đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș document âș jeff-ferrell-anarchy-against-the-discipline captured on 2023-07-10 at 17:39:58. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2023-03-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchy Against the Discipline Date: 1995 Source: Retrieved on December 21, 2019 from [[https://web.archive.org/web/20191221003320/https://www.albany.edu/scj/jcjpc/vol3is4/anarchy.html][web.archive.org]] Notes: Published in <em>Journal of Criminal Justice and Popular Culture</em>, 3(4) (1995) 86â91. Authors: Jeff Ferrell Topics: Book review, Criminology, Discipline Published: 2021-05-12 11:08:36Z
<strong>Author: DiCristina, B.
<br>
Title: **Method in criminology: A philosophical primer**.
<br>
Publisher: New York: Harrow and Heston.
<br>
Year: 1995</strong>
<em>Method in Criminology: A Philosophical Primer</em> is a deceptively innocuous title for a wonderfully outrageous enterprise: a thoroughgoing epistemic attack which Bruce DiCristina launches on both the day-to-day operations of criminology and the philosophical foundations on which these operations rest. In this brief but engaging book, DiCristina carefully and ruthlessly (Marx, 1972) dismantles the basic assumptions which undergird scientific criminology. In so doing, he exposes not only their internal illogic, but their external utility for the bureaucratic control of both crime and criminology, and for the structural maintenance of inequitable social relations. In place of the dangerous fraud which is scientific criminology, then, DiCristina proposes an anarchic criminology â a criminology which embraces alternative methods and epistemologies, encourages imaginative solutions to social and criminal problems, and in the process continually undermines encrusted hierarchies of certainty, truth, and power.
DiCristina begins his decomposition of contemporary criminology by posing a seemingly safe, simple question: âShould any research method be granted a privileged status in criminology?â (p. vii). DiCristinaâs pursuit of this question, though, quickly becomes the thread which, once pulled, unravels the entire enterprise of contemporary scientific criminology. The unravelling begins with a deconstruction of causality and causal certainty as the goals of criminology. Pitting the radical uncertainty of David Hume against the proto-scientific methods of John Stuart Mill, DiCristina demonstrates that causal assertions are in fact âlittle more than constructs of the imaginationâ (p. 15), with no firm footing in external validation.
Having demonstrated the futility of causal analysis for criminology, DiCristina generously offers those who would pursue a scientific criminology a variety of less stringent options â probability, prediction, falsification â and then proceeds to undermine these possibilities as well. Drawing heavily on Feyerabendâs (1975) brilliant attack on science and scientific method, and on philosophers of science like Kuhn (1970), Lakatos (1968), and Rorty (1989), DiCristina dismisses probability and prediction due to their reliance on wholly unreliable methods of induction and inductive reasoning. He likewise exposes the falsity of a falsification method which fails to understand that theories and the facts by which they are allegedly falsified in reality interpenetrate and intermingle. Finally, he considers the least stringent of options â that certain methods are, if not scientifically sound, at least the most plausible means for pursuing criminological goals. Again, though, he finds that fundamental epistemic uncertainty destroys any hierarchy of plausibility.
Significantly, DiCristina demonstrates that this consideration of criminologyâs underlying principles constitutes much more than an exercise in abstract philosophy. First, he shows that mainstream criminology is carefully guarded by various gatekeepers of scientific authority and methodological purity: journal and book editors and reviewers, curriculum designers, granting agencies, and others. In demanding that criminological work meet the standards of science, and excluding that work which does not, these authorities shape the discipline around narrow (and, as DiCristina argues, unfounded) definitions of scholarship (see Vaughn, Sjoberg and Reynolds, 1993; Feagin, Orum and Sjoberg, 1991; Williams, 1984). Beyond this, the framing of criminology as objective science contributes to the functional rationality of the modern criminal justice system, and is in turn âespecially conducive to the maintenance of inequitable distributions of powerâ (p. 67). As DiCristina persuasively argues, the authority of allegedly objective knowledge, the sheen of scientific method and quantification, both construct new realms of legal domination and social control, and at the same time distance those in control from responsibility for their actions.
Against a criminology which is both unjustifiably narrow in its scope and overtly harmful in its consequences DiCristina, therefore, suggests an anarchic criminology characterized by openness, creativity, and inclusion (see Pepinsky, 1978; Tifft, 1979; Tifft and Sullivan, 1980; Ferrell, 1993; Ferrell, 1994). In place of the stale straightjacket of (pseudo)scientific criminology, anarchic criminology promotes the widest possible range of theories and methods, values marginal and even âunreasonableâ knowledge, and revitalizes the âcriminological imaginationâ (Williams, 1984). In place of the false objectivity of contemporary criminology, anarchic criminology employs a sort of âreflexive hermeneuticsâ (p. 80 â 84) which encourages both interpretive knowledge and critical awareness. In place of a criminology which is all too useful for inequitable social and legal control, anarchic criminology takes shape in humble conversation with those outside the domains of criminology and criminal justice.
This notion of an open, anarchic criminology sheds light on a variety of ongoing discussions within and beyond contemporary criminology. To begin with, it provides a useful framework for making sense of the various alternative criminologies which have emerged in recent years. The Russian anarchist Michael Bakuninâs infamous injunction â that âthe passion for destruction is a creative passion, tooâ (1974: 58) â here reflects the notion that the destruction of paradigmatic hegemony in criminology in fact opens up intellectual space for the creation of various alternative criminologies. If the deconstruction of theoretical certainty and methodological privilege by DiCristina and those who have gone before him has created a sort of negative space, an epistemic void, it is a void that has been quickly filled by a healthy tangle of fresh perspectives. In this sense, the plethora of criminologies which have blossomed in recent times â peacemaking, newsmaking, feminist, narrative, cultural, anarchist â constitutes perhaps a crisis of criminological certainty, but more so a measure of disciplinary life.
In unmasking the myth of an objectively scientific criminology â in realizing that we are only discarding something we never had â we are also pushed to reconceptualize research methods and methods of knowing. The âreflexive hermeneuticâ which DiCristina proposes incorporates âboth interactive analyses and historical-contextual analysesâ (p. 81), and demands a certain degree of consensual agreement between researcher and subjects; that is, it âtakes subjectivity seriouslyâ (p. 83). For criminological researchers, this implies experiential closeness in place of pseudo-scientific distance, and epistemic humility in place of intellectual arrogance. In other words, it demands, as a requisite feature of understanding and analysis, a sort of âcriminological verstehenâ (Hamm and Ferrell, 1994; Ferrell and Sanders, 1995) between criminological researchers and their subjects of study. And thus it is, within this model, that criminological ethnographers, anarchic criminologists, and others may know infinitely more about their subjects of study than do survey researchers or statisticians, and at the same time claim to know infinitely less.
Finally, anarchic criminology as sketched by DiCristina and others clearly informs, and is informed by, those orientations grouped under headings like âpostmodernismâ and âcultural studies.â DiCristina notes that âperhaps the most refreshing anarchic developments in criminology will be sifted from the work of postmodern criminologistsâ (p. 98), and indeed anarchic and postmodern criminologies have much in common. The epistemic assault on various forms of legal and intellectual authority; the decentering of both centralized power and the certainty which accompanies it; the rejection of metanarratives which position themselves as true and universal accounts of social or criminal life â these are the projects of postmodern and anarchic criminologies alike. And as these projects open up the constricted intellectual space of scientific criminology, they at the same time lead criminology into new domains of research and analysis. DiCristina in this sense argues that âcriminological inquiry is more than a question of logic. Questions of aesthetics and morality are just as importantâ (p. xi). Like others (see Ferrell and Sanders, 1995), he thus recognizes the importance of aesthetic and stylistic processes in constituting both criminology and criminal action, and attempts to reclaim this âcultural trashâ from the dustbin of scientific, rationalist criminology.
DiCristina might have productively explored many of these issues more fully; though he notes postmodern and aesthetic issues in the context of anarchic criminology, for example, he all but fails to follow his own lead. He might also have more thoroughly rooted his anarchic criminology not only in prior anarchist work within criminology, but in the long history of anarchist thought. Though brevity may be the soul of wit, a hundred page book might well be expanded to include more thorough exploration, and a few more pages. In addition, the book, though simply and understandably written, would have benefited in places from a good round of editing. Utilizing conventional language in new or intentionally inappropriate ways certainly carries anarchic potential; simply writing âand so forthâ or âetc.â into sentences seems more sloppy than seditious. These, though, are minor criticisms of an exciting and courageous contribution to criminological thinking. **Method in Criminology** transcends its own limitations in inventing a far- reaching critique of contemporary criminology, and imagining a humane and flexible alternative to it.
And in this spirit of anarchist imagination, I offer a closing note as to means and ends, process and product. Dicristina concludes that, given anarchic criminologyâs promotion of âfreedom of thought and creativityâ (p. 102), an anarchic criminology benefits criminology as a whole, despite the fact that it may never be fully accomplished. I would agree, but go a step further to argue that anarchic criminology is beneficial precisely **because** it can never be fully realized. By its own logic, anarchic criminology serves best, it seems, as an unfinished and uncertain project, an emerging sensibility floating around and âagainst criminologyâ (Cohen, 1988), a critique which folds back on itself so as to undermine not only mainstream criminological rigidity but its own encrustation as well. And in this sense, we arrive at an anarchic criminology only as we continue to stumble toward it.
Jeff Ferrell
<br>
Department of Criminal Justice
<br>
Northern Arizona University
<br>
<strong>References</strong>
<biblio>
Cohen, S. (1988). **Against criminology**. New Brunswick: Transaction.
Feagin, J. R., Orum, A.M., & Sjoberg, G. (Eds.). (1991). **A case for the case study**. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Ferrell, J. (1993). **Crimes of style: Urban graffiti and the politics of criminality**. New York: Garland.
Ferrell, J. (1994). Confronting the agenda of authority: Critical criminology, anarchism, and urban graffiti. In G. Barak (Ed.), **Varieties of criminology** (pp.161â178). Westport, CT: Praeger.
Ferrell, J., & Sanders, C. R. (Eds.). (1995). **Cultural criminology**. Boston: Northeastern University Press.
Feyerabend, P. (1975). **Against method**. London: Verso.
Hamm, M. S., & Ferrell, J. (1994). Rap, cops, and crime: Clarifying the âCop Killerâ controversy. **ACJS Today**, **13**, 1, 3, 29.
Kuhn, T. (1970). **The structure of scientific revolutions** (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lakatos, I. (1968). Criticism and the methodology of scientific research programmes. **Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society**, **69**, 149â186.
Lehning, A. (Ed.). (1974). **Michael Bakunin: Selected writings**. New York: Grove Press.
Marx, K. (1972). For a ruthless criticism of everything existing. In R. Tucker (Ed.), **The Marx- Engels Reader**, (pp.7â10). New York: Norton.
Pepinsky, H. E. (1978). Communist anarchism as an alternative to the rule of criminal law. **Contemporary Crises**, **2**, 315â327.
Rorty, R. (1989). **Contingency, irony, and solidarity**. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tifft, L. (1979). The coming redefinition of crime: An anarchist perspective. **Social Problems**, **26**, 392â402.
Tifft, L., & Sullivan, D. (1980). **The struggle to be human: Crime, criminology, and anarchism**. Orkney, U.K.: Cienfuegos Press.
Vaughn, T. R., Sjoberg, G., & Reynolds, L. T. (Eds.). (1993). **A critique of contemporary American sociology**. Dix Hill, NY: General Hall.
Williams, F. P. (1984). The demise of the criminological imagination: A critique of recent criminology. **Justice Quarterly**, **1**, 91â106.
</biblio>