by

Arkwright’s carding machine and preparatory frames; finally, Edmund Cartwright’s workable power loom by 1785. All of these

inventions totally revolutionized the production of textiles as it

had been pursued for thousands of years and catapulted English

cottons, woolens, linens, even lace and silken goods (as a result of

another group of machines invented in the first decade of the

nineteenth century) into a largely agrarian domestic and world

market. The opening of extensive coalfields and iron mines, owing

in large part to the use of coke, and the staggering enlargement

of smelting furnaces on a scale fifty times bigger than earlier, more

customary sizes paved the way for transportation changes that

were to open the most remote areas of the country to industrialization and “commodification.”

The men who invented the textile machines and prime movers

that powered them were plebeians and, by no means accidentally

within the context of modern English history, included a sprinkling of very pious individuals, even clergymen. Watt was an instrument maker; Hargreaves, an engineer; Arkwright, a barber;

and relegate the past, with all its humane as well as barbarous traditions, to a

historical “junk heap.” Eventually socialism, like Puritanism, was to be deprived

of all its ethical content and turned into a doctrine very much like the egoistic

political economy of the industrial bourgeoisie itself.

Crompton, an ordinary textile worker; and Cartwright, a minister,

who went on to work with Robert Fulton in the development of

the steamship. English society had opened itself, more than most

European societies, to advancement by individuals in the “lower

classes/’ Moreover, many of the inventors whose work introduced

the Industrial Age were to become major capitalists in their right.

Only a few exhibited the breadth of spirit that characterized Robert Owen, a textile manufacturer who demonstrated at New Lanark that relatively humane conditions for workers did not conflict

with the acquisition of high profits and later placed his life and his

fortune in the service of the rising labor movement.

The transportation revolution that paralleled the Industrial

Revolution is of monumental proportions in the development of

modern capitalism itself, a revolution that a century and a half

later was to turn into a “communications revolution” whose

effects have yet to be fully grasped. During the first forty years of

the nineteenth century, Scotland, much of which had been an

untamed “hinterland” only two generations earlier, was interlaced by nearly a thousand miles of good roads and an even larger

number of bridges. This was largely “the work of private enterprise,” Engels tells us, “the State having done very little in this

direction.”{78} Indeed by 1844 England, apart from Scotland, had

well over two thousand miles of canals, substantially in excess of

its navigable river mileage. Finally, the early railroad fines that

finked Manchester to Liverpool, were rapidly extended across the

entire industrial midlands, sweeping in Lancester, Sheffield,

Leeds, Newcastle, and, of course, London further to the south.

English industrial and commercial towns, too, exploded in sifee

and population. Within the first thirty or forty years of the nineteenth century, Birmingham increased its inhabitants from 73,000

to 200,000; Sheffield from 46,000 to 110,000; Halifax from 63,000

to 110,000; Leeds from 53,000 to 123,000. Such astonishing rates

of growth among comparatively small communities in so short a

time had never been seen before in European history. The congestion and diseases they produced have been fully chronicled in the

novels as well as the histories of the period. For the first time, apart

from a few cosmopolitan centers in antiquity and perhaps some

Flemish and Italian towns in medieval times, we begin to see the

authentic devouring of cities, not only the countryside, by urbanization. Birmingham, Sheffield, Halifax, and Leeds, among many

others in England, were beginning to lose their identity as cities

in any classical meaning of the term. Their factories, sprawling out

into the countryside, were phasing into urban agglomerations,

sweeping in villages and small towns that had existed with relatively little change for centuries. William Wylde’s panoramic

painting of Manchester in 1851 reveals a forest of smokestacks and

a dense collection of squalid dwellings, a new, formless, and repellent urban world that industrial capital began to introduce into the

world—first in England, then in France, Belgium, Germany, and,

of course, across the Atlantic where the grimmest images of Pittsburgh as a steel-making center seem interchangeable with

Wylde’s picture of Manchester as a textile center generations earlier.

Yet, what is very important about this period of rampant industrialization is the fact that the more commercial and administrative cities of England and even the industrial towns that blighted

the island’s landscape were to develop a communal character of

their own. Growing industry, commerce, and “commodification”

did not seep completely into the neighborhood fife of the new

cities, nor did it totally destroy the conditions for the regeneration

of domestic fife. The buffeting that towns and cities of the nineteenth century took from industrialization, however disastrous its

initial effects on traditional fife ways, did not destroy the inherently villagelike subcultures of workers and middle-class people

who were only a generation or two removed from a more rural

culture. Like the ethnic groups that entered the New World

through New York City throughout much of the nineteenth and

early twentieth centuries, displacement was followed by resettlement and recommunafization, even in the most desperately poor

slums of the overpopulated cities of Europe and America. The pub

in the industrial cities of England, the cafe in France, and the beer

hall in Germany, no less than the various community centers

around which the ethnic ghettos formed in New York and other

American cities, provided foci for a distinctly working-class culture, largely artisan in its outlook, class-oriented in its politics, and knitted together by mutual self-help groups.

This recolonization of community life was greatly abetted by

the organized labor movement in all its different forms. Socialist

clubs, trade-union centers, local cooperatives, mutual-aid societies, and educational groups created a public space that included

classes in reading, writing, literature, and history. The socialist

clubs and union centers provided libraries, periodicals, lectures,

and discussion groups to “elevate” worker consciousness as well as

mobilize them for political and economic ends. Picnics, athletic

activities, outdoor forays into the countryside served to add a very

intimate dimension to purely educational projects. The *casas del pueblo* established by Spanish socialists and the *centros obreros*

established by the Spanish anarchists, which existed up to the late

1930s, are reminders of the vigorous development of community

life even in the most depressed areas of Europe—indeed, of an

“underground” culture that always paralleled the received culture of the elite orders and classes.

There was always a plebeian cultural domain at the base of

society, even in the most dismal and squalid parts of ancient,

medieval, or modern cities, that was beyond the reach of the

conventional culture and the state apparatus. No economy or state

had the technical means, until very recently, to freely infiltrate

this domain and dissolve it for a lasting period of time. Left to

itself, the “underground” world of the oppressed remained a

breeding ground for rebels and conspirators against the prevailing

authority. No less urban in character than agrarian, it also remained a school for a grass-roots politics that, by definition, involved groups of ordinary people, even in sizable communities, in

a plebeian political sphere and often brought them into outright

rebellion. This “underground” school created new political forms

and new citizens to deal with changing social conditions. Even

after the great boulevards of Baron Haussmanri ripped into the

plebeian *quartiers* of Paris, opening the city to artillery fire and

cavalry charges against barricades, the sizable neighborhood

pockets left behind retained an imperturbable rebellious vitality

that finally culminated in the Paris Commune. Few of Europe’s

major cities were spared crowd actions and uprisings in the nineteenth century, indeed well into the first half of the twentieth. As

industrial capitalism spread out from England into western

Europe and America, the initial destabilization it produced as a

result of urbanization and mechanization was followed by a regeneration of popular culture along new patterns that also included

the integration of old ones. Just as the French village was reproduced as *quartiers* in French cities and the Spanish *pueblo* as

and “Little Irelands” were reproduced in altered form but with

much Of their cultural flavor, personal intimacies, and traditional

values in world cities such as New York. Even the industrial cities

replicated on a local basis the specific cultural origins of their

variegated populations and regions.

The elaboration of the Industrial Revolution into a textile economy in England, a luxury goods economy in France, an electrochemical economy in Germany (itself a second industrial revolution in the last half of the nineteenth century), and an automotive

economy in America did not eliminate this “underground” communal world. Which is not to say that any of the countries cited

above did not also, expand economically and technologically into

the key industries that distinguished each from the other. But the

textile manufacturing that catapulted England into the world

market and even helped to make it; the fashioning of luxury goods

that gaye France, especially Paris, its distinction as the artistic

center of the world; and the mass production of electrochemical

commodities and automobiles by Germany and the United States,

respectively, which finally began to transform the world into its

present form—all seemed to carry over into the popular culture

and give it specific national features. We find a fixidity in England

along industrial lines that appears in its conventional and underground cultures as well: a strong system’of orders, open enough

to add titles to the names of its gifted plebeians but consciously

hierarchical in its cultural and social structure with a tendency to.

retain social status and elaborate it along stable lines. The intellectuality of France, expressed by its esthetic emphasis in industrial

production, carried over into the popular culture as a discursive

politics that nourished an ideologically innovative working class,

largely ar tisanal in its outlook but with all the intellectuality of that

stratum. Germany, which seems to have straddled the hierarchical

culture of England and the intellectual culture of France, gave rise

to a philosophically inclined popular Culture that took pride in its

academic spokesmen as surely as English workers were endeared

to noblemen who often spoke on their behalf. The pragmatism

and dynamism of American culture, with its strong republican

values, carried into the popular culture as various images of the

“American Dream,” partly utopian, partly materialistic, in which

the automobile symbolized enhanced sexuality together with freedom of movement, both socially upward and territorially outward.

This symbolism was to shape American architecture and city planning by producing the first skyscrapers and the most sprawling,

homogeneous “cities” of the twentieth century, even if one includes London.

Yet every class culture was always a community culture, indeed

a civic culture—a fact that finks the period of the Industrial Revolution and its urban forms with precapitalist cultures of the past.

This continuity has been largely overlooked by contemporary socialists and sociologists. While the factory and mill formed the first

fine of the class struggle in the last century, a struggle that in no

way should be confused with the class war that is supposed to yield

working-class insurrections, its fines of supply reached back into

the neighborhood and towns where workers lived and often mingled with middle-class people, farmers, and intellectuals. Wage

earners had human faces, not merely mystified proletarian

faces, and functioned no less as human beings than class beings.

Accordingly, they were fathers and mothers, brothers and sisters,

sons and daughters, citizens and neighbors, not only “factory

hands.” Their concerns included issues such as war and peace,

environmental dislocation, educational opportunities, the beauty

of their surroundings as well as its ugliness, and in times of international conflict, a heavy dose of jingoism and nationalism—indeed

a vast host of problems and concerns that were broadly human,

not only class-oriented and rooted in wages and working conditions.

This communal dimension of the industrial era is of tremendous

importance in understanding how class conflicts often spilled over

beyond economic issues into broadly social, even utopian, concerns. Indeed as long as the market did not dissolve the communal

dimension of industrialism, there was a richly fecund, highly

diversified, cooperative, and innovative domain of social and political fife to which the proletariat could retreat after working hours,

a domain that retained a vital continuity with precapitalist fife-ways and values. This partly municipal, partly domestic domain

formed a strong countervailing force to the impact of an industrial

economy and the nation-state. Here, workers mingled with a great

variety of individuals, particularly artisans, intellectuals, and farmers who brought their produce into the towns. In a purely human

fashion that revealed all the facets of their personalities, they

developed a sense of shared, active citizenship. This communal or

municipal citizenship kept political fife alive even in highly centralized and bureaucratized nation-states. It would be difficult to

understand not only the radical uprisings of the nineteenth century but also the twentieth—particularly the series of urban and

agrarian uprisings that culminated in the Spanish Civil War—without keeping this communal dimension of the “class struggle”

clearly in mind. Every class movement from the late eighteenth

to the early twentieth centuries was also a civic movement, a

product of neighborhood, town, and village consociation, not only

the factory, farm, and office. It was not until a technology developed that could make deep, perhaps decisive, inroads into this

“underground” municipal domain that politics and citizenship

were faced with the total “commodification” of society, the supremacy of statecraft, and the subversion of the city’s ecological

diversity and creativity.

----

The older generation of our time is still too close to the present and

the younger too far from the past to realize the extent to which

communal, precapitalist cultural traditions permeated the first

half of the twentieth century. Nor do we fully realize how rapidly

these traditions are being simplified and the extent to which they

are disappearing in the second half of the century, largely as a

result of sweeping technological and cultural developments that

occurred during the Second World War and its aftermath. Science

systematically applied to technics has only recently revealed the

deepest secrets of matter and fife with nucleonics and bioengineering. We are just making contact with the possibilities opened

by cybernetics, space travel, and communications systems for public surveillance, not to speak of mass “mind bending” with techniques that will make conventional advertising methods seem

childish and means of detection that will make fingerprints seem

primitive.

The psychological implications of these chilling advances are as

significant as their cultural and institutional ones. The military

armamentorium they have produced is as disempowering to the

individual as it is frightening to the public. The result is that the

ego itself tends to become passive, disembodied, and introverted

in the face of a technological and bureaucratic gigantism unprecedented, indeed unimaginable, in earlier human history. Public

life, already buffeted by techniques for engineering public consent, tends to dissolve into private life, a form of mere survivalism

that can easily take highly sinister forms. Citizenship, in turn,

tends to retreat into an increasingly trivialized egoism in which

banal conversation and venal pursuits replace searching discourse

and rebellious demands. Even more than ordinary individuals, the

people of mind and art who formed for ages the troubled conscience of past societies and were deeply engaged in public life as

the principal catalysts for achieving the good society—in short,

those socially involved thinkers whom the Russians of the last

century called the *intelligentsia*—retreat into the confines of the

academy and are transformed into mere intellectuals. Research

tends to replace creative speculation; libraries tend to replace the

cafes that nourished a Diderot; classrooms replace the squares that

brought a Desmoulins to the surface of public life; the academic

conference and its journals replace the clubs and presses that

provided the public forum for a Thomas Paine.

Industrial capitalism in the nineteenth century treated a market economy in which production and exchange still formed a

layer;of social life, not a substitute for society. The “cash nexus”

that Marx and Engels regarded as the core of the new economy

in *The Communist Manifesto*—culturally as well as commercially—was evidence more of their foresight than a description of the f

actual conditions of their times. Important barriers stood between

the penetration of the “cash nexus” created by the factory and by

commerce into the community and domestic life, where the oppressed in all their different forms and even the agrarian squirearchy seethed with hatred of the new economy. The Speenhamland Law, which English country squires passed in the 1790s to

provide the material means for keeping the rural population out

of the emerging factory system, reveals the stronghold precapitalist patronal traditions had on a society in the very midst of the Industrial Revolution.

What is Unique about the post-World War II era, now unfolding

four decades after tbe war’s end, is that the market *economy* to

which industrial capitalism gave a firm and dominant productive

base is turning into a *market society*. The “cash nexus” has become

an all-embracing commodity nexus in which consumption, not

only production, has become an end in itself. Objects now mediate

nearly all the social relationships that once had a living and creative flesh-and-blood character. Popular culture, which meant the

disdained culture produced from below by the people, has now

become “pop culture,” the synthetic “culture” generated from

above by the mass manufacture of books, sounds, pictures, movies,

radio shows, and, above all, television “goodies”—from news to

situation comedies, soap operas, and even serialized novels that

transfix millions of viewers to their “tubes.” Human relationships

are increasingly defined in terms of material things and expressed

in a commercial vernacular—be it marriage as an “investment,”

child rearing as a “job,” life as a “balance sheet,” ideals as things

one “buys,” and community as a “business.” The notion that towns

and cities should be “managed” by “entrepreneurs” as though the

civic bond has no dimensions to it other than its “efficiency” in

coordinating “services” and its capacity for generating “revenues” permeates the language not only of bankers, merchants,

politicians, and retailers but even liberal and—most tellingly—socialist public officials. Social life, so conceived and lived in the

form of marriage, child rearing, education, friendship, conviviality, entertainment, culture, and values, reveals a degree of commodity penetration and commercialism unprecedented even in

the halcyon days of “free trade” and capitalist production.

Which is not to say that the period following the Second World

War did not have its preludes in the pre-war era. Technologically,

the radio and particularly the cinema had a strong grip on popular

culture throughout the twenties and thirties. The automobile and

the vast economy created were already part of American life well

before the outbreak of the war. Mercifully, the Great Depression

of the 1930s froze this development for a decade, and the war

aborted it for an added five years while the world reverted to the

barbarism of organized slaughter and urban demolition. The assembly line was a portent of what was soon to come as was the

increasing wedding of science to technology, which the war put

on a thoroughly systematic basis.

But there was much that these pre-war preludes to the post-war

era left untouched. The Depression had given a bad name to

capitalism and placed its legitimacy in grave doubt. This loss of

faith stimulated a sweeping drift toward cultural and social movements that challenged the system’s integrity and claims to meet

human needs. Agrarian life still had a strong base in American and

French society, even as depression foreclosures reduced its economic significance. As late as 1929, twenty-five percent of the

employed labor force in the United States owned or worked labor-intensive farms that had changed very little from the last century.

Approximately three-fourths of American agricultural produce

was sold at home. Although tractors were beginning to appear in

growing numbers, horses were still in wide use and kerosene was

still a major fuel for illuminating farm homes. Culturally, agrarian

values were very much alive in America. They were embodied in

the high proportion of immigrants from the villages of eastern

Europe, Italy, and Ireland, and in the yeoman farmers who were

being scattered throughout the continent by the dust storms that

swept over middle America.

The Depression, in fact, witnessed a remarkable regeneration

of precapitalist agrarian values. The end of the First World War

had seen a cultural mystification of urbanism and substantial migrations of young people from rural areas to cities. Songs such as

“How Can You Keep Them Down on the Farm After They’ve

Seen ‘Par-ee!’ ” typified a glorification of urban lifestyles in the

1920s. The rural “hick,” once conceived as the source of America’s

sturdy republican values and the “pioneer” of continental settlement, had become a caricature in the cartoons, literature, and

cinema of the twenties, a “country-cousin” bumpkin who would

do well to conceal his identity in the “big city.” This remarkable

change in the historical imagery of Americans reflected the ascendancy of the industrial city and the modern age over the small town and the Jeffersonian age—in short, the cosmopolitan capitalistic era over the parochial precapitalist era.

The Depression decade reversed this imagery dramatically. For

millions of unemployed or economically uncertain Americans,

capitalism was patently not a working system. For all the hoopla

about the decline of socialism as a movement from its high point

in the period immediately preceding the First World War, it is

worth recalling that Norman Thomas, the presumed heir of Eugene V. Debs, received 900,000 votes in 1932 as the Socialist

Party’s presidential candidate, a figure that comes very close to

Debs’s highest vote some fifteen years earlier. The Depression

reversed the migration from farm to city, at least until the dust

storms of later years drove many farmers to other parts of the

country. Rural culture also began to thrive in the mass media of

the decade, particularly as an evocation of community values,

mutual aid, and compassion for less fortunate people. The extraordinary degree of social vitality that marked the 1930s stands in

marked contrast to the socially devitalizing selfishness of the

1920s, which celebrated Calvin Coolidge’s maxim: “America’s

business is business”—and, one might reasonably add, let morality

go to the devil. Social justice, not personal venality, rings through

the thirties as the motif of the radical left and radical right. Indeed,

for much of the political spectrum, the business ethic was relegated to damnation together with the values of the twenties,

which to many Americans had brought on the crises of the thirties.

Characteristically, the cinematic foppery of the twenties and

early thirties began to give way to movies that focused on such

themes as poverty, unionism, justice, and the pristine values of

agrarian lifeways. Even where capitalists are shown in a benign

light, such as in *The Devil and Miss Jones*, businessmen were seen

as converts to the new humanitarianism and the high sense of

public responsibility that marked the decade. Others, like

precapitalist rural values and vilified the rich, hypostasizing the

face-to-face simplicity and high moral sense of the small town. The

rural community was set ethically against the spiritual poverty and

cynicism of the city. A cultural populism swept over America after

1935 that has no parallel with any time before the 1890s, one that

gave to community, public service, political idealism, and social

justice a premium that makes the decade unique in twentieth-century American history.

To a leftist of the 1930s, it seemed that industrial capitalism had

reached its economic, social, and cultural limits; that from an ascending society, it had begun to descend historically, just as feudalism did centuries earlier. The Depression held on doggedly up

to the Second World War; indeed, in the judgement of some

economists, the closing years of the thirties appeared to be drifting

into a new economic crisis comparable to or worse than the one

that had darkened the decade’s opening years. Technological advance, saddled by the inertial weight of an increasingly monopolistic economy, seemed to have come to a virtual end. The monographs of the Temporary National Economic Committee of the

late thirties, established to assess the growth and effects of business

concentration in the United States, were filled with citations of

technological stagnation, indeed the suppression of technical innovations that made for higher productivity and lower prices.

That these innovations, seen as a source of economic instability

and oligarchic control, had been generally arrested was’ cited by

the literature of the time as evidence of a “decline” of capitalism

itself and as proof of the Marxian thesis that “bourgeois social

relations” stood in a “historical contradiction” to the “mode of

production.” Capitalism, it was argued by liberals and leftists alike,

was incapable of furthering the “productive forces” of society and could no longer play a “historically progressive” role.

Yet there were also harbingers of significant tendencies counteractive to the radical analyses that marked the decade. Rural

electrification was to basically alter the traditional agrarian life-ways that the Depression decade celebrated. It brought the radio

into the home and exposed a socially pristine population to the

mass media. The spate of public works that marked the Roosevelt

era opened roads into the remaining hinterlands of the continent

and the automobile culture improved existing roads for engine-powered vehicles. The great federal highway system of a later

generation was to give, the *coup de grĂące* to regional isolation and

network the entire country with a remarkable road system that all

but obliterated centuries-old cultural variations and customs. Distance and time were being overcome by the internal combustion

engine, whether by rail, road, or air.

Finally, the need for state intervention into a failing “free enterprise” economy vastly strengthened the nation-state and enlarged its bureaucratic apparatus. Rural life, however much it was

celebrated culturally, was being locked into urban life and the city

increasingly placed in a position subordinate to the nation-state.

Business, too, was becoming concentrated and centralized. By

1929, nearly half of American industrial wealth was controlled by

200 large corporations and by 1932, despite the ravages of the

Depression—or perhaps because of them—600 corporations controlled nearly two-thirds of the country’s industrial economy.

Politically and economically, power was to concentrate and centralize into fewer hands, linked together by an endless number of

bureaus, bureaucrats, and shared interests that were to prepare

the way for the “technobureaucratic” nation-state so characteristic of our own time.

The Second World War, while holding the values of die thirties

somewhat in place during the first half of the forties, foisted another Industrial Revolution on western society whose scope, as we

are now beginning to see, rivals the shift of humanity from a

hunting-gathering society to an agricultural one. By 1946, the

technical basis had been created for a world that men and women

of the thirties could never have anticipated. Electronics, nuclear

power, giant strides in biochemical research, and the sophistication of rocket propulsion, not to speak of less visible but monumental advances in physics, chemistry, and biology that were tb yield

revolutionary applications of scientific knowledge to industry,

were to totally change the economic landscape. Political change

for “total war” had already given rise in Europe to a new phenomenon in the west—the totalitarian state—beside which royal absolutism seems in retrospect like a feeble thing. The population

dislocations created by military mobilization as well as war refugees, followed by the expansion of migration of industry to the

western United States, and the pouring of billions into European

reconstruction, vastly transformed the urban landscape. Los Angeles, a “small” city in the thirties by present-day standards, became the “paradigm” for unlimited, unplanned, and sprawling

urbanization with its individual anomie, and a predatory form of

capitalistic enterprise that overshadowed the “Roaring Twenties,”

with its naive imagery of personal greed and vice. The fifties

introduced a more anonymous and faceless phenomenon: corporate greed and commercialized vice, the marketing of managerialism and suburban self-indulgence (material as well as sexual) as a

new way of life and a new set of values.

Cities were to lose not only their territorial form; they were to

to lose their cultural integrity and uniqueness.

managerial bureaucratism, despite the movie’s tribute to suburban family fife. Social justice, idealism, and agrarian values of

community gave way to privatization, self-indulgence, and suburban cookouts. The desiderata of a corporate age, its synthetic and

highly personalized culture, was a sanitized and socially vacuous

world, held together not by the “underground” culture of past

centuries but by an “above-ground” culture engineered by government and corporations. A mass society, notable for its de-spiritualized and amoral version of “possessive individualism” had

emerged from the debris of the thirties, a mass society structured

around television networks, counseling offices, bureaucratic agencies, and, above all, commodities. The market society had begun

to come into its own, destructuring the city, the domestic world,

the psyche, and ultimately the natural world. “Man,” brought into

collision with “man” in a highly competitive world mediated by

commodities, was finally brought into collision with nature on a

scale unprecedented in history.

Urbanization may be taken as the symbol and the reality of this

historic ecological disarray of the modern landscape—indeed this

reversal of the evolutionary clock—from organic to synthetic

human and biotic relationships. Nor can this disarray be sorted out

and pieced together on the summits of social fife. Historically, the

power of preindustrial fifeways to survive and preserve a moral

sense of social fife depended on the existence of an “underground”

culture in towns, neighborhoods, and cities—even during the stormiest periods of nation-building, industrialization, and “commodification”—to countervail the power of the market and the

official culture. They depended, in effect, upon the power of a

popular culture to resist the elite culture and, in no small part, on

the inability of the elite culture to successfully penetrate the popular one. The crisis of our time as expressed in the decline of political fife and citizenship, of community and individuality in the

classical sense of these concepts, stems from the invasion and

colonization of culture’s subterranean domain by a highly metastatic capitalistic technics and its commodities. Objectified and

fragmented, the social bond itself faces dissolution. What we call

the “grassroots” of society is turning into straw, and its soil—the

locality or municipality—is turning into sand. Whatever evidence

of “fertility” and “fife” these roots exhibit seems to be the result

of toxic chemicals—mass media, bureaucratic sinews, and

managerial controls—the nation-state and corporations seem to be

pouring into its bedrock, just as agribusiness generates “food” out

of the chemically saturated sponge we call “soil” today.

Redemption must come from below, from the municipal level

where the “underground” culture of past times flourished, not

from an “above” that constitutes the very source of the problems

we face. The “long march through the institutions,” which sixties

radicals such as Rudi Dutschke advocated in Germany and Herbert Marcuse evoked in America more than a decade ago, has

demonstrated that it is the institutions that ultimately absorb modern rebels, not the rebels who capture the institutions.

Urbanization, insofar as it still permits the city to retain any

identity, alters not only its form but its function as a civilizing

arena for humanity. The “stranger” who could once find a home

in the city and a role in its political fife as a citizen atavistically

reverts to his or her status as an alien. Ghettoization moves hand

in hand with urban sprawl, the dissolution of the self hand in hand

with the city’s dissolution. Bureaucracy fills the vacuum created by

the absence of an active community fife, notably the police officer

who is the last custodian of order in disintegrating neighborhoods

and the social worker who is the last custodian of order in domestic

life. Critically viewed, the social ecology of urbanization is the’

compelling story of the destructuring of all social life from home

to community, the erosion of heterogeneity, interaction, and civic

creativity. The return of the stranger expresses the change from

the “lonely crowd,” explored by David Reisman three decades ago

in his book of same name—indeed, to, the fearful crowd of today,

a crowd in which everyone moves guardedly through the modern

city with a sense of subdued dread toward surrounding people and

unfamiliar neighborhoods. As urbanization spreads, so too does

the state machinery needed to administer it. Whatever its form,

the nation : state increasingly approximates a totalitarian state and

the privatized individual, riddled by egoism and fear, increasingly

becomes more like one commodity among many rather than a

consumer. Ultimately, society threatens to become as inorganic as

an ecosystem that has been divested of its flora and fauna. When

totalitarianism eventually does emerge, it is likely that the coherent self, so direly needed to resist it, will have undergone such erosion that it may well lack the psychological resources to recognize the danger, much less oppose it.

Chapter Eight: The New Municipal Agenda

From the moment nomadic hunter-gatherers began to settle down

into stable villages, they introduced radically new changes that go

beyond the turn’from food gathering to food cultivation. Where

villages became towns, human beings began to “detribalize”

themselves, and create those civic institutions we associate with

“civilization/’ The blood tie, the male-female divisions in functions, and status groups based on age formed the sinews of tribalism and were slowly absorbed into an entirely new social dispensation: the city. Cities were to be structured primarily around

residence, a vocational division of labor, and a variety of “orders”

and classes, some of which were united by economic interests but

others by power and prestige. The biological facts of blood, sex,

and age, in effect, began to slowly phase into the social facts of

propinquity, Vocation, wealth, and privilege.

Out of this sweeping historical transformation, new ways of

ordering life began to emerge. The biological realm of life, seemingly “natural” in its origins, became what we normally regard as

the social: the realm in which people formed to meet their material needs, to reproduce as well as produce, to “relate” with each

other as individuals and family groups, to fraternize in a variety

of personal associations and degrees of intimacy. The town and

city, even the village, provided a political realm of life, human-made in origins, in which individuals related to each other as

citizens in order to manage their communities and cope with its

“civic” affairs. Until comparatively recent times, to be sure, “biological” and political realms overlapped significantly so that political elites such as aristocracies legitimated their authority over

towns and cities by the highly tribalistic claims of ancestry and

genealogy. Until the Emperor Caracalla made all free men in the

Roman Empire citizens of the state, citizenship was largely regarded as an ancestral privilege. The rights it conferred to citizens

in the management of the community were marked by various

degrees of ethnic exclusivity.

But the city, initially the Hellenic *polis*, created a new social

dispensation: minimally, a territorial space in which the “stranger” or “alien” could reside with a reasonable degree of protection—later even a measure of participation—that few tribal communities allowed to outsiders, however hospitably they were treated.

Two new civilizatory categories—politics and citizenship—began

to absorb the largely biosocial forms that held early familial and

tribal lifeways together.

The professionalization of power and violence that we associate

with the state came much later. Indeed, in its national form it is

a fairly recent phenomenon. State and the practice of statecraft

has no authentic basis in community life—by which I mean that,

until recently, the acquisition of power by professionals encountered the greatest difficulty in legitimating itself. Tribal institutions can be easily understood because human beings are, after all,

natural organisms. They must feed themselves, acquire their

means of subsistence, reproduce, live in safety, and, given their

evolution as primates, engage in some kind of communal intercourse. In contradistinction to other animals, however, they organize these activities into institutions and make them operationally

systematic—hopefully rational, predictable, and ideologically legitimate. Animals, including the genetically programmed “social

insects,” do not have institutions, however habituated and predictable their behavior may be; in short, they do not have consciously

formed ways of ordering their communities that are continually

subject to historical change.

It is important to distinguish the social in humanity from the

political and, still further, the political from the statist. We have

created a terrible muddle by confusing the three and thereby

legitimating one by mingling it with the other. This confusion has

serious consequences for the present and future. We have lost our

sense of what it means to be political by assigning political functions and prerogatives to “politicians,” actually to a select, often

elite, group of people who practice a form of institutional manipulation called statecraft. Inasmuch as many politicians are viewed

with a certain measure of contempt, we have degraded the concept of politics—once a participatory dimension of societal life and

the activity of an entire community—by confusing it with statecraft, a distinctly power-oriented form of activity. Accordingly, we

have lost our sense of what it means to be a citizen, a status we

increasingly accept as mere “constituents” or, worse, voters and

taxpayers who are the passive recipients of the goods and services

provided to us by an all-powerful state and our “elected” representatives.

Ideologically, we tend to justify this historical degradation of

our status as political beings by invoking the “nation” as the basic

and most elemental unit of social life, an entity that is itself of very

recent origin. That nations are made up of cities, towns, and villages on which our well-being, culture, and security ultimately

depend has begun to elude us and slip from our consciousness. It

remains a lasting contribution of Jane Jacobs to have demonstrated

in a very compelling way that our economic well-being depends

on cities, not on nation-states; indeed that while nations may be

“political and military entities it doesn’t necessarily follow from

this that they are also the basic, salient entities of economic life or

that they are particularly useful for probing the mysteries of economic structure, the reasons for rise and decline of wealth.... We

can’t avoid seeing, too, that among all the various types of economies, cities are unique in their abilities to shape and reshape the

economies of other settlements, including those far removed from

them geographically.”{79} We may leave aside Jacobs’s conventional

use of such words as politics, her imagery of the economy as a

strictly market, indeed, a capitalistic economy, and her strongly

economistic interpretation of cities primarily as centers of production and exchange. Her argument invites a debate about the

superfluity of the state that has been too long neglected, and her

examples can only be ignored for the most dubious ideological

reasons.

A close reading of history has demonstrated that the state—and,

in our own time, the nation-state—is not only the repository of

agents and institutions that have made a mockery of politics; it

shows, in fact,’ that these state agents and institutions have degraded the individual as a public being, as a citizen who plays a

‘ participatory role in the operations of his or her community. In

this respect, the nation-state has impeded the development of

much that is uniquely human in human beings^ disempowering

the individual and rendering him or her a warped and self-degraded being. ’

It is equally demonstrable that the state—and, again, the nation-state—parasitizes the community, denuding it of its resources

and its potential for development. It does this partly by draining

the community of its material and spiritual resources; partly, too,

by steadily divesting it of the power, indeed of its legitimate right,

to shape its own destiny. Despite recent rhetoric to the contrary,

nothing has seemed more challenging to the state than demands

for local self-management and civic liberty. Decentralization, a

term that is often abused these days for the most cynical ends of

statecraft, is not merely rich in geographic, territorial, and political values; it is eminently a spiritual and cultural value that links

the reempowerment of the community with the reempowerment

of the individual.

Municipal freedom, in short, is the basis for political freedom

and political freedom is the basis for individual freedom—a recovery of a new participatory politics structured around free, self-empowered, and active citizens. For centuries, the city was the

public sphere for politics and citizenship, and in many areas the

principal source of resistance to the encroachment of the nation-state. In its acts of defiance it often delayed the development of

the nation-state and created remarkable forms of association to

counteract the state’s encroachment upon municipal freedom and

individual liberties.

----

The case for the nation-state today is almost entirely logistical and

administrative. Social life, we are normally told, is too “complex”

to allow for municipal autonomy and participatory citizenship.

This argument does not stand up very well against historical and

contemporary evidence. Fascinating examples can be found of

economic and political coordination within and between communities that render statecraft and the nation-state utterly superfluous.

Aside from Hellenic, Italian, medieval German, and Castilian

endeavors, one of the most lasting are the Swiss communes whose

practice of using local resources without turning them into private

property was to be an object of fascination for generations to

visitors in the mountain areas of central Europe. These communes

and the confederations they formed for their common welfare, and

safety seem to have absorbed almost tribalistic forms of intimacy

into their practices, even attitudes that Viewed sharing according

to need rather than work into their ways of dealing with material

goods. According to some accounts, the word “land,” which was

often open to use by all who needed it, included streams, clay pits,

quarries, or, in H. Mooseburger’s words, “the entire region with

every and all its products and fruits.”{80} Let me emphasize that this

was a municipal form of “ownership” about which we shall have

more to say later, riot the nationalized forms advocated by Marxian socialists, the “economic democracy” advanced by many liberals, or systems of “workers’ control” demanded by orthodox

anarchists—all of which, I may add, involve some degree of state

involvement or a particularistic and potentially competitive body

of interests within the community, however collectively “owned”

or, democratically “managed” an enterprise may be.

The Gray Leagues (**Graubunden**), the source of the Swiss referendum and the town meetings of its 222 communes, have to be singled out as the most libertarian of all. Until Napoleon forced it

into the Swiss Confederation, the *Freistaat der Drei Bunde* (literally, the Free State of the Three Leagues) arid specifically the

Graubund itself, the league that give its name to the confederation of the three leagues that composed it, was to exist for nearly

three centuries (1524–1800) and place its distinctly decentralistic

imprint on Switzerland as a whole. This Free State “was not

merely democratic,” observes Benjamin Barber in his superb account of the league and its standards of community freedom. The

fact is that “it was democratic in a particular way not easily accounted for by the conceptual perspective of Anglo-American

thought... **Graubunden**’s experience with democracy has been

inseparable from its experience with community, and as a model

of integral community, no region of Switzerland can equal

it”{81}

Barber’s conclusions cannot be emphasized too strongly. What

they concretely indicate is that the ultimate source of sovereignty

reposed in the commune—the village, town, and city—whose assent or opposition to a course of action was achieved by referendum. The confederal system that united the communes had the

right to deal with foreign affairs, and little more. Beyond this

sphere, confederal bodies were concerned mainly with preventing their component leagues from making foreign alliances on

their own than with any formulation of foreign policy. Issues such

as war and peace were decided directly by the communes themselves. “The only instrument of the central government was a

three-man commission (*Haupter*) made up of the heads of each of

the leagues that, with the assistance of an elective assembly (*Beytag*), prepared the referendum and executed the will of the communes,” Barber tells us. “In the new structure power was an

inverse function of level of organization. The central ‘federal’

government had almost none, the regional communes had a great

deal.”{82} Whatever its capacity to deal with the problems that confronted the Free State, the people were provided “with several

centuries of real thoughtful independence and a measure of autonomous self-government rare in Germanic Europe.”

The challenges faced by the Free State and its component

leagues over these centuries require a lengthy study of the kind

provided by Barber. The problem of dealing with foreign intervention; the incorporation of sizable towns and the expansion of

older ones into cities; the disparities in status, wealth, and power

that developed, not to speak of local parochialism at one extreme

and cosmopolitian “modernity” at the other, were never fully

resolved. But they were held in remarkable balance for most of

the Free State’s history. Even after Napoleon had reduced the

Free State to a canton in the more centralized Swiss Confederation, Barber notes that the peasant still turned the harshness of his

sparse land “into a discipline of individuality, a teacher of autonomy. He held the intuitive conviction that his rural mountain life,

his uncomplicated involvement in a pastoral economy that left

him considerable leisure time, was inextricably bound up with his

independence and his freedom.”{83}

By no means should this strong sense of individuality be mistaken for the “individualism” associated with traditional “natural

law” ideologues and the modern-day proprietary emphasis on

egoism. The hardships inflicted on Alpine dwellers, locked in a

glacial land of heavy snowfalls, avalanches, and floods, placed a

high premium on “collective labor and common decision making.

... Thus as the hardness of life molded a man’s sense of autonomy,

it also compelled him to cooperation and collective action.” As

Herman Weilenmann has put it, to the villagers of the **Graubunden** freedom involved “not individual emancipation from his obligations to the whole, but the right to bind himself by his own

choice.”{84} Neither the individual nor the collective, in effect,

claimed sovereignty over each other but rather they formed a

complementary relationship that supported each other.

These are abiding notions that are difficult for modern Euro-Americans to accept nowadays. Yet they are deeply rooted in the

American tradition itself. I refer more to the New England town

meeting tradition from which so many of the authentic libertarian

aspects of the “American Dream” derive rather than the “cowboy” tradition that presumably “tamed the West” and threatens

to reduce it to a battleground of sheer avarice. We are only now

becoming aware of the localist and communitarian motives that

drove Puritan settlers to New England. Religious persecution by

Charles I was only one of several reasons that the lives of the

Puritans were intolerable under the Stuart kings. “If Charles I is

remembered at all today, it is as an ineffectual monarch who lost

his head on the chopping block,” observes T. H. Breen, whose

work on Puritan institutions is perhaps one of the best that has

been published in recent years. “During the first years of his reign,

however, he brought considerable energy to his position. He instituted or tried to institute far-reaching changes in civil, ecclesiastical, and military affairs. These unprecedented, often arbitrary

policies disrupted the fabric of local society, and they were a major

preoccupation of the men and women who moved to Massachusetts Bay. One cannot fully understand the institutional decisions

that the colonists made in America unless one realizes how gravely

Stuart centralization threatened established patterns of daily life

in England’s local communities.”{85}

The men and women who formed the New England townships

of the seventeenth century sought not only to restore Christianity

to its “pure,” ecclesiastically untainted, biblical forms; they also

sought to restore society itself to its pristine, egalitarian, and devoutly communitarian patterns, presumably paralleling the ethical and social covenants that appear in “Acts” and the quasitribal

democracy of the Hebrew Bedouins and their compacts. A shared

assumption seemed to exist that the English town corresponded

to the Hebrew tribal community and that its restoration was a

necessary move toward social as well as religious purification.

Every community was conceived as an ethical compact, not simply a form of association for personal and collective survival—a

notion decidedly antithetical to the Hobbesian and Lockean principles that enter into liberal conceptions of republicanism as we

know them today. Men and women, in the Puritan world view,

formed communities to achieve a “good society” in the moral, not

merely the material, sense of the term: a society marked by virtue

as defined in Christian precept. Individual and community, in this

sense, were no less inseparable among the early colonists of New

England than they were among the villagers of the Swiss *Graubund*.

The stormy declamations of angry prophets such as Amos,

whom Ernst Bloch has so aptly called a “barn burner,” sear the

Puritan soul, and explain the institutional development of Puritan

communities. It was Charles I and his “ill-advised attempt to increase his authority by attacking local English institutions” who

appears as the Moloch in this drama, and the Puritan divines as the

prophets who denounced royal encroachments on the “liberties of

Englishmen,” to use the language of the day. Despite the diversity

of their origins, ranging from “populous commercial centers such

as London and Norwich” to “isolated rural communities ... most

had been affected in some personal way by the king’s aggressive

efforts to extend his civil and ecclesiastical authority ... The

experience of having to resist Stuart centralization, a resistance

that pitted small congregations against meddling bishops, incorporated boroughs and guilds against grasping courtiers, local train-bands against demanding deputy lieutenants, and almost everyone in the realm against the collectors of unconstitutional revenues, shaped the New Englanders’ ideas about civil, ecclesiastical,

and military polity. The settlers departed from England determined to maintain their local attachments against outside interference, and to a large extent the Congregational churches and self-contained towns of Massachusetts Bay stood as visible evidence of

the founders’ decision to preserve in America what had been

threatened in the mother country.”{86}

In view of the grim reputation the Puritan towns acquired as

dour “theocracies” and parochial, self-righteous, dogmatic nests of

intolerance, we must provide, with more nuance, a picture of their

variety, roundedness, and militancy—not simply as they existed at

any given moment in time but as they evolved, eventually to

become centers of social rebellion, civic autonomy, and collective

liberty. Nor can we ignore the strong-minded yeomanry they produced, the high sense of individuality and citizenship they nourished. We must bear in mind that these personal and social traits

persisted in New England for some three centuries—not as mere

historical ephemera that pass like wispy clouds across the social

horizon but as an established democratic legacy. No less ingrained

in the mythology of the American tradition than the reality of

business and its virtues, this legacy has always acted as a force

countervailing the egoistic sensibility fostered by reactionary nationalists and liberal centralists in other parts of America.

Let us quickly rid ourselves of the idea that this Yankee yeomanry was “tight-fisted,” “commercially oriented,” “grasping,”

and emotionally guarded. This imagery mistakes Boston, a commercially oriented and acquisitive port, for New England as a

whole. The port cities, in fact, often stood at odds with the many

small townships that were networked into the interior of the New

England colonies and states. These colonies and their interiors

were unique insofar as they were municipal entities, vital towns,

in contrast to other regions of America, which were generally

marked by dispersed settlements and farmsteads. Two facts

emerge that deserve emphasis. Firstly, Boston and other port cities in New England were no different in their outlook and interests

than Baltimore or Charleston, hence they were fairly atypical of

the Yankee spirit of the region. Indeed, they were no different as

commercial ports than port cities elsewhere in the world. Secondly, the fact that small towns could be planted so firmly, indeed, doggedly in New England’s thin, rocky, glaciated soil was an

act of ethical defiance, for the region is a poor agricultural area

that offers no congenial home for flourishing communities.

The towns and townships that emerged on the rocky soils of

Massachusetts, Connecticut, Rhode Island, and particularly New

Hampshire, Maine, and Vermont were a challenging moral statement of firm intentions to live in a very definite way, a structural

expression of what constitutes a virtuous life, not merely a bountiful one. Whereas Boston eventually visualized itself as the “New

World’s” counterpart of London, many New England townships

saw themselves as biblical communities, united by Old Testament

convenants that hypostasized simple living, a high regard for essentials over frivolities, fairness and mutuality in relationships,

egalitarianism in status, self-sufficiency in the development of

needs and their satisfaction, and more elaboration of communitarian values than fetishization of change. In short, they were

committed to a moral economy and society, not to lifeways premised on the market and gain.

We must look at these lifeways closely if we are to understand

the political institutions and economic relationships that expressed them and were designed to reinforce them. However

much these moral lifeways varied—owing, in part, to their ties

with the commercially oriented port cities—they were remarkably self-sufficient. I speak, here, of a world in which the yeomanry

comprised 70 percent of the agrarian population. Crops were cultivated mainly for survival rather than trade. As one yeoman

wrote in the 1770s, a farm gave “me and my whole family a good

living on the produce of it. Nothing to wear, eat or drink was

purchased, as my farm provided all.”{87} That surplus crops were

used to purchase manufactured goods such as iron, nails, glass,

weapons, gunpowder, and medicine does not alter the marginality

of commerce for most townships. Land utilization reflected the

domestic nature of the economy. It was very sparsely used despite

the large amount that was available for cultivation. Although yeomen often had fifty or more acres of land, generally only a fifth to

a tenth was actually put to pasture and food cultivation, and usually only for the family and its livestock. Women were engaged in

caring for the home, child rearing, making homespun clothing,

and other family and farm chores; men, in the also arduous tasks

of farming, woodcutting, and construction. Diversified crop cultivation is evidence of efforts to meet domestic more than market needs.

If anything, this yeomanry seems to have viewed commerce

disdainfully, indeed as parasitic and demeaning to a productive

and spiritually oriented way of life. In the words of the Bostonian,

George Richards Minot, writing in the 1780s, yeoman-landed

property “had always been held in higher esteem and more valuable nature than any personal estate.” Indeed, its “possession ... seems to be of greater gratification to the pride and independence of men.”{88} This image of agriculture, divested of acquisitive

and commercial ends, provided the New England farmer with a

sense of personal and ethical autonomy that made him eschew the

word “farmer” or “peasant” for “yeoman” or “husbandman,” an

example of the way in which men think of themselves that was to

profoundly alter their behavior and the course of history.

Yet as David P. Szatmary points out, “a feeling of independence

did not necessarily lead to individualism. Although priding themselves on their autonomy, yeomen lived in a community-oriented

culture. To ease their backbreaking work during planting and

harvesting, they asked family and friends for help. The independent status of yeomen, then, resulted neither from self-s uffi ciency

nor a basically competitive system but led, rather, to cooperative,

community-oriented interchanges.”{89} More concretely, this communal orientation brought women directly into food cultivation

and enhanced their social status, all talk of Puritan “patriarchy” to

the contrary notwithstanding. The enormous respect—and troubled concern—that made dissenters such as Anne Hutchinson the

center of religious and political controversy in the early years of

the colony attest to the forwardness of women in this society and

their enormous strength of character.

Barter and the sharing of resources reinforced neighborliness

and fostered a warmly hospitable openness to people, even to

newcomers, as the Marquis de Chastellex was to observe in his

tour of New England during the early 1780s. The all-encompassing egalitarianism that pervaded this yeoman world included even

agricultural laborers, a mere ten percent of the rural workforce,

who usually owned some land in their own right or were given

land in reward for their services. New England did not really have

a rural proletariat Indeed, disparities in wealth were too insignificant to give rise to a stable class society.

Out of this world emerged the town meeting, a direct democracy in which local and, in times of social unrest, broadly political

issues were fervently debated and resolved. Here, in contrast to

Swiss democracy, attempts to trace the New England town meeting back to Germanic tribal traditions may well be examples of

historical overkill. The immediate source of the town meeting lies

very much at hand. Puritans were mainly Congregationalists, a

form of Protestantism that denies by definition the need for any

ecclesiastical hierarchy or centralizing body. In this utterly anarchic conception of Christianity, all powers of religious interpretation belong to the local congregation, which is mystically united

to others of the same kind by the presence of Christ, a spiritual

metaphor rather than an institution. This radically decentralistic

interpretation of the community as an autonomous congregation

can easily extend outward into the civil, world in the form of an

equally autonomous political body, the town meeting. The periodic meeting of the entire male population of a community in

order to govern its own affairs is a logical outcome of Puritan

religious belief and forms of organization. Property and income

restrictions on the right to participate in town meetings were not

taken too seriously. Disparities in land ownership and the payment of taxes could have excluded only a small number of residents in most New England towns. In the more rural areas, these

restrictions counted for virtually nothing. By the 1760s, when

colonial unrest was to lead to outright revolution^ town meetings

were so notoriously open that even newly arrived or transient

residents could participate ih them. Historians who tend to tie

property qualifications to New England’s franchise system have

proven themselves to be sticklers for regulations that went unenforced two centuries ago or were essentially nonexistent.

The reaction to Charles I’s attempts to place localities under

centralized control and weaken local militias heightened the sensitivity of the New England towns to their autonomy and right to

bear arms. It is contemporary libel regarding the role of an armed

people to invoke the insecurities of the American frontier as an

excuse to ban arms ih the more “stable” and, presumably, more

“secure” society of our own day. By the late eighteenth century,

the New England states were largely free of Indian attacks. The

prevalent notion of a covenanted township and a covenanted militia had very little to do with personal safety. The yeomen of New

England were not so much in fear of Indian forays against their

persons as they were concerned with statist forays, against their

liberties. In one of the most radical state constitutions to be

adopted during the American Revolution, Vermont yeomen,

gathering at Windsor in July 1777, not only abolished slavery and

property qualifications for the franchise, they also avowed that “as

standing armies, in the time of peace, are dangerous to liberty,

they ought not to be kept up.” Accordingly, “the people have a

right to bear arms for a defense of themselves and the State,” a

right that explicitly goes far, beyond the reticent wording of ‘the

Second Amendment to the United States Constitution. These, sentiments reflected the yeomanry’s state of mind two-hundred years

ago. They had nothing to do with the West’s “gun slinging” and

its bullying machismo. Rather they expressed the sound conviction that the state cannot be trusted to claim a monopoly of violence over its citizenry and the full custody of public freedom.

Democracy, if it was to mean anything, presupposed the active

involvement of the citizen in developing a participatory politics,

public security, and the direct face-to-face resolution of community problems. Hacking the means and instruments, particularly

the weapons, to enforce its decisions, such a citizenry in the eyes

of the yeomanry would be reduced to a mere instrument of the

state, whose legitimacy in their eyes was extremely dubious.

The township formed the living repository of institutions such

as the town meeting and the militia. “When the eighteenth-century Yankee reflected on government,” observes Robert A. Gross,

“he thought first of his town. Through town meetings, he elected

his officials, voted his taxes, and provided for the well-ordering of

community affairs. The main business of the town concerned roads

and bridges, schools, and the poor—the staples of local government even today. But the colonial New England town claimed

authority over anything that happened within its borders. It hired

a minister to preach in the town-built meetinghouse and compelled attendance at his sermons. It controlled public uses of private property, from the location of slaughterhouses and tanneries

to the quality of bread sold at market. And it gave equal care to

the moral conduct of its inhabitants ... No issue was in theory

exempt from a town’s action, even if in practice the provincial

government occasionally intervened in local disputes and told the

inhabitants how to run their lives.”{90}

Not surprisingly, the town meeting in even more secular form

swept out of New England during the Revolution and was to

extend as far south as Charleston. With the end of the Revolution

itself, municipal “counterrevolutions” (to use the language of the

historians) essentially pushed it back to the region of its origin and

replaced municipal assemblies with mayors and aldermanic councils. New England and a number of towns bordering the region

tenaciously, even defiantly, held on to their democratic municipal

institutions, at least in the smaller towns and villages.

The “Founding Fathers” who fashioned the national constitution of 1788 created a fairly centralized republic, but they were

also obliged to tolerate a basically confederal, face-to-face municipal democracy within their instrument of government and a fairly

radical “Bill of Rights” that had been foisted upon them by a

restless yeomanry. The United States Constitution, in effect, expresses a precarious compromise between demands for a municipal democracy and a centralized nation-state. Running at cross

purposes throughout the document and the quasilegal “Declaration of Independence” are agrarian, precapitalist commitments to

freedom, a participatory politics, and an involved citizenry on the

one hand, and a distinctly capitalistic imagery of acquisitive individualism favored by the rising commercial elements in the port

cities and inland market towns of the new nation.

----

Having examined the yeoman world of New England in the eighteenth century, our account would be incomplete if we failed to

look at the urban commercial world that coexisted with it. It was

in this world that the seeds of urbanization were already planted.

Port cities and inland market towns of New England “lived in a

largely commercial culture,” notes Szatmary, “The market-oriented way of life included the drive toward acquisition and accumulation and emphasized the individual over the community.

Merchants, shopkeepers, professionals, commercial farmers,

urban artisans, sailors, and fishermen formed the most important

economic groups in this society. New England merchants, residing

in large port towns such as Boston, Newport, and Providence,

dominated and represented the most successful sector in the commercial culture. Handling and transporting farm goods, manufactured commodities, and, at times, human cargoes, they primarily

sought personal wealth. Such middlemen, although they worked

at as lower pace than modern industrialists, had the accumulation

of money as their primary goal.”{91}

Commerce and acquisitiveness, as I have emphasized, are not

new to the precapitalist world. What makes the merchant stratum

unique in the modern social landscape is that it funneled its earnings into its various enterprises and sought unceasingly to expand

them—partly as a response to the intense competition that existed

in new markets, partly in an effort to gain control of home markets. This difference between an acquisitive and expanding market economy on the one hand and precapitalist markets that were

not nearly as accumulative on the other is important. The yeomanry outside the cities bartered produce to meet its basic survival needs. The merchants within the city exchanged goods to

expand and absorb rivals. The simple commodity markets of the

village, even of many medieval communes, encountered cultural

constraints to growth that placed socially accepted moral limits on

the acquisition of wealth. Gilds and public opinion enforced these

limits hand-in-hand with religious precepts. Acquisition seemed

demonic rather than elevating. Hence trade could be held in

check and a mixed economy developed that maintained its integrity against the corrosive, homogenizing effects of an uncontrolled market economy.

By contrast, the rising capitalists of the eighteenth century in

their port and inland commercial towns removed virtually all of

these moral, public, and religious constraints to acquisition and

expansion. Even land, once the refuge of the ancient capitalists

from a life devoted to commerce, became a mere commodity so

that its acquisition in the eighteenth century, particularly in the

“New World,” conferred no special status on the new merchant

stratum.‘The Ohio Land Company, a speculative enterprise

formed in the late 1780s by New England and New York merchants, did not intend to cultivate any of the vast territories it

acquired on the western frontier. Its goal was “to profit from their

purchases through quick sales to incoming settlers.”{92} As one Boston lawyer put it in 1785: “Money is the only object attended to,

and the only acquisition that commands respect.”{93}

This monetary and speculative mentality, while not unprecedented historically, is unique when it acquires such complete centrality! What is significant here is that moneymaking became an

ethic such that prestige, personal integrity, indeed social status

depend upon the acquisition of capital, not upon the ownership of

land and the acquisition of titles. By the eighteenth century, the

new republican ethos of the cities was altered such that it placed

a high premium on the accumulation of money and the means for

making money, not on social position and. high living. The aristocratic values that had permeated merchant strata from time immemorial were replaced by acquisitive values, egoism, and a brutalizing appetite for profit. In such a highly acquisitive and

competitive economy, the virtues of community were subordinated to the value-of personal gain and capital expansion.

From an ethical association for mutual support community was

turned into an entrepreneurial nexus for competition and manipulation. This sweeping inversion of the very meaning of consociation and friendship has no precedent in human history. Whatever

else the seafaring warriors of the Bronze Age did during their acts

of brigandage or the merchants of the classical and feudal eras did

in their forays abroad, their own communities were seen as refuges from their predations, and they made lavish contributions to

civic beautification! The new merchant and particularly the industrialist who followed, began to view his own community as an

object of predation and often plundered it ruthlessly. This behavior, graduated to the level of the “business ethic,” began to supplant the religious precepts and cultural values that had been

passed on from time immemorial, even to earlier merchants and

entrepreneurs. Herein lay its enormous power: the ability to replace one set of ethical ideals with another, in short, to make gain

itself a value that could be used to countervail and ultimately

overcome all traditional constraints to asociality and predation.

Enveloping this distinctly antisocial form of individualism was a

new ideological support system: laws that gave an almost religious

sanction to contracts irrespective of their content and clerics who

legitimated gain as a heavenly calling. The courtierlike profligacy

and extravagance of French merchants and, the passion for titles’

that existed among English merchants, were dissolved by American merchants into an ethos of prudence, simple living, and the

embellishment of gain with the myth of “republican virtue.”

Let it be noted that this ethos did not roll over the new American republic like a moral tidal wave. Most of the country still adhered to yeoman values, albeit in a less communitarian form

than we still find among rural New England Yankees, Southern

plantation owners still held to aristocratic values that placed a

higher premium on consumption than acquisition. To spend one’s

substance in a grand fashion was the sign of a gentleman, in contrast to the craven acquisitiveness of the New England merchant.

On the frontier, material self-sufficiency and personal autonomy

were still ends in themselves, and the acquisition of wealth that

sent so many adventurers to the West in pursuit of gold originated

more in visions of luxurious living than capital expansion. It was

not until the Reconstruction Era following the Civil War that

American capitalism, seen as a system of growth for its own sake,

began to hypostasize all of these acquisitive values and steadily

destructure earlier institutional, ethical, and personal ideals.

Urbanization became the physical expression of this destructuring process, the way in which it assumed visibility. I speak here of

the industrial, commercial, and residential sprawl that we call

urban belts. Already early in the twentieth century cities such as

New York, Chicago, Boston, Philadelphia, and, in Europe, London, Manchester, Berlin, even Paris began to absorb adjacent

towns and cancerously afflict the landscape with overbuilt, densely

populated, and overextended structures. The new electric trolley

systems that networked communities within regions supplemented the railroads that networked regions into nation-states.

Vast areas of the western world, once relatively impenetrable to

the deadening effects of capitalistic forms of urbanism, were ruthlessly opened to exploitation and homogenization. By the 1920s,

the automobile became the vehicle of choice for expanding suburban development and for subverting the remaining distinctions

between town and country that were so vital for maintaining the

identity of both. The famous “antagonism between town and

country,” so celebrated by historians as a driving force in social

development, had produced much of the political and cultural

variety we associate with the mixed economy preceding modern

capitalism and energized the movements that gave us modern

concepts of democracy. The tension between rural and urban

society and the diversity it created as people moved between both

worlds accounts in very great part for the fecundity of social life

in the past. The 1930s, perhaps mercifully, arrested urban homogenization and reinforced agrarian values that had nourished the

democratic images of the yeomanry and artisans. Placed in the

urban context of the decade, this remarkable marriage of countryside and town had produced a vitally creative hybridization of

outlooks from which the Depression years gained so rich a sense

of humanism and social commitment.

The end of the Second World War—notwithstanding the 1960s

decade—revived the trends initiated by the twentieth century.

The acquisitive individualism that existed on a pocket-size scale in

American society during the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries ballooned out over the entire country. Today it constitutes

a social malignancy, more properly a cancer *of* society that threatens to destructure and undermine not only the social bond but the

natural world. Its primary effect is simplification, the unraveling

of all social ties into the loose threads of the marketplace with its

anonymous buyers and sellers, its objectification of all values, its

monetization of ideals—and its unrelenting “growth,” which takes

the demonic form of turning everything organic into the inorganic, ossifying community and individual alike. That it may yield

a society divested of all cultural variety, a human psyche divested

of all uniqueness, and a natural world divested of all diversity is the

hidden intuition of our times for which nuclear immolation and

the wasteland it may yield is as much a metaphor for our times as

it is a potential reality. Politics and citizenship are not only the

victims of this corrosive process. It may well be that they are also

the antidote for it—provided, to be sure, that we can reconstruct

them in ways that are redolent of their classical meaning and

enlarged by what we can learn from the modern world.

----

Any agenda that tries to restore and amplify the classical meaning

of politics and citizenship must clearly indicate what they are not

because of the confusion that surrounds the two words.

Politics is not statecraft, which, alas, is what we ordinarily mean

when we speak of “politics” today. And citizens are not “constituents” or “voters.” Statecraft consists of operations that engage the

state: the exercise of its monopoly of violence, its control of the

entire regulative apparatus of society in the form of legal and

ordinance-making bodies, its governance of society by means of

professional legislators, armies, police forces, bureaucracies, and

the ancillary professionals who service its operations such as lawyers, educators, technicians, and the like. Statecraft takes on a

political patina when so-called “political” parties attempt, in various power plays, to occupy the offices that make state policy and

execute it. This kind of “politics” has an almost tedious typicality.

A political “party” is normally a highly structured hierarchy,

fleshed out by a membership that functions in a top-down manner.

It is a miniature state, and in some countries, notably modern

Russia, actually constitutes the state itself.

The Soviet example of the state *qua* party is simply the logical

extension of the party into the state if only because every party has

its roots in the state, not in the citizenry. The conventional party

is hitched to the state like a garment on a clothing hook. However

varied the garment and its design may be, it is not part of the body

politic; it merely clothes it. There is nothing authentically political

about this phenomenon: it is meant precisely to contain the body

politic, to control it and to manipulate it, not to express its will—or even permit it to develop a will. In no sense is a conventional

“political” party derivative of the body politic or constituted by it.

Leaving metaphors aside, “political” parties are replications of the

state when they are out of power and often synonomous with the

state when they are in power. They are formed to mobilize, to

command, to acquire power, and to rule. Thus they are as inorganic as the state itself—an excrescence of society that has no real

roots in it, no responsiveness to it beyond the needs of faction,

power, and mobilization.

Politics, by contrast, is an organic phenomenon. It is organic in

the very real sense that it is the activity of a public body—a community, if you will—just as a plant is rooted in and nourished by

soil. Politics, conceived as an activity, involves rational discourse,

public empowerment, the exercise of practical reason, and its

realization in a shared, indeed participatory, activity. It is the

sphere of societal life beyond the family and the personal needs

of the individual that still retains the intimacy, involvement, and

sense of responsibility that is enjoyed in private arenas of life.

Groups may form to advance specific political views and programs, but these views and programs are no better than their

capacity to answer to the needs of an active public body. A clear

failing of many “political” parties is the fact that their programs

or “ideologies” are imposed on the public by individuals or their

acolytes whose relationship to the community is tenuous and

largely conceptual: One thinks here of the insights of a Karl Marx

whose ideas were developed within the confines of the British

Museum and then foisted on the world with a scriptural authority

that still generates an endless stream of academic dissertations

even though they exercise virtually no influence in public life.

By contrast, political movements, in the authentic sense of the

word, emerge out of the body politic itself, and their programs are

formulated not only by theorists, invaluable as they may be, but

in great part by the public itself, which plays a participatory role

in their elucidation and dissemination. The populist movements

that swept out of agrarian America and Tsarist Russia or the anarchosyndicalist and peasant movements of Spain and Mexico—all,

despite their ideological patina, emerged from the populace and

articulated their deepest social and political aspirations. They developed into political cultures that solidified completely into the body politic.

Social theorists seem to lack a sufficient awareness of the public’s power to create its own political institutions and forms of

organization. Twentieth-century popular uprisings such as the

Russian, German, Spanish, and, most recently, the Hungarian

revolutions witnessed the widespread self-organization of the people into councils (some that were networked into regional and

national congresses), popular assemblies in a wide variety of areas,

and autonomous municipalities—often without party leadership.

The notion, so common across the political spectrum, that a party

structured along conventional hierarchical lines and guided by a

commanding leadership is indispensable to political change is, in

fact, thoroughly belied by experience.

Robert Michels, despite his jaundiced view of the “competence” of the “masses” in *Political Parties* and his proclivity for

charismatic leaders, provides a compelling argument for the inertial effect of conventional political parties in periods of rapid social

change. They tend to take over institutions that the people create

rather than innovate them, indeed, ultimately reworking them

along statist lines.

The Bolshevik Revolution of 1917–21 is a textbook example of

the appropriation of a popular movement by a highly centralized

party. The revolution ended, in the evisceration of an elaborate

grass-roots council system (the Soviets) by a state-oriented party

and the complete divestiture of all power that the populace had

so painstakingly acquired. A new state apparatus was largely embodied in the Bolshevik party. By the 1920s in Russia, statecraft

had completely replaced politics, and constituents—more properly, subjects—had replaced citizens. The Russian Bolsheviks had

introduced a new wrinkle in the concept of a constituent, Deprived even of the status of “voters” and any representation in the

state, the Russian people were turned by Bolshevism into a

“mass.” Bolshevism, in effect, established a pattern for “mass mobilization” that was to be emulated and used with socially disastrous effects by National Socialism in Germany.

The recovery and development of politics must, I submit, take

its point of departure from the citizen and’his or her immediate

environment beyond the familial and private arenas of life. There

can be no politics without community. And by community! mean

a municipal association of people reinforced by its own economic

power, its own institutionalization of the grass roots, and the confederal support of nearby communities organized into a territorial

network on a local and regional scale. Parties that do not intertwine with these grass-roots forms of popular organization are not

political in the classical sense of the term. In fact, they are bureaucratic and antithetical to the development of a participatory politics and participating citizens. The authentic unit of political life,

in effect, is the municipality, whether as a whole, if it is humanly

scaled, or as its various subdivisions, notably the neighborhood.

Nor can politics be structured around the delegation of power.

The words “representative democracy,” taken literally, are a contradiction in terms. Democracy, conceived as the “rule by the

people” is totally inconsistent with the more republican vision of

“rule by representatives” of the people. It is historical cliche to

emphasize that the authors of the United States Constitution,

which replaced the Articles of Confederation in the 1780s, meant

that they and their social strata were the “People” in the opening

sentence of the document. The Constitution did not create a democracy along Hellenic lines; it created a republic along Roman

lines. And like the Roman Republic it unavoidably and reluctantly

incorporated inherited democratic institutions such as popular

assemblies, which the brothers Gracchi tried to radically expand—an endeavor that ended in tragic failure.

All statist objections aside, the problem of restoring municipal

assemblies seems formidable if it is cast in strictly structural and

administrative forms. New York City has no way of “assembling”

if it tries to emulate Athens with its comparatively small citizen

body. New York City, in fact, is no longer a city in the classical

sense of the term and hardly rates as a municipality even by

nineteenth-century standards of urbanism. The “city” is a sprawling urban belt that sucks up millions of people daily from communities at a substantial distance from its commercial center. But

New York City is made up of neighborhoods—that is to say, largely

organic communities that have a certain measure of identity,

whether they are defined by a shared cultural heritage, economic

interests, a commonality of social views, or even an esthetic tradition such as in Greenwich Village. However much its administration as a logistical, sanitary, and commercial artifact requires a

high degree of coordination by experts and their aides, it is quite

open to political decentralization. Popular, even block, assemblies

can be formed irrespective of the size of a city, provided its organic cultural components can be identified and their uniqueness

fostered. Discussions about the “optimal” size of such components, while interesting to statistically minded sociologists, are politically irrelevant.

Assemblies can be formed from populations that may consist of

anywhere from a typical residential block to a dozen or more.

They can be coordinated by strictly mandated delegates who are

rotatable, recallable, and, above all, rigorously instructed in written form to support or oppose any issue that appears on the agenda

of local confederal councils composed of delegates from several

neighborhood assemblies. There is no mystery involved in this

form of organization. The historical evidence of their efficacy and

their continual reappearance in times of rapid social change is

considerable and persuasive. The Parisian sections of 1793, despite the size of Paris (between 700,000 and a million) and the

logistical difficulties of the era (a time when nothing moved faster

than a horse) functioned with a great deal of success on their own,

coordinated by sectional delegates in the Paris Commune. They

are notable not only for their effectiveness in dealing with political

issues based on a face-to-face democratic structure; they also

played a major role in provisioning the city, in preventing the

hoarding of food, and in suppressing speculation, supervising the

maximum for fixed prices, and many other complex administrative tasks. No city, in fact, is so large that it cannot be networked

by popular assemblies for political purposes. The real difficulty is

largely administrative: how to provide for the material amenities

of city life, support their immense logistical and traffic burdens, or

maintain a sanitary environment.

This issue is often obscured by a serious confusion between the

formulation of policy and its administration. For a community to

decide in a participatory manner what course of action it should

take in dealing with a problem does not oblige all its citizens to

execute that policy—unless, to be sure, there are obvious forms of

behavior that involve everyone in the community. The decision to

build a road, for example, does not mean that everyone must know

how to design and construct one. That is a job for engineers, who

can offer alternative designs—a very important political function

of experts, to be sure, but one that the people in assembly can be

free to decide. But to design and construct a road is a strictly

administrative responsibility. To debate and decide the need for

a road, including the choice of its site and the suitability of its

design, is a political process. If the distinction between policy

making and administration is kept clearly in mind, the role of

popular assemblies and the people who administer their decisions

easily unscrambles logistical problems from political ones, both of

which are normally entangled with each other in discussions on

decentralistic politics based on municipalities and assemblies. Superficially, the assembly system is a “referendum” form of politics:

it is based on a “social contract” to share decision making with the

population at large and abide by the rule of the majority in dealing

with problems that confront a municipality, a regional confederation of municipalities, or, for that matter, a national entity.

Why, then, is there reason to emphasize the assembly form as

crucial to self-governance? Is it not enough to use the referendum,

as the Swiss profess to do today, and resolve the problem of democratic procedure in a simple and seemingly uncomplicated way?

A number of vital issues, involving the nature of citizenship and

the recovery of an enhanced classical vision of politics, must be

considered in answering these questions. The autonomous individual *qua* “voter” who forms the social unit of the referendum

process in liberal theory is a fiction—whether in seemingly democratic notions at one extreme or a totalitarian politics of mass

mobilization at the other. The individual, left to his or her own

destiny in the name of autonomy and independence, becomes a

seemingly asocial being whose very freedom is denuded of vital

traits that provide the necessary flesh and blood for genuine individuality. Indeed, “individuality is impaired when each man

decides to shift for himself,” observes Max Horkheimer in a pithy

critique of personalistic atomism. “... as the ordinary man withdraws, from participation in political affairs, society tends to revert

to the law of the jungle, which crushes all vestiges of individuality.

The absolutely isolated individual has always been an illusion. The

most esteemed personal qualities, such as independence, will to

freedom, sympathy, and the sense of justice, are social as well as

individual virtues. The fully developed individual is the consummation of a fully developed society. The emancipation of the individual is not an emancipation from society, but the deliverance of

society from atomization, an atomization that may reach its peak

in periods of collectivization and mass culture.”{94}

One can take these observation still further. The dependent

individual violates the justifiably high premium we place on autonomy, will, control of one’s destiny, and untrammeled assertion

of ideas. In liberal society, this has led to a mythic “individualism”

that in popular parlance is presumably “rugged”—that is to say,

totally “independent” and “self-seeking.” “Rugged individualism” is as little a desideratum as dependence, which we normally

associate with an inadequate formation of selfhood. The real anthropology of our species involves the prolonged dependence of

the infant and young on elders, a socialization process that, until

recent times, ultimately led to a deep sense of interdependence

in adulthood, riot a brash sense of “independence.” The notion of

“independence,” which is often confused with independentthinking and autonomy of behavior, has been so marbled by pure bourgeois egoism that we tend to forget that our freedom as individuals

depends heavily on community support systems arid solidarity. It

is not by childishly subordinating ourselves to the community on

the one hand or by detaching ourselves from it on the other that

we become authentically human. What distinguishes us as social

beings, hopefully with rational institutions, from solitary beings,

presumably with minimal or no institutions, are our capacities for

solidarity with each other, for mutually enhancing our self-developnient and creativity and attaining freedom within a socially creative and institutionally rich collectivity.

“Citizenship” apart from community is as debasing to our political selfhood as “citizenship” within a totalitarian community. In

both cases, We, are thrust back to the state of dependency that

characterizes our infancy and renders us dangerously vulnerable

to manipulation, whether by powerful personalities in private fife

or the state and corporations in public life. In neither case do we

attain individuality or community. Both, in fact, are dissolved by

removing the communal ground on which authentic individuality

depends. Rather, it is interdependence within an institutionally

rich and rounded community that fleshes out the individual with

the rationality, solidarity, sense of justice, and, ultimately, the reality of freedom that makes for a creative arid caring citizen.

Paradoxical as it may seem; the authentic elements of a rational

and free society are communal ones, not individual bnes. Conceived in more institutional terms, the municipality is the basis for

a free society, the irreducible ground for individuality as well as

society. The significance, of the’municipality is all the greater because it constitutes the discursive arena in which people can intellectually and emotionally confront each other, indeed, experience

each other through dialogue, body language, personal intimacy,

and face-to-face modes of expression in the course of making collective decisions. I speak, here, of the all-important process of

communizing, of the on-going intercourse of many levels of fife,

that makes for solidarity, not only the “neighborliness,” so indispensable for truly organic interpersonal relationships. The referendum, conducted in the privacy of one’s voting booth or, as some “Third Wave” enthusiasts would have it, in the electronic isolation

of one’s home privatizes democracy and thereby subverts it. Voting, like registering one’s “preferences” for soap and detergents

in opinion polls, is the total quantification of citizenship, politics,

individuality, and the very formation of ideas as a mutually informative process. The mere vote reflects a preformulated “percentage” of our perceptions and values, not their full expression.

It is the technical debasing of views into mere preferences, of

ideals into mere taste, of overall comprehension into quantification such that human aspirations and beliefs can be reduced to numerical digits.

Finally, the “autonomous individual,” lacking any community

context, support systems, and organic intercourse, is disengaged

from the character-building process—the *paideia*—that the Athenians assigned to politics as one of its most important educational

functions. True citizenship and politics entail the on-going formation of personality, education, a growing sense of public responsibility and commitment that render communing and an active

body politic meaningful, indeed that give it existential substance.

It is not in the privacy of the school, any more than in the privacy

of the voting booth, that these vital personal and political attributes are formed. They require the existence of a public presence,

embodied by vocal and thinking individuals, a responsive and

discursive public sphere, to achieve reality. “Patriotism,” as the

origin of the word indicates, is the nation-state’s conception of the

citizen as a child, the obedient creature of the nation conceived

as a *paterfamilias* or stern father, who orchestrates belief and

commands devotion. To the extent that we are the “sons” and

“daughters” of a “fatherland,” we place ourselves in a mindless,

indeed infantile, relationship to the state.

Loyalty, by contrast, implies a sense of commitment to a human

community that is guided by knowledge, training, experience, and

a sense of caring—in short, by a political education created in the

course of political participation, not by institutional obedience.

The Greek term, *philia*, ordinarily translated as “friendship,” but

which I prefer to call “solidarity,” is the ultimate result of the

educational and self-formative process that *paideia* was meant to

achieve. In the absence of a humanly scaled, comprehensible, and

institutionally accessible municipality, this all-important function

of politics and its embodiment in citizenship is simply impossible

to achieve. Indeed, it ceases to even enter into contemporary

notions of “politics” and “citizenship.” Accordingly, we begin to

gauge “political involvement” by the “percentage” of “voters”

who “participate” in the “political process”—a degradation of

words that totally denatures their authentic meaning and eviscerates their ethical content. If the class-oriented politics in the past

was ultimately a civic politics, individual politics today is ultimately a municipal politics. In both cases, I use the term “politics”

to denote not only the direct self-management of the *polis* or

community by its citizens but the educational process of forging

a self that is capable of the self-management of the municipality.

----

There are many questions that arise when one tries to develop a

new municipal agenda today, and many possibilities, I may add,

that open the way to a new, richly imaginative politics as well as

a traditional conception of citizenship as participatory, educative,

and community oriented.

In an era of growing power in nation-states and corporations,

when administration, property ownership, production, bureaucracies, and the flow of capital as well as power are notoriously centralized, how can we invoke a localist, municipally oriented society without seeming to be starry-eyed visionaries? Is this

municipalist, decentralist, and participatory vision of self-governance and selfhood utterly incompatible with the overwhelming

trend toward public massification? Does the notion of clearly

definable, humanly scaled communities not seem to be redolent

of atavistic, backward-looking parochial ideas of a premodern

world, indeed of the “folk community” (*Volksgemeinschaft*) advocated by German Nazism? Do its advocates, specifically this

writer, wish to undo the technological gains achieved by the several industrial revolutions that followed the first one, two centuries ago? Can a “modern society” be governed any longer by local

groups in an era when centralized power is presumably “here to

stay”?

To these largely theoretical questions, I can add a host of very

practical ones. How will politically localized citizens’ assemblies

be coordinated to deal with the practical questions of such simple

facts as rail transportation, road maintenance, the supply of resources and foodstuffs, from distant or select regions? How can we

readapt an economy based on the business ethic (including its

plebeian counterpart, the “work ethic”) to one that is guided by

an ethics of self-fulfillment and self-realization in productive activity? How can we change present-day instruments of government

such as national constitutions and city charters to reflect a system

of self-governance based on municipal autonomy? How can we

restructure a profit-oriented market economy, reinforced by a

centralists technology, into a humanly oriented moral economy,

reinforced by an alternative decentralis,tic technology? Finally,

how can all of these visions be brought into accord with an ecological society that seeks a harmonious, indeed participatory, relationship with the natural world, free of social hierarchy,’ class and gender domination, and cultural homogeneity?

This work, let me emphasize, is not a handbook for social

recipes that meet the taste of every palate. To make it so—and

more than enough books exist that profess to do so is to subvert

the very meaning of the libertarian municipal project it seeks to

advance. In the last analysis, these pages are an effort to apply the

principles of social ecology to ah interpretation of the present and

to a past that really is always with us, informed by a deep concern

for the contours of a liberatory and ecological future society. To

provide a detailed institutional and economic map of what such a

future society should or “must” look like is to use a seemingly

ecological interpretation of the future against one of the most

fundamental precepts of social ecology: unity in diversity. The

ecological belief that every human community, indeed every individual—not to speak of every natural ecocommunity is deliciously unique permeates this book from its opening lines to those

that close it. Detailed recipes that profess to resolve every problem that every decentralized human community will face—and

should creatively face, given its uniqueness and specificity—is to

cut across the grain of all the ecological ideas that give coherence

to this book. It is to assume precisely what social ecology emphatically denies: namely, that all our social problems are so universal,

indeed so “global” (to use the pop vernacular of environmentalism

today), that we have no need to “act locally.” Localism, taken

seriously, implies a sensitivity to speciality, particularity, and the

uniqueness of place, indeed a sense of place or *topos* that involves

deep respect (indeed “loyalty,” if I may use a term that I would

like to offset against “patriotism”) to the areas in which we live and

that are given to us in great part by the natural world itself.

Once this is emphasized, there are still broad answers that can

be advanced to the questions I have raised, particularly to those

that have a highly polemical character. In trying to answer these

questions, I presuppose a thorough understanding of the essential

principles raised in this book: not only is politics to be sharply

distinguished from statecraft, but policy making is to be distinguished from administration; not only is “rugged individualism” to

be’ distinguished from authentic individuality, but the notion of

the isolated individual is to be distinguished from the rounded

individual who is rooted in a rounded community; not only is

independence to be distinguished from dependence, but authentic independence is indistinguishable from interdependence.

These caveats cannot be restated often enough. The notion that

decentralized communities are premodern, indeed antimodern,

“atavisms” reflects an almost willful failure to recognize that an

organic community is not necessarily an “Organism” in which the

individual parts are subordinated to the collective whole. That

such highly bourgeois prejudices should be echoed by socialists

and liberals alike reflects a very clouded view of individualism that

confuses individuality with egoism. Our market society, riddled by

its preoccupation with objects called “commodities” and its gross

monetization of all aspects of life, has never produced authentic

individuality, unless one chooses to mistake buccaneering industrial and commercial predators for authentic personalities. While

any attempt to fashion an ecological society out of free, autonomous, and organic communities—organic no less in their respect

for land, flora, and fauna than in their attempts to foster human

solidarity and social support systems—always risks the possibility

of becoming a “folk community” in the parochial, even fascistic,

sense of the term, they also open the possibility of producing a

highly fecund terrain for promoting the development of deeply

individuated and richly creative personalities. Ironically, Nazism,

for all its bombast about the desirability of a German *Volksgemeinschaft*, opportunistically surrendered the utopian content of this

popular yearning for a sense of place and community to a leadership principle” that totally subordinated localism to centralism,

community to nationalism, technical conservatism to industrial

innovation, particularly in the design of weapons and methods of

political surveillance. The academic frippery that clothes the hard

realities of Nazism with myths that it patently discarded is almost

textbook evidence of the yawning separation of campus scholasticism from the real world beyond its confines.

There is nothing that is either “backward looking” or “forward

looking” about humanity’s effort to find community together with

individuality. The impulse to achieve these complementary aims—especially in times like our own, when both of them are faced

with sweeping disintegration—is an abiding human goal that has

been expressed as much in religion as in secular radicalism, in

utopian experiments as in city neighborhoods, in self-enclosed

ethnic groups as in expansive cosmopolitan cities. Nothing but a

feeling for truth and its custody by the human mind has ever kept

any notion of community and individuality from tipping over into

spiteful parochialism at one extreme or fragmented atomism at

the other.

The result is that consciousness—not pat formulas—ultimately

determine whether humanity will achieve a rich sense of collectivity without sacrificing a rich sense of individuality. A creative

politics without a creative citizenry is as unattainable as a creative

citizenry without a creative politics. The guarded mind, whether

we call it “class consciousness” or “social consciousness,” is the sole

guarantor of a social and personal life that will be guided by the

thin line of truth. The tendency of radicals and liberals who emphasize abstractions such as “class” and “social” over the more

existential need for consciousness is the true “betrayal of the intellectuals” that was mourned in earlier times. Any expectation that

a formula, even a salad of democratic institutions, will in itself

rescue us from any impulses that yield totalitarianism, whether in

its “futuristic” or atavistic forms, is sheer myth. The guarded

mind, informed by knowledge and a humane sense of solidarity,

is all that we possess as a fortress against authoritarian “reversion”

at one extreme and authoritarian “progress” at the other. Indeed

the “dark past” has become the counterpart of the “dark future”

in an age that seeks form rather than content to guide us through

its modern dilemmas and panaceas.

Paradoxical as it seems and dialectically irascible as it may be,

the conflict—more precisely, the tension—that exists between a

localistic vision and a nationalistic reality is the most important

basis for a new politics that we can redeem from the present crisis

for which “urbanization” is a metaphor. The growing power and

centralization of the state and its corporate underpinnings are not

necessarily the harbingers of victory over the municipality. It may

well be that they are the harbingers of a deepening social crisis

that may give new vitality to municipal politics and alter the very

shape of politics itself. One does not have to be a visionary (apparently, a pejorative term, these days) to see that every human

impulse is now being affronted by the disempowerment of ordinary people in everyday life. Locked increasingly into an inward

world in which society and collectivity are excluded, transclass

desires seem to be slowly welling up in countless individuals who

are seeking the open air of a meaningful public life, not to speak

of a more creative personal one. Like the tensions that gathered

together in western society during the four centuries directly

preceding the emergence of industrial capitalism, we are witnessing a new period of transition with deep-seated tensions that are emerging in our own era.

Localism, in fact, has never been so much in the air as it is today—all the more because centralism and corporatism have never

seemed more overwhelming than they are today. The state and

the corporations have “ghettoized” the western world, particularly North America, to such a suffocating extent that public sentiment threatens to overflow the barriers they have created and

perhaps in time to burst them. Demands for local control and

attempts to redefine democracy along ever-expansive lines are

yielding a multitude of interest groups and citizen-initiative committees. Demands for local control and redefinitions of democracy

that are normally preceded by such adjectives as “grass-roots” are

yielding a multitude of various local associations, “alliances,” and

block committees that stress local control as well as economic

justice. “Socialist” mayors have been elected in several American

communities for the first time since the 1930s. The town meeting,

initially a New England institution, is becoming a byword in regions of the United States that have no shared tradition with the,

American Northeast. Community and action groups have invaded

local politics, a terrain that was once the exclusive preserve of

political parties, on a scale that has significantly altered the entire

landscape of municipal policy making.

That these grass-roots organizations are often ephemeral or

co-optable does not alter the fact that the underlying ferment at

the base of American society is vitalized precisely by the fact that

the centralized state has made the most elementary hmnan demands for self-expression and self-empowerment highly problematical, a fact that may well change the entire texture of American politics. The tension between vision and reality is no less a

creative force than it was in times past, particularly in periods of

social and economic transition.

Put bluntly, a latent “dual power” seems to be emerging today

in which, the local base of society is beginning to challenge the

authority of its seemingly invulnerable state and corporate apex.

It. is precisely the inaccessibility of this apex to grass-roots influence that threatens to disintegrate the very architecture of power

as such. The fact that public control over public fife has never

seemed more visionary is precisely what makes the demands for

such control particularly compelling, just as intractable resistance

by power tends to foster opposition rather than mute it. Almost

intuitively, people seem to be molding their own institutions for

expression in the public realm with an obstinacy that may well

render localist politics an irrepressible force. The very ephemeral

nature of many such grass-roots institutions and organizations is

evidence less of failure than of persistence. I am no longer talking

of the explosive episodes that marked the’ uprisings of the 1960s,

such as those in black ghettos or antiwar street actions. Grass-roots

politics, specifically popular municipal politics, is becoming an

integral part of American politics as a whole, one that has yet to

find a coherent voice and sense of direction. But the fact is that

it is here to stay and has worked its way, however confusedly, into

the real world of the political landscape.

In trying to formulate a municipal agenda for our time, the real

question is how will this often formless political energy be institutionalized? What structures will it create that will turn it into a

powerful force to countervail the growing power of the state and

a centralized corporate economy? What kind of political culture

can it create that will play a transformative role in an era of urban

and governmental gigantism? And what kind of political economy

can it fashion that will avoid the pitfalls of a property-oriented

market economy on the one hand and a totalitarian nationalized

economy on the other?

I do not profess to have answers to these questions that apply’

to all municipalities—nor, giyen their variety, would it be anything but presumptuous to provide them. But certain basic coordinates can be formulated that are integrally wedded to any conception of municipal freedom, certainly of a kind that is meant to recover a participatory idea of politics and a classical idea of citizenship.

The most important of these coordinates is the’revival of the

scaled communities or neighborhood assemblies in large, even

metropolitan urban entities. Such assemblies are not merely a

historical legacy that belong to the archaeology of urbanism. A

large portion of this book would be completely meaningless if the

reader failed to see that in nearly all periods of social upheaval

people have turned to assembly forms as a way of entering the

doors of history and taking control of their destiny, If these assemblies seem remote, even archaic, when we stray back to ancient

Mesopotamia and classical Greece, they become very close to our

fives when we see them in revolutionary America and France, and

even seem to make direct contact with us when we find them in

the Paris Commune of 1871 and the post-World War II era. Apparently, we have something at work here that has a more abiding

reality than the distant “age of cities,” which has since been supplanted by the “age of nation-states.” They seem to be speaking

to something in the human spirit that demands systems of governance based on face-to-face! decision making, a personafistic as

well as a participatory politics. It is as though the need for community and communing were not simply a social desideratum but an ethical one that emanates from the human spirit itself.

The second of these major coordinates is the need fpr the assemblies to “speak” to each other, literally, to confederate. Leagues of

towns and cities, as I have argued earlier, have always surfaced,

however, temporarily, as centripetal forms of municipal association. Calls for the creation of nationlike entities structured around

confederations of municipalities go back to Greek times and range

over history up to the Paris Commune, indeed into very recent

times when the centralized nation-state threatens to become an

overbearing force in local affairs. The concept of confederation is

as old as the fact of municipal life itself. Initially more defensive

than creative in character, it has provided us with extraordinary,

indeed inspiring, examples of freedom within localities and in the

relationships between localities. Even as a word, “confederation”

implies a commitment to liberatory ways of associating that “nationalism,” with its jingoistic and totalitarian nuances has rarely

possessed. It is notable that the first American constitution was

deliberately called “the Articles of Confederation,” which, for all

its limitations, was cynically and secretively replaced by a so-called

“federal” Constitution, one that Hamilton and his supporters

foisted on the American people as the next best alternative to a

constitutional monarchy.

The third of the major coordinates for guiding us toward a

municipal democracy is the need to create politics as a school for

genuine citizenship. Ultimately, there is no civic “curriculum,” as

it were, that can be a substitute for a living and creative political

realm. But what we must clearly do in an era of commodification,

rivalry, anomie, and egoism is formulate and consciously inculcate

the values of humanism, cooperation, community, and public service in the everyday practice of civic fife, not only in our schools,

religious institutions, and local societies. Grass-roots citizenship

must go hand in hand with grass-roots politics. The Athenian *polis*,

for all its many shortcomings, offers us remarkable examples of

how its high sense of citizenship was reinforced not only by systematic education, but by the development of an etiquette of civic

behavior and an artistic culture that adorned its ideals of civic

service with the realities of civic practice. Deference to opponents

in debates, the use of language to achieve consensus, on-going

public discussion in the *agora* in which even the most prominent

of the *polis*’s figures were expected to debate public issues with

the least known, the use of wealth not only to meet personal needs

but to adorn the *polis* itself (thus placing a high premium on the

disaccumulation rather than the accumulation of wealth), a multitude of public festivals, dramas, and satires largely centered on

civic affairs and the need to foster civic solidarity—all of these and

many other aspects of Athens’s political culture created the civic

loyalty and responsibility that made for actively involved citizens

with a deep sense of civic mission.

The development of citizenship, in effect, must become an art,

not merely an education—and creative art in the esthetic sense

that appeals to the deeply human desire for self-expression in a

meaningful spiritual community. It must be a personal art in

which every citizen is fully aware of the fact that his or her community entrusts its destiny to his or her moral probity, loyalty, and

rationality. The very essence of state power and statecraft today

is that the “citizen” is an incompetent being, indeed infantile and

normally untrustworthy, while the state is a disciplinary institution, not an avenue of self-expression. Even liberal theory, not to

speak of Christian theology, justifies the existence of the state as

a whip to keep its “naturally” irascible subjects in hand and correct their inherent “incompetence” by entrusting public affairs to

professional politicians and bureaucratic institutions. For citizens

to directly intervene in public affairs beyond obediently voting

annually for preselected candidates and paying their taxes with a

reasonable modicum of honesty has been regarded as a safety

valve for public dissatisfaction at best and “anarchy” at worst.

The municipalist conception of citizenship assumes precisely

the opposite. Every citizen is regarded as competent to participate directly in the “affairs of state,” indeed what is more important, encouraged to do so. Every means is provided, whether esthetic or institutional, to foster participation in full and see it as an

educative and ethical process that turns the citizen’s latent competence into an actual reality. Social and political fife are consciously orchestrated to foster a profound sensitivity, indeed a real

sense of caring for the adjudication of differences without denying

the need for vigorous dispute when it is needed. Public service is

seen as a uniquely human attribute, not a “gift” that a citizen

confers on the community or an onerous task that he or she must

fulfill. Cooperation and civic responsibility are seen as expressions

of care, concern, and sociability, not as ordinances that the citizen

is expected to honor in the breach and evade where he can do so.

Put bluntly and clearly, the municipality is seen as a theater in

which life in its most meaningful public form is the plot, a political

drama whose grandeur imparts nobility and grandeur to the citizenry that forms the cast. By contrast, our modern cities have

become in large part agglomerations of bedroom apartments in

which men and women spiritually wither away and their personalities are trivialized by the petty concerns of entertainment, consumption, and small talk.

The last and perhaps the most intractable of our coordinates is

economic. Today, economic issues tend to center around “who

owns what,” “who owns more than whom,” and, above all, how

disparities in wealth are to be reconciled with a sense of civic

commonality. Nearly all municipalities have been fragmented by

differences in economic status, pitting poor, middle, and wealthy

classes against each other often to the ruin of municipal freedom

itself as the bloody history of Italy’s medieval and Renaissance

cities so clearly demonstrates.

These problems have not disappeared in recent times. Indeed

in many cases they are as severe as they have ever been. But what

is unique about our own time—a fact so little understood by many

liberals and radicals in North America and Europe—is that entirely new *transclass* issues have begun to emerge that concern

environment, growth, transportation, cultural degradation, and

the quality of urban life generally—issues that have been produced by urbanization, not by citification. Cutting across conflicting class interests are such transclass issues as the massive dangers of thermonuclear war, growing state authoritarianism, and, ultimately, global ecological breakdown. To an extent unparalleled in

American history, an enormous variety of citizens’ groups have

brought people of all class backgrounds into common projects

around problems, often very local in character, that concern the

destiny and welfare of their community as a whole.

Issues such as the siting of nuclear reactors or nuclear waste

dumps, the dangers of acid rain, and the presence of toxic dumps,

to cite only a few of the many problems that beleaguer innumerable American municipalities, have united an astdnishing variety of

people into movements with shared concerns that render a ritualistic “class analysis” of their motives utterly irrelevant. No less

remarkable in crossing traditional class, ethnic, and economic barriers is the emergence of feminism, a movement that sees the

gender oppression that afflicts wealthy women, no less than poor,

a matter of dignity and self-respect. Carried still further, the absorption of small communities by larger ones, of cities by urban

belts, and urban belts by “standard metropolitan statistical areas”

has given rise to militant demands for communal integrity and

self-government, an issue that surmounts strictly class and economic interests. The literature on the emergence of these trans-class movements, once so secondary’ to internecine struggles

within the cities of earlier times, is so immense that to merely list

the sources would require a sizable volume.

I have given this brief overview of an emerging general social

interest over old particularistic interests to demonstrate that a

new politics is already coming into being—indeed one that is not

only restructuring the political landscape on a municipal level but

the economic landscape as well. The old debates between “private

property” and “nationalized property,” between “individual ownership” and “public ownership,” are becoming threadbare. Not

that these different kinds of ownership and the forms of exploitation they imply have disappeared; rather, they are being increase

ingly overshadowed by new realities and concerns. “Private property?’’ in the traditional sense of the term, with its case for

perpetuating the citizen as an economically self-sufficient and

politically self-empowered individual, is fading away. It is disappearing not because “creeping socialism” is devouring the “free

entrepreneur” but because “creeping corporatism” is devouring

everyone—ironically, in the name of “free enterprise,” The economy of North America, like that of Europe and even Third World

countries, is becoming either “corporatized” or “nationalized”—or to use the one term that embraces both, “bureaucratized.” The

Greek ideal of the politically sovereign citizen who can make a

rational judgment in public affairs because he is free from material

need or clientage has been reduced to a mockery. The oligarchic

character of economic life, whether in the “western bloc” of the

“eastern,” threatens democracy such as it is—not only on a national level but also on a municipal level, where it still preserves

a certain degree of intimacy and leeway.

We come here to a breakthrough approach to a municipalist

economics that innovatively dissolves the mystical aura surrounding corporatized property and nationalized property, indeed

workplace elitism and “workplace democracy.” I refer to the

municipalization of property, not its corporatization or its nationalization. As for the workplace, I refer to more than “economic

democracy” or “economic collectivization.” Rather, I refer to the

substitution of public democracy for both of these traditional images of productive management and operations. Significantly, “economic democracy” in the workplace is no longer incompatible

with corporatized or nationalized economy. Quite to the contrary:

the effective use of “workers’ participation” in production, even

the outright handing over of industrial operations to the workers

who perform them, has become another form of time-studied,

assembly-line rationalization, the systematic exploitation of labor

by bringing labor itself into complicity with its own exploitation.

Many workers, in fact, would like to get away from their factories and find more creative types of work, not simply “participate”

in their own misery. What “economic democracy” meant in its

profoundest sense was free, “democratic” access to the means of

life, the guarantee of freedom from material want, not simply the

involvement of workers with onerous productive activities that

we would do better to turn over to machines. It is a blatant bourgeois trick, in which many radicals unknowingly participate, that

“economic democracy” has been reinterpreted to mean “employee ownership” or that “workplace democracy” has come to

mean workers’ “participation” in industrial management rather

than freedom from the tyranny of the factory, rationalized labor,

and “planned production.”

A municipal politics, based on libertarian principles, scores a

significant advance over all of these conceptions by calling for the

municipalization of the economy—and its management by the

community as part of a politics of self-management. Syndicalist

demands for the “collectivization” of industry and “workers’ control” of individual industrial units are based on contractual relationships between all “collectivized” enterprises, thereby reprivatizing the economy and opening it to traditional forms of private

property—whether collectively owned or not, while libertarian

municipalism politicizes the economy and dissolves it into the

civic domain. Neither factory nor land becomes a separate or

potentially competitive unit within a seemingly communal collective. Nor do workers, farmers, technicians, engineers, professionals, and the like perpetuate their vocational identities as separate

interests that exist apart from the citizen body in face-to-face

assemblies. “Property” is integrated into the municipality as a

material constituent of its free institutional framework, indeed as

part of a larger whole that is controlled by the citizen body in

assembly as citizens—not as “workers,” “farmers,” “professionals,” or any other vocationally oriented special-interest groups.

What is equally important, the famous “contradiction” or “antagonism” between town and country, so crucial in social theory

and history, is transcended by the “township,” the traditional New

England jurisdiction, in which an urban entity is the nucleus of its

agricultural and village environs—not a domineering urban entity

that stands opposed to them. A township, in effect, is a small region

within still larger ones, such as the county and the bioregion.

So conceived, the municipalization of the economy should be

distinguished not only from “corporatization” but also from seemingly more “radical” demands such as “nationalization” and “collectivization.” Nationalization of the economy invariably has led

to bureaucratic and top-down economic control; collectivization,

in turn, could easily lead to the emergence of a privatized economy in a collectivized form with the perpetuation of class or caste

identities. By contrast, municipalization brings the economy as a

whole into the orbit of the public sphere, where economic policy

can be formulated by the *entire* community—notably its citizens

in face-to-face relationships working to achieve a general interest

that surmounts separate, vocationally defined specific interests.

The economy ceases to be merely an economy in the strict sense

of the term, composed of capitalistic, “worker-controlled” enterprises. It becomes a truly political economy (to use a very traditional terminology in a very untraditional sense): the economy of

the *polis* or the municipality. The municipality, more precisely,

the citizen body in face-to-face assembly, absorbs the economy

into its public business, divesting it of a separate identity that can

become privatized into a self-serving enterprise.

What can prevent the municipality, now reinforced by its own

economic apparatus, from becoming a parochial city-state of the

kind that appeared in the late Middle Ages? Once again I would

like to Emphasize that anyone who is looking for guaranteed solutions to the problems raised here will not find them in the form

of blissfully insulated institutions that take on a life of their own

apart from the role of consciousness and ethics in human affairs.

But if we are looking for countertendencies rather than “guarantees,” there is an answer that can be given. The most important

single factor that gave rise to the late medieval city-state was its

stratification from within—not only as a result of differences in

wealth, but also in status positions, partly originating in family

origins, partly, too, in vocational differences. Indeed, to the extent

that the city lost its sense of collective unity arid divided its affairs

into private and public business, public life itself became segmented into the “blue nails” or plebeians who. dyed cloth in cities

such as Florerice and the’ more arrogant strata of artisans who

produced quality goods. Wealth, too, factored heavily in a privatized economy where material differences could expand and foster a variety of hierarchical differences.

The municipalization of the economy not only absorbs the vocational differences that could militate, against a publically controlled economy; it also absorbs the material means of life into

‘ communal forms of distribution. “From each according to his ability and to each according to his needs” is now institutionalized as

part of the public sphere. This traditional maxim, which is meant to assure that people will have, access to the means of life irrespective of the work they are capable of performing, ceases to be

merely a precarious credo: it becomes a practice, a way of functioning politically—one that is structurally built into the community as a way of existing as a political entity.

Happily, no community can hope to achieve economic autarchy, nor should it try to do so unless it wishes to become self-enclosed and parochial. Interdependence between communities

is no less important than interdependence between individuals.

Divested of the cultural crossfertilization that is often a product of

economic intercourse, the municipality tends to shrink into itself

and disappear into its own civic privatism, Shared needs and resources imply the existence of sharing and, with sharing, communication, rejuvenation by new ideas, a wider social horizon that

yields a wider sensibility to new experiences. The recent emphasis

in environmental theory on “self-sufficiency,” if it does not mean

a greater degree of prudence in dealing with material resources,

is regressive. Localism should never be interpreted to mean parochialism nor should decentralism ever be interpreted to mean that

smallness is a virtue in itself. Small is not necessarily “beautiful.”

The concept of human scale, by far the more preferable expression for a truly ecological community, is built around the ability of

people to completely grasp their political environment, not to

parochially bury themselves in it to the exclusion of cultural stimuli from outside their community’s boundaries.

, Given these coordinates, it is possible to envision anew political

culture with a new revival of citizenship, popular civic institutions, a new kind of economy, and a countervailing dual power,

confederally networked, that could arrest and hopefully reverse

the growing centralization of the state and corporate enterprises.

Moreover, it is also possible to envision an eminently practical

point of departure for going beyond the town and city as we have

known them up to now and developing future forms of habitation

as genuine ecocommunities—human ecocommuniti.es, in this

case, that seek to achieve a new harmonization between people

and between humanity and the natural world. I have emphasized

the word “practical” because it is now clear that any attempt to

tailor a human community to a natural “ecosystem” in which it is

located cuts completely against the grain of centralized power, be

it state or corporate. Centralized power invariably reproduces

itself in centralized forms at all levels of social, political, arid economic life. It is not only “big”; it thinks big. Indeed, this way of

being and thinking is a condition for its survival, not only its growth.

Not surprisingly, the ecotechnologies that came very much into

vogue during the 1970s, such as solar, wind, and methane power,

later to be explored and toyed with by the national governments

of the world, literally collapsed under their own weight. Governments almost invariably designed them with technical gigantism

in mind. One thinks here of the huge tidal dams that were constructed in France, the plans for immense solar installations that

were designed in American universities, the oversized windmills

that were reared by federal agencies, some of which were almost

calculated to fail and few of which could have significantly affected

local life. Organic agriculture, while given a ritualistic nod of approval and a modicum of funding by state agencies, was virtually

elbowed out by the more earnest attention that was given to

conventional agribusiness and industrial techniques for cultivating food.

Ecotechnologies of this kind have been earnestly used almost

entirely by individuals and local communities. To the extent that

solar and wind power are used today, it is mainly because ecologically concerned citizens and their neighbors have introduced

them as part of their home dwellings, not because their use has

been taken very seriously as part of a national agenda. To induce

the nation-state and corporations to think about energy, designers

are obliged to speak about the feasibility of nuclear power plants,

immense, ecologically destructive hydroelectric dams, and large

fossil fuel installations. The ideological terrain of the nation-state

is primarily continental, not local, just as the ideological terrain of

the medical profession is primarily disease, not health. The very

notion of sensitively tailoring technology to fit the natural ecocommunity in which people five is possible to a serious extent only

within a locally oriented political community where the uniqueness of the natural environment can be fully experienced in all its intimacy.

Moreover, it is the only level in which natural cycles can be

respectfully lived out—not as the mere rhetoric of “environmentally”-oriented politicians but as the everyday experience of

householders who are able to return domestic wastes to their

organic gardens and recycle the American consumers’ kitchen-middens of discardable trash for more rational ends. Nation-states

are instruments for the domination of other nation-states and for

the domination of the natural world. If we are to remove this

fixation on domination that first appeared with the emergence of

hierarchy, particularly with the domination of women by men, we

are in dire need of local communities, technologies, and a political

culture that will bring people into a face-to-face relationship with

their natural habitat and the communities around them. In such

communities, technology will then hopefully cease to be a force

for “dominating nature” as the received wisdom of our era would

have it. Indeed, like the political culture that is meant to bring

citizens into a participatory relationship with each other, we can

expect that such ecologically oriented municipalities will see

themselves as integral parts of the natural world and technology

as a way of fostering natural fecundity rather than exploiting or

vitiating it.

We five today in a world that casts relationships oppositionally,

not integratively. Mind is set against body, thought against materiality, individual against community, urban belts against towns,

towns against country—and humanity as a whole against a natural

world that is seen as “stingy,” “cruel,” and “intractable,” a world

that has to be conquered by science and technology before society

can hope to be free. Nation-states and corporate enterprises invoke large-scale technology presumably to achieve this very end.

They not only presuppose the basic divisions that have separated

humanity from nature but exacerbate them as justification for the

rationalization and exploitation of human labor. Urbanization is

the physical expression of this divisive reality at one of its most

fundamental levels: the place where people live, produce goods,

and consume them, indeed the most immediate arena in which

they enter into contact with each other apart from their places of

work. Urbanization not only removes these relationships and activities from the individual’s control; it undermines, simplifies, and

literally fossilizes them such that people and their habitats become

entirely inorganic, indeed synthetic objects that can be easily

manipulated and ultimately divested of all their living attributes.

To restructure our institutions into richly articulated forms, to

reorganize our relationships into creative forms of human solidarity, to reempower our communities and cities so that they can

effectively counteract state and corporate power—indeed replace

the nation-state with politically confederated and economically

vital municipalities—and to create a new, nonhierarchical and

participatory relationship between humanity and nature by means

of a sensibility and technics that fosters a participatory form of

complementarity rather than atomistic antagonisms—all, taken

together as one coherent ensemble, constitute not only a desideratum of major proportions but anew ethical calling. The incarnation

of this human project is the immediate, indeed unmediated, community that enters so profoundly into the fashioning of our humanity. This is the community in which we genuinely encounter each

other, the public world that is only a bare step above our private

world, in short, our towns, neighborhoods, and municipalities. How

we begin the great project of refashioning this, public world and

articulating it institutionally, economically, eonfederally, and technically will determine whether we exist as public beings, interactively as discursive and rational human beings, or whether we

disappear in the huge maw of modern-day urbanization.

----

It is always tempting—and perhaps eminently human—to break

away from abstractions about municipalism arid personalize them

in the hard realities of one’s own experiences. I have hesitated to

fix my general coriclusions in speculative details. Utopias have a

bad way of becoming fixed blueprints—after which they degenerate into inflexible dogmas. But perhaps it would not be amiss if I

take the liberty of fleshing out some of my speculations with my

lived experience, notably in the urban area with which I am most

fa mil iar at the present time—Burlington, Vermont—and in the

“bioregion” I know best, the excitingly libertarian state of Vermont. Reduced to basics, it is in these two areas that my speculations may take on some concrete meaning that has relevance to

problems that face many urban dwellers today.

Vermont, the fourteenth state to enter the original union of

thirteen American colonies,‘was a free republic between 1777 and

1791, and it still retains many of the libertarian traditions, of that

revolutionary era. This historical legacy may make it somewhat

exceptional, but it does not make the area any less real. That

Vermont exists is a fact that is existentially more real than many

myths that have moved human beings over the ages to greater acts

of nobility than reality itself. One thinks, here, of the Judeo-Christian tradition that kept the Jews intact for two thousand years of

incredible persecution and also sent other millions—their Christian brethren—into bloody spiritual conflicts over the same span

of time. This is true, too, for Moslems and men and women of other

faiths. Here, I Would like to, repeat the caveat that what humans

think of themselves, however fancifully, often determines their

behavior more decisively than their “objective” material interests—many social thinkers, including Marx, to the contrary notwithstanding.

So it is with Vermont, or, for that matter, America and the rest

of the world. If history would have it otherwise and people acted

immediately, even ultimately, according to their “objective” or

material interests, this world would long have been the best of all

possible worlds—or maybe the worst, depending very much on

what one regards as objective. Iriany case, Vermont thinks of itself

as what America “used to be” rather than what it is today and

often acts upon this self-conception as though it were true. Generally, this means that the state is remarkably unencumbered by the

extravagant amount of statecraft that afflicts so many other American states. It has a citizens’ legislature in which no elected official

apart from the executive branch (the governor, a modest bureaucracy, the police, and judiciary) receives a livable, full-time salary

for public service and must answer for his or her public service

every two years in contrast to the four-year terms that prevail in

most of the United States. The accessibility of nearly all public

officials, including the state’s governor, to the public has few

equals in most Euro-American republics; face-to-face discussion,

inquiries, and debates turn politics into a very intimate affair;

Vermonters would not have it otherwise. They take for granted a

wide array of political rights that would be regarded as deferential

privileges in almost any sizable political jurisdiction.

Vermont is also town-meeting country—indeed vigorous town-meeting country notwithstanding the ritualistic articles that appear annually in *The New York Times* and *Wall Street Journal*

that lament the decline of these remarkable democratic institutions. Having attended many town meetings over the past fifteen

years, I can personally attest to their vitality. In fact, I have seen

a remarkable resurgence of town meetirig democracy in Vermont,

partly because the citizenry has begun to treasure the power this

institution accords them in a period of growing centralism elsewhere; partly, too, because town meetings have intervened into

international affairs such as the nuclear-breeze issue and have

given these Yankee Americans an enhanced sense of “grass-roots”

control over seemingly historic public affairs. This control, to be

sure, is strictly moral; it does not carry the ponderous weight of

law. But it is’ characteristically American that a republican national

constitution, permeated by a countervailing revolutionary democratic tradition, has given rise to a state of mind that imparts a

higher authority to a grass-roots moral movement than a legislative mandate. In this case, American politics can be credited with

being more vulnerable to moral movements than its critics fully

realize, Vermont’s town meetings, like those of its New England

neighbors, are often more effective nationally than they truly realize, precisely because they are hallowed by moral traditions that

give America its national identity. It is the enormous weight of

their moral voice, their invocation of an ethically charged past that

ha un ts the present with its ambience of virtue and freedom, that

gives them enormous potential power for social change.

This past affects the so-called “cities” of Vermont, not only its

small towns and villages. Despite the fact that Vermont’s few

sizable towns—particularly Burlington, its largest, with a population of 37,000—are structured around a mayoralty system with a

typical board of aldermen, election day is still called “town-meeting day.” The possibility of restructuring Burlington’s “big city”

apparatus around town meetings, each located in one of the city’s

six wards, has been in the air for more than a decade. Personally,

this writer raised such a proposal fifteen years ago, and it began

to surface in the city’s political discourse in 1981, when a conference of Burlington’s neighborhood organizations passed a very

strong “resolve,” taking up my proposal and voting it through

almost unanimously. Thereafter, in September 1982, Burlington’s

Board of Aldermen accepted a more attenuated structure of

“Neighborhood Planning Assemblies” (NPAs) to implement citizen participation in the allocation of federal community-development block grants. NPAs were thereupon established in each of

the wards and proceeded to formulate constitutions for periodic

meetings, coordinating committees, and the like. They were open

to all registered voters of a given ward, although their agendas

were often presented by agencies in the mayor’s office.

By adding the word “planning” to the words “neighborhood

assembly,” the city’s mayoral administration (which is headed by

a fairly authoritarian “socialist” mayor for whom leadership often

is equatable with a high degree of “paternalism”) limits the assemblies’ power to a largely consultative role. At this writing, the

situation is very much in flux: the NPAs are occasionally “assembled” by agencies in the mayor’s office to rubber stamp or give

legitimation to the mayor’s pet schemes. In still other cases, they

do exhibit a certain amount of initiative. Generally, the life of the

assemblies has been muted by the centralistic or paternalistic behavior of this highly self-centered “socialist” mayor who is committed, together with his “class enemy,” the business community,

to economic growth, expansionist “planning” notions, and a presumably “radical” version of Reaganesque “supply-side” economics in which the “poor, the elderly, and the working people” (to

use City Hall’s most favored nouns) are supposed to indirectly

benefit from the construction of hotels, condominiums, boutiques,

department stores, and the like. That this kind of “growth” has

significantly changed Burlington physically and produced major

economic differences between its poorer neighborhoods and more

well-to-do ones is an experience that is not unique to the otherwise

easy-going communities of northern New England.

What can be done in a city like this—and, for that matter, in a

state like Vermont?

Minimally, Burlington could benefit enormously from a municipalist political movement whose candidates are ultimately mandated and recallable by citizens’ assemblies. I refer not to the

NPAs, which are actually gerrymandered ward organizations, but

to assemblies that are rooted in authentic neighborhoods where

the citizenry shares common economic, cultural, and political interests. Such neighborhoods exist in Burlington, as they do in

many cities and towns of America. But they have been shrewdly

amalgamated with other neighborhoods, often very different in

character, to produce a melange of conflicting interests that favor

oligarchic control of municipal politics.

These mandated and recallable delegates—in no way to be

confused with “representatives” who are free to make policy decisions—could initially form a “board of aldermen” or, if you like, a

council of assembly delegates to parallel the official aldermanic

board itself. The council, while legally powerless in its initial

phases, could exercise a very effective moral influence on the

official Board of Aldermen until it acquires increasing legal power

of its own. It could track the agenda and business of the official

board in every detail, expand it at will, or challenge such legislative measures that it finds unsuitable in the public interest. By the

same token, it could run its own regular aldermanic candidates

who, hopefully, would be expected to act as a voice for the parallel

council within the city administration. All actions of the council,

in turn, would have to be confirmed or could be altered by the

assemblies so that each delegate would merely be the repository

of his or her assembly’s views on specific issues.

Optimally, it would be the goal of the Council of Assembly

Delegates to replace the Board of Aldermen and institute genuine

town-meeting democracy in Burlington. There is no reason why,

from a strictly administrative viewpoint, such a change would

affect in any way the normal operations of the city. The only

objection to this system of self-governance I have encountered is

that it is “too democratic,” not that it is “disruptive.” Such objections generally imply that the citizenry of the city is “incompetent” to deal with public matters, an objection that could obviously be raised against town-meeting governance itself if its

centuries of success were not compelling testimony to the contrary.

What I have described for Burlington could exist for Vermont

as a whole. Actually, until the late 1960s, state government in

Vermont was largely run by the municipalities. The state’s House

of Representatives was chosen by townships, riot by electoral districts based on population numbers. Accordingly, large Vermont,

towns had two representatives for example, and small communities had one. Towns thus directly controlled the House, not anonymous voters who were demographic ally agglomerated together

with no political roots in a civic collectivity. Admittedly, a system

so constricted to one or two representatives from a city or township favored a minority of voters, generally rural at the expense

of urban populations, but politics was conducted in a more organic

fashion than it is today. Town-meeting discussions favored a decent measure of public consensus and widespread public participation in a richer political process than mere “voting.” Voters

were not mere spectators in a legislative duel conducted in the

state capital; they came fairly close to being direct participants in

it, placing their representatives under regular public review at

town meetings or in the daily life of their communities. A 1966

U.S. Supreme Gourt decision, the famous “one vote for one voter”

decision, swept this structure away as an “undemocratic” archaism. However faulty the original system—faults that could have

easily been corrected by increasing the representation of larger

communities, not by eliminating this kind of representation completely—Vermonters were not reduced to a mere electorate or its

politically concerned people turned into mere constituqnts..

Federal law preempts state law—in Vermont, of course, no less

than other American states, although the Vermont Senate, from

its inceptioii early in the nineteenth century, has always been

elected from couritywide voting,districts. Hence, there is a sense

in which both systems, the strictly electoral one as well as the

municipal one, coexisted throughout most of the state’s history

and, balanced each other out. Short of changing the federal Constitution itsfelf, there is no way in which this balance can be restored

or made more equitable. Nor would it be desirable for any legislative body to structure itself around a system that provides one vote

in the House for a, sparsely populated township and the same for

another that is densely populated. But there is no reason why a

third house in addition to the Senate and House of Representatives cannot be established on a statewide basis, a Council of Assembly Delegates, from all the townships and cities of Vermont,

which would function as a *moral* monitor of the official state legislature. This “parallel” ethical system of governance, legitiinated

by the will of the people in yermont’s municipalities and corresponding to the “second chamber” in Burlington’s civic government, could “enact” its own “laws” and ordinances^ carefully

scrutinizirig, criticizing, and correcting legislation that is under

consideration in the Senate and House. It could function as the

popular voice of the citizenry articulated into communities rather

than anonymous voters. No less than in Burlington, the delegates

of such a statewide council could be mandated and recallable by

the communities from which they are chosen, and their choice

would be more reflective of populatiori differences than the House

that existed before the 1966 Supreme Court decision.

I would like to advance a more general argument: firstly, that

the emergence of paralegal and morally powerful assemblies of

delegates from the, townships and cities of Vermont as well as

within the state’s cities could begin to create a radically new political climate, activating Vermont’s citizens and profoundly influencing the very nature of legislation and ways of legislating in

the state. With a visibly grass-roots and institutionalized assembly

of municipal delegates tracking a less representative state legislature, Vermont’s politics could probably change in a very crucial

way. Governance by legislative command, with its panoply of

penalties and coercion, would begin to yield to governance by

moral suasion, with its evocation of public responsibility and individual probity. Statecraft, which has always been premised on the

public’s incompetence to govern itself and its ultimate recourse to

violence, would increasingly give way to politics with its classical

vision of community life as an ethical compact. This conceptual

framework, which sees human consociation as a distinctly human,

and humane, attribute of individual socialization—so markedly in

contrast to the egoistic and interest-oriented, indeed disciplinary

image of the contemporary public sphere—would mark a highly

significant turn in the way we conceive the management of society

and the participation of its citizenry in the political process. A dual

structure of municipal government, paralleling the state’s conventional legal structure, could open a creative institutional restructuring of the body politic—one that would not only countervail the

centralizing and destructuring process of urbanization and growing state power but introduce a new principle of politics based on

morality as well as cooperation and personal responsibility.

Secondly, I would like to point out that the leap from local to

statewide forms of municipal control, even in so small a state as

Vermont, may well open an institutional gap between town and

state that could create a problematic area for a hybridized form

of statecraft, neither political nor statist—one that would vitiate

the entire project of a moral politics. What is worth recognizing

is that the county system in Vermont provides a remarkable arena

not only for closing this structural gap but also for enhancing this

new kind of politics. Vermont’s seventeen counties, patched together by their quiltwork of numerous townships, provide an almost ideal jurisdictional unit for municipal confederations, each of which could be united by its own County Confederation of

Municipalities and organized in all essentials like the councils of

assembly delegates within the cities and the Council of Assembly

Delegates for the entire state. These countywide confederations

would have the extremely important function of pooling the resources of Vermont’s townships and cities to maintain roads,

schools, public lands, and provide many other vital services that

have been preempted by the conventional state government and

legitimate its increasingly centralized powers. The countywide

confederations would thus not only enhance the moral authority

of Vermont’s municipal assemblies and form a connecting link

between the townships and their statewide council; they would

become the all-important material repository for reclaiming the

financial control exercised by the legislature and executive branch

over vital services such as road maintenance, services that cannot

be dealt with alone by smaller communities in the state.

The municipalization of Vermont’s economy would have to

occur in piecemeal steps, I suspect, and on many different levels,

indeed in such a way as not to infringe on the proprietary rights

of small retail outlets, service establishments, artisan shops, small

farms, local manufacturing enterprises, and the like. Rather, this

process might **begin as a transitional measure** with the reclamation of public lands by the municipalities, indeed where funds

exist with the purchase of sizable enterprises, particularly those

that are failing financially and could be managed more efficiently

by their workers than by profit-oriented entrepreneurs. The use

of land trusts as a means not only for providing good public housing but promoting small-scale, often artisanal production would

occupy a high place on the agenda of a municipality’s economic

program. Cooperatives, farms, and small retail outlets would be

fostered with municipal funds and placed under growing public

control—a policy that might very well command greater consumer loyalty than we would expect to find toward failing corporate enterprises.

Viewed in a still broader perspective, it is crucially important

that a municipal movement foster a new psychological ambience—a sense of civic loyalty and responsibility that would make each

citizen feel committed to the success of a moral economy. Even

more than the well-known “underground economy” that has

revived barter and mutual aid in the exchange of goods and services, the municipality’s citizens would have to feel that they have

a personal stake in the community’s welfare. This is a function of

citizen empowerment, not of political rhetoric. A citizen’s stake in

a moral economy has to be real and visible in the sense that the

municipality’s economy has to be public business in a highly expressive and democratic form—the subject of vigorous discussion

in neighborhood assemblies and town meetings, the object of voluntary services, stemming from a highly personalized knowledge

of how the economy is functioning as well as how it can he enhanced by greater citizen participation.

A moral economy is either a moral enterprise that is guided by

a genuine spiritual desire to create one, even at the expense of

strictly economic considerations, or it will degenerate into another

profit-oriented and exploitative, use of resources. Citizens who are

not prepared to pay higher prices to support such an economy and

volunteer their own efforts on its behalf are not likely to be prepared for self-governance in. any form. Hence the need for a new

municipal politics to become an intensely educational and participatory experience at every level of civic life. The appalling

failure of so many “progressive” movements in the towns and

cities of America to recognize the need for civic *paideia* in the

classical meaning of the term accounts for the repeated compromises that have made the heroic periods of their administrations

so listless and routine after a few years in office. Doubtless, a full

armamentorium of economic, fiscal, and administrative devices

can be psed to make a municipalist politics workable; for example,

Proudhon’s vision of a “People’s Bank” that will collect funds from

the populace at large to finance municipal projects; the direct sale

of locally grown food from farmer to consumer that will provide

special price advantages for both; more barter, comprehensive

mutual aid networks, and the use of public land to foster domestic

gardening—these are only some of the many possible projects that

could give tangibility to a moral economy. The fostering of civic

voluntarism, such as unpaid public efforts to construct community

centers, parks, squares, and other structures that would provide

citizens with places for public discussion and personal intercourse,

and efforts to collect funds (a sort of voluntary taxation, if you like)

to beautify and improve the community—all can be viewed as

moral challenges to the citizenry’s civic probity and its commitment to assume responsibility for its own community. But none of

these efforts or projects are likely to succeed if a new politics is not

educational, indeed if it is not a new form of civic enlightenment

that challenges the citizenry to take control of its own community.

It may well be that this *civicisme*, as the French called it two

centuries ago, can no longer flourish in an urbanized world that

has been so extensively commodified and permeated by a market

economy. But it may well be that precisely because of the deep

frustration this urbanized and commodified world has produced,

the will to create a new politics, citizenship, ecologically viable

habitat, and municipal economy lies directly below the surface of

conventional behavior as we know it today, waiting to break

through if creative and imaginative alternatives are developed.

Much of this book consists primarily of accounts drawn mainly

from the past that demonstrate how the hidden aspirations of

ordinary people welled up and exploded into powerful localist

movements that profoundly redefined politics and citizenship in

ways that emphasized the authority of the community over the

state and self-empowerment over statecraft. There is no reason to

believe that the most human of impulses, the need for consociation and community support, can be irretrievably cast into a limbo

from which there is no redemption. Indeed, once released, this

impulse often tends to surge forward beyond all the prescribed

boundaries we normally impose upon it. If state power begets

state power, so too does self-governance beget self-governance. It

has seldom failed that whatever power people gain from the state,

the state, in turn, loses institutionally as well as legitimately. A

historic verdict that will finally place the state over the municipality has yet to be rendered conclusively. The greater danger we,

face is that even those localists most committed in theory may

have lost the existential commitment to turn their visions into

practice. Sweeping as urbanization may be today, it has still not

swept the ideal of the free, confederally organized municipality

from the agenda of history—and as long as it exists there, it is

something devoutly worth fighting for.

----

Never has it been so necessary to place every innovative practice in

the light of a visionary ethical ideal. Ironically, this is the great

edge that reaction has over progress: its shrewd emphasis on ethics

and matters of spirit in an increasingly meaningless as well as

materialistic world. It has been noted With irony that Nazism

achieved much of its success among the German people a half

century ago not because of any economic panaceas it offered in

opposition to its competitors from the center and left but because

of its mythic ideal of nationhood, community, and social regeneration. In more recent times, reactionary movements in America

have won millions to their cause on such moral grounds as the

integrity of the family, religious dogma, the renewal of patriotism,

and the right to life—a message, I may add, that has been construed not only as a need for antiabortion legislation but as a hypostasization of the sacredness of the individual, born as well as

unborn.

Characteristically, liberal and radical causes are still mired in

economistic and productivistic panaceas. Their moral message,

once a heightened plea for social justice, has given way increasingly to strictly material demands. Far more than the right, which

avows egoism even as it emphasizes community virtues, the political middle ground and the left avow a solid bourgeois gospel of

bread on the table and money in the bank. The spiritual emptiness

that a market society produces in such large numbers of Americans has largely ceased to be a problem of the very people who

profess to oppose that society, a failure in ethical vision that has

left them isolated and puzzled.

The word “moral” must be repeated—not as rhetoric to match

the claims of reaction but as the felt spiritual underpinnings of a

new social vision. It must be repeated not as part of a patronizing

sermon but as a living practice that people incorporate into their

personal lives and their communities. The vacuity and triviality of

life today must be filled precisely by those visionary ideals that

sustain the human side of life as well as its material side, or else

the coordinates by which the future should be guided will totally

disappear in that commodity oriented world we call the “marketplace of ideas.” The more serious indecency of this “marketplace”

is that these ideals will be turned into objects—mere commodities—that will lack even the value of things we need to sustain us.

They will become the mere ornaments needed to garnish an inherently antihuman and antiecological society that threatens to

undermine moral integrity as such and the simple social amenities

that foster human intercourse.

A municipal agenda to countervail urbanization and all that it

signifies is not a mere program, such as we expect from rival

parties and electoral coalitions. Programs, whether “green” or

“red,” radical or liberal, are shopping fists of demands, precisely

suited for that “marketplace of ideas” we have misnamed “politics.” They are ideological agents for effacing crucial differences in

outlook. The need for thinking out ideas and giving them coherence, which alone imparts meaning to an agenda for a new municipal politics, is lost and in that loss is replaced by the chaos of

ideological confusion. A cranky pluralism replaces a stern appreciation of focused thinking; a confused eclecticism replaces the need

for wholeness, clarity, and consistency. The ecology movement

and movements for a new politics have been plagued by this

indigestible fare for decades, a problem that has grown even

worse due to the cultural illiteracy that plagues American society.

Any attempt to countervail urbanization and replace it with a

new politics and authentic citizenship must not only be a movement for ethical renewal, clearly focused in its analysis and goals;

it must also be a movement that has a sense of “home,” as it were,

as well as a sense of mission. Most movements that derive from the

liberal center or the left are notable for their lack of any roots in

traditions that are dear to Americans or articulate the best in their

history. Given the emphasis of these movements on centralism,

planning, coordination, and mass mobilization, they stand inherently at odds with a creative American legacy that formulated its

ideals of freedom around decentrafism, popular initiative, confederation, and individualism—ideals that admittedly can be degraded by manipulative reactionaries for authoritarian ends but

can also be enlarged and given a more responsive, humanistic

meaning for more emancipatory goals. That decentrafism can

mean local parochialism, even racism; confederation, a denial of

any rational coordination of resources and services; and individualism, a psychology of rampant egotism—all are simply the most

negative way of viewing a constellation of notions whose logic can

yield genuine freedom. That these very ideals of freedom guided

the radical movements of heretical Christianity centuries ago,

nourished the English, American, and French revolutions in a

more recent time, inspired the Communards of 1871, and surfaced again in Spain during the 1930s as well as among various

citizens’ and civic movements during the past two generations

should be enough to give the most sectarian radicals pause before

denouncing them. It remains to the great credit of early populism,

not only in America but in Russia and Spain, embellished by their

own anarchistic traditions, to have extracted the diamond of radicalism from the rubbish heap of reaction. A new politics and sense

of citizenship in America still awaits a movement that can occupy

itself with the difficult process of separating the jewel from its

matrix and making it glitter as it once did.

It will not do to live on a diet of hating America because of its

adventures abroad or its mistreatment of ethnic minorities at

home any more than it will due to immunize the country from

criticism by dressing it in a flag and perverting its revolutionary

origins in a struggle for freedom. Indeed, it would be a far more

worthy and historically sound enterprise to disengage the democratic traditions and institutions of the country such as its town

meetings and its Bill of Rights from a very mistaken notion that

they are, entangled with the “bourgeoisie,” whatever this word

means these days. The words “bourgeois democracy” turn history

into a canard: the real bourgeoise of the past never favored democracy in any form. A more searching account of the great democratic revolutions of two centuries ago reveals that they were

committed primarily to a constitutional monarchy and only resigned themselves to an oligarchic form of republicanism whose

model was senatorial Rome. It was the people, often of varied class

origins, who foisted the liberties we enjoy today on the possessing

classes, classes that consistently tried to pervert them and are still

in the business of perverting them. Tragically; reaction has been

permitted to appropriate the “American Dream” and give it a

chauvinistic meaning while liberals arid radicals have mocked it,

degrading it in their own way for ends that are often no less

authoritarian than those of their opponents.

Yet this “American Dream” has many faces, and it still remains

to be seen whether its most liberatory, visionary, and utopian

aspects will find expression in the credo of a new politics. One face

of the dream was born in yeoman New Erigland, where community acquired ascendancy over privatism; individuality over egotism; decentralism over the concentration of power; direct democracy over republicanism. Another face was born in the cowboy

west, where the privatism of the ruggedly individualistic “lone

rider” was hypostasized over the “fence-rearing” farmer and his

family; where egoism was enclosed by the perimeter of the lonely

campfire; where to be armed was a token not of the free citizen

but the marauding gun slinger; and where social chaos prevailed

over democracy and republicanism,alike. Still another face of the

“American Dream” was added by the late-coming immigrant for

whorri American cities were not only refuges from European oppression but, as the maxim has it, where “the streets were paved

with gold.” This face featured no particular virtues beyond personal security from arbitrary rule and material well-being. History

has scrambled these faces together so that they now appear a blur,

not a unified tradition in which one face stands at odds with the

others.

A municipal agenda that does not piece together the emancipatory features of the “American Dream” such that this agenda can

speak in a clear and unqualified voice to the American people will

not be worth the paper on which it is written. Americans, no less

than Europeans, must recover, a whole that has been served up to

them in fragments: their history as a story of human freedom, not

merely as the history of the freedom of property, trade, and the

unbridled egoism of greed. For decades, social innovators have

talked to the American people in German (Marx), Russian (Lenin),

Chinese (Mao), Vietnamese (Ho Chi Minh), indeed in virtually

every language but English—which is to say, in the language of

traditions and “isms” that are largely incomprehensible to Americans. An ethical and visionary case can now be made, perhaps

more than at any time before, that community, individuality, decentralism, and direct democracy are ideologically more “homelike” than “rugged individualism,” egoism, gun slinging, and

chaos. Arriericans have welcomed this yeoman American message

eagerly—as the cynical right and one of the country’s oldest presidents have clearly demonstrated—only to see it betrayed into a

cowboy parody. They no longer believe that their “streets are

paved with gold,” if only because the immigrant generation that

accepted this myth has already passed into history. The political

landscape is open again for the revival of a dream that emphasizes

community, decentralism, individuality, and direct democracy.

The yearning to render it applicable to a modern America is intense, if only it can be properly articulated and earnestly advanced. It will be an unpardonable failure in political creativity if

a movement that professes to speak for a new politics does not try

to occupy that landscape but rather, in a self-indulgent “hate

America” mood, debarks to a “Third World” ideological ghetto

abroad with shrieks about the ‘‘mad dogs of imperialism,” snarling

perpetually at its most natural allies at home—the ordinary citizen

desiccated by his or her own spiritual poverty.

Nor can a new politics ignore the most essential attribute of that

dream: its molecular nature and its gradual development from

neighborhood and town to county and region. Dreams are more

than party platforms, which are normally violated or ignored.

Attempts to reconstruct an authentic politics—not another ensemble of statecraft techniques—involve a remaking of the body

politic itself: politics conceived as the recovery of citizenship and

civic education. This kind of politics has an almost cellular form of

growth, a process that involves organic proliferation and differentiation such as that of a child in a womb. To “engineer” a politics

into existence the way one puts together an automobile engine

with its engine block, gaskets, cylinders, spark plugs, and the like

is to desecrate the meaning of the word “politics,” itself, not to

speak of the disdain it exhibits for the human freight that this

engine is meant to bring to polling booths and the “citizenry” or

“voters” it is meant to mobilize. Until the social innovators of our

day discard the notion that the “political process” is a matter of

mobilization rather than education, of charismatic leaders rather

than participatory citizens, of “bread-on-the-table” panaceas

rather than visionary ideals charged with ethical meaning, their

politics, far from being “new,” will be the old authoritarian statecraft garnished with mere rhetoric.

A new political agenda is necessarily a municipal agenda—or it

is neither an agenda for remaking society nor politics in any meaningful sense of the term. The living cell which forms the basic unit

of political life is the municipality from which everything else

must emerge: confederation, interdependence, citizenship, and

freedom. There is no way to piece together any politics—old or

new—unless we begin with its most elementary forms: the villages, towns, neighborhoods, and cities in which people live on the

most immediate level of political interdependence, the only level

that is the next step beyond private life. It is on this level that they

can begin to gain a familiarity with the political process, a process

that involves a good deal more than “voting” and “information”—a term that has become the modern substitute for wisdom. It is

on this level that they can go beyond the privateness and parochialism of family life—a life that is celebrated for its inwardness and

seclusion—and improvise those public institutions that make for

participation and consociation. In short, it is from the municipality

that people can reconstitute themselves from isolated monads into

a creative body politic and create an existentially vital, indeed

protoplasmic, civic life that has institutional form as well as civic

content: the block committees, assemblies, neighborhood organizations, cooperatives, citizens’ action groups, and public arena for

discourse that go beyond such episodic acts as demonstrations and

retain a lived as well as organized continuity. To ignore this irreducible civic unit of political life is to play chess without a chessboard,

for it is here that the coordinates exist for playing the game in its

most direct, basic, and intimate sense.

I have tried in this book to formulate a body of ideas that have

meaning for the political restructing of our times, not another

handbook that offers recipes for how to make a “revolution” in

one’s backyard or front lawn. I have tried to suggest a political

philosophy that lends itself to modification, extension, and a decent regard for the great variety of needs that distinguish one

community from another, not a blueprint that dogmatizes and

rigidifies the idea of freedom into an inflexible credo. But I do not

seek to rarify this political philosophy of civicism into a mere

intellectual duel with abstract philosophies that stand in opposition to it. This book has been thoroughly informed by history—not

because I seek lived “precedents” for truths that deserve to rest

on their own intrinsic worth rather than “expediency” or, to use

what has become a synonym for that term, “efficiency.” Political

life is not legitimated by how well it “works.” If it were, totalitarianism could be more successfully legitimated because it is generally more “efficient” than democracy, just as business techniques

are more “effective” than that “wasteful” process involved in’ debates and free forms of decision making. Doubtless, “time is

money,” but freedom is a way of life that even money cannot buy—or certainly should not.

My recourse to history and to speculations about my own community, Burlington, and its Vermont setting is primarily an endeavor to show that living human beings, not their science-fiction

replicas, actually engaged in and continue to involve themselves

in a political process that may initially seem visionary when it is

presented abstractly. I have tried to show that our contemporary

market society; only three or four decades old at best, and our

two-centuries-old market economy were preceded by a far more

mixed society and economy, possibly four centuries old, that

phased out of a rigidly structured feudalworld, later to phase into

a chaotically destructured capitalist world. What men and women

have done in the past and, in some degree, continue to do today

can certainly be recovered again. These people were no less real

than we—all rhetoric about the fixidity of human nature to the

contrary notwithstanding; If they went from a highly structured

world through a centuries-long “transition” formed around a

highly mixed, almost ecological economy and society, to a very

recent destructured market society, who is to say which of the

three is merely “transitional,” “climatic,”’ or constitutes evidence

of a steady ascent in history? It may well be that our present-day

market society is evidence of social regression, not of social progress; indeed that the insane proliferation of commodity relationships that embodies all human ties in mere objects constitutes a

cancer of social life as such, not, as Marx would have it, a “precondition” for a free society in an idealized, Eurocentric image of social progress.

This book has also been informed by another belief: power that

is not retained by the people is power that is given over to the

state. Conversely, whatever power the people gain is power that

must be taken away from the state. There can be no institutional

vacuum where power exists: it is either invested in the people or

it is invested in the state. Where the two “share” power, this

condition is only temporary and extremely precarious. Sooner of

later, the control of society arid its destiny will either shift toward

the people and their communities at its base or the professional

practitioners of statecraft at its summit. Only if the whole pyramidal structure is dismembered and turned from a vertical hierarchy

into a horizontal ecocommunity—modelled more on what ecologists diagram as a “food web” than a “food pyramid” (with humans invariably at its apex)—will the issue of power and domination as

such disappear and be completely replaced by participation and

the principle of complementarity.

Power, however, must be conceived as real, indeed solid and

tangible, not only as spiritual and psychological. To ignore the fact

that power is a muscular fact of life is to drift from the visionary

into the ethereal and mislead the public as to its crucial significance in affecting society’s destiny. What this means is that if

power is to be regained by the people from the state, the management of society must be deprofessionalized as much as possible.

That is to say, it must be simplified and rendered transparent,

indeed, clear, accessible, and manageable such that most of its

affairs can be run by ordinary citizens. This notion, with its emphasis on amateurism as distinguished frorn professionalism, is not

new. It formed the basis of Athenian democratic practice for generations. Indeed, it was so ably practiced that sortition rather than

election formed the basis of the *polis*’s democracy. It was to resurface again repeatedly, for example, in the very simple constitution

written by Vermont’s yeomanry two centuries ago, a constitution

that is still notable for the brevity of its articles and the minimal

amount of statute law that clothes it.

Power is also a solid and tangible fact to be reckoned’with

militarily, notably in the ubiquitous truth that the power of the

state or the people eventually reposes in force. Whether or not the

state has power depends upon whether or not the state exercises

a monopoly of violence. By the same token, whether or not the

people have power depends upon whether or not it is armed and

creates its own grass-roots militia, not only to guard itself from

criminals or invaders but also from the ever-encroaching power of

the state itself. Here, too, the Athenian and Vermont yeomen

knew only too well that a professiorial military was a threat to

liberty and the state was a vehicle for disarming the people.

A true civicism that tries to create an authentic politics, an

empowered citizenry, and a municipalized economy would be a

vulnerable project indeed if it failed to replace the police, the

professional army, even that pseridomilitia, the National Guard,

with an authentic militia, a civic guard, composed of rotating

patrols for police purposes and well-trained citizen military contingents for dealing with external dangers to freedom. Greek democracy would never have survived the repeated assaults of the

Greek aristocracy without its militia of citizen **hoplites**, those foot

soldiers who could answer the call to arms with their own weapons

and elected commanders. The tragic history of the state’s ascendancy over autonomous municipalities, even the history of the rise

of oligarchy within free cities of the past, is the story of armed

professionals who commandeered power from unarmed peoples

or disarmed them presumably (as so many liberals would have it

today) from the “hazards” of domestic and neighborhood “shootouts.” Typically, this is the cowboy or “gunslingers” image of the

“American Dream,” often cynically imposed on its more traditional yeoman face.

----

Beyond the immediate agenda i have presented thus far lies another

one: a political world in which the state as such will finally be

replaced by a confederal network of municipal assemblies; the

corporate economy reduced to a truly political economy in which

municipalities, interacting with each other economically as well as

politically, will resolve their material problems as citizen bodies in

open assemblies, not simply as professionals, farmers, and blue- or

white-collar workers. Not only will they then transform themselves from occupational beings into public beings, but they will

create a world in which all weapons can indeed be beaten into

plowshares and ultimately a human ecocommunity that will be

exquisitely tailored psychologically and spiritually as well as technologically, archictecturally, and structurally to the natural eco-communities that compose our planet.

I would hope that such an agenda would offer an image of a

nonhierarchical as well as a classless community in which differentiation, natural as well as social, is respected without that divisive

sense of “otherness” that has produced such disastrous effects—on

our relationship with our own kind and the life forms that share

the planet with us.

This second agenda for a more distant future embodies the

“ultimate” vision I have elaborated in greater detail in my previous writings. Its achievement can no longer be seen as a sudden

“revolution” that within a brief span of time will replace the

present society with a radically new one. Actually, such revolutions never really happened in history as the litany of their failures

so dramatically reveals. Even the French Revolution, which radicals have seized upon as a “paradigm” of sudden social change,

was generations in preparation and did not come to its end until

a century later, when the last of the *sans culottes* were virtually

exterminated on the barricades of the Paris Commune.

Nor can there be any myth today that barricades are more than

symbols and a civic guard is little more than a first step toward

disarming the state, a feeble step at that, albeit a crucial assertion

of where the “monopoly of violence” should really repose—if violence can be mitigated in a world that is overstocked with nuclear

bombs. What links my minimal agenda to my ultimate one is a

process, an admittedly long development in which the existing

institutions and traditions of freedom are slowly enlarged and

expanded. “Revolution” originally meant the restoration of.traditional rights in the context of a changed world, a legitimation of

emancipation by the power and dignity of tradition. For the present, we must try to democratize the republic, a call that often is

simply defensive and consists of preserving and expanding freedoms we have earned centuries ago together with the institutions

that give them reality. For the future it means that we must

radicalize our democracy, imparting a utopian and creative content to the democratic institutions we have rescued. Admittedly,

at that point we will have moved from a countervailing position

that tries to play our democratic institutions against the state into

an aggressive attempt to replace the state with municipally based

confederal structures. It is to be devoutly hoped that by that time,

the state power itself will have been hollowed out institutionally

by local or civic structures, indeed that its very legitimacy, not to

speak of its authority as a coercive force, will simply lead to its

collapse in any period of confrontation. If the great revolutions of

the past can be used to provide us with examples of how so major

a shift is possible, it would be well to remember that seemingly

all-powerful monarchies that the republics replaced two centuries

ago were so denuded of power that they crumbled rather than

“fell” much as a mummified corpse turns to dust after it has been

suddenly exposed to air.

Another ultimate vision also faces us: one in which urbanization

will so completely devour the city and the countryside that the

word “community” will become an archaism; a market society

filtering into the most private recesses of our lives as individuals

and effacing all sense of personality, much less individuality; a

state that will not only render politics and citizenship a mockery

of these words but a maw that will absorb the very notion of

freedom itself.

This “vision,” if such it can be called, is still sufficiently removed

from our most immediate experience so that its realization can be

arrested by those countervailing forces—that dual power—I have

outlined in the previous pages. Given the persistent destructuring

of the natural world as well as the social, more than human freedom and autonomy are in the balance. The proliferation of nuclear

reactors, like that of nuclear weapons, is a reminder that we are

reaching a point of almost cosmic finality in our affairs on this

planet; that the recovery of an authentic politics and citizenship

is not only a precondition for a free society. It is also a precondition

for our survival as a species. Hanging over us is the shadow of a

completely destructured and simplified natural world as well as a

completely destructured and simplified urban world—a natural

world so ossified and divested of its variety that we, like all other

complex life forms, will be unable to exist as viable beings.

{1} George Orwell: 1984 (New York: Signet; 1950), p. 156.

{2} James Melaart: Çatal HĂŒyĂŒk (London: Thames and Hudson; 1967),

pg. 58.

{3} Fred Wendorf, Romuald Schied, and Angela E. Close: “An Ancient

Harvest on the Nile,” Science 82, November, 1982, pg. 68.

{4} Ibid., p. 73.

{5} Karl Polanyi: Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economics: Essays of

Karl Polanyi, George Dalton, ed. (Boston: Beacon Press; 1968), p. 81.

{6} Jean-Jacques Rousseau: The Social Contract (New York: Everyman

Edition; 1950), p. 15.

{7} Aristotle: Politics (London: Loeb Classical Library; 1932), 1326a30-

40. Translation modified by author.

{8} Ibid., 1280a-1280b.

{9} Aristotle, op. cit., 1252a3. Translation modified by author.

{10} Lilly Ross Taylor: Roman Voting Assemblies (Ann Arbor: University

of Michigan Press; 1966), p. 2.

{11} Ibid., p. 3.

{12} Ibid., p. 3

{13} Jean-Jacques Rousseau, op. cit., p. 94.

{14} Niccolo Machiavelli: The Prince (New York: The Modern Library

Editions; 1940), pp. 45–46.

{15} Henri Frankfort: The Birth of Civilization in the Near East (New

York: Doubleday & Co.; 1956), p. 77.

{16} M.I. Finley: Democracy-Ancient and Modern (New Brunswick,

N.J.: Rutgers University Press; 1973), p. 22.

{17} Claude Mosse: The Ancient World at Work (New York: W.W. Norton

& Co.; 1969), pp. 27–28.

{18} Alfred Zimmern: The Greek Commonwealth (New York: The Modern Library Editions; n.d.), p. 59.

{19} Plutarch: “Solon” in The Rise and Fall of Athens (Harmondsworth:

Penguin Books, Ltd.; 1960), p. 54.

{20} Ibid., p. 62.

{21} Quoted in Thucydides: The Peloponnesian War (New York: Modern

Library Editions; 1944), pp. 121–22.

{22} T.B.L. Webster: Life in Classical Athens (London: B.T. Batsford,

Ltd.; 1969), p. 87.

{23} W.G. Forrest: The Emergence of Greek Democracy (New York:

McGraw-Hill Book Co.; 1966), p. 214.

{24} Aeschylus: *Oresteia* (Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1953),

735–40.

{25} Ibid., 681–706

{26} W.G. Forrest, op. cit., p. 204; George Thomson: Aeschylus and Athens (New York: Grosset & Dunlop; 1968).

{27} M. Rostovtzeff: Rome (London: Oxford Univerity Press; 1960), p. 104.

{28} Ibid., p. 100.

{29} Ibid., p. 104.

{30} Heinrich Heine: Reisebilder, quoted by Ian Scott-Kilvert in Makers

of Rome: Nine Lives by Plutarch (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books,

Ltd., 1965), p. 12.

{31} Chester Starr: Civilization and the Caesars (New York: W.W. Norton

& Co.; 1965), p. 90.

{32} Ibid., p. 105.

{33} John H. Mundy and Peter Riesenberg: The Medieval Town (New

York: Van Nostrand Reinhold Co.; 1958), p. 18.

{34} Lauro Martines: Power and Imagination (New York: Vintage Books;

1980).

{35} John H. Mundy in “Introduction” to Henri Pirenne: Early Democ-

racy in the Low Countries (New York: W. W. Norton & Co.; 1963),

p. xxii fn.

{36} Lauro Martines, op. cit., p. 27.

{37} John H. Mundy: Europe in the High Middle Ages (London: Longman

Group Ltd.; 1973), p. 409.

{38} Lauro Martines, op. cit., p. 35–36.

{39} Ibid., p. 37.

{40} Daniel Waley: The Italian City Republics (New York: McGraw-Hill

Book Co.; 1969), p. 63.

{41} Ibid., p. 63.

{42} Lauro Martines, op. cit., p. 49.

{43} Ibid., p. 52.

{44} Quoted in John H. Mundy: Europe in the High Middle Ages. op. cit.,

p. 408.

{45} Ephraim Emerton: The Beginnings of Modern Europe (New York:

Ginn and Co.; 1917), p. 207.

{46} Daniel Waley, op. cit., p. 221.

{47} Ibid.

{48} Benjamin Barber: The Death of Communal Liberty (Princeton:

Princeton University Press; 1974), p. 263.

{49} F. Furet, C. Mazauric, and L. Bergeron: “The Sans-Culottes and the

French Revolution” in New Perspectives on the French Revolution,

Jeffry Kaplow, ed. (New York: John Wiley & Sons; 1965), p. 235.

{50} Ibid., pp. 234–35.

{51} Cited in Daniel Guerin: Class Struggles in the French Revolution

(London: Pluto Press; 1977), pp. 32–33.

{52} R.R. Palmer: The Age of Democratic Revolutions (Princeton: Prince-

ton University Press; 1959).

{53} Jacob Burckhardt: The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy (New

York: Phaidon Publishers; 1950), p. 2.

{54} J.A.O. Larsen: Greek Federal States (London: Oxford University

Press; 1967), p. 27.

{55} Peter Kropotkin: Mutual Aid (Montreal: Black Rose Books; n.d.).

{56} Ibid., pp. 204–5

{57} Ibid., p. 205

{58} F. Grenfell Baker, The Model Republic (New York, 1892) p. 308.

Quoted in Benjamin Barber, op. cit., pp. 14–15.

{59} Lewis Mumford: The City in History (New York: Harcourt Brace and

World; 1961), pp. 339–40.

{60} Daniel Waley, op. cit., p. 126.

{61} Perez Zagorin: Rebels and Rulers. 1500–1600, Vol. I (New York:

Cambridge University Press; 1982), p. 232.

{62} Fredrich Engels: The Peasant War in Germany (New York: International Publishers; 1926), p. 150.

{63} Cf.Joseph R. Strayer: On the Medieval Origins of the Modern State

(Princeton: Princeton University Press; 1970).

{64} Cf. Eric Hobsbawn: Primitive Rebels (Manchester: Manchester University Press; 1959).

{65} Perez Zagorin, op. cit., p. 93.

{66} Karl Marx: “Preface” to A Contribution to the Critique of Political

Economy Selected Works, (Moscow: Progress Publishers; 1969), Vol.

I, p. 504.

{67} Perez Zagorin, op. cit., p. 243.

{68} Ibid., p. 244.

{69} Mary Beard: A History of Business, Vol. I (Ann Arbor: University of

Michigan Press; 1938), p. 50.

{70} R.S. Lopez: “The Evolution of Land Transport in the Middle Ages,”

Past and Present, April, 1956, p. 17.

{71} Ibid., p. 18

{72} Ibid., p. 17.

{73} Cf. Paul Sweezy: “A Critique” and “A Rejoinder” in The Transition

From Feudalism to Capitalism, Rodney Hilton, ed. (London: New

Left Books; 1976), pp. 33–56, 102–8.

{74} Cf. Immanuel Wallerstein: Historical Capitalism (London: Verso

Editions; 1983).

{75} Fredrich Engels: The Condition of the Working Class in England in

1844 in Marx-Engels Collected Works, Vol. 4 (New York: International Publishers; 1975), p. 320.

{76} Ibid., p. 308.

{77} Ibid., p. 398.

{78} Ibid., p. 319.

{79} Jane Jacobs: Cities and the Wealth of Nations (New York: Random

House; 1984), pp. 31, 32.

{80} H. Mooseburger: Die Bundnerische Allemande (1891), p. 5. Quoted

in Benjamin Barber, op. cit., p. 112.

{81} Benjamin Barber, ibid., p. 15.

{82} Ibid., p. 49.

{83} Ibid., p. 100.

{84} Herman Weilenman: Pax Helvetica: Oder Die Demokratie der

Kleinen Gruppen, (Zurich, 1951). Quoted in Benjamin Barber, ibid.,

p. 101.

{85} T.H. Breen: Puritans and Adventurers (New York: Oxford University

Press; 1980), p. 3.

{86} Ibid., pp. 4–5.

{87} Massachusetts Centinal, June 24, 1786. Quoted in David P. Szat·

mary: Shays’ Rebellion (Amherst: University of Massachusetts; 1980),

p.l.

{88} George Richard Minot, quoted in Jackson Turner Main: Political

Parties Before the Constitution (New York: Norton; 1974), p. 96 fn.

{89} David P. Szatmary, op. cit., p. 6–7.

{90} Robert A. Gross: The Minutemen and Their World (New York: Hill

and Wang; 1976), pp. 10–11.

{91} David P. Szatmary, op. cit., pp. 10–11.

{92} Ibid., p. 11.

{93} James Warren, letter to John Adams, January 28, 1785, in Warren-Adams Letters, Vol. II (Boston: Massachusetts Historical Society;

1925), p. 249. Quoted in David Szatmary, ibid., p. 11.

{94} Max Horkheimer: The Eclipse of Reason (New York: Oxford University Press; 1947), p. 135.

Home