💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › document › murray-bookchin-remaking-society captured on 2023-03-20 at 22:03:20. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-08-18)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Remaking Society
Subtitle: Pathways to a Green Future
Date: 1990
Source: [[https://libcom.org/library/remaking-society-pathways-green-future][libcom.org]] and [[https://aaaaarg.fail/thing/59cf58159ff37c0dbe0068e6][aaarg]]
Authors: Murray Bookchin
Topics: green anarchism, revolution, history, society, social policy, social ecology, libertarian municipalism, hierarchy, radicalism, Freedom, human ecology, social structure
Published: 2019-07-30 14:25:43Z

Dedication

<center>

**For Art and Libera Bartell,**

**who have fought for freedom all their lives.**

</center>

Acknowledgements

This book could not have been written without the suggestions, encouragement, and assistance of several dear friends. I owe my deepest debts to Dimitri Roussopoulos of Black Rose Books and to Rosella Di Leo and Amadeo Bertolo of Eleutheria Books who literally suggested that it be written and supervised its writing over the past two years. Abiding thanks are also due my dear friend and comrade Karl-Ludwig Schibel for our long and rich intellectual association. Important contributions to this project were also made by Janet Biehl, Beatrice Bookchin, Debby Bookchin, and Joseph Bookchin; by friends in the Burlington Greens who are much too numerous to name; and my colleagues at the Institute for Social Ecology in Plainsfield, Vermont, most particularly Dan Chodorkoff. Finally, I would like to thanks Steve Chase of South End Press for his personal interest and assistance in preparing the U.S. edition of *Remaking Society* for publication.

Why This Book Was Written

I had long thought of writing a compact book that would dearly

summarize my views on “remaking society” from an ecological view”

point. It seemed to me (as it did to many of my friends) that a need

existed to bring the ideas I have developed over several large books

into a work of some two hundred pages; one that would not be too

demanding for intelligent readers who are interested in social ecology.

But what finally made me decide to write this book was a rather

chilling incident. Early in June, 1987, I was privileged to be a feature

speaker in a six-day National Gathering of American Greens in Amherst, Massachusetts. The event received a surprising amount of national press coverage — and rightly so. About two thousand people from at least forty-two states came to Amherst to debate the theoretical and

practical problems of a Green movement in the United States. This was

the biggest gathering of independent American radicals in many years.

Largely anti-capitalist and activist, these Greens were deeply involved

in their neighbourhoods, communities, and workplaces. They reflected

a wide spectrum of radicalism in America — giving expression to its

promise and its problems, its hopes and limitations.

The gathering was marked by over a dozen plenary sessions of five

hundred to a thousand people and by an astonishing number of

workshops on issues as exotic as ecological ethics and as timely as

feminism, racism, imperialism, and economic democracy; indeed, almost every practical social problem that could be of interest to the

rapidly growing Green movement in America. There were heated

disputes over electoral versus non-electoral politics, independent versus coalition politics, revolutionary versus reformist politics, and, in

short, all the debates that have echoed over the years in major radical

gatherings.

But something fairly new surfaced in these debates. A number of

tendencies, indeed, ways of thinking, appeared that may seem uniquely

American, but which I think have already emerged or will emerge in

Green movements, and perhaps radical movements generally, outside

the United States.

I can best describe at least one of these tendencies by giving an

account of the incident that troubled me. It occurred in an after-dinner

small of our meeting place to discuss the events of the day. A young, tall,

rather robust man from California began to talk in a vague way about

the need to “obey” the “laws of nature,” to “humbly subjugate ourselves” (if I recall his words correctly) “to nature’s commands.” Rhetorical

as his words seemed at first utterance, I began to find his increasingly

strident monologue very disturbing.

His use of words like “obey,” “laws of nature,” “subjugate ” and

commands” reminded me of the very same language I have heard from

anti-ecological people who believe that nature must “obey” *our* commands and *its* “laws” must be used to “subjugate” the natural world

itself. Whether I was thinking of the young California Green who was

bombarding me with his seemingly “ecological” verbiage, or of modern

acolytes of the cold deities of science who believe that “man” must

ruthlessly control nature in “his” own interest, it was clear to me that

these two seemingly opposed views had a basic thing in common. They

jointly shared the vocabulary of domination and subjugation. Just as

my California Green believes that human beings should be dominated

by nature, so the acolytes of scientism believe that nature should be

dominated by “man.”

My California Green, in effect, had merely reversed this unsavoury

relationship between human beings and nature by turning people into

objects of domination, just as his scientistic opponents (usually big

industrialists, financiers, and entrepreneurs in our modern corporate

society) turn the world of life, including human beings, into objects of

domination. The fact that humanity, together with nature, were being

locked into a common destiny based on domination by a hierarchical

mentality and society, seemed to elude my California Green with his

simplistic message of “surrendering” to nature and its “laws.”

Already deeply disturbed by the fact that a self-professed Green

could think so much like his ecological opponents, I decided to ask him

a blunt question: “What do you think is the cause of the present

ecological crisis?” His answer was very emphatic: “Human beings! *People* are responsible for the ecological crisis!”

“Do you mean that people such as blacks, women, and the oppressed

are causing ecological imbalances — not corporations, agribusiness,

ruling elites, and the State?” I asked with complete astonishment.

“Yes, people!” he answered even more heatedly. “*Everyone!* They

overpopulate the earth, they pollute the planet, they devour its resources, they are greedy. That’s why corporations exist — to give people the things they want.”

I suspect our discussion would have become explosive if my California Green had not been distracted by a nearby game of volley-ball and leaped up to join it.

I could not forget this conversation. Indeed, it haunts me to the

present day because of the extent, as I have since learned, to which it

reflects the thinking of many environmentalists, some of whom would

militantly call themselves “radicals.”

The most striking feature of such a way of thinking is not only that

it closely parallels the way of thinking that is found in the corporate

world. What is more serious is that it serves to deflect our attention from

the role society plays in producing ecological breakdown. If “people”

as a *species* are responsible for environmental dislocations, these

dislocations cease to be the result of *social* dislocations. A mythic

“Humanity” is created — irrespective of whether we are talking about

oppressed ethnic minorities, women. Third World people, or people in

the First World — in which everyone is brought into complicity with

powerful corporate elites in producing environmental dislocations. In

this way, the social roots of ecological problems are shrewdly obscured.

A new kind of biological “original sin” is created in which a vague

group of animals called “Humanity” is turned into a destructive force

that threatens the survival of the living world.

Reduced to a mere species, human beings can now be treated as a

simple zoological phenomenon subject to the “biological laws” that

presumably determine the “struggle for existence” in the the natural

world. If there is a famine, for example, it can be “explained” by simple

biological notions like a “shortage of food,” presumably caused by

“excess population,” If there is a war, it can be explained by the

“stresses” produced by “overcrowding” or the need for “living space.”

In a like manner, we can dismiss or explain away hunger, misery,

or illness as “natural checks” that are imposed on human beings to

retain the “balance of nature.” We can comfortably forget that much of

the poverty and hunger that afflicts the world has its origin in the

corporate exploitation of human beings and nature — in agribusiness

and social oppression. Human beings, you see, are merely a species like

rabbits, lemmings, and the like, who are inexorably subject to relentless

“natural laws.” [1]

If one views the human condition this way, such that all life-forms

are “biocentrically” interchangeable despite their unique qualities,

people, too, become interchangeable with locusts or, for that matter,

viruses — as has been seriously suggested in a debate by advocates of

this viewpoint — and are equally expendable in the interplay of

so-called natural laws.

The young Californian who presented these views expressed only

the crudest notions that make up this growing ideology. He may very

well have been one of those people I have recently encountered in the

United States who believes that African children — presumably like

other “animals” — should be permitted to starve because they are

“overpopulating” the continent and burdening the biological “carrying

capacity” of their respective countries. Or, what is equally vicious, that

the AIDS epidemic should be welcomed as a means of reducing

“excessive” population. Or, more chauvinistically, that “immigrants”

to the United States from Latin America (often Indians whose ancestors

came to the Americas thousands of years ago) should be kept out

because they threaten “our” resources.

Presented in so crude and racist a form, with the use of words like

“our” to designate an America whose resources are actually owned by

a handful of giant corporations, this viewpoint is likely to be repugnant

to most Americans. Nevertheless, as simple-minded, purely zoological

answers to highly complex social questions, the viewpoint lends to gain

a growing following, particularly among the more macho,

authoritarian, and reactionary types who have always used “nature” and

“natural laws” as substitutes for a study of real social issues and

concerns.

The temptation to equate human beings who live in complex, highly

institutionalized, and bitterly divided societies with ordinary animals,

is finding its voice in seemingly sophisticated arguments that often

parade under the guise of “radical” ecological philosophies. The resurgence of a new Malthusianism that contends that growth rates in

population tend to exceed growth rates in food production is die most

sinister ideological development of all.

The myth that population increases in places like the Sudan, for

example, result in famine (not the notorious fact that the Sudanese could

easily feed themselves if they were not forced by the American-controlled World Bank and International Monetary Fund to grow cotton instead of grains) typically represents the kind of arguments that are

gaining popularity among many environmentalists, “Nature,” we are

arrogantly told by privileged Euro-Americans who parade as “natural

law” theorists, “must be permitted to take its course” — as though the

profits of corporations, banks, and agribusiness have anything to do

with the “course” of nature.

What renders this new “biocentrism,” with its antihumanistic image

of human beings as interchangeable with rodents or ants, so insidious

is that it now forms the premise of a growing movement called “deep

ecology.”[2] “Deep ecology” was spawned among well-to-do people

who have been raised on a spiritual diet of Eastern cults mixed with

Hollywood and Disneyland fantasies. The American mind is formless

enough without burdening it with “biocentric” myths of a Buddhist and

Taoist belief in a universal “oneness” so cosmic that human beings with

ail their distinctiveness dissolve into an all-encompassing form of

biocentric equality.” Reduced to merely one life-form among many,

the poor and the impoverished either become fair game for outright

extermination if they are socially expendable, or they become objects

of brutal exploitation if they can be used to aggrandize the corporate

world. Accordingly, terms like “oneness” and a “biocentric

democracy” go hand-in-hand with a pious formula for human oppression, misery, and even extermination.

Finally, ecological thinking is not enriched by recklessly blending

such disparate religions as Buddhism and Taoism with Christianity,

much less philosophers like the Jewish thinker Spinoza with a Nazi

apologist like Heidegger. To declare, as Ame Naess, the pontiff of

“deep ecology,” has done, that the “basic principles of the deep ecology

movement lie in religion or philosophy,” is to make a conclusion

notable for its absence of reference to social theory.[3]

There is enough in this mix of “biocentrism”, antihumanism,

mysticism, and religion with its “natural law” ethos to feed extremely

reactionary and atavistic tendencies, all well-meaning references in

deep ecology about “decentralization” and “nonhierarchy” aside. This

raises the question of still another exotic tendency that is percolating

through the ecology movements. I refer to the paradoxical need for a

new theistic ecological “spirituality.” That the word “spirituality” may

often mean a decent, indeed, a wholesome sensitivity to nature and its

subtle interconnections, is a very substantial reason to guard ourselves

against its degeneration into an atavistic, simple-minded form of nature

religion peopled by gods, goddesses, and eventually a new hierarchy

of priests and priestesses. Mystical versions of feminism, as well as the

ecology movement as a whole, alas, have sometimes proved themselves

to be all too vulnerable to this tendency. The clear-sighted *naturalism*

to which ecology so vividly lends itself is now in danger of being

supplanted by a **super**natural outlook that is inherently alien to nature’s

own fecundity and self-creativity.

May we not reasonably ask why the natural world has to be peopled

with earth gods and goddesses when natural evolution exhibits a

marvelous power of its own to generate such a rich and wondrous

variety of living beings? Is this alone not enough to Fill the human mind

with admiration and respect? Is it not the crudest form of

“anthropocentrism” (to use a word for the projection of the human into

the natural that evokes so much disdain in ecology movements) to

introduce deified forms created by the human imagination into the

natural world in the name of ecological “spirituality”?

To worship or revere *any* being, natural or supernatural, will always

be a form of self-subjugation and servitude that ultimately yields social

domination, be it in the name of nature, society, gender, or religion.

More than one civilization was riddled by “nature deities” that were

cynically used by ruling elites to support the most rigid, oppressive, and

dehumanizing of social hierarchies. The moment human beings fall to

their knees before *any* thing that is “higher” than themselves, hierarchy

will have made its first triumph over freedom, and human backs will

be exposed to all the burdens that can be inflicted on them by social

domination.

I have raised some of the problems posed by the misanthropic,

antihuman tendencies in the ecology movement not to defame the

movement as a whole. Quite to the contrary: my purpose in surveying

these tendencies is to peel away the fungus that has accumulated around

the movement and look at the promising fruit ecology can yield for the

future. The reason why this book has been written is to show as clearly

as possible that ecology alone, firmly rooted in *social* criticism and a

vision of *social* reconstruction, can provide us with the means for

remaking society in a way that will benefit nature *and* humanity.

However, we cannot achieve such a criticism and vision by swinging

mindlessly from one extreme that advocates the complete “domination

of nature” by “man” to another, rather confused “biocentric” or antihumanist extreme that essentially reduces humanity to a parasitic

swarm of mosquitoes in a mystified swamp called “Nature,” We must

remove ourselves from an ideological catapult that periodically flings

us from fad to fad and absurdity to absurdity.

It is tempting to return to the radicalism of the past where assured

dogmas were socially inspirational and had the aura of romantic rebellion around them. Having been raised in that era of a half-century ago,

I find it emotionally congenial — but intellectually very inadequate.

Traditional radical theory is now in debris. Much that passes for

socialism and communism, today, acts as a crucial support for the

prevailing market society. Archaic slogans like the “nationalization of

property” and a “planned economy” reinforce the growing centralization and rationalization of the corporate economy and the State. Marx’s

almost reverential attitude toward technological innovation and growth

threatens to express the most malignant goals of a technocratic ideology

and a technocratic bureaucracy. Even the strategic political goals of

orthodox radicalism, with its vision of the proletariat as a hegemonic

class, are fading away with the displacement of industrial workers by

automation. No great movements are gathering under the banner of the

red flag — only the ghostly rebels of the past who perished in the failed

insurrections of a bygone era and the leaders who guided them into a

historic limbo.

By the same token, liberal environmentalism has become a balm for

soothing the bad consciences of rapacious industrialists who engage in

a tasteless ballet with environmental lobbyists, lawyers, and public

officials. For this crew, nature is essentially a collection of natural

resources. Their environmental ballets have the goal of soothing consciences according to an ethics of lesser evils, not an ethics of the

greater good and virtue. Typically, a huge forest is usually “traded off”

for a small stand of trees and a large stretch of wetlands for a small,

presumably “improved” wildlife sanctuary.

In the meantime, the overall deterioration of the environment occurs

at a madcap pace. Basic planetary cycles, like the ratio of atmospheric

gases and the factors which determine it, are undermined, increasing

the proportion of carbon dioxide to oxygen in the air. Ecologically

fragile rain forests, that have been on earth for sixty million years or

more and whose role in maintaining the integrity of the air we breathe

is indeterminable, are recklessly removed. Chemical pollutants like

chlorofluoro-carbons threaten to thin out and open vast holes in the

ozone layer that protects all complex life-forms from the sun’s harmful

ultra-violet radiation. These are the major insults that are being inflicted

on the planet. They do not include the daily diet of chemical pollutants,

acid rain, harmful food additives, and agricultural poisons that may be changing

the whole spectrum of diseases that claim human and

non-human life today.

The control of these potentially disastrous alterations of the earth’s

ecological balance has virtually collapsed before the “compromises”

and “trade-offs” engineered by liberal enviornmentalists. Indeed, what

renders the liberal approach so hopelessly ineffectual is the fact that it

takes the present social order for granted, like the air we breathe and

the water we drink. All of these “compromises” and “trade-offs” rest

on the paralysing belief that a market society, privately owned property,

and the present-day bureaucratic nation-state cannot be changed in any

basic sense. Thus, it is the prevailing order that sets the terms of any

“compromise” or “trade-off,” just like the rules of a chess game and the

grid of a chess board determine in advance what the players can do —

not the dictates of reason and morality.

To “play by the rules” of the environmental game means that the

natural world, including oppressed people, always loses something

piece by piece until everything is lost in the end. As long as liberal

environmentalism is structured around the social status quo, property

rights always prevail over public rights and power always prevails over

powerlessness. Be it a forest, wetlands, or good agricultural soil, a

“developer” who owns any of these “resources” usually sets the terms

on which every negotiation occurs and ultimately succeeds in achieving

the triumph of wealth over ecological consideration.

Finally, liberal environmentalism suffers from a consistent refusal

to see that a capitalistic society based on competition and growth for

its own sake must ultimately devour the natural world, just like an

untreated cancer must ultimately devour its host. Personal intentions,

be they good or bad, have little to do with this unrelenting process. An

economy that is structured around the maxim, “Grow or Die,” must

*necessarily* pit itself against the natural world and leave ecological ruin

in its wake as it works its way through the biosphere. I need hardly add

that the growth-oriented, bureaucratic, and highly stratified “socialist”

world offers no alternatives to the failure of liberalism. Totalitarian

countries are equally culpable in the plundering of the planet. The most

important difference between them and their Western counterparts is

that a “planned economy” renders their efforts more systematic. Any

opposition — be it liberal or radical — is more easily silenced by the

institutions of a police state.

The narrowing choices that seem to confront us — notably, an

unfeeling misanthropic kind of “ecologism” and a queasy liberal environmentalism — require that we look for another way. Is the only

response to liberal environmentalism and its diet of failures a “deep

ecology” that mystifies “wild” nature and wildlife, important as

remaining areas of pristine nature may be? Are we obliged to choose

between lobbying, “compromises,” and “trade-offs” and a

“biocentric,” antihumanist mentality that tends to reduce humanity to

nothing more than a mere animal species and the human mind to blight

on the natural world? Is the only response to a technology gone wild a

return to a hunting and gathering way of life in which chipped flints are

our principal materials for acting on the natural world? And is the only

response to the logic of modern science and engineering a celebration

of irrationality, instinct, and religiosity?

Admittedly, I have simplified the alternatives. But I have done so

only to reveal their logic and implications. For one thing, I do not wish

to deny that even liberal environmentalism and the value of an instinctive sensibility have their roles in resisting a powerful technology that

has been placed in the service of mindless growth, accumulation, and

consumption. A stand against the construction of a nuclear reactor, a

new highway, an effort to clear-cut a mountainside, or a new condo

development that threatens to deface an urban landscape — all represent important acts, however limited, to prevent further environmental

deterioration. Land, wildlife, scenic natural beauty, and ecological

variety that is preserved from the bulldozer and profit-oriented

predators, are important enclaves of nature and aesthetics that must be

preserved wherever we can do so. It requires no great theoretical or

ideological wisdom to recognize that almost everything of wonder and

beauty, from a statuesque tree to a burrowing mammal, has its place in

the world and its function in the biosphere.

However, to carry these compelling facts to a point where humanity

is seen either as a blight on nature or the “lord of creation” leads to a

very sinister result. Both views serve to pit humanity against nature,

whether as “blight” or as “lord.” Humanity (insofar as this word denotes

a species rather than highly divided social beings who live in sharp

conflict with each other as oppressed and oppressor) is plucked out of

the evolution of life and placed on a shelf like an inanimate object.

Isolated from the world of life with either curses or praises, it is then

dispatched back into a primal world of the distant past or catapulted up

to the stars, regaled with space suits and exotic weapons. Neither of

these images touches upon an all-important fact: human beings exist in

various *societies*, all of which are profoundly relevant to our ecological

problems. As social beings, humans have developed ways of relating

to each other through *institutions* that, more than any single factor,

determine how they deal with the natural world.

I submit that we must go beyond the superficial layer of ideas created

by “biocentricity,” “antihumanism, Malthusianism, and “deep ecology” at one extreme, and the belief in growth, competition, human “supremacy,” and social power at the other extreme. We must look at

the *social* factors that have created both of these extremes in their many

different forms and answer key questions about the human condition if

we are to harmonize humanity’s relationship with nature.

What, after all, *is* human society when we try to view it from an

ecological perspective? A “curse?” An unmitigated “blessing?” A

device for coping with material needs? Or day I say a *product* of

natural evolution as well as culture that not only meets a wide variety

of human needs, but, potentially at least, can play a major role in

fostering the evolution of life on the planet?

What factors have produced ecologically harmful human societies?

And what factors could yield ecologically beneficial human societies?

Is a well-developed technology necessarily anti-ecological or can it

be used to enhance the biosphere and habitats of life?

What can we learn from history that will answer these questions and

advance our thinking beyond the bumper-sticker slogans that we encounter among the misanthropic and liberal environmentalists alike?

Indeed, how should we think out these questions? By means of

conventional logic? Intuition? Divine inspiration? Or, perhaps, by

developmental ways of thinking that are called “dialectical?”

Lastly, but by no means finally, what kind of social reconstruction

do we need to harmonize humanity’s relationship with nature —

assuming, to be sure, that society should not be dismissed and everyone

rush off to claim his or her mountain peak in the High Sierras or

Adirondaks? By what political, social, and economic means will such

a reconstruction be achieved? And by what ethical principles will it be

guided?

These are, at best, preliminary questions. There are many others that

we will have to consider before our discussion comes to its end I

hesitate to go further, here, because I have a deep aversion to a mere

laundry list of ideas, half-thought-out statements, flow diagrams, and

bumper-sticker slogans that are so much in vogue these days. When my

young man from California shouted the words “human beings” at me,

he did his best *not* to think and he sets an intellectually crude example

of mindlessness to others whose minds have been shaped by Hollywood, Disneyland, and television.

Hence, more than ever, we desperately need coherence. I do not

mean dogma. Rather, I mean a real *structure* of ideas that places

philosophy, anthropology, history, ethics, a new rationality, and

utopian visions in the service of freedom — freedom, let me add, for

*natural* development as well as human. This is a structure which we

shall have to build in the pages that follow, not simply to collect in

pell-mell fashion into a mere rubbish heap of ideas. The unfinished

thought is as dangerous as the totally finished dogma. Both yield an

uncreative vision of reality that can be bent and twisted in every

possible direction; hence the extremely contradictory notions that exist

in works on “deep ecology.”

This book was written to address the questions I have raised in the

hope that we can formulate the coherent framework to which I have

already alluded and develop a practice of which we are in dire need. It

has been initiated by an incident, by an encounter with real life — not

by reclusive academic reflections and private vagaries.

If the ecology movement which I helped to pioneer some thirty years

ago folds its tents for the mountains or turns to Washington for

influence, the loss will be irreparable. Ecological thinking, today, can

provide the most important synthesis of ideas we have seen since the

Enlightenment, two centuries ago. It can open vistas for a practice that

can effectively change the entire social landscape of our time. The

stylistic militancy readers encounter in this book stems from a troubled

sense of urgency. It is vitally incumbent upon us not to let an ecological

way of thinking and the movement it can produce degenerate and go

the way of traditional radicalism — into the lost mazes of an irrecoverable history.

Society and Ecology

The problems which many people face today in “defining” themselves,

in knowing “who they are” — problems that feed a vast psychotherapy

industry — are by no means personal ones. These problems exist not

only for private individuals; they exist for modern society as a whole.

Socially, we live in desperate uncertainty about how people relate to

each other. We suffer not only as individuals from alienation and

confusion over our identities and goals; our entire society, conceived

as a single entity, seems unclear about its own nature and sense of

direction. If earlier societies tried to foster a belief in the virtues of

cooperation and care, thereby giving an ethical meaning to social life,

modern society fosters a belief in the virtues of competition and

egotism, thereby divesting human association of all meaning — except,

perhaps, as an instrument for gain and mindless consumption.

We tend to believe that men and women of earlier times were guided

by firm beliefs and hopes — values that defined them as human beings

and gave purpose to their social lives. We speak of the Middle Ages as

an “Age of Faith” or the Enlightenment as an “Age of Reason.” Even

the pre-World War II era and the years that followed it seem like an

alluring time of innocence and hope, despite the Great Depression and

the terrible conflicts that stained it. As an elderly character in a recent,

rather sophisticated, espionage movie put it: what he missed about his

younger years during World War II were their “clarity” — a sense of

purpose and idealism that guided his behaviour.

That “clarity,” today, is gone. It has been replaced by ambiguity.

The certainty that technology and science would improve the human

condition is mocked by the proliferation of nuclear weapons, by massive hunger in the Third World, and by poverty in the First World. The

fervent belief that liberty would triumph over tyranny is belied by the

growing centralization of states everywhere and by the disempowerment of people by bureaucracies, police forces, and sophisticated

surveillance techniques — in our “democracies” no less than in visibly

authoritarian countries. The hope that we would form “one world,” a

vast community of disparate ethnic groups that would share their

resources to improve life everywhere, has been shattered by a rising

tide of nationalism, racism, and an unfeeling parochialism that fosters

indifference to the plight of millions.

We believe that our values are worse than those held by people of

only two or three generations ago. The present generation seems more

self-centred, privatized, and mean-spirited by comparison with earlier

ones. It lacks the support systems provided by the extended family,

community, and a commitment to mutual aid. The encounter of the

individual with society seems to occur through cold bureaucratic agencies rather than warm, caring people.

This lack of social identity and meaning is all the more stark in the

face of the mounting problems that confront us. War is a chronic

condition of our time; economic uncertainty, an all-pervasive presence;

human solidarity, a vaporous myth. Not least of the problems we

encounter are nightmares of an ecological apocalypse—a catastrophic

breakdown of the systems that maintain the stability of the planet. We

live under the constant threat that the world of life will be irrevocably

undermined by a society gone mad in its need to grow—replacing the

organic by the inorganic, soil by concrete, forest by barren earth, and

the diversity of life-forms by simplified ecosystems; in short, a turning

back of the evolutionary clock to an earlier, more inorganic, mineralized world that was incapable of supporting complex life-forms of any

kind, including the human species.

Ambiguity about our fate, meaning, and purpose thus raises a rather

startling question: is society itself a curse, a blight on life generally?

Are we any better for this new phenomenon called “civilization” that

seems to be on the point of destroying the natural world produced over

millions of years of organic evolution?

An entire literature has emerged which has gained the attention of

millions of readers: a literature that fosters a new pessimism toward

civilization as such. This literature pits technology against a presumably “virginal” organic nature; cities against countryside; countryside

against “wilderness”; science against a “reverence” for life; reason

against the “innocence” of intuition; and, indeed, humanity against the

entire biosphere.

We show signs of losing faith in all our uniquely human abilities

our ability to live in peace with each other, our ability to care for our

fellow beings and other life-forms. This pessimism is fed daily by

sociobiologists who locate our failings in our genes, by antihumanists

who deplore our “antinatural” sensibilities, and by “biocentrists” who

downgrade our rational qualities with notions that we are no different

in our “intrinsic worth” than ants. In short, we arc witnessing a

widespread assault against the ability of reason, science, and technology to improve the world for ourselves and life generally.

The historic theme that civilization must inevitably be pitted against

nature, indeed, that it is corruptive of human nature, has re-surfaced in

our midst from the days that reach back to Rousseau — this, precisely

at a time when our need for a truly human and ecological civilization

has never been greater if we are to rescue our planet and ourselves.

Civilization, with its hallmarks of reason and technics, is viewed

increasingly as a new blight. Even more basically, society as a

phenomenon in its own right is being questioned so much so that its

role as integral to the formation of humanity is seen as something

harmfully “unnatural” and inherently destructive.

Humanity, in effect, is being defamed by human beings themselves,

ironically, as an accursed form of life that all but destroys the world of

life and threatens its integrity. To the confusion that we have about our

own muddled time and our personal identities, we now have the added

confusion that the human condition is seen as a form of chaos produced

by our proclivity for wanton destruction and our ability to exercise this

proclivity all the more effectively because we possess reason, science,

and technology.

Admittedly, few antihumanists, “biocentrists,” and misanthropes,

who theorize about the human condition, are prepared to follow the

logic of their premises to such an absurd point. What is vitally important

about this medley of moods and unfinished ideas is that the various

forms, institutions, and relationships that make up what we should call

“society” are largely ignored. Instead, just as we use vague words like

“humanity” or zoological terms like *homo sapiens* that conceal vast

differences, often bitter antagonisms, that exist between privileged

whites and people of colour, men and women, rich and poor, oppressor

and oppressed; so do we, by the same token, use vague words like

“society” or “civilization” that conceal vast differences between free,

nonhierarchical, class, and stateless societies on the one hand, and

others that arc, in varying degrees, hierarchical, class-ridden, statist,

and authoritarian. Zoology, in effect, replaces socially oriented ecology, Sweeping “natural laws” based on population swings among

animals replace conflicting economic and social interests among

people.

Simply to pit “society” against “nature,” “humanity” against the

“biosphere,” and “reason,” “technology,” and “science” against less

developed, often primitive forms of human interaction with the natural

world, prevents us from examining the highly complex differences and

divisions within society so necessary to define our problems and their

solutions.

Ancient Egypt, for example, had a significantly different attitude

toward nature than ancient Babylonia. Egypt assumed a reverential

attitude toward a host of essentially animistic nature deities, many of

which were physically part human and part animal, while Babylonians

created a pantheon of very human political deities. But Egypt was no

less hierarchical than Babylonia in its treatment of people and was

equally, if not more, oppressive in its view of human individuality.

Certain hunting peoples may have been as destructive of wildlife,

despite their strong animistic beliefs, as urban cultures which staked

out an over-arching claim to reason. When these many differences are

simply swallowed up together with a vast variety of social forms by a

word called “society” we do severe violence to thought and even

simple intelligence. Society *per se* becomes something “unnatural”

“Reason,” “technology,” and “science” become things that are

“destructive” without any regard to the social factors that condition

their use. Human attempts to alter the environment are seen as threats

— as though our “species” can do little or nothing to improve the planet

for life generally.

Of course, we are not any less animals than other mammals, but we

are more than herds that browse on the African plains. The way in which

we are more — namely, the *kinds* of societies that we form and how

we are divided against each other into hierarchies and classes —

profoundly affects our behaviour and our effects on the natural world.

Finally, by so radically separating humanity and society from nature

or naively reducing them to mere zoological entities, we can no longer

see how human nature is *derived* from nonhuman nature and social

evolution from natural evolution. Humanity becomes estranged or

alienated not only from itself in our “age of alienation,” but from the

natural world in which it has always been rooted as a complex and

thinking life-form.

Accordingly, we are fed a steady diet of reproaches by liberal and

misanthropic environmentalists alike about how “we” as a species are

responsible for the breakdown of the environment. One does not have

to go to enclaves of mystics and gurus in San Francisco to find this

species-centred, asocial view of ecological problems and their sources.

New York City will do just as well. I shall not easily forget an

“environmental” presentation staged by the New York Museum of

Natural History in the seventies in which the public was exposed to a

long series of exhibits, each depicting examples of pollution and

ecological disruption. The exhibit which closed the presentation carried

a startling sign, “The Most Dangerous Animal on Earth” and it consisted simply of a huge mirror which reflected back the human viewer

who stood before it, I clearly recall a black child standing before the

mirror while a white school teacher tried to explain the message which

this arrogant exhibit tried to convey. There were no exhibits of corporate boards or directors planning to deforest a mountainside or

government officials acting in collusion with them. The exhibit

primarily conveyed one, basically misanthropic, message: people *as such*, not a rapacious society and its wealthy beneficiaries, are responsible for environmental dislocations — the poor no less than the

personally wealthy, people of colour no less than privileged whites,

women no less than men, the oppressed no less than the oppressor. A

mythical human “species” had replaced classes; individuals had

replaced hierarchies; personal tastes (many of which are shaped by a

predatory media) had replaced social relationships; and the disempowered who live meagre, isolated lives had replaced giant corporations, self-serving bureaucracies, and the violent paraphernalia of the

State.

The Relationship of Society to Nature

Leaving aside such outrageous “environmental” exhibitions that

mirror privileged and underprivileged people in the same frame, it

seems appropriate at this point to raise a highly relevant need: the need

to bring society back into the ecological picture. More than ever, strong

emphases must be placed on the fact that *nearly all ecological problems

are social problems*, not simply or primarily the result of religious,

spiritual or political ideologies. That these ideologies may foster an

anti-ecological outlook in people of all strata hardly requires emphasis.

But rather than simply taking their ideologies at face value, it is crucial

for us to ask from whence these ideologies develop.

Quite frequently, economic needs may compel people to act against

their best impulses, even strongly felt natural values. Lumberjacks who

— employed to clear-cut a magnificent forest normally have no

“hatred” of trees. They have little or no choice but to cut trees just as

stockyard workers have little or no choice but to slaughter domestic

animals. Every community or occupation has its fair share of destructive and sadistic individuals, to be sure, including misanthropic environmentalists who would like to see humanity exterminated. But

among the vast majority of people, this kind of work, including such

onerous tasks as mining, are not freely chosen occupations. They stem

from need and, above all, they are the product of social arrangements

over which ordinary people have no control.

To understand present-day problems — ecological as well as

economic and political — we must examine their social causes and

remedy them through social methods. “Deep,” “spiritual,” anti-humanist, and misanthropic ecologies gravely mislead us when they

refocus our attention on social symptoms rather than social causes. If

our obligation is to look at changes in social relationships in order to

understand our most significant ecological changes, these ecologies

steer us away from society to “spiritual” “cultural” or vaguely defined

“traditional” sources. The Bible did not create European antinaturalism; it served to justify an antinaturalism that already existed on

the continent from pagan times, despite the animistic traits of pre-Christian religions. Christianity’s antinaturaiistic influence became

especially marked with the emergence of capitalism. Society must not

only be brought into the ecological picture to understand why people

tend to choose competing sensibilities — some, strongly naturalistic;

others, strongly antinaturaiistic — but we must probe more deeply into

society itself. We must search out the *relationship of society to nature*,

the *reasons* why it can destroy the natural world, and, alternatively, the

reasons why it has and still can *enhance*, *foster*, and *richly contribute*

to natural evolution.

Insofar as we can speak of “society” in any abstract and general

sense — and let us remember that every society is highly unique and

different from others in the long perspective of history — we are

obliged to examine what we can best call “socialization,” not merely

“society.” Society is a given arrangement of relationships which we

often take for granted and view in a very fixed way. To many people

today, it would seem that a market society based on trade and competition has existed “forever,” although we may be vaguely mindful that

there were pre-market societies based on gifts and cooperation.

Socialization, on the other hand, is a *process*, just as individual living

is a process. Historically, the *process* of socializing people can be

viewed as a sort of social infancy that involves a painful rearing of

humanity to social maturity.

When we begin to consider socialization from an in-depth viewpoint, what strikes us is that society itself in its most primal form stems

very much *from* nature. Every social evolution, in fact, is virtually an

extension of natural evolution into a distinctly human realm. As the

Roman orator and philosopher, Cicero, declared some two thousand

years ago: “...by the use of our hands, we bring into being within the

realm of Nature, a second nature for ourselves.” Cicero’s observation,

to be sure, is very incomplete: the primeval, presumably untouched

“realm of Nature” or “first nature,” as it has been called, is reworked

in whole or part in to “second nature” not only by the “use of our hands.”

Thought, language, and complex, very important biological changes

also play a crucial and, at times, a decisive role in developing a “second

nature” within “first nature.”

I use the term “reworking” advisedly to focus on the fact that

“second nature” is not simply a phenomenon that develops outside of

“first nature” — hence the special value that should be attached to

Cicero’s use of the expression “*within* the realm of Nature...” To

emphasize that “second nature” or, more precisely, society (to use this

word in its broadest possible sense) emerges from *within* primeval “first

nature” is to re-establish the fact that social life always has a naturalistic

dimension, however much society is pitted against nature in our thinking. *Social* ecology clearly expresses the fact that society is not a sudden

“eruption” in the world. Social life does not necessarily face nature as

a combatant in an unrelenting war. The emergence of society is a

The human socialization process from which society emerges—be

it in the form of families, bands, tribes, or more complex types of human

intercourse — has its source in parental relationships, particularly

mother and child bonding. The biological mother, to be sure, can be

replaced in this process by many surrogates, including fathers, relatives, or, for that matter, alt members of a community. It is when *social* parents and *social* siblings — that is, the human community that

surrounds the young — begin to participate in a system of care, that is

ordinarily undertaken by biological parents, that society begins to truly

come into its own.

Society thereupon advances beyond a mere reproductive group

toward institutionalized human relationships, and from a relatively

formless animal community into a clearly structured social *order*. But

at the very inception of society, it seems more than likely that human

beings were socialized into “second nature” by means of deeply ingrained blood ties, specifically maternal ties. We shall see that in time

the structures or institutions that mark the advance of humanity from a

mere animal community into an authentic society began to undergo

far-reaching changes and these changes become issues of paramount

importance in social ecology. For better or worse, societies develop

around status groups, hierarchies, classes, and state formations. But

reproduction and family care remain the abiding biological bases for

every form of social life as well as the originating factor in the

socialization of the young and the formation of a society. As Robert

Briffault observed in the early half of this century, the “one known

factor which establishes a profound distinction between the constitution of the most rudimentary human group and all other animal groups

[is the] association of mothers and offspring which is the sole form of

true social solidarity among animals. Throughout the class of mammals, there is a continuous increase in the duration of that association,

which is the consequence of the prolongation of die period of infantile

dependence” [4] a prolongation which Briffault correlates with increases

in the period of feud gestation and advances in intelligence.

The biological dimension that Briffault adds to what we call society

and socialization cannot be stressed too strongly. It is a decisive

presence, not only in the origins of society over ages of animal evolution, but in the daily recreation of society in our everyday lives. The

appearance of a newly born infant and the highly extended care it

receives for many years reminds us that it is not only a human being

that is being reproduced, but society itself. By comparison with the

young of other species, children develop slowly and over a long period

of time. Living in close association with parents, siblings, kin groups,

and an ever-widening community of people, they retain a plasticity of

mind that makes for creative individuals and ever-formative social

groups. Although nonhuman animals may approximate human forms

of association in many ways, they do not create a “second nature” that

embodies a cultural tradition, nor do they possess a complex language,

elaborate conceptual powers, or an impressive capacity to restructure

their environment purposefully according to their own needs.

A chimpanzee, for example, remains an infant for only three years

and a juvenile for seven. By the age of ten, it is a full-grown adult.

Children, by contrast, are regarded as infants for approximately six

years and juveniles for fourteen. A chimpanzee, in short, grows mentally and physically in about half the time required by a human being,

and its capacity to learn or, at least to think, is already fixed by

comparison with a human being, whose mental abilities may expand

for decades. By the same token, chimpanzee associations are often

idiosyncratic and fairly limited. Human associations, on the other hand,

are basically stable, highly institutionalized, and they are marked by a

degree of solidarity, indeed, by a degree of creativity, that has no equal

in nonhuman species as far as we know.

This prolonged degree of human mental plasticity, dependency, and

social creativity yields two results that are of decisive importance. First,

early human association must have fostered a strong predisposition for

of anthropological evidence suggests that participation, mutual aid,

solidarity, and empathy were the social virtues early human groups

emphasized within their communities. The idea that people are dependent upon each each other for the good life, indeed, for survival, followed

from the prolonged dependence of the young upon adults. Independence, not to mention competition, would have seemed utterly

alien, if not bizarre, to a creature reared over many years in a largely

dependent condition. Care for others would have been seen as the

perfectly natural outcome of a highly acculturated being that was, in

turn, clearly in need of extended care. Our modern version of individualism, more precisely, of egotism, would have cut across the

grain of early solidarity and mutual aid — traits, I may add, without

which such a physically fragile animal like a human being could hardly

have survived as an adult, much less as a child.

Second, human interdependence must have assumed a highly structured form. There is no evidence that human beings normally relate to

each other through the fairly loose systems of bonding we find among

our closest primate cousins. That human social bonds can be dissolved

or de-institutionalized in periods of radical change or cultural breakdown is too obvious to argue here. But during relatively stable conditions, human society was never the “horde” that anthropologists of the

last century presupposed as a basis for rudimentary social life. On the

contrary, the evidence we have at hand points to the fact that all humans,

perhaps even our distant hominid ancestors, lived in some kind of

structured family groups, and, later, in bands, tribes, villages, and other

forms. In short they bonded together (as they still do), not only

emotionally and morally, but also structurally in contrived, clearly

definable, and fairly permanent institutions.

Nonhuman animals may form loose communities and even take

collective protective postures to defend their young from predators. But

such communities can hardly be called structured except in a broad,

often ephemeral sense. Humans, by contrast, create highly formal

communities that tend to become increasingly structured over the

course of time. In effect, they form not only communities, but a new

phenomenon called *societies*.

If we fail to distinguish animal communities from human societies,

we risk the danger of ignoring the unique features that distinguish

human social life from animal communities — notably, the ability of

society to *change* for better or worse and the factors that produce these

changes. By reducing a complex society to a mere community, we can

easily ignore how societies differed from each other over the course of

history. We can also fail to understand how they elaborated simple

differences in status into Firmly established hierarchies, or hierarchies,

into economic classes. Indeed, we risk the possibility of totally

misunderstanding the very meaning of terms like “hierarchy” as highly

organized systems of command and obedience — these, as distinguished from personal, individual, and often short-lived differences in

status that may, in all too many cases, involve no acts of compulsion.

We tend, in effect, to confuse the strictly institutional creations of

human will, purpose, conflicting interests, and traditions, with community life in its most Fixed forms, as though we were dealing with

inherent, seemingly unalterable, features of society rather than fabricated structures that can be modified, improved, worsened—or simply

abandoned. The trick of every ruling elite from the beginnings of

history to modern times has been to identify its own socially created

hierarchical systems of domination with community life *as such*, with

the result being that human-made institutions acquire divine or biological sanction.

A given society and its institutions thus tend to become reified into

permanent and unchangeable entities that acquire a mysterious life of

their own apart from nature — namely, the products of a seemingly

fixed “human nature” that is the result of genetic programming at the

very inception of social life. Alternatively, a given society and its

institutions may be dissolved into nature as merely another form of

animal community with its “alpha males,” “guardians,” “leaders,” and

“horde”-like forms of existence. When annoying issues like war and

social conflict are raised, they are ascribed to the activity of “genes”

that presumably give rise to war and even “greed.”

In either case, be it the notion of an abstract society that exists apart

from nature or an equally abstract natural community that is indistinguishable from nature, a dualism appears that sharply separates society

nature. These apparent! y contrasting, but closely related, notions are all

the more seductive because they are so simplistic. Although they are

often presented by their more sophisticated supporters in a fairly

nuanced form, such notions are easily reduced to bumper-sticker

slogans that are frozen into hard, popular dogmas.

Social Ecology

The approach to society and nature advanced by social ecology may

seem more intellectually demanding, but it avoids the simplicities of

dualism and the crudities of reductionism. Social ecology tries to show

how nature slowly *phases* into society without ignoring the differences

between society and nature on the one hand, as well as the extent to

which they merge with each other on the other. The everyday socialization of the young by the family is no less rooted in biology than the

everyday care of the old by the medical establishment is rooted in the

hard facts of society. By the same token, we never cease to be mammals

who still have primal natural urges, but we institutionalize these urges

and their satisfaction in a wide variety of social forms. Hence, the social

and the natural continually permeate each other in the most ordinary

activities of daily life without losing their identity in a shared process

of interaction, indeed, of interactivity.

Obvious as this may seem at first in such day-to-day problems as

caretaking, social ecology raises questions that have far-reaching importance for the different ways society and nature have interacted over

time and the problems these interactions have produced. How did a

divisive, indeed, seemingly combative, relationship between humanity

and nature emerge? What were the institutional forms and ideologies

that rendered this conflict possible? Given the growth of human needs

and technology, was such a conflict really unavoidable? And can it be

overcome in a future, ecologically oriented society?

How does a rational, ecologically oriented society fit into the processes of natural evolution? Even more broadly, is there any reason to

believe that the human mind — itself a product of natural evolution as

well as culture — represents a decisive highpoint in natural development, notably, in the long development of subjectivity from the sensitivity and self-maintenance of the simplest life-forms to the

remarkable intellectuality and self-consciousness of the most complex?

In asking these highly provocative questions, I am not trying to

justify a strutting arrogance toward nonhuman life-forms. Clearly, we

must bring humanity’s uniqueness as a species, marked by rich conceptual, social, imaginative, and constructive attributes, into synchronicity

with nature’s fecundity, diversity, and creativity. I have argued that this

synchronicity will not be achieved by opposing nature to society,

nonhuman to human life-forms, natural fecundity to technology, or a

natural subjectivity to the human mind. Indeed, an important result that

emerges from a discussion of the interrelationship of nature to society

is the fact that human intellectuality, although distinct, also has a

far-reaching natural basis. Our brains and nervous systems did not

suddenly spring into existence without a long antecedent natural history. That which we most prize as integral to our humanity — our

extraordinary capacity to think on complex conceptual levels—can be

traced back to the nerve network of primitive invertebrates, the ganglia

of a mollusk, the spinal cord of a fish, the brain of an amphibian, and

the cerebral cortex of a primate.

Here, too, in the most intimate of our human attributes, we are no

less products of natural evolution than we are of social evolution. As

human beings we incorporate within ourselves aeons of organic differentiation and elaboration. Like all complex life-forms, we are not

only part of natural evolution; we are also its heirs and the products of

natural fecundity.

In trying to show how society slowly grows out of nature, however,

social ecology is also obliged to show how society, too, undergoes

differentiation and elaboration. In doing so, social ecology must examine those junctures in social evolution where splits occurred which

slowly brought society into opposition to the natural world, and explain

how this opposition emerged from its inception in prehistoric times to

our own era. Indeed, if the human species is a life-form that can

consciously and richly enhance the natural world, rather than simply

damage it, it is important for social ecology to reveal the factors that

have rendered many human beings into parasites on the world of life

rather than active partners in organic evolution. This project must be

undertaken not in a haphazard way, but with a serious attempt to render

natural and social development coherent in terms of each other, and

relevant to our times and the construction of an ecological society.

Perhaps one of social ecology’s most important contributions to the

current ecological discussion is the view that the basic problems which

pit society against nature emerge form *within* social development itself

—not *between* society and nature. That is to say, the divisions between

society and nature have their deepest roots in divisions within the social

realm, namely, deep-seated conflicts between human and human that

are often obscured by our broad use of the word “humanity.”

This crucial view cuts across the grain of nearly all current ecological thinking and even social theorizing. One of the most fixed notions

that present-day ecological thinking shares with liberalism, Marxism,

and conservatism is the historic belief that the “domination of nature

requires the domination of human by human. This is most obvious in

social theory. Nearly all of our contemporary social ideologies have

placed the notion of human domination at the centre of their theorizing.

It remains one of the most widely accepted notions, from classical times

to the present, that human freedom from the “domination of man by

nature” entails the domination of human by human as the earliest means

of production and the use of human beings as instruments for harnessing the natural world. Hence, in order to harness the natural world, it

has been argued for ages, it is necessary to harness human beings as

well, in the form of slaves, serfs, and workers.

That this instrumental notion pervades the ideology of nearly all

ruling elites and has provided both liberal and conservative movements

with a justification for their accommodation to the status quo, requires

little, if any, elaboration. The myth of a “stingy” nature has always been

used to justify the “stinginess” of exploiters in their harsh treatment of

the exploited — and it has provided the excuse for the political

opportunism of liberal, as well as conservative, causes. To “work within

the system” has always implied an acceptance of domination as a way

of “organizing” social life and, in the best of cases, a way of freeing

humans from their presumed domination by nature.

What is perhaps less known, however, is that Marx, loo, justified the

emergence of class society and the State as stepping stones toward the

domination of nature and, presumably, the liberation of humanity. It

was on the strength of this historical vision that Marx formulated his

materialist conception of history and his belief in the need for class

society as a stepping stone in the historic road to communism.

Ironically, much that now passes for antihumanistic, mystical ecology involves exactly the same kind of thinking — but in an inverted

form. Like their instrumental opponents, these ecologists, too, assume

that humanity is dominated by nature, be it in the form of “natural laws”

or an ineffable “earth wisdom” that must guide human behaviour. But

while their instrumental opponents argue the need to achieve nature’s

“surrender” to a “conquering” active-aggressive humanity, antihumanist and mystical ecologists argue the case for achieving

humanity’s passive-receptive “surrender” to an “all-conquering” nature. However much the two views may differ in their verbiage and

pieties, *domination* remains the underlying notion of both: a natural

world conceived as a taskmaster — either to be controlled or obeyed.

Social ecology springs this trap dramatically by re-examining the

entire concept of domination, be it in nature and society or in the form

of “natural law” and “social law.” What we normally call domination

in nature is a human projection of highly organized systems of *social*

command and obedience onto highly idiosyncratic, individual, and

asymmetrical forms of often mildly coercive behaviour in animal

communities. Put simply, animals do not “dominate” each other in the

same way that a human elite dominates, and often exploits, an oppressed social group. Nor do they “rule” through institutional forms of

systematic violence as social elites do. Among apes, for example, there

is little or no coercion, but only erratic forms of dominant behaviour.

Gibbons and orangutans are notable for their peaceable behaviour

toward members of their own kind. Gorillas are often equally pacific,

although one can single out “high status,” mature, and physically strong

males among “lower status,” younger and physically weaker ones. The

“alpha males” celebrated among chimpanzees do not occupy very fixed

“status” positions within what are fairly fluid groups. Any status that

they do achieve may be due to very diverse causes.

One can merrily skip from one animal species to another, to be sure,

falling back on very different, asymmetrical reasons for searching out

“high” versus “low status” individuals. The procedure becomes rather

silly, however, when words like “status” are used so flexibly that they

are allowed to include mere differences in group behaviour and functions, rather than coercive actions.

The same is true for the word “hierarchy.” Both in its origins and its

strict meaning, this term is highly social, not zoological. A Greek term,

initially used to denote different levels of deities and, later, of clergy

(characteristically, Hicrapolis was an ancient Phrygian city in Asia

Minor that was a centre for mother goddess worship), the word has been

mindlessly expanded to encompass everything from beehive relationships to the erosive effects of running water in which a stream is seen

to wear down and “dominate” its bedrock. Caring female elephants are

called “matriarchs” and attentive male apes who exhibit a great deal of

courage in defense of their community, while acquiring very few

“privileges,” are often designated as “patriarchs.” The absence of an

organized system of rule — so common in hierarchical human communities and subject to radical institutional changes, including popular

revolutions — is largely ignored.

Again, the different functions that the presumed animal hierarchies

are said to perform, that is, the asymmetrical causes that place one

individual in an “alpha status” and others in a lesser one, is understated

where it is noted at all. One might, with much the same aplomb, place

all tall sequoias in a “superior” status over smaller ones, or, more

annoyingly, regard them as an “elite” in a mixed forest hierarchy over

“submissive” oaks, which, to complicate matters, are more advanced

on the evolutionary’ scale. The tendency to mechanically project social

categories onto the natural world is as preposterous as an attempt to

project biological concepts onto geology. Minerals do not reproduce

the way life-forms do. Stalagmites and stalactites in caves certainly do

increase in size over time. But in no sense do they grow in a manner

that even remotely corresponds to growth in living beings. To take

superficial resemblances, often achieved in alien ways, and group them

into shared identities, is like speaking of the “metabolism” of rocks and

the “morality” of genes.

This raises the issue of repeated attempts to read ethical, as well as

social, traits into a natural world that is only *potentially* ethical insofar

as it forms a basis for an objective social ethics. Yes, coercion does

exist in nature; so does pain and suffering. However, *cruelty* does not.

Animal intention and will are too limited to produce an ethics of good

and evil or kindness and cruelty. Evidence of inferential and conceptual

thought is very limited among animals, except for primates, cetaceans,

elephants, and possibly a few other mammals. Even among the most

intelligent animals, the limits to thought are immense in comparison

with the extraordinary capacities of socialized human beings. Admittedly, we are substantially less than human today in view of our still

unknown potential to be creative, caring, and rational. Our prevailing

society serves to inhibit, rather than realize, our human potential. We

still lack the imagination to know how much our finest human traits

could expand with an ethical, ecological, and rational dispensation of

human affairs.

By contrast, the known nonhuman world seems to have reached

visibly fixed limits in its capacity to survive environmental changes. If

mere *adaptation* to environmental changes is seen as the criterion for

evolutionary success (as many biologists believe), then insects would

have to be placed on a higher plane of development than any mammalian life-form. However, they would be no more capable of making

so lofty an intellectual evaluation of themselves than a queen bee

would be even remotely aware of her “regal” status — a status, I may

add, that only humans (who have suffered the social domination of

stupid, inept, and cruel kings and queens) would be able to impute to a

largely mindless insect.

None of these remarks are meant to metaphysically oppose nature

to society or society to nature. On the contrary, they are meant to argue

that what unites society with nature in a graded evolutionary continuum

is the remarkable extent to which human beings, living in a rational,

ecologically oriented society, could *embody* the *creativity* of nature

this, as distinguished from a purely *adaptive* criterion of evolutionary

success. The great achievements of human thought, art, science, and

technology serve not only to monumentalize culture, *they serve also to monumentalize natural evolution itself*. They provide heroic evidence

that the human species is a warm-blooded, excitingly versatile, and

keenly intelligent life-form not a cold-blooded, genetically

programmed, and mindless insect — that expresses *nature’s* greatest

powers of creativity.

Life-forms that create and consciously alter their environment,

hopefully in ways that make it more rational and ecological, represent

a vast and indefinite extension of nature into fascinating, perhaps

unbounded, lines of evolution which no branch of insects could ever

achieve—notably, the evolution of a fully *self-conscious nature*. If this

be humanism — more precisely, ecological humanism — the current

crop of antihumanists and misanthropes are welcome to make the most

of it.

Nature, in turn, is not a scenic view we admire through a picture

window — a view that is frozen into a landscape or a static panorama.

Such “landscape” images of nature may be spiritually elevating but they

are ecologically deceptive. Fixed in time and place, this imagery makes

it easy for us to forget that nature is not a static vision of the natural

world but the long, indeed cumulative, *history* of natural development.

This history involves the evolution of the inorganic, as well as the

organic, realms of phenomena. Wherever we stand in an open field,

forest, or on a mountain top, our feet rest on ages of development, be

they geological strata, fossils of long-extinct life-forms, the decaying

remains of the newly dead, or the quiet stirring of newly emerging life.

Nature is not a “person,” a “caring Mother,” or, in the crude materialist

language of the last century, “matter and motion.” Nor is it a mere

“process” that involves repetitive cycles like seasonal changes and the

building-up and breaking-down process of metabolic activity — some

“process philosophies” to the contrary notwithstanding. Rather, natural

history is a *cumulative* evolution toward ever more varied, differentiated, and complex forms and relationships.

This *evolutionary* development of increasingly variegated entities,

most notably, of life-forms, is also an evolutionary development which

contains exciting, latent possibilities. With variety, differentiation, and

complexity, nature, in the course of its own unfolding, opens new

directions for still further development along alternative lines of natural

evolution. To the degree that animals become complex, self-aware, and

increasingly intelligent, they begin to make those elementary choices

that influence their own evolution. They are less and less the passive

objects of “natural selection” and more and more the active subjects of

their own development.

A brown hare that mutates into a white one and sees a snow-covered

terrain in which to camouflage itself is *acting* on behalf of its own

survival, not simply “adapting” in order to survive. It is not merely

being “selected” by its environment; it is selecting its own environment

and making a *choice* that expresses a small measure of subjectivity and

judgement.

The greater the variety of habitats that emerge in the evolutionary

process, the more a given life-form, particularly a neurologicatly complex one, is likely to play an active and judgemental role in preserving

itself. To the extent that natural evolution fol lows this path of neurological development, it gives rise to life-forms that exercise an ever-wider

latitude of choice and a nascent form of freedom in developing themselves.

Given this conception of nature as the cumulative history of more

differentiated levels of material organization (especially of life-forms)

and of increasing subjectivity, social ecology establishes a basis for a

meaningful understanding of humanity and society’s place in natural

evolution. Natural history is not a “catch-as-catch-can” phenomenon.

It is marked by tendency, by direction, and, as far as human beings are

concerned, by conscious purpose. Human beings and the social worlds

they create can open a remarkably expansive horizon for development

of the natural world — a horizon marked by consciousness, reflection,

and an unprecedented freedom of choice and capacity for conscious

creativity. The factors that reduce many life-forms to largely adaptive

roles in changing environments are replaced by a capacity for consciously adapting environments to existing and new life-forms.

Adaptation, in effect, increasingly gives way to creativity and the

seemingly ruthless action of “natural law” to greater freedom. What

earlier generations called “blind nature” to denote nature’s lack of any

moral direction, turns into “free nature,” a nature that slowly finds a

voice and the means to relieve the needless tribulations of life for all

species in a highly conscious humanity and an ecological society. The

“Noah Principle” of preserving every existing life-form simply for its

own sake—a principle advanced by the antihumanist, David Ehrenfeld

— has little meaning without the presupposition, at the very least, of

the existence of a “Noah” — that is, a conscious life-form called

humanity that might well rescue life-forms that nature itself would

extinguish in ice ages, land desiccation, or cosmic collisions with

asteroids.[5] Grizzly bears, wolves, pumas, and the like, are not safer

from extinction because they are exclusively in the “caring” hands of

a putative “Mother Nature.” If there is any truth to the theory that the

great Mesozoic reptiles were extinguished by climatic changes that

presumably followed the collision of an asteroid with the earth, the

survival of existing mammals might well be just as precarious in the

face of an equally meaningless natural catastrophe unless there is a

conscious, ecologically oriented life-form that has the technological

means to rescue them.

The issue, then, is not whether social evolution stands opposed to

natural evolution. The issue is *how* social evolution can be situated in

natural evolution and *why* it has been thrown — needlessly, as I will

argue — against natural evolution to the detriment of life as a whole.

The capacity to be rational and free does not assure us that this capacity

will be realized. If social evolution is seen as the potentiality for

expanding die horizon of natural evolution along unprecedented creative lines, and human beings arc seen as the potentiality for nature to

become self-conscious and free, the issue we face is *why* these potentialities have been warped and *how* they can be realized.

It is part of social ecology’s commitment to natural evolution that

these potentialities arc indeed real and that they can be fulfilled. This

commitment stands flatly at odds with a “scenic” image of nature as a

static view to awe mountain men or a romantic view for conjuring up

mystical images of a personified deity that is so much in vogue today.

The splits between natural and social evolution, nonhuman and human

life, an intractable “stingy” nature and a grasping, devouring humanity,

have all been specious and misleading when they are seen as inevitabilities. No less specious and misleading have been reductionist

attempts to absorb social into natural evolution, to collapse culture into

nature in an orgy of irrationalism, theism, and mysticism, to equate the

human with mere animality, or to impose a contrived “natural law” on

an obedient human society.

Whatever has turned human beings into “aliens” in nature are social

changes that have made many human beings “aliens” in their own social

world: the domination of the young by the old, of women by men, and

of men by men. Today, as for many centuries in the past, there are still

oppressive human beings who literally own society and others who are

owned by it Until society can be reclaimed by an undivided humanity

that will use its collective wisdom, cultural achievements, technological innovations, scientific knowledge, and innate creativity for its own

benefit and for that of the natural world, all ecological problems will

have their roots in social problems.

Hierarchies, Classes, and States

Up to now, I have tried to show that humanity and the human capacity

to think are products of natural evolution, not “aliens” in the natural

world. Indeed, every intuition tells us that human beings and their

consciousness are results of an evolutionary tendency toward increasing differentiation, complexity, and subjectivity. Like most sound

intuitions, this one has its basis in fact: the palaeontological evidence

for this tendency. The simplest unicellular fossils of the distant past and

the most complex mammalian remains of recent times all testify to the

reality of a remarkable biological drama. This drama is the story of a

nature rendered more and more aware of itself, a nature that slowly

acquires new powers of subjectivity, and one that gives rise to a

remarkable primate life-form, called human beings, that have the power

to choose, alter, and reconstruct their environment — and raise the

moral issue of what *ought* to be, not merely live unquestioningly with

what *is*.

Nature, as I have argued, is not a frozen scene that we observe from

a picture window or a mountain top. Defined more broadly and richly

than a slogan on a bumper-sticker, nature *is* the very history of its

evolutionary differentiation. If we think of nature as a development, we

discern the presence of this tendency toward self-consciousness and,

ultimately, toward freedom. Discussions about whether the presence of

this tendency is evidence of a predetermined “goal,” a “guiding hand,”

or a “God” are simply irrelevant for the purposes of this discussion. The

fact is that such a tendency can be shown to exist in the fossil record,

in the elaboration of existing life-forms from previous ones, and in the

existence of humanity itself.

Moreover, to ask what humanity’s “place” in nature may be is to

implicitly acknowledge that the human species has evolved as a life-form that is organized to *make* a place for itself in the natural world,

not simply to *adapt* to nature. The human species and its enormous

powers to alter the environment were not invented by a group of

ideologues called “humanists” who decided that nature was “made” to

serve humanity and its needs. Humanity’s powers have emerged out of

aeons of evolutionary development and out of centuries of cultural

development. The question of this species’ “place” in nature is no longer a

zoological problem, a problem of locating humanity in the overall evolution

of life, as it was in Darwin’s time. The problem of the “descent of man,”

to use the title of Darwin’s great work, is as accepted by thinking people today

as are the enormous powers our species possesses.

To ask what humanity’s “place” in nature may be has now become

a moral and social question — and one that no other animal can ask of

itself, as much as many antihumanists would like to dissolve humanity

into a mere species in a “biospheric democracy.” And for humans to

ask what their “place” in nature may be is to ask whether humanity’s

powers will be brought to the *service* of future evolutionary development or whether they will be used to *destroy* the biosphere. The extent

to which humanity’s powers will be brought to or against the service

for future evolutionary development has very much to do with the kind

of society or “second nature” human beings will establish: whether

society will be a domineering, hierarchical, and exploitative one, or

whether it will be a free, egalitarian, and ecologically oriented one. To

sidestep the social basis of our ecological problems, to obscure it with

primitivistic cobwebs spun by self-indulgent mystics and anti-rationalists, is to literally turn back the clock of ecological thinking to

an atavistic level of trite sentiment that can by used for utterly reactionary purposes.

But if society is so basic to an understanding of our ecological

problems, it, too, cannot be viewed as a frozen scenic view that we

observe from the rarefied heights of an academic tower, the balcony of

a governmental building, or the windows of a room for a corporate

board of directors. Society, too, has emerged out of nature, as I have

tried to show in my account of human socialization and the everyday

reproduction of that socializing process up to the present day. To regard

society as “alien” to nature reinforces the dualism between the social

and the natural so prevalent in modern thinking. Indeed, such an

antihumanistic view serves to clear the field for exactly all the anti-ecological forces that pit society against nature and reduce the natural

world to mere natural resources.

By the same token, to dissolve society into nature by rooting social

problems in genetic, instinctive, irrational, and mystical factors is to

clear the field for exactly all those primitivistic

racist, misanthropic, and sexist tendencies, be they among women or

among men.

Far from being a frozen scene, one that makes it easy for reactionary

elements to identify the existing society with society *as such*, — just

as the oppressed and their oppressors are grouped into a single species

called *homo sapiens* and are held equally responsible for our present

ecological crisis — society *is* the history of social development with its

many different social forms and possibilities. Culturally, we are all the

repositories of social history, just as our bodies are the repositories of

natural history. We carry with us, often unconsciously, a vast body of

beliefs, habits, attitudes, and sentiments that foster highly regressive

views toward nature as well as toward each other.

We have fixed images, often inexplicable to ourselves, of a static

“human nature,” as well as a nonhuman nature, that subtly shape a

multitude of our attitudes toward members of the two sexes, the young,

the elderly, family bonds, kinship loyalties, and political authority, not

to mention different ethnic, vocational, and social groups. Archaic

images of hierarchy still shape our views of the most elementary

differences between people and between all living beings. Our mental

arrangement of the most simple differences among phenomena into

hierarchical orders, say, of “one-to-ten “ have been formed by socially

ancestral distinctions that go back to a time that is too remote for us to

remember.

These hierarchical distinctions have been developed over the course

of history, often from harmless differences in mere status, into full-blown hierarchies of harsh command and abject obedience. To know

our present and to shape our future calls for a meaningful and coherent

understanding of the past — a past which always shapes us in varying

degrees, and which profoundly influences our views of humanity and

nature.

The Notion of Domination

To gain a clear understanding of how the past bears upon the present,

I must briefly examine a basic view in social ecology, one that has now

percolated into current environmental thinking. I refer to social

ecology’s insight that all our notions of dominating nature stem from

the very real domination of human by human. This statement, with its

use of the word “stem,” must be examined in terms of its intent Not

only is it a historical statement of the human condition, but it is also a

challenge to our contemporary condition which has far-reaching implications for social change. As a historical statement it declares, in no

uncertain terms, that the domination of human by human *preceded* the

notion of dominating nature. Indeed, human domination of human gave

rise to the very *idea* of dominating nature.

In emphasizing that human domination precedes the notion of

dominating nature, I have carefully avoided the use of a slippery verb

that is very much in use today: namely, that the domination of nature

“involves” the domination of human by human. I find the use of this

verb particularly repellent because it confuses the order in which

domination emerged in the world and, hence, the extent to which it must

be eliminated if we are to achieve a free society. Men did not think of

dominating nature until they had already begun to dominate the young,

women, and, eventually, each other. And it is not until we eliminate

domination in all its forms, as we shall see, that we will really create a

rational, ecological society.

However much the writings of liberals and Marx convey the belief

that attempts to dominate nature “led” to the domination of human by

human, no such “project” ever existed in the annals of what we call

“history.” At no time in the history of humanity did the oppressed of

any period joyfully accede to their oppression in a starry-eyed belief

that their misery would ultimately confer a state of blissful freedom

from the “domination of nature” to their descendants in some future

era.

To take issue, as social ecology does, with words like “involve” or

“led” is not a form of medieval casuistry. On the contrary, the way these

words are used raises issues of radical differences in the interpretation

of history and the problems that lie before us.

Domination of human by human did not arise because people

created a socially oppressive “mechanism” — be it Marx’s class

structures or Lewis Mumford’s human-constructed “mega-machine”

in order to “free” themselves from the “domination by nature.” It is

exactly this very queasy idea that gave rise to the myth that the

domination of nature “requires,” “presupposes,” or “involves” the

domination of human by human.

Implied in this basically reactionary myth is the notion that forms

of domination, like classes and the State, have their sources in economic

conditions and needs; indeed, that freedom can only be attained after

the “domination of nature” has been achieved, with the resulting

establishment of a classless society. Hierarchy somehow seems to

disappear here in a shuffle of vague ideas or it is subsumed under the

goal of abolishing classes, as though a classless society were necessarily one that is free of hierarchy. If we are to accept Engel’s view, and to

some degree Marx’s, in fact, hierarchy in some form is “unavoidable”

in an industrial society and even under communism. There is a surprising agreement between liberals, conservatives, and many socialists, as

I have already noted, that hierarchy is unavoidable for the very existence of social life, and is an infrastructure for its organization and stability.

In contending that the notion of dominating nature *stems* from the

domination of human by human, social ecology radically reverses the

equation of human oppression and broadens its scope enormously. It

tries to search into institutionalized systems of coercion, command, and

obedience that preceded the emergence of economic classes, and that

are not necessarily economically motivated at all. The “social question”

of inequality and oppression that has plagued us for centuries is thereby

extended by social ecology well beyond economic forms of exploitation into cultural forms of domination that exist in the family, between

generations and sexes, among ethnic groups, in institutions of political,

economic, and social management, and very significantly, in the way

we experience reality as a whole, including nature and nonhuman

life-forms.

In short, social ecology raises the issue of command and obedience

in personal, social, historical, and reconstructive terms on a scale that

encompasses, but goes far beyond, the more restricted economic interpretations of the “social question” that are prevalent today. Social

ecology extends, as we shall see, the “social question” beyond the

limited realm of justice into the unbounded realm of freedom; beyond

a domineering rationality, science, and technology into libertarian

ones; and beyond visions of social reform into those of radical social

reconstruction.

Early Human Communities

We, of this era, are still victims of our own recent history. Modern

capitalism, the most unique, as well as the most pernicious, social order

to emerge in the course of human history, identifies human progress

with bitter competition and rivalry; social status with the rapacious and

limitless accumulation of wealth; the most personal values with greed

and selfishness; the production of commodities, of goods explicitly

made for sale and profit, as the motive force of nearly every economic

and artistic endeavour; and profit and enrichment as the reason for the

existence of social life.

No society known to history has made these factors so central to its

existence or, worse, identified them with “human nature” as such.

Every vice that, in earlier times, was seen as the apotheosis of evil has

been turned into a “virtue” by capitalist society.

So deeply ingrained are these bourgeois attributes of our everyday

lives and ways of thinking that we find it difficult to understand how

much precapitalist societies held to the very opposite images of human

values, however much they may have been honoured in the breach. It

is hard for the modern mind to appreciate that precapitalist societies

identified social excellence with cooperation rather than competition

disaccumulation rather than accumulation; public service rather that

private interest; the giving of gifts rather than the sale of commodities,

and care and mutual aid rather than profit and rivalry.

These values were identified with an uncorrupted human nature. Ii

many respects, they are still a part of a caring socialization process it

our own lives that tends to foster interdependence, not an aggressive

self-serving “independence” we call “rugged individualism.” To understand from whence we came socially and how we came to be where

we are, it is necessary to peel away our present system of values and

examine, however summarily, a body of ideas that provide a clearer

picture of a more organic, indeed, an ecological society that emerged

from the natural world.

This organic, basically preliterate or “tribal,” society was strikingly

nondomineering — not only in its institutionalized structure but in its

very language. If the linguistic analyses of anthropologists like the late

Dorothy Lee are sound, Indian communities like the Wintu of the

Pacific Coast lacked transitive verbs like “to have,” “to take,” and “to

own” which denote power over individuals and objects. Rather, a

mother “went” with her child into the shade, a chief “stood” with his

people, and, more commonly, people “lived with” objects rather than

“possessed” them.

However much these communities may have differed from each

other in many social respects, we hear in their language, and detect in

their behavioural traits, attitudes that go back to a shared body of

beliefs, values, and basic lifeways. As Paul Radin, one of Americas

most gifted anthropologists, observed, there was a basic sense of

respect between individuals and a concern over their material needs

that Radin called the principle of the “irreducible minimum.” Everyone

was entitled to the means of life, irrespective of his or her productive

contribution. The right to live went unquestioned so that concepts like

“equality” had no meaning if only because the “inequalities” that afflict

us all — from the burdens of age to the incapacities of ill-health — had

to be compensated for by the community.

Early notions of formal “equality,” in which we are all “equally”

free to starve or die of neglect, had yet to replace the *substantive*

equality in which those less able to be fully productive were nevertheless reasonably well provided for. Equality thus existed, as Dorothy Lee

tells us, “in the very nature of things, as a by-product of the democratic

structure of the culture itself, not as a principle to be supplied”[6] There

was no need in these organic societies to “achieve” equality, for what

existed was an absolute respect for man, for all individuals apart from

any personal traits.

This broad appraisal by Lee was to be echoed by Radin, who for

decades had lived among the Winnebago Indians and enjoyed their full

confidence:

If I were asked to state briefly and succinctly what are the
outstanding features of aboriginal civilization, I, for one,
would have no hesitation in answering that there are three: the
respect for the individual, irrespective of age or sex; the
amazing degree of social and political integration achieved by
them; and the existence of a personal security which
transcends all governmental forms and all tribal and group
interests and conflicts. [7]

The respect for the individual, which Radin lists first as an aboriginal

attribute, deserves to be emphasized, today, in an era that rejects the

collective as destructive of individuality on the one hand, and, yet, in

an orgy of pure egotism, has actually destroyed all the ego boundaries

of free-floating, isolated, and atomized individuals on the other hand.

A strong collectivity may be even more supportive of the individual,

as close studies of certain aboriginal societies reveal, than a “free

market” society with emphasis on an egoistic, but impoverished, self.

No less striking than the substantive equality achieved by many

organic societies was the extent to which their sense of communal

harmony was also projected onto the natural world as a whole. In the

absence of any hierarchical social structures, the aboriginal vision of

nature was also strikingly nonhierarchical. Accounts of many

aboriginal ceremonies among hunting and horticultural communities

leave us with the strong impression that the participant saw themselves

as part of a larger world of life. Dances seemed to resemble simulations

of nature, particularly animals, rather than human attempts to coerce

nature, be it game or forces like rainfall.

Magic, which the last century called the “primitive man’s science,”

apparently had a twofold aspect to it. One of these aspects seems to

have been recognizably “coercive” in the sense that a given ritual was

expected to necessarily produce a given effect. This kind of magic,

presumably, had its own form of hard “causality,” not unlike what we

would expect to find in chemistry.

However, as I have suggested elsewhere, there were rituals —

especially group rituals — that may have preceded in time the more

familiar, cause-effect magical activities; rituals that were not coercive,

but rather *persuasive*. Wildlife was seen in a complementary relationship of “give-and-take” in which game gave of itself to the hunter as a

participant in the broad orbit of life — an orbit based on propitiation,

respect, and mutual need. Humanity was no less a part than animals in

this complementary orbit in which human and nonhuman were seen to

give of themselves to each other according to mutual need rather than

“trade-offs.” [8]

This high sense of complementarity in rituals apparently reflected

an active sense of social equality that viewed personal differences as

parts of a larger natural whole rather than a pyramid-structured hierarchy of being. The attempt of organic society to place human beings in

the same community on a par with each other, to see in each an

interactive partner with others, yielded a highly egalitarian notion of

difference as such.

Which is not to say that aboriginal people regarded themselves as

“equal” to nonhuman creatures. In fact, they were acutely aware of the

inequalities that existed in nature and society, inequalities created by

differences in physical prowess, age, intelligence, genetic attributes,

infirmities, and the like. Tribal peoples tried to compensate for these

inequalities within their own groups, hence the emergence of an “irreducible minimum,” as Radin called it, that gave every member of the

community access to the means of life, irrespective of his or her abilities

or contribution to the common fund. Often, special “privileges were

allowed to individuals who were burdened by infirmities to equalize

their situations with respect to more endowed members of the community.

But in no sense did aboriginal people equate themselves with

animals. They did not act or think “biocentrically,” “eco-centrically”

(to use words that have recently come into vogue), or, for that matter,

“anthropocentrically” in dealing with nonhuman life-forms. It would

be more accurate to say that they had no sense of “centricity” as such,

except toward their own communities. The belief held by a tribe that it

was “The People,” as distinguished from outsiders or other communities, was a parochial weakness of tribal societies as a whole and

generally made for fear of strangers, wars, and a self-enclosed mentality

that the emergence of cities began to overcome. Indeed, until territorial

ways of living that appear with cities began to replace loyalties based

on blood ties, the notion of a common humanity was vague indeed, and

tribalism remained very restrictive in its view of outsiders and

strangers.

In this inner world of substantive equality, land and those “resources” our present society denotes as “property ” were available to

everyone in the community for use, at least to the extent that they were

needed. But in principle, such “resources” could not be “possessed” in

any personal sense, much less “owned” as property. Thus, in addition

to the principles of the “irreducible minimum,” substantive equality,

the arts of persuasion, and a conception of differentiation as complementarity, organic preliterate societies seem to have been guided by

a commitment to *usufruct*. Things were available to individuals and

families of a community because they were needed, not because they

were owned or created by the labour of a possessor.

The substantive equality of organic preliterate communities was not

only the product of institutional structures and ancestral custom. It

entered into the very sensibility of the individual: the way he or she

perceived differences, other human beings, nonhuman life, material

objects, land and forests, indeed, the natural world as a whole. Nature

and society, which are so sharply divided against each other in our

society and or sensibilities, were thereby slowly graded into each other

as a shared continuum of interaction and everyday experience.

Needless to say, neither humanity “mastered” nature nor did nature

“master” humanity. Quite to the contrary: nature was seen as a fecund

source of life, well-being, indeed, a providential parent of humanity,

not a “stingy” or “withholding” taskmaster that had to be coerced into

yielding the means of life and its hidden “secrets” to a Faustian man.

An image of nature as “stingy” would have produced “stingy” communities and self-seeking human participants.

This nature was anything but the relatively lifeless phenomenon it

has become in our era — the object of laboratory research and the

“matter” of technical manipulation. It consisted of wildlife that, in the

aboriginal mind, was structured along kinship lines like human clans;

forests, that were seen as a caring haven; and cosmic forces, like winds,

torrential rainfall, a blazing sun, and a benign moon. Nature literally

permeated the community not only as a providential environment, but

as the blood flow of the kinship tie that united human to human and

generation to generation.

The loyalty of kin to each other in the form of the blood oath — an

oath that combined an expression of duty to one’s relatives with

vengeance for their offenders — became the organic source of communal continuity. Fictitious as this source would eventually become,

especially in more recent times when the word “kin” has become a

tenuous surrogate for authentic kinship ties, there is little reason to

doubt its viability as a means for establishing one’s place in early human

communities. It was one’s affiliations by blood, be it because of a

shared ancestry or shared offspring, that determined whether an individual was an accepted part of a group, who he or she could marry,

the responsibility he or she had to others, as well as the responsibility

he or she had to him or her — indeed, the whole array of rights and

duties that a community’s members had in relation to each other.

It was on the basis of this biological fact of blood ties that nature

penetrated the most basic institutions of preliterate society. The continuity of the blood tie was literally a means of *defining* social association and even self-identity. Whether one belonged to a given group or

not, and who one was, in relation to others, was determined, at least

juridically, by one’s blood affiliations.

But still another biological fact defined one as a member of a

community: whether one was a male or female. Unlike the kinship tie,

which was to be slowly thinned out as distinctly nonbiological institutions like the State were gradually to encroach on the claims of

genealogy and paternity, the sexual structuring of society has remained

with us to this day, however much it has been modified by social

development.

Lastly, a third biological fact defined one as a member of a group,

namely, one’s age. As we shall see, the earliest truly social examples

of status based on biological differences were essentially the age-groups to which one belonged and the ceremonies that legitimated

one’s age-status. Kinship established the basic fact that one shared a

common ancestry with members of a given community. It defined one’s

rights and responsibilities to others of the same bloodline—rights and

responsibilities that might involve who one could marry of a particular

genealogical group, who was to be aided and supported in the normal

demands of life, and who one could turn to for aid in difficulties of any

kind. The bloodline literally gave definition to an individual and a

group, much as skin forms the boundary that distinguishes one person

from another.

Sexual differences, also biological in origin, defined the kind of

work one did in the community and the role of a parent in rearing the

young. Women essentially gathered and prepared food; men hunted

animals and assumed a protective role for the community as a whole.

These basically different tasks also gave rise to sororal and fraternal

cultures in which women developed associations, whether informal or

structured, and engaged in ceremonies and revered deities that were

dissimilar from those of men, who had a culture very much of their

own.

But none of these gender differences—not to mention genealogical

ones — initially conferred a commanding position on one member of

a sexual group or an obedient one on another. Women exercised full

control over the domestic world: the home, family hearth, and the

preparation of the most immediate means of life such as skins and food.

Often, a woman built her own shelter and tended to her own garden as

society advanced toward a horticultural economy.

Men, in turn, dealt with what we might call “civil” affairs — the

administration of the nascent, barely developed “political” affairs of

the Community such as relations between bands, clans, tribes, and

intercommunal hostilities. Later, as we shall see, these “civil” affairs

became highly elaborate as population movements brought communities into conflict with each other. Warrior fraternities began to

emerge within early societies that ultimately specialized in hunting men

as well as animals.

What is reasonably clear is that in early phases of social development, woman’s and man’s cultures complemented each other and

conjointly fostered social stability as well as provided the means of life

for the community as a whole. The two cultures were not in conflict

with each other. Indeed, it is doubtful that an early human community

could have survived if gender-oriented cultures initially tried to exercise any commanding position, much less an antagonistic one, over the

other. The stability of the community required a respectful balance

between potentially hostile elements if the community was to survive

in a fairly precarious environment.

Today, it is largely because “civil” or, if you like, “political” affairs

are so important in our own society that we read back into the preliterate

world a “commanding” role among men in their monopoly of “civil”

affairs. We easily forget that early human communities were really

domestic societies, structured mainly around the work of women, and

were often strongly oriented in reality, as well as mythology, toward

woman’s world.

Age groups, however, have more ambiguous social implications.

Physically, the old people of a community were the most infirm,

dependent, and often the most vulnerable members of the group in

periods of difficulty. It was they who were expected to give up their

lives in times of want that threatened the existence of a community.

Hence, they were its most insecure members — psychologically as well

as physically.

At the same time, the old people of a community were the living

repositories of its lore, traditions, knowledge, and collective experience. In a world that had no written language, they were the

custodians of its identity and history. In the tension between extreme

personal vulnerability on the one hand and the embodiment of the

community’s traditions on the other hand, they may have been more

disposed to enhance their status, to surround it with a quasi-religious

aura and a social power, as it were, that rendered them more secure with

the loss of their physical power.

The Emergence of Hierarchies and Classes

The logical beginnings of hierarchy, as well as a good deal of

anthropological data at our disposal, suggest that hierarchy stems from

the ascendancy of the elders, who seem to have initiated the earliest

institutionalized systems of command and obedience. This system of

rule by the elders, benign as it may have been initially, has been

designated as a “gerontocracy” and it often included old women as well

as old men. We detect evidence of its basic, probably primary, role in

virtually all existing societies up to recent times—be it as councils of

elders that were adapted to clan, tribal, urban and state forms, or, for

that matter, in such striking cultural features as ancestor-worship and

an etiquette of deference to older people in many different kinds of

societies.

The rise of growing male power in society did not necessarily

remove old women from high-status positions in this earliest of all

hierarchies. Biblical figures like Sara had a distinctly authoritative and

commanding voice in public as well as domestic affairs, even in the

patriarchal and polygamous family of Hebrew bedouins. In reality, Sara

is not an atypical figure in explicitly patriarchal families; indeed, in

many traditional societies, once a woman aged beyond the child-bearing years of her life, she often acquired the status of what has been

called a “matriarch” who enjoyed enormous influence within the community at large, at times even exceeding that of older males.

But even an early gerontocracy has a somewhat egalitarian dimension. If one lives long enough, one may eventually become an “elder”

in an honorific sense, or, for that matter, a domineering “patriarch” and

even a “matriarch.” Hierarchy in this early form seems to be less

structurally rigid because of a kind of biological “upward mobility.” Its

existence is still consistent with the egalitarian spirit of early communal

societies.

The situation changes, however, when the biological facts that

initially underpin early communal life become increasingly social —

that is to say, when society comes increasingly into its own and

transforms the form and content of relationships within and between

social groups. It is important to emphasize that the biological facts that

enter into the blood relationship, gender differences, and age-groups

do not simply disappear once society begins to acquire its own self-generative forces of development. Nature is deeply interwoven with

many of these social changes. But the natural dimension of society is

modified, complicated, and altered by the socialization of the biological

facts that exist in social life at all times.

Consider one of the major shifts in early societies that was to

profoundly influence social evolution: the growing authority of men

over women. By no means is it clear that the hierarchical supremacy of

males was the first or necessarily the most inflexible system of hierarchy to corrode the egalitarian structures of early human society. Gerontocracy probably preceded “patricentricity,” the orientation of society

toward male values, or (in its most exaggerated form) “patriarchal”

hierarchies. Indeed, what often passes for Biblical types of patriarchy

are patricentric modifications of gerontocracy in which *all* younger

members of the family — male as well as female — are under the

complete rule of the oldest male and often his oldest female consort,

the so-called matriarch.

That males are born into a special status in relationship to females

becomes an obvious social fact. But it also rests on biological facts that

are reworked for distinct social ends. Males are physically larger, more muscular, and normally possessed of great hemoglobin, within the same ethnic group, than females. I am obliged to add that they produce

significantly greater quantities of testosterone than females — an

androgen that not only stimulates the synthesis of protein and produces

a greater musculature, but also fosters behavioural traits that we associate with a high degree of physical dynamism. To deny these

evolutionary adaptations, which provide males with greater athleticism

in the hunting of game and, later, of people, by invoking individual

exceptions to these male traits is to simply overlook important biological facts.

None of these factors and traits need yield the subordination of

females to males. Nor is it likely that they did so. Certainly, male

domination served no function when woman’s role was so central to

the stability of the early human community. Attempts to institutionalize

the subordination of women, given their own rich cultural domain and

their decisive role in maintaining the community, would have been

utterly destructive to intragroup harmony. Indeed, the very idea of

domination, not to mention hierarchy, had yet to emerge in early human

communities that were socialized into the values of the irreducible

minimum, complementarity, substantive equality, and usufruct. These

values were not simply a moral credo; they were part of an all-encompassing sensibility that embraced the nonhuman as well as the

human world.

Yet we know that men began to dominate women and began to give

primacy to their “civil” over woman’s “domestic” culture. That this

occurred in a very shadowy and uncertain fashion is a problem that has

not received the careful attention it deserves. The two cultures—male

and female — retained a considerable distance from each other well

into history, even as the male seemed to move to the social forefront in

nearly every field of endeavour. There is a sense in which male “civil”

affairs simply upstaged female “domestic” affairs without fully supplanting them. We have many ceremonies in tribal societies in which

women seem to bestow powers on men that the men do not really have,

such as ceremonial re-enactments of the ability to give birth.

But as “civil” society became more problematic because of invaders,

intercommunal strife, and finally, systematic warfare, the male world

became more assertive and agonistic — traits that are likely to make

male anthropologists give the “civil” sphere greater prominence in their

literature, especially if they have no meaningful contact with the

women of a preliterate community. That women often mocked male

bellicosity and lived full lives of their own in very close personal

relationships, seems to wane to the footnote level in most accounts by

male anthropologists. The “men’s hut” stood actively opposed to the

woman’s home, where the everyday domain of child-rearing, food

preparation, and an intensely familial social life remained almost

unnoticed by male anthropologists, although it was psychologically

pivotal to the sullen men of a community. Indeed, sororal life retained

an amazing vitality and exuberance long after the emergence of urban

societies. Women’s talk, however, was deprecated as “gossip” and their

work was called “menial” even in Euro-American societies.

Ironically, the degradation of women, itself always variable and

often inconsistent, appears when males form hierarchies among themselves, as Janet Biehl has so ably shown in her splendid work on

hierarchy. [9] With increasing intercommunal conflicts, systematic warfare, and institutionalized violence, “civil” problems became chronic.

They demanded greater resources, the mobilization of men, and they

placed demands on woman’s domain for material resources.

Out of the skin of the most able hunter emerged a new kind of

creature: the “big man,” who was also a “great warrior.” Slowly, every

domain of preliterate society was reoriented toward maintaining his

heightened “civil” functions. The blood oath, based on kinship loyalties, was gradually replaced by oaths of fealty by his soldierly “companions” who were drawn from clans other than his own, indeed, from

solitary strangers, thereby cutting across traditional bloodlines and their

sanctity. “Lesser men” appeared who were obliged to craft his weapons,

provide for his sustenance, build and adorn his dwellings, and finally,

erect his fortifications and monumentalize his achievements with impressive palaces and burial sites.

Even woman’s world, with its secretive underpinnings, was

reshaped, to a lesser or greater degree, in order to support him with

young soldiers or able serfs, clothing to adorn him, concubines to

indulge his pleasures, and, with the growth of female aristocracies,

heroes and heirs to bear his name into the future. All the servile plaudits

to his great stature, that are commonly seen as signs of feminine

weakness, emerged, throwing into sharp contrast and prominence a

cultural ensemble based on masculine strength.

Servility to male chiefs, warriors, and kings was not simply a

condition imposed by warriors on women. Side by side with the servile

woman is the unchanging image of the servile man, whose back

provides a footrest for arrogant monarchs and demeaning capitalists.

The humiliation of man by man began early on in the “men’s hut,” when

cowering boys lived on a diet of mockery for their inexperience at the

hands of adult males; and “small men” lived on a diet of disdain for

their limited accomplishments by comparison with those of “big men.”

Hierarchy, which first rears its head tentatively with gerontocracies,

did not suddenly explode into prehistory. It expanded its place slowly,

cautiously, and often unnoticeably, by an almost metabolic form of

growth when “big men” began to dominate “small men,” when warriors

and their “companions” began to gradually dominate their followers,

when chiefs began to dominate the community, and finally, when

nobles began to dominate peasants and serfs.

By the same token, the “civil” sphere of the male began to slowly

encroach upon the “domestic” sphere of the female. By degrees, it

placed the female world increasingly in the service of the male, without

destroying it. The sororal world, far from disappearing, took on a

hidden form, indeed, a confidential form, that women shared with each

other behind the backs of men, as they confronted new “civil” relationships created by males.

Hence, in gender relationships as well as in intramale relationships,

there was no sudden leap from the sexual egalitarianism of early

preliterate societies to male “priority.” Indeed, it would be quite impossible, as Biehl has pointed out, to divorce the domination of woman by

man from the domination of man by man. The two always interacted

dialectically to reinforce each other with attitudes of command and

obedience that gradually permeated society as a whole, even producing

hierarchies of a more unstable nature among women. At the bottom of

every social ladder always stood the resident outsider — male or female

— and the assortment of war captives who, with economic changes,

became a very sizeable population of slaves.

The transition from a largely “domestic” to a largely “civil” society

was also conditioned by many less noticeable, but very important,

factors. Long before domination became rigorously institutionalized,

gerontocracy had already created a state of mind that was structured

around the power of elders to command and the obligation of the young

to obey. This state of mind went far beyond the indispensable care and

attention required for the instruction of children and youths in the arts

of survival. In many preliterate communities, elders acquired major

decision-making powers that dealt with marriage, group ceremonies,

decisions about war, and intracommunal squabbles between persons

and clans. This state of mind, or, if you like, conditioning, was a

troubling presence that presaged even greater troubles as hierarchy

generally extended itself over society.

But hierarchy even in early societies was still further reinforced by

shamans and, later, by shamanistic guilds that gained prestige and

privileges by virtue of their very uncertain monopoly over magical

practices. Be they “primitive man’s science” or not, the arts of the

shaman were naive at best and fraudulent at worst — and more often

the latter than the former, present-day culls, covens, and pop-literature

on the subject to the contrary notwithstanding. Repeated failures by

shamans in their use of magical techniques could be fatal, not only to

a troubled community or a sick person. Their failure could be dangerous

to the shaman as well, who might just as well be speared as exiled in

disgrace.

Hence, as Paul Radin notes in his excellent discussion of West

African shamans, shamanisdc guilds always sought influential allies

who could buffer them from popular anger and incredulity. Such allies

were often elders who felt insecure as a result of their own failing

powers or rising chiefs who were in need of ideological legitimation

from the spirit world. [10]

Still another refinement of hierarchy was the transition from the “big

man’s” status — whose prestige depended as much on his distribution

of gifts as it did upon his prowess as a hunter — to the status of a

hereditary chief. Here, we witness the remarkable transmutation of a

“big man,” who must actively earn public admiration with impressive

actions of all kinds, into a wise chiefly advisor, who commands respect

without any prerogative of power, and finally, into a quasi-monarchical

figure who evokes fear, be it because of his considerable entourage of

armed “companions,” his status as a demi-god with supernatural

powers of his own, or both.

This graded development of a “big man” into an outright autocrat

was leavened by basic alterations in the kinship bond and its importance. The kinship bond is surprisingly egalitarian when it is not twisted

out of shape. It evokes a simple sense of loyalty, responsibility, mutual

respect, and mutual aid. It rests on the *moral* strength of a shared sense

of ancestry, on the belief that we are all “brothers” and “sisters,”

however fictitious these ancestral ties may become in reality — not on

the basis of material interest, power, fear, or coercion.

The “big man,” chief, and finally, the autocrat undermines this

essentially egalitarian bond. He may do so by asserting the supremacy

of his own kin group over other ones, in which case an entire clan may

acquire a royal or dynastic status in relations to other clans in the

community. Or he may bypass his own kinspeople entirely and adopt

“companions,” be they warriors, retainers, and the like, who are drawn

into his fold exclusively on the basis of their own prowess and fealty

without any regard to blood affiliations.

This is a highly corrosive process. A new kind of “person” is created

again: a person who is neither a member of the “big man’s” kin group

or. for that matter, a member of the community. Like the mercenaries

of the Renaissance or even classical antiquity, he is a “companion,”

with other companions like himself, who collects into a military “company” that has no social loyalties or traditions.

Such “companies” can easily be set against the community or reared

above it into a coercive monarchy and aristocracy. Gilgamesh in the

famous Sumerian epic adopted Enkidu, a total stranger, as his “companion,” thereby challenging the integrity of the entire kinship system

as a form of social cement and undermining its complex network of

commitments that were so essential to the egalitarian values of

preliterate society.

What I would like to emphasize is how much hierarchical differentiation simply reworked existing relationships in early society into a

system of status long before the strictly economic relationship we call

“classes” emerged Age status merged with changes in gender status;

“domestic” society was placed in the service of “civil” society;

shamanistic guilds networked with gerontocracies and warrior groups;

and warrior groups reworked kinship ties, ultimately reducing tribal

blood communities to territorial communities based on residence rather

than blood ties and composed of peasants, serfs, and slaves.

Our present era is the heir to this vast reworking of differentiation

of humanity — not only along class lines but, much earlier in time, into

hierarchies in which class systems were incubated. These hierarchies

still form the fertile ground in our own time for the existence of hidden

oppressions by age groups, of women by men, and of men by men —

indeed, a vast landscape of domination that also gives rise in great part

to largely exploitative economic systems based on classes.

Only later was this immense system of social domination extended

into the notion of dominating nature by “humanity.” No ecological

society, however communal or benign in its ideals, can ever remove

the “goal” of dominating the natural world until it has radically

eliminated the domination of human by human, or, in essence, the entire

hierarchical structure within society in which the very notion of

domination rests. Such an ecological society must reach into the overlaid muck of hierarchy—a muck that oozes out from fissures in family

relationships that exist between generations and genders, churches and

schools, friendships and lovers, exploiters and exploited, and hierarchical sensibilities toward the entire world of life.

To recover and go beyond the nonhierarchical world that once

formed human society and its values of the irreducible minimum,

complementarity, and usufruct, is an agenda that belongs to the closing

portions of this book. It suffices, here, to bear in mind that social

ecology has made the understanding of hierarchy — its rise, scope, and

impact — the centrepiece of its message of a liberating, rational, and

ecological society. Any agenda that contains less than these imperatives

is obscure at best and grossly misleading at worst.

At the risk of repetition, let me emphasize that the word hierarchy

should be viewed strictly as a *social* term. To extend this term to cover

all forms of coercion is to permanently root consciously organized and

institutionalized systems of command and obedience in nature and give

it an aura of eternality that is comparable only to the genetic programming of a “social” insect. We have more to learn from the fate of our

own royal figures in human history that from the behaviour of “queen

bees” in beehives.

Figures like Louis XVI of France and Nicholas II of Russia, for

example, did not become autocrats because they had genetically

programmed strong personalities and physiques, much less keen minds.

They were inept, awkward, psychologically weak, and conspicuously

stupid men (even according to royalist accounts of their reigns) who

lived in times of revolutionary social upheaval. Yet their power was

virtually absolute until it was curtailed by revolution.

What gave them the enormous power they enjoyed? Their power

can only be explained by the rise of humanly contrived and supportive

institutions like bureaucracies, armies, police, legal codes and

judiciaries that consciously favoured absolutism, and a far-flung, and

largely servile. Church that itself was structured along highly hierarchical lines— in short, a vast, deeply entrenched institutional apparatus

that had been in the making for centuries and was overthrown in

revolutionary upheavals in a matter of weeks. Apart from genetically

programmed insects, we have absolutely no equivalent of such hierarchies in the nonhuman world. Remove the word “hierarchy” from its

social context in human life and we create the utmost confusion in

trying to understand its origins in our midst and the means for removing

it — a social capacity, I may add, that we alone, as human beings,

possess.

By the same token, the word “domination” should be viewed strictly

as a *social* term if we are not to lose sight of its various institutionalized

forms — forms that are unique to human beings. Animals certainly do

coerce each other, usually as individuals, occasionally even as small

“gangs” that presumably demand access to seeming “privileges,” (a

word which can also be stretched beyond all recognition if we examine

“privilege” comparatively, as it exists from one species to another.)

But not only is this “domineering” behaviour associated with one or

a few individual animals; it is highly tentative, often episodic, informal,

and among apes in particular, highly diffuse. The “privileges” our

closest animal relatives claim are very different from one species to

another, even one group to another. Lasting institutions like armies,

police, and even criminal groups, do not exist in the animal world.

Where they seem to exist, as among “soldiers” in insects like ants, they

are examples of genetically programmed behaviour, not socially contrived institutions open to radical change by rebellion.

It is tempting to ask *why* such coercive social institutions, indeed,

status systems and hierarchies, arose among human beings in the first

place, not only *how* they arose. In other words, what were the *causes*

that gave rise to institutionalized dominance and submission apart from

descriptions of their emergence and development?

Status, as I have already pointed out, appeared between age-groups,

albeit in an initially benign form. Hence, a psycho-social setting of

deference to the elderly was already present in early society even before

older generations began to claim very real privileges from younger

ones. I’ve cited the infirmities and insecurities aging produces in the

elderly and their capacity to bring their greater experience and

knowledge to the service of their increasing status.

Their gerontocracies present no real mystery as a source of status-**consciousness**. That age-hierarchies would appear is often merely a

matter of time: the socialization process with its need for careful

instruction, growing knowledge, and an increasing reservoir of experience virtually guarantees that elders would earn a justifiable degree

of respect and, in precarious situations, seek a certain amount of power.

The most challenging form of social status, however, is probably the

power that “big men” I gained and concentrated, initially in their own

persons, later in their increasingly institutionalized “companies” Here,

we encounter a very subtle and complex dialectic. “Big men” were

notable, as we have seen, for their generosity, not only for their prowess.

Their ceremonial distribution of gifts to people — a system for the

redistribution of wealth that acquired highly neurotic traits in the

potlatch ceremonies of the Northwest Indians, where bitter contests

between “big men” led to an orgiastic “disaccumulation” of everything

they owned in order to “accumulate” prestige within the community —

may have had very benign origins. To be generous and giving was a

social etiquette that promoted the unity, and contributed to the very

survival, of the early human community.

Given time and the likely susceptibility of men to seek communal

approval, a susceptibility that was rooted in their sense of “manliness”

and the community’s respect for their physical prowess, it is likely that

“bigness” meant little more than generosity and a high regard for skill

and courage. These would have been attributes that *any* preliterate

community would have prized in a male, just as women had many

different skills that were deeply valued. This kind of “bigness,” as

potlatch ceremonies suggest, could have easily become reified as an

end in itself. Or, as in certain communities like the Hopi, by contrast,

it could be seen as socially disruptive because of its strident individuality, and thus, it was sharply curtailed. Accordingly, when

Euro-American “educators” of the Hopi tried to teach Hopi children to

play competitive sports, they had immense difficulties in getting the

children to keep scores. Hopi custom discouraged rivalry and selfassertiveness as harmful to community solidarity.

Everywhere along the way, in effect, conflicting alternatives confronted each community as potential hierarchies began to appear, first,

as gerontocracies, later, as individual “big men” and warrior groups.

Such potential hierarchies could have been developed very much on

their own momentum, initially with very little divisive effects on the

community, or they could have been sharply curtailed even after they

began to appear. There is evidence to show that such opposing tendencies appeared in many different preliterate communities, either advancing into full-blown hierarchies or being arrested at various levels of development, when they were not simply pushed back to a more

egalitarian condition.

In fact, custom, socialization, and basic precepts like the irreducible

minimum, complementarity, and usufruct, might very well have tended

to favour the *curtailment* of hierarchy rather than its cultivation. This

is evident in the large number of human communities that existed well

into Euro-American history with little or no hierarchical institutions.

Only a surprisingly small part of humanity developed societies that

were structured overwhelmingly around hierarchies, classes, and the

State. Perhaps a majority avoided in varying degrees this dark path of

social development or, at least, entered onto it to a limited extent.

But one fact should be clearly noted: a community that does develop

along hierarchical, class, and statist lines has a profound impact upon

all the communities around it that continue to follow an egalitarian

direction. A warrior community led by an aggressive chiefdom compels

highly pacific neighbouring communities to create their own military

formations and chiefs if they are to survive. An entire region may thus

be drastically changed —culturally, morally, and institutionally —

merely as a result of aggressive hierarchies in a single community.

We can trace this clearly by studying one community’s grave sites

in the Andes which was initially free of weapons and distinctive

status-oriented ornaments, only to find that these sites began to exhibit

warrior and prestige artifacts at a later level of development. Actually,

this change could be attributed to the emergence of a neighbouring

community that had embarked upon an aggressive, warrior-oriented

social development earlier in time, thereby profoundly affecting the

internal life of more peaceful communities which surrounded it. So it

may have been in many parts of the world, each one in isolation from

the others.

No less striking is the evidence we find of changes in American

Indian societies from highly centralized, war-like, and quasi-statist

“empires” to decentralized, fairly pacific, and relatively nonhierarchical communities. In their centralistic and militaristic phases, these

“empires” apparently became so top-heavy, exploitative, and exhausting to the communities they controlled that they either collapsed under

their own weight or were simply overthrown by local rebellions. The

Indian mound-builders of the American midwest or the Mayans of

Mexico may very well have embarked on a vigorous militaristic expansion, only to disappear when they could no longer sustain themselves

or retain the obedience of subject populations. This historic see-saw of

communal institutions between centralization and decentralization,

warrior and peaceful communities, expansive and contractive societies,

all appeared in the West as well until the rise of the nation-state in

Europe during the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries.

In so far as women were reduced to the spectators of the intracommunity changes that gave rise to hierarchy, they were not significant

participants in its development. Victimized as they were, they shared

with the lower strata of male hierarchies an oppression and degradation

that all ruling elites inflicted on their underlings. Men not only

degraded, oppressed, and often used women as objects; they also

oppressed and killed other men in an orgy of slaughtering and cruelty.

The early kingdoms of the Near East were reluctant to keep male

prisoners of war because they were regarded as potentially too rebellious, so they were normally put to death rather than enslaved. When

male slaves began to appear in large numbers, they were often exploited

ruthlessly and were treated, especially in mines and large-scale agriculture, with appalling ruthlessness, Male physical strength became a

liability, not an asset, when it was used for exploitative purposes.

The causes of hierarchy, then, are not a mystery. They are quite

comprehensible when we dig into their roots in the more mundane

aspects of daily life such as the family, the rearing of young people, the

segmentation of society in to age-groups, the expectations that are

placed on the individual as a male or female in the everyday domestic

or “civil” worlds, and in the most personal aspects of acculturation as

well as community ceremonies. And hierarchy will not disappear until

we change these roots of daily life radically, not only economically,

with the removal of class society.

Not only did hierarchies precede classes, but, as Biehl has shown,

male domination over other males generally preceded the domination

of women. Women became the degraded bystanders of a male-oriented

civilization that reared itself up beside woman’s own culture, corroded

it, and established systematic ways of manipulating it When men tried

to absorb woman’s culture, they warped it and subordinated it — but

they succeeded in only a limited degree. Sororal relationships, affections, and lifeways continued behind the backs of men and often outside

the range of their vision in the secret alcoves of history, as it were.

Men, in turn, were often the objects of ridicule to women, even in

cultures that were overbearingly patriarchal. Nor did women always

aspire to participate in a “civil” society that was even more brutal to

men than to domestic animals. Let us not forget that it was not oxen

that dragged huge blocks of stone up the ramparts of the great pyramids

of ancient Egypt, but usually male serfs and slaves, who were regarded

as more expendable than cattle.

The Emergence of the State

The institutionalized apex of male civilization was the State. Here,

again, we find a tricky dialectic which, if we ignore its subtleties, can

lead us into very simplistic discussions of state formation in which state

institutions suddenly erupt into history, fully grown and overtly coercive. Indeed, such eruptions of states, from seemingly “democratic” to

highly “authoritarian” institutions, are more of a modern than a

premodern phenomenon, notably the sudden substitution of republican

by totalitarian states. Except in periods of invasions, when alien aristocracies were rapidly imposed on relatively egalitarian communities,

rapid changes in state institutions were a comparative rarity. Unless we

consider how the State began to emerge, how far it developed, and how

stable it was, we encounter many difficulties even in defining the State,

much less in exploring the forms it took in different societies.

Minimally, the State is a professional system of social coercion —

not merely a system of social administration as it is still naively

regarded by the public and by many political theorists. The word

“professional” should be emphasized as much as the word “coercion.”

Coercion exists in nature, in personal relationships, in stateless, non-hierarchical communities. If coercion alone were used to define a State,

we would despairingly have to reduce it to a natural phenomenon —

which it surely is not It is only when coercion is *institutionalized* into

a professional, systematic, and organized form of social control — that

is, when people are plucked out of their everyday lives in a community

and expected not only to “administer” it but to do so with the backing

of a monopoly of violence — that we can properly speak of a State.

There may be varying approximations of a State, notably incipient,

quasi, or partial states. Indeed, to ignore these gradations of coercion,

professionalization, and institutionalization toward fully developed

states is to overlook the fact that statehood, as we know it today, is the

product of a long and complex development. Quasi, semi, and even

fully developed States have often been very unstable and have often

haemorrhaged power over years that resulted in what essentially became stateless societies. Hence, we have the swings, historically, from

highly centralized empires to feudal manorial societies and even fairly

democratic “city-states,” often with swings back again to empires and

nation-states, be they autocratic or republican in form. The simplistic

notions that states merely come into existence like a new-born baby,

omit the all-important gestation process of state development and have

resulted in a great deal of political confusion to this very day. We still

live with confused notions of statecraft, politics, and society, each of

which is deeply in need of careful distinction from the other.

Each State is not necessarily an institutionalized system of violence

in the interests of a specific ruling class, as Marxism would have us

believe. There are many examples of States that *were* the “ruling class”

and whose own interests existed quite apart from—even in antagonism

to _ privileged, presumably “ruling” classes in a given society. The

ancient world bears witness to distinctly capitalistic classes, often

highly privileged and exploitative, that were bilked by the State,

circumscribed by it and ultimately devoured by it — which is in part

why a capitalist society never emerged out of the ancient world. Nor

did the Stale “represent” other class interests, such as landed nobles,

merchants, craftsmen, and the like. The Ptolemaic State in Hellenistic

Egypt was an interest in its own right and “represented” no other interest

than its own. The same is true of the Aztec and the Inca States until they

were replaced by Spanish invaders. Under the Emperor Domitian, the

Roman State became the principal “interest” in the empire, superseding

the interests of even the landed aristocracy which held such primacy in

Mediterranean society.

I shall have a good deal to say about the State when I distinguish

statecraft from politics and the authentically political from the social.

For the present, we must glance at state-**like** formations that eventually

produced different kinds of States.

A chieftainship, surrounded by a “company” of supportive warriors

such as the Aztec State, is still an incipient type of state formation. The

seemingly absolute monarch was selected from a royal clan by a council

of clan elders, was carefully tested for his qualifications, and could be

removed if he proved to be inadequate to meet his responsibilities. Like

the highly militaristic Spartan State, chieftains or kings were still

circumscribed by tribal traditions that had been reworked to produce

the centralization of power.

Near-Eastern States, like the Egyptian, Babylonian, and Persian,

were virtually extended households of individual monarchs. They

formed a remarkable amalgam of a “domestic” society with a territorial

one: an “empire” was seen primarily as the land attached to the king’s

palace, not a strictly territorial administrative unit. Pharaohs, kings, and

emperors nominally held the land (often co-jointly with the priesthood)

in the trust of the deities, who were either embodied in the monarch or

were represented by him. The empires of Asian and North African kings

were “households” and the population was seen as “servants of the

palace ” not as citizens in any Western sense of the term.

These “states,” in effect, were not simply engines of exploitation or

control in the interests of a privileged “class.” They were resplendent

households with vast bureaucracies and aristocratic entourages

were self-serving and self-perpetuating slates. Administration was

as the task of maintaining a very costly household with monuments to

its power that taxed and virtually undermined tire entire economy. In

Egypt’s Old Kingdom, possibly as much effort went into building

pyramids, temples, palaces, and manors as was devoted to the maintenance of the Nile valley’s all-important irrigation system. The Egyptian State was very real but it “represented” nothing other than itself.

Conceived as a “household” and a sacred terrain in which the Pharaoh

embodied a deity, the State was almost congruent with society itself. It

was, in effect, a huge *social* State in which the differentiation of politics

out of society was really minimal. The State did not exist above society

or apart from it; the two were essentially one — an extended social

household, not an assortment of independent coercive institutions.

The Greek *polis* of the classical era does not offer us any more a

complete picture of the State than we encounter in the Near East. Athens

may be regarded as the apogee of class *politics* as distinguished from

the private world of the household based on family life, work,

friendships, and material needs which we can properly call *social*, or

the administration of armies, bureaucrats, judicial systems, police, and

the like, which we can properly call *statecraft*. Placed within the context

of this threefold distinction — social, political, and statist — the

Athenian *polis* is very difficult to define. The State, more properly the

<em>quasi</em>-state created by the Athenians in the Periklean Age, possessed

highly tribalistic attributes that directly involved the participation of a

sizeable male citizenry in seemingly statist activities. These Athenians

had invented *politics* — the direct administration of public affairs by a

community as a whole.

Admittedly, this political community or “public domain,” as it has

been called, existed within a wider domain of disenfranchised alien

residents, women of all classes, and slaves. These large disenfranchised

populations provided the material means for many Athenian male

citizens to convene in popular assemblies, function as mass juries in

trials, and collectively administer the affairs of the community. Politics

here, had begun to differentiate itself from the social domain of the

family and work.

But was this *polis* really a State? That the Athenians of the classical

era used coercion against slaves, women, aliens, and rival *poleis* is

clearly evident Within the eastern Mediterranean, Athenian influence

became increasingly imperial as the city forced other *poleis* to join the

Athenian-controlled Delian League and taxed them, using these funds

to maintain the Athenian citizenry and aggrandize the *polis*. Women,

of upper and well-to-do strata, were often confined to their homes and

obliged to maintain a domestic establishment for their husbands’ public

life.

It does not absolve the limitations of the Athenian democracy to say

that women were degraded throughout much of the Mediterranean

world, perhaps even more so in Athens than other regions. Nor does it

absolve it to say that Athenians were generally less severe in their

treatment of slaves than Romans. But, by the same token, we cannot

ignore the fact that classical Athens was historically unique, indeed

unprecedented, in much of human history, because of the democratic

forms it created, the extent to which they worked, and its faith in the

competence of its citizens to manage public affairs. These institutions

were forms of a direct democracy, as we shall see, and reflected a public

aversion to bureaucracy that made them structurally the most

democratic in the career of human political life. The Athenian State, in

effect, was not a fully developed phenomenon.

Indeed, I cannot stress too strongly that Athens, like so many

“city-states,” would have normally developed toward an oligarchy if

we explore the way in which so many autonomous cities eventually

became increasingly authoritarian and internally stratified. This was

the case with Rome, the late medieval Italian city-states, the German

city federations, and New England townships of America. One can go

on endlessly and cite decentralized, seemingly free and independent

cities that eventually turned from fairly democratic communities into

aristocracies.

What is remarkable about Athens is that the apparently “normal”

trend toward oligarchy was consciously reversed by the radical changes

introduced by Solon, Kleisthenes, and Perikles in the *polis’s* entire

institutional structure. Aristocratic institutions were steadily weakened

and consciously abolished or reduced to mere ceremonial bodies, while

democratic ones were granted increasing power and eventually

embraced the entire male citizenry, irrespective of properly ownership

and wealth. The army was turned into a militia of foot-soldiers whose

power began to exceed, by far, that of the aristocratic cavalry. Thus all

the negative features of the Athenian democracy, so common to the

Mediterranean and the era as a whole, must be seen in the context of a

revolutionary reversal of the normal trend toward oligarchy in most

city-states.

It is easy to deprecate this democracy because it rested on a large

slave population and degraded the status of women. But to do this with

lofty arrogance from a distance of more than two thousand years, with

a hindsight that is enriched by endless social debate, is to lift oneself

up by one’s bootstraps from the rich wealth of historical facts. Indeed,

it is to ignore those rare moments of democratic creativity that appeared

in the West and have nourished rich utopian and libertarian traditions.

Indeed, we do not encounter the State as a fully professional and

distinctive apparatus rooted in class interest until we see the emergence

of modern nations in Europe. The nation-state, as we know it today,

finally divests politics of all its seemingly traditional features: direct

democracy, citizen participation in the affairs of governmental life, and

a sensitive responsiveness to the communal welfare. The word

“democracy” itself undergoes degradation. It becomes “representative”

rather than face-to-face; highly centralized rather than freely confederal

between relatively independent communities, and divested of its

grassroots institutions.

Educated, knowledgeable citizens become reduced to mere taxpayers who exchange money for “services,” and education surrenders

its civic orientation to a curriculum designed to train the young for

financially rewarding skills. We have yet to see how far this appalling

trend will go in a world that is being taken over by mechanical robots,

computers that can so easily be used for surveillance, and genetic

engineers who have very limited moral scruples.

Hence, it is of enormous importance that we know how we arrived

at a condition where our preening “control” of nature has actually

rendered us more servile to domineering society than at any time in the

past By the same token, it is immensely important to know precisely

those human achievements in history, however faulty, that reveal how

freedom can be institutionalized — and, hopefully, expanded beyond

any horizon we can find in the past.

There is no way that we can return to the naive egalitarianism of the

preliterate world or to the democratic *polis* of classical antiquity;

should we want to do so. Atavism, primitivism, and attempts to

ture a distant world with drums, rattles, contrived rituals, and — whose repetition and fantasies bring a supernatural presence into our

midst — however much this may be denied or affirmed as innocent or

“immanent” — deflect us from the need for rational discussion, a

searching investigation of community, and a searing critique of the

present social system. Ecology is based on the wondrous qualities,

fecundity, and creativity of natural evolution, all of which warrant our

deepest emotional, aesthetic, and, yes, intellectual appreciation not

on anthropomorphically projected deities, be they “immanent” or

“transcendental.” Nothing is gained by going beyond a naturalistic,

truly ecological, framework and indulging mystical fantasies that are

regressive psychologically and atavistic historically.

Nor will ecological creativity be served by dropping on all fours and

baying at the moon like coyotes or wolves. Human beings, no less a

product of natural evolution than other mammals, have definitively

entered the social world. By their very own biologically rooted mental

power, they are literally *constituted* by evolution to intervene into the

biosphere. Tainted as the biosphere may be by present social conditions, their presence in the world of life marks a crucial change in

evolution’s direction from one that is largely adaptive to one that is, at

least, potentially creative and moral. In great part, their human nature

is formed socially — by prolonged dependence, social interdependence, increasing rationality, and the use of technical devices and their

willful application. All of these human attributes are mutually biological and social, the latter forming one of natural evolution’s greatest

achievements.

Hierarchies, classes, and states warp the creative powers of

humanity. They decide whether humanity’s ecological creativity will

be placed in the service of life or in the service of power and privilege.

Whether humanity will be irrevocably separated from die world of life

by hierarchical society, or brought together with life by an ecological

society depends on our understanding of the origins, development, and,

above all, the scope of hierarchy — the extent to which it penetrates

our daily lives, divides us into age group against age group, gender

against gender, man against man, and yields the absorption of the social

and political into the all-pervasive State. The conflicts within a divided

humanity, structured around domination, inevitably lead to conflicts

with nature. The ecological crisis with its embattled division between

humanity and nature stems, above all, from divisions between human

and human.

Our times exploit these divisions in a very cunning way: they *mystify*

them. Divisions are seen not as social but personal. Real conflicts

between people are mollified, even concealed, by appeals to a social

“harmony” that has no reality in society. Like the atavistic ritual with

its barely concealed appeal to the spirit world and its theistic

“spiritualism,” the encounter group has become a privatized arena for

learning how to “conciliate” — this, while storms of conflict rage

around us and threaten to annihilate us. That this use of “encounter”

groups and theistic “spirituality” to mollify and despiritualize has come

so much into vogue from its breeding ground in the American sunbelt

is no accident It occurs when a veritable campaign, under the name of

“post-modernism” is going on to discard the past, to dilute our

knowledge of history, to mystify the origins of our problems, to foster

dememorization and the loss of our most enlightened ideals.

Hence, never before has it been more necessary to recover the past,

to deepen our knowledge of history, to demystify the origins of our

problems, to regain our memory of forms of freedom and advances that

were made in liberating humanity of its superstitions, irrationalities,

and, above all, a loss of faith in humanity’s potentialities. If we are to

re-enter the continuum of natural evolution and play a creative role in

it, we must re-enter the continuum of social evolution and play a

creative role there as well.

There will be no “re-enchantment” of nature or of the world until

we achieve a “re-enchantment” of humanity and the potentialities of

human reason.

Turning Points in History

I have tried to show how far we must go and how deeply we must enter

into the most everyday aspects of our lives in order to root out the notion

of dominating nature.

In so doing, I have tried to emphasize the extent to which the

domination of human by human precedes the notion of dominating

nature, indeed, even precedes the emergence of classes and the State. I

have asked — and tried to answer — how hierarchies emerged, why

they emerged, and the way they became increasingly differentiated into

initially temporary and, later, firmly based status groups, and, finally,

classes and the State.

My purpose has been to let these trends unfold from their own inner

logic and examine all their nuanced forms along the way. The reader

has been persistently reminded that humanity and its social origins are

no less a product of natural evolution than other mammals and their

communities; indeed, that human beings can express a conscious

creativity in nature’s evolutionary development and can enlarge it —

not arrest or reverse it.

Whether humanity will play such a role, I have contended, depends

upon the kind of society that emerges and the sensibility society fosters.

It is now important to examine those turning points in history which

could have led people to either achieve a rational, ecological society,

or an irrational, anti-ecological one.

The Rise of the Warriors

Perhaps the earliest change in social development that veered

society in a direction that became seriously harmful, both to humanity

and the natural world, was the hierarchical growth of male’s civil

domain — namely, the rise of male gerontocracies, warrior groups,

aristocratic elites, and the State. To reduce these highly complex

developments to “patriarchy,” as many writers are prone to do, is as

naive as it is simplistic. “Men” — a generic word that is as vague as

the word “humanity” and ignores the oppression of men by men as well

as of women by men — did not simply “take over” society. Nor did the

male’s civil society simply subvert woman’s domestic world through

invasions by patriarchal Indo-European and Semitic pastoralists, important as these invasions may have been in the subjugation of many

early horticultural societies. The emphasis of certain eco-feminists,

mystics, and Christian or pagan acolytes on this “take-over” and

“invasions” theory simply creates another unresolved mystery: how did

dramatic changes, like the emergence of patriarchy, occur in the pastoral societies that did the invading? We have evidence that the rise of

the male civil domain with its concern for intertribal affairs and warfare

gained ascendancy slowly and that some pastoral communities were

oriented toward women in such strategic areas as descent and the

inheritance of property, however much these communities were led by

bellicose warriors.

In many cases, the male’s civil domain developed slowly and

probably gained importance with increases in neighbouring populations. Men were, in fact, needed to protect the community as a whole

— including its women — from other marauding men. Warfare may

have even emerged or developed among seemingly “pacific” and

matricentric horticultural communities which tried to expel more pristine hunting, and gathering peoples from woodlands that later were

turned into farm lands. Let us be quite frank about this: matricentric or

pacific as early farming communities may have been, they probably

were very warlike in the eyes of the hunters they managed to displace — that is, those hunting peoples and cultures that were by no means predisposed to abandon their free-ranging ways and take up food

cultivation. The statements of the great Indian orators, the words of

Wovoka, the Paiute Indian messiah of the late nineteenth-century Ghost

Dance, on plow agriculture, are still evocative of this mentality: “Shall

I plunge a blade into the breast of my mother, the Earth?”

But there can be little doubt that the slow shift from rule by the

elderly, later the oldest male or patriarch, the change from the influence

of animistic shamans to deity worshipping priesthoods, and the rise of

warrior groups that finally culminated in supreme monarchs all

formed a major turning point in history toward domination, classes, and

the emergence of the State. There is the possibility that matricentric

communities of villagers might have shaped a pathway of an entirely

different character for humanity as a whole. Based on gardening, simple

tools, usufruct, the irreducible minimum, complementarity, and so-called feminine values of care and nurture (which, in any case, have

been with us in the socialization of their children up to recent times),

society might have taken a relatively benign turn in history. The

concern that mothers normally share with their young might have been

generalized into a concern that people could have shared with each

other. Technical development based on limited wants could have

continued very slowly into increasingly more sophisticated social

forms and cultural life could have been elaborated with considerable

sensitivity.

Whether unavoidable or not, the fact remains that this fork in the

road of early history was to be marked by a turn to patriarchal, priestly,

monarchical, and statist lines, not along matricentric and nonhierarchical lines. Warrior values of combat, class domination, and state rule

were to form the basic infrastructure of all “civilized development

no less in Asia than in Europe and no less in large areas of the New

World, like Mexico and the Andes, than in the Old World.

The wistful attempts by many people in the ecology and feminist

movements to return, in one way or another, to a presumably untroubled

Neolithic village world are understandable in the face of

“civilization’s” more nightmarish results. But their imagery of this

distant world and their growing hatred of civilization *as such* leaves

room for considerable doubt.

Certainly, it is not likely that pristine hunting and gathering communities had more love for equally pristine gardening societies than a

Wovoka, whether or not they shared a belief in the same Mother

Goddess. Nor is it likely that, with growing population, gardening

societies could have retained the tender sentiments celebrated by the

more atavistic feminists of our day. Patricentric pastoralists and sea

invaders may have telescoped a development that might have been

more benign, to be sure, but it would have been one that was difficult

to avoid. If “civilization” was conceived in “original sin ” it was

probably a “sin” or evil that pitted food cultivators against hunters (both

of whom may have been matricentric and animistic) and, much later,

pastoralists against food cultivators.

In any case, there was a great deal in tribal and village society — be

it composed of hunters or food cultivators — that needed remedying.

First of all, tribal and village societies are notoriously parochial, A

shared descent, be it fictional or real, leads to an exclusion of the

stranger — except, perhaps, when canons of hospitality are invoked.

Although the rules of exogamy and the imperatives of trade tend to

foster alliances between the “insider” and “outsider” of a tribal and

village community, an “outsider” can be killed summarily by an

“insider.” Rules of retribution for theft, assault, and murder apply

exclusively to the “insider” and his or her relatives, not to any authority

that exists apart from the common descent group.

Tribal and village societies, in effect, are very closed societies —

closed to outsiders unless they are needed for their skills, to repopulate

the community after costly wars and lethal epidemics, or as a result of

marriage. And they are closed societies not only to outsiders, but often

to cultural and technological innovations. While many cultural traits

may spread slowly from one tribal and village community to another,

such communities tend to be highly conservative in their view of basic

innovations. For better or worse, traditional lifeways tend to become

deeply entrenched with the passing of time. Unless they are developed

locally, new technologies tend to be resisted — for understandable

reasons, to be sure, if one bears in mind the socially disruptive effects

they may have on time-honoured customs and institutions. But the

harsh fact is that this conservatism makes a tribal and village community highly vulnerable to control, indeed, to eradication by other

communities that have more effective technological devices.

A second troubling feature of tribal and village societies is their

cultural limitations. These are not societies that are likely to develop

complex systems of writing, hence the terms “nonliterate and

“preliterate” that are used by many anthropologists to designate them.

Today, when irrationalism, mysticism, and primitivism have become

rather fashionable among affluent middle-class people (ironically,

through written works), the inability of nonliterate people to maintain

a recorded history and culture, or to communicate through pictographs,

is regarded as a pristine blessing. That the absence of alphabetic

writing, in fact, not only severely limited the scope of the cultural

landscape of early times but even fostered hierarchy, is easily overlooked. Knowledge of lore, ancestral ties, rituals, and survival techniques became the special preserve of the elderly who, through

experience, rote learning, or both, were strategically positioned to

manipulate younger people.

Gerontocracy, in my view the earliest form of hierarchy, became

possible because young people had to consult their elders for

knowledge. No scrolls or books were available to replace the wisdom

inscribed on the brains of older people. Elders used their monopoly

of knowledge with telling effect to establish the earliest form of

rule in prehistory. Patriarchy itself owes a good deal of power to the

knowledge which the eldest male of a clan commanded by virtue of the

experience conferred upon him by age. Writing could easily have

democratized social experience and culture — a fact shrewdly known

to ruling elites and especially to priesthoods, who retained stringent

control over literacy and confined a knowledge of writing to clerks

or clerics.

A large literature has emerged, today, that mystifies primitivism. It

is important to remind thinking people that humanity was not born into

a Hobbesian world of a war of “all against all”; that the two sexes were

once complementary to each other culturally as well as economically;

that disaccumulation, gift-giving, the irreducible’minimum, and substantive equality formed the basic norms of early organic societies; that

humanity lived in a harmonious relationship with nature because it

lived in a condition of internal social harmony within the same community. However, we cannot ignore that this innocent world, vulnerable to internal tendencies toward hierarchy as well as invaders who

placed them in subjugation to warrior elites, had major flaws that kept

humans from the full realization of their potentialities.

The idea of a shared *humanitas*, that could bring people of ethnically, even tribally, diverse backgrounds together in the common project

of building a fully cooperative society for all to enjoy, did not exist.

Tribal confederations certainly formed over time, often to mitigate

bloody intertribal warfare and for expansionist purposes to displace

“other” people of their land. The Iroquois Confederacy is perhaps one

of the most celebrated examples of intertribal cooperation based on

strong democratic traditions. But it was a Confederacy that was entirely

focused on its own interests, for all its merits. Indeed, it earned the bitter

hatred of the other Indian peoples like the Hurons and the Illinois,

whose lands it invaded and whose communities it ravaged.

The Emergence of the City

After the shift from a matricentric to a patricentric warrior pathway

of development, the next major turning point we encounter historically

is the emergence and development of the city. The city was to form an

entirely new social arena — a *territorial* arena in which one’s place of

residence and economic interests steadily replaced one’s ancestral

affinities based on blood ties.

The radical nature of this shift and its impact on history are difficult

to appreciate today. Urbanity is so much a part of modern social life

that it is simply taken for granted. Moreover, so much emphasis has

been placed on the extent to which the city accelerated cultural development (writing, art, religion, philosophy, and science) and the impetus

it gave to economic development (technology, classes, and the division

of labour between crafts and agriculture) that we often fail to stress the

new kinds of *human* association urbanity produced.

Perhaps for the first time, so far as we can judge, human beings were

able to interact with each other with relatively little regard for their

ancestral and blood ties. The notion that people were basically alike,

irrespective of their tribal and village ancestry, began to gain ascendancy over their ethnic differences. The city increasingly replaced the

group, by the *social* fact of residence and economic interests. People

were not simply *born* into a distinct social condition; in varying degrees

they could begin to *choose* and *change* their social condition. Social

institutions and the development of a purely human ecumene came to

the foreground of society and gradually edged the folk community into

the background of social life. Kinship retreated more and more into the

private realm of family affairs, and fading clan-type relations began to

shrink into the narrower extended family of immediate relatives rather

than a far-flung system of clan “cousins.”

What is vastly important about the new social dispensation created

by the city was the fact that the stranger or “outsider” could now find

a secure place in a large community of human beings. Initially, this new

place did not confer equality on the “outsider.” Despite its avowed

openness to resident aliens, Periklean Athens, for example, rarely gave

them citizenship and the right to plead their court cases, except through

the voices of Athenian citizens. But early cities did provide strangers

with increased protection from abuse by the “insider.” In many cases

of newly emerging cities, a compromise was struck between tribal

values based on blood ties and social values based on the realities of

residence in which the “outsider” acquired basic rights that tribal

society rarely conferred, while restricting citizenship to the “insider”

and giving him a wider latitude of civil rights.

Even more than hospitality, then, the city offered the “outsider” *de facto* or *de jure* justice — but it did so in the form of protection provided

by a monarch and, in later years, by written law codes. Minimally, both

the “outsider” and the “insider” were now seen as human beings with

a shared body of rights, not simply as mutually exclusive in their

humanity and needs. With the rise and development of the city, the

germinal idea that *all* people were in a certain sense *one* people, came

to fruition and achieved a new historic universality.

I do not wish to suggest that this enormous step in developing the

idea of a common *humanitas* occurred overnight or that it was not

accompanied by some very questionable changes in the human condition, as we shall see shortly. Perhaps the most liberal cities like the

Greek *poleis*, particularly democratic Athens, ceased to confer citizenship on resident aliens, as I have noted, in Perikles’s time. Solon, a

century or so earlier, had indeed freely and openly granted citizenship

to all foreigners who brought skills needed by Athens from abroad.

Perikles, the most democratic of the Athenian leaders, regrettably

abandoned Solon’s liberality and made citizenship a privilege for men

of proven Athenian ancestry.

Tribalistic beliefs and institutions also permeated early cities. They

lingered on in the form of highly archaic religious views: the deification

of ancestors, followed by tribal chiefs who eventually become divine

monarchs; patriarchal authority in domestic life; and feudal aristocracies that were inherited from village societies of the late Neolithic

and Bronze Ages. On the other hand, in Athens and Rome, the tribal

and village assembly form of decision-making was not only retained

but revitalized and, in Athens at least, given supreme authority during

the Periklean era.

The city existed in tension with these beliefs and institutions. It

continually tried to rework traditional religions into civic ones that

fostered loyalty to the city. The power of the nobility was steadily

eroded and that of the patriarch to command the lives of his sons was

repeatedly challenged in order to bring young men into the service

civic institutions, such as the bureaucracy and the army.

This tension never completely disappeared. Indeed, it formed

on-going drama of civic politics for nearly three thousand years and

surfaced in such violent conflicts as the attempts by medieval towns to

subdue overbearing territorial nobles and bishops. Cities sought

bring rationality, a measure of impartial justice, a cosmopolitan culture

and greater individuality to a world that was permeated by mysticism

arbitrary power, parochialism, and the subordination of the individual

to the command of aristocratic and religious elites.

Legally, at least, the city did not attain civic maturity until the

Emperor Caracalla in the third century CE proclaimed all free men in

the Roman Empire citizens of Rome. Caracalla’s motives may be justly

regarded with suspicion: he was patently interested in expanding the

empire’s tax base to meet rising imperial costs. But even as a legal

gesture, this act created a worldly sense that all human beings, even

slaves, belonged to the same species — that men and women were one,

irrespective of their ethnic background, wealth, occupations, or station

in life. The notion of a vast human ecumene had received legitimation

on a scale that was unknown in the past, except in philosophy and

certain religions — Judaism, no less than Christianity.

Caracalla’s edict, to be sure, did not dissolve the parochial barriers

that still divided differing ethnic groups, towns, and villages. Inland,

near the frontiers of the Empire and beyond, these differences were as

strong as they had been for millennia. But the edict, later reinforced by

Christianity’s vision of a unified world under the rule of a single

creator-deity and a commitment to individual free will, set a new

standard for human affinity that could only have emerged with the city

and its increasingly cosmopolitan, rationalistic, and individualistic

values. It is not accidental that Augustine’s most famous tract in defense

of Christianity was called the *City of God* and that the Christian fathers

were to look as longingly toward the city of Jerusalem as did the Jews.

The sweeping social dispensation initiated by the city was not

achieved without the loss of many profoundly important attributes of

tribal and early village life. The communal ownership of land and of

so-called natural resources gave way to private ownership. Classes,

those categories based on the ownership and management of these

“resources,” crystallized out of more traditional status hierarchies into

economic ones, so that slaves stood opposed to masters, plebians to

patricians, serfs to lords, and, later, proletarians to capitalists.

Nor did earlier and more basic hierarchies structured around status

groups like gerontocracies, patriarchies, chiefdoms, and, in time,

bureaucracies, disappear. As largely status groups, they formed the

hidden bases for more visible and stormy class relationships. Indeed,

status groups were simply taken for granted as a “natural” state of

affairs so that the young, women, the sons, and the common masses of

people began to enter unthinkingly into complicity with their own

elites. Hierarchy, in effect, became embedded in the human unconscious

while classes, whose legitimacy was more easy to challenge because

of the visibility of exploitation, came to the

foreground of an embattled and bitterly divided humanity.

Viewed from its negative side, then, the city consolidated

privatization of property in one form or another: class structures,

quasi-statist or fully developed statist institutions. A tension between

advances achieved by the emergence of the city and the loss of certain

archaic but deeply cherished values, including usufruct, complementarity, and the principle of the irreducible minimum, raised a puzzling

issue in human development that could properly be called the “social

question.” This phrase, once so popular among radical theorists,

referred to the fact that “civilization,” despite its many far-reaching

advances, has never been fully rational and free of exploitation. To use

this phrase more expansively, here, and with a more ethical meaning,

one might say that all of humanity’s extraordinary gains under

“civilization” have always been tainted by the “evil” of hierarchy.

Evil was not a word that Marx was wont to use when he tried to turn

the critique of capitalism into an “objective” science, freed of all moral

connotations. But it is to Michael Bakunin’s credit that “evil” was

indeed a condition to be reckoned with in his thinking and he quite

properly tried to show that many social changes, however “necessary”

or unavoidable they seemed in their own time, turned into an “evil” in

the overall drama of history. In his *Federalism, Socialism, and Anti-Theologism*, Bakunin observes: “And I do not hesitate to say that the

State is an evil but is a historically necessary evil, as necessary in the

past as its complete extinction will be necessary sooner or later, just as

necessary as primitive bestiality and theological divagations were

necessary to the past.”

Putting Bakunin’s reference to a “primitive bestiality” aside as a

prejudice that was understandable more than a century ago, his recognition that humanity developed as much through the medium of “evil”

as it did through the medium of “virtue,” touches upon the subtle

dialectic of “civilization” itself. Biblical precept did not curse humanity

in vain; there is an ancient recognition that certain evils could not easily

be avoided in humanity’s ascent out of animality. Human beings were

no more aware that they were creating hierarchy when they invested

authority in the elders than they were aware that they were creating

hierarchy when they invested authority in priesthoods. The ability to

reason out certain premises to their conclusion does not come too easily

in what is, after all, a largely unconscious primate whose capacity to

be rational is more of a potentiality than an actuality. In this respect,

preliterate people were no better equipped to deal with the development

of their social reality than those who have been tainted by the worst

aspects of “civilization.” The “social question” for us, today, exists

precisely in the fact that we raised ourselves into the light of freedom

with half-open eyes, burdened by dark atavisms, ancient hierarchies,

and deeply ingrained prejudices to which we may still regress, if the

present counter-Enlightenment of mysticism and antirationalism persists, and that may yet lead us to our ruin. We hold a proverbial knife

in our hands that easily could be used to cut both ways — for our

emancipation or our ruination.

“Civilization” has sharpened that knife into a razor’s edge, but it has

not provided us with a better guide to how we will use so dangerous an

instrument beyond the power conferred upon us by consciousness

itself.

The Nation-State and Capitalism

A third turning point we encounter historically

is the emergence of the nation-state and capitalism

The two — the nation-state and capitalism — do not

necessarily go together. But capitalism succeeds so rapidly with the

rise of the nation-state that they are often seen as co-jointly developing phenomena.

In point of fact, nation-building goes back as far as the twelfth

century when Henry II of England and Philip Augustus of France tried

to centralize monarchical power and acquire territories that were to

eventually form their respective nations. The nation was to slowly eat

away at all local power, ultimately pacifying parochial rivalries among

baronies and towns. The imperial patrimonies of the ancient world had

created immense states, but they were not lasting ones. Patched together

from completely different ethnic groups, these empires lived in strange

balance with archaic village communities that had hardly changed,

culturally and technologically, since Neolithic times.

The main function of this village society was to supply monarchs

with tribute and with corvee labour. Otherwise, they were usually left

alone. Hence, local life was subterranean, but intense. A great deal of

common land existed around these villages which were open to use by

all. There is evidence that even “private” land was regularly

redistributed to families according to their changing needs. Interference

from the top down was often minimal. The greatest dangers to this

stable village society came from invading armies and warring nobles.

Otherwise they were usually left to themselves, that is, when they were

not plundered by aristocrats and tax gatherers.

Justice, in this kind of society, was often arbitrary. The complaints

by the Greek farmer, Hesiod, about unfair, self-seeking local barons

echoes a long-standing grievance that seldom surfaces in the historical

literature we have at our disposal. The great law codes that were handed

down by the absolute monarch of Babylonia, Hammurabi, were not the

rule in the pre-Roman world. More often than not, avaricious nobles

made their own law” to suit their own needs. The peasant may have

sought the protection of nobles for himself and his community from

pillaging outsiders, but rarely justice. Empires were too big to manage

administratively, much less juridically. The Roman Empire was a major

exception to this rule, largely because it was mote of a coastal and fairly

urbanized entity rather than a vast inland area with very few cities.

European nations, by contrast, were formed out of continents that

history sculpted into increasingly manageable territories. Road systems, to be sure, were poor and communication was primitive. But as

strong kings emerged like Henry II of England and Philip Augustus of

France, royal justice and bureaucrats began to penetrate into once-remote areas and reach deeper into the everyday life of the people.

There is no question that the “king’s justice” was welcomed by commoners and his officials acted as a buffer between arrogant nobles and

the cowed masses. The early development of the nation-stale, in effect,

was marked by a genuine sense of promise and relief.

But the royal power was usually an interest in its own right, not a

moral agency for the redress of popular grievances, and it eventually

became as oppressive as the local nobles it displaced. Moreover, it was

not a pliant tool for achieving the ascendancy of the emerging bourgeoisie. The Stuart kings of England, who catapulted England into

revolution in the 1640s, viewed their nations as personal patrimonies

which both the powerful nobles and wealthy bourgeoisie threatened to

subvert.

The notion that the nation-state was “formed” by the bourgeoisie is

a myth that should be dispatched by now. In the first place, what we

call a “bourgeois” in the late Middle Ages was nothing like the

industrialist or industrial capitalist we know today. Apart from some

wealthy banking houses and commercial capitalists engaged in a far-ranging carrying trade, the nascent bourgeois was generally a master

craftsman who functioned within a highly restrictive guild system. He

seldom exploited a proletarian of the kind we encounter today.

Disparities in wealth, to be sure, eventually gave rise to craftsmen

who closed out apprentices and turned their guilds into privileged

societies for themselves and their sons. But this was not the rule. In

most of Europe, guilds fixed prices, determined the quality and quantity

of goods that were produced, and were open to apprentices who, in time,

could hope to be masters in their own right This system, which

carefully regulated growth, was hardly capitalistic. Work was done

mainly by hand in small shops where master sat side by side with

apprentice and attended to the needs of a limited, highly personalized

market.

By the late Middle Ages, the manorial economy with its elaborate

hierarchy and its land-based serfs was in dissolution, although by no

means did it disappear completely. Relatively independent farmers

began to appear who worked as owners of their land or as tenants of

absentee nobles. Looking over the broad landscape of Europe between

the fifteenth and eighteenth centuries, one encounters a highly mixed

economy. Together with serfs, tenant farmers, and yeomen, there were

craftsmen, some well-to-do and others of modest means, who co-existed with capitalists, most of whom were engaged in commerce rather than industry.

Europe, in effect, was the centre of a highly mixed economy, not a

capitalistic one, and its technology, despite major advances throughout

the Middle Ages, was still based on handicrafts, not on industry. Even

mass production, such as the system organized in the huge arsenal of

Venice (which employed three thousand workers), involved artisans,

each of whom worked in a very traditional fashion in small alcoves and

shops.

It is important to stress these features of the world that directly

preceded the Industrial Revolution because they greatly conditioned

the social options that were open to Europe. Prior to the era of the Stuart

monarchy in England, the Bourbon in France, and the Hapsburg in

Spain, European towns enjoyed an extraordinary amount of autonomy.

Italian and German cities, in particular, although by no means exclusively, formed strong states in their own right, ranging in political

forms from simple democracies in their early years, to oligarchies in

later periods. They also formed confederations to struggle against local

lords, foreign invaders, and absolute monarchs. Civic life flourished in

these centuries — not only economically, but culturally. Citizens

generally owed their allegiances primarily to their cities and only

secondarily to their territorial lords and emerging nations.

The growth of power of the nation-state from the sixteenth century

onward became as much a source of conflict as it was a source of order

in controlling unruly nobles. Attempts by monarchs to impose royal

sovereignty on the towns and cities of the period produced an era of

near-insurrectionary attacks on representatives of the crown. Royal

records were destroyed, bureaucrats assaulted, and their offices

demolished. Although the person of the monarch was given the customary respect accorded to a head of state, his edicts were often ignored

and his officials were all but lynched. The Fronde, a series of conflicts

initiated by the French nobility and Parisian burghers against growing

royal power during the youth of Louis XIV, virtually demolished

absolutism and drove the young king out of Paris until the monarchy

reasserted its power.

Behind these upsurges in many parts of Europe we find a mounting

resistance to encroachments by the centralized nation-state on the

prerogatives of the towns and cities. This municipal upsurge reached

its height in the early sixteenth century when the cities of Castile rose

up against Charles II of Spain and tried to establish what was essentially

a municipal confederation. The struggle, which went on for more than

a year, ended in the defeat of the Castilian cities after a series of striking

victories on their part — and their defeat marked the economic and

cultural decline of Spain for nearly three centuries. To the extent that

the Spanish monarchy was in the vanguard of royal absolutism during

that century and played a major role in European politics, the uprising

of the cities — or *Comuneros*, as their partisans were called — created

the prospect of an alternative pathway to the continent’s development

toward nation-states: namely, a confederation of towns and cities.

Europe genuinely vacillated for a time between these two alternatives

and it was not until the late seventeenth century that the nation-state

gained ascendancy over a confederal pathway.

Nor did the idea of confederation ever die. It surfaced among

radicals in the English Revolution who were condemned by the followers of Cromwell as “Switzering anarchists.” It reappeared, again,

in confederations that radical farmers tried to establish in New England

in the aftermath of the American Revolution. And, again, in France in

radical sectional movements—the neighbourhood assemblies of Paris

and other French cities established during the Great Revolution — and,

finally, in the Paris Commune of 1871, which called for a “Commune

of communes” and the dissolution of the nation-state.

In the era that immediately preceded the formation of the nationstate, Europe stood poised at a fork in the historic road. Depending upon

the fortunes of the *Comuneros* and the *sans culottes* who packed the

Parisian sections of 1793, the future of the nation-state hung very much

in the balance. Had the continent moved in the direction of urban

confederations, its future would have taken a socially more benign

course, perhaps even a more revolutionary, democratic, and cooperative form than it was to acquire in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.

By the same token, it is quite unclear that an industrial capitalist

development of the kind that exists today was preordained by history.

That capitalism greatly accelerated technological development at a rate

that has no precedent in history hardly requires any detailed discussion.

And I shall have much to say about what this technological development did to humanity and nature — and what it *could* do in a truly

ecological society. But capitalism, like the nation-state, was neither an

unavoidable “necessity,” nor was it a “precondition” for the establishment of a cooperative or socialist democracy.

Indeed, important forces tended to inhibit its development and

ascendancy. As a bitterly competitive market system based on production for exchange and the accumulation of wealth, capitalism and a

capitalistic mentality, with its emphasis on individual egoism, stood

very much at odds with deeply ingrained traditions, customs, and even

the lived realities of precapitalist societies. All precapitalist societies

had placed a high premium on cooperation rather than competition,

however much this emphasis was commonly disregarded or, indeed,

used to mobilize collective labour forces in the service of elites and

monarchs. Nevertheless, competition as a way of life — as “healthy

competition” to use modern bourgeois parlance — was simply inconceivable. Agonistic male behaviour in ancient and medieval times, to

be sure, was not uncommon, but it was generally focused on public

service in one form or another—not on material self-aggrandizement.

The market system was essentially marginal to a precapitalist world,

particularly one that emphasized self-sufficiency. Where the market

achieved prominence, say, in medieval times, it was carefully regulated

by guilds and Christian precepts against the taking of interest and

excessive profiteering. Capitalism, to be sure, always existed — as

Marx observed, “in the interstices of an ancient world” and, one can

add, medieval world — but it largely failed to achieve a socially

dominant status. The early bourgeoisie, in fact, did not have overly

capitalistic aspirations; its ultimate goals were shaped by the aristocracy so that the capitalists of ancient and medieval times invested

their profits in land and tried to live like gentry after retiring from

business affairs.

Growth, too, was frowned upon as a serious violation of religious

and social taboos. The ideal of “limit ” the classical Greek belief in the

“golden mean,” never entirely lost its impact on the precapitalist world.

Indeed, from tribal limes well into historical times, virtue was defined

as a strong commitment by the individual to the community’s welfare

and prestige was earned by disposing of wealth in the form of gifts, not

by accumulating it.

Not surprisingly, the capitalist market and the capitalist spirit that

emphasized endless growth, accumulation, competition, and still more

growth and accumulation for competitive advantages in the market —

all encountered endless obstacles in precapitalist societies. The nascent

capitalists of the ancient world rarely rose to a status of more than

functionaries of imperial monarchs who needed merchants to acquire

rare and exotic commodities from faraway places. Their profits were

fixed and their social ambitions were curtailed.

The Roman emperors gave a greater leeway to the early bourgeoisie,

to be sure, but plundered it freely by means of taxation and episodic

expropriations. The medieval world in Europe gave the bourgeoisie a

substantially more freer hand, particularly in England, Flanders, and

northern Italy. But even in the more individualistic Christian world,

capitalists came up against entrenched guild systems that sharply

circumscribed the market and were usually mesmerized by aristocratic

values of high living that worked against the bourgeois virtues of

parsimony and material accumulation.

Indeed, in most of Europe, the bourgeoisie was seen as a contemptible underclass — demonic in its passion for wealth, parvenu in

its ambitions to belong to the nobility, culturally unsettling in its

proclivity for growth, and threatening in its fascination for technological innovation. Its supremacy in Renaissance Italy and Handers was

highly unstable. Free-spending *condotierri* like the Medici, who gained

control of major northern Italian cities, devoured the gains of trade in

lavish expenditures for palaces, civic monuments, and warfare. Changes in trade routes, such as the shift of commerce from the Mediterranean to the Atlantic in the years following the Turkish capture of

Constantinople (1453), ultimately doomed the Italian city-states to

occupy a secondary place in Europe. It was the historic breakthrough

of capitalism in England that gave this economy national, and finally

global, supremacy.

This breakthrough, too, was not an unavoidable fact of history, nor

was the form it took predetermined in any way by suprahuman social

forces. The English economy and state were perhaps the most loosely

constructed of any in Europe. The monarchy never achieved the absolutism attained by Louis XIV of France, nor was England a clearly definable nation

feudalism deeply entrenched in the realm, despite the current English

preoccupation with status. In so porous a society with so unstable a

history, the merchant and, later,the industrially oriented capitalist found

a greater degree of freedom for development there than elsewhere.

The English nobility, in turn, was largely a *nouveau elite* that had

been installed by the Tudor monarchs after the traditional Norman

nobility all but destroyed itself in the bloody Wars of the Roses in the

fifteenth century. The nobles, often of humble birth, were not averse to

turning a penny in trade. To raise substantial fortunes by selling wool

in the Handers textile industry, they wantonly enclosed the common

lands of the peasantry and turned them into sheep runs.

The spread of the capitalist “putting out” system, moreover, in which

so-called factors brought wool to family cottages, passing on unfinished yam to weavers and then to dyers, eventually led to the

concentration of all the cottagers in “factories,” where they were

obliged to work under harsh, exploitative, and highly disciplined conditions. In this way, the new industrial bourgeoisie circumvented the

traditional guild restrictions in the towns and brought a growing class

of dispossessed proletarians into its service. Each worker could now be

competitively played against others in a presumably “free” labour

market, driving down the wages and providing immense profits in the

new factory system that developed near England’s major urban centres.

In the so-called Glorious Revolution of 1688 — not to be confused

with the stormy English Revolution of the 1640s — the avaricious

English nobles and their bourgeois counterparts came to a political

compromise. The aristocracy was permitted to run the state, the monarchy was reduced to a mere symbol of interclass unity, and the bourgeoisie was granted a free hand in running the economy. Allowing for

quarrels between various ruling elites, the English capitalist class

enjoyed the virtually unrestrained right to plunder England and to move

its operations abroad to claim India, large parts of Africa, and commercially strategic strongholds in Asia.

Market economies had existed before capitalism. Indeed, they coexisted with fairly communal economies. There are periods in the

Middle Ages that bear witness to a fascinating balance between town

and country, crafts and agriculture, burghers and food cultivators, and

technological innovations and cultural constraints. This world was to

be idealized by romantic writers in the nineteenth century and by Peter

Kropotkin, the Russian anarchist, who exhibited an acute sensitivity to

the various alternatives to capitalism offered by a cooperative society

and mentality at various periods in history.

The upsurge of English capitalism in the eighteenth century, and its

global outreach in the nineteenth century, altered such prospects radically. For the first time, competition was seen to be “healthy”; trade, as

“free”; accumulation, as evidence of “parsimony”; and egoism, as

evidence of a self-interest that worked like a “hidden hand” in the

service of the public good. Concepts of “health,” “freedom,” “parsimony,” and the “public good” were to subserve unlimited expansion

and wanton plunder — not only of nature, but of human beings. No

class of proletarians in England suffered less during the Industrial

Revolution than the huge bison herds that were exterminated on the

American plains. No human values and communities were warped any

less than the ecosystems of plants and animals that were despoiled in

the original forests of Africa and South America. To speak of

“humanity’s” depredation of nature makes a mockery of the unbridled

depredation of human by human as depicted in the tormented novels of

Charles Dickens and Emile Zola. Capitalism divided the human species

against itself as sharply and brutally as it divided society against nature.

Competition began to permeate every level of society, not only to

throw capitalist against capitalist for control of the marketplace. It

pitted buyer against seller, need against greed, and individual against

individual on the most elementary levels of human encounters. In the

marketplace, one individual faced another with a snarl, even as working

people, each seeking, as a matter of sheer survival, to get the better of

the other. No amount of moralizing and pietizing can alter the fact that

rivalry at the most molecular base of society is a bourgeois law of life,

in the literal sense of the word “life ” Accumulation to undermine, buy

out, or otherwise absorb or outwit a competitor *is a condition for existence in a capitalist economic order.*

That nature, too, is a victim of this competitive, accumulative, and

ever-expanding social fury, should be obvious if it were not for the fact

that there is a strong tendency to date this social trend’s origins back to

technology and industry as such. That modern technology *magnifies*

more fundamental economic factors, notably, growth as a law of life in

a competitive economy and the commodification of humanity and

nature, is an apparent fact. But technology and industry in themselves

do not turn every ecosystem, species, tract of soil, waterway, or, for

that matter, the oceans and the air, into mere natural resources. They

do not monetize and give a price-tag to everything that could be

exploited in the competitive struggle for survival and growth.[11] To

speak of “limits to growth” under a capitalistic market economy is as

meaningless as to speak of limits to warfare under a warrior society.

The moral pieties, that are voiced today by many well-meaning environmentalists, are as naive as the moral pieties of multinationals are

manipulative. Capitalism can no more be “persuaded” to limit growth

than a human being can be “persuaded” to stop breathing. Attempts to

“green” capitalism, to make it “ecological,” are doomed by the very

nature of the system as a system of endless growth.

Indeed, the most basic precepts of ecology, such as the concern for

balance, a harmonious development toward greater differentiation, and

ultimately, the evolution of greater subjectivity and consciousness,

stand *radically* at odds with an economy that homogenizes society,

nature, and the individual, and that divides human against human and

society against nature with a ferocity that must ultimately tear down

the planet.

For generations, radical theorists opined about the “inner limits” of

the capitalist system, the “internal” mechanisms within its operations

as an economy, that would yield its self-destruction. Marx gained the

plaudits of endless writers for advancing the possibility that capitalism

would be destroyed and replaced by socialism because it would enter

a chronic crisis of diminishing profits, economic stagnation, and class

war with an ever-impoverished proletariat In the face of vast biogeochemical dislocations that have opened vast holes in the earth’s

ozone layer and increased the temperature of the planet by the “greenhouse effect,” these limits are now clearly ecological. Whatever may

be the destiny of capitalism as a system that has “internal limits”

economically, we can emphatically say that it has *external* limits

ecologically.

Indeed, capitalism completely incarnates Bakunin’s notion of “evil”

without the qualification that it is “socially necessary.” Beyond the

capitalist system there are no further “turning points in history.”

Capitalism marks the end of the road for a long social development in

which evil permeated the good and irrationality permeated the rational.

Capitalism, in effect, constitutes the point of *absolute negativity* for

society and the natural world. One cannot improve this social order,

reform it, or remake it on its own terms with an ecological prefix such

as “eco-capitalism.” The only choice one has is to destroy it, for it

embodies *every* social disease — from patriarchal values, class exploitation, and statism to avarice, militarism, and now, growth for the

sake of growth — that has afflicted “civilization” and tainted all its

great advances.

Ideals of Freedom

I have touched upon popular attempts to resist the immersion of society

into “evil,” namely, the resistance of the Spanish *Comuneros* and the

French *sans culottes* to the nation-state and, less directly, of craftsmen

and independent farmers to capitalism.

But the drift of patricentric, urban, and economic institutions in an

increasingly antihumanistic and anti-ecological direction was fought

by people on a very sweeping scale and with more explosive ideas than

I have indicated. Today, when we run the risk of losing all knowledge

of history and, particularly, of the revolutionary tradition and utopian

alternatives it offered, it is very important that we examine the libertarian movements that emerged at each of history’s turning points and

the ideas of freedom they advanced. Here, we shall find a remarkable

development of ideas that sought to countervail “civilization’s” immersion into evil. Indeed, we shall find progress in its truly authentic sense:

a widening of social struggles to encompass more and more fundamental issues and a sophistication of the concept of freedom itself.

From the outset, let me draw a very important distinction: namely,

between the ideals of freedom and the notions of justice. The two words

have been used so interchangeably that they have almost become

synonymous. Actually, justice differs profoundly from freedom, and it

is important that we clearly disengage one from the other. Historically,

they have given rise to very different kinds of struggles and they have

voiced radically different demands from systems of authority to this

very day. The distinction between mere reforms and fundamental

changes in society rests, in great part, on demands for justice and

demands for freedom, however much the two have been closely related

to each other in highly fluid social situations.

Justice is the demand for equity, for “fair play,” and a share in the

benefits of life that are commensurable with one’s contribution. In

Thomas Jefferson’s words, it is “equal and exact...” based on a respect

for the principle of equivalence. This fair, or equivalent, apportionment

of treatment one receives — socially, juridically, and materially — in

return for what one gives has traditionally been depicted by the balance

or scale Justitia, the Roman goddess, holds in one hand, the sword she

holds in the other, and the blindfold that covers her eyes. Taken

together, the accoutrements of Justitia testify to the quantification of an

equity which can be parcelled out and apportioned on both tables of the

scale; the power of violence that stands behind her judgement in the

form of her sword (under conditions of “civilization,” the sword was

to become the equivalent of the State); the “objectivity” of her views

as expressed by the blindfold.

Elaborate discussions of theories of justice, from Aristotle’s in the

ancient world to those of John Rawls in the modern, need not be

examined here. They involve explorations into natural law, contract,

reciprocity, and egoism — issues that are not of immediate concern to

our exploration. But the blindfold around Justitia’s eyes and the scale

she holds in her hands are symbols of a highly problematic relationship

that we cannot afford to ignore. In the presence of Justitia, all human

beings are presumably “equal.” They stand “naked” before Justitia, to

use a common word, bereft of social privilege, special rights, and status.

The famous “cry for Justice!” has a long and complex pedigree. From

the earliest days of systematic oppression and exploitation, people gave

Justitia a voice — blindfold or not — and made her the spokesperson

of the downtrodden against unfeeling inequity and violations of the

principle of equivalence.

Initially, Justitia was pitted against the tribal canon of blood vengeance, of unreasoning retribution for the harm inflicted on one’s kin. The

famous *lex talionis* — an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth, a life for a

life — was applied exclusively for losses inflicted on one’s relatives,

not to people in general. Rational as the demand for tribal equity may

seem in its command for equivalence of treatment, this principle was

parochial and restricted. No one stood up for the stranger who was

abused or killed — apart from his or her kin in a distant territory.

Punishment, in turn, was often very arbitrary. More than one life was

commonly claimed for crimes that existed only in the eyes of the

beholder, with the harsh result that blood feuds could go on for

generations, claiming entire communities and people who were patently innocent of infractions that had long faded from the memory of the combatants.

The highly debated meaning of Aeskylos’s *Orestaeia* — a dramatic

Greek trilogy in which tribal vengeance for the murder of a mother by

her son in retribution for the death she inflicted on his father — has

several different themes. Important among them was the higher sense

of obligation a son (as well as a daughter) had to a mother under a

system of so-called matriarchal law, in which women, rather than men,

presumably formed the socially recognized knots of kinship and ancestry

But no less important as a theme — and possible more so for classical Athenians,

who prized this trilogy justice out of an archaic world of crude, unreasoning vengeance into a

domain of rational and objective equity: to render justice “equal and exact.”

Which is not to say that justice had its origins in Greece. In the period

following the transition from tribal societies to feudal aristocracies and

absolute monarchies, the cry for justice — indeed, for written codes of

law that clearly spelled out penalties for crimes — became a major

demand of the oppressed. Equivalence in the form of justice “equal and

exact” was slowly shorn of its class biases, be it in the Hebrew

Deuteronomic Code or the reforms of Solon in Athens. Roman law, the

basis for much of modern Western jurisprudence, sophisticated early

popular gains enormously, acknowledging in the *jus naturale* and the

were rendered unequal by society. Even chattel slavery was acknowledged as a “contract” of sorts in which a slave, whose life could have

been claimed in warfare, was kept alive if he forfeited his body and

labour to the victor.

What is problematic about justice “equal and exact,” however, is

that all people are *not* equal naturally, despite the *formal* equality that

is conferred upon them in a “just” society. Some individuals are born

physically strong; others may be born weaker, by comparison. Still

others differ markedly from each other by virtue of health, age, infirmities, talent, intelligence, and the material means of life at their

disposal. These differences may be either trivial or highly important in

terms of the demands that are imposed upon them in everyday life.

Ironically, then, the notion of equality can be used subtly for dealing

with people on highly unequal terms: the same burdens are imposed on

very disparate individuals who have very different abilities to deal with

them. The rights they acquire, “equal and exact” as they may be,

become meaningless for those who cannot exercise them because of

physical or material liabilities. Justice thus becomes very unequal in

substance precisely because it is established in mere *form*. An *inequality of equals* may emerge from a society that deals with everyone

as juridically equal, that is, without regard for his or her physical and

mental condition.

So-called egalitarian tribal societies actually recognized that such

major inequalities did exist and tried to find *compensatory* mechanisms

to establish substantive equality. The principle of the irreducible minimum, for example, created a bedrock basis for overcoming economic

disparities that, in modern society, make many people who are formally

equal highly unequal in substance. Everyone, irrespective of his or her

status, capacities, or even willingness to contribute materially to the

community, was entitled to the basic means of life. These means could

not be denied to anyone who was a member of the community.

Whenever possible, special treatment was given to the infirm, the

elderly, and the weak to “equalize” their material position and to

minimize their feelings of dependency. There is evidence that such care

goes back to Neandethal communities some fifty thousand years ago.

Skeletal remains have been found of a mature man who was seriously

handicapped at birth and whose survival would not have been possible

without the special attention he received from his community. Certainly

on the level of economic life, the guiding maxim of justice — the

inequality of equals — had not yet fully emerged. Preliterate peoples

seem to have been guided by another maxim — the *equality of unequals*

— a maxim that forms the foundations for the ideal of freedom.

The attempt to equalize unavoidable inequalities, to compensate at

nearly every level of life for lacks produced by circumstances over

which one has no control — be it a physical impairment of any kind or

even a lack of rights because of shortcomings that may arise for a host

of inescapable factors — forms the point of departure for a free society.

I speak, here, not only of the obvious compensatory mechanisms that

come into play when an individual is ill or impaired. I speak of attitudes

as well; indeed, of an outlook that manifests itself in a sense of care,

responsibility, and a decent concern for human and nonhuman beings

whose suffering, plight, and difficulties can be lightened or removed

by our intervention. The concept of the equality of unequals may rest

on emotional determinants such as a sense of sympathy, community,

and a tradition that evokes a sense of solidarity; indeed, even an

aesthetic sense that finds beauty in nature and freedom in wilderness.

The basically libertarian notion that what often passes for justice “exact

and equal” is inadequate — indeed, that it may doom countless people

to underprivileged lives or worse, because of factors that can be

remedied by rational means — is the cornerstone of freedom conceived

as an ethics. To “freely” realize one’s potentialities and achieve fulfillment presupposes that these very potentialities *are* realizable because

society lives by an ethic of the equality of unequals.

Let me stress the word “ethic,” here. Preliterate communities lived

by the maxim of the equality of unequals as a matter of *custom* — as a

dim form of inherited tradition. Owing to their parochialism, moreover,

custom applied exclusively to members of the community, not to

“outsiders.” Viewed against the broad landscape of early society,

preliterate peoples were as vulnerable to onslaughts against their customs as they were to invasions by technically more sophisticated

communities. It was not very difficult to shatter customs like the

equality of unequals and to replace them with systems of privilege that

lacked even the notion of justice. Once customary freedoms had been

destroyed, the “cry for justice” came to the forefront — a poor but

necessary substitute for the unbridled power of nobles and kings. Moral

injunctions, later to be formulated into laws, began to confine their

power. Biblical prophets, particularly the anarchic Amos, cast not only

rhetorical thunderbolts against the privileged and the kings of Judah;

they also extended the boundaries of unthinking custom, based on

tradition, into the domain of *morality*.

No longer were the oppressed obliged to find the authority for the

redress of injustice in the dim mists of tradition. They could establish

moral codes, based on already existing systems of authority, to retain

the limited rights they claimed. But no serious attempt was made to

formulate these rights in rational terms, that is to say, to turn them into

a coherent ethics that lent itself to reason and discourse.

For many centuries, then, justice remained a moral concern which

took the form of quasi-religious, often outright supernatural, commandments rather than discursive judgements. “Equal and exact” meant

precision, not a reasoned case for right and wrong. Indeed, right and

wrong were said to be ordained from the heavens and treated more often

as “virtue” and “sin” than as “just” and “unjust.” We must turn mainly

to the Greeks and Romans — and as much to their philosophers as to

their jurists — to find reasoned debates in the secular language of the

real world around justice and, eventually, freedom.

It was among these thinkers that justice, conceived as a rational and

secular affair, was to take the form of an ethical problem. People began

to reason out the differences between just and unjust acts, not simply

adopt them as moral injunctions by a deity or inherit them as a

time-honoured custom. Freedom, in turn, began to emerge not only as

a wistful longing but as an ever-expansive body of ideas, sophisticated

by critique and by thoughtful projects to remake society. A new realm

of evolution was initiated which was not only natural and social but

also ethical and emancipatory. Ideals of freedom began to become part

of the evolution of the good society and, in our own time, of an

ecological society.

Myth

I have drawn a fairly sharp distinction between custom, morality,

and ethics because the ideals of freedom over the course of history were

to take very different forms when they began to advance from a

traditional to a prescriptive, and finally, to a rational outlook.

These distinctions are not merely matters of historical interest.

Today, justice has become more entangled with freedom than at any

time in the recent past, so that mere reforms are often unthinkingly

confused with radical social change. Attempts to achieve a just society

that involve little more than corrective alterations in a basically irrational society are becoming muddled with attempts to achieve a free

society that involve fundamental social reconstruction. Present-day

society, in effect, is not being remade; it is being *modified* by means of

cosmetic alterations rather than basic changes. Reforms in the name of

justice are being advanced, in effect, to *manage* a profound and growing

crisis rather than eliminate it.

No less troubling is the fact that reason, with its demands for

fundamental critique, analyses, and intellectual coherence, is being

subverted by “pop” moralizing, often of a blatantly religious character,

while mystical mythmaking is invading even moral interpretations of

freedom, evoking primitivistic and potentially reactionary images of

liberation. These atavistic tendencies are usually personally oriented

rather than socially oriented. Personal therapy is replacing politics

under the aegis of “self-liberation”; mythmaking is mingling with

religion to produce luxuriant growth of mystical exotica. All taken together,

are being thrown against rationality in the name of cosmic

“Oneness” — a “night,” to use Hegel’s expression, “in which all cows

are black.”

The regressive character of this development deserves careful

scrutiny. Early ideas of freedom were confined to a mythopoeic imagination. Their realization was doomed to failure largely because they

lived in dreamlike fantasies of a return to a “golden age” that was

beyond recovery, because of the extent to which even early humanity

was separated from a presumed state of pristine animality. It was only

in myths, such as Homer’s Island of the Lotus-eaters, that we fancifully

imagined a condition where nature completely prevails and animality

completely permeates the human community so that even memory is

effaced. The placidity of the Lotus-eaters, who have no will and no

sense of identity, divests them of any past or future in its timeless

immediacy and seemingly “natural” eternality. Odysseus’s seamen,

who are ordered to reconnoitre the island, are received “kindly” and

served “the honeyed fruit of the lotus,” which deprives them “of any

desire to return or send word” to their ship. Not only are they content

to stay” and allow themselves to be sedated; they become “forgetful of

home” and of themselves as individuated beings. Like modern-day

offspring of the therapeutic and mystical age, they have no “self” to

fulfill because they possess no “self” to be evoked.

This mythic fantasy of prehistory and of a lost harmony with nature

that is more vegetative than even animalistic, is a libel on human beings

as a whole — beings that possess intellect as well as physiological

functions and a sense of the “ought-to-be” as well as the “is,” That mind

and body have been wrongly thrown into sharp opposition to each other

by religion as well as philosophy does not remove the fact that they are

different from each other in very marked ways.

None of these remarks are meant to deny that humanity did live in

harmony with nature in varying degrees in the past. But that harmony

was never so *static*, so *timeless*, and so divested of *development* as it

corresponds to the world of the Lotus-eaters in all its variations in

different myths. Here, the utterly arbitrary character of myth, its lack

of any critical correction by reason, delivers us to complete falsehoods.

Viewed from a primitivistic viewpoint, “freedom” takes on the

treacherous form of an absence of desire, activity, and will

condition so purposeless that humanity ceases to be capable of reflecting upon itself rationally and thereby preventing emerging ruling elites

from completely dominating it. In such a mythic — and mystified

world, there would be no basis for being guarded against hierarchy or

for resisting it.

Nor is nature, however pristine and “wild,” so fixed in time, so

lacking in dynamism, and so eternal that it is little more than the scene

one seems to behold from the picture-window of a middle class summer

home. This basically *suburban* image of nature belies its fecundity,

its wealth of change, and its richness of development Nature is turbulently active, even if the Lotus-eaters are not. We shall see, in fact,

that ruling class ideology fosters such static and mindless visions of

paradise all the more to render freedom remote and desire incompatible

with its fulfillment. Indeed, the island of the Lotus-eaters is a regressive

myth of a return to infancy and passivity, when the newly born merely

responds to caresses, a full breast, and is lulled into a sedated receptivity

by an ever-attentive mother. The fact that the earliest word for

“freedom” is *amargi*, the Summerian expression for a “return to

mother” is ambiguous. It may well be as regressive as it is suggestive

of a belief that nature in the past was bountiful and freedom existed

only in the cradle of matricentric society.

That there was a freedom to be *won* by activity, will, and consciousness after society had gone beyond mere custom and that hope was

needed to achieve a new, rational, and ecological dispensation for

humanity and nature had yet to be discovered. Indeed, once the ties

between humanity and nature were severed, this became the harsh work

of history. To retreat back into myth, today, is to lay the basis for a

dangerous quietism that thrusts us beyond the threshold of history into

the dim,often imagined, and largely atavistic world of prehistory. Such

a retreat obliges us to forget history and the wealth of experience it has

to offer. Personality dissolves into a vegetative state that antedates

animal development and nature’s evolutionary thrust toward greater

sensibility and subjectivity. Thus, even “first nature” is libeled,

degraded, and denied its own rich dynamic in favour of a frozen and

static image of the natural world where the richly coloured evolution

of life is painted in washed-out pastels, bereft of form, activity, and

self-directiveness.

Such vegetative images of a “golden age” — and they are being

revived today, by mystics in American, English, and central European

ecology movements — did not simply spring from the oppressed in

history. It is true that, as tribal life gave way to “civilization” in the Near

East, Egypt, and Asia, a sense of loss and a wistful look backward to a

forsaken garden of Eden permeated the utopian dreams of the underclasses, People spoke longingly of an age when the lion and the lamb

lay side by side and nature provided a harmonized humanity with all

the means of life. The human condition was conceived in terms of a

golden era that was followed by a less paradisial silver one, finally

descending into an iron age that ushered in conflict, injustice, and

warfare — only to be repeated again into eternity like the seasons of

the year. There was very little conception of history in a truly developmental sense — merely degeneration, recovery, and continual repetition.

Let there be no mistake, however, that this imagery was advanced

only by the oppressed. The belief in a purely passive relationship with

nature and nonhuman beings more easily served the interests of ruling

elites in history than it did the ruled, however often it was evoked in

the day dreams of oppressed peoples. In the first place, these images

remained nothing more than day dreams — myths that functioned as

safety valves, for the very real discontents of the dominated, and

deflected active attempts to change the world into cathartic rituals and

sedated longings. Hoarded up by priests and priestesses, they were

served out as carefully choreographed dramas to the beat of drums and

the noise of flutes, enacting in controlled rituals the anger that might

have overflowed into action and basic social change. No society ever

returned to its “golden” past; indeed, the imagery of an inevitable cycle,

with its specious promise of an “eternal return,” reinforced the priestly

manipulation of passive congregants.

Even more ironically, the image of a lost “golden age” was used to

justify the tyranny of the “iron age.” Priest, priestess, and noble combined to explain the loss of a “golden age” as humanity’s penalty for a

fall from grace. Be it an Eve who induced Adam to eat the fruit of the

tree of knowledge or a Pandora who opened the box that contained the

ills that were to afflict humanity, paradise or the “golden age” was lost

— so it was claimed — because humanity or its surrogates violated its

covenant with supernatural power. Misery, in effect, had been brought

upon humanity by its own failings, or by hubris—not by the emergence

of hierarchy, property, the State, and ruling elites.

Indeed, rule it is various forms was needed to discipline an unruly

humanity that lacked the sense of obedience needed to maintain an

orderly world. Hence, we encounter a remarkable persistence of

retrospective myths of a “golden age” not only in the myths of the

oppressed but in the literature of their oppressors. That myth was

cannily used to justify the domination of women in the Pandora story

and the domination of men in the *Odyssey* (a truly aristocratic epic in

which the next island Odysseus encounters after leaving the Lotus-eaters is the island of the harshly patriarchal Cyclopes), reveals that the

drama is surprisingly gender-blind in its treatment of subjugation. Men

are no less victims of the various demonic beings who rule the islands

Odysseus encounters — each of which seems to be a mythic epoch —

than are women.

The gropings of Greek rationalism toward a sense of history — of

advances forward rather than returns backward — are far more radical

than images based on false notions of a cyclic and basically static

nature Thukidides’s history of the Greek people in the opening portions

of *The Peloponnesian War* is impeccably secular and naturalistic. No

myths burden this matter-of-fact account of the emergence of the *polis*

and the settlement of the Greek homeland. Centuries later, Diodorus

Siculus is distinctly realistic in his history of humanity’s evolution from

prehistory into history, a drama of changes that break the bonds of myth,

cycles, and parochialism. It is not even the Greeks alone who claim

Diodorus’s attention, but “the race of all human beings and their history

parts of the inhabited earth.”

Christianity, despite its ambivalences and its retreat from the

secularism of the Greek chroniclers, brought a sense of hi story, futurity,

and redemption to masses who were captive to cycles of eternal return.

That Christian fathers like Augustine invoked the Fall from innocence

in the Garden of Eden was only to be expected from a religion that

plainly adapted itself to authority and the Roman State. But its own

origins as a popular, even a rebellious Judaic movement, mired it in

inconsistency that left it open to radical as well as conservative interpretations. The Jewish religion, for all its transcendental and dualistic

visions of a creator god who is clearly separated from its creation,

removed the deity from social life as well as nature.

As H. and H.A. Frankfort have observed, social problems could now be fought out in

a largely *secular* domain. No longer were they completely entangled

with myth and divine claims to authority. In ancient empires, tyranny

had been immersed in the authority of divinity and the claims of

monarchs to divine sanction. Indeed, a “sacred cosmos” included a

“sacred society,” so that social oppression acquired the mystical properties of nature — a line of thought as Janet Biehl has pointed out,

that has been revived in present-day attempts to treat the natural world

as “sacred” and restore Goddess worship to eminence in a nonsocial,

myth-ridden form of “eco-feminism.”

The Church inherited this transcendental tradition, however much

it tried to modify it. Ernst Bloch was to observe that: “...for the first

time a *political* utopia appears in history [my emphasis]. In fact, it

produces history; history comes to be as *saving history in the direction of the kingdom*, as a single unbroken process extending from Adam to

Jesus on the basis of the Stoic unity of mankind and the Christian

salvation it is destined for,” [12] Utopia, in effect, became an earthbound

vision oriented toward the future rather than the past. Despite its

religious trapping, salvation could be achieved on earth with the return

of Jesus and the sorting out of the evil from the virtuous.

Indeed, the Hebrew scriptures are charged by an activism and a bias

for the oppressed that was virtually unknown to other religions of the

Near East. As the Frankforts point out, Egyptian texts which give an

account of the social upheaval that followed the collapse of the Old

Kingdom of pyramid builders “viewed the disturbance of the established order...with horror.” The power acquired by the oppressed is

evidence “of lamentation and distress... I show thee how the undermost is turned to uppermost” bemoans the chronicler. “The poor man will acquire riches.” By contrast, the Hebrew scriptures deal with social

revolt by the oppressed with exuliance. The birth of the prophet Samuel,

for example, is celebrated with the words: “The bows of the mighty

men are broken, and they that stumbled are girded with strength. They

that were full have hired themselves out for bread; and they that were

hungry ceased.” The poor are raised “out of the dust” and beggars are

lifted “from the dunghill, to set them among princes, and to make them

inherit the throne of glory...” [13]

Not only are the mentally numbing effects of myth shaken off, like

the lethargic after-effects of a powerful sedative; its fixity and conservatism are replaced by a sense of the dynamic and temporal that yields

increasingly expansive ideals of freedom. The Joachimites, one of the

most subversive tendencies in medieval Christianity, break away radically from the cloudy and calculated vagueness of official scriptural

history, and provocatively divide it into distinct *epochs* of human

liberation. Even more important than the great chiliastic popular movements, like half-crazed ascetics such as the Flaggelants and the Shepherds or *Pastoreaux*, who were to aimlessly attack the clergy and

Jews in their wanderings, were monks like Joachim of Floris who were

to lay the bases for more lasting libertarian tendencies. Writing in the

twelfth century, Joachim, a Cistercian abbot of Corazzo, a Calabrian

town in Italy, reworked the trinity, a largely mystical unity of the deity’s

triune nature, into a radical chronology. The Old Testament was said

to represent the era of the Father; the New, of the Son; and the Holy

Ghost was a “Third Kingdom,” yet to come, a world without masters

in which people would live in harmony, irrespective of their religious

beliefs, and a bountiful nature would supply the means of life for all.

From the fourteenth century in England to the sixteenth century in

Germany — including the Hussite wars in Bohemia, which produced

stormy communistic movements like the extreme Taborites—peasants

and artisans fought valiantly in chronic insurrections to retain their

communal, guild, and localist rights. Conservative as they seem in the

light of “modernity,” with its harsh urban, technological, and individualistic values, this centuries-long tide of unremitting conflict gave to freedom a *moral meaning* that it has lost in our own era of “scientific socialism” and narrow economistic analyses.

During the centuries that culminated in the Protestant Reformation,

religion became increasingly earth-bound and less supernatural than it

had been in the past, despite its abiding influence on peasant and artisan

movements. By the time of the English Revolution of the 1640s, the

democratic Levellers were largely secular in their outlook and derided

Cromwell’s opportunistic pieties. It was not Christianity as much as it

was a naturalistic pantheism (if a theism of any sort it could be called)

that influenced the thinking of communistic revolutionaries like Gerrard Winstanlcy, who led the small Digger movement in the English

civil wars of the 1650s.

Freedom, a relatively exotic word by comparison with the cry for

justice, had acquired a distinctly realistic content. Men and women

began to fight not only for freedom of religion but also for freedom

from religion. They began to fight not only against specific forms of

domination, but also against domination *as such* and for freedom to the

means of life in a communitarian society. Activism began to replace

the vegetative placidity of a wistful reverence of the past. Morality

began to efface custom; naturalism began to edge out supematuralism;

opposition to ecclesiastical hierarchy began to produce opposition to

civil hierarchy. A refreshing sense of development began to replace the

Fixity of mythopoesis, its repetitive rituals, and the atavistic grip of a

dark superstitious past on the present and future.

Reason

If there is a single fact which marks the expansion of the ideals of

freedom, it is the extent to which they were nourished by reason.

Contrary to popular histories of philosophy, religion, and morality,

rationalism had never been abandoned in the closing centuries of the

ancient world and in the Middle Ages. Despite the infestation of the

late Roman Empire by the Isis cult and ascetic religions from the East,

the Hellenic effort to give a rational interpretation of the world was not

only retained but it slowly became differentiated into new interpretations of what constituted reason.

Indeed, we today live in a paralysing ignorance of the different kinds

of logic and rationalism that thinkers developed well into our own time.

The notion that there is only one kind of reason—a fairly static, formal,

and basically syllogistic logic of the kind assembled by Aristotle in his

developmental and organic kind of reason in his other writings. Formal

kinds of reason were modelled on mathematics, particularly geometry.

Organic, or shall we say, *dialectical* reason, on the other hand, stressed

phenomena from generalized, nascent, indeed seed-like, beginnings

into richly developed wholes rather than the schematic deduction of

fixed conclusions based on rigidly stated premises. In short, a richly

speculative, organic dialectic co-existed with the formal, commonsensical logic we use for matter-of-fact problems in everyday life.

Theology was, if anything, an attempt to rationally understand the

ways of the creator-deity in his interaction with his creation, particularly with humankind. In the “Age of Faith” or medieval world, both

systems of thought were used to explicate a good deal more than faith

to which, ironically, mysticism turned more readily, in its wistful

longing for a long-gone innocence, than clerical scholasticism. Francis

of Assisi felt deeply for the suffering of the poor and, more problematically, saw in-nonhuman life-forms a tribute primarily to the glory of a

creator-god. But the Franciscan order was very easily co-opted by the

Papacy and, in inquisitorial times, turned from persecuted into persecutor, including the persecution of its own Joachimite acolytes. Innocence, intuition, and atavistic longings — our modern mystics to

the contrary — are not strong barriers to manipulation. It was often keen

thinkers like Galileo who were silenced by house arrest and speculative

rationalists like Bruno who were burned at the stake by the Inquisition

rather than mystics like Francis or Meister Eckhart.

My point, however, is that reason is not cut from a single cloth. In

its dialectical form, reason imparts a sense of history, development, and

process to thinking, not ‘‘linear; I propositional, and syllogistic means

and analyses. Similarly, the early glimmerings of an organismic approach to the world, not a mechanistic one, also began to revive with

explorations into biology as well as physics. Evolution was already in

the air as early as the Fifteenth century, if we are to judge from Leonardo

da Vinci’s writings on the marine fossils that were found in inland

mountains, and his remarks that, in an ever-changing world, the Po river

will eventually “lay dry land in the Adriatic in the same way it has

already deposited a great part of Lombardy.” By the eighteenth century,

evolution was an accepted fact among the French *philosophes*, thanks

to the work of Maupertuis, Diderot, and Buffon.

The recovery of the body, the claims of the sensuous, the right to

physical pleasure — not merely a restful happiness — began to raise a

major challenge to ascetism, not simply of the kind advanced by official

Christianity, but also by its radical spiritualists. The belief, so widely

held by the poor, that the privileged should share with them in a

presumably god-given fund of misery and self-denial, was steadily

undermined by ordinary people themselves. The joys of the body and

the full satisfaction of material needs were increasingly seen in Renaissance times as a heavenly dispensation. Lusty utopias like the land of

Cockaygne, in which toil was unknown and roasted partridges dropped

into one’s lap, began to abound among the masses, often in marked

contrast to the monastic lifeways of denial preached by their mystical

leaders.

Unlike radical millenarians, or even Joachimites, the masses did not

place these utopias in some distant future or in the heavens above. They

existed geographically in the West, off the known maps of the Renaissance; and they were worlds to be discovered by *active* exploration, not

by the lazy play of one’s imagination. Indeed, it was not always the

rationalistic Christian scholastics who posed the most serious obstacles

to this naturalistic trend, but rather medieval mystics like Fra

Savonarola, the monkish voice of the oppressed, who burned the

artworks of Florence and preached a fiery gospel of self-denial.

By comparison with the rich differentiation of liberatory ideas and visions

that appeared as the “Age of Reason” approached, the movements

of the oppressed by the likes of Pastoreaux, Flaggelants, and even

the Joachimites seem faltering and wayward. Unscrambling the more

secular threads of Greek rationalism that had been entangled by Christian and Islamic theology, the Renaissance provided a voice for richly

speculative and critical ideas.

What is important is that the best of these ideas, whether they are

presented in systematic tracts, dialogues, or imaginary utopias, are

amazingly all-sided. They are not only rational (even dialectically so)

but sensuous; they advance a message of a new society in which

everything human is basically good and should be afforded full expression.

From a social viewpoint, they are *ecological* in the sense that they are

fully participatory: all aspects of experience play a complementary role

in making a richly differentiated whole. The human body is given

citizenship in these new eco-communities no less than the mind; the

organic, no less than the inorganic; passion, no less than reason; nature,

no less than society; women, no less than men. However time-bound

they may sometimes seem from the perspective of our own ideas of

modernity, no part of the human and natural landscape seems to escape

critical investigation and efforts at reconstruction. They penetrate not

only into social organization, culture, morality, technology, and political institutions, but into family relations, education, the status of

women, and the most mundane features of everyday life. Like the

Renaissance and the Enlightenment themselves, everything is brought

up before the bar of reason and is rejected or justified in terms of its

value to an emerging secularity and naturalism.

That thinkers can hardly hope to go much beyond their time should

not surprise us. We need a true generosity of spirit to appreciate the

expansiveness of their ideas — given the periods in which they lived.

It is one of the great truths of dialectical wisdom that all great ideas,

limited as they may seem to their own time and inadequate as they may

appear in ours, lose their relativity when they are viewed as part of an

ever-differentiating whole — just as a block of marble ceases to be a

piece of mere mineral matter when it is sculpted into a magnificent

structure. Seen within the larger whole of which it is a part, it can no

longer be viewed as a mere mineral, anymore than the atoms that make

up a living organism can be viewed as mere particles. With life emerges

metabolism, a phenomenon that never existed on the inorganic level,

and one that can never be imputed to an atom, much less to its

electromagnetic properties.

So the thinkers of the liberatory, indeed revolutionary, tradition must

be appreciated as much for what they add to our lime as they did to their

own if the abiding character of their work is to be grasped.

Thus, we can distinguish several great tendencies in the expanding

ideals of freedom: first, a commitment to the *existing* world, to *secular*

reality, not to one that exists in the heavens or lies off the map of the

known world. I am not saying, by this, that the radical theorists,

utopists, and ideologists of the Renaissance, Enlightenment, and the

early part of the last century conformed “realistically” to the world in

which they lived. On the contrary, they tried in the best of cases to see

far beyond it and they tried to rest their ideals on the best features of

the times in which they lived.

Which brings us to the second tendency they expressed: the need for

a *carefully structured* society that was free of the explosions produced

by unruly nobles in England and on the European continent. The

Renaissance, particularly the aristocracy of the age, had thrown society

into a condition of chronic warfare. Amidst the ruins left by the Wars

of the Roses in England and the religious wars in central Europe, no

humane society could be conceived of by radical social theorists and

utopists other than one that was totally stable and almost machine-like

in the cooperative symmetry of its operations. Long before Descartes

had made mechanism into a philosophical world view, explosive social

dislocations made it into a radical desideratum. That many utopists had

taken the well-regulated monastery as their model is radical in itself;

they could have easily opted for the centralized nation-states aborning

in their midst, as was to happen in the nineteenth century within the

socialist movement. If a “planned economy” was needed in their time,

partly to countervail the chaotic behaviour of the nobles, partly to

control the depredations of an emerging commercial bourgeoisie on the

peasantry and urban poor, the traditional and socially responsible rules

adopted by the monastery for the conduct of everyday life seemed more

ethical and humane than other alternatives. Only later, in the nineteenth

century, and to some degree earlier, would an orderly society and a

“planned economy” be identified with the centralized nation-state; this,

ironically, in the name of a value-free notion of “scientific socialism”

and attempts to achieve a “nationalized” economy.

A third tendency that contributed to the expanding ideals of freedom

in the radical thought of the Renaissance and, again, in the Enlightenment, was the high esteem that was placed on *work(. Not only did

Thomas More, Tommaso Campanella, Valentin Andreae, and Francis

Bacon, among others, impart an honoured role to the artisan and food

cultivator, but Denis Diderot brought their crafts and their contributions

to society into the pages of the French *Encyclopedia*, where they are

given almost unprecedented attention, and their skills are explored in

breath-taking detail. Kropotkin cites a medieval ordinance which

declares: “Everyone must be pleased with his work, and no one shall,

while doing nothing, appropriate for himself what others have produced

by application and work, because laws must be a shield for applications

and work.” [14] This constellation of traditions and ideas has no precedent

in antiquity and was to be honoured in the breach during the Industrial

Revolution. Indeed, deeply humane values permeated the mixed

economy of peasants, artisans, freeholders, and proletarians in the

centuries that immediately preceded the ascendancy of industrial

capitalism in England. Even limits to toil were imposed in this dim,

often little-understood era. As the late Marie-Louise Bemeri was to

observe in her searching work, *Journey Through Utopia*:

The Utopian idea of a short working day which to us, accustomed to think of the past in terms of the nineteenth century,
seems a very radical one, does not appear such an innovation,
if it is compared with an ordinance of Ferdinand the First
relative to the Imperial coal mines, which settled the miner’s
day at eight hours. And according to Thorold Rogers, in
fifteenth century England men worked forty-eight hours a
week.[15]

Lastly, among the tendencies that surface in this mixed society,

particularly during the Renaissance, is the high premium that is placed

on *community*. This was an era that was directly faced with the

disintegration of villages and towns by an ever-growing and atomizing

market place. The unruly bourgeois-**cum**-burgher had to be controlled.

He assailed not only the fragile bonds that held people together in a

shared communal interest, but he also threatened its guilds, religious

societies that cared for the poor and ill, its extended family ties, and its

high values of human solidarity. To the extent that everything came up

for grabs, from common land to kinship responsibilities, radical

theorists and utopists tightened their muscles — and their vision —

against the asocial behaviour of the new bourgeois and the money

oriented aristocrat.

We must not think too harshly, then, of Thomas More for trying to

retain strong family ties in his *Utopia* and holding fast to Catholic

orthodoxy in the face of a rambunctious monarch, Henry VIII, whose

“reformation” replaced the hat of the bishop of Rome with the crown

of an English king. More, like so many of his Renaissance contemporaries, leaned more toward a humanistic ecumene as expressed by

the principle of the papacy than the nationalism as expressed by a

parochial monarch. Indeed, More’s reservations about a monarchical

dispensation for his ideal society are expressed through Hythloday, the

narrator of *Utopia* who speaks for its author, in a very pointed comment;

“...most princes apply themselves to affairs of war than to the useful

arts of peace; and in these I neither have any knowledge, nor do I much

desire it; they are generally set on acquiring new kingdoms, right or

wrong, than on governing those they possess...”

Even more far-reaching than More’s ideal society is Valentin

Andreae’s “Christianopolisa severely moral community that places

stringent regulations on behaviour, albeit with a deeply humane attitude

toward human needs and suffering. “Christianopolis” is indeed a polis

— a humanly scaled city with clearly defined walls, not a nation-state.

But it is highly standardized in its dwellings and its almost mathematical division of functions, zones, and its balance between industry and

agriculture. None of these utopias are based on private property —

another monastic feature — and they distribute the means of life

according to need. Whether they are described as islands as in the case

of “Utopia” or communities as in the case of “Christianopolis,” they

are really cities, and they have ascetic qualities, however well their

populations live. These significantly prenational and precapitalistic

traits must not be overlooked; the monastic ideal of service, work,

sharing, and regimentation in the interests of a visible community good

pervade the radical thinking of the day, particularly among the utopists. They appear in Tommaso Campanella’s “City of the Sun,” in which

women enjoy an unusually high status, with its Platonistic eugenics and

the emphasis that is given to the natural sciences. The orderly, work-oriented, and literate world they offer is a tight meld between medieval

tradition and modern innovation. The social theorists and utopists of

the Renaissance were fascinated by the possibilities for human improvement opened by science, as evident in Francis Bacon’s sketchy

“New Atlantis” I which strongly emphasized the role of education in

remaking society.

These themes — particularly, enlightenment through learning, the

application of reason and order to human affairs, a keen fascination

with science and a high regard for work — were to extend into the

Enlightenment of the eighteenth century. By now, the nation-state had

clearly established itself and the city had ceased to be the basic unit for

radical innovation. With Montesquieu, who sets the tone for the century, political institutions began to supplant property concerns, family

relationships, and cultural issues. It is interesting to note that the

communistic programs advanced by the Abbe Mably and Morelly are

completely marginal to the work of the *philosophes*; indeed, to this day,

we do not even know Morelly’s first name and his influence was very

limited until we arrive at the closing years of the French Revolution,

when apparently his *Code of Nature* was read by Gracchus Babeuf, the

ill-fated leader of the “Conspiracy of Equals.”

The Enlightenment was more particularized than the Renaissance,

when entire disciplines were created by single individuals with a

flourish of a pen, and it was more oriented toward individual rights than

the preservation of community. Its engagement with ecclesiastical

‘authority and a hierarchically structured body politic made the

monastery an anachronism at best and anathema at worst. Indeed, more

psychological than rationalistic. Enlightenment thinkers were often

preoccupied with human nature, not only human reason. Both Diderot

and Rousseau, perhaps the era’s most important figures, were men of

“heart” as well as brilliant minds, and spontaneous passion played as

much a role in their works as reason.

Anarchy and Libertarian Utopias

From beneath the surface interchange of radical ideas between the

sixteenth and eighteenth centuries, several issues came into sharp

confrontation with each other. Could material well-being for people in

a time of profound economic distress be acquired only at the expense

of the individual’s subordination to a well-ordered society, based on

monastic discipline and, later, on state authority? Could equality in

material things be purchased by surrendering freedom to compulsory

economic plans? Did a full, sensuous, even playful, way of life endanger the need for all to work, a need that had nourished the ascetism

that afflicts so many utopias and radical ideas about society? Was

abundance for all possible in a time that had yet to prove it could meet

the most elementary needs of life? And to what extent could men, not

to mention women, create a lively, participatory political culture while

working eight or even less hours at demanding tasks to satisfy their

basic material needs? For all the moral admonitions that the ideals of

that extraordinary time advance, most of the visions they embody are

patently shaped by questions of this kind. It is simply impossible to

understand their possibilities and limitations without taking these questions into account.

But amidst the drift from city to nation, from monastery to state,

from ethics to politics, from communal property to private property,

and from an artisanal world to an industrial world, a fascinating

combination of visions emerged that often contained the best — and

the worst — of these sweeping social antinomies, I use the word

“antinomies” advisedly rather than “changes” because I am speaking

of seemingly contradictory *co-existents*, few of which fully supplanted

the earlier ones in the minds of nineteenth century radical thinkers.

Indeed, as we shall see, they have re-emerged again, today, as highly

modified demands in an entirely new synthesis of ideas under the rubric

of social ecology. It is true that paired each against the other, certain

radical theorists were to choose one over the other in many cases.

Marxism, for example, distinctly chose the nation over the city and the

State over the self-disciplined monastic commonwealth advanced particularly by Andreae, whose views often anticipate Robert Owen’s “industrial village.”

But other forms of radical thought were to emerge and develop a

synthesis for their own time — one of rapid industrialization and

urbanization — and give rise to a rich legacy of ideas that radicals can

no longer ignore. And the time has come to examine that legacy, free

from a biased sense of partisanship that stems more from petty factional

hatreds than serious reflection.

I refer to the libertarian utopias and the expressly anarchist ideas that

appeared in the nineteenth century: traditions that advanced ideals of

freedom that were as rational as they were ethical and as self-reflective

as they were passionate. One cannot simply ignore the compelling

analyses that were advanced by William Godwin’s *Enquiry Concerning Social Justice*, the corpus of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon’s writings, the

incisive critiques of Michael Bakunin, the reconstructive work of Peter

Kropotkin, particularly his far-reaching ecological insights, and the

utopian visions of Robert Owen and Charles Fourier without forfeiting

the rational and moral wealth of ideas that enter into their works from

centuries of liberatory struggles and hopes.

Nor can they be dealt with as visionary “precursors” — or worse,

ideological protagonists — of Karl Marx and “scientific socialism.”

One might with equal arrogance dismiss the naturalism of Aristotle for

the philosophical idealism of Hegel, or the historical work of

Thukidides for that of Charles Beard. At most, all of these thinkers

complement each other; at the very least, they illuminate important

problems where they do conflict, each spawned by a different social

condition in a drama of history that is *still* unfolding.

The course of human development has no more moved in clearly

defined and necessarily “progressive” stages than has the history of

human ideas. If we were to return to a more decentralized society, an

Aristotle and a Thukidides would be more relevant to our concerns

because of their stored wisdom of the Greek *poleis* is than a Hegel or

Beard, who were concerned with nation-states. We have yet to fully

assess the meaning of human history, the paths it should have followed,

and the ideas that are most appropriate in the remaking of society based

on reason and ecological principles.

The radical theorists and utopists following upon the French Revolution exhibited more expansive ideals of freedom than their predecessors

in the Enlightenment — and they were to sum up a sweeping body of

alternatives to the course followed by history; alternatives that were

naively ignored by their socialist successors.

Both of these legacies are of immense importance for modern

radicalism — the expansiveness of their ideals and the alternatives that

confronted humanity. The anarchist thinkers and libertarian utopists

were deeply sensitive to *choices* that could have been made in redirecting human society along rational and liberatory lines. They raised the

far-reaching questions of whether community and individuality could

be brought into harmony with each other; whether the nation was the

necessary, indeed the ethical, successor to the community or *commune*;

whether the State was the unavoidable successor to city and regional

confederations; whether the communal use of resources had to be

supplanted by private ownership; whether the artisanal production of

goods and small, humanly scaled, agricultural operations were destined

by “historical necessity” to be abandoned for giant assembly lines and

mechanized systems of agribusiness. Finally, they raised the question

of whether ethics had to give way to statecraft and what would be the

destiny of politics if it tried to adapt itself to centralized states.

They saw no contradictions between material well being and a

well-ordered society, between substantive equality and freedom, or

between sensuousness, play, and work. They envisioned a society

where abundance would be possible and a gender-blind political culture

would emerge as the working week, superfluous production, and excessive consumption diminished. These questions, anticipated nearly

two centuries ago and infused by the moral fervour of more than two

thousand years of heretical movements like the Joachimites, have

surfaced in the late twentieth century with a vengeance. Words like

“precursors” have become simply meaningless from the standpoint of

a crisis-ridden society like our own which must re-evaluate the *entire*

history of ideas and the alternatives opened by social history in the past.

What is immediately striking about their work is their acute sense of

the alternatives to the abuses of their day and to the abuses of our own.

We cannot ignore the differences that distinguish the anarchist

theorists and the libertarian utopists of the last century from those of a

more distant past Anarchic tendencies such as the primitive Christians,

the radical Gnostics, the medieval Brotherhood of Free Spirit, the

Joachimites, and the Anabaptists viewed freedom more as a result of a

supernaturalistic visitation than as the product of human activity. This

basically passive-receptive mentality, based on mystical underpinnings, is crucial. That certain premodern tendencies in the anarchic

tradition *did* act to change the world does not alter the fact that even

their very actions were seen as the expression of a theistic preordination, In their eyes, action stemmed from the transmutation of the deity’s

will into human will. It was the product of a social alchemy that was

possible because of a supernatural decision, not because of human

autonomy. The “philosopher’s stone” of change in this early approach

reposed in heaven, not on earth. Freedom had to “come,” as it were,

from agents that were suprahuman, be they a “second coming” of Christ

or the preachings of a new messiah. Generally, in accord with Gnostic

thinking, there were always elites like “psychics” who were free of evil

or leaders blessed with moral perfection. History, in effect, was as much

of a clock as it was a Joachimite chronicle: it ticked away a form of

metaphysical time until the sins of the world became so intolerable that

they activated the deity, who no longer forswore his creation as well as

the suffering of the poor, deprived, and oppressed.

The Renaissance, Enlightenment, and, above all, the nineteenth

century, radically altered this naive social dispensation. The “Age of

Revolutions,” if we are to properly characterize the period from the late

1770s to the mid-twentieth century, banished supernatural visitations

and a passive-receptive stance by the oppressed from its historical

agenda. The oppressed had to *act* if they wished to free themselves.

They had to make their own history willfully, an incisive concept which

Jean Jacques Rousseau, for all his failings, added to the history of

radical ideas and for which he deserves immortality. The oppressed had

to *reason*. There was no appeal to powers other than their own minds.

The combination of reason and will, of thought and action, of reflection

and intervention, changed the whole landscape of radicalism, divesting

it of its mythic, mystical, religious, and intuitive qualities — which,

regrettably, are beginning to return today in a disempowered and

psychologically therapized world.

The radicalism of the “Age of Revolutions,” however, went further.

The Joachimite treatment of history moves, not unlike the Marxist, to

the drumbeat of an inexorable “final days,” an end, even a Hegelian

absolute, where all that was had to be, in some sense, all that unfolded,

followed the guidance of a “hidden hand,” be it of God, Spirit and the

“cunning of reason” (to use Hegel’s language), or economic interest,

however concealed that interest may have been from those who were

influenced by it. There were no real alternatives to what was, is, or even

would be — as absurd debates about the “inevitability of socialism”

revealed a generation or two ago.

The emphasis of anarchist and libertarian utopists on *choice* in

history was to create a radically new point of departure from the

increasingly teleological visions of religious and later “scientific”

socialisms. In great part, this emphasis explains the attention the

nineteenth century anarchists and libertarian utopists were to place on

individual autonomy, the individual’s capacity to make choices based

on rational and ethical judgements. This view is markedly different

from the liberal tradition with which anarchic views of individuality

have been associated by their opponents, particularly by Marxists.

Liberalism offered the individual a modicum of “freedom,” to be sure,

but one that was constricted by the “invisible hand” of the competitive

marketplace, not by the capacity of free individuals to act according to

ethical considerations. The “free entrepreneur” on whom liberalism

modelled its image of individual autonomy was, in fact, completely

trapped in a market collectivity, however “emancipated” he seemed

from the overtly medieval world commune of guilds and religious

obligations. He was the plaything of a “higher law” of market interactions based on competing egos, each of whom cancelled out his egoistic

interests in the formation of a general social interest.

Anarchism and the libertarian utopists never cast the free individual

in this light. The individual had to be free to function as an *ethical* being,

according to anarchist theorists — not as a narrow egoist—in making

rational, hopefully disinterested, choices between rational and irrational alternatives in history. The Marxist canard that anarchism is a product

of liberal or bourgeois “individualism” has its roots in ideologies that

are bourgeois to their very core, such as those based on myths of an

“invisible hand” (liberalism), Spirit (Hegelianism), and economic

determinism (Marxism). The anarchist and libertarian utopist emphasis

on individual freedom meant the emancipation of history itself from an

ahistorical preordination and stressed the importance of ethics in influencing choice. The individual is, indeed, truly free and attains true

individuality when he or she is guided by a rational, humane, and

high-minded notion of the social and communal good.

Finally, anarchist visions of a new world, particularly libertarian

utopias, imply that society can always be remade. Indeed, utopia is, by

definition, the world as it *should* be according to the canons of reason

in contrast to the world as it is, according to the blind, unthinking

interaction of uncomprehending forces. The nineteenth-century anarchist tradition, less graphic and pictorial than the utopists who painted

a canvas of now and detailed images, reasoned out its theories in

accordance with human history, not theological, mystical, or

metaphysical history. The world had always made itself through the

agency of real flcsh-and-blood human beings, facing real choices at

turning points of history. And it could remake itself along proven

alternative lines that confronted people in the past.

Indeed, much of the anarchist tradition is not a “primitivistic”

yearning for the past, as Marxist historians like Hobsbawn would have

us believe, but a recognition of past possibilities that remain unfulfilled,

such as the far-rcaching importance of community, confederation,

self-management of the economy, and a new balance between

humanity and nature. Marx’s famous injunction that the dead should

bury the dead is meaningless, however well-intended it may be, when

the present tries to parody the past. Only the *living* can bury the dead

and they can do so on ly i f they understand what is dead and what is still

living; indeed, what is intensely vital in the body-strewn battlefields of

history.

Herein lies the power of William Godwin’s concern for individual

autonomy, for the ethical person whose mind is unfettered by the social

burdens of suprahuman forces and all forms of domination, including

deities as well as statesmen, the authority of custom as well as the

authority of the State. Herein, too, lies the power of Pierre-Joseph

Proudhon’s concern for municipalism and confederalism as principles

of associations, indeed, as ways of life whose freedom is unfettered by

the nation-state as well as the pernicious role of property. Herein lies

Michael Bakunin’s hypostasization of popular spontaneity and the

transformative role of the revolutionary act, of the deed as an expression

of will that is unfettered by the constraints of compromise and parliamentary cretinism. Herein, finally, lies the power of Peter

Kropotkin’s ecological visions, his practical concern with human scale,

decentralization, and the harmonization of humanity with nature as

distinguished from the explosive growth of urbanization and centralization.

I shall have the opportunity to examine and restate the ideas of these

remarkable and little appreciated thinkers in the context of the problems

we face today and the need for an ecological society. For the present,

let me pause to examine the issue of emancipation of another kind —

the emancipation of the body in the form of a new sensuousness and of

the human spirit in the form of an ecological sensibility. These issues

rarely figure in most discussions of social renovation, although they

have a prominent place in utopian thinking.

A sense of sheer *joie de vivre*, of joy of living, is closely wedded to

the anarchic tradition, despite the arid patches of asceticism that surface

in its midst. Emma Goldman’s admonition — “If I can’t dance in your

revolution, I don’t want ill” — is typically anarchic in its disposition.

A colourful tradition exists that goes back centuries in time to artisan

and even certain peasant anarchists who demanded as much for the

emancipation of the senses as they did for their communities. The

Ophites in the backwash of antiquity reread the Biblical scriptures to

make knowledge the key to salvation; the snake and Eve, the agents of

freedom; the ecstatic release of the flesh, the medium for the full

expression of soul. The Brethren of the Free Spirit, an abiding movement over many different names in medieval Europe, rejected the

ecclesiastical reverence for self-denial and celebrated their version of

Christianity as a message of sheer libertinism as well as social liberation. In Rabelais’s “Abbey of Thelcme” narrative, the maxim, “Do As Thou Wilt!” removed all restraint from the members of its playful order,

who were free to rise, dine, love, and cultivate all the pleasures of the

flesh and the mind as they chose.

The technical limits of past eras, the fact that pleasure could rarely

be separated from parasitism in a demanding world of toil, made all of

these movements and utopias elitist. What the Brethren of the Free

Spirit stole from the rich, the rich, in turn, took from the poor. What the

members of the Abbey of Theleme enjoyed as a matter of right was

expropriated from the labour of builders, food cultivators, cooks, and

the grooms who served them. Nature was not bountiful, it was assumed,

except in a few usually favoured areas of the world. Emancipation of

the senses was often assumed by the poor and their revolutionary

prophets to be a ruling class privilege, although it was more widespread

in villages and towns than we have been led to believe. And even the

oppressed had their dreams of utopistic pleasures, of visions where

nature was indeed bountiful and rivers flowed with milk and honey.

But always this marvelous dispensation was the product of a being other

than themselves who bestowed the gift of plenty upon them in the form

of a “promised land” — be it deities or irascible demons rather than

technology and new, more equitable, arrangements of work and distribution.

The greatest Utopians of the nineteenth century represent a radical

change in this traditional mix of outlooks and, in this respeetthey invite

our attention. Robert Owen’s early “industrial villages,” which combined the most advanced technologies of the time with agriculture in

humanly scaled communities were structured around the technological

opportunities opened by the Industrial Revolution. Whether “first nature” is bountiful or not, it is dearly “second nature” or human society

that is economically productive. Humanity makes its own social utopia

rather than awaiting its messianic delivery from suprahuman beings.

And it does so through its own technical ingenuity, powers of

cooperation, and social imagination. A technological utopianism was

to develop a life of its own, to be sure, culminating in the present century

with H.G. Wells’s technocratically administered world, and guided by

Francis Bacon’s “New Atlantis” of centuries earlier, a sketchy scientistic utopia of the sixteenth century. William Morris’s utopia, on the

other hand, was more artisanal and wistfully medieval, albeit libertarian

to the core. His “News from Nowhere,” overthrows capitalism and

recreates the commune of the Middle Ages with its pride in craftsmanship, its human scale, and its cooperative values. Industry, by and large,

goes by the board, together with authority, and quality production

compensates for any gains provided by the mass manufacture of shoddy

goods.

Morris’s utopia, in this respect, is a romantic throwback to a world

that was gone forever, but not one that was lacking in lessons for his

time and ours. The quality of production and artistry of the artisan still

haunts us as a standard of excellence and a means of conserving goods

for generations in what is not a “throw-away” economy whose products

are transient and insult every canon of good taste. Morris’s values were

clearly ecological They advance a message of human scale, the integration of agriculture with crafts, the production of lasting, truly artistic works, and a nonhierarchical society.

The utopist who was to meld these seemingly opposing traditions —

sensuousness with mind, the production of lasting goods with

industry, the belief in a bountiful nature with human activity, play with

work — was neither a socialist nor an idle visionary, namely, Charles

Fourier, who turned (in his view) imagination into a science and

Newtonian models of an orderly world into a cosmological fantasy. It

is not important for the purposes of our discussion to explore Fourier’s

sense of mission and the depth of his social principles. He was not only

not a socialist; he was not an egalitarian. His works are riddled with

contradictions, hefty prejudices, and are a totally failed endeavour to

make his system of “passionate intercourse” into a mathematical system, and to enlist the support of the powerful and wealthy to establish

his ideal phalansteries — enormous palaces that could house the

minimum 1,620 people of suitable and complementary dispositions

who would make for emotionally balanced communities. Needless to

say, his phalanstery was to be as self-sufficient as possible with

workshops, farming land surrounding it, residences, educational

centres, and ballrooms, all linked by covered galleries to protect the

inhabitants from inclement weather and give them easy access to each

other.

What is significant about Fourier’s phalanstery is not its structural

principles, but the principles that guided its way of life, many of which

were formulated in opposition to the monotony of industrial work, the

puritanical values of the time, the burden of poverty that was inflicted

on the senses as well as the body. Accordingly, sexual freedom was to

wash out traditional familial inhibitions and philistine conventions.

God rules the universe by attraction and not by force. This was a novel

viewpoint, indeed, a socially rebellious one. Rule consists of self-satisfaction not of obedience to authority. The answer to industrial discipline is the daily rotation of work interspersed by personal delights

for body and mind, magnificent cuisine to satisfy the palate, a gallery

of highly imaginative suggestions for easing life, and the all-important

belief that irksome work could be turned into play by adding charm,

festivities, and the company of complementary passionate natures in

the form of co-workers. Fourier thereby tried to efface the demanding

“realm of necessity” which held everyone in yoke to toil, and replace

it with the artful “realm of freedom” which made even hard work a

pleasurable desideratum.

The “Harmonian World” Fourier envisioned, based on attraction

rather than coercion, became a social program — certainly for his

acolytes who were to give it a distinctly anarchic character after his

death. There was no contradiction in Fourier’s mind between human

artifice and natural fecundity, any more than there was between body

and mind, play and work, freedom and order, unity and diversity. As

yet, these were rebellious intuitions that a naturalistic version of dialectic has to work out, Fourier’s writings converge in time, if not in place,

with Robert Owen’s “industrial village” which realistically combined

factories and workshops with farms in fully integrated communities, a

vision that was to form the prototype for Kropotkin’s idea of a libertarian community.

Between the closing years of the French Revolution and the midnineteenth century, the ideals of freedom had acquired a solidly

naturalistic, technologically viable, and solidly material base. Here,

too, was a remarkable turning point in history when humanity, by

whatever action, might well have swerved from a path of market-oriented and profit-oriented expansion to one of community-oriented

and ecology-oriented harmony, a harmony between human and

non-human that could have been projected by virtue of a new sensibility

into a harmony between humanity and nature. More so than the latter

half of the nineteenth century, when society became engulfed by a

degree of industrial development that was totally remaking the natural

world, if not turning it in time into a synthetic one, the first half of the

century was filled with the promise of a new integration between

society and nature and a cooperative commonwealth that would have

satisfied the most generous impulses toward freedom. That this did not

occur was due in no small measure to the extent to which the bourgeois

spirit began to enfold the Euro-American mixed society of the past

century — and, no less significantly, even the revolutionary project of

remaking society that had found such rich expression in the Utopians,

the visionary socialists, and the anarchists who followed in the wake

of the French Revolution.

The revolutionary project had acquired a richly ethical heritage, a

commitment to reconciling the dualities of mind, body, and society that

pitted reason against sensuality, work against play, town against

country, and humanity against nature, Utopian and anarchist thought at

their best saw these contradictions clearly and tried to overcome them

with an ideal of freedom based on complementarity, the irreducible

minimum, and the equality of unequals. The contradictions were seen

as evidence of a society mired in “evil,” indeed, as a “civilization,” to

use Fourier’s word, that was turned against humanity and culture by

the irrational directions it had followed up to the time. Reason, in its

power to be employed speculatively beyond the existing state of affairs,

was becoming a crude rationalism, which was based on the efficient

exploitation of labour and natural resources. Science, in its searching

probe of reality and its underlying order, was turning into a cult of

scientism, which was little more than the instrumental engineering of

control over people and nature. Technology, with its promise of

ameliorating labour, was turning into a technocratic ensemble of means

for exploiting the human and nonhuman world.

The anarchist theorists and the libertarian utopists, despite their

understandable belief that reason, science, and technics could be creative forces for remaking society, voiced a collective protest against the

reduction of these forces to purely instrumental ends. They were

acutely aware, as we can now see retrospectively from the vantage point

of our own historical malaise, of the rapid transitions through which

the century was going. Their fiery demands for immediate change along

liberatory lines was permeated by a sense of anxiety that society as a

whole was faced with “embourgeoisment,” to use Bakunin’s word for

the remarkably anticipatory fears and the fatalism that gripped him in

the last years of his life.

Contrary to the philistine judgements of Gerald Brenan and

Hobsbawn, the anarchist emphases on “propaganda of the deed” were

not primitive acts of violence and mere catharsis in the face of public

passivity to the horrors of industrial capitalism. They were, in great part,

the product of a desperate insight into the fact that a historic moment

in social development was being lost, one whose loss would produce

immense obstacles in the future to the realization of the revolutionary

project. Imbued with ethical and visionary concepts, they rightly saw

their time as one that demanded immediate human emancipation, not

as one “stage” among many in the long history of humanity’s evolution

toward freedom with its endless “preconditions” and technological

“substructures.”

What did anarchist theorists and libertarian utopists did not see is

that ideals of freedom were themselves faced with “embourgeoisment.” No one, perhaps not even Marx himself who played so important a role

in this infection, could have anticipated that the attempt to make the

emancipatory project into a “science” under the rubric of “scientific

socialism” would have made it even more of a “dismal science” than

economics; indeed, that it would divest it of its ethical heart, its

visionary spirit, and its ecological substance. What is no less compelling, is thatMarx’s “scientific socialism” was to develop in tandem with

the bourgeoisie’s sinister undoing of the very objective as well as

ideological premises of the revolutionary project by justifying the

absorption of decentralized units into the centralized state, confederalist visions into chauvinistic nations, and humanly scaled technologies into all-devouring systems of mass production.

Defining the Revolutionary Project

The ideals of freedom, tainted as they have been, still exist in our midst.

But rarely has the revolutionary project been more diluted by the

“embourgeoisment” that Bakunin feared toward the end of his life. Nor

have its terms been more ambiguous than they are today. Words like

“radicalism” and “leftism” have become murky and they are in grave

danger of being severely compromised. What passes for revolutionism,

radicalism, and leftism, today, would have been dismissed a generation

or two ago as reformism and political opportunism. Social thought has

moved so deeply into the bowels of the present society that self-styled

“leftists” — be they socialists, Marxists, or independent radicals of

various kinds — risk the possibility of being digested without even

knowing it. There is simply no conscious left of any significance in

many Euro-American countries. Indeed, there is not even a critically

independent radicalism, apart from small enclaves of revolutionary

theorists.

What is perhaps more serious in the long run is that the revolutionary

project risks the loss of its very identity, its capacity for self-definition,

its sense of direction. Not only do we witness a lack of revolutionary

insight today, but there is even an inability to define what is meant by

the words “revolutionary change” and the full meaning of terms like

“capitalism.” Bakunin’s troubled remark about the “embourgeoisment” of the working class can be matched by Marx’s fear that a day

might come when a future generation of workers would take capitalism

so much for granted that it would seem like a “natural” form of human

affairs, not a society limited to a specific period of history. To speak of

Euro-American society as “capitalist” often invites puzzlement at best

or specious contrast with the so-called socialist societies of countries

like Russia and China at worst. That the former is a corporate form of

capitalism while the latter is a bureaucratic form often seems incomprehensible to conventional wisdom.

It may well be, to be sure, that we still do not understand what

capitalism really is. Since the outbreak of the First World War, radicals

have described every period of capital ism as its “last stage,” even while

the system has grown, acquired international dimensions, and innovated technologies that were not foreseeable by science fiction a few

generations ago. Capitalism has also exhibited a degree of stability and

an ability to co-opt its opposition that would have thoroughly shaken

the elders of socialism and anarchism in the last century. Indeed, it may

well be that capitalism has not come *completely* into its own as the

absolute incarnation of social evil, to use Bakunin’s words — that is to

say, as a system of unrelenting social rivalry between people at all levels

of life and an economy based on competition and accumulation. But

this much is clear: it is a system that must *continually* expand until it

explodes all the bonds that tie society to nature — as growing holes in

the ozone layer and the increase in the greenhouse effect indicate. It is

literally the cancer of social life as such.

In this case, nature will take its “revenge.” This “revenge,” to be

sure, may assume the form of an uninhabitable planet for complex

life-forms like our own and our mammalian cousins. But given the

accelerating rate of technological innovation, including means for

plumbing the very secrets of matter and life in the form of nuclear

science and bioengineering, it is possible that the breakdown of natural

cycles will be dealt with by a completely synthetic substitute in which

huge industrial installations will supplant natural processes. It would

be utterly blind, today, to overlook such a possibility — and the

possibility too that future generations will be obliged to accept a

nightmarish totalitarian society structured around a completely technocratic administration of social and natural affairs on a global scale.

In that case the planet conceived as a self-regulating natural system

of checks and balances under the rubric of the “Gaia hypothesis,” would

be replaced by a partially or totally engineered technological system,

perhaps a “Daedalus hypothesis,” as it were, without the Greek notion

of limit and restraint.

But until such a grim prospect becomes a dear issue on the historical

agenda, we desperately need to recover the revolutionary project and

the new elements that have been added to it over the past half-century.

Nor can we be impeded by taunts that the very idea of a *revolutionary*

project is evidence of “sectarianism” or “radical dogmatism.” What

today calls itself “liberal” or “left-of-centre,” to use the prudent political verbiage of our time, is too debilitated intellectually to know what

constitutes “sectarianism” as distinguished from a searching analysis

of contemporary social and ecological problems.

We, in turn, must resolutely and independently re-examine the past

and present periods into which the revolutionary project can be sorted

out, such as the era of “proletarian socialism,” the “New Left,” and the

so-called Age of Ecology. We must explore the answers that have been

given in the recent past to the problems that have arisen today and the

ones that lie ahead. Until we engage in a critical examination of earlier

solutions, we will still be groping in the darkness of an unknown history

that has much to teach us. We will be burdened by a naivety and

ignorance that can completely mislead us into meaningless, futile, and

even frivolous directions.

The Failure of Proletarian Socialism

To a great extent what sharply confronts us today is the fact that one

of the great revolutionary projects of the modern era is no longer viable

or meaningful in our present predicament. I refer in part to the Marxist

analyses of society — but, as we shall see, to proletarian socialism as

a whole, which extended far beyond Marxism into libertarian forms of

socialism and even certain utopian ideas. That “being determines

consciousness” or, put less philosophically, that material factors determine cultural life, is at once too simplistic to carry the enormous weight

it had in the latter half of the last century and the first half of the present

one, when *capitalism itself* shaped the mentality of Europe and America

along highly economistic lines.

A closer view of history shows that this largely bourgeois image of

reality, which Marxism turned into a seemingly “radical” ideology, is

limited to specific times in the past, however prevalent it may seem at

present It would have been impossible to understand why capitalism

did not become a dominant social order at various times in the ancient

world if inherited cultural traditions had not restrained and ultimately

undermined the capitalistic drives that were very much at work in the

past ages. One could go on with endless examples of the extent to which

“consciousness” seemed to determine “being” (if one wants to use such

“deterministic” language) by turning our eyes to the histories of Asia,

Africa, and Indian America, not to mention many European countries

early in modern times. On the broad level of the relationship of

consciousness to being — which still carries considerable weight with

Marxist academics even as all else in the theory lies in debris —

Marxism begs its own questions. Looking back from its entrenched

economistic and bourgeois viewpoint, it defines in bourgeois terms a

host of problems that have distinctly nonbourgeois and surprisingly

noneconomic bases. Even the failure of precapitalist societies to move

into capitalism, for example, is explained by a “lack” of technological

development, the poverty of science and, as often happens to be the

case in many of Marx’s less rigorous works like the *Grundrisse*, by the

very cultural factors that are supposed to be contingent on economic

factors.

Apart from the circular reasoning that characterizes so much of

Marxism, what is of more serious concern in trying to define the

revolutionary project for our time is the ideal of proletarian socialism

and the historical myths that have grown up around it. Revolutionary

projects have always been rooted in the special features of their period,

however much they have tried to universalize their ideas and speak for

humanity at all times. Peasant radicalism dates back almost to the

beginnings of settled village life. Dressed in a universal religious

morality, it always professed to speak for timeless values and hopes

centred on land and village forms. Figures like the Ukrainian anarchist,

Nestor Makhno in 1917–1921, and the Mexican populist, Emiliano

Zapata, around the same time period, voiced almost identical goals. By

the same token, artisanal radicalism surfaced throughout the Middle

Ages and reached its zenith in the *enrages* movement of the French

Revolution and the Paris Commune of 1871. Pierre-Joseph Proudhon

was perhaps its most conscious spokesperson, although his

municipalist and confederalist ideas were more far-reaching in their

reconstructive implications than those of any particular class for which

he spoke.

Proletarian socialism, which still lingers on today in the ideals of

many independent socialists and syndicalists, has a more complex and

convoluted pedigree. It stems, in part, from the transformation of many

fairly self-sufficient craftsmen, by capitalism, into industrial workers

during the explosive years of the Industrial Revolution. Similarly, it

was influenced as a movement — all theories aside — by its rural and

small town origins, notably, by the proletarianization of peasants, who

were obliged to leave their villages and agrarian cultures. That they

brought these precapitalist cultures, with their naturalistic rhythms and

values, into industrial cities is a matter of crucial importance in explaining the character of their discontent and their militancy. The working

classes of traditional industrial capitalism, even as late as the 1920s and

1930s in America and Europe, were not “hereditary” proletarians.

American auto workers, for example, were recruited from the Appalachian mountains in the first half of the present century. Many

French, and especially Spanish, workers were recruited from villages

and small towns, when they were not simply craftspeople in large cities

like Paris. The same is true of the working classes that made the 1917

revolution in Russia. Marx, it is worth noting, to his lasting confusion,

generally viewed these highly volatile strata as *der alte scheisse* (literally, “the old shit”) and in no way counted on them to make the

revolutions that his followers were to celebrate after his death.

This agrarian background yielded a highly complex mosaic of

attitudes, values, and tensions between pre-industrial and industrial

cultures — all of which gave a fiery, almost millenarian, character to

men and women who, even though they worked with modern

machinery and lived in major, often highly literate, urban areas, were

guided by largely artisanal and peasant values. The magnificent anarchist workers who burned the money they found in the looted gunshops

of Barcelona during the hectic days of the July, 1936 uprising (as

Ronald Fraser reports), were people who acted from deep utopistic and

ethical impulses, not simply from the economic interests that capitalism

was to imbue in much of the working class as time passed by.[16] The

proletariat of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries were a

very special social breed. They were *delasee* in their thinking, spontaneous in the vital naturalism of their behaviour, angry over the loss

of their autonomy, and shaped in their values by a lost world of

craftsmanship, a love of land, and community solidarity.

Hence, there was the highly revolutionary spirit that surged up in

the workers’ movement from the June barricades of Paris in 1848, when

a largely artisanal working class raised the red flags of a “social

republic,” to the May barricades of Barcelona in 1937, where an even

more socially conscious working class raised the red and black flags of

anarcho-syndicalism.

What has so drastically changed in the decades that followed this

century-long movement, and the revolutionary project that was built

around it, is the social composition, political culture, heritage, and aims

of the present-day proletariat. The agrarian world and the cultural

tensions with the industrial world that fostered their revolutionary

fervour, have waned from history. So, loo, have the people, indeed the

very personalities, that embodied this background and these tensions.

The working class has now become completely industrialized, not

radicalized as socialists and anarcho-syndicalists so devoutly hoped. It

has no sense of contrast, no clash of traditions, and none of the

millenarian expectations of its antecedents. Not only has the mass

media commandeered it and defined its expectations (a convenient

explanation, if one wants to anchor everything in the power of modern

media), but the proletariat as a *class* has become the counterpart of the

bourgeoisie as a class, not its unyielding antagonist. To use the language that was spawned by proletarian socialism against its own myths,

the working class is simply an organ within the body of capitalism, not

the developing “embryo” of a future society, a concept that figured so

significantly in the revolutionary project of proletarian socialism.

We are simply witnesses not only to its failure as a “historical agent”

for revolutionary change, but to its completion as a product spawned

by capitalism with the development of capitalism itself. In its “pure”

form, the proletariat has never been a threat, as a class, to the capitalist

system. It was precisely the “impurities” of the proletariat, like the bits

of tin and zinc that turn copper into hardened bronze, that gave the

earlier proletariat its militancy and, at certain high points, its millenarian zeal.

We come, here, to a terribly flawed model of social change that Marx

introduced into the revolutionary project of the last hundred years —

one that was to be implicitly accepted by non-Marxist radicals as well.

This is the belief that a new society is born within the womb of the old

and eventually grows out of it like a robust child that commandeers or

destroys its parents.

Nothing in antiquity supported this “embryo” theory of revolution,

if it can be called that. European feudalism replaced ancient society on

the northern shores of the Mediterranean — and only there — because

feudal relationships were generally the form into which tribal relations

decompose almost everywhere when they are not reworked into absolute monarchies of the kind that appeared in the East. The great

European hinterland north of the Alps was rapidly losing its tribalistic

features when it encountered Roman society. Capitalism was not born

within the womb of the new European feudalism and there was no

inevitability about its birth, as we are led to believe by Marxist historians of the past or by Ferdinand Braudel and Immanuel Wallerstein

in more recent times. I have tried to show elsewhere that Europe,

between the fourteenth and eighteenth centuries, was very mixed

socially and economically, offering many alternatives to capitalism and

the nation-state.[17] The myth of an “embryonic” development of

capitalism and the “inevitability” of its predominance was to wreak

havoc in the revolutionary project of proletarian socialism.

First, it was to create the myth that the proletariat was the analogue

of the bourgeoisie in modern times and presumably, like the medieval

bourgeoisie, was developing along revolutionary lines within

capitalism itself. That the proletariat never even had the economic

predominance assigned by Marx to the early bourgeoisie, indeed, that

it would have to seize economic as well as political power—all of this

created a can of theoretical worms that should have shown how absurd

the “embryo” theory was for the proletariat, even if the medieval

bourgeoisie enjoyed the power imputed to it. Precisely how the working

class could rise beyond its own narrow interests, in an economy to

which it was integrally wedded by its narrow demands for jobs, higher

wages, shorter hours, and better working conditions *within* the capitalist

system, remained an impenetrable mystery.

Marxian economics, for all its extraordinary insights into the commodity relationship and accumulation process, was a largely contrived

ideology to show that capitalism would drive the proletariat to revolt

through misery and chronic crises. The proletariat, it was presumed,

enjoyed an advantage over all precapitalist oppressed classes in that the

industrial system made for cooperation within the factory itself and that

time would make it the overwhelming population of the country as

capitalism itself expanded. That the factory system would, if anything,

utterly *domesticate* the proletariat through the deadening industrial

routine of the factory; that it would subdue the proletariat’s unruliness

by conditioning it to a managerial hierarchy and the rationalized

methods of production; that the proletariat would not be driven by sheer

desperation to revolution, but would be stratified against itself in the

course of which the well-paid and racially “superior” would be

resolutely pitted against the poorly paid and racially “inferior”; that

hopes of a chronic economic crisis would be dashed by shrewd techniques of crisis-management; that nationalism and even patriotic

chauvinism would prevail over international class solidarity; indeed,

that technological innovation would reduce the proletariat numerically

and bring it into collusion with its own exploitation through Japanese-type management approaches — all of this was not even faintly

understood as the logic of the capitalist development.

Second, Marx’s myth of an “embryonic” development was to mystify history and remove its essential element of spontaneity. Basically,

there could be only one course of development in such a theory, not

alternative ones. Choice played a very insignificant role in social

evolution. Capitalism, the nation-state, technological innovation, the

breakdown of all traditional ties that once fostered a sense of social

responsibility — all were seen not only as inevitable but desirable.

History, in effect, allowed for minimal human autonomy. “Men make

their own history...” wrote Marx — a rather obvious statement that

culture-oriented Marxists were to emphasize long after his death and

amidst growing contradictions between his theories and objective

reality. They often forgot to note, however, that Marx made his statement primarily to emphasize its closing phrase: “... they do not make

it under circumstances chosen by themselves, but under circumstances

directly encountered, given and transmitted from the past” [18]

The Marxian revolutionary project, but by no means the Marxian

alone, became saddled with an array of “stages,” “substages,” and still

further “substages” that rested on technological and political “preconditions.” In contrast to the anarchist policy of continually pressing

against the society in search of its weak-points and trying to open areas

that would make revolutionary change possible, Marxian theory was

structured around a strategy of “historical limits” and “stages of

development” The Industrial Revolution was welcomed as a technological “precondition” for socialism and Luddite tendencies were

denounced as “reactionary”; the nation-state was heralded as a crucial

step in the direction of a “proletarian dictatorship” and confederalist

demands were denounced as atavistic. Everywhere along the way,

centralization of the economy and the State were welcomed as advances in the direction of a “planned economy,” that is, of a highly

rationalized economy. Indeed, so strongly were Marxists, including

Engels personally, committed to these fatal views that the Marxist

Social Democrats of Germany were reluctant to pass anti-monopoly

legislation in the 1920s (to the lasting chagrin of the German petty

bourgeoisie, which soon turned to the Nazis for relief) because the

concentration of industry and commerce in fewer corporate hands was

seen as “historically progressive” in bringing the country closer to a

planned economy.

Third, the proletariat itself, already reduced to a fairly pliant instrument of production by capitalism, was treated as such by its Marxist

vanguard. Workers were seen primarily as economic beings and the

embodiment of economic interests. Efforts by radicals like Wilhelm

Reich to appeal to their sexuality or revolutionary artists like

Mayakovsky to appeal to their aesthetic sensibilities invited opprobrium by Marxist parties. Art and culture were treated largely as

conduits of propaganda to be placed in the service of workers’ organizations.

The Marxian revolutionary project was notable for its lack of interest

in urbanism and community. These issues were dismissed as “super-structural” and presumably had no bearing on “basic” economic concerns. Human beings and their wide range of interests as creative

people, parents, children, and neighbours were reconstituted artificially

into economic beings, so that the Marxian revolutionary project reinforced the very degradation, deculturalization, and depersonalization

of the workers produced by the factory system. The worker was at his

or her best as a good trade-unionist or a devoted party functionary, not

as a culturally sophisticated being with wide human and moral concerns.

Finally, this denaturing of human beings into vacuous class beings

led to a denaturing of nature itself. Not only were ecological issues alien

to the Marxian revolutionary project, but they were seen as insidiously

counterproductive in the literal sense of the word. They inhibited the

growth of industry and the mining of the natural world. Nature was

treated as “stingy,” “blind,” a cruel “realm of necessity,” and an

ensemble of “natural resources” that labour and technology had to

subdue, dominate, and rework. The great historical advance produced

by capitalism, which Marx welcomed as “necessary,” was its ruthless

capacity to destroy all restraints and limits on the ravaging of the natural

world. Hence we encounter encomiums by Marx to the new industrial

dispensation introduced by capital which, in his eyes, was “permanently revolutionary” because of its reduction of nature to “simply an

object” for human utility.[19]

Marx’s language and his views on the unbridled use of nature for

social ends does not reflect the so-called humanism or

anthropocentricity that is denigrated these days by so many Anglo-American environmentalists. Marx’s “humanism” actually rested on a

remarkably insidious reduction of *human beings* to objective forces of

“history,” their subjugation to a social lawfulness over which they had

no control. This is a mentality that is more disconcerting than the most

unfeeling form of “anthropocentrism.” Nature is turned into mere

“natural resources” because human beings are conceived as mere

“economic resources.” Marx’s view of human labour as the means by

which “man” discovers himself in conflict with nature has the sinister

implication that labour is the “essence” of humankind, a trait that set it

aside from all other human traits.

In this respect, Marx cut across the grain of the authentic humanist

tradition of the past, which singled out human beings because of their

consciousness, morality, aesthetic sensibilities, and empathy for all

living things. Even more troubling, if human beings in the Marxist

theory are merely “instruments of history,” the happiness and welfare

of the existing generation can be mortgaged to the emancipation of later

generations—an immortality that the Bolsheviks generally, and Stalin

in particular, were to use with deadly effect and on a frightful scale to

“build the future” on the corpses of the present.

The contribution proletarian socialism made to the revolutionary

project was minimal, at best, and largely economic in character, Marx s

critique of the bourgeois economy, while largely limited to his own

time, was masterful. It revealed the latent power of the commodity to

develop into an all-corrosive force in changing history and the subversive power of the market place to erase all traditional forms of social

life. It anticipated the accumulative power of capital to a point where

monopoly was seen as its outcome and automation as the logic of capitalistic technological innovation. Marx also saw that once

capitalism emerged, it produced a profound sense of scarcity that no

society before had generated in the human spirit Alienated humanity

lived in awe and fear of the very products of its own labour. Commodities had become fetishes which seemed to govern humanity through the fluctuations of the market place and their mysterious power

to decide crucial matters of economic survival. A free society could

only hope to come to terms with its own fears, material insecurities,

and artificially generated wants when technology had reached a level

development where a superfluity of goods would render scarcity meaningless —after which it could be hoped that, in a rational and ecological

society, human beings would develop meaningful wants that were not

distorted by the mystified economic world created by capitalism. That

this mystified world should become personalized, as it has in recent

years by various reborn religions — Christian or pagan — and by the

hypostasization of myth, shamanism, witchcraft, and other self-indulgent lures of the arcane, is evidence of the extent to which capitalism

has infested not only the economy but also private life.

It is important to make the need for a technology that can remove

modern fears of scarcity a part of the revolutionary project, that is, a

post-scarcity technology. But such a technology must be seen within

the context of a social development rather than as a “precondition” for

human emancipation under all conditions and in all eras. For all their

faults and shortcomings, precapitalist societies were structured around

certain powerful moral constraints. I have already cited a medieval

ordinance, singled out by Kropotkin, that “Everyone must be pleased

with his work. This was by no means a rarity. The notion that work

should be pleasant and that needs and wealth should not expand

indefinitely served to greatly condition popular notions of scarcity

itself. In fact, wealth was often seen as demonic and an excessive

indulgence of needs was regarded as morally debasing. To offer gifts,

to divest oneself of needless things, as we have seen, was hypostasized

over the accumulation of goods and the expansion of wants. Not that

the precapitalist societies consistently lacked an appetite for luxury

items and the good things of life—certainly not in imperial Rome. But

society quickly reacted against these “vices,” as they were seen, with

ascetism and paeans to self-denial.

Ironically, it was these very traditions that Marx was to deride in the

strongest language, praising capitalism for undermining “the inherited,

self-sufficient satisfaction of existing needs confined within well-defined bounds, and the reproduction of the traditional ways of life” [20]

Production for its own sake — the typically capitalist disregard for all

quality goods and their utility for mere quantity and profit—was to be

matched by *consumption* for its own sake. This notion is comparatively

recent, to be sure. But it is very deeply entrenched today among broad

masses of people in the western world. Given the fetishization of

commodities and the identification of material security with affluence,

modern notions of consumption can no longer be modified significantly

by moral persuasion alone, important as such efforts may be. Present-day consumption patterns must be shown to be irrelevant, indeed

ridiculous, by virtue of the fact that technology can provide the good

life for all and that the very notion of the good life can now be redefined

along rational and ecological lines.

In any case, Marxism began to ebb as a revolutionary project when

capitalism restabilized itself after the Second World War without any

of the projected “proletarian revolutions” that were expected to end the

war and rescue society from the alternative of barbarism. Its decline

was still further accelerated by the transparent degeneration of Soviet

Russia into another nation-state, riddled by national chauvinism and

imperialistic ambitions. That Marxist studies have retreated into the

enclaves of academe is testimony to its death as a revolutionary

movement. It has become safe and toothless because it is so intrinsically

bourgeois in its overall orientation.

Capitalist countries, in turn, have nationalized large areas of their economies.

They “plan” production in one way or another and they

have buffered economic fluctuation with a large variety of reforms. The

working class has become a largely devitalized force for basic social

change, not to mention revolution. The red flag of Marxian socialism

is now draped over a coffin of myths that celebrate economic and

political centralization, industrial rationalization, a simplistic theory of

linear progress, and a basically anti-ecological stance, all in the name

of radicalism. But red flag or not, it still remains a coffin. The myths it

contains were to tragically deflect radical thought and practice from the

generous ideals of freedom that had preceded it in the early half of the

nineteenth century.

New Left Radicalism and Counterculture Utopianism

The revolutionary project did not die with the ebbing of Marxism,

to be sure, although vulgar Marxian ideas were to taint it for decades

after the thirties. By the late fifties and into the early sixties, an entirely

new constellation of ideas began to fall into place. The upsurge of the

civil rights movement in the United States created a social momentum

around the simple demand for ethnic equality, one that was in many

ways redolent of demands for equality that go back to the age of the

democratic revolutions in the eighteenth century and their sweeping

visions of a new human fraternity.

Martin Luther King’s speeches, for example, have a strikingly

millenarian quality about them that is almost precapitalist in character.

His words are openly utopistic and quasi-religious. They contain references to “dreams,” to ascents to the “mountain top like Moses, they appeal to an ethical fervour that surpasses a pica for special interests and parochial biases. They are voiced against a background of choral music that advances messages like “Freedom Now!” and “We Shall Overcome!”

The broadening of the idea of emancipation, indeed, its sanctification by a religious terminology and a prayer-like demeanour, replaced

the pseudo-science of Marxism. It was a pointedly ethical message of

spiritual redemption and a utopian vision of human solidarity that

transcended class, property, and economic interests. Ideals of freedom

were now being restated in the vernacular of the pre-Marxist revolutionary project — in language, that is, that would have been understandable to the day-dreaming Puritan radicals of the English

Revolution and perhaps even the radical yeomen of the American Revolution. By degrees, the movement became more and more secular. Peaceful protests orchestrated primarily by black ministers and

pacifists to bear witness to the infringement of basic human freedoms, gave way to angry encounters and violent resistance against the rambunctious use of authority.

Ordinary assemblies ended in riots until, from 1964 onward, almost every summer in the United States was climaxed by black ghetto uprisings of near-insurrectionary proportions.

The civil rights movement did not monopolize the egalitarian ideals

that emerged in the sixties. Preceded to a considerable extent by the

“antibomb” movement of the fifties, including the Campaign for

Nuclear Disarmament (CND) in England and Women’s Strike for

Peace in the United States, several trends began to converge to produce

the New Left, a movement which sharply distinguished itself from the

Old Left in its aims, forms of organization, and strategies for social

change. The revolutionary project was being recovered — not in

continuity with proletarian socialism, but with **pre**-Marxist libertarian

ideals. Percolating into this project were the counterculture strains of

the “youth revolt” with its emphasis on new lifestyles, sexual freedom,

and a wide-ranging body of communal libertarian values. A richly

coloured horizon of social ideas, experiments, and relationships

emerged that glowed with extravagant hopes of radical change.

This glow did not come from ideology alone, to be sure. It was fueled

by sweeping technological, economic, and social transitions in Euro-American society. Between the end of the Second World War and the

early sixties, a good deal more than proletarian socialism had died in

the interim that separated the two periods. Other major features of the

Old Left were waning, such as the institutionalization of radicalism in

the form of hierarchical workers’ parties, the economic desperation that

marked the Great Depression decade, and an archaic technological

heritage based on massive industrial facilities and an oversized, labour-intensive factory system. The industrial plant of the Great Depression

years was not very technically innovative. The thirties may have been

a decade of earnest but grim hope; the sixties, by contrast, was a decade

of exuberant promise, even one that demanded the immediate gratification of its desires.

After World War II, capitalism, far from receding into the chronic

depression that preceded the war, had restabilized itself on stronger

foundations than it had ever known in history. It created a managed

economy based on military production, buoyed by dazzling technological advances in electronics, automation, nucleonics, and agribusiness.

Goods in vast quantities and varieties seemed to flow from an endless

horn of plenty. This was a wealth so massive, in fact, that sizeable

portions of the population could live on its mere leavings. It is difficult

from a distance of decades to realize what a buoyant sense of promise

infused the era.

This sense of promise was clearly materialistic. The

counterculture’s rejection of material things did not conflict with its

own consumption of stereos, records, television sets, “mind-expanding” pharmaceuticals, exotic clothing, and equally exotic foods. Early

liberal treatises like the “Triple Revolution” encouraged the highly

justified belief that technologically, in the Western world at least, we

had entered an era of greater freedom from toil. That society could be

adjusted to take full advantage of these material and social goodies was

hardly in doubt, provided, to be sure, that it could create a good life

structured around a new ethical viewpoint.

These expectations infused every stratum of society, including those

who were most deprived and underprivileged. The civil rights movement did not spring simply from the resentment that black people had

suffered during three centuries of oppression and discrimination. In the

sixties, it arose even more compellingly from popular expectations of

the better life enjoyed by the white middle classes and the belief that

there was more than enough to go around for all. The ethical message

of King and his lieutenants had deep roots in the tension between black

poverty and white affluence, a tension that made black oppression more

intolerable than it had been before.

By the same token, the radicalism of the New Left became more

encompassing and fundamental to the degree that the economic largess

that America enjoyed was so inequitably distributed and so irrationally

employed — particularly in military adventures abroad. The buoyancy

of the counterculture and its claims became increasingly utopian to the

degree that a comfortable life for all became more feasible. Young

people, the famous “drop-outs” of the sixties, made an ethical calling

of the fact that they could live well from the garbage pails of society

and with “a little help from one’s friends” to reword the lyrics of a

famous song by the Beatles.

I say this not to denigrate the New Left’s radicalism and the

counterculture’s utopianism. Rather, I seek to explain why they took

the extravagant forms they did—as well as why they were to fadeaway

when the crisis management” techniques of the system re-invented the

myth of scarcity and pulled in the reins of its welfare programs.

Nor do I claim that ethical ideals of freedom mechanically march in

step with material realities of poverty and abundance. The revolt of

peasants over five centuries of history and the utopian visions they

produced, of artisans over a similar span of time with similar vision, of

religious radicals tike the Anabaptists and Puritans, finally of rationalistic anarchists and libertarian Utopians — most of whom advanced ascetic massages in times that were technologically undeveloped — would be inexplicable in terms of this premise. These revolutionary

projects accepted parameters for freedom that were based on poverty,

not abundance. What commonly moved them to action were the hard

facts of the social transition from village to city, from city to nation-state, from artisanal forms of work to industrial toil, from mixed social

forms to capitalism—each a *worse* condition, psychologically as well

as materially, than its predecessor.

What moved the New Left to its own revolutionary project and the

counterculture to its version of unlicensed utopia were parameters for

freedom based on abundance — each period a potentially *better* condition than its predecessor. Indeed, for the first time, it seemed, society

could begin to forget about potentialities of technology to produce

material well-being for all and concentrate on the ethical well-being of

all.

Abundance, at least to the extent that it existed for the middle classes,

and a technology of an incalculable productivity fostered a radical

ethics of its own: the reasonable certainty that the abolition of oppression in any form — of the senses as well as of the body and mind —

could be achieved even on the *bourgeois* grounds of economic instrumentalism. What may very well account for the liberal tone of the

New Left’s early documents like the “Port Huron Statement was the

assumption that technology was so very productive that it could be used

to placate the wealthy and remove traditional fears of dispossession.

The wealthy could enjoy their wealth and, leaving questions of power

and social control aside, more than enough seemed to be at society’s

disposal to provide an affluent life for all. Capitalism and the State, in

effect, seemed to have lost their *raison d’etre*, their reason for being.

No longer need the means of life be distributed along hierarchical lines

because technology was rendering these means available for the asking.

Hence, toil ceased to be a historically explicable burden on the

masses. Sexual repression was no longer necessary to divert one s

libidinal energies into arduous labour. Conventions that stood in the

way of pleasure were insufferable under these new conditions, and need

could be replaced by desire as a truly human impulse. The “realm of

necessity,” in effect, could finally be replaced by the “realm of

freedom”_hence the vogue that Charles Fourier’s writings began to

enjoy at the time in many parts of the Western world.

In its initial phases, the New Left and the counterculture were

profoundly anarchistic and utopistic. Several popular concerns became

of focal importance in the projects that began to rise to the surface of

their collective consciousness. The first was richly democratic, appeals

were voiced for a face-to-face system of decision-making. The words

“participatory democracy” came very much into vogue as a description

of grassroots control over all aspects of life, not simply political ones.

Everyone was expected to be free to enter into the political sphere and

to deal with people in everyday life in a “democratic” manner. What

this meant, in effect, was that people were expected to be *transparent*

in all of their relationships and the ideas they held.

The New Left and, in no small degree, the emerging counterculture

that paralleled it, had a strong antiparliamentary ambience that often

verged on outright anarchism. Much has been written about the “fire in

the streets” that became part of the radical activities of the time.

However, there were also strong impulses toward an institutionalization of decision-making processes that went beyond the level of street

protests and the demonstrations that were so common during the

decade.

The principle American New Left organization. Students for a

Democratic Society (SDS) and its German counterpart, the Socialists

Students Union (also SDS) were distinguished by the formality of their

many conferences and workshops. But few limitations were placed on

attendance — which left these organizations open to cynical invasions

of parasitic dogmatic radical sects. Many of their conferences and

workshops, apart from the fairly large ones, acquired an egalitarian

geometry of their own — the circle, in which there was no formal

chairperson or leader. Individuals yielded the forum to speakers merely

by designating their successors from among the raised hands of those

who wanted to voice their views.

This geometry and procedure was not simply an idle form of

organizational and democratic symbolism. The entire configuration

expressed an earnest belief in the ideal of face-to-face dialogue and a

spontaneous form of discussion. Leadership was grossly mistrusted to

a point where offices were often rotated and an entrenched officialdom

was frowned upon as a step toward authoritarian control. New Left

conferences contrasted dramatically with the highly formalized, often

carefully orchestrated gatherings that had marked conferences in the

workers’ movement a generation or two earlier. Indeed, democracy as

a radical form of decision-making was seen by proletarian socialism,

particularly in its Marxian form, as marginal to economic factors.

In a sense, the New Left, almost knowingly, was reviving traditions

that had been spawned by the democratic revolutions of two centuries

earlier. Precisely because the means of life seemed to be potentially

available to all in abundance, the New Left seemed to sense that

democracy and an ethical ideal of freedom was the direct pathway to

the very social egalitarianism that proletarian socialism had sought to

achieve by largely economic and party-oriented means. This was a

remarkable shift in orientation toward the role of ethics in an era when

all of humanity’s material problems could be solved in principle.

The pre-Marxist age of the democratic revolutions, in effect, had melded

with pre-Marxist forms of socialism and utopianism under the rubric

of a participatory democracy. Economics had now become truly political

and the political had begun to shed the patina of statecraft which

had surrounded it for a century — a change that had fundamentally

anarchic implications.

Secondly such a democratic disposition of social life was meaningless without

decentralization. Unless the institutional structure of

democratic life could be reduced to comprehensible, indeed a

graspable, human scale that all could understand, democracy could

hardly acquire a truly participatory form. New units of social intercourse had to be developed and new ways of relating to each other had

to be established. In short, the New Left began to grope toward new

forms of freedom. But it never developed these new forms beyond

conferences that were usually convened on college campuses.

In France, during the 1968 May-June uprising, there is some

evidence that neighbourhood assemblies were convened in several

Paris *arrondissements*. Neighbourhood projects were started half-heartedly in the United States, notably rent-strike groups and ghetto-oriented service collectives. But the idea of developing new kinds of

libertarian municipal forms as counterpower to the prevailing state

forms did not take root, except in Spain where the Madrid Citizens’

Movement clayed a major role in marshalling public sentiment against

the Franco regime. Thus, demands for decentralization remained an

important *inspirational* slogan. But they never took a tangible form off

the campus, where radical concerns centred on “student power.”

The counterculture offered its own version of decentralized structures in the form of communal lifestyles. The 1960s became the decade

subject have called them. In cities, no less than in the countryside,

communal establishments became very widespread. These establishments aimed not so much at the development of new politics than

at attempts to develop radically new ways of living that were counter

to the conventional ones that surrounded them. They were literally the

nuclei of a counter**culture**. These new lifeways involved the communalization of property, the practice of usufruct in dealing with the means of life, a sharing and rotation of work tasks, collective childcare by both sexes, radically new sexual mores, attempts to achieve a certain

measure of economic autonomy, and the creation of a new music,

poetry, and art that were meant to cut against the grain of received tastes

in aesthetics. The human body and its beautification, whatever one may

think of the standards that were developed, became part of attempts to

beautify the environment. Vehicles, rooms, the exteriors of buildings,

even the brick walls of apartment houses were decorated and covered

with murals.

The fact that entire neighbourhoods were largely composed of these

communes led to informal systems of inter-communal associations and

support systems, such as so-called tribal councils. The idea of

“tribalism,” which the counterculture borrowed rather faciley from

American Indian cultures, found its expression more in a vernacular of

“love” and the wide use of Indian customs, rituals, and especially

jewelry, than in the reality of lasting relationships and mutual aid.

Groups did arise which tried to live by these tribalistic, indeed, in some

cases, conscious anarchist principles, but they were comparatively rare.

Many young people who made up the counterculture were temporary exiles from middle-class suburbia, to which they were to return

after the sixties. But the values of many communal lifestyles were

abiding ideals that were to filler into the New Left, which established

its own collectives for specific tasks like the printing of literature, the

management of “free schools,” and even day-care centres. Anarchist

terms like “affinity groups,” the action and cellular units of the Spanish

anarchist movement, came very much into vogue. The Spanish anarchists developed these groups as personal forms of association in

opposition to anonymous Socialist Party branches based on residence

or places of employment, but the more anarchic elements in the New

Left mixed broader counterculture elements, like lifestyle, with action

in the affinity groups that they established.

Thirdly, the accumulation of property was viewed with derision. The

ability to successfully “liberate” food, clothing, books, and the like,

from department stores and shopping centres became a calling, as it

were, and a badge of honour. This mentality and practice became so

widespread that it even infected conventional middle-class people.

Shop-lifting reached epidemic proportions in the sixties. Property was

generally seen as something of a public resource that could be freely

used by the public at large or personally “expropriated.”

Aesthetic values and utopistic ideals that had been buried away in

the artistic as well as political manifestoes of the past underwent an

extraordinary revival. Museums were picketed as mausoleums of art,

whose works the picketers felt should be located in public places so

that they could be part of a living environment. Street theatre for the

public was conducted in the most improbable locations, such as the

sidewalks of business districts; rock bands conducted their concerts in

the streets or in public squares; parks were used as ceremonial areas,

or places for discussion, or simply open-air habitats for semi-nude

young people, who flagrantly smoked marijuana under the very noses

of the police.

Lastly, the imagination of western society became overheated with

insurrectionary images. A fatal belief began to develop within the New

Left that the entire world was on the verge of violent revolutionary

change. The war in Vietnam mobilized crowds in the hundreds of

thousands in Washington, New York, and other cities, followed by

comparable numbers in European cities as well — mobilizations of

people that had not been seen since the days of the Russian Revolution.

Black ghetto uprisings became commonplace, followed by bloody

encounters between troops as well as police that claimed scores of lives.

The assassination of public figures like Martin Luther King and Robert

Kennedy were only the most publicized of murders that claimed the

lives of civil rights’ activists, student protesters, and, in one horrendous

crime, black children at a church ceremony. These counter-actions

began to place left-wing individual terrorism on the agenda of certain

New Left tendencies.

The year 1968 saw the most spectacular upsurges of the student and

black movements. In France, during May and June, millions of workers

followed the students into a general strike that lasted for weeks. This

“near-revolution,” as it has recently been called, was echoed

throughout the world in various forms, albeit with minimal working

class support—indeed, with active hostility by American and German

workers, a fact that should have placed a fatal seal on the death of

proletarian socialism.

Despite another major upsurge in 1970 by students in the United

States, in which a general strike followed the American invasion of

Cambodia, the movement was more an imaginative projection of an

insurrection than the real thing. In France, workers eventually beat a

retreat under the commands of their parties and unions. The middle

classes were genuinely in conflict between the material benefits they

acquired from the established order and the moral appeal voiced by the

New Left, and even by their own children. Books by Theodore Roszak

and Charles Reich, which tried to explain the ethical message of the

New Left and particularly the counterculture to the older generation,

met with a surprisingly favourable reception. Perhaps millions of fairly

conventional people might have veered toward an actively sympathetic

attitude toward anti war demonstrators, even toward the New Left itself,

if its ideology had been advanced in the populist and libertarian forms

that were consistent with America’s own revolutionary heritage.

The late sixties, in fact, was a profoundly important period in

American history. Had there been a slower, more patient and more

graded development by the New Left and the counterculture, large

areas of popular consciousness could have been changed. The

“American Dream ” perhaps like the national “dreams” of other

countries, had deep-seated ideological roots, not only material ones.

Ideals of liberty, community, mutual aid, even of decentralized confederations, had been carried over to America by its radical Puritan

settlers with their congregational form of Protestantism that disallowed

any clerical hierarchy. These radicals preached a gospel of a primitive

Christian communalism rather than the “rugged individualism” (essentially, a western cowboy ideal of purely personal “anarchism” in which

the lonely “campfire” of the armed soloist is substituted for the family

hearth of the village yeomanry). Puritans had placed a high premium

on face-to-face popular assemblies or town meetings as instruments of

self-government rather than centralized government. Perhaps honoured

more in the breach than in consistent observance, this gospel still

exercised enormous influence on the American imagination, an influence that could have easily wedded the New Left and counterculture

ideas with an ethical democracy that many Americans would have

accepted.

It is one of the appalling facts of history that the New Left, far from

following this historic course, did the very opposite in the late sixties.

It separated itself from its anarchic and utopistic origins. What is worse,

it uncritically adopted Third World ideologies, inspired by Vietnamese,

Chinese, North Korean, and Cuban social models. These were introduced to a sickening extent by the sectarian Marxist debris that lingered

on from the thirties, not only in the U.S. but in Europe. The very

democracy of the New Left was used against it by Maoist-type

authoritarians in an attempt to “capture” SDS in America and Germany.

Guilt for a middle-class pedigree was the principle mechanism for

imbuing these movements with a subservient attitude to self-styled

working class and black groups; indeed, for adopting a rambunctious

ultra-revolutionary zealotry that totally marginalized the followers of

this trend and eventually demoralized them completely. The failure of

many anarchists in American and German SDS, as well as similar

movements elsewhere, to develop a well-organized movement within

the larger ones (particularly with the “ultra-revolutionary” braggadocio

and radical swaggering in the U.S.) played directly into the hands of

the more well-organized Maoist tendencies — with disastrous results

for the New Left as a whole.

But it was not a lack of ideology and organization alone that brought

the New Left and a rather wavering counterculture to an end. The

expanding, overheated economy of the sixties was steadily replaced by

the cooler, more wavering economy of the seventies. The accelerating

rate of economic growth was deliberately arrested and its direction was

partly reversed. Under Nixon in America and Thatcher in England, as

well as their counterparts in other European countries, a new political

and economic climate was created that replaced the ebullient post-scarcity mentality of the sixties with one of economic uncertainty.

The material insecurity of the seventies, and the political reaction

that followed the election of conservatives in America and Europe,

began to foster a personal retreat from the public sphere. Privatism,

careerism and self-interest increasingly gained ascendancy over the

desire for a public life, an ethics of care, and a commitment to change.

The New Left waned even more rapidly than it rose and the counter-culture became the industry for boutiques and pornographic forms of

sexual license. Indeed, the m ind-expanding “drug culture” of the sixties

gave way to the sedating “drug culture” of the seventies — one which

has created national crises in Euro-American society with the discovery

of new pharmaceuticals and their exotic combinations in more intense

“highs” and “lows.”

A perceptive account of the New Left and counterculture, with a full

knowledge of the facts that led to their origins, development, and decay,

has yet to be written. Much of the material that is now available to us

is marked more by sentimentality than serious analyses.

The radicalism of that era, however, has been sensed intuitively. The

New Left was never as educated as the Old, which it tried to succeed

more by an emphasis on activism than theoretical insight. Despite a

spate of high-minded and electrifying propaganda tracts, it produced

no perceptive intellectual accounts of the events which it had created

or of the real possibilities that it confronted. Unlike the Old Left which,

for all its failings, was part of a century-long historical tradition, indeed

an epoch, filled with analyses of cumulative experiences and critical

evaluations of their outcome, the New Left seems more like an isolated

island in history whose very existence is difficult to explain as part of

a larger historical era.

Given more to action than to reflection, the New Left seized upon

refurbished versions of the most vulgar Marxist dogmas to shore up its

guilt-ridden reverence of Third World movements, its own middle-class insecurities, and the hidden elitism of its more opportunistic,

media-oriented leaders who were proof that power ultimately docs

corrupt The more dedicated of the sixties radical youth went into

factories for brief spans of time to “win” a largely indifferent working

class, while others turned to “terrorism” — in some cases, a parody of

the real thing, in other cases, a costly tragedy that claimed the lives of

highly dedicated, if sadly misguided, young people.

Errors that had been repeated generation after generation over the

past century were thus being recycled again: a disregard for theory, an

emphasis on action that excluded all serious thought, a tendency to fall

back on shopworn dogmas when action is reified, and the resulting

certainty of defeat and demoralization. And this was precisely what

occurred as the sixties began to draw to a close.

But not everything is lost in a development. Proletarian socialism

had focused the attention of the revolutionary project on the *economic*

aspects of social change — the need to create the material conditions,

particularly under capitalism, for a forward-looking vision of human

liberation. It revived and fully explored the fact — long emphasized by

writers like Aristotle — that people had to be reasonably free from

material want to be able to function fully as citizens in the political

sphere. Freedom that lacked the material bases for people to act as self-managing and self-governing individuals or collectives was the purely

formal freedom of the inequality of equals, the realm of mere justice.

Proletarian socialism died partly because of its sobriety and lack of

imagination, but it also provided a necessary corrective to a purely

ethical emphasis by earlier radicals on political institutions and a

largely imaginative vision of the economic arrangements that were so

necessary for full popular participation in shaping society.

The New Left restored the anarchic and utopian visions of the

pre-Marxian revolutionary project and it greatly expanded them in

accordance with the new material possibilities created by technology

after the Second World War. To the need for solid economic underpinnings of a free society, the New Left and the counterculture added

certain Fourieresque qualities. They advanced the image of a sensuous

society, not only one that was well-fed; a society free from toil, not only

one that was free from economic exploitation; a substantive democracy,

not only a formal one; the release of pleasure, not only the satisfaction

of need.

Antihierarchical, decentralist, communalist, and sensuous values

were to still persist into the seventies, despite the ideological contortions of the decomposing New Left and its drift into an imaginative

world of insurrection, “days of rage,” and terrorism.

While it is true that many of the New Left’s activists were to find

their way into the very university system they despised in the sixties

and lead fairly convendonal lives, the movement also vastly broadened

the definition of freedom and the scope of the revolutionary project,

extending them beyond their traditional economic confines into vastly

cultural and political domains. No radical movement of any importance

in the future could ignore the ethical, aesthetic, and anti-authoritarian

legacy created by the New Left and the communalist experiments that

emerged in the counterculture, although the two tendencies were by no

means identical. But two questions now remained. What specific forms

should a future movement assume if it hoped to reach the people

generally? And what new possibilities and additional ideas lay before

it that would still further expand the ideals of freedom?

Feminism and Ecology

The answers to these questions began to emerge even while the New Left

and the new counterculture were very much alive and begun to centre

around two basically new issues: ecology and feminism.

Conservative movements, even environmental movements to correct specific pollution abuses, have a long history in English-speaking

countries, particularly in the United States and in central Europe, where

nature mysticism reaches back to the late Middle Ages. The emergence

of capitalism and the appalling damage it inflicted on the natural world

gave these movements a new sense of urgency. The recognition that

particular diseases like tuberculosis — the famous “White Plague” of

the nineteenth century — have their main origins in poor living and

working conditions became a major issue for socially conscious physicians

like Rudolph Virchow, a German liberal, who was deeply concerned with the

lack of proper sanitation among Berlin’s poor. Similar movements

arose in England and spread throughout most of the western world. A

relationship between the environment and health was thus seen as a

problem of paramount importance for well over a century.

For the most part, this relationship was seen in very practical terms.

The need for cleanliness, good food, airy living quarters, and healthful

working conditions were dealt with in rather narrow terms that posed

no challenge to the social order. Environmentalism was a *reform*

movement. It raised no broad problems beyond the humanitarian treatment of the poor and the working class. In time, and with piecemeal reforms, its supporters could expect that there would be no serious

conflict between a strictly environmental orientation and the capitalist

system.

Another environmental movement, basically American (albeit fairly

widespread in England and Germany), emerged from a mystical passion for wilderness. The various strains that entered into this movement

are too complex to unravel, here. American conservationists like John

Muir found in wilderness a spiritually reviving form of communion

with nonhuman life; one that presumably awakened deep-seated human

longings and instincts. This view goes back even further in time to

Rousseau’s idyllic passion for a solitary way of life amidst natural

surroundings. As a sensibility, it has always been marked by a good

deal of ambiguity. Wilderness, or what is left of it today, can give one

a sense of freedom, a heightened sense of nature’s fecundity, a love of

nonhuman life-forms, and a richer aesthetic outlook and appreciation

of the natural order.

But it also has a less innocent side. It can lead to a rejection of *human*

nature, an introverted denial of social intercourse, a needless opposition

between wilderness and civilization. Rousseau leaned toward this

viewpoint in the eighteenth century for very mixed reasons that need

not concern us in this discussion. That Voltaire called Rousseau an

“enemy of mankind” is not entirely an overstatement. The wilderness

enthusiast who retreats into remote mountain areas and shuns human

company has provided a bouquet of innumerable misanthropes over the

ages. For tribal peoples, such individual retreats, or “vision quests” are

ways of *returning* to their communities with greater wisdom; for the

misanthrope it is often a revolt *against* one’s own kind; indeed, a

disclaiming of natural evolution as it is embodied in human beings.

This pitting of a seemingly wild “first nature” against social “second

nature” reflects a blind and tortured inability to distinguish what is

irrational and anti-ecological in capitalist society from what *could* be

rational and ecological in a free society. Society is simply condemned

wholesale. Humanity, irrespective of its own internal conflicts between

oppressor and oppressed, is lumped together as a single “species” that

constitutes an accursed blight on a presumably pristine, “innocent,” and

“ethical” natural world.

Such views easily lend themselves to a crude biologism that offers

no way of fixing humanity and society in nature, or, more precisely, in

natural evolution. The fact that human beings, too, are products of

natural evolution and that society grows out of that evolutionary

process, incorporating in its own evolution the natural world as transmuted into social life, is generally given a subordinate place to a very

static image of nature. This simplistic type of imagery sees nature as a

mere piece of scenery of the kind we encounter in picture postcards.

There is very little naturalism in this view; rather, this view is largely

aesthetic rather than ecological The wilderness enthusiast is usually a

visitor or a vacationer to a world that, uplifting as it may be for a time,

is basically alien to their authentic social environment.

Such wilderness enthusiasts carry their social environment within themselves

whether they know it or not, no less than the fact that the knapsacks

they shoulder are often products of a highly industrialized society.

The need to go beyond these traditional trends in environmentalism

emerged in the early 1960s, when an attempt was made in 1964 by

anarchist writers to rework libertarian ideas along broadly ecological

lens. Without denying the need to stop the degradation of the environment from pollution, insensate deforestation, the construction of

nuclear reactors, and the like, a reformist approach with its focus on

single issues was abandoned for a revolutionary one, based on the need

to totally reconstruct society along ecological lines.

What is significant about this new approach, rooted in the writings

of Kropotkin, was the relationship it established between hierarchy and

the notion of dominating nature. Put simply: the very idea of dominating

nature, it was argued in this anarchistic interpretation, stemmed

from the domination of human by human. As I have pointed out earlier

in this book, this interpretation totally reversed the traditional liberal

and Marxist view that the domination of human by human stems from

a shared historical project to dominate nature by using human labour

to overcome a seemingly “stingy,” withholding, intractable natural

world whose “secrets” had to be unlocked and rendered available to all

in order to create a beneficent society.

No ideology, in fact, has done more to justify hierarchy and domination since Aristotle’s time than the myth that the domination of nature

presupposes the domination of “man by man.” Liberalism, Marxism,

and earlier ideologies had indissolubly linked the domination of nature

with human freedom. Ironically, the domination of human by human,

the rise of hierarchy, of classes, and the State, were seen as “preconditions” for their very elimination in the future.

The views advanced by anarchists were deliberately called *social*

ecology to emphasize that major ecological problems have their roots

in social problems — problems that go back to the very beginnings of

patricentric culture itself. The rise of capitalism, with a law of life based

on competition, capital accumulation, and limitless growth, brought

these problems — ecological and social — to an acute point; indeed,

one that was unprecedented in any prior epoch of human development.

Capitalist society, by recycling the organic world into an increasingly

inanimate, inorganic assemblage of commodities, was destined to

simplify the biosphere, thereby cutting across the grain of natural

evolution with its ages-long thrust toward differentiation and diversity.

To reverse this trend, capitalism had to be replaced by an ecological

society based on nonhierarchical relationships, decentralized communities, eco-technologics like solar power, organic agriculture, and

humanly scaled industries—in short, by face-to-face democratic forms

of settlement economically and structurally tailored to the ecosystems

in which they were located. These views were explored in such pioneering articles like “Ecology and Revolutionary Thought” (1964) and “Toward a Liberatory Technology” (1965), years before “Earth Day”

was proclaimed and an obscure word, “ecology,” began to enter into

everyday discourse.

What should be emphasized is that this literature anchored ecological problems for the first time in hierarchy, not simply in economic

classes; that a serious attempt was made to go beyond single-issue

environmental problems into deep-sealed ecological dislocations of a

monumental character; that the relationship of nature to society,

formerly seen as an inherently antagonistic one, was explored as part

of a long continuum in which society had phased out of nature through

a complex and cumulative evolutionary process.

It may have been asking too much of an increasingly Maoist New

Left and an increasingly commercialized counterculture, both with a

strong predilection for action and a deepening mistrust of theoretical

ideas, to absorb social ecology as a whole. The use of words like

“hierarchy,” a term rarely employed in New Left rhetoric, surfaced

widely in the radical discourse of the late sixties and began to assume

particular relevance for a new movement — notably, feminism. With

the notion that woman, as such, is a victim of a male-oriented “civilization” irrespective of her “class position” and economic status, the term

“hierarchy” became particularly relevant to early feminist analyses.

Social ecology was increasingly reworked by early radical feminist

writers into a critique of hierarchical forms, not simply class forms.

In a broad sense, social ecology and early feminism directly challenged the economistic emphasis Marxism had placed on social

analysis and reconstruction. It rendered the New Left’s anti-authoritarian outlook more explicit and more clearly definable by

singling out hierarchical domination, not simply anti-authoritarian

oppression. Woman’s degraded status as a gender and status-group was

rendered clearly visible against the background of her seeming

“equality” in a world guided by justice’s inequality of equals. At a time

when the New Left was decomposing into Marxist sects and the

counterculture was being transformed into a new form of boutique

retailing, social ecology and feminism were expanding ihe ideal of

freedom beyond any bounds that had been established in recent

memory. Hierarchy *as such* — be it in the form of ways of thinking,

basic human relationships, social relations, and society’s interaction

with nature—could now be disentangled from the traditional nexus of

class analyses that concealed it under a carpet of economic interpretations of society. History could now be examined in terms of general

interests such as freedom, solidarity, and empathy for one’s own kind;

indeed, the need to be an active part of the balance of nature.

These interests were no longer specific to a particular class, gender,

race, or nationality. They were *universal* interests that were shared by

humanity as a whole. Not that economic problems and class conflicts

could be ignored, but to confine oneself to them left a vast residue of

perverted sensibilities and relationships that had to be confronted and

corrected on a broader social horizon.

In terms that were more expansive than any that had been formulated

in the sixties or earlier, the revolutionary project could now be clearly

defined as the abolition of hierarchy, the reharmonization of humanity

with nature through the reharmonization of human with human, the

achievement of an ecological society structured on ecologically sound

technologies and face-to-face democratic communities. Feminism

made it possible to highlight the significance of hierarchy in a very

of social ecology, it rendered hierarchy concrete, visible, and poignantly real owing to the status of women in all classes, occupations, social

institutions, and familial relationships. As long as it revealed the

demeaned human condition that all people suffered, particularly

women, it demystified subtle forms of rule that existed in the nursery,

bedroom, kitchen, playground, and school—not only in the workplace

and the public sphere generally. Hence social ecology and feminism

logically intertwined with each other and complemented each other in

a shared process of demystification. They exposed a demonic incubus

that had perverted every advance of “civilization” with the poison of

hierarchy and domination. An agenda even larger than that advanced

by the early New Left and counterculture had been created by the

mid-sixties; one that required elaboration, educational activity, and

serious organization to reach people as a whole, not merely a particular

sector of the population.

This project could have been reinforced by issues that cut across all

traditional class lines and status groups: the subversion of vast natural

cycles, the growing pollution of the planet, massive urbanization, and

increases in environmentally induced diseases. A growing public began

to emerge that felt deeply implicated in environmental problems.

Questions of growth, profit, the future of the planet, assumed in their

no longer single issues or class issues but human and ecological issues.

That various elites and privileged classes still advanced their own

bourgeois interest could have served to highlight the extent to which

capitalism was *itself* becoming a special interest whose existence could

no longer be justified. It could be made clearly evident that capitalism

did not represent a universal historical force, much less a universal

human interest.

The close of the sixties and the opening of the seventies formed a

period filled with extraordinary alternatives. The revolutionary project

had come into its own. Ideals of freedom whose threads had been

broken by Marxism were once again picked up and advanced along

anarchic and utopian lines to encompass *universal* human interests —

the interests of society as a whole, not of the nation-stale, the bourgeoisie, or the proletariat as particularistic social phenomena.

Could enough of a New Left and a counterculture be rescued from

the process of decomposition that followed 1968 to embrace the expanded revolutionary project opened by social ecology and feminism?

Could a radical sentiment and the energies of radicals generally be

mobilized on a scale and with the intellectuality that equaled the broad

revolutionary project advanced by these two tendencies?

Vague demands for participatory democracy, social justice, disarmament, and the like, had to be linked together into a coherent outlook

and program. They required a sense of direction that could be given

only by a deeper theoretical insight, a relevant program, and more

definable organizational forms than the New Left of the sixties could

generate, Rudi Dutschke’s appeal to German SDS for a “Long march

through the institutions,” which amounted to little more than adapting

to the institutions that exist without troubling to create new ones, led to

the loss of thousands within the institutions. They went in—and never

came out.

From Here to There

The door that can open the way to a New Left of the future, one that

embodies the experience of the thirties, sixties, and the decades that

have followed them, is still swinging to and fro on its hinges.

It has neither opened fully nor closed. Its swings depend partly upon

the hard realities of everyday social life — namely, whether the

economy is depressed or rising, the kind of political climate that exists

in various parts of the world, events in the Third World as well as the

First and Second, the fortunes of radical tendencies at home and abroad,

and the sweeping environmental changes that confront humanity in the

years that lie ahead.

Ecologically, humanity is faced with major climatic changes, rising

levels of pollution, and new, environmentally induced illnesses. Terrible human tragedies in the form of hunger, famine, and malnutrition

are claiming millions of lives annually. An incalculable number of

animal and plant species face extinction as a result of deforestation from

lumbering activities and acid rain. The global changes that are degrading the natural environment, and may eventually render it uninhabitable

for complex life-forms, have an almost geological massiveness, and

they may be occurring at a pace that verges on the catastrophic for many

plant and animal species.

One might have hoped that these planetary changes would have

catapulted the ecology movement into the foreground of social thought

and added new insights to the ideals of freedom. This has not been the

case. The ecology movement has divided into several questionable

tendencies that often directly contradict each other. Many people are

simply pragmatic environmentalists. Their efforts are focused on

single-issue reforms such as the control of toxic wastes, opposition to

the construction of nuclear reactors, restrictions on urban growth, and

the like. These are necessary struggles, to be sure, that can never be

disdained simply because they are limited and piecemeal. They serve

to slow down a headlong race to disasters like Chernobyl or Love Canal.

But they cannot supplant the need to get to the roots of environmental dislocations. Indeed, insofar as they are restricted merely to reforms,

they often create the dangerous illusion that the present social order is

capable of rectifying its own abuses. The denaturing of the environment

must always be seen as *inherent* to capitalism, the product of its very

law of life, as a system of limitless expansion and capital accumulation.

To ignore the anti-ecological core of the present social order — be it

in its Western corporate form or its Eastern bureaucratic fonn — is to

allay public concern about the depth of the crisis and lasting means to

resolve it.

Environmentalism, conceived as a piecemeal reform movement,

easily lends itself to the lure of statecraft, that is, to participation in

electoral, parliamentary, and party-oriented activities. It requires no

great change in consciousness to turn a lobby into a party or a petitioner

into a parliamentarian. Between a person who humbly solicits from

power and another who arrogantly exercises it, there exists a sinister

and degenerative symbiosis. Both share the same mentality that change

can be achieved only through the *exercise* of power, specifically,

through the power of a self-corrupting professionalized corps of legislators, bureaucrats, and military forces called the State. The appeal to

this power invariably legitimates and strengthens the State, with the

result that it actually disempowers the people. Power allows for no

vacuum in public life. Whatever power the State gains, it always does

so at the expense of popular power. Conversely, whatever power the

people gain, they always acquire at the expense of the State. To

legitimate State power, in effect, is to delegitimate popular power.

Ecology movements that enter into parliamentary activities not only

legitimate State power at the expense of popular power, but they are

obliged to function *within* the State, ultimately to become blood of its

blood and bone of its bone. They must “play the game ” which means

that they must shape their priorities according to predetermined rules

over which they have no control. This not only involves a given

constellation of relationships that emerges with participation in State

power; it becomes an ongoing *process* of degeneration, a steady

devolution of ideals, practices, and party structures. Each demand for

the “effective” exercise of parliamentary power raises the need for a

further retreat from presumably cherished standards of belief and

conduct.

If the State is a realm of “evil,” as Bakunin emphasized, the “art” of

statecraft is essentially a realm of lesser or greater evils, not a realm of

ethical right and wrong. Ethics itself is radically redefined from the

classical time-honoured study of good and evil into the more sinister

contemporary study of compromises between lesser and greater evils — in short, what I have elsewhere called an “ethics of evil.” {1} This basic

redefinition of ethics has had deadly consequences over the course of

recent history. Fascism made its way to power in Germany when Social

Democracy lived in a diet of choices between liberals and centrists;

later, centrists and conservatives; and, finally, between conservatives

and Nazis — a steady devolution in which a conservative President,

Marshall von Hindenberg, finally appointed the Nazi leader, Adolf

Hitler, to the position of Reich Chancellor. That the German working

class with its huge parties and its massive trade unions permitted this

appointment to occur without any ac t of resistance is an easily forgotten

and dismal event in history. Not only did this moral devolution occur

on the level of the State, but also on the level of German popular

movements themselves, in a cruel dialectic of political degeneration

and moral decomposition.

{1} See my forthcoming book. The Ethics of Evil (Montreal, 1990).

Environmental movements have not fared better in their relationship

to State power. They have bartered away entire forests for token

reserves of trees. Vast wilderness areas have been surrendered for

national parks. Huge stretches of coastal wetlands have been exchanged

for a few acres of pristine beaches. To the extent that environmentalists

have entered into national parliaments as Greens, they have generally

attained little more than public attention for their self-serving parliamentary deputies and achieved very little to arrest environmental

decay.

The Hesse coalition of the German Greens with a Social Democratic

government in the mid-1980s ended in ignominy. Not only did the

“realist wing” of the German Green party taint the movement’s finest

principles with compromises, it made the party more bureaucratic,

manipulative, and “professional” — in short, very much like the rivals

it once denounced.

Reformism and parliamentarism, at least, have a tangibility about

them that raises real questions of political theory and a sense of social

direction. The most recent tendency in the environmental movement,

however, is completely ghostly and vaporous. Bluntly put: it consists

of attempts to turn ecology into a religion by peopling the natural world

with gods, goddesses, woodsprites, and the like — all serviced by a

corps of financially astute gurus from India, their home-bred competitors, a variety of witches, and self-styled “wiccan anarchists,”

The American roots of this tendency, of course, should be emphasized. The United States is currently the most ill-read, ill-informed,

and, culturally, the most illiterate country in the Western world. The

sixties counterculture opened a rupture not only with the past, but with

all knowledge of the past, including its history, literature, art, and

music. The young people who arrogantly refused to “trust anyone over

thirty,” to use a popular slogan of the day, severed all (heir ties with the

best traditions of the past. In an era of junk food, the opening created

by this breach was filled by an appalling mixture of junk ideas. Patently

contradictory fantasies were congealed by drugs and rock music into a

squalid ooze of atheistic religions, natural supematuralisms, pri vatistic

politics, and even liberal reactionaries. If this pairing of completely

opposing terms seems irrational, the reader should bear in mind that the

amalgam was “made in America,” where everything is believed to be

possible and the absurd is normally the result.

That ecology, an eminently *naturalistic* outlook and discipline,

could be infested with supernatural rubbish, would seem explicable if

such nonsense were confined stricdy to its American borders. What is

astonishing, however, is that it has spread like a worldwide pollutant to

Europe, especially to England, Germany, and Scandinavia, Given time,

it will almost certainly invade the Mediterranean countries as well.

As a form of “cultural feminism,” this extension of a quasi-theological ecology to gender relationships already commands a growing,

indeed enormous, following in English and German-speaking

countries. The hope that ecology would enrich feminism has taken the

bizarre form of a theistic “eco-feminism,” structured around woman’s

uniquely “nurturing” role in the biosphere. Leaving aside this crassly

anthropomorphic extension of human behaviour to nature as a whole,

theistic “eco-feminists” have essentially reversed the eminent role

patriccntric cultures assign to men by simply inverting the same

relationship in woman’s favour. Women are privileged in nature just

as men are privileged in history, with the result that male chauvinism

is simply replaced by female chauvinism.

Accordingly, presumably “pacific” female goddesses are substituted for male warrior gods, as though trading one deity for another

is not an extension of religion and superstition into human affairs —

whether they are called “immanent,” “transcendental,” “paganistic,” or

“Judeo-Christian,” Female-oriented myths based on “nurture” are substituted for male-oriented myths based on military conquest, as though

myths are not inherently fictitious and arbitrary — whether they are

“naturalistic” or “supernaturalistic,” “earth-based,” or “heaven-based.”

The world, viewed as a complex biosphere that should invite wonder,

admiration, and foster an aesthetic as well as caring sensibility, is

re-envisioned as a basically female terrain, occupied by woodsprites,

witches, goddesses, and regaled by rituals and mystified by contrived

myths — an ensemble that is borne on a lucrative tidal wave of books,

artifacts, and bejeweled ornaments.

Political activity and social engagement in this theistic terrain tends

to shrivel from activism into quietism and from social organization into

privatistic encounter-groups. One has only to cover a personal problem

with the patina of gender — be it a failed love affair or a business

misfortune — and it is easily designated as “political” or a form of

gender victimization. The notion that the “personal is the political,” in

effect, is stretched to the frivolous point where political issues are cast

increasingly in a therapeutic vernacular, so that one’s “manner” of

presenting ideas is considered more important than their substance.

Form is increasingly replacing content and eloquence is increasingly

decried as “manipulative,” with the result that a deadening mediocrity

of form *and* content tends to become the rule in political discourse. The

moral outrage that once stirred the human spirit over the ages in the

thundering words of the Hebrew prophets is denounced as evidence of

“aggressiveness,” “dogmatism,” “divisiveness,” and “male behaviour.” What “counts,” today, is not what one says but *how* one says

it — even if statements are insultingly naive and vacuous. “Care” can

easily regress into naivety and “concern” into a childishness that makes

one’s politics more infantile than feminist.

None of this is to deny the feminist claim that woman has been the

pariah of a largely male history, a history that has never prevented males

from dominating, exploiting, torturing, and murdering each other on a

scale that beggars description. But to see woman as the protypical

victim of hierarchy and her oppression as the source of all hierarchy,

as some feminists claim, is to simplify the development of hierarchy in

a very reductive manner. The origins of a phenomenon do not exhaust

our understanding of the phenomenon any more than the origins of the

cosmos exhaust or understanding of its development from a compact

undifferentiated mass into extremely complex forms. Male hierarchies

are highly complex affairs. They embody subtle interactions between

men as fathers, brothers, sons, workers, and ethnic types, including their

cultural status and their individual proclivities. The caring father, who

often stands in a warm relationship with his daughter by comparison

with a competitive mother, should remind us that hierarchy is intricate

enough on the familial level to give us pause when we consider it on

the social level.

Nor does anthropology supply conclusive support for the status of

woman as the protypical victim of hierarchy. Elderly women, in fact,

enjoyed a high status together with elderly men in early hierarchical

gerontocracies. Nor were women the sole, or necessarily the most

oppressed, victims of patriarchy. Sons of patriarchs were often confronted with unendurable demands and dealt with far more harshly on

many occasions by their fathers than were their sisters or mothers.

Indeed, the power of patriarchs was often shared quite openly with their

eldest wives, as is evident in the commanding status of Sara in the

Hebrew scriptures.

Finally it is by no means clear that women do not form hierarchies

among themselves or that the abolition of male dominance will remove

hierarchy as such. Hierarchy embraces vast areas of social life, today,

such as bureaucracies, ethnic groups, nationalities, occupational classes, not to mention domestic life in all its aspects. It permeates the

human unconscious in ways that often have no direct or even indirect

relationship with women. It involves ways of looking at the natural

world that in no way relate to the putative assignment of a presumably

“instinctive” proclivity of women to be “caretakers” and “custodians”

of life as such—a piece of crude biologism that defames woman’s role

in the making of a very human-oriented culture and its artifacts like

pottery, woven cloth, and agriculture. In any case, many priestesses,

witches, and shamanesses seem to have stood — and still stand — in a

distinctly hierarchical relationship with their female congregants and

acolytes.

Toward a General Human Interest

The antirational, theistic, even antisecular impulses that are surfacing in the ecology and feminist movements raise an issue of very

fundamental concern for our time. They are evidence of a sinister

<em>anti</em>-Enlightenment tendency that is sweeping through much of contemporary Western society.

In America and Europe, nearly all the high ideals of the Enlightenment are being currently impugned: its goals of a rational society, its

belief in progress, its high hopes for education, its demands for the

human use of technology and science, its commitment to reason, and

its ethical belief in humanity’s power to attain a materially and culturally viable world. Not only have dark atavisms replaced these goals

among certain tendencies within the ecology and feminist movements;

they have branched outward in the world at large in the form of a Yuppie

nihilism called postmodernism, in a mystification of wilderness as “true

reality” (to quote one vulgarian), in a sociobiology that festers with

racism, and in a crude neo-Malthusianism that lends itself to indifference to human suffering.

The eighteenth century Enlightenment, to be sure, had serious

limitations — limitations of which many of its foremost spokespersons

were fully aware. But the Enlightenment left society and the centuries

that followed it with heroic ideals and values. It brought the human

mind from heaven down to earth, from the realm of the supernatural to

the natural It fostered a clear-eyed secular view toward the dark mythic

world that festered in feudalism, religion, and royal despotism. It

challenged notions of political inequality, of aristocratic supremacy, of

clerical hierarchy — a challenge that ultimately laid the basis for much

of the antihierarchical sentiments of later generations.

Above all, the Enlightenment tried to formulate a general human

interest over feudal parochialism and to establish the idea of a shared

human nature that would rescue humanity as a whole from a folk-like,

tribalistic, and nationalistic particularism.

The abuse of these ideals by industrial capitalism through the

commodification and mechanization of the world does not negate these

ideals by one whit Indeed, the Enlightenment reconnoitred areas of

reason, science, and technology that are by no means reflected by the

present-day forms these achievements have taken. Reason, to thinkers

like Hegel, meant a dialectic of eductive development, a process that

is best expressed by organic growth, not simply the deductive inferences we find in geometry and other branches of mathematics. Science,

in the thinking of Leibnitz, centred on the the study of the qualitative

dimensions of phenomena, not simply on Cartesian models of a

machine-like mathematical world. Technology was studied by Diderot

primarily from an artisanal viewpoint, with a keen eye for craft skills

as well as mass production. Indeed, Fourier, the true heir of this

Enlightenment tradition, was to give technology a strongly ecological

bias and stress the crucial importance of natural processes in the

satisfaction of material needs.

That capitalism warped these goals, reducing reason to a harsh

industrial rationalism focused on efficiency rather than a high-minded

intellectuality; that it used science to quantify the world and dualize

thought and being; that it used technology to exploit nature, including

human nature — all of these distortions have their roots in society and

in ideologies that seek to dominate humanity as well as the natural

world.

The trends that denigrate reason, science, and technology, today, are

perhaps understandable reactions to the bourgeois distortions of the

Enlightenment’s goals. They are understandable, too, in terms of the

disempowerment that is felt by the individual in an era of ever-centralized and concentrated power in corporate and State hands, in the

anonymity produced by urbanization, mass production, and mass consumption, and in the fragile condition of a human ego that is beset by

incomprehensible and uncontrollable social forces.

But these trends, as understandable reactions, become profoundly

reactionary when the substitutes they offer involve a dissolution of the

general human interest advanced by the Enlightenment into gender

parochialism, the substitution of a tribalistic folkdom for an emphatic

humanism, and a “return to wilderness” for an ecological society.

They become crudely atavistic when they blame ecological dislocations on technics instead of the corporate and state institutions that

employ them. And they retreat into the mythic darkness of a tribalistic

past when they evoke a dread of the “outsider” — be it a male, an

immigrant, or the member of a different ethnic group — as a threat to

the integrity of the “insider’s” group.

That groups of people may have unique cultural identities—claims

that are justifiable as long as they are truly *cultural* and not “biological”

— is not in dispute, especially if we acknowledge that their strongest

commitment is to humanity as a whole in a free society, not to a special

portion of it. Ecology’s motifs of complementarity, mutualism, and

nonhierarchical relationships are completely dishonoured by evocations of a racial, gender-oriented, or national particularism. If the

Enlightenment left us any single legacy that we might prize above all

others, it is the belief that humanity in a *free* society must be conceived

as a unity, a “one” that is bathed in the light of reason and empathy.

Rarely in history have we been called upon to make a stronger stand

for this legacy than today, when the sludge of irrationality, mindless

growth, centralized power, ecological dislocation, and mystical retreats

into quietism threaten to overwhelm the human achievements of past

times. Rarely before have we been called upon not only to contain this

sludge but to push it back into the depths of a demonic history from

which it emerged.

I have tried to show that Western history has not been a unilinear

advance from one stage to another and from one “precondition” to

another in an untroubled ascent to ever-greater control over a “blind,”

“stingy,” and intractable “first nature.” Quite to the contrary: prehistory

may have allowed for alternatives before the emergence of patricentric

warrior societies—societies that might have seen a more benign social

development than the one that formed our own history.

Possible alternatives were opened in the “age of cities,” before the

nation-state foreclosed the opportunities opened by urban confederations with their humanly scaled communities, artisanal technologies,

and sensitive balance between town and country. As recently as two

centuries ago, in the “age of democratic revolutions,” the Western

world with its mixed precapitalist society and economy seemed poised

for an anarchic social dispensation.

Throughout, ever-expanding ideals of freedom based on the equality

of unequals paralleled the more ancient “cry for justice” with its

inequality of equals. To the extent that inherited custom was absorbed

by a commandeering morality and both became part of a rational ethics,

freedom began to develop a forward rather than a backward gaze and

turn from a mere longing for a “golden age” to a fervent hope for a

humanly created utopia.

The ideals of freedom became secular rather than heavenly, work-a-day rather than the fanciful bounty of nature or the largess of a

privileged class. They became sensuous as well as intellectually sophisticated. Scientific and technological advances placed material security

and the leisure time needed for a participatory democracy on the agenda

of a radically new revolutionary project. From antinomies, or seemingly contradictory co-existent$ of these advances, particularly in the

mixed economy that existed in Europe between the fourteenth and

eighteenth centuries, various choices were possible between city and

nation, commonwealth and state, artisanal production and mass

production.

Anarchism, which came fully into its own in the “age of revolutions,” stressed the importance of choice; Marxism stressed the inexorability of social laws. Anarchism remained sensitive to the

spontaneity of social development, a spontaneity, to be sure, informed

by consciousness and the need for a structured society. Marxism

anchored itself deeply in an “embryonic” theory of society, a “science”

based on “prerequisites” and “preconditions.” Tragically, Marxism

virtually silenced all earlier revolutionary voices for more than a

century and held history itself in the icy grip of a remarkably bourgeois

theory of development based on the domination of nature and the

centralization of power.

We have noted that capitalism has yet to fully define itself. No “last

stage” exists, as far as we can see, anymore than such a “stage,” which

was greeted with certainty by revolutionaries during the First World

War and the Second, emerged in their time. If capitalism has any limits,

they are neither internal, based on chronic crises, nor dependent upon

the proletariat’s pursuit of its particularistic interests. Proletarian

socialism, or the Old Left foundered on these myths and now lies in

debris.

The success of the revolutionary project must now rest on the

emergence of a general human interest that cuts across the particularistic interests of class, nationality, ethnicity, and gender. The New Left,

nourished by dazzling advances in the technologies of the post—Wortd

War II era and the gratification of the most trivial wants by unprecedented levels of production, thawed out the economistic grip of Marxism and returned the sixties, for a time, to the ethical, indeed sensuous, radicalism of the pre-Marxist era.

If a general interest can be reformulated today as a new libertarian

agenda, it must be based on the most obvious limits capitalism faces:

the ecological limits to growth imposed by the natural world. And if

that general interest can be embodied in a nonhierarchical demand, it is

the demand raised by women for a substantive equality of unequals — that is, the expansive ideal of freedom. The question we now face

whether the ecological and feminist movements can live up to this

storical challenge. That is whether these movements can be

broadened into a sweeping *social movement*; indeed, into a libertarian

New Left that will speak for a general human interest — or whether

they will shatter into the particularized interests that centre around

reformist parliamentarism, mysticism and theism in their various

forms, and gender chauvinism.

Finally, whatever may have been the prospect of achieving a free,

ecological society in the past, there is not the remotest chance that it

can be achieved today unless humanity is free to reject bourgeois

notions of abundance precisely because abundance is available to all.

We no longer live in a world that treasures gift-giving over accumulation and moral constraints that limit growth. Capitalism has warped the

values of that earlier world to a point where only the prospect of

abundance can eliminate insensate consumption and a sense of scarcity

that exists among all underprivileged people. No general human interest can emerge when the “haves” constitute a standing reproach to the

material denial of the “have-nots” and when those who are idle mock,

by their very existence, the lifetime of toil imposed on working classes.

Nor will a participatory democracy ever be achieved by society as a

whole as long as a public life is available only to those who have the

free time to participate in it.

Insofar as humanity could make decisive choices about the social

direction it should follow, its choices have been largely bad ones. The

result has been that humanity has generally been less than human.

Rarely has it fulfilled what it could be, given its potentialities for

thought, feeling, ethical judgements, and rational social arrangements.

The ideals of freedom are now in place, as I have noted, and they

can be described with reasonable clarity and coherence. We are confronted with the need not simply to improve society or alter it; we are

confronted with the need to *remake* it. The ecological crises we face

and the social conflicts that have torn us apart and have made our century the bloodiest in history, can be resolved only if we clearly

recognize that our problems go to the heart of a domineering *civilization*, not simply to a badly structured ensemble of social relations.

Our present civilization is nothing if it is not Janus-faced and riddled

with ambiguity. We cannot simply denounce it as male-oriented, exploitative, and domineering without recognizing that it also freed us, at

least in part, from the parochial bonds of tribalism and an abject

obedience to superstition, which ultimately made us vulnerable to

domination. By the same token, we cannot simply praise it for its

growing universality, the extent to which it fostered individual

autonomy, and the rational secularism it brought to human affairs

without recognizing that these achievements were generally purchased

at the cost of human enslavement, mass degradation, class rule, and the

establishment of the State. Only a dialectic that combines searching

critique with social creativity can disassemble the best materials from

our shattered world and bring them to the service of remaking a new

one.

I have stressed that our foremost need is to create a general human

interest that can unify humanity as a whole. Minimally, this interest

centres around the establishment of a harmonious balance with nature.

Our viability as a species depends upon our future relationship with the

natural world. This problem cannot be settled by the invention of new

technologies that will supplant natural processes without making

society more technocratic, more centralized, and ultimately completely

totalitarian. For technology to replace the natural cycles that determine

the ratio of atmospheric carbon dioxide to oxygen, to provide a substitute for the decomposing ozone layer that protects all life from lethal

solar radiation, to substitute hydroponic solutions for soil — all of this,

if it were possible, would require a highly disciplined system of social

management that is radically incompatible with democracy and political participation by the people.

Such an overwhelming, indeed global, reality raises questions about

the future of humanity on a scale that no historical period in die past

has ever been compelled to face. The message raised by an “ecological

technocracy,” if it can be called that, is for a degree of social coordination that beggars the most centralized despotisms of history. Even so,

it remains very unclear that such an ecological technocracy can be

achieved on scientific grounds, or that, in view of the delicate checks

and balances involved, whether technological substitutes for natural

processes can be so well adjusted that they will not be subject to

catastrophic misjudgements.

If the life processes of the planet and those of our species are not to

be administered by a totalitarian system, modern society must follow

certain basic ecological precepts. I have argued in this book that the

harmonizadon of nature cannot be achieved without the harmonization

of human with human. This means that our very notion of what

constitutes humanity must be clarified. If we remain merely conflicting

class beings, genders, ethnic beings, and nationalities, it is obvious that

any kind of harmony between human beings will be impossible. As

members of classes, genders, ethnic groups, and nationalities, we will

have narrowed our meaning of what it is to be human by means of

particularistic interests that explicitly set us against each other.

Although ecology advances a message of diversity, it does so as

conflict; it rests on differentiation, on the wholeness that is enhanced

by the variety of its constituents. Socially, this view is expressed in the

Greek ideal that the complete, many-sided person is the product of a

complete, many-sided society. Class, gender, ethnic, and national interests are fearfully similar in their reduction of a widely expansive

view of the world to a narrow one, of larger interests to smaller ones,

of complementarity to conflict. To preach a message of reconciliation

when class, gender, ethnic, and national interests are very real and

objectively grounded in major conflicts, would be absurd, to be sure.

Our Janus-faced civilization looks toward a long past that has seen mere

differences in age, sex, and kinship reworked into domineering hierarchies, hierarchies into classes, and classes into state structures. The

bases for conflicting interests in society must themselves be confronted

and resolved in a revolutionary manner. The earth can no longer be

owned; it must be shared. Its fruits, including those produced by

technology and labour, can no longer be expropriated by the few; they

must be rendered available to all on the basis of need. Power, no less

that material things, must be freed from the control of the elites; it must

be redistributed in a form that renders its use participatory. Until these

basic problems are resolved, there can be no development of a general

interest that will formulate a policy to resolve the growing ecological

crisis and the inadequacy of this society to deal with it.

The point I wish to make, however, is that no general interest of this

kind can be achieved by the particularistic means that marked earlier

revolutionary movements. The present ecological crisis is potentially

capable of mobilizing a degree of public support and involvement that

is more transclass and wider than any issue that humanity has faced in

the past And with the passing of time, this crisis will become starker

and more all-embracing than it is today. Its mystification by religious

ideologists and corporate hirelings threatens to place the very future of

the biosphere in the balance.

Nor can we ignore the recent history of the revolutionary project and

the advances it scored over earlier ones. Past revolutions were largely

struggles for justice, not for freedom. The ideals of liberty, equality,

and fraternity, so generously advanced by the French Revolution,

foundered on the faulty definition of the terms themselves. I will not

belabour the fact that the crassly particularistic interests of the bourgeoisie interpreted liberty to mean free trade; equality to mean the right

to contract labour; and fraternity to mean the obedience on an emerging

proletariat to capitalist supremacy. Hidden more deeply in this slogan

of classical republicanism was the fact that liberty meant little more

than the right of the ego to pursue its own self interest; equality, the

principle of justice; fraternity, taken literally, a male-centred society of

“brothers” however much some men exploited others.

Taken at face value, the slogans of the revolution never ascended to

the domain of freedom. On whatever level we examine the revolution,

it was a project to achieve an inequality of equals, not to achieve an

equality of unequals. The tragically aborted Spanish Revolution of

1936–1937 tried to go beyond this limited project but it was isolated.

Its most revolutionary elements — the anarchists — never gained the

popular support they needed in the country as a whole to realize their

richly emancipatory goals.

Capitalism has changed in the decades that followed the era of

proletarian socialism. Its impact on society and nature is perhaps more

devastating than at any time since the Industrial Revolution. The

modern revolutionary project, initiated by the New Left of the sixties,

with its call for a participatory democracy, has gone far beyond the level

of the classical revolutions and their particularistic aims. The idea of

“the People,” an illusory concept that informed the emergence of

democratic movements in the eighteenth century just as society was

beginning to differentiate itself into clearly definable classes, has now

taken on a new meaning with the steady decomposition of traditional

classes and with the emergence of transclass issues like ecology, feminism, and a sense of civic responsibility to neighbourhoods and

communities. Movements like the Greens in Germany, and possibly

other countries, or various citizens’ initiative movements in a growing

number of cities and towns are addressing larger human issues than

increased wages and class conflicts at the point of production. With the

rise of ecology, feminist, and citizens’ movements, new possibilities

exist for generalizing the ideals of freedom, for giving them a broadly

human and truly populist dimension.

To talk vaguely of “the People,” however, without examining the

relationship of the ordinary citizen to populist-type goals, raises the

danger of dealing with the kind of vague abstractions that characterized

Marxism for more than a century. Over and beyond the need to share

the earth, to distribute its fruits according to need, and to develop a

general human interest that goes beyond the particularistic ones of the

past, the revolutionary project must take its point of departure from a

fundamental libertarian precept; every normal human being is *competent* to manage the affairs of society and, more specifically, the

community in which he or she is a member.

This precept lays down a radical gauntlet to Jacobin abstractions like

“the People” and Marxist abstractions like “the Proletariat” by demanding that society must be existentially “peopled” by real, living beings

who are free to control their own destinies and that of their society. It

challenges parliamentarism as a surrogate for an authentic democracy

with Rousseau’s classical observation:

Sovereignty, for the same reason as it makes it inalienable,
cannot be represented. It lies essentially in the general will,
and will does not admit of representation: it is either the same,
or other; there is no intermediate possibility. The deputies of
the people, therefore, are not and cannot be its representatives:
they are merely its stewards, and can carry through no definitive acts. Every law the people has not ratified in person is null
and void — is, in fact, not a law. The people of England
regards itself as free; but it is grossly mistaken: it is free only
during the election of members of parliament. As soon as they
are elected, slavery overtakes it, and it is nothing. [21]

Whatever interpretation one may give to Rousseau’s “general will”

and other formulations he advances, the statement’s basic thrust forms

an imperishable and unnegotiable ideal of human freedom. It implies

that no substantive democracy is possible and no concept of self-administration is meaningful unless the people convene in open, face-to-face assemblies to formulate policies for society. No policy, in effect, is democratically legitimate unless it has been proposed, discussed, and

decided upon by the people directly — not through representatives or

surrogates of any kind. The *administration* of these policies can be left

to boards, commissions, or collectives of qualified, even elected, individuals who, under close public purview and with full accountability

to policy-making assemblies, may execute the popular mandate.

This distinction between policy and administration — one which

Marx failed to make in his writings on the Paris Commune of 1871 —

is crucial. Popular assemblies are the minds of a free society; the

administrators of their policies are the hands. The former can always

recall the latter and end their operations, depending upon need, dissatisfaction and the like. The latter merely effects what the former decides

and remains totally dependent upon their will.

This crucial distinction makes the popular assembly’s existence a

largely functional issue in democratic procedures, not a structural one.

In principle, assemblies can function under any demographic and urban

conditions — on the block, neighbourhood, or town levels. They have

only to be coordinated by appropriately confederal sinews to become

forms of self-governance. Given modern logistical conditions, there

can be no emergency so great that assemblies cannot be rapidly convened to make important policy decisions by a majority vote and die

appropriate boards convened to execute these decisions—irrespective

of a community’s size or the complexity of its problems. Experts will

always be available to offer their solutions, hopefully competing ones

that will foster discussion, to the more specialized problems a community may face.

Nor can populations be so large or the number of assemblies so

numerous that they cannot be coordinated in a manner that perpetuates

their integrity as face-to-face policy-making bodies. Delegates to town,

city, and regional bodies, can be regarded simply as the walking

mandates of the local assemblies. Furthermore, we must disabuse

ourselves of the idea that consensus can always be attained in large

groups. A minority does not have the right to abort a decision of a

majority — be it within an assembly or between assemblies. If

Rousseau’s “general will” could, in fact, be transformed into a *generalized will* — that is to say, if it could be supposed that rational people

who have no interests apart from those of the community at large will

make shared rational decisions about transparently clear issues — it

may well be that consensus can be achieved.

But by no means is this goal even desirable. It is a hidden tyranny

based on unthinking custom, in fact, an atavistic throwback to times

when *public opinion* was as coercive as outright violence (which, at

least, existed in the open). A tyranny of consensus, like the famous

“tyranny of structurelessness,” demeans a free society. It tends to

subvert individuality in the name of community and dissent in the name

of solidarity. Neither true community nor solidarity are fostered when

the individual’s development is aborted by public disapproval and his

or her deviant ideas are “normalized” by the pressure of public opinion.

Underlying the development of self-managing, face-to-face assemblies are a number of ethical, even educational problems that enter

into developing competent individuals. The assembly reached its most

sophisticated form of development in the Athenian *polis*, where, contrary to current criticisms of the Hellenic city as “patriarchal,” most

ancients viewed it as a huge “mobocracy.” It retained this pejorative

reputation well into modern times. That radicals in the twentieth

century, who view it from the hindsight of more than two thousand

years, can denounce it as a “tyranny” that oppressed women, slaves,

and resident aliens, is not without a certain irony. Given the more

morbid abuses of the ancient world, which was drenched in patriarchy,

slavery, and despotism, the Athenian democracy stands out like a

beacon of light. The view that Western democracy can be dismissed

simply as a “male” tradition and that we should return to “tribal”

traditions, whatever these may be, is atavistic to the core. In the *polis*,

the Janus-faced nature of Western civilization — the East offers no

notable improvements upon it, I may add — actually exhibits its better

profile in the history of freedom.

All of this raises the question of what constitutes the ethical basis of

the assembly and its time-honoured standards of competence. The first

was the ideal of solidarity or friendship (*philia*), an ideal in which

loyalty to the community was given flesh and blood by intimate

relationships between its members. A lived, vital, and deeply felt

consociation existed among many members of the Athenian *polis*, in

the guilds of the medieval towns, and among an endless network of

small societies in the towns and cities of the precapitalist world. The

Greek symposium, in which knots of friends gathered to dine, drink,

and discuss, was matched in part by the rich neighbourhood cafe life

of French, Spanish, and Italian cities. The community was made up, in

a sense, of smaller “communes,” The counterculture of the sixties

turned this literally into communal forms of living. The ideal of a

Commune of communes was openly advanced in 1871 in the revolutionary proclamations of the Paris Commune during its brief lifespan.

Popular societies clustered around the Parisian sections of 1793 and

provided ways of associating that made the revolution an intimate

exercise in civic affinity.

Still another ethical ideal was the importance that was attached to

roundedness. The Greeks mistrusted specialists, despite Plato’s

favourable view of them, because excessive expertise seemed to involve a warping of one’s character around a particular interest or skill.

To know a little bit about everything and not too much about one thing

was evidence of a rounded person who, as need arose, could form an

intelligent view of an issue and advance a good case for his judgements.

This emphasis on amateurism, an emphasis that did not prevent the Greeks from founding Western philosophy, science, mathematics, and

drama, was to be an abiding ideal for centuries after the *polis* disappeared into history.

Roundedness also implied a measure of self-sufficiency. To be one’s

“own man” meant not only that one was competent but also independent. In earlier times, this rounded person was expected to be free

of a client position. A special interest might render an individual

vulnerable to and dependent upon the wishes of a master. The individual who could perform many different tasks, it was supposed,

could understand a wide array of problems. If he was independent

materially, say, like a farmer who owned the land he worked, and could

meet most of his needs by his own efforts and skills, he was presumably

capable of forming an objective judgement, free of undue influence by

the opinions of others. The Greeks believed in owning property not

because they were acquisitive; indeed, to give generously to one’s

friends and neighbours earned the highest esteem in Greek society. But

a modest piece of land that could provide the farmer and his family with

the basic means of life freed him from manipulation by landed aristocracies and merchants.

To give of one’s free time and services to the *polis* was seen as

another ideal that often led to agonistic efforts to gain public recognition, a Greek character trait that has been sharply reproached but often

grossly misunderstood. The zeal with which the Greeks served their

communities, in fact, was idealized as a form of civic dedication up to

our own time. Civic recognition often required considerable personal

sacrifices, and the zeal exhibited by leading Greeks stemmed from a

desire for social immortality. Indeed, to destroy a Greek city meant to

efface the memory and immortality of its more heroic figures as well

as to destroy the very identity of its inhabitants.

If civic zealotry threatened to upset the relatively delicate balances

of a class society that could easily plunge into insurrection, the Greeks

formulated an ideal of “limit” — the “golden mean” which meant

“nothing in excess”—that was to be carried deeply into Western ethics.

The notion of limit was to appear in medieval towns and cities and even

well into the Renaissance. Beneath the clamour that marked the Italian

city-states of the late Middle Ages, there were unstated rules of civic

behaviour that placed constraints on excessive zealotry and fractious

behaviour, despite the ultimate emergence of oligarchies and one-man

rule.

As M.I. Finley has pointed out, the Athenian *polis* — and, I would

contend, many democratic towns that followed it in time — essentially

established a system of civic etiquette that kept excessive ambition

under a measure of control. Medieval Italian cities, for example, created

remarkable checks and balances to prevent one interest in the city from

gaining too much ascendancy over another, a balance that the Greek

psychological attributes that many precapitalist cities, structured

around assemblies, actually translated into institutions in a system of

checks that fostered harmony, however tentative they may seem. Power

was often divided and subdivided so that countervailing forces existed

to prevent the ascendancy of any one institution, and the interests it

represented, from becoming excessively powerful.

Taken together, this ethical ensemble was personified in a new kind

of individual — a *citizen*. The citizen was neither a tribal person nor

the member of a kin group, although strong family relationships existed

in the precapitalist cities of the past and kinship ties played a major role

in political conflicts. But to be a citizen in the traditional sense, one had

to be more than a kinsman. The primary allegiances of the citizen were

to the *polis*, town, or city — at least, before the nation-state turned

citizenship into a parody of its original meaning.

Citizens, in turn, were created through training, a process of **character**-building that the Greeks called *paidaia*. which is not quite properly translated by the word “education.” One had to learn civic responsibility, to reason out one’s views with scrupulous care, to confront opposing arguments with clarity, and, hopefully, to advance tested principles that exhibited high ethical standards. Additionally, a citizen was expected to learn martial arts, to work together with fellow citizens in militia detachments; indeed, in many cases, to learn how to command properly during military engagements.

The citizen of a precapitalist democratic city, in short, was not the

“constituent” of a parliamentary representative, or a mere “taxpayer,”

to use modern civic jargon. He was, in the best of cases, a knowledgeable, civically dedicated, active, and, above all, *self-governing* being

who exercised considerable inner discipline and made the welfare of

his community — its general interest — his primary interest to the

exclusion of his own self-interest.

This constellation of ethical precepts formed a unified whole,

without which civic democracy and popular assemblies would not have

been possible. Rousseau’s remarkable statement that citizens make

cities, not merely buildings, cannot be restated often enough. Without

citizens, viewed in this classical sense, cities were mere clusters of

buildings which tended to degenerate into oligarchies or become absorbed into nation-states.

Libertarian Municipalism

From the foregoing, it should be obvious that the assembly of the

people found its authentic home in the city — and in cities of a very

special kind. The Janus-faced character of Western civilization obliges

us to sift the unsavoury features of the city — the legitimation it gave

to the private ownership of property, classes, patricentricity, and the

State — from the great civilized advances it scored as a new terrain for

a universal *humanitas*. Today, at a time when anti-city biases have cast

the city in an ugly social light, it may be well to emphasize the major

advance the city scored in providing a shared domain for people of

different ethnic backgrounds, occupations, and status groups.

“Civilization,” a term that is derived from the Latin word for city, was

not simply a “slaughter bench,” to use Hegel’s dramatic phrase. It was

literally Janus-faced (as Hegel only too well appreciated) in its look

toward the prospect of a common humanity as well as in its look toward

barbarities that were to be justified in the name of progress and cultural

advances.

Participatory democracies and popular assemblies, to be sure,

originated in tribal and village communities. But they did not become

themselves until the city emerged. There is some evidence that they

existed as early as Sumerian times in the cities that appeared in

Mesopotamia. But it was the Greek *polis* and later medieval towns that

made these democracies and assemblies acutely aware of the fact that

they were a *way of life*, not simply a technique for managing society,

and that they should be constructed along *ethical* and *rational* lines

that met certain ideals of justice and the good life, not merely institutions sanctified by custom. Cities comprised a decisive step forward in

social life and, for all their limitations, gave us works like Plato’s

presence in the Western imagination for centuries.

The self-reflective nature of the city turned it into a remarkably

unique and creative human institution. To Aristotle, the city — more

properly, the *polis*, which was a highly self-conscious ethical entity —

had to conform to certain structural standards if it was to fulfill its

ethical functions. It had to be large enough so that its citizens could

meet most of their material needs, yet not so large that they were unable

to gain a familiarity with each other and make policy decisions in open,

face-to-face discourse. Structure and ethics, function and ideals of

freedom, were inseparable from each other. For all his faults, Aristotle

tried — as did so many of the Athenians among whom he lived — to

bring form into the service of content He opposed any separation of

the two, even in detailed discussions of city planning.

This approach became a cornerstone of the Western democratic

tradition. It may have existed in the minds of figures like the Gracchi

brothers in ancient Rome, Cola di Rienzi in medieval Rome, and

Etienne Marcel in the Paris of the fourteenth century; men who led the

urban masses in dramatic revolts to achieve city confederations and

establish civic democracies. It was raised by Spanish cities that revolted

against centralized rule in the sixteenth century and, again, in the

French Revolution and the Paris Commune of 1871. It exists in our own

time in New England town meetings, many of which still vigilantly

guard their localist rights.

The city, in effect, opened a new terrain for social management that

involves neither the use of state institutions — that is, statecraft—nor

a strictly private domain that involves one’s home, workplace, schools,

religious institutions, and circles of friends. Taken literally from the

Greek term in which it originates, the city created *politics*, a very unique

world in which citizens gather together to rationally discuss their problems

as a community and administer their affairs in a face-to-face manner.

Whether a municipality can be administered by all its citizens in a

single assembly or has to be subdivided into several confederally

related assemblies depends very much upon its size, hence Aristotle’s

injunction that a *polis* should not be so large that one could not hear a

cry for help from the city walls. Although assemblies can function as

networks on a block, neighbourhood, or town level, they fulfill traditional ideals of civic democracy when the cities in which they arc

located are decentralized. The anarchic vision of decentralized communities, united in free confederations or networks for coordinating the

communities of a region, reflects the traditional ideals of a participatory

democracy in a modern radical context.

Today, in the prevailing social condition that casts a dark shadow

over the future of the present era, we are losing sight of the very *idea*

of a city, of citizenship, and of politics as a domain of municipal

self-management. Cities are being confused with huge urban belts that

should properly be described as a seemingly unending process of

“urbanization ” Vast stretches of concrete and high-rise buildings are

engulfing the definable, humanly scaled entities we once called cities

and they are sweeping in the countryside as well.

By the same token, citizens are shrivelling to the status of

anonymous “constituents” of elected representatives. Their principal

function is to pay taxes, to do the onerous work-a-day job of maintaining the present society, to reproduce, and to decorously withdraw from

all political life — a domain that is reserved for the State and its

officialdom. Our warped discourse blurs the crucial distinctions between citification and urbanization, citizens and constituents, politics and statecraft.

The city, as a humanly scaled, self-governing municipality freely

and confederally associated with other humanly scaled, self-governing

municipalities, is dissolving into huge urban belts. The citizen, as an

active formulator of policies, is being reduced to a passive taxpayer,

the mere recipient of public services provided by bureaucratic agencies.

Politics is being degraded into statecraft, an art practised by cynical,

professional manipulators of power.

The entire ensemble is managed like a business. It is regarded as

successful if it earns fiscal “surpluses” and provides needed services,

or, it is a failure if it is burdened by fiscal “deficits” and operates

inefficiently. The *ethical* content of city life as an arena for the inculcation of civic virtue, democratic ideals, and social responsibility is

simply erased and its place is taken by an entrepreneurial mentality that

emphasizes income, expenses, growth, and employment.

At the same time, power is thoroughly bureaucratized, centralized,

and concentrated into fewer and fewer hands. The power that should

be claimed by the people is pre-empted by the State and by semi-monopolistic economic entities. Democracy, far from acquiring a participatory character, becomes purely formal in character. Indeed, the

New Left was an expression of a deeply felt desire for reempowerment

that has continued unabatedly since the sixties — a desire to regain

citizenship, to end the degradation of politics into statecraft: the need

to revive public life.

These issues still remain at the top of the present social agenda. The

rise of citizens initiative movements in Germany, of municipal movements in the United States, of attempts to revive civic ideals in various

European countries, including France’s recovery of words like

are evidence of popular attempts to achieve reempowerment over social

life. In many places, the State, with its extensive cutbacks of social

services, has left a vacuum that cities are obliged to Fill merely to remain

functional. Transportation, housing, and welfare needs are being met

more by localities than they have been in the past. Urban residents,

obliged to fend for themselves, are learning the arts of teamwork and

cooperation.

A gap, ideological as well as practical, is opening up between

nation-state, which is becoming more anonymous, bureaucratic,

remote, and the municipality, which is the one domain outside

personal life that the individual must deal with on a very direct basis.

We do not go to the nation-state to find suitable schools for our children

for jobs, culture, and decent places in which to live. Like it or not, the

ill the most immediate environment which we encounter and

which we are obliged to deal, beyond the sphere of family and

in order to satisfy our needs as social beings.

Potentially, the sense of disempowerment that has become the

popular malaise of our time could also become a source of dual power

in the great nation-states of the Western world. Conscious movements

have yet to arise that search for ways to get from a centralized, statist

“here” to a civically decentralized and confederal “there,” movements

that can raise the demand for communal confederation as a popular

alternative to the modern-day centralization of power. Unless we try

— vainly, I believe — to revive myths of proletarian insurrections, of

a feeble armed confrontation with the vast nuclear armamentarium of

the modern nation-state, we are obliged to seek out counter-**institutions** that stand opposed to the power of the nation-state.

Communes, cooperatives, and various vocational collectives, to be

sure, may be excellent schools for teaching people how to administer

self-managed enterprises. But they are usually marginal projects, often

very short-lived, and more useful as examples than as working institutions. No cooperative will ever replace a giant supermarket chain

merely by competing with it, however much good will it may earn, nor

will a Proudhonian “People’s Bank” replace a major Financial institution, however many supporters it may have.

We have other things we can learn from a Proudhon, who saw in the

municipality an important arena of popular activity. I do not hesitate to

use the word *politics*, here, if it is understood in its Hellenic meaning

as the management of the community or *polis* by popular assemblies,

not as statecraft and parliamentary activity. Every society contains

vestiges of the past—of earlier, often more libertarian institutions that

have been incorporated into present ones. The American Republic, for

example, still has elements of a democracy like the town meeting,

which Tocqueville described in his book, *Democracy in America*.

Italian cities still have vital neighbourhoods that can form a basis for

new community relationships. French towns still retain mainly humanly scaled features that can be organized into new political entities. Such

observations can be made about communities throughout the world —

communities whose solidarity opens the prospect of a new politics

based on libertarian municipalism — which eventually could become

a counterpower to the nation-state.

Let me emphasize that this approach presupposes that we are talking

about a *movement*, not isolated instances where people in a single

community assume control of their municipality and restructure it on

the basis of neighbourhood assemblies. It presupposes that a movement

will exist that alters one community after another and establishes a

system of confederal relationships between municipalities; one that

will form a regional power in its own right. How far we can take this

libertarian municipalist approach is impossible to judge without knowing in detail the lived traditions of a region, the civic resources it

possesses, and the problems it faces. Given this writer’s experience

with the issue of local control in the United States, this much can be

said: no demand, when it has been raised, has been met with greater

resistance by the State power. The nation-state knows, far better than

its opponents in radical movements, how destabilizing to its authority

demands for local control can be.

Yet the idea of libertarian municipalism has a pedigree that dates

back to the American and French revolutions and to the Paris Commune, in which confederalism was a viable proposal to large masses of

people. Dramatic as the changes have been since that time, there is no

reason in principle to doubt why libertarian municipalism cannot be

raised today, when squatters’ movements, neighbourhood organizations, and community welfare groups have risen and fallen — only to rise again as evidence of a chronic impulse that the nation-state has

never been able to exorcise.

Decentralization and Technology

Social ecology has added a unique, indeed urgent, dimension to the

need for a libertarian municipalist movement and the issues it faces.

The need to rescale communities to fit the natural carrying capacity of

the regions in which they are located and to create a new balance

between town and country — all traditional demands of the great

utopian and anarchist thinkers of the last century — have become

ecological imperatives today. Not only are they the seemingly utopian

visions of yester-year, the dreams and desiderata of lonely thinkers;

they have compelling necessities if we are to remain a viable species

and live in harmony with a complex natural world that is threatened

with destruction. Ecology, in effect, has essentially advanced the sharp

alternatives: either we will turn to seemingly “utopian” solutions based

on decentralization, a new equilibrium with nature, and the harmonization of social relations, or we face the very real subversion of the

material and natural basis for human life on the planet. {2}

{2} I cannot help but make an observation about the massive ignorance that exists in the American and European ecology movements with respect to the long pedigree of these ideals. Anarchism, which has been pilfered repeatedly and scandalously by “neo-Marxists” of ideas like workers’ control and decentralization, not to speak of the general strike — notions that Marx and Engels explicitly denigrated — are today common fare in self-styled “Marxist” movements. The same is true of Fourier, Owen, and particularly Kropotkin’s ideas, not to mention views advanced by anarchists in the early sixties. Yet barely a word of acknowledgement is made by the ill-informed wags who, particularly in the shelter of the academy, have recycled so many eco-anarchist ideas in the name of “deep ecology” and “eco-feminism.” Apparently, nothing exists in American and European thought until it has first been duly registered in an academic journal as a “paper” and, to be sure, by a professor or an aspiring one.

Urbanization threatens to efface not only the city but the

countryside. The famous contradiction between town and country

which figured so significantly in the history of social thought has now

become meaningless. This contradiction is now being effaced by the

spread of concrete over irredeemable areas of agricultural land and

historically unique agrarian communities. The homogenization of rural

cultures by the mass media, urban lifestyles, and an all-pervasive

consumerist mentality threatens to destroy not only regionally unique

and colourful lifeways; it is totally degrading the natural landscape.

What argibusiness has not already poisoned with its pesticides, chemical fertilizers, and heavy machines that compact the soil, acid rain and

socially induced climatic changes are destroying in the form of deforestation and aridity. The urbanization of the planet is simplifying complex

ecosystems, eliminating soil that was in the making for ages, reducing

wilderness to fragile “reserves,” and, whether directly or indirectly,

profoundly altering regional climatic zones for the worst.

The technology we have inherited from earlier industrial revolutions, the insensate use of private motor vehicles, the concentration of

massive industrial facilities near waterways, the massive use of fossil

and nuclear fuels, and an economic system whose law of life is growth

all are producing in only a few decades a degree of environmental

degradation that human habitation did not produce from its inception.

Nearly all our waterways are odious sewers. “Dead seas” have been

found in oceanic waters that extend over hundreds of miles in once

thriving aquatic areas. I do not have to elaborate on this dark litany of

widespread, possibly deadly, wounds that are being inflicted on every

part of the planet. It is only too well-known what is being done to our

atmosphere, to the ozone layer that protects life on the planet, even to

more remote areas of the globe like the Arctic and, more recently,

Antarctica, rain forests and, of course, temperate forests.

Our ultimate survival on the planet, not only our commitment to live

fully human lives and fulfill our more libertarian visions, dictates that we

re-assess our notions of urbanism and the relationship of cities to the

ecological substrate. It also dictates that we re-assess our technologies

and the goods they produce, indeed, our entire view toward nature.

We need smaller cities not only to realize cherished ideas of freedom

but also to meet the most elementary needs to live in some kind of

balance with nature. Giant cities, more precisely, sprawling urban belts,

not only make for cultural homogeneity, individual anonymity, and

centralized power, they place an impossible burden on local water

resources, the air we breathe, and all the natural features of the areas

which they occupy. Congestion, noise, and the stresses introduced by

modern urban living arc becoming increasingly intolerable, psychically

as well as physically. Cities which historically served to bring people

of diverse background together, and made for communal solidarity, are

now atomizing them. The city is the place in which to hide, as it were,

not to seek human propinquity. Fear tends to replace sociality, rudeness

eats away at solidarity, the herding of people into overcrowded dwellings, means of transportation, offices, and shopping centres subverts

their sense of individuality and fosters indifference to the overall human

condition.

Decentralization of large cities into humanly scaled communities is

neither a romantic mystification of a nature-loving soloist nor is it a

remote anarchic ideal. It has become *indispensable* to an ecologically

sound society. What is now at stake in these seemingly “utopian”

demands is a choice between a rapidly degrading environment and a

society that will live in balance with nature in a viable and on a

sustainable basis.

The same can be said for reconsidering the technological basis of

modern society. Production can no longer be seen as a source of profit

and the realization of one’s self-interest. The finished goods human

beings need to maintain their very lives as well as their cultural and

physical well-being, are more hallowed than the mystified fetishes that

have been used by various religions and superstitious cults to dazzle

them. Bread, if you please, is more “sacred” than a priestly benediction;

everyday clothing is more “holy” than clerical vestments; personal

dwellings are more spiritually meaningful than churches and temples;

the good life on earth is more sanctifying than the promised one in

heaven. The means of life must be taken for what they literally are:

than “theft” (to use Proudhon’s choice word for property); it is outright

homicide.

No one has a right to own property on which the lives of others

depend, — either morally, socially, or ecologically. Nor does anyone

have a right to design, employ, or impose privately owned technological equipment on society that damages human health and the health of the planet.

Here, ecology completely dovetails with society to yield a social

ecology that emphasizes the close interconnection between ecological

social problems. Technology — the kind society uses to maintain

human planetary life and the kind that undermines both — is one of the

social values and ecological values. At a time of sweeping ecological degradation, we can no longer retain techniques that wantonly damage human beings and the planet alike — and it is hard to think that damage can be inflicted on the one

without being inflicted on the other.

A major tragedy of our times is that we no longer look at technics

as an ethical relationship, Greek thought maintained that to produce an

object of high quality and artistry was a moral calling that involved a

special relationship between an artisan and the object he or she

produced. Indeed, to many tribal peoples, to craft a thing was to

actualize the raw material’s potentialities, to give soapstone, marble.

bronze, and other materials, a “voice,” as it were, an expression that

realized its latent capacity for form.

Capitalism eliminated this outlook completely. Indeed, it severed

the relationship of the producer to the consumer, eliminating any sense

of ethical responsibility of the former to the latter, leaving all other

ethical or moral responsibilities aside. If there was any moral dimension

to capitalist production, it was the claim that self interest was guided by

an “invisible hand” — the interplay of market forces — so that

production for profit and personal gain would ultimately serve the

“general good.”

But even this shabby apologia has all but disappeared today,

abated greed, another example of the ethics of evil, has replaced

any sense of the public good. A corporation is lauded simply because

it is less greedy than another — not because its operations are intrinsically

good. Although it is all too easy to blame on technics what is really the

result of bourgeois interest, technics, when divested of any moral constraints

can also become demonic under capitalism. A nuclear power plant, for example

is intrinsically evil; it can have no justification for existence. That increased nuclear reactors will eventually turn the entire planet into a huge nuclear bomb if enough Chernobyl accidents occur — and with more plants, they cease to be a matter of mere accident and become one of probability — is no longer doubted by any informed person today.

Growing ecological dislocations are making what were once conventional industrial operations equally problematic. Agribusiness, at

one time marginal to die family-type farm, has become so widespread

in recent decades that its pesticides and synthetic fertilizers are becoming global problems. Smoke-belching installations and the wanton use

of automobiles are changing the entire ecological balance of nature,

particularly the earth’s atmosphere, for the worse. If one surveys the

landscape of modern technology, it is not hard to see a profound need

to alter it enormously. Not only ecological interests, but human self-interest requires that we move toward ecological technologies and render

our technological interaction with nature creative rather than destructive.

Let me emphasize again that such a change cannot be made without

doing the same for our interaction with each other and formulating a

general interest that outweighs the particularized interests of hierarchy,

class, gender, ethnic backgrounds, and the Stale. The precondition for

a harmonious relationship with nature is social: a harmonious relationship between human and human. This involves the abolition of hierarchy in all its forms — psychological and cultural as well as social — and of classes, private property, and the State.

<br>

<br>

The move from “here to there” will not be a sudden explosion of

change without a long period of intellectual and ethical preparation.

The world has to be educated as fully as possible if people are to change

their lives, not merely have it changed for them by self-anointed elites

who will eventually become self-seeking oligarchies. Sensibility,

ethics, ways of viewing reality, and selfhood have to be changed by

educational means, by a politics of reasoned discourse, experimentation, and the expectation of repeated failures from which we have to

learn, if humanity is to achieve the self-consciousness it needs to finally

engage in self-management.

No longer can radical movements afford to plunge unthinkingly into

action for its own sake. We have never been in greater need of

theoretical insight and study than we are today, when political illiteracy

has reached appalling proportions and action has become a fetish as an

end in itself. We are also in dire need of organization—not the nihilistic

chaos of self-indulgent egotists in which structure of any kind is decried

as “elitist” and “centralist,” Patience, the hard work of responsible

commitment in the day-to-day work of building a movement, is to be

prized over the theatrics of prima donnas who are always willing to

“die” on the barricades of a distant “revolution” but who are too

high-minded to engage in the humdrum tasks of spreading ideas and

maintaining an organization.

To move from “here to there” is a demanding *process*, not a dramatic

gesture. It will always be marked by uncertainties, failures, digressions,

and disputes before it finds its sense of direction. Nor is there any

certainty that basic social change will succeed in one’s lifetime.

Revolutionaries today must draw their inspiration from the high

idealists of the past like the great Russian and French revolutionaries

of the last century who had little hope that they would witness the great

upheavals that confronted later generations but to which they contributed the example of their lives, dedication, and convictions. Revolutionary commitment is not only a calling that seeks to change the world; it is also an inward imperative to save one’s own identity and individuality from a corruptive society that degrades one’s very personality with the lure of cheap emoluments and the promise of status in a totally meaningless world.

A new politics must be created that eschews the snares of parliamentarism and the immediate gratification of a media-contrived “forum,”

which is more self-aggrandizing than educational. Movements like the

German Greens are already filled with self-serving stars who are

undermining the integrity, ethical outlook, and elan of their more heroic

days. New programs and a new politics must be structured around the

immediate environment of the individual — his or her housing conditions, neighbourhood problems, transportation facilities, economic

conditions, pollution issues, and workplace conditions. Power must be

steadily shifted to neighbourhoods and municipalities in the form of

community centres, cooperatives, occupational centres, and ultimately,

citizens’ assemblies.

Success cannot be measured by the immediate and constant support

a movement of this kind gains. Only a relatively small number of people

will initially work with such a movement and only a relatively few are

likely to participate in neighbourhood assemblies and municipal confederations — except perhaps when very important issues emerge that

command wide public attention. Old ideas and methods which have

become routine in every day life die very slowly; new ones are likely

to grow very slowly. Citizen initiatives’ groups may spring up suddenly

with fervour and elan when a community is confronted with, say, the

siting of a nuclear power plant in its midst or the discovery of a toxic

dump in its environs. An ecologically oriented municipalist movement

must never delude itself that such mass activities are necessarily lasting

ones. They can fade away as quickly as they emerge. One can only hope

that they establish a tradition that can be invoked in the future and that

the popular education they provide has not been lost on the community

at large.

At the same time, truly committed members of such a movement

must advance with a vision of what society should be like in the long

run. They must go very far in their goals so that others increasingly go

far enough in their activities. Such a core of people must advance

historic solutions as well as immediately practical ones. The present

society makes all the rules of the game by which even the most

well-intentioned rebels play. If this all-important fact is not clearly

seen, morally debilitating compromises will, in fact, become the rule

that will lead to an ethics of evil based on lesser evils that eventually

yield the worst of evils. No radical movement, in effect, can lose sight

of its ultimate vision of an ecological society without losing, bit by bit,

all the constituents that give it its own identity.

This vision must be stated clearly so that it can never be compromised. The vagueness of socialist and Marxist ends has done irreparable damage in degrading these ends by the exigencies of a

“pragmatic” politics and by manipulative compromises — ultimately,

the surrender of a movement’s very reason for existing. A movement

must give a visual character to its ideals so that it enters into the

imagination of a new politics, not merely present its ideas in programmatic statements. Such attempts have been made with considerable

success in the past by groups like People’s Architecture, which took

the pains to replan entire neighbourhoods in Berkeley, California, and

visually demonstrate how they could become more habitable, communal, and aesthetically attractive.

An Ecological Society

Today, we have a magnificent repertoire of new ideas, plans, technological designs, and working data that can give us a graphic picture

of an ecological community and a participatory democracy. Valuable

as these materials may be in demonstrating that we can finally build

sustainable communities based on renewable resources, they should not

be seen simply as new systems of engineering society into a balanced

relationship with a given natural environment.

They also have far-reaching *ethical* implications that can only be

ignored by fostering an eco-technocratic mentality toward so-called

appropriate technologies, a term that is too ambiguous to be used in a

larger ecological context of ideas. That organic gardening can meet our

basic requirements for chemically untreated food, provide us with a

superior inventory of nutrients, and improve our soil rather than destroy

it are the conventional arguments for shifting from agribusiness to

ecological forms of food cultivation. But organic farming does much

more than this. It brings us *into* the cultivation of food, not merely its

consumption. We enter into the food chain itself that has its beginnings

in the soil, a chain of which we are a living component and play a

transformative role. It brings us closer to the natural world as a whole

from which we have been alienated. We grow part or all of our food

and use our bodies artfully to plant, weed, and harvest crops. We engage

in an ecological “ballet,” if you like, that greatly improves upon the

current fad for jogging on asphalt roads and concrete sidewalks. As one

occupation among many that the individual can practise in the course

of a day (to follow Fourier’s advice), organic gardening enriches the

diversity of our everyday lives, sharpens our natural sensibilities to

growth and decay, and attunes us to natural rhythms. Hence, organic

gardening, to take only one case in point, would be seen in an ecological

society as more than the solution to our nutritional problems. It would

become part of our entire being as socially, culturally, and biologically

aware beings.

The same is true if we engage in aqua-culture, particularly in

monitoring self-sustaining systems developed at the pioneering Institute for Social Ecology in Vermont, where the very wastes of

herbivorous fish were recycled by aquatic plants to provide food for

the fish themselves, thus creating a fairly closed, self-sufficient ecological cycle in providing human communities with edible proteins. The

use of solar power, a technology that has reached an extraordinarily

high degree of sophistication and efficiency, can be regarded as

ecological not only because it is based on a renewable energy resource,

but also because it brings the sun, changing climatic conditions, indeed

the heavens, as it were, into our everyday lives in a very palpable way.

The same can be said for windpower, the presence of livestock in a

community, mixed farming, composting techniques that recycle a

community’s wastes into soil nutrients; indeed, an entire ecological

ensemble or pattern in which one component is used to interact with

others to produce a humanly modified ecosystem that meets human

needs while enriching the natural ecosystem as a whole. {3}

{3} These views were advanced decades ago, in the author’s essay, “Toward a liberatory Technology” and have since percolated into the ecology movement. Acknowledged or not, they have since become part of our contemporary conventional wisdom in a technocratic rather than an ecological and ethical form.

An ecological society, structured around a confederal Commune of

communes, each of which is shaped to conform with the ecosystem and

bioregion in which it located, would deploy this ensemble of technologies in an artistic way. It would make use of local resources, many

of which have been abandoned because of mass production techniques.

How would property and the control of property be dealt with in

such a society? Historically, modern radicalism has emphasized

nationalization of land and industry or workers’ control of these resources. A nationalized economy, as anarchists have been quick to point

out, presupposes the existence of the State. This single fact would be

enough to reject it outright. What is no less disquieting is that a

nationalized economy is the breeding ground for parasitic economic

bureaucracies that have left even the so-called socialist countries of the

East in an economic, crisis-ridden limbo. We no longer have to question

its operational validity on strictly theoretical grounds as a source of

statism, even totalitarianism. Its own acolytes have been abandoning

it, ironically, for a relatively “free-market” solution.

Workers’ control, long favoured by syndicalist tendencies in opposition to nationalized economies, has serious limitations of its own.

Except for Spain, where anarchist-influenced unions like the CNT

maintained a tight grip on any wayward enterprises that might easily

have turned into collective capitalist concerns, a collective enterprise

is not necessarily a commune — nor is it necessarily communistic in

its outlook. More than one workers’ controlled enterprise has functioned in a capitalistic manner, competing with like concerns for

resources, customers, privileges, and even profits. Publicly owned, or

workers’-controlled cooperatives all too often turn into oligarchic

corporations, a trend widely experienced in the United States and

Scandinavia. What singles out many of these enterprises is the fact that

they become a particularistic interest, more or less benign. But they are

no different in kind from capitalistic enterprises and are subjected to

the same social pressures by the market in which they must function.

This particularism tends increasingly to encroach on their higher ethical

goals — generally, in the name of “efficiency,” the need to “grow” if

they are to survive, and the overwhelming temptation to acquire larger

earnings.

Libertarian municipalism advances a holistic approach to an

ecologically oriented economy. Policies and concrete decisions that

deal with agriculture and industrial production would be made by

citizens in face-to-face assemblies—as *citizens*, not simply as workers,

farmers, or professionals who, in any case, would themselves be

involved in rotating productive activities, irrespective of their professional expertise. As citizens, they would function in such assemblies at

their highest level — their *human* level — rather than as socially

ghettoized beings. They would express their general human interests,

not their particular status interests.

Instead of nationalizing and collectivizing land, factories,

workshops, and distribution centres, an ecological community would

workshops would be controlled by the popular assemblies of free

communities, not by a nation-state or by worker-producers who might

very well develop a proprietary interest in them. Everyone, in a sense,

would function as a citizen, not as a self-interested ego, a class being,

or pan of a particularized “collective.” The classical ideal of the rational

citizen, engaged in a discursive, face-to-face relationship with other

members of his or her community, would acquire *economic* underpinnings as well as pervade every aspect of public life. Such an individual,

presumably free of a particularistic interest in a community where each

contributes to the whole to the best of his or her ability and takes from

the common fund of produce what he or she needs, would give

citizenship a broad, indeed unprecedented, material solidity that goes

beyond the private ownership of property.

It is not too fanciful to suppose that an ecological society would

ultimately consist of moderately sized municipalities, each a commune

of smaller household communes or private dwellings that would be

delicately attuned to the natural ecosystem in which it is located. The

wisdom of living communally or individually is an issue that can only

be left to decisions made by future generations, individual by individual, just as it is made today.

Communal intimacy would be consciously fostered. No

municipality would be so far from another that it would not be within

reasonable walking distance from its neighbours. Transportation would

be organized around the collective use of vehicles, be they monorails,

railroads, bicycles, automobiles, and the like, not single drivers who

clutter huge highway systems with their largely empty vehicles.

Work would be rotated between town and country and between

everyday tasks. Fourier’s ideal of a highly variegated workday might

well be honoured in apportioning the working day into gardening, the

crafting of objects, reading, recitations, and a fair portion of time for

manufacturing installations. Land would be used ecologically such that

forests would grow in areas that are most suitable for aboreal flora and

widely mixed food plants in areas that are most suitable for crops.

Orchards and hedges would abound to provide niches for a wide

diversity of life-forms and thereby remove the need for pesticides

through a system of biological checks and balances. Still other areas

would be set aside, perhaps more extensively than they are today, for

wildlife. The physical use of the body would be fostered as part of a

diversified work process and greater athleticism. Solar and wind power

would be used extensively and wastes would be collected, composted,

and recycled. Production would emphasize quality over quantity:

homes, furnishings, utensil, and clothing would be made to last for

years, in some cases, for generations. The entire municipal pattern I

have described would be planned with a deep sensitivity for a given

region to preserve its natural features as much as possible with a

concern for nonhuman life-forms and the balance of nature.

Industrial installations, based on small, multipurpose machines, the

latest innovations in humanly scaled technologies, the production of

quality goods, and a minimal expenditure of energy, would be placed

within regions to serve as many communities as possible without the

mindless duplication of the same facilities and products that occurs in

a market economy.

Let me state flatly that a high premium would be placed on labour-saving devices — be they computers or automatic machinery — that

would free human beings from needless toil and give them unstructured

leisure time for their self-cultivation as individuals and citizens. The

recent emphasis of the ecology movement, particularly in the United

States, on labour-intensive technologies, presumably to “save” energy

by exhausting the working classes of society, is a scandalous, often

self-indulgent, middle-class affectation. The salad of academics, students, professionals, and their like, who have expressed these views are

often people who have never been obliged to do a day of onerous toil

in their lives in, say, a foundry or on an automobile assembly line. Their

own labour-intensive activities have generally been centred around

their “hobbies,” which may include jogging, sports, and elevating hikes

in national parks and forests. A few weeks during a hot summer in a

steel foundry would quickly disabuse them of the virtues of labour-intensive industries and technologies.

Between a here that is totally irrational, wasteful, based on giant

industrial and urban belts, a highly chemical agribusiness, centralized

and bureaucratic power, a staggering armaments economy, massive

pollution, and mindless labour on the one hand, and the ecological

society I have tried to describe on the other, lies an indefinable zone of

highly complex transitions, one that involves the development of a new

sensibility as well as new politics. There is no substitute for the role of

consciousness and the support of history to mediate this transition. No

nor should we desire one. What people cannot shape for themselves,

they will never control. It can be taken away from them as readily as it

is bestowed upon them.

Ultimately, every revolutionary project rests on the hope that the

people will develop a new consciousness if they are exposed to thoughtful ideas that patently meet their needs and if objective reality — be it

history, nature, or both—renders them susceptible to the need for basic

social change. Without the objective circumstances that favour a new

consciousness and the organized means to advance it publicly, there

will be no long-range change or even the measured steps needed to

achieve it. Every revolutionary project is, above all, an *educational* one.

The rest must come from the real world in which people live and the

changes that occur in it.

An educational process that does not retain contact with that real

world, its traditions as well as everyday realities, will perform only a

part of its task. Every people has its own libertarian background, to

repeat a claim I made earlier, and its own libertarian dreams, however

much they may be confused with media-generated propaganda and the images that distort them.

The “American Dream,” so much in fashion today, for example, has

anarchistic components as well as bourgeois ones and has taken many

different forms. One strand can be traced back to the revolutionary

Puritans who crossed the Atlantic Ocean to establish a quasi-communistic

“New Jerusalem.” For all their failings, they produced coherent

basically egalitarian communities which governed themselves in directly democratic town-meetings. Another “American Dream” was shaped by the southwest cowboy culture in which the New England domestic hearth was replaced by the lonely campfire. Its heroes were fiercely individualistic gun-slingers that are celebrated in Sergio

Leone’s so-called spaghetti westerns such as the movie, “The Good,

the Bad, and the Ugly “ Still another that emerged at the turn of the

century was the impoverished immigrant “American Dream,” the myth

that American streets are “paved of gold,” in short, a dream of unlimited

material possibilities for betterment and the notion that “everything is

possible” in the United States.

I have adduced these quasi-utopian visions, each uniquely national

when one tries to ferret out a variety of “dreams” in European countries,

to emphasize that in one way or another, the revolutionary project must

make contact with these popular longings and find ways to rework them

into the contemporary ideals of freedom. Anarchism is not a product

of the labours of a genius who spent most of his life in the London

Museum and delivered a socialist “science” to the world of his tinier

Either it is a social product—sophisticated, to be sure, by able theorists,

but one that stems from the deepest, most generous, and liberty loving

aspirations of a people — or it is nothing. Such was the case with

Spanish anarchism between the 1880s and the late 1930s or Italian and

Russian anarchism before the rise of Mussolini and Stalin, when the

writings of Bakunin, Kropotkin, and Malatesta gave theoretical expression to deeply felt aspirations of oppressed people. Wherever anarchism took root, it did so because it literally became a voice of freedom for a yearning people and spoke in their language — notably, their most cherished ideals, most fervent hopes, and in the idiom of their specific tongues. It is this deeply popular attribute, its rootedness in the social life of a people and their communities, that has made anarchist ideas profoundly ecological in nature and that has made anarchist theorists the authentic radical initiators of ecological ideas in our own day.

Toward a Free Nature

Anarchism and social ecology — that is, eco-anarchism — must

count on the probability that normal people have the untapped power

to reason on a level that does not differ from that of humanity’s most

brilliant individuals. Eco-anarchism must work with the supposition

that humanity as a whole is highly distinctive. It occupies a very unique

place in evolution, which, to be sure, does not justify the notion that it

should, much less can, “dominate” nature. What makes human beings

unique in contrast to all nonhuman forms of life is that they have

extraordinary powers of conceptual thought, verbal communication

structured around a formidable array of concepts, and sweeping powers

to alter the natural world in ways that could be utterly destructive or

magnificently creative.

Can we dismiss these remarkable powers as mere accidents or

incidents in the evolution of life, indeed, of nature as a whole? There

is no way to disprove Bertrand Russell’s famous lament that human

consciousness is the mere accidental product of unforeseeable circumstances, a short-lived spark of light in a black, meaningless, and

lifeless cosmos that emerged out of the nothingness of reality and must

eventually disappear into it without leaving a trace. Perhaps — but

every philosophical approach that raises the question of the “meaning”

of humanity must be derived from unprovable presuppositions. In the

last century, physics made the all-important presupposition that motion

is an “attribute” of matter and proceeded to erect a highly sophisticated

body of tenable ideas on this unprovable notion. The ability of these

presuppositions to clarify reality may well have been the best “proof”

physics needed to validate the role of presuppositions as such.

Modern ecology, specifically social ecology, is also in need of

presuppositions if it is to become a coherent outlook that tries to explain

humanity’s place in the natural world. A number of frivolous ecological

theories have emerged that essentially deny humanity any unique place

in nature, say, one that is different from the “intrinsic worth” of a snail.

This view, as I have observed, has a name — “biocentricity” — and it

advances the view that human beings are neither more nor less “worthy” than snails in the natural world (hence the myth of a “biocentric

democracy”). In the natural scheme of things the two are merely

“different.” That they are “different” is a rather trite fact, but one that

tells us nothing whatever about the *way* they are different and the

We are thus faced with an important question. What is humanity’s

place in nature? Looking back almost intuitively over the evolution of

the universe, we can see — *as no other animal can* — an overall

tendency of active, turbulent substance to develop from the simple to

the complex, from the relatively homogeneous to the relatively

heterogeneous, from the simple to the variegated and differentiated.

The most striking attribute of substance — a term I believe we require

to single out the dynamic and creative notion of a seemingly “dead,”

static “matter” — is a process of development. By development, I do

not mean a mere change of place or location; rather I refer to an

unfolding of the latent potentialities of a phenomenon, the actualization

of possibility and undeveloped form in the fullness of being. Within

substance at its most primal level is a germinal unfolding over varying

gradations of development in which each whole is a potentiality for a

more differentiated whole, of tendency toward ever-greater subjectivity and flexibility. I speak, here, not of a preordained teleology or a

predetermined end that marks the completion of an inexorable development. Rather, what I am trying to explore is an inherent striving or nisus

and tendency toward greater differentiation, complexity, increasing

subjectivity (which is not yet intellectuality until we encounter it in

human beings), and physical flexibility.

These are presuppositions, and basic ones. But apparently, at a

certain point, the tendency of the inorganic development toward complexity does reach a visible and clear threshold at which point life

emerges. The dividing line between the two domains consists of a

phenomenon called *metabolism*, in which proteins, formed from amino

acids, developed the property of *active* self-maintenance and, with it,a

vague sense of self-identity. Rocks and the running water that erodes

them are passive. Water simply erodes and dissolves the mineral

material in rocks.

By contrast, a mere amoeba is intensely active. It is literally occupied with being itself by maintaining a dynamic equilibrium between

the building-up and breaking-down process that determines its existence. It is not simply passive in its relationship to its environment: it is

an incipient self, an identifiable being, that is engaged in immanently

preserving its identity. Indeed, it exhibits a dim sense of self-directiveness, the germ of what eventually appears as purposiveness, will, and

intentionality when we examine more complex and more subjectively

developed life-forms at later periods of evolution.

The further differentiation of unicellular organisms like the amoeba

into multicellular ones like the sponge and eventually high complex

ones like mammals yields an ever-greater specialization of organs and

organ-systems. A point arrives in this process where we begin to clearly

witness the emergence of nerve networks, autonomic nervous systems,

layered brains, and finally, self-conscious beings over a long evolutionary process.

This is simply evidence of a trend in nature itself that reaches back

to the interactivity of atoms to form complex molecules, amino acids,

and proteins. Life acquires greater flexibility with warm-bloodedness,

a development that renders specific life-forms more adaptable to different climates. Species interact with each other and their environment,

moreover, to produce increasingly more diversified ecosystems, many

of which open new avenues for evolutionary development and greater

subjectivity that leads to elementary choices in following, even

developing, new evolutionary pathways. Life, at these levels of complexity, begins to play an increasingly active role in its own evolution.

It is not the mere passive object of “natural selection”; it participates

in its evolution so that we are obliged to change our terminology from

Darwin’s day and speak of “participatory evolution.”

If we survey the evolutionary unfolding of this ever-cumulative

process — in which life-forms reabsorb early developments into their

own development, be it early nerve networks that cover skin, nerve

ganglia that form our spinal cord, “reptile” brains and the like — we

can more than hypothesize that nature exhibits a tendency towards its

own self-directive evolution, a drift toward a more conscious development

in which *choice*, however dim, reveals that biotic evolution

contains a potential for freedom. To speak of nature simply as a “realm

of necessity” is to overlook its fecundity, trend toward diversity, matrix

as a development of subjectivity, self-identity, rudimentary choice, and

conscious intentionality, in short, a realm of potential freedom in which

life, at least, emerges from its long evolution as the basis for genuine

selfhood and self-directiveness. It is in the human species that we find

this development fully actualized, at least within the limits created by

social life and the application of reason to the conduct of human affairs.

Humanity, in effect, becomes the potential voice of a nature rendered

self-conscious and self-formative.

We can thus speak of prehuman nature as “first nature” in the sense

that selfhood, consciousness, and the bases for freedom are still too dim

and rudimentary to be regarded as fully self-directive. We may even

encounter many approximations of self-consciousness, primarily in the

primate world. But it is not until we reach humanity that this potentiality

acquires a new social or “second nature” that lends itself to full

realization: a product of evolution that has the fullness of mind, of

extraordinary communicative abilities, of conscious association, and

the ability to knowingly alter itself and the natural world. To deny these

extraordinary human attributes which manifest themselves in real life,

to submerge them in notions like a “biocentric democracy” that renders

human beings and snails “equal” in terms of their “intrinsic worth”

(whatever that phrase may mean) is simply frivolous.

Moreover — and very significantly—this “biocentric” approach is

meant to dilute the most characteristic trait of humankind: its capacity

to engage in purposeful *activity*. It denies humanity’s power to *change*

the world and, in great part, to change itself. Instead, disarmed by a

deadening gospel of passivity and receptivity, the trend of this

“biocentric” mode of thinking is largely adaptive and basically noncritical. One hears such quietistic tenets from Taoism and from Western

philosophies of “Being” that range from the static views of Parmeniedes up to, Martin Heidegger, whose outlook, in my view, can be

easily brought into conformity with the ideas of National Socialism, a

movement to which he belonged for more than a decade.

The great precepts of early radicals, from Robert Owen, Charles

Fourier, Michael Bakunin, and Karl Marx, among many others, to our

own time, placed a crucial emphasis on the belief that humanity must

be an *active* agent in the world. These precepts lie at the core of the

revolutionary project and the ideals of freedom. That various schools

of ecology have emerged that preach the need for a passive relationship

between humanity and nature; indeed, for an abject obedience of human

beings to the “laws of nature,” which presumably produce famines as

“checks on population,” may well earn ecology a reputation even worse

than that of economics. If economics once acquired a reputation as the

“dismal science,” ecology, in its more reactionary forms, may well

deserve the sobriquet of the “cruel science.”

Humanity, as I have noted, is still less than human. Given the present

competitive, divided, and unfeeling society, it has a long way to go in

order to fulfill its potentiality for reason, care, and sympathy. But that

potentiality expresses itself in countless ways that have no equal in

other life-forms and its actualization depends upon basic social changes

that have yet to be made. The most heinous crime of certain ecologists

in dealing with these social imperatives stems from the ease with which

they have dropped the human social condition from the very discourse

of their concerns. This treatment of people merely as a “species” brings

all human beings into complicity with their own degradation by elites,

classes, and the State, not only the degradation of nature by a grow-or-die society.

Viewed from the standpoint of what humanity *can* be, we have

reason to speak of a relationship between human and human and

between humanity and nature that will transcend the pristine “first

nature” from which a social “second nature” emerges and will open the

way to a radically new “free nature” in which an emancipated humanity

will become the voice, indeed the expression, of a natural evolution

rendered self-conscious, caring, and sympathetic to the pain, suffering,

and incoherent aspects of an evolution left to its own, often wayward,

unfolding. Nature, due to human rational intervention, will thence

acquire the intentionality, power of developing more complex lifeforms, and capacity to differentiate itself. We encounter at this point

the far-reaching questions of developing an ecological ethics. Human

intervention into the natural world is not a sick aberration of evolution.

Human beings can no more be separated from nature and their own

animality than lemmings can thrive without their skins. What makes

the human animal a product of natural evolution is not only its physical

primate characteristics; it is also the extent to which humanity actualizes a deep-seated nisus in evolution toward self-consciousness and

freedom. Herein lies the grounding for a truly objective ethics, conceived in terms of a philosophy of potentiality and actuality, not a

mechanical cause-and-effect relationship or the causal agnosticism of

Hume and his modern-day positivist followers.

exists no further than what we can perceive with our eyes and noses.

Conceived as formative, reality is always a process of actualization of

potentialities. It is no less “real” or “objective” in terms of what it *could*

be as well as what it is at any given moment.

Humanity, conceived from this dialectical notion of causality, is

more than it is today; it is also what it *could* be — and perhaps *will* be

tomorrow or generations from now. Insofar as we encounter a tendency,

even a potentiality, that could yield freedom and self-consciousness,

freedom and self-consciousness are no less real (or, in Hegel’s more

precise term, “actual”) in society than they are as potentialities in

nature.

What also makes the human animal a product of nature is not only

the voice it gives to nature, but the fact that it can intervene into nature

precisely as a *product* of natural evolution; indeed, that it has been

organized over aeons of organic development to do precisely that,

insofar as it has any place in the natural world. What is warped about

the human condition is not that people actively intervene in nature and

alter it, but that they intervene actively to destroy it because hum anity’s

even terminate it, as so many concerned ecologists have done, today,

is as naive as the behaviour of a child that furiously lucks the chair over

which it has stumbled.

Social ecology advances a message that calls not only for a society

free of hierarchy and hierarchical sensibilities, but for an ethics that

places humanity in the natural world as an agent for rendering evolution

— social and natural — fully self-conscious and as free as possible in

its ability to make evolution as rational as possible in meeting nonhuman and human needs. I am not advancing a view that approves of

“natural engineering.” The natural world, as I have stressed repeatedly

in earlier writings, is much too complex to be “controlled” by human

ingenuity, science, and technology. My own anarchist proclivities have

fostered in my thinking a love of spontaneity, be it in human behaviour

or in natural development. The imagination has a major place beside

the rational; the intuitive, aesthetic, and a sense of wonder for the

marvelous, belong as much to the human spirit as does the intellectual.

Natural evolution can not be denied its own spontaneity and fecundity

any more than can social evolution.

But we cannot reject the place of rationality in life and the extent to

which it is no less a product of natural development than it is of human

development We stand at a crossroads of conflicting pathways: either

we will surrender to a mindless irrationalism that mystifies social

evolution with myths, deities, and a crude particularism in the name of

gender or hidden elites — one that renders social evolution aimless,

with grim results for human and nonhuman life alike — or we will

regain the activism, that is denigrated today, and turn the world into an

ever-broader domain of freedom and rationality. This entails a new

form of rationality, a new technology, a new science, a new sensibility

and self — and, above all, a truly libertarian society.

[1] I have not penned this reference to viruses lightmindedly. The “unimpeachable right” of pathogenic viruses to exist is seriously discussed in David Ehrenfeld’s *The Arrogance of Humanism*. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978), 208–210.

[2] See Bill Devall and George Sessions, *Deep Ecology*, (Salt Lake City: Peregrine Smith Books, 1985) for a comprehensive book-length account of the views expressed by the “deep ecology” movement. Much of the language used by “deep ecologists” — such as “biocentric equality” — will be found in this work.

[3] *Ibid*., 225.

[4] Robert Briffault, “The Evolution of the Human Species” in *The Making of Man*, V.F. Calverton, ed. (New York: Modern Library, 1931), 765–766.

[5] David Ehremfeld, *op.cit.*,207

[6] Dorothy Lee, *Freedom and Culture* (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, Inc, 1959), 42.

[7] Paul Radin, *The World of Primitive Man* (New York: Grove Press, 1960), 11.

[8] I’ve examined this important, and largely neglected, aspect of magic in my book, *The Ecology of Freedom*, (Palo Alto: Cheshrire Books, 1982). By no means do I think, however, that this noncoercieve form of magic has any meaning for our time. I cite it merely as an example of *how* nonhierarchical communities viewed the natural world, not as another technique that should be recovered for use by modern mystics and theists. Early hunters were wrong, of course. Game did not obligingly expose themselves to spears and arrows any more than they were “forced” by more coercive magical practices to become food in a Paleolithic diet. To try to restore these rituals today (and no one quite knows what forms they took) would be naive at best and cynical at worst. To the extent that ritual has any place in a free society, it should be new ones that foster a high regard for life and for human consociation — not descend into an atavism that is absurd and meaningless to the modern mind.

[9] Janet Biehl, “What is Social Ecofeminism?” in *Green Perspectives*, No. 11.

[10] Paul Radin, *op.cit.*, 212, 215.

[11] To substitute words like “industrial society” for capitalism can thus be highly misleading. “Industrial” capitalism actually preceded the Industrial Revolution. In Venice’s famous arsenal, a large labour force worked with very traditional tools, and in England’s early factories the labour force was structured around simple machines and techniques. What these factories did was to intensify the labour process, not introduce particularly startling technical innovations. The innovations came later. To speak of an “industrial society” without clear reference to the new social relations introduced by capitalism, namely wage and labour and a dispossessed proletariat, often willfully endows technology with mystical powers and a degree of autonomy that it does not really have. It also creates the highly misleading notion that society can live with a market economy that is “green,” “ecological,” or “moral,” even under the conditions of wage labour, exchange, competition, and the like. This misuse of language imputes to technology — much of which may be very useful socially and ecologically — what should really be directed against a very distinct body of social relationships, namely, capitalistic ones. One may gain greater “influence” with an unknowing public by using this expression, but often at the expense of miseducating people.

[12] Ernst Bloch, *Man on His Own* (New York: Herder and Herder, 1970), 128.

[13] H. and H.A. Frankfort, “The Emancipation of Thought From Myth,” in *Before Philosophy*, H. and H.A. Frankfort, *et.al.* (Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1951), 242–243. The passages from Egyptian chronicles appear in the pages above.

[14] Peter Kropotkin, *Mutual Aid* (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1989). 195.

[15] Marie Louise Berneri, *Journey Through Utopia* (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, n.d.), 54.

[16] Ronald Fraser, *Blood of Spain* (New York: Pantheon Books, 1979). 66.

[17] For a fairly complete discussion of this mixed precapitalist economy, see my book, *The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship* (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1987).

[18] Karl Marx, “The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleion,” *Collected Works*, Vol. 11 (New York: International Publishers, 1979), 103.

[19] Karl Marx, *Grundrisse* (New York: Random House, 1973), 109–110.

[20] *Ibid.*

[21] Jean Jacques Rousseau, *The Social Contract* (New York: Modern Library, 1950), 94.

Home