đŸ Archived View for beyondneolithic.life âș articles âș smolin_interview.gmi captured on 2023-04-26 at 13:13:21. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ïž Previous capture (2021-11-30)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Ethan Siegel
bigthink.com
At a fundamental level, we often assume that there are two ways of describing nature that each work well in their own regime, but that donât seem to play well together. On the one hand, we know that the matter and energy that makes up the Universe, from stars to atoms to neutrinos to photons, all require a quantum description in order to extract their properties and behavior. The Standard Model, the pinnacle of quantum physics, works perfectly well to describe every interaction weâve ever measured in the Universe.
On the other hand, we also have General Relativity: our theory of gravity. However, this is fundamentally a classical theory, where the presence of matter and energy curves the fabric of space, and that curved space in turn tells matter and energy how to move through it. Although each one works quite well over its own range of validity, there are plenty of questions that require a thorough knowledge of both, together to answer. Due not only to their fundamental differences but their fundamental incompatibilities, many questions that we can imagine are currently beyond our ability to answer.
That doesnât necessarily imply that anything is broken with physics, but it certainly seems to indicate that our current understanding of matters is, at the very least, incomplete. In an attempt to uncover just what it is that we know, what we donât, and what the path forward might look like, I sat down in an interview with physicist Lee Smolin, whoâll be appearing at the HowTheLightGetsIn festival in London this September 18 and 19. Lee is a pioneer in the field of quantum gravity and someone whose latest book, Einsteinâs Unfinished Revolution, details the search for what lies beyond whatâs presently known about the quantum Universe.
Ethan Siegel: What are the motivations behind why you would say quantum field theory and the Standard Model, and General Relativity for gravity, why can that not describe the Universe at a fundamental level?
Lee Smolin: Well it just canât. Itâs easy to think of experiments that that collection of ideas doesnât give consistent predictions for. More than that, there are reasons, in principle, why the principles that quantum physics is based on contradict the principles that General Relativity is based on, and we need to make these things fit together on a level of principle, because itâs supposed to be a fundamental theory of nature.
There are both experimental reasons and reasons of principle â and between them there are also lots of technical problems that we see when we get to know them â are a consequence of these conceptual clashes: clashes of principle.
ES: Can you give one example?
LS: Sure, what does âcollapse of the wavefunction,â which is a part of quantum mechanics, look like in a spacetime which is dynamical, and which evolves according to some equations of motion in General Relativity?
ES: Einsteinâs original idea of unification was originally to geometrically add in classical electromagnetism to General Relativity, and we know that canât be right because we know the Universe is quantum mechanical in nature. You write about what you call âEinsteinâs unfinished dream.â Why is this dream important, even if Einsteinâs original ideas about it are no longer relevant?
LS: Well, I disagree with you about how relevant Einsteinâs original ideas were, for better or for worse. There are, in the history of science revolutions, where our understanding of nature changes profoundly and on every possible scale. When you go from being an Aristotelian scientist to a Newtonian scientist, your picture of the world changed drastically, on all scales, and there are many applications of that.
Hereâs what at stake. Einstein started two revolutions at the start of the 20th century: general relativity and quantum mechanics. He understood that they did not give a consistent picture put together. And in fact, he believed, and I agree with him, that quantum mechanics all by itself doesnât give a consistent picture. To put it directly, it just doesnât make sense: the quantum mechanics as it was formulated in the 1920s, by his friends and colleagues.
LS: So we have two tasks on the agenda. One is to make sense of quantum mechanics. And two is to fix that theory which is better than quantum mechanics, and to make that theory thatâs better than quantum mechanics also complete General Relativity. So I see it as a question of completion.
General Relativity covers very well, to a certain degree of approximation, certain phenomena. Quantum mechanics covers very well, to a certain degree of approximation, certain phenomena. Theyâre both incomplete. Highly incomplete. At the level of experiments, you have to use some imagination, but itâs not all down at the Planck scale. There are experiments which involve timescales of minutes or seconds where we have no clear prediction. But this double revolution needs to be completed on both sides, and thatâs whatâs at stake: itâs to complete the revolution, because weâre living in a conceptual situation much analogous to that faced by Kepler and Galileo, who were contemporaries, they were each halfway between Aristotelian and Newtonian physics. They understood certain things very well, but they were deeply confused about other things. And thatâs our situation now.
ES: From the quantum side, Iâve heard many people argue, counter to what youâre arguing, that quantum physics works exactly fine for describing every quantum phenomenon in the Universe, so long as you donât also fold in quantum gravitational effects. If I can treat spacetime as being a classical or semi-classical background, then I can do everything that my quantum field theory predicts I should do without any errors or uncertainties. Do you disagree with that?
LS: Am I supposed to be impressed by that?
Aristotle worked with orbits and the positions of the planets that were accurate to a part in a thousand over a millennium. That was impressive, but it was bloody wrong. That simple-minded theory that youâre describing⊠why would somebody take such a little, little, low-ambitious thing? Of course you can make it work if you put in enough caveats and enough approximations, thatâs what weâre trained to do.
And there are some beautiful things that come out of it, like Steve Hawkingâs prediction of black hole radiation. So thatâs fine, but man, thatâs 1970s physics; do we want to do 1970s physics forever? Iâm being deliberately a bit provocative, but, you know, weâve got to wake these people up!
ES: So I read, back in 2003, you co-wrote a paper [with Fotini Markopoulou] that showed what Iâll say is an intriguing link between general ideas in quantum gravity and the fundamental non-locality of quantum physics. Now, maybe I should even ask you a setup question for this: we often state that quantum physics is fundamentally a non-local theory. And when we talk about quantum entanglement, we use that as sort of an illustration of that. But critics of that will say that no information ever travels faster than light from one quantum to another. Does this create any conflict in your mind? Would you say that quantum mechanics is fundamentally non-local?
LS: That quantum mechanics is fundamentally non-local, and therefore, making sense of quantum mechanics requires a strong modification in our understanding of what space is. And that General Relativity requires a strong modification in our ideas of what space is. And therefore, the things should go together. We shouldnât try to ignore that and do this and then ignore this and do that, we should fix them together, in one move. And thatâs what Iâve been trying to do since 19⊠since I was in college.
That [paper], that was mostly [Markopoulouâs] idea, and that was a very clever demonstration of the principle that space could be is be emergent, so that time could be fundamental. And thatâs what she believed and she convinced me, and thatâs what Iâve been working on, really, the last 20 years. Is the idea that time and causation are at the bottom, and are fundamental, and that space is a secondary, emergent quantity, like pressure of the air or temperature of the Earth. And so thatâs what weâve been trying to do, and weâve been having some moderate success along the road.
So that what we experience of the world, evolving in time event-by-event, event-by-event, is real, thatâs how the world really is. And out of that fundamental, active notion of time and causation, we make space as a derivative concept, the same way that out of the motion of atoms, you make a gas.
ES: Interesting. So you are very strongly an advocate that this classical notion of cause-and-effect, persists all the way down to the quantum level. I would assume that this means you are not a fan of quantum mechanics interpretations that do not maintain cause-and-effect as a fundamental tenet of all interactions?
LS: Mmm-hmmm, yes.
ES: I know that you have stated, and I donât know if itâs for ideological or physical reasons, that reality ought to be independent of us, the observer.
LS: Yes, of course.
ES: You say, âyes, of course.â And many people throughout the history of quantum mechanics have not thought, âyes, of course.â Can you explain why reality should be independent of the observer?
LS: Because Iâm a realist, and for me the goal of science is precisely the description of nature as it would be in our absence. Now, that doesnât mean that there isnât a role for the observer. For example, in the theories Iâve been developing for the last five years â itâs called the theory of views â what is real in that Universe is a view of that Universe, looking back, causally, into the past. And thatâs exactly whatâs real. John Bell, who was very much a realist, used to say, âwe have to say not what the observables are, but what the viewables are.â So Iâve been developing this theory where we have events, and then have information or news that comes to them from the past, and thatâs whatâs real: those views. And the dynamics of the world doesnât depend on differential equations in space, or fields, it depends on the views, and the differences between those views. And the basic dynamical principle of the theory is that the Universe evolves to make the views as varied and as different from each other as possible.
ES: So you have a principle, then, of something thatâs either maximized or minimized.
LS: Of course.
ES: Is that something you could describe for us?
LS: Sure. Itâs called, âthe variety.â It can be applied to many different kinds of systems, so letâs take cities. Consider an old city: the center of Rome, which was preserved. Think of calling a friend and saying, âIâm lost, Iâm at some corner and hereâs what I see around me.â Now, Rome is a city with a lot of variety, so your friend is gonna be able to say, âOh, youâre there, near the [whatever] because every corner looks different.â Rome is a city with high variety. On the other hand, there are some very suburban-dominated cities, in which you wouldnât know very much about where you are just from what you see when you look around, because many of the corners are similar to each other. So that can give you an example of what we mean when we say, âwe want to increase the variety.â
ES: So when you say, âwe want to increase the variety,â do you think that nature extremizes variety?
LS: Yes, and I can write that down as an equation within the framework I discussed, where there are these causal relations, and thereâs energy and momentum, but thereâs no space. We can construct a dynamical theory that extremizes, over time, the variety of the system. And we derive from that, quantum mechanics, and as a limit of that, classical mechanics.
Why do we get quantum mechanics out? Roughly speaking, there was an original realist interpretation of quantum mechanics called pilot wave theory, that Louis de Broglie invented in 1927, and it was reinvented by David Bohm in about 1952. And in that theory, thereâs potential energy and thereâs another new function of the wavefunction, and it sits where the potential energy usually sits. And they derive the Schrodinger equation from maximizing the influence of this function. Well, it turns out that this function that David Bohm invented is a certain limit of the quantity we call the variety, by the way with Julian Barbour, back in the â80s. And this was one of the great surprises of my working life.
ES: When you take this limit of the quantity you call the variety, and youâre saying, âweâre extremizing over that,â this sounds to me like something that would be pretty analogous to some type of entropy, some type of thermodynamic quantity. So far, everyone I know whoâs tried to come up with a concept of âgravity is emergentâ or âspace is emergentâ or some other quantity that we normally look at as fundamental is in fact emergent, takes something that in typical physics thought we view as emergent and makes that fundamental. I would say the typical view of physics is that entropy is an emergent property that you can calculate based on, say, the microscopic quantum state of all the particles aggregated together. Are you basically doing something similar to that, except with this thing you define as âvarietyâ instead of entropy?
LS: Roughly speaking yes, but thatâs a long discussion. Because the role of entropy in cosmological theory is something we have to get our heads straight about. Thereâs a series of three very beautiful papers that Marina CortĂȘs, Andrew Liddle and Stu Kauffman have that weâve been working on for a few years, and they contain some important new insights about very far-from-equilibrium systems and their relation to cosmology.
ES: Iâd like to ask about this idea that Heisenberg and a lot of other people had, which is that unless you have what we call an interaction in some sense â one quantum interacting with another quantum â thatâs the only thing that provides meaningful information about the Universe. If you donât make a measurement, then you donât have a quantifiable property of the Universe. So all of the information that we have has to come out of that act, which I look at, maybe naively, as fundamentally antagonistic to this idea of an objective reality. The fact that we canât make any measurements that discern between this Heisenberg-esque picture of reality and a âobjective reality existsâ picture of reality⊠you have a certainty about your perspective that I donât share and that many physicists donât share. How do you make sense of this if you canât tell experimentally between these different interpretations?
LS: No, thatâs a fake. I donât know that, but itâs a good working fake. Let me tell you about how I look at quantum mechanics these days, because itâs new and itâs been very exciting to me. Our realization, actually following down some quotes of Heisenberg which were very mysterious at first, you know that Heisenberg said that the wavefunction description does not apply to the past. Somehow, the wavefunction was about the future, and the classical description is about the past. And a few people said this. Freeman Dyson said this at length; Schrodinger said something like that, and even deeper and more mysterious.
Recently Iâve been working on these questions with Clelia Verde, and we realized they were trying to say is that in the Copenhagen version of quantum mechanics, there is a quantum world and there is a classical world, and a boundary between them: when things become definite. When things that are indefinite in the quantum world become definite. And what theyâre trying to say is that is the fundamental thing that happens in nature, when things that are indefinite become definite. And thatâs what ânowâ is. The moment now, the present moment, that all these people say is missing from science and missing from physics, that is the transition from indefinite to definite. And quantum mechanics, the wavefunction, is a description of the future which is indefinite and incomplete. And classical physics is how we describe the past.
Why? Because the past happened, what happened was definite, and it doesnât change, because itâs the past. So we have this different way of thinking about quantum mechanics, and it seems to be helpful, weâre having a good time.
ES: Itâs very hard to disagree with that. So when you look at, letâs say, Wheelerâs delayed choice experiment. And Iâm thinking in particular of one where you send in a photon and you have a beam splitter, and the photon can take two paths around mirrors, and theyâll meet up on the other side. And either youâll have another beam splitter that will combine them and youâll get your detector that will see an interference pattern of the recombined photons, or you wonât put the splitter in there, and youâll just get one of the photons that comes into your detector.
So, you can do this, and Wheelerâs idea is that you can send the photon through that first splitter, to have it go those two different ways. And then you can either put the second splitter there or not. And at the last second, you can either remove the splitter that was there (or not) or you can insert the splitter that wasnât there to try and, he called it, âcatch the photon deciding on what it was going to do before you made that measurement.â
In hindsight, to no oneâs surprise, what did you measure at the detector? Well, if the splitter was there, you get the interference pattern back. And if the splitter wasnât there, youâd just get the one photon back. Basically, nature doesnât know in advance what youâre going to do. But once you do it, itâs like it knew all along what you were going to do. That, to me, and youâre going to tell me thatâs not the only interpretation, has always meant the act of interacting, itself, is what gives you that meaningful information. If you didnât have any interactions taking place, you have not determined your reality yet. Your reality remains indeterminate until you make a measurement that would discern between the different possibilities.
LS: Yeah, but you see, I agree with that. Only, our line is ânow,â is the boundary between the future and the past.
ES: Are you saying that right now, the âin progressâ things, that have not yet been decided, that will be decided with an interaction at some point in the future, are you saying that everything in the past has already been determined, even those things where that measurement that will draw that line has not yet occurred?
LS: So that event has not yet occurred, so thatâs rather compatible. The notion of the ânowâ that gives rise to is not a thin instant, where it has to happen here; itâs what the philosophers call a thick now. So there can be events that turn something definite, that are late, or that are early, so our ânowâ can zigzag quite a bit. At least, thatâs the way we try to understand those cases. Theyâre not in the original papers with Verde, but weâre going through all these thought experiments in detail and show how to think about whatâs going on.
ES: This is stuff thatâs right on the cutting edge of trying to understand what the fundamental nature of reality is. Youâve written very much, Iâd say, non-positively about many of the ideas in string theory, and how theyâve become this dominant theoretical paradigm. One of the things Iâve noticed about your work is that it seems to be relatively agnostic about other extensions to what might be out there: string theory, supersymmetry, grand unification, etc., you seem pretty agnostic about this all, which is maybe in contrast to what peopleâs public perception of you is.
LS: If people want to express an opinion about [my 2006 book, The Trouble With Physics], I would ask them the favor that they should read it. There was a lot of angst and conflict in that period, and I think people would be surprised here, but let me just tell you what I think. What I believe is that there are a number of interesting different approaches to quantum gravity, which so far are all incomplete. They all manage to explain something to us about what a quantum description of spacetime may be, but each of them also get stuck somewhere on some characteristic.
String theory is a beautiful set of ideas, which in my view has gotten stuck. And loop quantum gravity, which Iâm fortunate enough to have had the experience of working on while it was being invented, but itâs also clearly gotten stuck. Both of them express the same idea: that thereâs a duality between fields carrying forces, like the electromagnetic field, and quantum excitations of those fields can look like extended objects, like strings or loops, propagating. Both loop quantum gravity and string theory express in different contexts that fundamental conjecture.
What I tried to express in that book, and itâs always the authorâs fault when youâre misunderstood, that book started as a case study of the role of conflict in science. Being a student of Paul Feyerabend, I think that conflict and disagreement are vital to the progress of science. And that book was meant to be an argument for that, using the case study that I knew best. As the book got shaped by me and by the editors, we flipped the book so that the case study came first and the analysis in terms of how the conflict plays a driving role in science came second, and most people only read the first half.
What I was against, and what I am against wherever I see it, is premature dogmatism: premature believing in something more than what the evidence supports. And this, unfortunately, is very common in science, because we all want to believe that weâve done something good and discovered something. There was an atmosphere at the time, which I think is very dissipated now, of over-optimism in my view. I try to give a balanced view of what the strengths of string theory were and what the weaknesses were, and unfortunately some people reacted to that. But that was a long time ago.
ES: Can I ask you what you think of certain effective approaches to quantum gravity? Like asymptotically safe gravity, do you think that offers any promise? Iâve always had an appreciation for that one because it seems to allow for predictions to be made in an otherwise inaccessible regime.
LS: Asymptotic safety has some very attractive points. Itâs basically an application by Steve Weinberg about some ideas about perturbatively non-renormalizable theories that Ken Wilson had, and he applied their ideas to gravity. Itâs a very attractive story, but thereâs a problem; as I said thereâs always a problem. The problem in asymptotic safety is unitarity. We know of an asymptotically safe theory which is present even in perturbation theory. Can we speak a little math here?
ES: Go ahead, Iâll translate.
LS: The action principle to the theory is the Einstein action principle, plus the cosmological constant term, plus a term in the Ricci scalar squared plus a term in the Ricci tensor squared. And this last one invariably introduces instabilities and an impossibility to satisfy the principle of unitarity, which among other things means you canât guarantee that the probabilities for all the things that will happen will add up to one. And this has been a known problem since 1978 or 1982 or something, and I wrote the third paper in response to Steveâs paper that showed the violation of unitarity. So thatâs where it stands in my mind, but itâs always good to follow the kids, and thereâs a bunch of smart, young people working on this. Itâs not my bet, but itâs their bet, and theyâre really good.
We donât have any senior faculty working on asymptotic safety at Perimeter, but we were so impressed by some of the young people who applied to us that, despite our own misgivings, we hired them for a few years. Because itâs interesting and exciting to have them around, and if you want your field to prosper, youâve got to be able to listen to and promote young people who disagree with you, otherwise itâs not science.
ES: When Iâve felt optimistic about it, Iâve looked towards asymptotically safe gravity in the same way I now look back at the time-dependent Schrodinger equation. I say, âokay, look, this has cases where it doesnât apply, and cases where it breaks down,â because itâs not a relativistically invariant theory. But if you can find a formulation of it, like the Dirac equation, that is relativistically invariant, or if you could find a more general formulation, like quantum field theory that eliminates the need for that sort of thing. Maybe this idea can be salvaged, despite the fact that the way itâs formulated now, it doesnât guarantee unitarity.
LS: But if you turn it up so that it is giving you unitary answers to second or third order in perturbation theory, then the condition that there should be a non-trivial fixed point constrains the top quark mass by a measurable amount. They actually get a prediction that if this all works out, then hereâs the top quark mass.
ES: I remember reading a paper by Wetterich and Shaposhnikov years before they had measured the mass of the Higgs boson where they used the mass of all the particles except the Higgs to say, well, instead of getting the mass of the top weâre going to get the mass of the Higgs, and the value they got was ~126 ± 1. But if I remember right, since then, the mass of the top has changed a little bit, and now if you put that same math back in, youâd get something like 129 or 130, which doesnât agree with what theyâve seen at the LHC.
LS: I didnât know that; thatâs interesting. Thatâs great. What else excites you?
ES: One thing Iâd like to press you on a little bit is this: if you have a dynamical spacetime, versus a static spacetime, how can you describe wavefunction collapse in a changing spacetime? If you have a wavefunction in a changing spacetime, what does wavefunction collapse look like, if your spacetime isnât static?
LS: Roger Penroseâs view of that is that the collapse of the wavefunction is a physical thing that happens when a certain measure of energy involved in that possible event is equal to the planck energy per planck time, or something like that. I donât remember the exact way he did it. So then, youâre in a domain where neither the Einstein equation or the Schrodinger equation is quite right.
What Iâm really, really excited about is that there are some experiments under development where they actually test that. Thereâs a whole new generation of tabletop gravity or quantum gravity experiments that different people are working on.
ES: I like the tabletop experiments that are happening. One thing that I definitely wanted to ask you about is, youâve talked, Iâll say derisively about people who treat conclusions as if theyâre foregone conclusions without having evidence to back that up. You want to remain open-minded to anything that may be possible before that critical evidence comes in. Do you worry that taking the stance of saying, âI am a realist when it comes to quantum physicsâ is violating that piece of advice. Do you worry about saying, Iâm a realist and I believe that reality is observer-independent is making that mistake?
LS: <laughs> You know, I donât know whatâs wrong with me, but I love this stuff to death. I am having so much fun and thereâs nothing like it to be able to think about this stuff. Some people have this wire in them that says they have to be right, and I donât have that. I donât know why, maybe itâs a defect? So, sure, if you ask me, yeah, I could be wrong about that. I could be wrong about a lot of things.
Letâs put us 1000 years in the future, weâll all look like fools for having missed the obvious things in neuroscience or planetary science or something that turned out to be important. There was a famous boxer who was asked how he felt about his career, and he said, âyou know, I did the best I could with what I was given.â And Iâm happy with that. I donât gotta be right, but if I didnât follow what I believe in, I wouldnât be as happy a person now.
ES: I want to pull out a Niels Bohr quote and ask you your opinion of this, then. âWhen we measure something, we are forcing an undetermined, undefined world to assume an experimental value. We are not measuring the world; we are creating it.â This strikes me as a statement that I would expect you to fundamentally disagree with, but you might surprise me.
LS: No, it doesnât appeal to me, but wow, Iâm really sorry I never got to meet Bohr. He was an interesting guy; canât we just be on that level? In the end, Bohr was at a very weird place from our point of view in the development of western culture and society. He was influenced by Schopenhauer and people like that, and so he had what we would consider not just a non-realist viewpoint, but a radical non-realist viewpoint, and he did the best he could with that. But I donât believe that, that doesnât keep me up at night, but⊠sure.
ES: Do you have any thoughts youâd like to share that I havenât asked you about that you think are too important to not share?
LS: Open up the scientific community to more people who are highly trained and really good. And maybe Iâm just getting this in because I like these ideas. For me, when people talk about diversity, that means not just women and blacks and aboriginals and who else, those are all very very important, but also very important are people who think differently. Now, to make a success in physics, you canât just be anyone off the streets, itâs like I couldnât compose a piece of music and send it to the New York Philharmonic and have them play it.
Youâve gotta have your tools, youâve got to be practiced, you gotta be good with your tools, youâve gotta make a convincing case for the results that youâve found in your work. Thatâs what a Ph.D. symbolizes. But among the people who are excellent, technically, we want as wide a variety of ideas and viewpoints and types and personalities and gender and race⊠itâs yes yes yes yes. I would hope that the next generation and the second-to-next generation live in a scientific world that is much more fun. Because if everyoneâs like you, itâs not fun.