đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș anarcho-review-radical-economics-and-labor captured on 2023-07-22 at 20:48:36. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-07-10)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Review: Radical Economics and Labor Date: December 19, 2011 Source: Retrieved on 24<sup>th</sup> April 2021 from [[https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=595][anarchism.pageabode.com]] Authors: Anarcho, Iain Mc Kay Topics: Book review, Economics, Labor Published: 2021-04-24 14:03:31Z
The revolutionary union the **Industrial Workers of the World** marked its 100th anniversary in 2005. To mark this event a conference was held at the University of Missouri-Kansas City, hosted by the editors (Fred Lee and Jon Bekken) of this useful selection of talks from it. As well as an introduction, this book has ten chapters on a wide range of subjects on something often not much discussed in radical circles, political economy.
The first three chapter discuss aspects of the history of radical economics. The first, Noel Thompsonâs âSenexâs **Letters on Associated Labour** and **The Pioneer**, 1834â, discusses working class socialism in 1830s Britain. Focusing upon a series of letters published in the paper **The Pioneer**, it discusses the proto-syndicalist ideas of British socialists who had formulated both a critique of wage-labour (hired labour) and a vision of **associated** (free) labour to replace it. The aim was, to quote Letter XII, to âbanish the word wages from the language and consign it, with the word slavery, to histories and dictionaries.â (18).
This vision was one of co-operative market socialism, predating Proudhonâs vision â even down to the idea of establishing a bank. (16) Strangely, the introduction calls this an âalmost proto-Marxistâ (5) political economy so failing, like the article itself, to mention, never mind discuss, the clear links to Proudhonâs mutualism (who presented a critique of wage-labour that also predated Marxâs). Unsurprisingly given the nature of the conference, Thompson stresses the links to syndicalism and the IWW yet while these aimed to end âthe commodification of labourâ and ensure âdecentralised economic decision-makingâ (22) both tended to aim for communism rather than have fair prices.
The second chapter, Jon Bekkenâs âPeter Kropotkinâs anarchist economics for a new societyâ, is exceptional. Bekken makes the key point that Kropotkinâs economics âarose out an engagement with the workersâ movement of his dayâ and so reflected ânot abstract principlesâ but rather was âhoned in workersâ struggles and debates.â (27) This chapter covers almost all aspects of Kropotkinâs vision for communist-anarchism, presenting an excellent introduction to his ideas and ideals.
Bekken correctly stresses that Kropotkin argued what is efficient under capitalism may not be technically efficient but rather established âto facilitate manager controlâ (30) and âfacilitate market domination and control.â (40) Sadly, most on the left still follow Lenin in proclaiming the âefficiencyâ of large-scale production and so fail to comprehend that this is based on **capitalist** definitions of efficiency and economy and so on **capitalist** criteria! That Marxism bases itself on centralised, large scale industry because it is more âefficientâ and âeconomicâ suggests nothing less than that its âsocialismâ will be based on the same priorities of capitalism. This can be seen from Leninâs idea that Russia had to learn from the advanced capitalist countries, that there was only one way to develop production and that was by adopting capitalist methods of ârationalisationâ and management. Thus, for Lenin in early 1918 âour task is to study the state capitalism of the Germans, to spare **no effort** in copying it and not to shrink from adopting **dictatorial** methods to hasten the copying of it.â
Kropotkin was right to argue that socialism will need to develop **new** forms of economic organisation based on socialist principles. Thus we find Kropotkin arguing for the division of work against the division of labour, the latter being âinefficient â demoralising and fatiguing workers and stripping them of the knowledge and the means necessary to innovate in their work.â (39) The need was for the wealth of society (workplaces, lands, housing, roads, etc.) âmust be socialised and marshalled to meet the needs of the entire society.â (30)
Bekken rightly notes that Kropotkin recognised that workers are exploited by capital. âIf workers could meet their daily needs without hiring out their labour power,â he summarises, âfew would consent to surrender their control over their own labour in order to work for wagesâ which are âa mere fraction of the goods they produce.â (31) He also presents Kropotkin critique of the Labour Theory of Value (28â9) although this will not necessary convince someone familiar with all of Marxâs work. This is because while Kropotkin was right to point out Marx argued that prices were âproportionalâ to âthe amount of labour necessary for productionâ (28) this ignores that this was in volume 1 of **Capital** and was related to a simplifying assumption (namely, the same level of investment in all workplaces) which was later dropped in volume 3. Similarly, volume 1 does not actually suggest that commodityâs price is equal to its labour-cost (i.e., exchange value) independently of âexternal markets and social conditionsâ (28) but rather that prices are regulated by their cost of production towards which market prices are tending. However to be fair to Kropotkin, Marx mentioned this in a footnote.
So market prices are influenced by competition and, in the case of labour, Marx argued that wages were influenced by moral and historical factors (i.e., âsocial conditionsâ). Bekken is right to argue that âwage levels have little to do with the cost of reproductionâ but rather âthe relative economic, military and social power held by the respective parties.â (29) Marx did **not** explore how recognising that wages have a historical and moral element impacted on his core aim to reconcile exploitation of labour with goods selling at their values (cost of production). Similarly, he abstracted from (i.e., ignored!) class struggle in all three volumes of **Capital**, making these comments extremely relevant.
Finally, Bekken is correct to note the current poverty in the radical visions presented today that âmany socialists still accept the wage system and moneyâ (40) and, again rightly, points to Parecon (43) as an example. He fails to discuss Kropotkinâs ideas on the process of revolutionary change and transition (which Kropotkin considered as taking 4 or 5 years, as per the Great French Revolution). He does mention that Kropotkin argued that goods in short supply should be rationed during a revolution but does not discuss in the early stages of a social revolution all forms of money can/will be abolished. As no social revolution has so far done so, it is a valid question to discuss in light of this. To be fair, most would rightly consider this outside the scope of the article. Suffice to say, this is a different issue than systems like Parecon which envision money being used forever.
So an altogether impressive summary of Kropotkinâs ideas but while chapter 2 is extremely good, the next one by Matthew Forstater (âSome notes on anarchist economic thoughtâ) is disappointing. It tries to cover too much in too little space and so is lacking. At times it is extremely superficial. For example, he rightly rejects addressing âanarcho-capitalismâ when discussing anarchist economic ideas but he proclaims that this âshould more properly be called **libertarian**â! (46) Now, if anarchists acquiesce to the capitalist-right stealing the good name libertarian to describe their authoritarian, albeit privately hierarchical, ideology then what is the point?
Forstater is right that anarchism âis not only opposed to the State, but also capitalismâ he is just wrong to think that it is only anarchism âin this senseâ which is so. Anarchism, from the start, has always been anti-capitalist and anti-state and so to oppose just the latter is not libertarian in any sense of the word (as is more than confirmed if you read âanarcho-capitalistâ ideologues). So it is not quite right to state, like Forstater, that âanarchists share many of the traditional socialist positions opposing capitalismâ and that we âpart from socialists on a number of accounts.â Anarchists are libertarian socialists, so we part with **state** socialists on key issues. As for sharing âsocialist positionsâ, anarchists have often been first in advocating them (for example, Proudhon predated Marxâs theory of surplus-value being the result of exploitation in production caused by wage-labour by a few decades!).
Another example of the essayâs superficial nature is the repeating of the stereotype that anarchists favour âsmallâ levels of production and these must ânot be at a scale beyond the needs of the local productionâ (47) While Marxist diatribes against anarchism proclaim this with abandon, it is sad to see it here. Particularly when the **correct** position is stated on the next page, namely that anarchists âembrace the notion of appropriate (or intermediate) technology, that is, utilising organisational and technological means that are ecologically, politically, socially and economically appropriate.â (49) Thus we find Kropotkin stating that âif we analyse the modern industries, we soon discover that for some of them the co-operation of hundred, even thousands, of workers gathered at the same spot is really necessary. The great iron works and mining enterprises decidedly belong to that category; oceanic steamers cannot be built in village factories.â Similar arguments can be found in Proudhon.
It also seems strange to read that anarchists view âmunicipal confederalismâ as âthe basis for alternative economic planningâ (48) given that we have been arguing for economic federalism since Proudhon! Pointing to Bravermanâs âdistinction between the social division of labour and the detail worker, and his conclusionâ (48) is equally perplexing given this is also found in Proudhonâs work. It gets worse when he states the âMarxist approach may offer helpâ by suggesting âan historic approachâ (51) when this was precisely Proudhonâs argument in **System of Economic Contradictions** â not to mention the French anarchistâs general influence on Marx!
So this is weak chapter, promising far more than it delivers. The next two chapters are inspired by Piero Sraffaâs economic analysis and, ironically, come to completely opposite conclusions. Frederic S. Leeâs âThe economics of the Industrial Workers of the World: Job control and revolutionâ does not convince. The logic of his argument, backed up by numerous equations, is that âdirect action designed to affect the âreal wageâ for the working class by altering the money wage is not possibleâ and that âdirect action for increasing job control is necessary.â (72) While the current economic crisis may make you think otherwise, Lee argues that the âamount of surplus is determined by the capitalist class and by the stateâ and âthe only limit to profits is how many goods and services the capitalists and state want.â (69) If this were the case, why are bosses so keen to resist pay rises and unionisation? Or how can there be periodic general crisis periods when capital simply cannot make a profit? This is not to suggest that fighting for job control is not important, simply that this must be done **in addition to** fighting for wage increases â something this essay would end if taken to heart by workers.
While Lee is right to state that âMarxian and anarchist economic theory and critiques of capitalism draw largely on the same body of ideasâ and that âtheir analysis is similar if not identical in many respects,â (73) he fails to note that anarchists generally argued it first (although perhaps not to the same depth) and, his arguments to the otherwise not withstanding, we were correct to root exploitation in production and seek a solution there. To state âthe Marxian-anarcho-syndicalist arguments for direct actionâ (55) seems problematic given that the original Marxian position was that workers should use âpolitical actionâ (voting) to seizure power and syndicalist arguments for direct action developed in opposition to them (directly, in the case of Bakunin and the libertarian wing of the First International).
Which brings us to Tony Aspromourgosâ âEconomic Science and the Left: Thoughts on Sraffaâs equations and the efficiency of organised labor.â This is a much better use of Sraffaâs theoretical legacy, producing an excellent introduction to both his ideas and why they can be useful for rebel workers. This is because of its emphasis on the impact of class struggle on the distribution of income in an economy.
Unlike the neo-classical ideology that sees factors of production receiving their rightful âcontributionsâ to a commodity automatically, Saffraâs model points to the fact that âthe division of surplus between labour and capital is open to contest by wider forces, by social forces.â (81) This allows the impact of working class strength to be included in the analysis of the economy. Thus workers can, by struggle, influence the real wage, income distribution and profit rates (as they are, in the Saffrian analysis) âgiven from outside the system of price equationsâ it uses to model the economy. (81) The truth of this can be seen, as Aspromourgos notes, by the attitude of bosses to workers organising for âif unions were so impotent to affect outcomes, the Right would not be so determined to curtailâ them. (90)
In short, regardless of neo-classical claims otherwise, âcapitalism in and of itself does not require a unique outcome for the wage share and associated profitability of capital.â (82) Class struggle plays a key role â hence the support by capitalists of economic ideologies that deny it. As Aspromourgos, this means that economics is âa subject close to the (greedy) hearts of vested material interestsâ and so âextremely attractive forâ and âvery vulnerable to, ideological capture.â He uses the example of Chemists and how their political views are unlikely to be âpertinent to the scientific statusâ of their work â unlike economists! (83) How very true.
Also true is his conclusion, namely that this analysis gives the boss class âa rational basis to pursue class struggleâ (86) â which, of course, they do. Aspromourgos also recognises its importance for us, for âthis provides âspaceâ for organised labour to influence, and influence persistently (not merely temporarily), the distribution between wage and non-wage income.â (85) He then spoils it by stating âit is also open to organised labour to vigorously support political parties that project policiesâ that âadvanceâ working class interests. (87) It is almost like the last 150-plus years of trying this has not happened for many radicals! Suffice to say, we should not ignore political power (and no anarchist, Marxist myths notwithstanding, has ever suggested that) but rather than we recognise that electioneering has been the Achillesâ heal of socialism, becoming as reformist as Bakunin predicted.
Finally, Aspromourgos indicates how Sraffaâs work has âdestructive implicationsâ for âmarginalist capital theory (and thereby, it should be said, for the whole marginalist edifice).â (78) So it must be stressed that while the bruising debates of the 1960s (usually called the Cambridge Capital Controversy) saw the neo-classical economists lose to the Sraffa-inspired radicals (led by Joan Robinson), the mainstream economics professions continued on as if nothing had happenedâŠ
So this is an important chapter and one all radicals should read to get a better idea of why knowing economic theory (and its history) is important! And talking of which, the next chapter by Spencer J.Pack (âJohn Kenneth Galbraithâs new industrial state 40 years laterâ) usefully discusses an intellectual giant of post-war economic thought, left-liberal John Kenneth Galbraith.
Galbraith was Americaâs leading Keynesian and Institutionalist economist (with some post-Keynesians claiming him also) and Pack presents a good introduction and evaluation of his ideas and works, its strengths and weaknesses. Thus Pack notes that class struggle was âinsufficiently stressedâ (96) by Galbraith and that he âpaid insufficient attentionâ to the global nature of capitalism (97) but like Galbraith does not really discuss the stock market and rentier interests (like Keynes, Galbraith underestimated how willing these were to undergo euthanasia). On the positive side, Galbraith described capitalism as it was, not what the ideology proclaimed it and so âthe nature and role of big businessâ was âalways a central concern in his writings.â (101) He rightly placed planning at the heart of the modern corporate dominated economy, discussing their attempts to âtry to gain control over what is sold and what is supplied to minimise or get rid of disruptive market influencesâ (101) and uncertainty. It was this ever-expanding capitalist planning based on one criteria (profit) which Marx so tragically confused with a requirement for (even more) centralised social planning under socialism.
Moreover, Galbraithâs ideas on âcountervailing powerâ are important, even if we must ignore his hope that the (capitalist!) government would âhelp organise countervailing powers.â (98) He was right that countervailing power âis needed to counter original economic powerâ (98) but there is no requirement for it, as can be seen for the last 30 years of neo-liberalism. Indeed a powerful case can be made that our current problems flow from the fact that the people in charge of big business have no unions around to hold back the imposing of their craziest visions on their companies (and so society).
Pack usefully discusses the impact of this destruction on workersâ living standards, noting âstagnant living standardsâ with âall gains in productivityâ going âto the capitalists and their hired managersâ and so the real wage for non-supervisory workers âhas been falling since 1973.â (105) In short, the âmanagerial class has been making out like banditsâ with the amount of âsurplus value being appropriated ... getting larger.â (104) Interesting, and rightly, Pack links the declining/stagnating wages of workers with longer hours and more family members working and notes this implies we are on the âbackward bending part of their labour supply function.â (109) He also notes how the elite has used the wealth flooding upwards to promote âpro-capitalist cultural hegemony and movementsâ including âresearch centresâ and âpartisan news media and commentators.â (106)
Pack also discusses where Galbraithâs vision went wrong, based in part on Galbraithâs own reflections on his ideas. Thus Galbraith âunderestimated the intensity of the class struggle and the power of the capitalists, the formal owners of the means of productionâ (i.e., the rentier class), that the US was not âa closed economic systemâ (105) and that he had âoveremphasised the competence and ability of the technostructure.â (107) Ultimately, he underestimated how willing the capitalist class would be to let enlightened liberal intellectuals get into office in order to do the right thing.
Yet insofar as he described and understood reality, Galbraith is useful to radicals today â and it was this feature of his work which ensured his hatred by the right along with his use of his wit to critique their self-serving positions â it is fair to say that his work can only **contribute** to our understanding of capitalism, an understanding which must have its foundations in revolutionary thinkers (in all senses of the word). As Pack notes, âGalbraith was not a radicalâ but his and the radicalâs âview of the state of the world may not be that far apart.â (108) Suffice to say, compared it his great rival of his lifetime, Milton Friedman, Galbraith was a far better economist who based his ideas on reality, not the myths of neo-classical economics. Sadly, as Galbraith was on the side of the many (even if somewhat paternalistically) and did not enrich and empower the few as Friedman did, it was his rival who got the so-called Nobel Prize in economics (only a few years before applying his ideas refuted them!). History, though, will judge them more accurately than their obituaries in the mainstream economics press did!
This chapter is followed by one presenting a feminist-Marxist critique of âthe academic field of industrial relationsâ by Richard McIntyre and Michael Hillard. This is extremely Marxist, so much so in fact that it seems to equate class analysis with Marx (116) and links âinequality of bargaining power, management authoritarianism, and workersâ economic insecurityâ solely to **Capital** in spite of Proudhon raising these 27 years previously. (117) While bemoaning the academics for ignoring Marx, they are keen to present long-standing anarchist positions as innovations from Marxism! Thus they present an expanded definition of the working class as âeveryone subordinated to capitalâ and so âthere is no longer a special significance to the industrial working classâ (124) that Bakunin would have agreed with. Similarly, they note that primitive accumulation was âtreated by Marx mostly as an historical phenomenonâ but is âin fact a key site of conflict in the contemporary worldâ (124) so repeating Kropotkinâs critique of 1912:
âWhat, then, is the use of talking, with Marx, about the âprimitive accumulationâ â as if this⊠were a thing of the past?⊠nowhere has the system of ânon-intervention of the Stateâ ever existed⊠The State has **always** interfered in the economic life in favour of the capitalist exploiter⊠**And it could not be otherwise.** To do so was one of the functions â the chief mission â of the State.â
But, then, they proclaim that Rosa Luxemburg âwas perhaps the first and most important radical to understand and advocate for community-based militancy, one that included women and eschewed centralismâ! (130) That this ignoring, say, the community organising by Spanish anarchists from the 1860s onwards (see, for example, Temma Kaplanâs **Anarchists of Andalusia 1868â1903**) and the likes of Louise Michel, Lucy Parsons and Emma Goldman should go without saying. As for centralism, perhaps this **may** be true within the Marxist wing of socialism but libertarian socialists had been opposing it since the 1840s. Surely they are aware of the likes of Proudhon, Bakunin and Kropotkin?
So there is nothing wrong as such with much of what they argue, it just seems incredulous that they think this is something new and that we should be grateful for the Marxist tradition for it!
In Chapter 8 John Marangos discusses âLabor during transitionâ in the ex-Stalinist countries from an Institutionalist economics perspective. This is a useful summary of the terrible impact of the implementation of neo-classical economic dogma after the fall of the Warsaw Pact. As he suggests, the âcultural and institutional conditions of existence were ignored accounts for the disastrous resultsâ (143) while âreal wages declined, working conditions deteriorated, and unemployment and poverty was instituted as a permanent feature of the labour market.â (155) Moreover, the state acted to âcurtail the development of embryonic labour unionsâ and âto institutionalise managementâs powerâ (153) This is unsurprising given that it was class war that was being waged during this time, although perhaps it is just the academic tone of this chapter which gives the impression its author is surprised by it!
Marangos is right to mention Karl Polanyi and his argument that there is nothing ânaturalâ about free-market capitalism, that the state acts to create âfictitious commodityâ like labour and land in the initial rise of capitalism and that it was the state which did so in the ex-Stalinist regimes as well. As such, his chapter is a useful introduction to the power of Institutionalist economic analysis. However, there are aspects of his account which are debatable, not least the assertion that these regimes moved âto capitalism.â (143) It would be more accurate to state they were going from state-capitalism to market-capitalism. He also makes the inaccurate assertion that â[u]nder Stalinism trades unions were totally controlled by the party and their character changed so that they could function as an element of the state.â (153) In fact, this had happened under Lenin and Trotsky (with the latter keen to militarise labour and abolish **all** union independence rather than most of it as Lenin did). Finally, those class warriors Bakunin, Kropotkin and Goldman would have been surprised to read about âclass, consciousness, and conflict as articulated by Karl Marx and his followers.â (145)
Marangos stresses the âimportance of culture, history, working rules, conflict, power, inequality, and governmentâ (144) to economic theory. That mainstream economic ideology ignores all this (and, moreover, was designed to exclude it) shows the importance of Institutionalism and other forms of heterodox economics.
The last two chapters are more practically focused. Chapter 9 is a discussion of offshoring and outsourcing production in low-income countries and its impact on labour. This, of course, is extremely relevant to a union with global aspirations like the IWW but to ponder whether this is a ânewâ era of capitalism seems misplaced, given that Bakunin was arguing for global unionism in the First International back in the 1860s. Unfortunately, its conclusions are reformist. The final chapter is an analysis of a real struggle, namely the bank workersâ union movement in Brazil between 1994 and 2004. Suffice to say, more articles like this would be helpful for workers to learn from the struggles of others and it is a fitting end for a book inspired by the IWW.
So, a mixed bag. Some articles are excellent and will be read by activists and academics with great interest and benefit (Bekken on Kropotkin and Aspromourgos on Saffra spring to mind) while others are useful introductions for further reading/research (Thompson on Senex and Pack on Galbraith). Some would definitely benefit from a reading of libertarian theory â suffice to say, why squeeze in Marxism when anarchism has been addressing the issue for some time? The essays, though, are about relevant subjects for the IWW in its second century and do their inspiration justice.
<strong>Radical Economics and Labor: Essays inspired by the IWW Centennial</strong>
Edited by Frederic S. Lee and Jon Bekken
Routledge Advances in Heterodox Economics
Routledge
New York
2009