💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › document › albert-camus-the-myth-of-sisyphus captured on 2023-03-20 at 19:53:23. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2023-07-10)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Myth of Sisyphus
Subtitle: and Other Essays
Date: 1955
Source: https://postarchive.files.wordpress.com/2015/03/myth-of-sisyphus-and-other-essays-the-albert-camus.pdf
Notes: Translated by Justin O'Brien
Authors: Albert Camus
Topics: philosophy, absurdism, myths, existentialism, Sisyphus

Preface

For me “The Myth of Sisyphus” marks the beginning of an idea

which I was to pursue in The Rebel. It attempts to resolve the

problem of suicide, as The Rebel attempts to resolve that of

murder, in both cases without the aid of eternal values which,

temporarily perhaps, are absent or distorted in contemporary

Europe. The fundamental subject of “The Myth of Sisyphus” is

this: it is legitimate and necessary to wonder whether life has a

meaning; therefore it is legitimate to meet the problem of suicide

face to face. The answer, underlying and appearing through the

paradoxes which cover it, is this: even if one does not believe in

God, suicide is not legitimate. Written fifteen years ago, in 1940,

amid the French and European disaster, this book declares that

even within the limits of nihilism it is possible to find the means to

proceed beyond nihilism. In all the books I have written since, I

have attempted to pursue this direction. Although “The Myth of

Sisyphus” poses mortal problems, it sums itself up for me as a

lucid invitation to live and to create, in the very midst of the desert.

It has hence been thought possible to append to this

philosophical argument a series of essays, of a kind I have never

ceased writing, which are somewhat marginal to my other books.

In a more lyrical form, they all illustrate that essential fluctuation

from assent to refusal which, in my view, defines the artist and his

difficult calling. The unity of this book, that I should like to be

apparent to American readers as it is to me, resides in the

reflection, alternately cold and impassioned, in which an artist

may indulge as to his reasons for living and for creating. After

fifteen years I have progressed beyond several of the positions

which are set down here; but I have remained faithful, it seems to

me, to the exigency which prompted them. That is why this hook is

in a certain sense the most personal of those I have published in

America. More than the others, therefore, it has need of the

indulgence and understanding of its readers.

—Albert Camus, Paris, March 1955

for PASCAL PIA

O my soul, do not aspire to immortal life, but exhaust the limits

of the possible.

—Pindar, Pythian iii

The pages that follow deal with an absurd sensitivity that can

be found widespread in the age—and not with an absurd

philosophy which our time, properly speaking, has not known. It is

therefore simply fair to point out, at the outset, what these pages

owe to certain contemporary thinkers. It is so far from my intention

to hide this that they Will be found cited and commented upon

throughout this work.

But it is useful to note at the same time that the absurd, hitherto

taken as a conclusion, is considered in this essay as a starting-

point. In this sense it may be said that there is something

provisional in my commentary: one cannot prejudge the position it

entails. There will be found here merely the description, in the pure

state, of an intellectual malady. No metaphysic, no belief is

involved in it for the moment. These are the limits and the only

bias of this book. Certain personal experiences urge me to make

this clear.

The Myth Of Sisyphus

An Absurd Reasoning

Absurdity and Suicide

There is but one truly serious philosophical problem, and that

is suicide. Judging whether life is or is not worth living amounts to

answering the fundamental question of philosophy. All the rest—

whether or not the world has three dimensions, whether the mind

has nine or twelve categories—comes afterwards. These are

games; one must first answer. And if it is true, as Nietzsche claims,

that a philosopher, to deserve our respect, must preach by example,

you can appreciate the importance of that reply, for it will precede

the definitive act. These are facts the heart can feel; yet they call

for careful study before they become clear to the intellect.

If I ask myself how to judge that this question is more urgent

than that, I reply that one judges by the actions it entails. I have

never seen anyone die for the ontological argument. Galileo, who

held a scientific truth of great importance, abjured it with the

greatest ease as soon as it endangered his life. In a certain sense, he

did right.[1] That truth was not worth the stake. Whether the earth

or the sun revolves around the other is a matter of profound

indifference. To tell the truth, it is a futile question. On the other

hand, I see many people die because they judge that life is not

worth living. I see others paradoxically getting killed for the ideas

or illusions that give them a reason for living (what is called a

reason for living is also an excellent reason for dying). I therefore

conclude that the meaning of life is the most urgent of questions.

How to answer it? On all essential problems (I mean thereby those

that run the risk of leading to death or those that intensify the

passion of living) there are probably but two methods of thought:

the method of La Palisse and the method of Don Quixote. Solely

the balance between evidence and lyricism can allow us to achieve

simultaneously emotion and lucidity. In a subject at once so

humble and so heavy with emotion, the learned and classical

dialectic must yield, one can see, to a more modest attitude of mind

deriving at one and the same time from common sense and

understanding.

Suicide has never been dealt with except as a social

phenomenon. On the contrary, we are concerned here, at the outset,

with the relationship between individual thought and suicide. An

act like this is prepared within the silence of the heart, as is a great

work of art. The man himself is ignorant of it. One evening he

pulls the trigger or jumps. Of an apartment-building manager who

had killed himself I was told that he had lost his daughter five

years before, that be bad changed greatly since, and that that

experience had “undermined” him. A more exact word cannot be

imagined. Beginning to think is beginning to be undermined.

Society has but little connection with such beginnings. The worm

is in man’s heart. That is where it must be sought. One must follow

and understand this fatal game that leads from lucidity in the face

of existence to flight from light.

There are many causes for a suicide, and generally the most

obvious ones were not the most powerful. Rarely is suicide

committed (yet the hypothesis is not excluded) through reflection.

What sets off the crisis is almost always unverifiable. Newspapers

often speak of “personal sorrows” or of “incurable illness.” These

explanations are plausible. But one would have to know whether a

friend of the desperate man had not that very day addressed him

indifferently. He is the guilty one. For that is enough to precipitate

all the rancors and all the boredom still in suspension.[2]

But if it is hard to fix the precise instant, the subtle step when

the mind opted for death, it is easier to deduce from the act itself

the consequences it implies. In a sense, and as in melodrama,

killing yourself amounts to confessing. It is confessing that life is

too much for you or that you do not understand it. Let’s not go too

far in such analogies, however, but rather return to everyday

words. It is merely confessing that that “is not worth the trouble.”

Living, naturally, is never easy. You continue making the gestures

commanded by existence for many reasons, the first of which is

habit. Dying voluntarily implies that you have recognized, even

instinctively, the ridiculous character of that habit, the absence of any

profound reason for living, the insane character of that daily

agitation, and the uselessness of suffering.

What, then, is that incalculable feeling that deprives the mind

of the sleep necessary to life? A world that can be explained even

with bad reasons is a familiar world. But, on the other hand, in a

universe suddenly divested of illusions and lights, man feels an

alien, a stranger. His exile is without remedy since he is deprived

of the memory of a lost home or the hope of a promised land. This

divorce between man and this life, the actor and his setting, is

properly the feeling of absurdity. All healthy men having thought

of their own suicide, it can be seen, without further explanation,

that there is a direct connection between this feeling and the

longing for death.

The subject of this essay is precisely this relationship between

the absurd and suicide, the exact degree to which suicide is a

solution to the absurd. The principle can be established that for a

man who does not cheat, what he believes to be true must

determine his action. Belief in the absurdity of existence must then

dictate his conduct. It is legitimate to wonder, clearly and without

false pathos, whether a conclusion of this importance requires

forsaking as rapidly as possible an incomprehensible condition. I

am speaking, of course, of men inclined to be in harmony with

themselves.

Stated clearly, this problem may seem both simple and

insoluble. But it is wrongly assumed that simple questions involve

answers that are no less simple and that evidence implies evidence.

A priori and reversing the terms of the problem, just as one does or

does not kill oneself, it seems that there are but two philosophical

solutions, either yes or no. This would be too easy. But allowance

must be made for those who, without concluding, continue

questioning. Here I am only slightly indulging in irony: this is the

majority. I notice also that those who answer “no” act as if they

thought “yes.” As a matter of fact, if I accept the Nietzschean

criterion, they think “yes” in one way or another. On the other

hand, it often happens that those who commit suicide were assured

of the meaning of life. These contradictions are constant. It may

even be said that they have never been so keen as on this point

where, on the contrary, logic seems so desirable. It is a

commonplace to compare philosophical theories and the behavior

of those who profess them. But it must be said that of the thinkers

who refused a meaning to life none except Kirilov who belongs to

literature, Peregrinos who is born of legend,[3] and Jules Lequier

who belongs to hypothesis, admitted his logic to the point of

refusing that life. Schopenhauer is often cited, as a fit subject for

laughter, because he praised suicide while seated at a well-set

table. This is no subject for joking. That way of not taking the

tragic seriously is not so grievous, but it helps to judge a man.

In the face of such contradictions and obscurities must we

conclude that there is no relationship between the opinion one has

about life and the act one commits to leave it? Let us not

exaggerate in this direction. In a man’s attachment to life there is

something stronger than all the ills in the world. The body’s

judgment is as good as the mind’s and the body shrinks from

annihilation. We get into the habit of living before acquiring the

habit of thinking. In that race which daily hastens us toward death,

the body maintains its irreparable lead. In short, the essence of that

contradiction lies in what I shall call the act of eluding because it is

both less and more than diversion in the Pascalian sense. Eluding is

the invariable game. The typical act of eluding, the fatal evasion

that constitutes the third theme of this essay, is hope. Hope of

another life one must “deserve” or trickery of those who live not

for life itself but for some great idea that will transcend it, refine it,

give it a meaning, and betray it.

Thus everything contributes to spreading confusion.

Hitherto, and it has not been wasted effort, people have played

on words and pretended to believe that refusing to grant a meaning

to life necessarily leads to declaring that it is not worth living. In

truth, there is no necessary common measure between these two

judgments. One merely has to refuse to he misled by the

confusions, divorces, and inconsistencies previously pointed out.

One must brush everything aside and go straight to the real

problem. One kills oneself because life is not worth living, that is

certainly a truth yet an unfruitful one because it is a truism. But

does that insult to existence, that flat denial in which it is plunged

come from the fact that it has no meaning? Does its absurdity

require one to escape it through hope or suicide—this is what must

be clarified, hunted down, and elucidated while brushing aside all

the rest. Does the Absurd dictate death? This problem must be

given priority over others, outside all methods of thought and all

exercises of the disinterested mind. Shades of meaning,

contradictions, the psychology that an “objective” mind can always

introduce into all problems have no place in this pursuit and this

passion. It calls simply for an unjust—in other words, logical—

thought. That is not easy. It is always easy to be logical. It is

almost impossible to be logical to the bitter end. Men who die by

their own hand consequently follow to its conclusion their

emotional inclination. Reflection on suicide gives me an

opportunity to raise the only problem to interest me: is there a logic

to the point of death? I cannot know unless I pursue, without

reckless passion, in the sole light of evidence, the reasoning of

which I am here suggesting the source. This is what I call an

absurd reasoning. Many have begun it. I do not yet know whether

or not they kept to it.

When Karl Jaspers, revealing the impossibility of constituting

the world as a unity, exclaims: “This limitation leads me to myself,

where I can no longer withdraw behind an objective point of view

that I am merely representing, where neither I myself nor the

existence of others can any longer become an object for me,” he is

evoking after many others those waterless deserts where thought

reaches its confines. After many others, yes indeed, but how eager

they were to get out of them! At that last crossroad where thought

hesitates, many men have arrived and even some of the humblest.

They then abdicated what was most precious to them, their life.

Others, princes of the mind, abdicated likewise, but they initiated

the suicide of their thought in its purest revolt. The real effort is to

stay there, rather, in so far as that is possible, and to examine

closely the odd vegetation of those distant regions. Tenacity and

acumen are privileged spectators of this inhuman show in which

absurdity, hope, and death carry on their dialogue. The mind can

then analyze the figures of that elementary yet subtle dance before

illustrating them and reliving them itself.

Absurd Walls

Like great works, deep feelings always mean more than they

are conscious of saying. The regularity of an impulse or a repulsion

in a soul is encountered again in habits of doing or thinking, is

reproduced in consequences of which the soul itself knows

nothing. Great feelings take with them their own universe, splendid

or abject. They light up with their passion an exclusive world in

which they recognize their climate. There is a universe of jealousy,

of ambition, of selfishness, or of generosity. A universe in other

words, a metaphysic and an attitude of mind. What is true of

already specialized feelings will be even more so of emotions

basically as indeterminate, simultaneously as vague and as

“definite,” as remote and as “present” as those furnished us by

beauty or aroused by absurdity.

At any streetcorner the feeling of absurdity can strike any man

in the face. As it is, in its distressing nudity, in its light without

effulgence, it is elusive. But that very difficulty deserves reflection.

It is probably true that a man remains forever unknown to us and

that there is in him something irreducible that escapes us. But

practically I know men and recognize them by their behavior, by

the totality of their deeds, by the consequences caused in life by

their presence. Likewise, all those irrational feelings which offer

no purchase to analysis. I can define them practically, appreciate

them practically, by gathering together the sum of their

consequences in the domain of the intelligence, by seizing and

noting all their aspects, by outlining their universe. It is certain that

apparently, though I have seen the same actor a hundred times, I

shall not for that reason know him any better personally. Yet if I

add up the heroes he has personified and if I say that I know him a

little better at the hundredth character counted off, this will be felt

to contain an element of truth. For this apparent paradox is also an

apologue. There is a moral to it. It teaches that a man defines

himself by his make-believe as well as by his sincere impulses.

There is thus a lower key of feelings, inaccessible in the heart but

partially disclosed by the acts they imply and the attitudes of mind

they assume. It is clear that in this way I am defining a method.

But it is also evident that that method is one of analysis and not of

knowledge. For methods imply metaphysics; unconsciously they

disclose conclusions that they often claim not to know yet.

Similarly, the last pages of a book are already contained in the first

pages. Such a link is inevitable. The method defined here

acknowledges the feeling that all true knowledge is impossible.

Solely appearances can be enumerated and the climate make itself

felt.

Perhaps we shall be able to overtake that elusive feeling of

absurdity in the different but closely related worlds of intelligence,

of the art of living, or of art itself. The climate of absurdity is in the

beginning. The end is the absurd universe and that attitude of mind

which lights the world with its true colors to bring out the

privileged and implacable visage which that attitude has discerned

in it.

<br>

All great deeds and all great thoughts have a ridiculous

beginning. Great works are often born on a street-corner or in a

restaurant’s revolving door. So it is with absurdity. The absurd

world more than others derives its nobility from that abject birth.

In certain situations, replying “nothing” when asked what one is

thinking about may be pretense in a man. Those who are loved are

well aware of this. But if that reply is sincere, if it symbolizes that

odd state of soul in which the void be-comes eloquent, in which

the chain of daily gestures is broken, in which the heart vainly

seeks the link that will connect it again, then it is as it were the first

sign of absurdity.

It happens that the stage sets collapse. Rising, streetcar, four

hours in the office or the factory, meal, streetcar, four hours of

work, meal, sleep, and Monday Tuesday Wednesday Thursday

Friday and Saturday according to the same rhythm—this path is easily followed most of

the time. But one day the “why” arises and everything begins in

that weariness tinged with amazement.

“Begins”—this is

important. Weariness comes at the end of the acts of a mechanical

life, but at the same time it inaugurates the impulse of

consciousness. It awakens consciousness and provokes what

follows. What follows is the gradual return into the chain or it is

the definitive awakening. At the end of the awakening comes, in

time, the consequence: suicide or recovery. In itself weariness has

something sickening about it. Here, I must conclude that it is good.

For everything be-gins with consciousness and nothing is worth

anything except through it. There is nothing original about these

remarks. But they are obvious; that is enough for a while, during a

sketchy reconnaissance in the origins of the absurd. Mere

“anxiety,” as Heidegger says, is at the source of everything.

Likewise and during every day of an unillustrious life, time

carries us. But a moment always comes when we have to carry it.

We live on the future: “tomorrow,” “later on,” “when you have

made your way,” “you will understand when you are old enough.”

Such irrelevancies are wonderful, for, after all, it’s a matter of

dying. Yet a day comes when a man notices or says that he is

thirty. Thus he asserts his youth. But simultaneously he situates

himself in relation to time. He takes his place in it. He admits that

he stands at a certain point on a curve that he acknowledges having

to travel to its end. He belongs to time, and by the horror that

seizes him, he recognizes his worst enemy. Tomorrow, he was

longing for tomorrow, whereas everything in him ought to reject it.

That revolt of the flesh is the absurd.[4]

A step lower and strangeness creeps in: perceiving that the

world is “dense,” sensing to what a degree a stone is foreign and

irreducible to us, with what intensity nature or a landscape can

negate us. At the heart of all beauty lies something inhuman, and

these hills, the softness of the sky, the outline of these trees at this

very minute lose the illusory meaning with which we had clothed

them, henceforth more remote than a lost paradise. The primitive

hostility of the world rises up to face us across millennia, for a

second we cease to understand it because for centuries we have

understood in it solely the images and designs that we had attributed to it beforehand, because henceforth we lack the power to

make use of that artifice. The world evades us because it becomes

itself again. That stage scenery masked by habit becomes again

what it is. It withdraws at a distance from us. Just as there are days

when under the familial face of a woman, we see as a stranger her

we had loved months or years ago, perhaps we shall come even to

desire what suddenly leaves us so alone. But the time has not yet

come. Just one thing: that denseness and that strangeness of the

world is the absurd.

Men, too, secrete the inhuman. At certain moments of lucidity,

the mechanical aspect of their gestures, their meaningless

pantomime makes silly everything that surrounds them. A man is

talking on the telephone behind a glass partition; you cannot hear

him, but you see his incomprehensible dumb show: you wonder

why he is alive. This discomfort in the face of man’s own

inhumanity, this incalculable tumble before the image of what we

are, this “nausea,” as a writer of today calls it, is also the absurd.

Likewise the stranger who at certain seconds comes to meet us in a

mirror, the familiar and yet alarming brother we encounter in our

own photographs is also the absurd.

I come at last to death and to the attitude we have toward it. On

this point everything has been said and it is only proper to avoid

pathos. Yet one will never be sufficiently surprised that everyone

lives as if no one “knew.” This is because in reality there is no

experience of death. Properly speaking, nothing has been

experienced but what has been lived and made conscious. Here, it

is barely possible to speak of the experience of others’ deaths. It is

a substitute, an illusion, and it never quite convinces us. That

melancholy convention cannot be persuasive. The horror comes in

reality from the mathematical aspect of the event. If time frightens

us, this is because it works out the problem and the solution comes

afterward. All the pretty speeches about the soul will have their

contrary convincingly proved, at least for a time. From this inert

body on which a slap makes no mark the soul has disappeared.

This elementary and definitive aspect of the adventure constitutes

the absurd feeling. Under the fatal lighting of that destiny, its

uselessness becomes evident. No code of ethics and no effort are

justifiable a priori in the face of the cruel mathematics that

command our condition.

Let me repeat: all this has been said over and over. I am

limiting myself here to making a rapid classification and to

pointing out these obvious themes. They run through all literatures

and all philosophies. Everyday conversation feeds on them. There

is no question of reinventing them. But it is essential to be sure of

these facts in order to be able to question oneself subsequently on

the primordial question. I am interested let me repeat again—not

go much in absurd discoveries as in their consequences. If one is

assured of these facts, what is one to conclude, how far is one to go

to elude nothing? Is one to die voluntarily or to hope in spite of

everything? Beforehand, it is necessary to take the same rapid

inventory on the plane of the intelligence.

<br>

The mind’s first step is to distinguish what is true from what is

false. However, as soon as thought reflects on itself, what it first

discovers is a contradiction. Useless to strive to be convincing in

this case. Over the centuries no one has furnished a clearer and

more elegant demonstration of the business than Aristotle: “The

often ridiculed consequence of these opinions is that they destroy

themselves. For by asserting that all is true we assert the truth of

the contrary assertion and consequently the falsity of our own

thesis (for the contrary assertion does not admit that it can be true).

And if one says that all is false, that assertion is itself false. If we

declare that solely the assertion opposed to ours is false or else that

solely ours is not false, we are nevertheless forced to admit an

infinite number of true or false judgments. For the one who

expresses a true assertion proclaims simultaneously that it is true,

and so on ad infinitum.”

This vicious circle is but the first of a series in which the mind

that studies itself gets lost in a giddy whirling. The very simplicity

of these paradoxes makes them irreducible. Whatever may be the

plays on words and the acrobatics of logic, to understand is, above

all, to unify. The mind’s deepest desire, even in its most elaborate

operations, parallels man’s unconscious feeling in the face of his

universe: it is an insistence upon familiarity, an appetite for clarity.

Understanding the world for a man is reducing it to the human,

stamping it with his seal. The cat’s universe is not the universe of

the anthill. The truism “All thought is anthropomorphic” has no

other meaning. Likewise, the mind that aims to understand reality

can consider itself satisfied only by reducing it to terms of thought.

If man realized that the universe like him can love and suffer, he

would be reconciled. If thought discovered in the shimmering

mirrors of phenomena eternal relations capable of summing them

up and summing themselves up in a single principle, then would be

seen an intellectual joy of which the myth of the blessed would be

but a ridiculous imitation. That nostalgia for unity, that appetite for

the absolute illustrates the essential impulse of the human drama.

But the fact of that nostalgia’s existence does not imply that it is to

be immediately satisfied. For if, bridging the gulf that separates

desire from conquest, we assert with Parmenides the reality of the

One (whatever it may be), we fall into the ridiculous contradiction

of a mind that asserts total unity and proves by its very assertion its

own difference and the diversity it claimed to resolve. This other

vicious circle is enough to stifle our hopes.

These are again truisms. I shall again repeat that they are not

interesting in themselves but in the consequences that can be

deduced from them. I know another truism: it tells me that man is

mortal. One can nevertheless count the minds that have deduced

the extreme conclusions from it. It is essential to consider as a

constant point of reference in this essay the regular hiatus between

what we fancy we know and what we really know, practical assent

and simulated ignorance which allows us to live with ideas which,

if we truly put them to the test, ought to upset our whole life. Faced

with this inextricable contradiction of the mind, we shall fully

grasp the divorce separating us from our own creations. So long as

the mind keeps silent in the motionless world of its hopes,

everything is reflected and arranged in the unity of its nostalgia.

But with its first move this world cracks and tumbles: an infinite

number of shimmering fragments is offered to the understanding.

We must despair of ever reconstructing the familiar, calm surface

which would give us peace of heart. After so many centuries of

inquiries, so many abdications among thinkers, we are well aware

that this is true for all our knowledge. With the exception of

professional rationalists, today people despair of true knowledge. If

the only significant history of human thought were to be written, it

would have to be the history of its successive regrets and its

impotences.

Of whom and of what indeed can I say: “I know that!” This

heart within me I can feel, and I judge that it exists. This world I

can touch, and I likewise judge that it exists. There ends all my

knowledge, and the rest is construction. For if I try to seize this self

of which I feel sure, if I try to define and to summarize it, it is

nothing but water slipping through my fingers. I can sketch one by

one all the aspects it is able to assume, all those likewise that have

been attributed to it, this upbringing, this origin, this ardor or these

silences, this nobility or this vileness. But aspects cannot be added

up. This very heart which is mine will forever remain indefinable

to me. Between the certainty I have of my existence and the

content I try to give to that assurance, the gap will never be filled.

Forever I shall be a stranger to myself. In psychology as in logic,

there are truths but no truth. Socrates’”Know thyself” has as much

value as the “Be virtuous” of our confessionals. They reveal a

nostalgia at the same time as an ignorance. They are sterile

exercises on great subjects. They are legitimate only in precisely so

far as they are approximate.

And here are trees and I know their gnarled surface, water and

I feel its taste. These scents of grass and stars at night, certain

evenings when the heart relaxes—how shall I negate this world

whose power and strength I feel? Yet all the knowledge on earth

will give me nothing to assure me that this world is mine. You

describe it to me and you teach me to classify it. You enumerate its

laws and in my thirst for knowledge I admit that they are true. You

take apart its mechanism and my hope increases. At the final stage

you teach me that this wondrous and multicolored universe can be

reduced to the atom and that the atom itself can be reduced to the

electron. All this is good and I wait for you to continue. But you

tell me of an invisible planetary system in which electrons

gravitate around a nucleus. You explain this world to me with an

image. I realize then that you have been reduced to poetry: I shall

never know. Have I the time to become indignant? You have

already changed theories. So that science that was to teach me

everything ends up in a hypothesis, that lucidity founders in

metaphor, that uncertainty is resolved in a work of art. What need

had I of so many efforts? The soft lines of these hills and the hand

of evening on this troubled heart teach me much more. I have

returned to my beginning. I realize that if through science I can

seize phenomena and enumerate them, I cannot, for all that,

apprehend the world. Were I to trace its entire relief with my

finger, I should not know any more. And you give me the choice

between a description that is sure but that teaches me nothing and

hypotheses that claim to teach me but that are not sure. A stranger

to myself and to the world, armed solely with a thought that

negates itself as soon as it asserts, what is this condition in which I

can have peace only by refusing to know and to live, in which the

appetite for conquest bumps into walls that defy its assaults? To

will is to stir up paradoxes. Everything is ordered in such a way as

to bring into being that poisoned peace produced by

thoughtlessness, lack of heart, or fatal renunciations.

Hence the intelligence, too, tells me in its way that this world is

absurd. Its contrary, blind reason, may well claim that all is clear; I

was waiting for proof and longing for it to be right. But despite so

many pretentious centuries and over the heads of so many eloquent

and persuasive men, I know that is false. On this plane, at least,

there is no happiness if I cannot know. That universal reason,

practical or ethical, that determinism, those categories that explain

everything are enough to make a decent man laugh. They have

nothing to do with the mind. They negate its profound truth, which

is to be enchained. In this unintelligible and limited universe,

man’s fate henceforth assumes its meaning. A horde of irrationals

has sprung up and surrounds him until his ultimate end. In his

recovered and now studied lucidity, the feeling of the absurd

becomes clear and definite. I said that the world is absurd, but I

was too hasty. This world in itself is not reasonable, that is all that

can be said. But what is absurd is the confrontation of this

irrational and the wild longing for clarity whose call echoes in the

human heart. The absurd depends as much on man as on the world.

For the moment it is all that links them together. It binds them one

to the other as only hatred can weld two creatures together. This is

all I can discern clearly in this measureless universe where my

adventure takes place. Let us pause here. If I hold to be true that

absurdity that determines my relationship with life, if I become

thoroughly imbued with that sentiment that seizes me in face of the

world’s scenes, with that lucidity imposed on me by the pursuit of

a science, I must sacrifice everything to these certainties and I must

see them squarely to be able to maintain them. Above all, I must

adapt my behavior to them and pursue them in all their

consequences. I am speaking here of decency. But I want to know

beforehand if thought can live in those deserts.

<br>

I already know that thought has at least entered those deserts.

There it found its bread. There it realized that it had previously

been feeding on phantoms. It justified some of the most urgent

themes of human reflection.

From the moment absurdity is recognized, it becomes a

passion, the most harrowing of all. But whether or not one can live

with one’s passions, whether or not one can accept their law,

which is to burn the heart they simultaneously exalt—that is the

whole question. It is not, however, the one we shall ask just yet. It

stands at the center of this experience. There will be time to come

back to it. Let us recognize rather those themes and those impulses

born of the desert. It will suffice to enumerate them. They, too, are

known to all today. There have always been men to defend the

rights of the irrational. The tradition of what may be called

humiliated thought has never ceased to exist. The criticism of

rationalism has been made so often that it seems unnecessary to

begin again. Yet our epoch is marked by the rebirth of those

paradoxical systems that strive to trip up the reason as if truly it

had always forged ahead. But that is not so much a proof of the

efficacy of the reason as of the intensity of its hopes. On the plane

of history, such a constancy of two attitudes illustrates the essential

passion of man torn between his urge toward unity and the clear

vision he may have of the walls enclosing him.

But never perhaps at any time has the attack on reason been

more violent than in ours. Since Zarathustra’s great outburst: “By

chance it is the oldest nobility in the world. I conferred it upon all

things when I proclaimed that above them no eternal will was

exercised,” since Kierkegaard’s fatal illness,

“that malady that

leads to death with nothing else following it,” the significant and

tormenting themes of absurd thought have followed one another.

Or at least, and this proviso is of capital importance, the themes of

irrational and religious thought. From Jaspers to Heidegger, from

Kierkegaard to Che-stov, from the phenomenologists to Scheler,

on the logical plane and on the moral plane, a whole family of

minds related by their nostalgia but opposed by their methods or

their aims, have persisted in blocking the royal road of reason and

in recovering the direct paths of truth. Here I assume these

thoughts to be known and lived. Whatever may be or have been

their ambitions, all started out from that indescribable universe

where contradiction, antinomy, anguish, or impotence reigns. And

what they have in common is precisely the themes so far disclosed.

For them, too, it must be said that what matters above all is the

conclusions they have managed to draw from those discoveries.

That matters so much that they must be examined separately. But

for the moment we are concerned solely with their discoveries and

their initial experiments. We are concerned solely with noting their

agreement. If it would be presumptuous to try to deal with their

philosophies, it is possible and sufficient in any case to bring out

the climate that is common to them.

Heidegger considers the human condition coldly and

announces that that existence is humiliated. The only reality is

“anxiety” in the whole chain of beings. To the man lost in the

world and its diversions this anxiety is a brief, fleeting fear. But if

that fear becomes conscious of itself, it becomes anguish, the

perpetual climate of the lucid man

“in whom existence is

concentrated.” This professor of philosophy writes without

trembling and in the most abstract language in the world that “the

finite and limited character of human existence is more primordial

than man himself.” His interest in Kant extends only to

recognizing the restricted character of his “pure Reason.” This is to

coincide at the end of his analyses that “the world can no longer

offer anything to the man filled with anguish.” This anxiety seems

to him so much more important than all the categories in the world

that he thinks and talks only of it. He enumerates its aspects:

boredom when the ordinary man strives to quash it in him and

benumb it; terror when the mind contemplates death. He too does

not separate consciousness from the absurd. The consciousness of

death is the call of anxiety and “existence then delivers itself its

own summons through the intermediary of consciousness.” It is the

very voice of anguish and it adjures existence “to return from its

loss in the anonymous They.” For him, too, one must not sleep, but

must keep alert until the consummation. He stands in this absurd

world and points out its ephemeral character. He seeks his way

amid these ruins.

Jaspers despairs of any ontology because he claims that we

have lost “naivete.” He knows that we can achieve nothing that

will transcend the fatal game of appearances. He knows that the

end of the mind is failure. He tarries over the spiritual adventures

revealed by history and pitilessly discloses the flaw in each system,

the illusion that saved everything, the preaching that hid nothing.

In this ravaged world in which the impossibility of knowledge is

established, in which everlasting nothingness seems the only

reality and irremediable despair seems the only attitude, he tries to

recover the Ariadne’s thread that leads to divine secrets.

Chestov, for his part, throughout a wonderfully monotonous

work, constantly straining toward the same truths, tirelessly

demonstrates that the tightest system, the most universal

rationalism always stumbles eventually on the irrational of human

thought. None of the ironic facts or ridiculous contradictions that

depreciate the reason escapes him. One thing only interests him,

and that is the exception, whether in the domain of the heart or of

the mind. Through the Dostoevskian experiences of the

condemned man, the exacerbated adventures of the Nietzschean

mind, Hamlet’s imprecations, or the bitter aristocracy of an Ibsen,

he tracks down, il-luminates, and magnifies the human revolt

against the irremediable. He refuses the reason its reasons and

begins to advance with some decision only in the middle of that

colorless desert where all certainties have become stones.

Of all perhaps the most engaging, Kierkegaard, for a part of his

existence at least, does more than discover the absurd, he lives it.

The man who writes: “The surest of stubborn silences is not to

hold one’s tongue but to talk” makes sure in the beginning that no

truth is absolute or can render satisfactory an existence that is

impossible in itself. Don Juan of the understanding, he multiplies

pseudonyms and contradictions, writes his Discourses of

Edification at the same time as that manual of cynical spiritualism,

The Diary of the Seducer. He refuses consolations, ethics, reliable

principles. As for that thorn he feels in his heart, he is careful not

to quiet its pain. On the contrary, he awakens it and, in the

desperate joy of a man crucified and happy to be so, he builds up

piece by piece—lucidity, refusal, make believe—a category of the

man possessed. That face both tender and sneering, those

pirouettes followed by a cry from the heart are the absurd spirit

itself grappling with a reality beyond its comprehension. And the

spiritual adventure that leads Kierkegaard to his beloved scandals

begins likewise in the chaos of an experience divested of its setting

and relegated to its original incoherence.

On quite a different plane, that of method, Husserl and the

phenomenologists, by their very extravagances, reinstate the world

in its diversity and deny the transcendent power of the reason. The

spiritual universe becomes incalculably enriched through them.

The rose petal, the milestone, or the human hand are as important

as love, desire, or the laws of gravity. Thinking ceases to be

unifying or making a semblance familiar in the guise of a major

principle. Thinking is learning all over again to see, to be attentive,

to focus consciousness; it is turning every idea and every image, in

the manner of Proust, into a privileged moment. What justifies

thought is its extreme consciousness. Though more positive than

Kierkegaard’s or Chestov’s, Husserl’s manner of proceeding, in

the beginning, nevertheless negates the classic method of the

reason, disappoints hope, opens to intuition and to the heart a

whole proliferation of phenomena, the wealth of which has about it

something inhuman. These paths lead to all sciences or to none.

This amounts to saying that in this case the means are more

important than the end. All that is involved is “an attitude for

understanding” and not a consolation. Let me repeat: in the

beginning, at very least.

How can one fail to feel the basic relationship of these minds!

How can one fail to see that they take their stand around a

privileged and bitter moment in which hope has no further place? I

want everything to be explained to me or nothing. And the reason

is impotent when it hears this cry from the heart. The mind aroused

by this insistence seeks and finds nothing but contradictions and

nonsense. What I fail to understand is nonsense. The world is

peopled with such irrationals. The world itself, whose single

meaning I do not understand, is but a vast irrational. If one could

only say just once: “This is clear,” all would be saved. But these

men vie with one another in proclaiming that nothing is clear, all is

chaos, that all man has is his lucidity and his definite knowledge of

the walls surrounding him.

All these experiences agree and confirm one another. The

mind, when it reaches its limits, must make a judgment and choose

its conclusions. This is where suicide and the reply stand. But I

wish to reverse the order of the inquiry and start out from the

intelligent adventure and come back to daily acts. The experiences

called to mind here were born in the desert that we must not leave

behind. At least it is essential to know how far they went. At this

point of his effort man stands face to face with the irrational. He

feels within him his longing for happiness and for reason. The

absurd is born of this confrontation between the human need and

the unreasonable silence of the world. This must not be forgotten.

This must be clung to because the whole consequence of a life can

depend on it. The irrational, the human nostalgia, and the absurd

that is born of their encounter—these are the three characters in the

drama that must necessarily end with all the logic of which an

existence is capable.

Philosophical Suicide

The feeling of the absurd is not, for all that, the notion of the

absurd. It lays the foundations for it, and that is all. It is not limited

to that notion, except in the brief moment when it passes judgment

on the universe. Subsequently it has a chance of going further. It is

alive; in other words, it must die or else reverberate. So it is with

the themes we have gathered together. But there again what

interests me is not works or minds, criticism of which would call

for another form and another place, but the discovery of what their

conclusions have in common. Never, perhaps, have minds been so

different. And yet we recognize as identical the spiritual

landscapes in which they get under way. Likewise, despite such

dissimilar zones of knowledge, the cry that terminates their

itinerary rings out in the same way. It is evident that the thinkers

we have just recalled have a common climate.

To say that that climate is deadly scarcely amounts to playing

on words. Living under that stifling sky forces one to get away or

to stay. The important thing is to find out how people get away in

the first case and why people stay in the second case. This is how I

define the problem of suicide and the possible interest in the

conclusions of existential philosophy.

But first I want to detour from the direct path. Up to now we

have managed to circumscribe the absurd from the outside. One

can, however, wonder how much is clear in that notion and by

direct analysis try to discover its meaning on the one hand and, on

the other, the consequences it involves.

If I accuse an innocent man of a monstrous crime, if I tell a

virtuous man that he has coveted his own sister, he will reply that

this is absurd. His indignation has its comical aspect. But it also

has its fundamental reason. The virtuous man illustrates by that

reply the definitive antinomy existing between the deed I am

attributing to him and his lifelong principles. “It’s absurd” means

“It’s impossible” but also “It’s contradictory.” If I see a man armed

only with a sword attack a group of machine guns, I shall consider

his act to be absurd. But it is so solely by virtue of the

disproportion between his intention and the reality he will

encounter, of the contradiction I notice between his true strength

and the aim he has in view. Likewise we shall deem a verdict

absurd when we contrast it with the verdict the facts apparently

dictated. And, similarly, a demonstration by the absurd is achieved

by comparing the consequences of such a reasoning with the

logical reality one wants to set up. In all these cases, from the

simplest to the most complex, the magnitude of the absurdity will

be in direct ratio to the distance between the two terms of my

comparison. There are absurd marriages, challenges, rancors,

silences, wars, and even peace treaties. For each of them the

absurdity springs from a comparison. I am thus justified in saying

that the feeling of absurdity does not spring from the mere scrutiny

of a fact or an impression, but that it bursts from the comparison

between a bare fact and a certain reality, between an action and the

world that transcends it. The absurd is essentially a divorce. It lies

in neither of the elements compared; it is born of their

confrontation.

In this particular case and on the plane of intelligence, I can

therefore say that the Absurd is not in man (if such a metaphor

could have a meaning) nor in the world, but in their presence

together. For the moment it is the only bond uniting them. If wish

to limit myself to facts, I know what man wants, I know what the

world offers him, and now I can say that I also know what links

them. I have no need to dig deeper. A single certainty is enough for

the seeker. He simply has to derive all the consequences from it.

The immediate consequence is also a rule of method. The odd

trinity brought to light in this way is certainly not a startling

discovery. But it resembles the data of experience in that it is both

infinitely simple and infinitely complicated. Its first distinguishing

feature in this regard is that it cannot be divided. To destroy one of

its terms is to destroy the whole. There can be no absurd outside

the human mind. Thus, like everything else, the absurd ends with

death. But there can be no absurd outside this world either. And it

is by this elementary criterion that I judge the notion of the absurd

to be essential and consider that it can stand as the first of my

truths. The rule of method alluded to above appears here. If I judge

that a thing is true, I must preserve it. If I attempt to solve a

problem, at least I must not by that very solution conjure away one

of the terms of the problem. For me the sole datum is the absurd.

The first and, after all, the only condition of my inquiry is to

preserve the very thing that crushes me, consequently to respect

what I consider essential in it. I have just defined it as a

confrontation and an unceasing struggle.

And carrying this absurd logic to its conclusion, I must admit

that that struggle implies a total absence of hope

(which has

nothing to do with despair), a continual rejection (which must not

be confused with renunciation), and a conscious dissatisfaction

(which must not be compared to immature unrest). Everything that

destroys, conjures away, or exorcises these requirements (and, to

begin with, consent which overthrows divorce) ruins the absurd

and devaluates the attitude that may then be proposed. The absurd

has meaning only in so far as it is not agreed to.

<br>

There exists an obvious fact that seems utterly moral: namely,

that a man is always a prey to his truths. Once he has admitted

them, he cannot free himself from them. One has to pay something.

A man who has be-come conscious of the absurd is forever bound

to it. A man devoid of hope and conscious of being so has ceased

to belong to the future. That is natural. But it is just as natural that

he should strive to escape the universe of which he is the creator.

All the foregoing has significance only on account of this paradox.

Certain men, starting from a critique of rationalism, have admitted

the absurd climate. Nothing is more instructive in this regard than

to scrutinize the way in which they have elaborated their

consequences.

Now, to limit myself to existential philosophies, I see that all of

them without exception suggest escape. Through an odd reasoning,

starting out from the absurd over the ruins of reason, in a closed

universe limited to the human, they deify what crushes them and

find reason to hope in what impoverishes them. That forced hope is

religious in all of them. It deserves attention.

I shall merely analyze here as examples a few themes dear to

Chestov and Kierkegaard. But Jaspers will provide us, in

caricatural form, a typical example of this attitude. As a result the

rest will be clearer. He is left powerless to realize the transcendent,

incapable of plumbing the depth of experience, and conscious of

that universe upset by failure. Will he advance or at least draw the

conclusions from that failure? He contributes nothing new. He has

found nothing in experience but the confession of his own

impotence and no occasion to infer any satisfactory principle. Yet

without justification, as he says to himself, he suddenly asserts all

at once the transcendent, the essence of experience, and the

superhuman significance of life when he writes: “Does not the

failure reveal, beyond any possible explanation and interpretation,

not the absence but the existence of transcendence?” That

existence which, suddenly and through a blind act of human

confidence, explains everything, he defines as “the unthinkable

unity of the general and the particular.” Thus the absurd becomes

god (in the broadest meaning of this word) and that inability to

understand becomes the existence that illuminates everything.

Nothing logically prepares this reasoning. I can call it a leap. And

para-doxically can be understood Jaspers’s insistence, his infinite

patience devoted to making the experience of the transcendent

impossible to realize. For the more fleeting that approximation is,

the more empty that definition proves to be, and the more real that

transcendent is to him; for the passion he devotes to asserting it is

in direct proportion to the gap between his powers of explanation

and the irrationality of the world and of experience. It thus appears

that the more bitterly Jaspers destroys the reason’s preconceptions,

the more radically he will explain the world. That apostle of

humiliated thought will find at the very end of humiliation the

means of regenerating being to its very depth.

Mystical thought has familiarized us with such devices. They

are just as legitimate as any attitude of mind. But for the moment I

am acting as if I took a certain problem seriously. Without judging

beforehand the general value of this attitude or its educative power,

I mean simply to consider whether it answers the conditions I set

myself, whether it is worthy of the conflict that concerns me. Thus

I return to Chestov. A commentator relates a remark of his that

deserves interest:

“The only true solution,” he said, “is precisely where human

judgment sees no solution. Otherwise, what need would we have of

God? We turn toward God only to obtain the impossible. As for

the possible, men suffice.” If there is a Chestovian philosophy, I

can say that it is altogether summed up in this way. For when, at

the conclusion of his passionate analyses, Chestov discovers the

fundamental absurdity of all existence, he does not say: “This is

the absurd,” but rather: “This is God: we must rely on him even if

he does not correspond to any of our rational categories.” So that

confusion may not be possible, the Russian philosopher even hints

that this God is perhaps full of hatred and hateful,

incomprehensible and contradictory; but the more hideous is his

face, the more he asserts his power. His greatness is his

incoherence. His proof is his inhumanity. One must spring into him

and by this leap free oneself from rational illusions. Thus, for

Chestov acceptance of the absurd is contemporaneous with the

absurd itself. Being aware of it amounts to accepting it, and the

whole logical effort of his thought is to bring it out so that at the

same time the tremendous hope it involves may burst forth. Let me

repeat that this attitude is legitimate. But I am persisting here in

considering a single problem and all its consequences. I do not

have to examine the emotion of a thought or of an act of faith. I

have a whole lifetime to do that. I know that the rationalist finds

Chestov’s attitude annoying. But I also feel that Chestov is right

rather than the rationalist, and I merely want to know if he remains

faithful to the commandments of the absurd.

Now, if it is admitted that the absurd is the contrary of hope, it

is seen that existential thought for Chestov presupposes the absurd

but proves it only to dispel it. Such subtlety of thought is a

conjuror’s emotional trick. When Chestov elsewhere sets his

absurd in opposition to current morality and reason, he calls it truth

and redemption. Hence, there is basically in that definition of the

absurd an approbation that Chestov grants it. If it is admitted that

all the power of that notion lies in the way it runs counter to our

elementary hopes, if it is felt that to remain, the absurd requires not

to be consented to, then it can be clearly seen that it has lost its true

aspect, its human and relative character in order to enter an eternity

that is both incomprehensible and satisfying. If there is an absurd,

it is in man’s universe. The moment the notion transforms itself

into eternity’s springboard, it ceases to be linked to human lucidity.

The absurd is no longer that evidence that man ascertains without

consenting to it. The struggle is eluded. Man integrates the absurd

and in that communion causes to disappear its essential character,

which is opposition, laceration, and divorce. This leap is an escape.

Chestov, who is so fond of quoting Hamlet’s remark: “The time is

out of joint,” writes it down with a sort of savage hope that seems

to belong to him in particular. For it is not in this sense that Hamlet

says it or Shakespeare writes it. The intoxication of the irrational

and the vocation of rapture turn a lucid mind away from the

absurd. To Chestov reason is useless but there is something beyond

reason. To an absurd mind reason is useless and there is nothing

beyond reason.

This leap can at least enlighten us a little more as to the true

nature of the absurd. We know that it is worthless except in an

equilibrium, that it is, above all, in the comparison and not in the

terms of that comparison. But it so happens that Chestov puts all

the emphasis on one of the terms and destroys the equilibrium. Our

appetite for understanding, our nostalgia for the absolute are

explicable only in so far, precisely, as we can understand and

explain many things. It is useless to negate the reason absolutely. It

has its order in which it is efficacious. It is properly that of human

experience. Whence we wanted to make everything clear. If we

cannot do so, if the absurd is born on that occasion, it is born

precisely at the very meeting-point of that efficacious but limited

reason with the ever resurgent irrational. Now, when Chestov rises

up against a Hegelian proposition such as “the motion of the solar

system takes place in conformity with immutable laws and those

laws are its reason,” when he devotes all his passion to upsetting

Spinoza’s rationalism, he concludes, in effect, in favor of the

vanity of all reason. Whence, by a natural and illegitimate reversal,

to the pre-eminence of the irrational.[5] But the transition is not

evident. For here may intervene the notion of limit and the notion

of level. The laws of nature may be operative up to a certain limit,

beyond which they turn against themselves to give birth to the

absurd. Or else, they may justify themselves on the level of

description without for that reason being true on the level of

explanation.

Everything is sacrificed here to the irrational, and, the demand

for clarity being conjured away, the absurd disappears with one of

the terms of its comparison. The absurd man, on the other hand,

does not undertake such a leveling process. He recognizes the

struggle, does not absolutely scorn reason, and admits the

irrational. Thus he again embraces in a single glance all the data of

experience and he is little inclined to leap before knowing. He

knows simply that in that alert awareness there is no further place

for hope.

What is perceptible in Leo Chestov will be perhaps even more

so in Kierkegaard. To be sure, it is hard to outline clear

propositions in so elusive a writer. But, despite apparently opposed

writings, beyond the pseudonyms, the tricks, and the smiles, can be

felt throughout that work, as it were, the presentiment (at the same

time as the apprehension) of a truth which eventually bursts forth

in the last works: Kierkegaard likewise takes the leap. His

childhood having been so frightened by Christianity, he ultimately

returns to its harshest aspect. For him, too, antinomy and paradox

become criteria of the religious. Thus, the very thing that led to

despair of the meaning and depth of this life now gives it its truth

and its clarity. Christianity is the scandal, and what Kierkegaard

calls for quite plainly is the third sacrifice required by Ignatius

Loyola, the one in which God most rejoices: “The sacrifice of the

intellect.”[6]

This effect of the “leap” is odd, but must not surprise us any

longer. He makes of the absurd the criterion of the other world,

whereas it is simply a residue of the experience of this world. “In

his failure,” says Kierkegaard, “the believer finds his triumph.”

It is not for me to wonder to what stirring preaching this

attitude is linked. I merely have to wonder if the spectacle of the

absurd and its own character justifies it. On this point, I know that

it is not so. Upon considering again the content of the absurd, one

understands better the method that inspired Kierkegaard. Between

the irrational of the world and the insurgent nostalgia of the absurd,

he does not maintain the equilibrium. He does not respect the

relationship that constitutes, properly speaking, the feeling of

absurdity. Sure of being unable to escape the irrational, he wants at

least to save himself from that desperate nostalgia that seems to

him sterile and devoid of implication. But if he may be right on

this point in his judgment, he could not be in his negation. If he

substitutes for his cry of revolt a frantic adherence, at once he is

led to blind himself to the absurd which hitherto enlightened him

and to deify the only certainty he henceforth possesses, the

irrational. The important thing, as Abbe Galiani said to Mme

d’Epinay, is not to be cured, but to live with one’s ailments.

Kierkegaard wants to be cured. To be cured is his frenzied wish,

and it runs throughout his whole journal. The entire effort of his

intelligence is to escape the antinomy of the human condition. An

all the more desperate effort since he intermittently perceives its

vanity when he speaks of himself, as if neither fear of God nor

piety were capable of bringing him to peace. Thus it is that,

through a strained subterfuge, he gives the irrational the

appearance and God the attributes of the absurd: unjust,

incoherent, and incomprehensible. Intelligence alone in him strives

to stifle the underlying demands of the human heart. Since nothing

is proved, everything can be proved.

Indeed, Kierkegaard himself shows us the path taken. I do not

want to suggest anything here, but how can one fail to read in his

works the signs of an almost intentional mutilation of the soul to

balance the mutilation accepted in regard to the absurd? It is the

leitmotiv of the Journal. “What I lacked was the animal which also

belongs to human destiny

But give me a body then.” And

further on: “Oh! especially in my early youth what should I not

have given to be a man, even for six months ... what I lack,

basically, is a body and the physical conditions of existence.”

Elsewhere, the same man nevertheless adopts the great cry of hope

that has come down through so many centuries and quickened so

many hearts, except that of the absurd man. “But for the Christian

death is certainly not the end of everything and it implies infinitely

more hope than life implies for us, even when that life is

overflowing with health and vigor.” Reconciliation through

scandal is still reconciliation. It allows one perhaps, as can be seen,

to derive hope of its contrary, which is death. But even if fellow-

feeling inclines one toward that attitude, still it must be said that

excess justifies nothing. That transcends, as the saying goes, the

human scale; therefore it must be superhuman. But this “therefore”

is superfluous. There is no logical certainty here. There is no

experimental probability either. All I can say is that, in fact, that

transcends my scale. If I do not draw a negation from it, at least I

do not want to found anything on the incomprehensible. I want to

know whether I can live with what I know and with that alone. I

am told again that here the intelligence must sacrifice its pride and

the reason bow down. But if I recognize the limits of the reason, I

do not therefore negate it, recognizing its relative powers. I merely

want to remain in this middle path where the intelligence can

remain clear. If that is its pride, I see no sufficient reason for

giving it up. Nothing more profound, for example, than

Kierkegaard’s view according to which despair is not a fact but a

state: the very state of sin. For sin is what alienates from God. The

absurd, which is the metaphysical state of the conscious man, does

not lead to God.[7] Perhaps this notion will become clearer if I risk

this shocking statement: the absurd is sin without God.

It is a matter of living in that state of the absurd I know on

what it is founded, this mind and this world straining against each

other without being able to embrace each other. I ask for the rule—

of life of that state, and what I am offered neglects its basis,

negates one of the terms of the painful opposition, demands of me

a resignation. I ask what is involved in the condition I recognize as

mine; I know it implies obscurity and ignorance; and I am assured

that this ignorance explains everything and that this darkness is my

light. But there is no reply here to my intent, and this stirring

lyricism cannot hide the paradox from me. One must therefore turn

away. Kierkegaard may shout in warning: “If man had no eternal

consciousness, if, at the bottom of everything, there were merely a

wild, seething force producing everything, both large and trifling,

in the storm of dark passions, if the bottomless void that nothing

can fill underlay all things, what would life be but despair?” This

cry is not likely to stop the absurd man. Seeking what is true is not

seeking what is desirable. If in order to elude the anxious question:

“What would life be?” one must, like the donkey, feed on the roses

of illusion, then the absurd mind, rather than resigning itself to

falsehood, prefers, to adopt fearlessly Kierkegaard’s reply:

“despair.” Everything considered, a determined soul will always

manage.

<br>

I am taking the liberty at this point of calling the existential

attitude philosophical suicide. But this does not imply a judgment.

It is a convenient way of indicating the movement by which a

thought negates itself and tends to transcend itself in its very

negation. For the existentials negation is their God. To be precise,

that god is maintained only through the negation of human

reason.[8] But, like suicides, gods change with men. There are

many ways of leaping, the essential being to leap. Those

redeeming negations, those ultimate contradictions which negate

the obstacle that has not yet been leaped over, may spring just as

well (this is the paradox at which this reasoning aims) from a

certain religious inspiration as from the rational order. They always

lay claim to the eternal, and it is solely in this that they take the

leap.

It must be repeated that the reasoning developed in this essay

leaves out altogether the most widespread spiritual attitude of our

enlightened age: the one, based on the principle that all is reason,

which aims to explain the world. It is natural to give a clear view

of the world after accepting the idea that it must be clear. That is

even legitimate, but does not concern the reasoning we are

following out here. In fact, our aim is to shed light upon the step

taken by the mind when, starting from a philosophy of the world’s

lack of meaning, it ends up by finding a meaning and depth in it.

The most touching of those steps is religious in essence; it

becomes obvious in the theme of the irrational. But the most

paradoxical and most significant is certainly the one that attributes

rational reasons to a world it originally imagined as devoid of any

guiding principle. It is impossible in any case to reach the

consequences that concern us without having given an idea of this

new attainment of the spirit of nostalgia.

I shall examine merely the theme of “the Intention” made

fashionable by Husserl and the phenomenologists. I have already

alluded to it. Originally Husserl’s method negates the classic

procedure of the reason. Let me repeat. Thinking is not unifying or

making the appearance familiar under the guise of a great

principle. Thinking is learning all over again how to see, directing

one’s consciousness, making of every image a privileged place. In

other words, phenomenology declines to explain the world, it

wants to be merely a description of actual experience. It confirms

absurd thought in its initial assertion that there is no truth, but

merely truths. From the evening breeze to this hand on my

shoulder, everything has its truth. Consciousness illuminates it by

paying attention to it. Consciousness does not form the object of its

understanding, it merely focuses, it is the act of attention, and, to

borrow a Bergsonian image, it resembles the projector that

suddenly focuses on an image. The difference is that there is no

scenario, but a successive and incoherent illustration. In that magic

lantern all the pictures are privileged. Consciousness suspends in

experience the objects of its attention. Through its miracle it

isolates them. Henceforth they are beyond all judgments. This is

the “intention” that characterizes consciousness. But the word does

not imply any idea of finality; it is taken in its sense of “direction”:

its only value is topographical.

At first sight, it certainly seems that in this way nothing

contradicts the absurd spirit. That apparent modesty of thought that

limits itself to describing what it declines to explain, that

intentional discipline whence results paradoxically a profound

enrichment of experience and the rebirth of the world in its

prolixity are absurd procedures. At least at first sight. For methods

of thought, in this case as elsewhere, always assume two aspects,

one psychological and the other metaphysical.[9] Thereby they

harbor two truths. If the theme of the intentional claims to illustrate

merely a psychological attitude, by which reality is drained instead

of being explained, nothing in fact separates it from the absurd

spirit. It aims to enumerate what it cannot transcend. It affirms

solely that without any unifying principle thought can still take

delight in describing and understanding every aspect of experience.

The truth involved then for each of those aspects is psychological

in nature. It simply testifies to the “interest” that reality can offer.

It is a way of awaking a sleeping world and of making it vivid to

the mind. But if one attempts to extend and give a rational basis to

that notion of truth, if one claims to discover in this way the

“essence” of each object of knowledge, one restores its depth to

experience. For an absurd mind that is incomprehensible. Now, it

is this wavering between modesty and assurance that is noticeable

in the intentional attitude, and this shimmering of

phenomenological thought will illustrate the absurd reasoning

better than anything else.

For Husserl speaks likewise of

“extra-temporal essences”

brought to light by the intention, and he sounds like Plato. All

things are not explained by one thing but by all things. I see no

difference. To be sure, those ideas or those essences that

consciousness “effectuates” at the end of every description are not

yet to be considered perfect models. But it is asserted that they are

directly present in each datum of perception. There is no longer a

single idea explaining everything, but an infinite number of

essences giving a meaning to an infinite number of objects. The

world comes to a stop, but also lights up. Platonic realism becomes

intuitive, but it is still realism. Kierkegaard was swallowed up in

his God; Parmenides plunged thought into the One. But here

thought hurls itself into an abstract polytheism. But this is not all:

hallucinations and fictions likewise belong to

“extra-temporal

essences.” In the new world of ideas, the species of centaurs

collaborates with the more modest species of metropolitan man.

For the absurd man, there was a truth as well as a bitterness in

that purely psychological opinion that all aspects of the world are

privileged. To say that everything is privileged is tantamount to

saying that everything is equivalent. But the metaphysical aspect of

that truth is so far-reaching that through an elementary reaction he

feels closer perhaps to Plato. He is taught, in fact, that every image

presupposes an equally privileged essence. In this ideal world

without hierarchy, the formal army is composed solely of generals.

To be sure, transcendency had been eliminated. But a sudden shift

in thought brings back into the world a sort of fragmentary

immanence which restores to the universe its depth.

Am I to fear having carried too far a theme handled with

greater circumspection by its creators? I read merely these

assertions of Husserl, apparently paradoxical yet rigorously logical

if what precedes is accepted: “That which is true is true absolutely,

in itself; truth is one, identical with itself, however different the

creatures who perceive it, men, monsters, angels or gods.” Reason

triumphs and trumpets forth with that voice, I cannot deny. What

can its assertions mean in the absurd world? The perception of an

angel or a god has no meaning for me. That geometrical spot

where divine reason ratifies mine will always be incomprehensible

to me. There, too, I discern a leap, and though performed in the

abstract, it nonetheless means for me forgetting just what I do not

want to forget. When farther on Husserl exclaims: “If all masses

subject to attraction were to disappear, the law of attraction would

not be destroyed but would simply remain without any possible

application,” I know that I am faced with a metaphysic of

consolation. And if I want to discover the point where thought

leaves the path of evidence, I have only to reread the parallel

reasoning that Husserl voices regarding the mind: “If we could

contemplate clearly the exact laws of psychic processes, they

would be seen to be likewise eternal and invariable, like the basic

laws of theoretical natural science. Hence they would be valid even

if there were no psychic process.” Even if the mind were not, its

laws would be! I see then that of a psychological truth Husserl

aims to make a rational rule: after having denied the integrating

power of human reason, he leaps by this expedient to eternal

Reason.

Husserl’s theme of the “concrete universe” cannot then surprise

me. If I am told that all essences are not formal but that some are

material, that the first are the object of logic and the second of

science, this is merely a question of definition. The abstract, I am

told, indicates but a part, without consistency in itself, of a

concrete universal. But the wavering already noted allows me to

throw light on the confusion of these terms. For that may mean that

the concrete object of my attention, this sky, the reflection of that

water on this coat, alone preserve the prestige of the real that my

interest isolates in the world. And I shall not deny it. But that may

mean also that this coat itself is universal, has its particular and

sufficient essence, belongs to the world of forms. I then realize that

merely the order of the procession has been changed. This world

has ceased to have its reflection in a higher universe, but the

heaven of forms is figured in the host of images of this earth. This

changes nothing for me. Rather than encountering here a taste for

the concrete, the meaning of the human condition, I find an

intellectualism sufficiently unbridled to generalize the concrete

itself.

<br>

It is futile to be amazed by the apparent paradox that leads

thought to its own negation by the opposite paths of humiliated

reason and triumphal reason. From the abstract god of Husserl to

the dazzling god of Kierkegaard the distance is not so great.

Reason and the irrational lead to the same preaching. In truth the

way matters but little; the will to arrive suffices. The abstract

philosopher and the religious philosopher start out from the same

disorder and support each other in the same anxiety. But the

essential is to explain. Nostalgia is stronger here than knowledge.

It is significant that the thought of the epoch is at once one of the

most deeply imbued with a philosophy of the non-significance of

the world and one of the most divided in its conclusions. It is

constantly oscillating between extreme rationalization of reality

which tends to break up that thought into standard reasons and its

extreme irrationalization which tends to deify it. But this divorce is

only apparent. It is a matter of reconciliation, and, in both cases,

the leap suffices. It is always wrongly thought that the notion of

reason is a oneway notion. To tell the truth, however rigorous it

may be in its ambition, this concept is nonetheless just as unstable

as others. Reason bears a quite human aspect, but it also is able to

turn toward the divine. Since Plotinus, who was the first to

reconcile it with the eternal climate, it has learned to turn away

from the most cherished of its principles, which is contradiction, in

order to integrate into it the strangest, the quite magic one of

participation.[10] It is an instrument of thought and not thought

itself. Above all, a man’s thought is his nostalgia.

Just as reason was able to soothe the melancholy of Plotinus, it

provides modern anguish the means of calming itself in the

familiar setting of the eternal. The absurd mind has less luck. For it

the world is neither so rational nor so irrational. It is unreasonable

and only that. With Husserl the reason eventually has no limits at

all. The absurd, on the contrary, establishes its lim-its since it is

powerless to calm its anguish. Kierkegaard independently asserts

that a single limit is enough to negate that anguish. But the absurd

does not go so far. For it that limit is directed solely at the reason’s

ambitions. The theme of the irrational, as it is conceived by the

existentials, is reason becoming confused and escaping by negating

itself. The absurd is lucid reason noting its limits.

Only at the end of this difficult path does the absurd man

recognize his true motives. Upon comparing his inner exigence and

what is then offered him, he suddenly feels he is going to turn

away. In the universe of Husserl the world becomes clear and that

longing for familiarity that man’s heart harbors becomes useless.

In Kierkegaard’s apocalypse that desire for clarity must be given

up if it wants to be satisfied. Sin is not so much knowing (if it

were, everybody would be innocent) as wanting to know. Indeed, it

is the only sin of which the absurd man can feel that it constitutes

both his guilt and his innocence. He is offered a solution in which

all the past contradictions have become merely polemical games.

But this is not the way he experienced them. Their truth must be

preserved, which consists in not being satisfied. He does not want

preaching.

My reasoning wants to be faithful to the evidence that aroused

it. That evidence is the absurd. It is that divorce between the mind

that desires and the world that disappoints, my nostalgia for unity,

this fragmented universe and the contradiction that binds them

together. Kierkegaard suppresses my nostalgia and Husserl gathers

together that universe. That is not what I was expecting. It was a

matter of living and thinking with those dislocations, of knowing

whether one had to accept or refuse. There can be no question of

masking the evidence, of suppressing the absurd by denying one of

the terms of its equation. It is essential to know whether one can

live with it or whether, on the other hand, logic commands one to

die of it. I am not interested in philosophical suicide, but rather in

plain suicide. I merely wish to purge it of its emotional content and

know its logic and its integrity. Any other position implies for the

absurd mind deceit and the mind’s retreat before what the mind

itself has brought to light. Husserl claims to obey the desire to

escape “the inveterate habit of living and thinking in certain well-

known and convenient conditions of existence,” but the final leap

restores in him the eternal and its comfort. The leap does not

represent an extreme danger as Kierkegaard would like it to do.

The danger, on the contrary, lies in the subtle instant that precedes

the leap. Being able to remain on that dizzying crest—that is

integrity and the rest is subterfuge. I know also that never has

helplessness inspired such striking harmonies as those of

Kierkegaard. But if helplessness has its place in the indifferent

landscapes of history, it has none in a reasoning whose exigence is

now known.

Absurd Freedom

Now the main thing is done, I hold certain facts from which I

cannot separate. What I know, what is certain, what I cannot deny,

what I cannot reject—this is what counts. I can negate everything

of that part of me that lives on vague nostalgias, except this desire

for unity, this longing to solve, this need for clarity and cohesion. I

can refute everything in this world surrounding me that offends or

enraptures me, except this chaos, this sovereign chance and this

divine equivalence which springs from anarchy. I don’t know

whether this world has a meaning that transcends it. But I know

that I do not know that meaning and that it is impossible for me

just now to know it. What can a meaning outside my condition

mean to me? I can understand only in human terms. What I touch,

what resists me—that is what I understand. And these two

certainties—my appetite for the absolute and for unity and the

impossibility of reducing this world to a rational and reasonable

principle—I also know that I cannot reconcile them. What other

truth can I admit without lying, without bringing in a hope I lack

and which means nothing within the limits of my condition?

If I were a tree among trees, a cat among animals, this life

would have a meaning, or rather this problem would not arise, for I

should belong to this world. I should be this world to which I am

now opposed by my whole consciousness and my whole insistence

upon familiarity. This ridiculous reason is what sets me in

opposition to all creation. I cannot cross it out with a stroke of the

pen. What I believe to be true I must therefore preserve. What

seems to me so obvious, even against me, I must support. And

what constitutes the basis of that conflict, of that break between the

world and my mind, but the awareness of it? If therefore I want to

preserve it, I can through a constant awareness, ever revived, ever

alert. This is what, for the moment, I must remember. At this

moment the absurd, so obvious and yet so hard to win, returns to a

man’s life and finds its home there. At this moment, too, the mind

can leave the arid, dried-up path of lucid effort. That path now

emerges in daily life. It encounters the world of the anonymous

impersonal pronoun “one,” but henceforth man enters in with his

revolt and his lucidity. He has forgotten how to hope. This hell of

the present is his Kingdom at last. All problems recover their sharp

edge. Abstract evidence retreats before the poetry of forms and

colors. Spiritual conflicts become embodied and return to the

abject and magnificent shelter of man’s heart. None of them is

settled. But all are transfigured. Is one going to die, escape by the

leap, rebuild a mansion of ideas and forms to one’s own scale? Is

one, on the contrary, going to take up the heart-rending and

marvelous wager of the absurd? Let’s make a final effort in this

regard and draw all our conclusions. The body, affection, creation,

action, human nobility will then resume their places in this mad

world. At last man will again find there the wine of the absurd and

the bread of indifference on which he feeds his greatness.

Let us insist again on the method: it is a matter of persisting. At

a certain point on his path the absurd man is tempted. History is

not lacking in either religions or prophets, even without gods. He is

asked to leap. All he can reply is that he doesn’t fully understand,

that it is not obvious. Indeed, he does not want to do anything but

what he fully understands. He is assured that this is the sin of

pride, but he does not understand the notion of sin; that perhaps

hell is in store, but he has not enough imagination to visualize that

strange future; that he is losing immortal life, but that seems to him

an idle consideration. An attempt is made to get him to admit his

guilt. He feels innocent. To tell the truth, that is all he feels—his

irreparable innocence. This is what allows him everything. Hence,

what he demands of himself is to live solely with what he knows,

to accommodate himself to what is, and to bring in nothing that is

not certain. He is told that nothing is. But this at least is a certainty.

And it is with this that he is concerned: he wants to find out if it is

possible to live without appeal.

Now I can broach the notion of suicide. It has already been felt

what solution might be given. At this point the problem is

reversed. It was previously a question of finding out whether or not

life had to have a meaning to be lived. It now becomes clear, on

the contrary, that it will be lived all the better if it has no meaning.

Living an experience, a particular fate, is accepting it fully. Now,

no one will live this fate, knowing it to be absurd, unless he does

everything to keep before him that absurd brought to light by

consciousness. Negating one of the terms of the opposition on

which he lives amounts to escaping it. To abolish conscious revolt

is to elude the problem. The theme of permanent revolution is thus

carried into individual experience. Living is keeping the absurd

alive. Keeping it alive is, above all, contemplating it. Unlike

Eurydice, the absurd dies only when we turn away from it. One of

the only coherent philosophical positions is thus revolt. It is a

constant confrontation between man and his own obscurity. It is an

insistence upon an impossible transparency. It challenges the world

anew every second. Just as danger provided man the unique

opportunity of seizing awareness, so metaphysical revolt extends

awareness to the whole of experience. It is that constant presence

of man in his own eyes. It is not aspiration, for it is devoid of hope.

That revolt is the certainly of a crushing fate, without the

resignation that ought to accompany it.

This is where it is seen to what a degree absurd experience is

remote from suicide. It may be thought that suicide follows

revolt—but wrongly. For it does not represent the logical outcome

of revolt. It is just the contrary by the consent it presupposes.

Suicide, like the leap, is acceptance at its extreme. Everything is

over and man returns to his essential history. His future, his unique

and dreadful future—he sees and rushes toward it. In its way,

suicide settles the absurd. It engulfs the absurd in the same death.

But I know that in order to keep alive, the absurd cannot be settled.

It escapes suicide to the extent that it is simultaneously awareness

and rejection of death. It is, at the extreme limit of the condemned

man’s last thought, that shoelace that despite everything he sees a

few yards away, on the very brink of his dizzying fall. The

contrary of suicide, in fact, is the man condemned to death.

That revolt gives life its value. Spread out over the whole

length of a life, it restores its majesty to that life. To a man devoid

of blinders, there is no finer sight than that of the intelligence at

grips with a reality that transcends it. The sight of human pride is

unequaled. No disparagement is of any use. That discipline that the

mind imposes on itself, that will conjured up out of nothing, that

face-to-face struggle have something exceptional about them. To

impoverish that reality whose inhumanity constitutes man’s

majesty is tantamount to impoverishing him himself. I understand

then why the doctrines that explain everything to me also debilitate

me at the same time. They relieve me of the weight of my own life,

and yet I must carry it alone. At this juncture, I cannot conceive

that a skeptical metaphysics can be joined to an ethics of

renunciation.

Consciousness and revolt, these rejections are the contrary of

renunciation. Everything that is indomitable and passionate in a

human heart quickens them, on the contrary, with its own life. It is

essential to die unrecon-ciled and not of one’s own free will.

Suicide is a repudi—ation. The absurd man can only drain

everything to the bitter end, and deplete himself. The absurd is his

extreme tension, which he maintains constantly by solitary effort,

for he knows that in that consciousness and in that day-to-day

revolt he gives proof of his only truth, which is defiance. This is a

first consequence.

<br>

If I remain in that prearranged position which consists in

drawing all the conclusions (and nothing else) involved in a newly

discovered notion, I am faced with a second paradox. In order to

remain faithful to that method, I have nothing to do with the

problem of metaphysical liberty. Knowing whether or not man is

free doesn’t interest me. I can experience only my own freedom.

As to it, I can have no general notions, but merely a few clear

insights. The problem of “freedom as such” has no meaning, for it

is linked in quite a different way with the problem of God.

Knowing whether or not man is free involves knowing whether he

can have a master. The absurdity peculiar to this problem comes

from the fact that the very notion that makes the problem of

freedom possible also takes away all its meaning. For in the

presence of God there is less a problem of freedom than a problem

of evil. You know the alternative: either we are not free and God

the all-powerful is responsible for evil. Or we are free and

responsible but God is not all powerful. All the scholastic

subtleties have neither added anything to nor subtracted anything

from the acuteness of this paradox.

This is why I cannot act lost in the glorification or the mere

definition of a notion which eludes me and loses its meaning as

soon as it goes beyond the frame of reference of my individual

experience. I cannot understand what kind of freedom would be

given me by a higher being. I have lost the sense of hierarchy. The

only conception of freedom I can have is that of the prisoner or the

individual in the midst of the State. The only one I know is

freedom of thought and action. Now if the absurd cancels all my

chances of eternal freedom, it restores and magnifies, on the other

hand, my freedom of action. That privation of hope and future

means an increase in man’s availability.

Before encountering the absurd, the everyday man lives with

aims, a concern for the future or for justification (with regard to

whom or what is not the question). He weighs his chances, he

counts on “someday,” his retirement or the labor of his sons. He

still thinks that something in his life can be directed. In truth, he

acts as if he were free, even if all the facts make a point of

contradicting that liberty. But after the absurd, everything is upset.

That idea that “I am,” my way of acting as if everything has a

meaning (even if, on occasion, I said that nothing has)—all that is

given the lie in vertiginous fashion by the absurdity of a possible

death. Thinking of the future, establishing aims for oneself, having

preferences—all this presupposes a belief in freedom, even if one

occasionally ascertains that one doesn’t feel it. But at that moment

I am well aware that that higher liberty, that freedom to be, which

alone can serve as basis for a truth, does not exist. Death is there as

the only reality. After death the chips are down. I am not even free,

either, to perpetuate myself, but a slave, and, above all, a slave

without hope of an eternal revolution, without recourse to

contempt. And who without revolution and without contempt can

remain a slave? What freedom can exist in the fullest sense without

assurance of eternity?

But at the same time the absurd man realizes that hitherto he

was bound to that postulate of freedom on the illusion of which he

was living. In a certain sense, that hampered him. To the extent to

which he imagined a purpose to his life, he adapted himself to the

demands of a purpose to be achieved and became the slave of his

liberty. Thus I could not act otherwise than as the father (or the

engineer or the leader of a nation, or the post-office sub-clerk) that

I am preparing to be. I think I can choose to be that rather than

something else. I think so unconsciously, to be sure. But at the

same time I strengthen my postulate with the beliefs of those

around me, with the presumptions of my human environment

(others are so sure of being free, and that cheerful mood is so

contagious!). However far one may remain from any presumption,

moral or social, one is partly influenced by them and even, for the

best among them (there are good and bad presumptions), one

adapts one’s life to them. Thus the absurd man realizes that he was

not really free. To speak clearly, to the extent to which I hope, to

which I worry about a truth that might be individual to me, about a

way of being or creating, to the extent to which I arrange my life

and prove thereby that I accept its having a meaning, I create for

myself barriers between which I confine my life. I do like so many

bureaucrats of the mind and heart who only fill me with disgust

and whose only vice, I now see clearly, is to take man’s freedom

seriously.

The absurd enlightens me on this point: there is no future.

Henceforth this is the reason for my inner freedom. I shall use two

comparisons here. Mystics, to begin with, find freedom in giving

themselves. By losing themselves in their god, by accepting his

rules, they become secretly free. In spontaneously accepted slavery

they recover a deeper independence. But what does that freedom

mean? It may be said, above all, that they feel free with regard to

themselves, and not so much free as liberated. Likewise,

completely turned toward death (taken here as the most obvious

absurdity), the absurd man feels released from everything outside

that passionate attention crystallizing in him. He enjoys a freedom

with regard to common rules. It can be seen at this point that the

initial themes of existential philosophy keep their entire value. The

return to consciousness, the escape from everyday sleep represent

the first steps of absurd freedom. But it is existential preaching that

is alluded to, and with it that spiritual leap which basically escapes

consciousness. In the same way (this is my second comparison) the

slaves of antiquity did not belong to themselves. But they knew

that freedom which consists in not feeling responsible.[11] Death,

too, has patrician hands which, while crushing, also liberate.

Losing oneself in that bottomless certainty, feeling henceforth

sufficiently remote from one’s own life to increase it and take a

broad view of it—this involves the principle of a liberation. Such

new independence has a definite time limit, like any freedom of

action. It does not write a check on eternity. But it takes the place

of the illusions of freedom, which all stopped with death. The

divine availability of the condemned man before whom the prison

doors open in a certain early dawn, that unbelievable

disinterestedness with regard to everything except for the pure

flame of life—it is clear that death and the absurd are here the

principles of the only reasonable freedom: that which a human

heart can experience and live. This is a second consequence. The

absurd man thus catches sight of a burning and frigid, transparent

and limited universe in which nothing is possible but everything is

given, and beyond which all is collapse and nothingness. He can

then decide to accept such a universe and draw from it his strength,

his refusal to hope, and the unyielding evidence of a life without

consolation.

<br>

But what does life mean in such a universe? Nothing else for

the moment but indifference to the future and a desire to use up

everything that is given. Belief in the meaning of life always

implies a scale of values, a choice, our preferences. Belief in the

absurd, according to our definitions, teaches the contrary. But this

is worth examining.

Knowing whether or not one can live without appeal is all that

interests me. I do not want to get out of my depth. This aspect of

life being given me, can I adapt myself to it? Now, faced with this

particular concern, belief in the absurd is tantamount to

substituting the quantity of experiences for the quality. If I

convince myself that this life has no other aspect than that of the

absurd, if I feel that its whole equilibrium depends on that

perpetual opposition between my conscious revolt and the darkness

in which it struggles, if I admit that my freedom has no meaning

except in relation to its limited fate, then I must say that what

counts is not the best living but the most living. It is not up to me

to wonder if this is vulgar or revolting, elegant or deplorable. Once

and for all, value judgments are discarded here in favor of factual

judgments. I have merely to draw the conclusions from what I can

see and to risk nothing that is hypothetical. Supposing that living in

this way were not honorable, then true propriety would command

me to be dishonorable.

The most living; in the broadest sense, that rule means nothing.

It calls for definition. It seems to begin with the fact that the notion

of quantity has not been sufficiently explored. For it can account

for a large share of human experience. A man’s rule of conduct

and his scale of values have no meaning except through the

quantity and variety of experiences he has been in a position to

accumulate. Now, the conditions of modern life impose on the

majority of men the same quantity of experiences and

consequently the same profound experience. To be sure, there must

also be taken into consideration the individual’s spontaneous

contribution, the “given” element in him. But I cannot judge of

that, and let me repeat that my rule here is to get along with the

immediate evidence. I see, then, that the individual character of a

common code of ethics lies not so much in the ideal importance of

its basic principles as in the norm of an experience that it is

possible to measure. To stretch a point somewhat, the Greeks had

the code of their leisure just as we have the code of our eight-hour

day. But already many men among the most tragic cause us to

foresee that a longer experience changes this table of values. They

make us imagine that adventurer of the everyday who through

mere quantity of experiences would break all records

(I am

purposely using this sports expression) and would thus win his

own code of ethics.[12] Yet let’s avoid romanticism and just ask

ourselves what such an attitude may mean to a man with his mind

made up to take up his bet and to observe strictly what he takes to

be the rules of the game.

Breaking all the records is first and foremost being faced with

the world as often as possible. How can that be done without

contradictions and without playing on words? For on the one hand

the absurd teaches that all experiences are unimportant, and on the

other it urges toward the greatest quantity of experiences. How,

then, can one fail to do as so many of those men I was speaking of

earlier—choose the form of life that brings us the most possible of

that human matter, thereby introducing a scale of values that on the

other hand one claims to reject?

But again it is the absurd and its contradictory life that teaches

us. For the mistake is thinking that that quantity of experiences

depends on the circumstances of our life when it depends solely on

us. Here we have to be over-simple. To two men living the same

number of years, the world always provides the same sum of

experiences. It is up to us to be conscious of them. Being aware of

one’s life, one’s revolt, one’s freedom, and to the maximum, is

living, and to the maximum. Where lucidity dominates, the scale of

values becomes useless. Let’s be even more simple. Let us say that

the sole obstacle, the sole deficiency to be made good, is

constituted by premature death. Thus it is that no depth, no

emotion, no passion, and no sacrifice could render equal in the

eyes of the absurd man (even if he wished it so) a conscious life of

forty years and a lucidity spread over sixty years.[13] Madness and

death are his irreparables. Man does not choose. The absurd and

the extra life it involves therefore do not defend on man’s will, but

on its contrary, which is death.[14] Weighing words carefully, it is

altogether a question of luck. One just has to be able to consent to

this. There will never be any substitute for twenty years of life and

experience.

By what is an odd inconsistency in such an alert race, the

Greeks claimed that those who died young were beloved of the

gods. And that is true only if you are willing to believe that

entering the ridiculous world of the gods is forever losing the

purest of joys, which is feeling, and feeling on this earth. The

present and the succession of presents before a constantly

conscious soul is the ideal of the absurd man. But the word “ideal”

rings false in this connection. It is not even his vocation, but

merely the third consequence of his reasoning. Having started from

an anguished awareness of the inhuman, the meditation on the

absurd returns at the end of its itinerary to the very heart of the

passionate flames of human revolt.[15]

<br>

Thus I draw from the absurd three consequences, which are my

revolt, my freedom, and my passion. By the mere activity of

consciousness I transform into a rule of life what was an invitation

to death—and I refuse suicide. I know, to be sure, the dull

resonance that vibrates throughout these days. Yet I have but a

word to say: that it is necessary. When Nietzsche writes: “It clearly

seems that the chief thing in heaven and on earth is to obey at

length and in a single direction: in the long run there results

something for which it is worth the trouble of living on this earth

as, for example, virtue, art, music, the dance, reason, the mind—

something that transfigures, something delicate, mad, or divine,”

he elucidates the rule of a really distinguished code of ethics. But

he also points the way of the absurd man. Obeying the flame is

both the easiest and the hardest thing to do. However, it is good for

man to judge himself occasionally. He is alone in being able to do

so.

“Prayer,” says Alain, “is when night descends over thought.”

“But the mind must meet the night,” reply the mystics and the

existentials. Yes, indeed, but not that night that is born under

closed eyelids and through the mere will of man—dark,

impenetrable night that the mind calls up in order to plunge into it.

If it must encounter a night, let it be rather that of despair, which

remains lucid—polar night, vigil of the mind, whence will arise

perhaps that white and virginal brightness which outlines every

object in the light of the intelligence. At that degree, equivalence

encounters passionate understanding. Then it is no longer even a

question of judging the existential leap. It resumes its place amid

the age-old fresco of human attitudes. For the spectator, if he is

conscious, that leap is still absurd. In so far as it thinks it solves the

paradox, it reinstates it intact. On this score, it is stirring. On this

score, everything resumes its place and the absurd world is reborn

in all its splendor and diversity.

But it is bad to stop, hard to be satisfied with a single way of

seeing, to go without contradiction, perhaps the most subtle of all

spiritual forces. The preceding merely defines a way of thinking.

But the point is to live.

The Absurd Man

If Stavrogin believes, he does not think he believes. If he does
not believe, he does not think he does not believe.
—The Possessed

My field,” said Goethe, “is time.” That is indeed the absurd

speech. What, in fact, is the absurd man? He who, without

negating it, does nothing for the eternal. Not that nostalgia is

foreign to him. But he prefers his courage and his reasoning. The

first teaches him to live without appeal and to get along with what

he has; the second informs him of his limits. Assured of his

temporally limited freedom, of his revolt devoid of future, and of

his mortal consciousness, he lives out his adventure within the

span of his lifetime. That is his field, that is his action, which he

shields from any judgment but his own. A greater life cannot mean

for him another life. That would be unfair. I am not even speaking

here of that paltry eternity that is called posterity. Mme Roland

relied on herself. That rashness was taught a lesson. Posterity is

glad to quote her remark, but forgets to judge it. Mme Roland is

indifferent to posterity.

There can be no question of holding forth on ethics. I have seen

people behave badly with great morality and I note every day that

integrity has no need of rules. There is but one moral code that the

absurd man can accept, the one that is not separated from God: the

one that is dictated. But it so happens that he lives outside that

God. As for the others (I mean also immoralism), the absurd man

sees nothing in them but justifications and he has nothing to

justify. I start out here from the principle of his innocence.

That innocence is to be feared.

“Everything is permitted,”

exclaims Ivan Karamazov. That, too, smacks of the absurd. But on

condition that it not be taken in the vulgar sense. I don’t know

whether or not it has been sufficiently pointed out that it is not an

outburst of relief or of joy, but rather a bitter acknowledgment of a

fact. The certainty of a God giving a meaning to life far surpasses

in attractiveness the ability to behave badly with impunity. The

choice would not be hard to make. But there is no choice, and that

is where the bitterness comes in. The absurd does not liberate; it

binds. It does not authorize all actions. “Everything is permitted”

does not mean that nothing is forbidden. The absurd merely

confers an equivalence on the consequences of those actions. It

does not recommend crime, for this would be childish, but it

restores to remorse its futility. Likewise, if all experiences are

indifferent, that of duty is as legitimate as any other. One can be

virtuous through a whim.

All systems of morality are based on the idea that an action has

consequences that legitimize or cancel it. A mind imbued with the

absurd merely judges that those consequences must be considered

calmly. It is ready to pay up. In other words, there may be

responsible persons, but there are no guilty ones, in its opinion. At

very most, such a mind will consent to use past experience as a

basis for its future actions. Time will prolong time, and life will

serve life. In this field that is both limited and bulging with

possibilities, everything in himself, except his lucidity, seems

unforeseeable to him. What rule, then, could emanate from that

unreasonable order? The only truth that might seem instructive to

him is not formal: it comes to life and unfolds in men. The absurd

mind cannot so much expect ethical rules at the end of its

reasoning as, rather, illustrations and the breath of human lives.

The few following images are of this type. They prolong the

absurd reasoning by giving it a specific attitude and their warmth.

Do I need to develop the idea that an example is not necessarily

an example to be followed (even less so, if possible, in the absurd

world) and that these illustrations are not therefore models?

Besides the fact that a certain vocation is required for this, one

becomes ridiculous, with all due allowance, when drawing from

Rousseau the conclusion that one must walk on all fours and from

Nietzsche that one must maltreat one’s mother. “It is essential to be

absurd,” writes a modern author, “it is not essential to be a dupe.”

The attitudes of which I shall treat can assume their whole

meaning only through consideration of their contraries. A sub-

clerk in the post office is the equal of a conqueror if consciousness

is common to them. All experiences are indifferent in this regard.

There are some that do either a service or a disservice to man.

They do him a service if he is conscious. Otherwise, that has no

importance: a man’s failures imply judgment, not of

circumstances, but of himself.

I am choosing solely men who aim only to expend themselves

or whom I see to be expending themselves. That has no further

implications. For the moment I want to speak only of a world in

which thoughts, like lives, are devoid of future. Everything that

makes man work and get excited utilizes hope. The sole thought

that is not mendacious is therefore a sterile thought. In the absurd

world the value of a notion or of a life is measured by its sterility.

Don Juanism

If it were sufficient to love, things would be too easy. The more

one loves, the stronger the absurd grows. It is not through lack of

love that Don Juan goes from woman to woman. It is ridiculous to

represent him as a mystic in quest of total love. But it is indeed

because he loves them with the same passion and each time with

his whole self that he must repeat his gift and his profound quest.

Whence each woman hopes to give him what no one has ever

given him. Each time they are utterly wrong and merely manage to

make him feel the need of that repetition. “At last,” exclaims one

of them, “I have given you love.” Can we be surprised that Don

Juan laughs at this? “At last? No,” he says, “but once more.” Why

should it be essential to love rarely in order to love much?

Is Don Juan melancholy? This is not likely. I shall barely have

recourse to the legend. That laugh, the conquering insolence, that

playfulness and love of the theater are all clear and joyous. Every

healthy creature tends to multiply himself. So it is with Don Juan.

But, furthermore, melancholy people have two reasons for being

so: they don’t know or they hope. Don Juan knows and does not

hope. He reminds one of those artists who know their limits, never

go beyond them, and in that precarious interval in which they take

their spiritual stand enjoy all the wonderful ease of masters. And

that is indeed genius: the intelligence that knows its frontiers. Up

to the frontier of physical death Don Juan is ignorant of

melancholy. The moment he knows, his laugh bursts forth and

makes one forgive everything. He was melancholy at the time

when he hoped. Today, on the mouth of that woman he recognizes

the bitter and comforting taste of the only knowledge. Bitter?

Barely: that necessary imperfection that makes happiness

perceptible!

It is quite false to try to see in Don Juan a man brought up on

Ecclesiastes. For nothing is vanity to him except the hope of

another life. He proves this because he gambles that other life

against heaven itself. Longing for desire killed by satisfaction, that

commonplace of the impotent man, does not belong to him. That is

all right for Faust, who believed in God enough to sell himself to

the devil. For Don Juan the thing is simpler. Molina’s Burlador

ever replies to the threats of hell: “What a long respite you give

me!” What comes after death is futile, and what a long succession

of days for whoever knows how to be alive! Faust craved worldly

goods; the poor man had only to stretch out his hand. It already

amounted to selling his soul when he was unable to gladden it. As

for satiety, Don Juan insists upon it, on the contrary. If he leaves a

woman it is not absolutely because he has ceased to desire her. A

beautiful woman is always desirable. But he desires another, and

no, this is not the same thing.

This life gratifies his every wish, and nothing is worse than

losing it. This madman is a great wise man. But men who live on

hope do not thrive in this universe where kindness yields to

generosity, affection to virile silence, and communion to solitary

courage. And all hasten to say: “He was a weakling, an idealist or a

saint.” One has to disparage the greatness that insults.

<br>

People are sufficiently annoyed (or that smile of complicity

that debases what it admires) by Don Juan’s speeches and by that

same remark that he uses on all women. But to anyone who seeks

quantity in his joys, the only thing that matters is efficacy. What is

the use of complicating the passwords that have stood the test? No

one, neither the woman nor the man, listens to them, but rather to

the voice that pronounces them. They are the rule, the convention,

and the courtesy. After they are spoken the most important still

remains to be done. Don Juan is already getting ready for it. Why

should he give himself a problem in morality? He is not like

Milosz’s Manara, who damns himself through a desire to be a

saint. Hell for him is a thing to be provoked. He has but one reply

to divine wrath, and that is human honor: “I have honor,” he says

to the Commander, “and I am keeping my promise because I am a

knight.” But it would be just as great an error to make an

immoralist of him. In this regard, he is “like everyone else”: he has

the moral code of his likes and dislikes. Don Juan can be properly

understood only by constant reference to what he commonly

symbolizes: the ordinary seducer and the sexual athlete. He is an

ordinary seducer.[16] Except for the difference that he is conscious,

and that is why he is absurd. A seducer who has become lucid will

not change for all that. Seducing is his condition in life. Only in

novels does one change condition or become better. Yet it can be

said that at the same time nothing is changed and everything is

transformed. What Don Juan realizes in action is an ethic of

quantity, whereas the saint, on the contrary, tends toward quality.

Not to believe in the profound meaning of things belongs to the

absurd man. As for those cordial or wonder-struck faces, he eyes

them, stores them up, and does not pause over them. Time keeps

up with him. The absurd man is he who is not apart from time. Don

Juan does not think of “collecting” women. He exhausts their

number and with them his chances of life. “Collecting” amounts to

being capable of living off one’s past. But he rejects regret, that

other form of hope. He is incapable of looking at portraits.

<br>

Is he selfish for all that? In his way, probably. But here, too, it

is essential to understand one another.

There are those who are made for living and those who are

made for loving. At least Don Juan would be inclined to say so.

But he would do so in a very few words such as he is capable of

choosing. For the love we are speaking of here is clothed in

illusions of the eternal. As all the specialists in passion teach us,

there is no eternal love but what is thwarted. There is scarcely any

passion without struggle. Such a love culminates only in the

ultimate contradiction of death. One must be Werther or nothing.

There, too, there are several ways of committing suicide, one of

which is the total gift and forget-fulness of self. Don Juan, as well

as anyone else, knows that this can be stirring. But he is one of the

very few who know that this is not the important thing. He knows

just as well that those who turn away from all personal life through

a great love enrich themselves perhaps but certainly impoverish

those their love has chosen. A mother or a passionate wife

necessarily has a closed heart, for it is turned away from the world.

A single emotion, a single creature, a single face, but all is

devoured. Quite a different love disturbs Don Juan, and this one is

liberating. It brings with it all the faces in the world, and its tremor

comes from the fact that it knows itself to be mortal. Don Juan has

chosen to be nothing.

For him it is a matter of seeing clearly. We call love what binds

us to certain creatures only by reference to a collective way of

seeing for which books and legends are responsible. But of love I

know only that mixture of desire, affection, and intelligence that

binds me to this or that creature. That compound is not the same

for another person. I do not have the right to cover all these

experiences with the same name. This exempts one from

conducting them with the same gestures. The absurd man

multiplies here again what he cannot unify. Thus he discovers a

new way of being which liberates him at least as much as it

liberates those who approach him. There is no noble love but that

which recognizes itself to be both short-lived and exceptional. All

those deaths and all those rebirths gathered together as in a sheaf

make up for Don Juan the flowering of his life. It is his way of

giving and of vivifying. I let it be decided whether or not one can

speak of selfishness.

<br>

I think at this point of all those who absolutely insist that Don

Juan be punished. Not only in another life, but even in this one. I

think of all those tales, legends, and laughs about the aged Don

Juan. But Don Juan is already ready. To a conscious man old age

and what it portends are not a surprise. Indeed, he is conscious

only in so far as he does not conceal its horror from himself. There

was in Athens a temple dedicated to old age. Children were taken

there. As for Don Juan, the more people laugh at him, the more his

figure stands out. Thereby he rejects the one the romantics lent

him. No one wants to laugh at that tormented, pitiful Don Juan. He

is pitied; heaven itself will redeem him? But that’s not it. In the

universe of which Don Juan has a glimpse, ridicule too is included.

He would consider it normal to be chastised. That is the rule of the

game. And, indeed, it is typical of his nobility to have accepted all

the rules of the game. Yet he knows he is right and that there can

be no question of punishment. A fate is not a punishment.

That is his crime, and how easy it is to understand why the men

of God call down punishment on his head. He achieves a

knowledge without illusions which negates everything they

profess. Loving and possessing, conquering and consuming—that

is his way of knowing.

(There is significance in that favorite

Scriptural word that calls the carnal act “knowing.”) He is their

worst enemy to the extent that he is ignorant of them. A chronicler

relates that the true Burlador died assassinated by Fransciscans

who wanted “to put an end to the excesses and blasphemies of Don

Juan, whose birth assured him impunity.” Then they proclaimed

that heaven had struck him down. No one has proved that strange

end. Nor has anyone proved the contrary. But without wondering if

it is probable, I can say that it is logical. I want merely to single out

at this point the word “birth” and to play on words: it was the fact

of living that assured his innocence. It was from death alone that

he derived a guilt now become legendary.

What else does that stone Commander signify, that cold statue

set in motion to punish the blood and courage that dared to think?

All the powers of eternal Reason, of order, of universal morality,

all the foreign grandeur of a God open to wrath are summed up in

him. That gigantic and soulless stone merely symbolizes the forces

that Don Juan negated forever. But the Commander’s mission

stops there. The thunder and lightning can return to the imitation

heaven whence they were called forth. The real tragedy takes place

quite apart from them. No, it was not under a stone hand that Don

Juan met his death. I am inclined to believe in the legendary

bravado, in that mad laughter of the healthy man provoking a non-

existent God. But, above all, I believe that on that evening when

Don Juan was waiting at Anna’s the Commander didn’t come, and

that after midnight the blasphemer must have felt the dreadful

bitterness of those who have been right. I accept even more readily

the account of his life that has him eventually burying himself in a

monastery. Not that the edifying aspect of the story can he

considered probable. What refuge can he go ask of God? But this

symbolizes rather the logical outcome of a life completely imbued

with the absurd, the grim ending of an existence turned toward

short lived joys. At this point sensual pleasure winds up in

asceticism. It is essential to realize that they may be, as it were, the

two aspects of the same destitution. What more ghastly image can

be called up than that of a man betrayed by his body who, simply

because he did not die in time, lives out the comedy while awaiting

the end, face to face with that God he does not adore, serving him

as he served life, kneeling before a void and arms outstretched

toward a heaven without eloquence that he knows to he also

without depth?

I see Don Juan in a cell of one of those Spanish monasteries

lost on a hilltop. And if he contemplates anything at all, it is not the

ghosts of past loves, but perhaps, through a narrow slit in the sun-

baked wall, some silent Spanish plain, a noble, soulless land in

which he recognizes himself. Yes, it is on this melancholy and

radiant image that the curtain must be rung down. The ultimate

end, awaited but never desired, the ultimate end is negligible.

Drama

“The play’s the thing,” says Hamlet, “wherein I’ll catch the

conscience of the king.”

“Catch” is indeed the word. For conscience moves swiftly or

withdraws within itself. It has to be caught on the wing, at that

barely perceptible moment when it glances fleetingly at itself. The

everyday man does not enjoy tarrying. Everything, on the contrary,

hurries him onward. But at the same time nothing interests him

more than himself, especially his potentialities. Whence his interest

in the theater, in the show, where so many fates are offered him,

where he can accept the poetry without feeling the sorrow. There at

least can be recognized the thoughtless man, and he continues to

hasten toward some hope or other. The absurd man begins where

that one leaves off, where, ceasing to admire the play, the mind

wants to enter in. Entering into all these lives, experiencing them

in their diversity, amounts to acting them out. I am not saying that

actors in general obey that impulse, that they are absurd men, but

that their fate is an absurd fate which might charm and attract a

lucid heart. It is necessary to establish this in order to grasp

without misunderstanding what will follow.

The actor’s realm is that of the fleeting. Of all kinds of fame, it

is known, his is the most ephemeral. At least, this is said in

conversation. But all kinds of fame are ephemeral. From the point

of view of Sirius, Goethe’s works in ten thousand years will be

dust and his name forgotten. Perhaps a handful of archaeologists

will look for

“evidence” as to our era. That idea has always

contained a lesson. Seriously meditated upon, it reduces our

perturbations to the profound nobility that is found in indifference.

Above all, it directs our concerns toward what is most certain—

that is, toward the immediate. Of all kinds of fame the least

deceptive is the one that is lived.

Hence the actor has chosen multiple fame, the fame that is

hallowed and tested. From the fact that everything is to die

someday he draws the best conclusion. An actor succeeds or does

not succeed. A writer has some hope even if he is not appreciated.

He assumes that his works will bear witness to what he was. At

best the actor will leave us a photograph, and nothing of what he

was himself, his gestures and his silences, his gasping or his

panting with love, will come down to us. For him, not to be known

is not to act, and not acting is dying a hundred times with all the

creatures he would have brought to life or resuscitated.

<br>

Why should we be surprised to find a fleeting fame built upon

the most ephemeral of creations? The actor has three hours to be

Iago or Alceste, Phedre or Gloucester. In that short space of time

he makes them come to life and die on fifty square yards of boards.

Never has the absurd been so well illustrated or at such length.

What more revelatory epitome can be imagined than those

marvelous lives, those exceptional and total destinies unfolding for a few hours within a stage set? Off the stage, Sigismundo ceases to count. Two hours later he is seen dining out.

Then it is, perhaps, that life is a dream. But after Sigismundo

comes another. The hero suffering from uncertainty takes the place

of the man roaring for his revenge. By thus sweeping over

centuries and minds, by miming man as he can be and as he is, the

actor has much in common with that other absurd individual, the

traveler. Like him, he drains something and is constantly on the

move. He is a traveler in time and, for the best, the hunted traveler,

pursued by souls. If ever the ethics of quantity could find

sustenance, it is indeed on that strange stage. To what degree the

actor benefits from the characters is hard to say. But that is not the

important thing. It is merely a matter of knowing how far he

identifies himself with those irreplaceable lives. It often happens

that he carries them with him, that they somewhat overflow the

time and place in which they were born. They accompany the

actor, who cannot very readily separate himself from what he has

been. Occasionally when reaching for his glass he resumes

Hamlet’s gesture of raising his cup. No, the distance separating

him from the creatures into whom he infuses life is not so great. He

abundantly illustrates every month or every day that so suggestive

truth that there is no frontier between what a man wants to be and

what he is. Always concerned with better representing, he

demonstrates to what a degree appearing creates being. For that is

his art—to simulate absolutely, to project himself as deeply as

possible into lives that are not his own. At the end of his effort his

vocation becomes clear: to apply himself wholeheartedly to being

nothing or to being several. The narrower the limits allotted him

for creating his character, the more necessary his talent. He will die

in three hours under the mask he has assumed today. Within three

hours he must experience and express a whole exceptional life.

That is called losing oneself to find oneself. In those three hours he

travels the whole course of the dead-end path that the man in the

audience takes a lifetime to cover.

<br>

A mime of the ephemeral, the actor trains and perfects himself

only in appearances. The theatrical convention is that the heart

expresses itself and communicates itself only through gestures and

in the body—or through the voice, which is as much of the soul as

of the body. The rule of that art insists that everything be

magnified and translated into flesh. If it were essential on the stage

to love as people really love, to employ that irreplaceable voice of

the heart, to look as people contemplate in life, our speech would

be in code. But here silences must make themselves heard. Love

speaks up louder, and immobility itself becomes spectacular. The

body is king, Not everyone can be “theatrical,” and this unjustly

maligned word covers a whole aesthetic and a whole ethic. Half a

man’s life is spent in implying, in turning away, and in keeping

silent. Here the actor is the intruder. He breaks the spell chaining

that soul, and at last the passions can rush onto their stage. They

speak in every gesture; they live only through shouts and cries.

Thus the actor creates his characters for display. He outlines or

sculptures them and slips into their imaginary form, transfusing his

blood into their phantoms. I am of course speaking of great drama,

the kind that gives the actor an opportunity to fulfill his wholly

physical fate. Take Shakespeare, for instance. In that impulsive

drama the physical passions lead the dance. They explain

everything. Without them all would collapse. Never would King

Lear keep the appointment set by madness without the brutal

gesture that exiles Cordelia and condemns Edgar. It is just that the

unfolding of that tragedy should thenceforth be dominated by

madness. Souls are given over to the demons and their saraband.

No fewer than four madmen: one by trade, another by intention,

and the last two through suffering—four disordered bodies, four

unutterable aspects of a single condition.

The very scale of the human body is inadequate. The mask and

the buskin, the make-up that reduces and accentuates the face in its

essential elements, the costume that exaggerates and simplifies—

that universe sacrifices everything to appearance and is made

solely for the eye. Through an absurd miracle, it is the body that

also brings knowledge. I should never really understand Iago

unless I played his part. It is not enough to hear him, for I grasp

him only at the moment when I see him. Of the absurd character

the actor consequently has the monotony, that single, oppressive

silhouette, simultaneously strange and familiar, that he carries

about from hero to hero. There, too, the great dramatic work

contributes to this unity of tone.[17] This is where the actor

contradicts himself: the same and yet so various, so many souls

summed up in a single body. Yet it is the absurd contradiction

itself, that individual who wants to achieve everything and live

everything, that useless attempt, that ineffectual persistence. What

always contradicts itself nevertheless joins in him. He is at that

point where body and mind converge, where the mind, tired of its

defeats, turns toward its most faithful ally. “And blest are those,”

says Hamlet, “whose blood and judgment are so well commingled

that they are not a pipe for fortune’s finger to sound what stop she

please.”

How could the Church have failed to condemn such a practice

on the part of the actor? She repudiated in that art the heretical

multiplication of souls, the emotional debauch, the scandalous

presumption of a mind that objects to living but one life and hurls

itself into all forms of excess. She proscribed in them that

preference for the present and that triumph of Proteus which are

the negation of everything she teaches. Eternity is not a game. A

mind foolish enough to prefer a comedy to eternity has lost its

salvation. Between

“everywhere” and

“forever” there is no

compromise. Whence that much maligned profession can give rise

to a tremendous spiritual conflict. “What matters,” said Nietzsche,

“is not eternal life but eternal vivacity.” All drama is, in fact, in

this choice. Celimene against Elianthe, the whole subject in the

absurd consequence of a nature carried to its extreme, and the

verse itself, the “bad verse,” barely accented like the monotony of

the character’s nature.

Adrienne Lecouvreur on her deathbed was willing to confess

and receive communion, but refused to abjure her profession. She

thereby lost the benefit of the confession. Did this not amount, in

effect, to choosing her absorbing passion in preference to God?

And that woman in the death throes refusing in tears to repudiate

what she called her art gave evidence of a greatness that she never

achieved behind the footlights. This was her finest role and the

hardest one to play. Choosing between heaven and a ridiculous

fidelity, preferring oneself to eternity or losing oneself in God is

the age-old tragedy in which each must play his part.

The actors of the era knew they were excommunicated.

Entering the profession amounted to choosing Hell. And the

Church discerned in them her worst enemies. A few men of letters

protest: “What! Refuse the last rites to Moliere!” But that was just,

and especially in one who died onstage and finished under the

actor’s make-up a life entirely devoted to dispersion. In his case

genius is invoked, which excuses everything. But genius excuses

nothing, just because it refuses to do so.

The actor knew at that time what punishment was in store for

him. But what significance could such vague threats have

compared to the final punishment that life itself was reserving for

him? This was the one that he felt in advance and accepted wholly.

To the actor as to the absurd man, a premature death is irreparable.

Nothing can make up for the sum of faces and centuries he would

otherwise have traversed. But in any case, one has to die. For the

actor is doubtless everywhere, but time sweeps him along, too, and

makes its impression with him.

It requires but a little imagination to feel what an actor’s fate

means. It is in time that he makes up and enumerates his

characters. It is in time likewise that he learns to dominate them.

The greater number of different lives he has lived, the more aloof

he can be from them. The time comes when he must die to the

stage and for the world. What he has lived faces him. He sees

clearly. He feels the harrowing and irreplaceable quality of that

adventure. He knows and can now die. There are homes for aged

actors.

Conquest

“No,” says the conqueror, “don’t assume that because I love

action I have had to forget how to think. On the contrary I can

throughly define what I believe. For I believe it firmly and I see it

surely and clearly. Beware of those who say: ‘I know this too well

to be able to express it.’ For if they cannot do so, this is because

they don’t know it or because out of laziness they stopped at the

outer crust.

“I have not many opinions. At the end of a life man notices that

he has spent years becoming sure of a single truth. But a single

truth, if it is obvious, is enough to guide an existence. As for me, I

decidedly have something to say about the individual. One must

speak of him bluntly and, if need be, with the appropriate

contempt.

“A man is more a man through the things he keeps to himself

than through those he says. There are many that I shall keep to

myself. But I firmly believe that all those who have judged the

individual have done so with much less experience than we on

which to base their judgment. The intelligence, the stirring

intelligence perhaps foresaw what it was essential to note. But the

era, its ruins, and its blood overwhelm us with facts. It was

possible for ancient nations, and even for more recent ones down

to our machine age, to weigh one against the other the virtues of

society and of the individual, to try to find out which was to serve

the other. To begin with, that was possible by virtue of that

stubborn aberration in man’s heart according to which human

beings were created to serve or be served. In the second place, it

was possible because neither society nor the individual had yet

revealed all their ability.

“I have seen bright minds express astonishment at the

masterpieces of Dutch painters born at the height of the bloody

wars in Flanders, be amazed by the prayers of Silesian mystics

brought up during the frightful Thirty Years’ War. Eternal values

survive secular turmoils before their astonished eyes. But there has

been progress since. The painters of today are deprived of such

serenity. Even if they have basically the heart the creator needs—I

mean the closed heart—it is of no use; for everyone, including the

saint himself, is mobilized. This is perhaps what I have felt most

deeply. At every form that miscarries in the trenches, at every

outline, metaphor, or prayer crushed under steel, the eternal loses a

round. Conscious that I cannot stand aloof from my time, I have

decided to be an integral part of it. This is why I esteem the

individual only because he strikes me as ridiculous and humiliated.

Knowing that there are no victorious causes, I have a liking for lost

causes: they require an uncontaminated soul, equal to its defeat as

to its temporary victories. For anyone who feels bound up with this

world’s fate, the clash of civilizations has something agonizing

about it. I have made that anguish mine at the same time that I

wanted to join in. Between history and the eternal I have chosen

history because I like certainties. Of it, at least, I am certain, and

how can I deny this force crushing me?

“There always comes a time when one must choose between

contemplation and action. This is called becoming a man. Such

wrenches are dreadful. But for a proud heart there can be no

compromise. There is God or time, that cross or this sword. This

world has a higher meaning that transcends its worries, or nothing

is true but those worries. One must live with time and die with it,

or else elude it for a greater life. I know that one can compromise

and live in the world while believing in the eternal. That is called

accepting. But I loathe this term and want all or nothing. If I

choose action, don’t think that contemplation is like an unknown

country to me. But it cannot give me everything, and, deprived of

the eternal, I want to ally myself with time. I do not want to put

down to my account either nostalgia or bitterness, and I merely

want to see clearly. I tell you, tomorrow you will be mobilized. For

you and for me that is a liberation. The individual can do nothing

and yet he can do everything. In that wonderful unattached state

you understand why I exalt and crush him at one and the same

time. It is the world that pulverizes him and I who liberate him. I

provide him with all his rights.

“Conquerors know that action is in itself useless. There is but

one useful action, that of remaking man and the earth. I shall never

remake men. But one must do ’as if.’ For the path of struggle leads

me to the flesh. Even humiliated, the flesh is my only certainty. I

can live only on it. The creature is my native land. This is why I

have chosen this absurd and ineffectual effort. This is why I am on

the side of the struggle. The epoch lends itself to this, as I have

said. Hitherto the greatness of a conqueror was geographical. It

was measured by the extent of the conquered territories. There is a

reason why the word has changed in meaning and has ceased to

signify the victorious general. The greatness has changed camp. It

lies in protest and the blind-alley sacrifice. There, too, it is not

through a preference for defeat. Victory would be desirable. But

there is but one victory, and it is eternal. That is the one I shall

never have. That is where I stumble and cling. A revolution is

always accomplished against the gods, beginning with the

revolution of Prometheus, the first of modern conquerors. It is

man’s demands made against his fate; the demands of the poor are

but a pretext. Yet I can seize that spirit only in its historical act,

and that is where I make contact with it. Don’t assume, however,

that I take pleasure in it: opposite the essential contradiction, I

maintain my human contradiction. I establish my lucidity in the

midst of what negates it. I exalt man be-fore what crushes him, and

my freedom, my revolt, and my passion come together then in that

tension, that lucidity, and that vast repetition.

“Yes, man is his own end. And he is his only end. If he aims to

be something, it is in this life. Now I know it only too well.

Conquerors sometimes talk of vanquishing and overcoming. But it

is always ‘overcoming oneself’ that they mean. You are well aware

of what that means. Every man has felt himself to be the equal of a

god at certain moments. At least, this is the way it is expressed.

But this comes from the fact that in a flash he felt the amazing

grandeur of the human mind. The conquerors are merely those

among men who are conscious enough of their strength to be sure

of living constantly on those heights and fully aware of that

grandeur. It is a question of arithmetic, of more or less. The

conquerors are capable of the more. But they are capable of no

more than man himself when he wants. This is why they never

leave the human crucible, plunging into the seething soul of

revolutions.

“There they find the creature mutilated, but they also encounter

there the only values they like and admire, man and his silence.

This is both their destitution and their wealth. There is but one

luxury for them—that of human relations. How can one fail to

realize that in this vulnerable universe everything that is human

and solely human assumes a more vivid meaning? Taut faces,

threatened fraternity, such strong and chaste friendship among

men—these are the true riches because they are transitory. In their

midst the mind is most aware of its powers and limitations. That is

to say, its efficacity. Some have spoken of genius. But genius is

easy to say; I prefer the intelligence. It must be said that it can be

magnificent then. It lights up this desert and dominates it. It knows

its obligations and illustrates them. It will die at the same time as

this body. But knowing this constitutes its freedom.

“We are not ignorant of the fact that all churches are against us.

A heart so keyed up eludes the eternal, and all churches, divine or

political, lay claim to the eternal. Happiness and courage,

retribution or justice are secondary ends for them. It is a doctrine

they bring, and one must subscribe to it. But I have no concern

with ideas or with the eternal. The truths that come within my

scope can be touched with the hand. I cannot separate from them.

This is why you cannot base anything on me: nothing of the

conqueror lasts, not even his doctrines.

“At the end of all that, despite everything, is death. We know

also that it ends everything. This is why those cemeteries all over

Europe, which obsess some among us, are hideous. People beautify

only what they love, and death repels us and tires our patience. It,

too, is to be conquered. The last Carrara, a prisoner in Padua

emptied by the plague and besieged by the Venetians, ran

screaming through the halls of his deserted palace: he was calling

on the devil and asking him for death. This was a way of

overcoming it. And it is likewise a mark of courage characteristic

of the Occident to have made so ugly the places where death thinks

itself honored. In the rebel s universe, death exalts injustice. It is

the supreme abuse.

“Others, without compromising either, have chosen the eternal

and denounced the illusion of this world. Their cemeteries smile

amid numerous flowers and birds. That suits the conqueror and

gives him a clear image of what he has rejected. He has chosen, on

the contrary, the black iron fence or the potter’s field. The best

among the men of God occasionally are seized with fright mingled

with consideration and pity for minds that can live with such an

image of their death. Yet those minds derive their strength and

justification from this. Our fate stands before us and we provoke

him. Less out of pride than out of awareness of our ineffectual

condition. We, too, sometimes feel pity for ourselves. It is the only

compassion that seems acceptable to us: a feeling that perhaps you

hardly understand and that seems to you scarcely virile. Yet the

most daring among us are the ones who feel it. But we call the

lucid ones virile and we do not want a strength that is apart from

lucidity.”

<br>

Let me repeat that these images do not propose moral codes

and involve no judgments: they are sketches. They merely

represent a style of life. The lover, the actor, or the adventurer

plays the absurd. But equally well, if he wishes, the chaste man,

the civil servant, or the president of the Republic. It is enough to

know and to mask nothing. In Italian museums are sometimes

found little painted screens that the priest used to hold in front of

the face of condemned men to hide the scaffold from them. The

leap in all its forms, rushing into the divine or the eternal,

surrendering to the illusions of the everyday or of the idea—all

these screens hide the absurd. But there are civil servants without

screens, and they are the ones of whom I mean to speak. I have

chosen the most extreme ones. At this level the absurd gives them

a royal power. It is true that those princes are without a kingdom.

But they have this advantage over others: they know that all

royalties are illusory. They know that is their whole nobility, and it

is useless to speak in relation to them of hidden misfortune or the

ashes of disillusion. Being deprived of hope is not despairing. The

flames of earth are surely worth celestial perfumes. Neither I nor

anyone can judge them here. They are not striving to be better;

they are attempting to be consistent. If the term “wise man” can be

applied to the man who lives on what he has without speculating

on what he has not, then they are wise men. One of them, a

conqueror but in the realm of mind, a Don Juan but of knowledge,

an actor but of the intelligence, knows this better than anyone:

“You nowise deserve a privilege on earth and in heaven for having

brought to perfection your dear little meek sheep; you nonetheless

continue to be at best a ridiculous dear little sheep with horns and

nothing more—even supposing that you do not burst with vanity

and do not create a scandal by posing as a judge.”

In any case, it was essential to restore to the absurd reasoning

more cordial examples. The imagination can add many others,

inseparable from time and exile, who likewise know how to live in

harmony with a universe without future and without weakness.

This absurd, godless world is, then, peopled with men who think

clearly and have ceased to hope. And I have not yet spoken of the

most absurd character, who is the creator.

Absurd Creation

Philosophy and Fiction

All those lives maintained in the rarefied air of the absurd

could not persevere without some profound and constant thought

to infuse its strength into them. Right here, it can be only a strange

feeling of fidelity. Conscious men have been seen to fulfill their

task amid the most stupid of wars without considering themselves

in contradiction. This is because it was essential to elude nothing.

There is thus a metaphysical honor in enduring the world’s

absurdity. Conquest or play-acting, multiple loves, absurd revolt

are tributes that man pays to his dignity in a campaign in which he

is defeated in advance.

It is merely a matter of being faithful to the rule of the battle.

That thought may suffice to sustain a mind; it has supported and

still supports whole civilizations. War cannot be negated. One

must live it or die of it. So it is with the absurd: it is a question of

breathing with it, of recognizing its lessons and recovering their

flesh. In this regard the absurd joy par excellence is creation. “Art

and nothing but art,” said Nietzsche; “we have art in order not to

die of the truth.”

In the experience that I am attempting to describe and to stress

on several modes, it is certain that a new torment arises wherever

another dies. The childish chasing after forgetfulness, the appeal of

satisfaction are now devoid of echo. But the constant tension that

keeps man face to face with the world, the ordered delirium that

urges him to be receptive to everything leave him another fever. In

this universe the work of art is then the sole chance of keeping his

consciousness and of fixing its adventures. Creating is living

doubly. The groping, anxious quest of a Proust, his meticulous

collecting of flowers, of wallpapers, and of anxieties, signifies

nothing else. At the same time, it has no more significance than the

continual and imperceptible creation in which the actor, the

conqueror, and all absurd men indulge every day of their lives. All

try their hands at miming, at repeating, and at recreating the reality

that is theirs. We always end up by having the appearance of our

truths. All existence for a man turned away from the eternal is but

a vast mime under the mask of the absurd. Creation is the great

mime.

Such men know to begin with, and then their whole effort is to

examine, to enlarge, and to enrich the ephemeral island on which

they have just landed. But first they must know. For the absurd

discovery coincides with a pause in which future passions are

prepared and justified. Even men without a gospel have their

Mount of Olives. And one must not fall asleep on theirs either. For

the absurd man it is not a matter of explaining and solving, but of

experiencing and describing. Everything begins with lucid

indifference.

Describing—that is the last ambition of an absurd thought.

Science likewise, having reached the end of its paradoxes, ceases

to propound and stops to contemplate and sketch the ever virgin

landscape of phenomena. The heart learns thus that the emotion

delighting us when we see the world’s aspects comes to us not

from its depth but from their diversity. Explanation is useless, but

the sensation remains and, with it, the constant attractions of a

universe inexhaustible in quantity. The place of the work of art can

be understood at this point.

It marks both the death of an experience and its multiplication.

It is a sort of monotonous and passionate repetition of the themes

already orchestrated by the world: the body, inexhaustible image

on the pediment of temples, forms or colors, number or grief. It is

therefore not indifferent, as a conclusion, to encounter once again

the principal themes of this essay in the wonderful and childish

world of the creator. It would be wrong to see a symbol in it and to

think that the work of art can be considered at last as a refuge for

the absurd. It is itself an absurd phenomenon, and we are

concerned merely with its description. It does not offer an escape

for the intellectual ailment. Rather, it is one of the symptoms of

that ailment which reflects it throughout a man’s whole thought.

But for the first time it makes the mind get outside of itself and

places it in opposition to others, not for it to get lost but to show it

clearly the blind path that all have entered upon. In the time of the

absurd reasoning, creation follows indifference and discovery. It

marks the point from which absurd passions spring and where the

reasoning stops. Its place in this essay is justified in this way.

It will suffice to bring to light a few themes common to the

creator and the thinker in order to find in the work of art all the

contradictions of thought involved in the absurd. Indeed, it is not

so much identical conclusions that prove minds to be related as the

contradictions that are common to them. So it is with thought and

creation. I hardly need to say that the same anguish urges man to

these two attitudes. This is where they coincide in the beginning.

But among all the thoughts that start from the absurd, I have seen

that very few remain within it. And through their deviations or

infidelities I have best been able to measure what belonged to the

absurd. Similarly I must wonder: is an absurd work of art possible?

<br>

It would be impossible to insist too much on the arbitrary

nature of the former opposition between art and philosophy. If you

insist on taking it in too limited a sense, it is certainly false. If you

mean merely that these two disciplines each have their peculiar

climate, that is probably true but remains vague. The only

acceptable argument used to lie in the contradiction brought up

between the philosopher enclosed within his system and the artist

placed before his work. But this was pertinent for a certain form of

art and of philosophy which we consider secondary here. The idea

of an art detached from its creator is not only outmoded; it is false.

In opposition to the artist, it is pointed out that no philosopher ever

created several systems. But that is true in so far, indeed, as no

artist ever expressed more than one thing under different aspects.

The instantaneous perfection of art, the necessity for its renewal—

this is true only through a preconceived notion. For the work of art

likewise is a construction and everyone knows how monotonous

the great creators can be. For the same reason as the thinker, the

artist commits himself and becomes himself in his work. That

osmosis raises the most important of aesthetic problems.

Moreover, to anyone who is convinced of the mind’s singleness of

purpose, nothing is more futile than these distinctions based on

methods and objects. There are no frontiers between the disciplines

that man sets himself for understanding and loving. They interlock,

and the same anxiety merges them.

It is necessary to state this to begin with. For an absurd work of

art to be possible, thought in its most lucid form must be involved

in it. But at the same time thought must not be apparent except as

the regulating intelligence. This paradox can be explained

according to the absurd. The work of art is born of the

intelligence’s refusal to reason the concrete. It marks the triumph

of the carnal. It is lucid thought that provokes it, but in that very

act that thought repudiates itself. It will not yield to the temptation

of adding to what is described a deeper meaning that it knows to be

illegitimate. The work of art embodies a drama of the intelligence,

but it proves this only indirectly. The absurd work requires an artist

conscious of these limitations and an art in which the concrete

signifies nothing more than itself. It cannot be the end, the

meaning, and the consolation of a life. Creating or not creating

changes nothing. The absurd creator does not prize his work. He

could repudiate it. He does sometimes repudiate it. An Abyssinia

suffices for this, as in the case of Rimbaud.

At the same time a rule of aesthetics can be seen in this. The

true work of art is always on the human scale. It is essentially the

one that says “less.” There is a certain relationship between the

global experience of the artist and the work that reflects that

experience, between Wilhelm Meister and Goethe’s maturity. That

relationship is bad when the work aims to give the whole

experience in the lace-paper of an explanatory literature. That

relationship is good when the work is but a piece cut out of

experience, a facet of the diamond in which the inner luster is

epitomized without being limited. In the first case there is

overloading and pretension to the eternal. In the second, a fecund

work because of a whole implied experience, the wealth of which

is suspected. The problem for the absurd artist is to acquire this

savoir-vivre which transcends savoir-faire. And in the end, the

great artist under this climate is, above all, a great living being, it

being understood that living in this case is just as much

experiencing as reflecting. The work then embodies an intellectual

drama. The absurd work illustrates thought’s renouncing of its

prestige and its resignation to being no more than the intelligence

that works up appearances and covers with images what has no

reason. If the world were clear, art would not exist.

I am not speaking here of the arts of form or color in which

description alone prevails in its splendid modesty.[18] Expression

begins where thought ends. Those adolescents with empty

eyesockets who people temples and museums—their philosophy

has been expressed in gestures. For an absurd man it is more

educative than all libraries. Under another aspect the same is true

for music. If any art is devoid of lessons, it is certainly music. It is

too closely related to mathematics not to have borrowed their

gratuitousness. That game the mind plays with itself according to

set and measured laws takes place in the sonorous compass that

belongs to us and beyond which the vibrations nevertheless meet in

an inhuman universe. There is no purer sensation. These examples

are too easy. The absurd man recognizes as his own these

harmonies and these forms.

But I should like to speak here of a work in which the

temptation to explain remains greatest, in which illusion offers

itself automatically, in which conclusion is almost inevitable. I

mean fictional creation. I propose to inquire whether or not the

absurd can hold its own there.

<br>

To think is first of all to create a world (or to limit one’s own

world, which comes to the same thing). It is starting out from the

basic disagreement that separates man from his experience in order

to find a common ground according to one’s nostalgia, a universe

hedged with reasons or lighted up with analogies but which, in any

case, gives an opportunity to rescind the unbearable divorce. The

philosopher, even if he is Kant, is a creator. He has his characters,

his symbols, and his secret action. He has his plot endings. On the

contrary, the lead taken by the novel over poetry and the essay

merely represents, despite appearances, a greater intellectualization of the art. Let there be no mistake about it; I am speaking of

the greatest. The fecundity and the importance of a literary form

are often measured by the trash it contains. The number of bad

novels must not make us forget the value of the best. These,

indeed, carry with them their universe. The novel has its logic, its

reasonings, its intuition, and its postulates. It also has its

requirements of clarity.[19]

The classical opposition of which I was speaking above is even

less justified in this particular case. It held in the time when it was

easy to separate philosophy from its authors. Today when thought

has ceased to lay claim to the universal, when its best history

would be that of its repentances, we know that the system, when it

is worth while, cannot be separated from its author. The Ethics

itself, in one of its aspects, is but a long and reasoned personal

confession. Abstract thought at last returns to its prop of flesh.

And, likewise, the fictional activities of the body and of the

passions are regulated a little more according to the requirements

of a vision of the world. The writer has given up telling “stories”

and creates his universe. The great novelists are philosophical

novelists—that is, the contrary of thesis-writers. For instance,

Balzac, Sade, Melville, Stendhal, Dostoevsky, Proust, Malraux,

Kafka, to cite but a few.

But in fact the preference they have shown for writing in

images rather than in reasoned arguments is revelatory of a certain

thought that is common to them all, convinced of the uselessness

of any principle of explanation and sure of the educative message

of perceptible appearance. They consider the work of art both as an

end and a beginning. It is the outcome of an often unexpressed

philosophy, its illustration and its consummation. But it is

complete only through the implications of that philosophy. It

justifies at last that variant of an old theme that a little thought

estranges from life whereas much thought reconciles to life.

Incapable of refining the real, thought pauses to mimic it. The

novel in question is the instrument of that simultaneously relative

and inexhaustible knowledge, so like that of love. Of love, fictional

creation has the initial wonder and the fecund rumination.

<br>

These at least are the charms I see in it at the outset. But I saw

them likewise in those princes of humiliated thought whose

suicides I was later able to witness.

What interests me, indeed, is knowing and describing the force

that leads them back toward the common path of illusion. The

same method will consequently help me here. The fact of having

already utilized it will allow me to shorten my argument and to

sum it up without delay in a particular example. I want to know

whether, accepting a life without appeal, one can also agree to

work and create without appeal and what is the way leading to

these liberties. I want to liberate my universe of its phantoms and

to people it solely with flesh-and-blood truths whose presence I

cannot deny. I can perform absurd work, choose the creative

attitude rather than another. But an absurd attitude, if it is to remain

so, must remain aware of its gratuitousness. So it is with the work

of art. If the commandments of the absurd are not respected, if the

work does not illustrate divorce and revolt, if it sacrifices to

illusions and arouses hope, it ceases to be gratuitous. I can no

longer detach myself from it. My life may find a meaning in it, but

that is trifling. It ceases to be that exercise in detachment and

passion which crowns the splendor and futility of a man’s life.

In the creation in which the temptation to explain is the

strongest, can one overcome that temptation? In the fictional world

in which awareness of the real world is keenest, can I remain

faithful to the absurd without sacrificing to the desire to judge? So

many questions to be taken into consideration in a last effort. It

must be already clear what they signify. They are the last scruples

of an awareness that fears to forsake its initial and difficult lesson

in favor of a final illusion. What holds for creation, looked upon as

one of the possible attitudes for the man conscious of the absurd,

holds for all the styles of life open to him. The conqueror or the

actor, the creator or Don Juan may forget that their exercise in

living could not do without awareness of its mad character. One

becomes accustomed so quickly. A man wants to earn money in

order to be happy, and his whole effort and the best of a life are

devoted to the earning of that money. Happiness is forgotten; the

means are taken for the end. Likewise, the whole effort of this

conqueror will be diverted to ambition, which was but a way

toward a greater life. Don Juan in turn will likewise yield to his

fate, be satisfied with that existence whose nobility is of value only

through revolt. For one it is awareness and for the other, revolt; in

both cases the absurd has disappeared. There is so much stubborn

hope in the human heart. The most destitute men often end up by

accepting illusion. That approval prompted by the need for peace

inwardly parallels the existential consent. There are thus gods of

light and idols of mud. But it is essential to find the middle path

leading to the faces of man.

So far, the failures of the absurd exigence have best informed

us as to what it is. In the same way, if we are to be informed, it will

suffice to notice that fictional creation can present the same

ambiguity as certain philosophies. Hence I can choose as

illustration a work comprising everything that denotes awareness

of the absurd, having a clear starting-point and a lucid climate. Its

consequences will enlighten us. If the absurd is not respected in it,

we shall know by what expedient illusion enters in. A particular

example, a theme, a creator’s fidelity will suffice, then. This

involves the same analysis that has already been made at greater

length.

I shall examine a favorite theme of Dostoevsky. I might just as

well have studied other works.[20] But in this work the problem is

treated directly, in the sense of nobility and emotion, as for the

existential philosophies already discussed. This parallelism serves

my purpose.

Kirilov

All of Dostoevsky’s heroes question themselves as to the

meaning of life. In this they are modern: they do not fear ridicule.

What distinguishes modern sensibility from classical sensibility is

that the latter thrives on moral problems and the former on

metaphysical problems. In Dostoevsky’s novels the question is

propounded with such intensity that it can only invite extreme

solutions. Existence is illusory or it is eternal. If Dostoevsky were

satisfied with this inquiry, he would be a philosopher. But he

illustrates the consequences that such intellectual pastimes may

have in a man’s life, and in this regard he is an artist. Among those

consequences, his attention is arrested particularly by the last one,

which he himself calls logical suicide in his Diary of a Writer. In

the installments for December

1876, indeed, he imagines the

reasoning of “logical suicide.” Convinced that human existence is

an utter absurdity for anyone without faith in immortality, the

desperate man comes to the following conclusions:

“Since in reply to my questions about happiness, I am told,

through the intermediary of my consciousness, that I cannot be

happy except in harmony with the great all, which I cannot

conceive and shall never be in a position to conceive, it is evident

...”

“Since, finally, in this connection, I assume both the role of the

plaintiff and that of the defendant, of the accused and of the judge,

and since I consider this comedy perpetrated by nature altogether

stupid, and since I even deem it humiliating for me to deign to play

it ...”

“In my indisputable capacity of plaintiff and defendant, of

judge and accused, I condemn that nature which, with such

impudent nerve, brought me into being in order to suffer—I

condemn it to be annihilated with me.”

There remains a little humor in that position. This suicide kills

himself because, on the metaphysical plane, he is vexed. In a

certain sense he is taking his revenge. This is his way of proving

that he “will not be had.” It is known, however, that the same

theme is embodied, but with the most wonderful generality, in

Kirilov of The Possessed, likewise an advocate of logical suicide.

Kirilov the engineer declares somewhere that he wants to take his

own life because it “is his idea.” Obviously the word must be taken

in its proper sense. It is for an idea, a thought, that he is getting

ready for death. This is the superior suicide. Progressively, in a

series of scenes in which Kirilov’s mask is gradually illuminated,

the fatal thought driving him is revealed to us. The engineer, in

fact, goes back to the arguments of the Diary. He feels that God is

necessary and that he must exist. But he knows that he does not

and cannot exist. “Why do you not realize,” he exclaims, “that this

is sufficient reason for killing oneself?” That attitude involves

likewise for him some of the absurd consequences. Through

indifference he accepts letting his suicide be used to the advantage

of a cause he despises. “I decided last night that I didn’t care.” And

finally he prepares his deed with a mixed feeling of revolt and

freedom. “I shall kill myself in order to assert my insubordination,

my new and dreadful liberty.” It is no longer a question of revenge,

but of revolt. Kirilov is consequently an absurd character—yet

with this essential reservation: he kills himself. But he himself

explains this contradiction, and in such a way that at the same time

he reveals the absurd secret in all its purity. In truth, he adds to his

fatal logic an extraordinary ambition which gives the character its

full perspective: he wants to kill himself to become god.

The reasoning is classic in its clarity. If God does not exist,

Kirilov is god. If God does not exist, Kirilov must kill himself.

Kirilov must therefore kill himself to become god. That logic is

absurd, but it is what is needed. The interesting thing, however, is

to give a meaning to that divinity brought to earth. That amounts to

clarifying the premise: “If God does not exist, I am god,” which

still remains rather obscure. It is important to note at the outset that

the man who flaunts that mad claim is indeed of this world. He

performs his gymnastics every morning to preserve his health. He

is stirred by the joy of Chatov recovering his wife. On a sheet of

paper to be found after his death he wants to draw a face sticking

out his tongue at “them.” He is childish and irascible, passionate,

methodical, and sensitive. Of the superman he has nothing but the

logic and the obsession, whereas of man he has the whole

catalogue. Yet it is he who speaks calmly of his divinity. He is not

mad, or else Dostoevsky is. Consequently it is not a

megalomaniac’s illusion that excites him. And taking the words in

their specific sense would, in this instance, be ridiculous.

Kirilov himself helps us to understand. In reply to a question

from Stavrogin, he makes clear that he is not talking of a god-man.

It might be thought that this springs from concern to distinguish

himself from Christ. But in reality it is a matter of annexing Christ.

Kirilov in fact fancies for a moment that Jesus at his death did not

find himself in Paradise. He found out then that his torture had

been useless.

“The laws of nature,” says the engineer,

“made

Christ live in the midst of falsehood and die for a falsehood.”

Solely in this sense Jesus indeed personifies the whole human

drama. He is the complete man, being the one who realized the

most absurd condition. He is not the God-man but the man-god.

And, like him, each of us can be crucified and victimized—and is

to a certain degree.

The divinity in question is therefore altogether terrestrial. “For

three years,” says Kirilov, “I sought the attribute of my divinity

and I have found it. The attribute of my divinity is independence.”

Now can be seen the meaning of Kirilov’s premise: “If God does

not exist, I am god.” To become god is merely to be free on this

earth, not to serve an immortal being. Above all, of course, it is

drawing all the inferences from that painful independence. If God

exists, all depends on him and we can do nothing against his will.

If he does not exist, everything depends on us. For Kirilov, as for

Nietzsche, to kill God is to become god oneself; it is to realize on

this earth the eternal life of which the Gospel speaks.[21] But if this

metaphysical crime is enough for man’s fulfillment, why add

suicide? Why kill oneself and leave this world after having won

freedom? That is contradictory. Kirilov is well aware of this, for he

adds: “If you feel that, you are a tsar and, far from killing yourself,

you will live covered with glory.” But men in general do not know

it. They do not feel “that.” As in the time of Prometheus, they

entertain blind hopes.[22] They need to be shown the way and

cannot do without preaching. Consequently, Kirilov must kill

himself out of love for humanity. He must show his brothers a

royal and difficult path on which he will be the first. It is a

pedagogical suicide. Kirilov sacrifices himself, then. But if he is

crucified, he will not be victimized. He remains the man-god,

convinced of a death without future, imbued with evangelical

melancholy. “I,” he says, “am unhappy because I am obliged to

assert my freedom.”

But once he is dead and men are at last enlightened, this earth

will be peopled with tsars and lighted up with human glory.

Kirilov’s pistol shot will be the signal for the last revolution. Thus,

it is not despair that urges him to death, but love of his neighbor

for his own sake. Before terminating in blood an indescribable

spiritual adventure, Kirilov makes a remark as old as human

suffering: “All is well.”

This theme of suicide in Dostoevsky, then, is indeed an absurd

theme. Let us merely note before going on that Kirilov reappears in

other characters who themselves set in motion additional absurd

themes. Stavrogin and Ivan Karamazov try out the absurd truths in

practical life. They are the ones liberated by Kirilov’s death. They

try their skill at being tsars. Stavrogin leads an “ironic” life, and it

is well known in what regard. He arouses hatred around him. And

yet the key to the character is found in his farewell letter: “I have

not been able to detest anything.” He is a tsar in indifference. Ivan

is likewise by refusing to surrender the royal powers of the mind.

To those who, like his brother, prove by their lives that it is

essential to humiliate oneself in order to believe, he might reply

that the condition is shameful. His key word is: “Everything is

permitted,” with the appropriate shade of melancholy. Of course,

like Nietzsche, the most famous of God’s assassins, he ends in

madness. But this is a risk worth running, and, faced with such

tragic ends, the essential impulse of the absurd mind is to ask:

“What does that prove?”

Thus the novels, like the Diary, propound the absurd question.

They establish logic unto death, exaltation, “dreadful” freedom, the

glory of the tsars become human. All is well, everything is

permitted, and nothing is hateful—these are absurd judgments. But

what an amazing creation in which those creatures of fire and ice

seem so familiar to us. The passionate world of indifference that

rumbles in their hearts does not seem at all monstrous to us. We

recognize in it our everyday anxieties. And probably no one so

much as Dostoevsky has managed to give the absurd world such

familiar and tormenting charms.

Yet what is his conclusion? Two quotations will show the

complete metaphysical reversal that leads the writer to other

revelations. The argument of the one who commits logical suicide

having provoked protests from the critics, Dostoevsky in the

following installments of the Diary amplifies his position and

concludes thus:

“If faith in immortality is so necessary to the

human being (that without it he comes to the point of killing

himself), it must therefore be the normal state of humanity. Since

this is the case, the immortality of the human soul exists without

any doubt.” Then again in the last pages of his last novel, at the

conclusion of that gigantic combat with God, some children ask

Aliocha: “Karamazov, is it true what religion says, that we shall

rise from the dead, that we shall see one another again?” And

Aliocha answers: “Certainly, we shall see one another again, we

shall joyfully tell one another everything that has happened.’’

Thus Kirilov, Stavrogin, and Ivan are defeated. The Brothers

Karamazov replies to The Possessed. And it is indeed a conclusion.

Aliocha’s case is not ambiguous, as is that of Prince Muichkin. Ill,

the latter lives in a perpetual present, tinged with smiles and

indifference, and that blissful state might be the eternal life of

which the Prince speaks. On the contrary, Aliocha clearly says:

“We shall meet again.” There is no longer any question of suicide

and of madness. What is the use, for anyone who is sure of

immortality and of its joys? Man exchanges his divinity for

happiness. “We shall joyfully tell one another everything that has

happened.” Thus again Kirilov’s pistol rang out somewhere in

Russia, but the world continued to cherish its blind hopes. Men did

not understand “that.”

Consequently, it is not an absurd novelist addressing us, but an

existential novelist. Here, too, the leap is touching and gives its

nobility to the art that inspires it. It is a stirring acquiescence,

riddled with doubts, uncertain and ardent. Speaking of The

Brothers Karamazov, Dostoevsky wrote: “The chief question that

will be pursued throughout this book is the very one from which I

have suffered consciously or unconsciously all life long: the

existence of God.” It is hard to believe that a novel sufficed to

transform into joyful certainty the suffering of a lifetime. One

commentator[23] correctly pointed out that Dostoevsky is on Ivan’s

side and that the affirmative chapters took three months of effort

whereas what he called “the blasphemies” were written in three

weeks in a state of excitement. There is not one of his characters

who does not have that thorn in the flesh, who does not aggravate

it or seek a remedy for it in sensation or immortality.[24] In any

case, let us remain with this doubt. Here is a work which, in a

chiaroscuro more gripping than the light of day, permits us to seize

man’s struggle against his hopes. Having reached the end, the

creator makes his choice against his characters. That contradiction

thus allows us to make a distinction. It is not an absurd work that is

involved here, but a work that propounds the absurd problem.

Dostoevsky’s reply is humiliation,

“shame” according to

Stavrogin. An absurd work, on the contrary, does not provide a

reply; that is the whole difference. Let us note this carefully in

conclusion: what contradicts the absurd in that work is not its

Christian character, but rather its announcing a future life. It is

possible to be Christian and absurd. There are examples of

Christians who do not believe in a future life. In regard to the work

of art, it should therefore be possible to define one of the directions

of the absurd analysis that could have been anticipated in the

preceding pages. It leads to propounding “the absurdity of the

Gospel.” It throws light upon this idea, fertile in repercussions, that

convictions do not prevent incredulity. On the contrary, it is easy

to see that the author of The Possessed, familiar with these paths,

in conclusion took a quite different way. The surprising reply of

the creator to his characters, of Do-stoevsky to Kirilov, can indeed

be summed up thus: existence is illusory and it is eternal.

Ephemeral Creation

At this point I perceive, therefore, that hope cannot be eluded

forever and that it can beset even those who wanted to be free of it.

This is the interest I find in the works discussed up to this point. I

could, at least in the realm of creation, list some truly absurd

works.[25] But everything must have a beginning. The object of this

quest is a certain fidelity. The Church has been so harsh with

heretics only because she deemed that there is no worse enemy

than a child who has gone astray. But the record of Gnostic

effronteries and the persistence of Manichean currents have

contributed more to the construction of orthodox dogma than all

the prayers. With due allowance, the same is true of the absurd.

One recognizes one’s course by discovering the paths that stray

from it. At the very conclusion of the absurd reasoning, in one of

the attitudes dictated by its logic, it is not a matter of indifference

to find hope coming back in under one of its most touching guises.

That shows the difficulty of the absurd ascesis. Above all, it shows

the necessity of unfailing alertness and thus confirms the general

plan of this essay.

But if it is still too early to list absurd works, at least a

conclusion can be reached as to the creative attitude, one of those

which can complete absurd existence. Art can never be so well

served as by a negative thought. Its dark and humiliated

proceedings are as necessary to the understanding of a great work

as black is to white. To work and create “for nothing,” to sculpture

in clay, to know that one’s creation has no future, to see one’s

work destroyed in a day while being aware that fundamentally this

has no more importance than building for centuries—this is the

difficult wisdom that absurd thought sanctions. Performing these

two tasks simultaneously, negating on the one hand and

magnifying on the other, is the way open to the absurd creator. He

must give the void its colors.

This leads to a special conception of the work of art. Too often

the work of a creator is looked upon as a series of isolated

testimonies. Thus, artist and man of letters are confused. A

profound thought is in a constant state of becoming; it adopts the

experience of a life and assumes its shape, likewise, a man’s sole

creation is strengthened in its successive and multiple aspects: his

works. One after another, they complement one an-other, correct or

overtake one another, contradict one another too. If something

brings creation to an end, it is not the victorious and illusory cry of

the blinded artist: “I have said everything,” but the death of the

creator which closes his experience and the book of his genius.

That effort, that superhuman consciousness are not necessarily

apparent to the reader. There is no mystery in human creation. Will

performs this miracle. But at least there is no true creation without

a secret. To be sure, a succession of works can be but a series of

approximations of the same thought. But it is possible to conceive

of another type of creator proceeding by juxtaposition. Their works

may seem to be devoid of interrelations. To a certain degree, they

are contradictory.

But viewed all together, they resume their natural grouping.

From death, for instance, they derive their definitive significance.

They receive their most obvious light from the very life of their

author. At the moment of death, the succession of his works is but

a collection of failures. But if those failures all have the same

resonance, the creator has managed to repeat the image of his own

condition, to make the air echo with the sterile secret he possesses.

The effort to dominate is considerable here. But human

intelligence is up to much more. It will merely indicate clearly the

voluntary aspect of creation. Elsewhere I have brought out the fact

that human will had no other purpose than to maintain awareness.

But that could not do without discipline. Of all the schools of

patience and lucidity, creation is the most effective. It is also the

staggering evidence of man’s sole dignity: the dogged revolt

against his condition, perseverance in an effort considered sterile.

It calls for a daily effort, self-mastery, a precise estimate of the

limits of truth, measure, and strength. It constitutes an ascesis. All

that “for nothing,” in order to repeat and mark time. But perhaps

the great work of art has less importance in itself than in the ordeal

it demands of a man and the opportunity it provides him of

overcoming his phantoms and approaching a little closer to his

naked reality.

Let there be no mistake in aesthetics. It is not patient inquiry,

the unceasing, sterile illustration of a thesis that I am calling for

here. Quite the contrary, if I have made myself clearly understood.

The thesis-novel, the work that proves, the most hateful of all, is

the one that most often is inspired by a smug thought. You

demonstrate the truth you feel sure of possessing. But those are

ideas one launches, and ideas are the contrary of thought. Those

creators are philosophers, ashamed of themselves. Those I am

speaking of or whom I imagine are, on the contrary, lucid thinkers.

At a certain point where thought turns back on itself, they raise up

the images of their works like the obvious symbols of a limited,

mortal, and rebellious thought.

They perhaps prove something. But those proofs are ones that

the novelists provide for themselves rather than for the world in

general. The essential is that the novelists should triumph in the

concrete and that this constitute their nobility. This wholly carnal

triumph has been prepared for them by a thought in which abstract

powers have been humiliated. When they are completely so, at the

same time the flesh makes the creation shine forth in all its absurd

luster. After all, ironic philosophies produce passionate works.

Any thought that abandons unity glorifies diversity. And

diversity is the home of art. The only thought to liberate the mind

is that which leaves it alone, certain of its limits and of its

impending end. No doctrine tempts it. It awaits the ripening of the

work and of life. Detached from it, the work will once more give a

barely muffled voice to a soul Forever freed from hope. Or it will

give voice to nothing if the creator, tired of his activity, intends to

turn away. That is equivalent.

Thus, I ask of absurd creation what I required from thought—

revolt, freedom, and diversity. Later on it will manifest its utter

futility. In that daily effort in which intelligence and passion

mingle and delight each other, the absurd man discovers a

discipline that will make up the greatest of his strengths. The

required diligence, the doggedness and lucidity thus resemble the

conqueror’s attitude. To create is likewise to give a shape to one’s

fate. For all these characters, their work defines them at least as

much as it is defined by them. The actor taught us this: there is no

frontier between being and appearing.

Let me repeat. None of all this has any real meaning. On the

way to that liberty, there is still a progress to be made. The final

effort for these related minds, creator or conqueror, is to manage to

free themselves also from their undertakings: succeed in granting

that the very work, whether it be conquest, love, or creation, may

well not be; consummate thus the utter futility of any individual

life. Indeed, that gives them more freedom in the realization of that

work, just as becoming aware of the absurdity of life authorized

them to plunge into it with every excess.

All that remains is a fate whose outcome alone is fatal. Outside

of that single fatality of death, everything, joy or happiness, is

liberty. A world remains of which man is the sole master. What

bound him was the illusion of another world. The outcome of his

thought, ceasing to be renunciatory, flowers in images. It frolics—

in myths, to be sure, but myths with no other depth than that of

human suffering and, like it, inexhaustible. Not the divine fable

that amuses and blinds, but the terrestrial face, gesture, and drama

in which are summed up a difficult wisdom and an ephemeral

passion.

The Myth Of Sisyphus

The gods had condemned Sisyphus to ceaselessly rolling a rock

to the top of a mountain, whence the stone would fall back of its

own weight. They had thought with some reason that there is no

more dreadful punishment than futile and hopeless labor.

If one believes Homer, Sisyphus was the wisest and most

prudent of mortals. According to another tradition, however, he

was disposed to practice the profession of highwayman. I see no

contradiction in this. Opinions differ as to the reasons why he

became the futile laborer of the underworld. To begin with, he is

accused of a certain levity in regard to the gods. He stole their

secrets. AEgina, the daughter of AEsopus, was carried off by

Jupiter. The father was shocked by that disappearance and

complained to Sisyphus. He, who knew of the abduction, offered

to tell about it on condition that AEsopus would give water to the

citadel of Corinth. To the celestial thunderbolts he preferred the

benediction of water. He was punished for this in the underworld.

Homer tells us also that Sisyphus had put Death in chains. Pluto

could not endure the sight of his deserted, silent empire. He

dispatched the god of war, who liberated Death from the hands of

her conqueror.

It is said also that Sisyphus, being near to death, rashly wanted

to test his wife’s love. He ordered her to cast his unburied body

into the middle of the public square. Sisyphus woke up in the

underworld. And there, annoyed by an obedience so contrary to

human love, he obtained from Pluto permission to return to earth in

order to chastise his wife. But when he had seen again the face of

this world, enjoyed water and sun, warm stones and the sea, he no

longer wanted to go back to the infernal darkness. Recalls, signs of

anger, warnings were of no avail. Many years more he lived facing

the curve of the gulf, the sparkling sea, and the smiles of earth. A

decree of the gods was necessary. Mercury came and seized the

impudent man by the collar and, snatching him from his joys, led

him forcibly back to the underworld, where his rock was ready for

him.

You have already grasped that Sisyphus is the absurd hero. He

is, as much through his passions as through his torture. His scorn

of the gods, his hatred of death, and his passion for life won him

that unspeakable penalty in which the whole being is exerted

toward accomplishing nothing. This is the price that must be paid

for the passions of this earth. Nothing is told us about Sisyphus in

the underworld. Myths are made for the imagination to breathe life

into them. As for this myth, one sees merely the whole effort of a

body straining to raise the huge stone, to roll it and push it up a

slope a hundred times over; one sees the face screwed up, the

cheek tight against the stone, the shoulder bracing the clay-covered

mass, the foot wedging it, the fresh start with arms outstretched,

the wholly human security of two earth-clotted hands. At the very

end of his long effort measured by skyless space and time without

depth, the purpose is achieved. Then Sisyphus watches the stone

rush down in a few moments toward that lower world whence he

will have to push it up again toward the summit. He goes back

down to the plain.

It is during that return, that pause, that Sisyphus interests me. A

face that toils so close to stones is already stone itself! I see that

man going back down with a heavy yet measured step toward the

torment of which he will never know the end. That hour like a

breathing-space which returns as surely as his suffering, that is the

hour of consciousness. At each of those moments when he leaves

the heights and gradually sinks toward the lairs of the gods, he is

superior to his fate. He is stronger than his rock.

If this myth is tragic, that is because its hero is conscious.

Where would his torture be, indeed, if at every step the hope of

succeeding upheld him? The workman of today works every day in

his life at the same tasks, and this fate is no less absurd. But it is

tragic only at the rare moments when it becomes conscious.

Sisyphus, proletarian of the gods, powerless and rebellious, knows

the whole extent of his wretched condition: it is what he thinks of

during his descent. The lucidity that was to constitute his torture at

the same time crowns his victory. There is no fate that cannot be

surmounted by scorn.

If the descent is thus sometimes performed in sorrow, it can

also take place in joy. This word is not too much. Again I fancy

Sisyphus returning toward his rock, and the sorrow was in the

beginning. When the images of earth cling too tightly to memory,

when the call of happiness becomes too insistent, it happens that

melancholy rises in man’s heart: this is the rock’s victory, this is

the rock itself. The boundless grief is too heavy to bear. These are

our nights of Gethsemane. But crushing truths perish from being

acknowledged. Thus, CEdipus at the outset obeys fate without

knowing it. But from the moment he knows, his tragedy begins.

Yet at the same moment, blind and desperate, he realizes that the

only bond linking him to the world is the cool hand of a girl. Then

a tremendous remark rings out: “Despite so many ordeals, my

advanced age and the nobility of my soul make me conclude that

all is well.” Sophocles’ CEdipus, like Dostoevsky’s Kirilov, thus

gives the recipe for the absurd victory. Ancient wisdom confirms

modern heroism.

One does not discover the absurd without being tempted to

write a manual of happiness. “What! by such narrow ways—?”

There is but one world, however. Happiness and the absurd are two

sons of the same earth. They are inseparable. It would be a mistake

to say that happiness necessarily springs from the absurd

discovery. It happens as well that the feeling of the absurd springs

from happiness. “I conclude that all is well,” says CEdipus, and

that remark is sacred. It echoes in the wild and limited universe of

man. It teaches that all is not, has not been, exhausted. It drives out

of this world a god who had come into it with dissatisfaction and a

preference for futile sufferings. It makes of fate a human matter,

which must be settled among men.

All Sisyphus’ silent joy is contained therein. His fate belongs

to him. His rock is his thing. Likewise, the absurd man, when he

contemplates his torment, silences all the idols. In the universe

suddenly restored to its silence, the myriad wondering little voices

of the earth rise up. Unconscious, secret calls, invitations from all

the faces, they are the necessary reverse and price of victory. There

is no sun without shadow, and it is es-sential to know the night.

The absurd man says yes and his effort will henceforth be

unceasing. If there is a personal fate, there is no higher destiny, or

at least there is but one which he concludes is inevitable and

despicable. For the rest, he knows himself to be the master of his

days. At that subtle moment when man glances backward over his

life, Sisyphus returning toward his rock, in that slight pivoting he

contemplates that series of unrelated actions which becomes his

fate, created by him, combined under his memory’s eye and soon

sealed by his death. Thus, convinced of the wholly human origin of

all that is human, a blind man eager to see who knows that the

night has no end, he is still on the go. The rock is still rolling.

I leave Sisyphus at the foot of the mountain! One always finds

one’s burden again. But Sisyphus teaches the higher fidelity that

negates the gods and raises rocks. He too concludes that all is well.

This universe henceforth without a master seems to him neither

sterile nor futile. Each atom of that stone, each mineral flake of

that night-filled mountain, in itself forms a world. The struggle

itself toward the heights is enough to fill a man’s heart. One must

imagine Sisyphus happy.

Appendix: Hope and the Absurd in the Work of Franz Kafka

The whole art of Kafka consists in forcing the reader to reread.

His endings, or his absence of endings, suggest explanations

which, however, are not revealed in clear language but, before they

seem justified, require that the story be reread from another point

of view. Sometimes there is a double possibility of interpretation,

whence appears the necessity for two readings. This is what the

author wanted. But it would be wrong to try to interpret everything

in Kafka in detail. A symbol is always in general and, however

precise its translation, an artist can restore to it only its movement:

there is no word-for-word rendering. Moreover, nothing is harder

to understand than a symbolic work. A symbol always transcends

the one who makes use of it and makes him say in reality more

than he is aware of expressing. In this regard, the surest means of

getting hold of it is not to provoke it, to begin the work without a

preconceived attitude and not to look for its hidden currents. For

Kafka in particular it is fair to agree to his rules, to approach the

drama through its externals and the novel through its form.

At first glance and for a casual reader, they are disturbing

adventures that carry off quaking and dogged characters into

pursuit of problems they never formulate. In The Trial, Joseph K.

is accused. But he doesn’t know of what. He is doubtless eager to

defend himself, but he doesn’t know why. The lawyers find his

case difficult. Meanwhile, he does not neglect to love, to eat, or to

read his paper. Then he is judged. But the courtroom is very dark.

He doesn’t understand much. He merely assumes that he is

condemned, but to what he barely wonders. At times he suspects

just the same, and he continues living. Some time later two well-

dressed and polite gentlemen come to get him and invite him to

follow them. Most courteously they lead him into a wretched

suburb, put his head on a stone, and slit his throat. Before dying the

condemned man says merely: “Like a dog.”

You see that it is hard to speak of a symbol in a tale whose

most obvious quality just happens to be naturalness. But

naturalness is a hard category to understand. There are works in

which the event seems natural to the reader. But there are others

(rarer, to be sure) in which the character considers natural what

happens to him. By an odd but obvious paradox, the more

extraordinary the character’s adventures are, the more noticeable

will be the naturalness of the story: it is in proportion to the

divergence we feel between the strangeness of a man’s life and the

simplicity with which that man accepts it. It seems that this

naturalness is Kafka’s. And, precisely, one is well aware what The

Trial means. People have spoken of an image of the human

condition. To be sure. Yet it is both simpler and more complex. I

mean that the significance of the novel is more particular and more

personal to Kafka. To a certain degree, he is the one who does the

talking, even though it is me he confesses. He lives and he is

condemned. He learns this on the first pages of the novel he is

pursuing in this world, and if he tries to cope with this, he

nonetheless does so without surprise. He will never show sufficient

astonishment at this lack of astonishment. It is by such

contradictions that the first signs of the absurd work are

recognized. The mind projects into the concrete its spiritual

tragedy. And it can do so solely by means of a perpetual paradox

which confers on colors the power to express the void and on daily

gestures the strength to translate eternal ambitions.

Likewise, The Castle is perhaps a theology in action, but it is

first of all the individual adventure of a soul in quest of its grace,

of a man who asks of this world’s objects their royal secret and of

women the signs of the god that sleeps in them. Metamorphosis, in

turn, certainly represents the horrible imagery of an ethic of

lucidity. But it is also the product of that incalculable amazement

man feels at being conscious of the beast he becomes effortlessly.

In this fundamental ambiguity lies Kafka’s secret. These perpetual

oscillations between the natural and the extraordinary, the

individual and the universal, the tragic and the everyday, the

absurd and the logical, are found throughout his work and give it

both its resonance and its meaning. These are the paradoxes that

must be enumerated, the contradictions that must be strengthened,

in order to understand the absurd work.

A symbol, indeed, assumes two planes, two worlds of ideas

and sensations, and a dictionary of correspondences between them.

This lexicon is the hardest thing to draw up. But awaking to the

two worlds brought face to face is tantamount to getting on the trail

of their secret relationships. In Kafka these two worlds are that of

everyday life on the one hand and, on the other, that of

supernatural anxiety.[26] It seems that we are witnessing here an

interminable exploitation of Nietzsche’s remark: “Great problems

are in the street.”

There is in the human condition (and this is a commonplace of

all literatures) a basic absurdity as well as an implacable nobility.

The two coincide, as is natural. Both of them are represented, let

me repeat, in the ridiculous divorce separating our spiritual

excesses and the ephemeral joys of the body. The absurd thing is

that it should be the soul of this body which it transcends so

inordinately. Whoever would like to represent this absurdity must

give it life in a series of parallel contrasts. Thus it is that Kafka

expresses tragedy by the everyday and the absurd by the logical.

An actor lends more force to a tragic character the more careful

he is not to exaggerate it. If he is moderate, the horror he inspires

will be immoderate. In this regard Greek tragedy is rich in lessons.

In a tragic work fate always makes itself felt better in the guise of

logic and naturalness. CEdipus’s fate is announced in advance. It is

decided supernaturally that he will commit the murder and the

incest. The drama’s whole effort is to show the logical system

which, from deduction to deduction, will crown the hero’s

misfortune. Merely to announce to us that uncommon fate is

scarcely horrible, because it is improbable. But if its necessity is

demonstrated to us in the framework of everyday life, society,

state, familiar emotion, then the horror is hallowed. In that revolt

that shakes man and makes him say: “That is not possible,” there is

an element of desperate certainty that “that” can be.

This is the whole secret of Greek tragedy, or at least of one of

its aspects. For there is another which, by a reverse method, would

help us to understand Kafka better. The human heart has a tiresome

tendency to label as fate only what crushes it. But happiness

likewise, in its way, is without reason, since it is inevitable.

Modern man, however, takes the credit for it himself, when he

doesn’t fail to recognize it. Much could be said, on the contrary,

about the privileged fates of Greek tragedy and those favored in

legend who, like Ulysses, in the midst of the worst adventures are

saved from themselves. It was not so easy to return to Ithaca.

What must be remembered in any case is that secret complicity

that joins the logical and the everyday to the tragic. This is why

Samsa, the hero of Metamorphosis, is a traveling salesman. This is

why the only thing that disturbs him in the strange adventure that

makes a vermin of him is that his boss will be angry at his absence.

Legs and feelers grow out on him, his spine arches up, white spots

appear on his belly and—I shall not say that this does not astonish

him, for the effect would be spoiled—but it causes him a “slight

annoyance.” The whole art of Kafka is in that distinction. In his

central work, The Castle, the details of everyday life stand out, and

yet in that strange novel in which nothing concludes and

everything begins over again, it is the essential adventure of a soul

in quest of its grace that is represented. That translation of the

problem into action, that coincidence of the general and the

particular are recognized likewise in the little artifices that belong

to every great creator. In The Trial the hero might have been

named Schmidt or Franz Kafka. But he is named Joseph K. He is

not Kafka and yet he is Kafka. He is an average European. He is

like everybody else. But he is also the entity K. who is the x of this

flesh-and-blood equation.

Likewise, if Kafka wants to express the absurd, he will make

use of consistency. You know the story of the crazy man who was

fishing in a bathtub. A doctor with ideas as to psychiatric

treatments asked him “if they were biting,” to which he received

the harsh reply: “Of course not, you fool, since this is a bathtub.”

That story belongs to the baroque type. But in it can be grasped

quite clearly to what a degree the absurd effect is linked to an

excess of logic. Kafka’s world is in truth an indescribable universe

in which man allows himself the tormenting luxury of fishing in a

bathtub, knowing that nothing will come of it.

Consequently, I recognize here a work that is absurd in its

principles. As for The Trial, for instance, I can indeed say that it is

a complete success. Flesh wins out.

Nothing is lacking, neither the unexpressed revolt (but it is

what is writing), nor lucid and mute despair (but it is what is

creating), nor that amazing freedom of manner which the

characters of the novel exemplify until their ultimate death.

Yet this world is not so closed as it seems. Into this universe

devoid of progress, Kafka is going to introduce hope in a strange

form. In this regard The Trial and The Castle do not follow the

same direction. They complement each other. The barely

perceptible progression from one to the other represents a

tremendous conquest in the realm of evasion. The Trial propounds

a problem which The Castle, to a certain degree, solves. The first

describes according to a quasi scientific method and without

concluding. The second, to a certain degree, explains. The Trial

diagnoses, and The Castle imagines a treatment. But the remedy

proposed here does not cure. It merely brings the malady back into

normal life. It helps to accept it. In a certain sense (let us think of

Kierkegaard), it makes people cherish it. The Land Surveyor K.

cannot imagine another anxiety than the one that is tormenting

him. The very people around him become attached to that void and

that nameless pain, as if suffering assumed in this case a privileged

aspect. “How I need you,” Frieda says to K. “How forsaken I feel,

since knowing you, when you are not with me.” This subtle

remedy that makes us love what crushes us and makes hope spring

up in a world without issue, this sudden “leap” through which

everything is changed, is the secret of the existential revolution and

of The Castle itself.

Few works are more rigorous in their development than The

Castle. K. is named Land Surveyor to the Castle and he arrives in

the village. But from the village to the Castle it is impossible to

communicate. For hundreds of pages K. persists in seeking his

way, makes every advance, uses trickery and expedients, never

gets angry, and with disconcerting good will tries to assume the

duties entrusted to him. Each chapter is a new frustration. And also

a new beginning. It is not logic, but consistent method. The scope

of that insistence constitutes the work’s tragic quality. When K.

telephones to the Castle, he hears confused, mingled voices, vague

laughs, distant invitations. That is enough to feed his hope, like

those few signs appearing in summer skies or those evening

anticipations which make up our reason for living. Here is found

the secret of the melancholy peculiar to Kafka. The same, in truth,

that is found in Proust’s work or in the landscape of Plotinus: a

nostalgia for a lost paradise.

“I become very sad,” says Olga,

“when Barnabas tells me in the morning that he is going to the

Castle: that probably futile trip, that probably wasted day, that

probably empty hope.”

“Probably”—on this implication Kafka gambles his entire

work. But nothing avails; the quest of the eternal here is

meticulous. And those inspired automata, Kafka’s characters,

provide us with a precise image of what we should be if we were

deprived of our distractions[27] and utterly consigned to the

humiliations of the divine.

In The Castle that surrender to the everyday becomes an ethic.

The great hope of K. is to get the Castle to adopt him. Unable to

achieve this alone, his whole effort is to deserve this favor by

becoming an inhabitant of the village, by losing the status of

foreigner that everyone makes him feel. What he wants is an

occupation, a home, the life of a healthy, normal man. He can’t

stand his madness any longer. He wants to be reasonable. He wants

to cast off the peculiar curse that makes him a stranger to the

village. The episode of Frieda is significant in this regard. If he

takes as his mistress this woman who has known one of the

Castle’s officials, this is because of her past. He derives from her

something that transcends him while being aware of what makes

her forever unworthy of the Castle. This makes one think of

Kierkegaard’s strange love for Regina Olsen. In certain men, the

fire of eternity consuming them is great enough for them to burn in

it the very heart of those closest to them. The fatal mistake that

consists in giving to God what is not God’s is likewise the subject

of this episode of The Castle. But for Kafka it seems that this is not

a mistake. It is a doctrine and a “leap.” There is nothing that is not

God’s.

Even more significant is the fact that the Land Surveyor breaks

with Frieda in order to go toward the Barnabas sisters. For the

Barnabas family is the only one in the village that is utterly

forsaken by the Castle and by the village itself. Amalia, the elder

sister, has rejected the shameful propositions made her by one of

the Castle’s officials. The immoral curse that followed has forever

cast her out from the love of God. Being incapable of losing one’s

honor for God amounts to making oneself unworthy of his grace.

You recognize a theme familiar to existential philosophy: truth

contrary to morality. At this point things are far-reaching. For the

path pursued by Kafka’s hero from Frieda to the Barnabas sisters is

the very one that leads from trusting love to the deification of the

absurd. Here again Kafka’s thought runs parallel to Kierkegaard. It

is not surprising that the “Barnabas story” is placed at the end of

the book. The Land Surveyor’s last attempt is to recapture God

through what negates him, to recognize him, not according to our

categories of goodness and beauty, but behind the empty and

hideous aspects of his indifference, of his injustice, and of his

hatred. That stranger who asks the Castle to adopt him is at the end

of his voyage a little more exiled because this time he is unfaithful

to himself, forsaking morality, logic, and intellectual truths in order

to try to enter, endowed solely with his mad hope, the desert of

divine grace.[28]

The word “hope” used here is not ridiculous. On the contrary,

the more tragic the condition described by Kafka, the firmer and

more aggressive that hope becomes. The more truly absurd The

Trial is, the more moving and illegitimate the impassioned “leap”

of The Castle seems. But we find here again in a pure state the

paradox of existential thought as it is expressed, for instance, by

Kierkegaard: “Earthly hope must be killed; only then can one be

saved by true hope,”[29]which can be translated: “One has to have

written The Trial to undertake The Castle.”

Most of those who have spoken of Kafka have indeed defined

his work as a desperate cry with no recourse left to man. But this

calls for review. There is hope and hope. To me the optimistic

work of Henri Bordeaux seems peculiarly discouraging. This is

because it has nothing for the discriminating. Malraux’s thought,

on the other hand, is always bracing. But in these two cases neither

the same hope nor the same despair is at issue. I see merely that the

absurd work itself may lead to the infidelity I want to avoid. The

work which was but an ineffectual repetition of a sterile condition,

a lucid glorification ol the ephemeral, becomes here a cradle of

illusions. It explains, it gives a shape to hope. The creator can no

longer divorce himself from it. It is not the tragic game it was to

be. It gives a meaning to the author’s life.

It is strange in any case that works of related inspiration like

those of Kafka, Kierkegaard, or Chestov—those, in short, of

existential novelists and philosophers completely oriented toward

the Absurd and its consequences—should in the long run lead to

that tremendous cry of hope.

They embrace the God that consumes them. It is through

humility that hope enters in. For the absurd of this existence

assures them a little more of supernatural reality. If the course of

this life leads to God, there is an outcome after all. And the

perseverance, the insistence with which Kierkegaard, Chestov, and

Kafka’s heroes repeat their itineraries are a special warrant of the

uplifting power of that certainty.[30]

Kafka refuses his god moral nobility, evidence, virtue,

coherence, but only the better to fall into his arms. The absurd is

recognized, accepted, and man is resigned to it, but from then on

we know that it has ceased to be the absurd. Within the limits of

the human condition, what greater hope than the hope that allows

an escape from that condition? As I see once more, existential

thought in this regard (and contrary to current opinion) is steeped

in a vast hope. The very hope which at the time of early

Christianity and the spreading of the good news inflamed the

ancient world. But in that leap that characterizes all existential

thought, in that insistence, in that surveying of a divinity devoid of

surface, how can one fail to see the mark of a lucidity that

repudiates itself? It is merely claimed that this is pride abdicating

to save itself. Such a repudiation would be fecund. But this does

not change that. The moral value of lucidity cannot be diminished

in my eyes by calling it sterile like all pride. For a truth also, by its

very definition, is sterile. All facts are. In a world where everything

is given and nothing is explained, the fecundity of a value or of a

metaphysic is a notion devoid of meaning.

In any case, you see here in what tradition of thought Kafka’s

work takes its place. It would indeed be intelligent to consider as

inevitable the progression leading from The Trial to The Castle.

Joseph K. and the Land Surveyor K. are merely two poles that

attract Kafka.[31] I shall speak like him and say that his work is

probably not absurd. But that should not deter us from seeing its

nobility and universality. They come from the fact that he managed

to represent so fully the everyday passage from hope to grief and

from desperate wisdom to intentional blindness. His work is

universal (a really absurd work is not universal) to the extent to

which it represents the emotionally moving face of man fleeing

humanity, deriving from his contradictions reasons for believing,

reasons for hoping from his fecund despairs, and calling life his

terrifying apprenticeship in death. It is universal because its

inspiration is religious. As in all religions, man is freed of the

weight of his own life. But if I know that, if I can even admire it, I

also know that I am not seeking what is universal, but what is true.

The two may well not coincide.

This particular view will be better understood if I say that truly

hopeless thought just happens to be defined by the opposite criteria

and that the tragic work might be the work that, after all future

hope is exiled, describes the life of a happy man. The more

exciting life is, the more absurd is the idea of losing it. This is

perhaps the secret of that proud aridity felt in Nietzsche’s work. In

this connection, Nietzsche appears to be the only artist to have

derived the extreme consequences of an aesthetic of the Absurd,

inasmuch as his final message lies in a sterile and conquering

lucidity and an obstinate negation of any supernatural consolation.

The preceding should nevertheless suffice to bring out the

capital importance of Kafka in the framework of this essay. Here

we are carried to the confines of human thought. In the fullest

sense of the word, it can be said that everything in that work is

essential. In any case, it propounds the absurd problem altogether.

If one wants to compare these conclusions with our initial remarks,

the content with the form, the secret meaning of The Castle with

the natural art in which it is molded, K.’s passionate, proud quest

with the everyday setting against which it takes place, then one

will realize what may be its greatness. For if nostalgia is the mark

of the human, perhaps no one has given such flesh and volume to

these phantoms of regret. But at the same time will be sensed what

exceptional nobility the absurd work calls for, which is perhaps not

found here. If the nature of art is to bind the general to the

particular, ephemeral eternity of a drop of water to the play of its

lights, it is even truer to judge the greatness of the absurd writer by

the distance he is able to introduce between these two worlds. His

secret consists in being able to find the exact point where they

meet in their greatest disproportion.

And, to tell the truth, this geometrical locus of man and the

inhuman is seen everywhere by the pure in heart. If Faust and Don

Quixote are eminent creations of art, this is because of the

immeasurable nobilities they point out to us with their earthly

hands. Yet a moment always comes when the mind negates the

truths that those hands can touch. A moment comes when the

creation ceases to be taken tragically; it is merely taken seriously.

Then man is concerned with hope. But that is not his business. His

business is to turn away from subterfuge. Yet this is just what I

find at the conclusion of the vehement proceedings Kafka institutes

against the whole universe. His unbelievable verdict is this hideous

and upsetting world in which the very moles dare to hope.[32]

Summer In Algiers

**for JACQUES HEURGON**

The loves we share with a city are often secret loves. Old

walled towns like Paris, Prague, and even Florence are closed in on

themselves and hence limit the world that belongs to them. But

Algiers (together with certain other privileged places such as cities

on the sea) opens to the sky like a mouth or a wound. In Algiers

one loves the commonplaces: the sea at the end of every street, a

certain volume of sunlight, the beauty of the race. And, as always,

in that unashamed offering there is a secret fragrance. In Paris it is

possible to be homesick for space and a beating of wings. Here at

least man is gratified in every wish and, sure of his desires, can at

last measure his possessions.

Probably one has to live in Algiers for some time in order to

realize how paralyzing an excess of nature’s bounty can be. There

is nothing here for whoever would learn, educate himself, or better

himself. This country has no lessons to teach. It neither promises

nor affords glimpses. It is satisfied to give, but in abundance. It is

completely accessible to the eyes, and you know it the moment you

enjoy it. Its pleasures are without remedy and its joys without

hope. Above all, it requires clairvoyant souls—that is, without

solace. It insists upon one’s performing an act of lucidity as one

performs an act of faith. Strange country that gives the man it

nourishes both his splendor and his misery! It is not surprising that

the sensual riches granted to a sensitive man of these regions

should coincide with the most extreme destitution. No truth fails to

carry with it its bitterness. How can one be surprised, then, if I

never feel more affection for the face of this country than amid its

poorest men?

During their entire youth men find here a life in proportion to

their beauty. Then, later on, the downhill slope and obscurity. They

wagered on the flesh, but knowing they were to lose. In Algiers

whoever is young and alive finds sanctuary and occasion for

triumphs everywhere: in the bay, the sun, the red and white games

on the seaward terraces, the flowers and sports stadiums, the cool-

legged girls. But for whoever has lost his youth there is nothing to

cling to and nowhere where melancholy can escape itself.

Elsewhere, Italian terraces, European cloisters, or the profile of the

Provencal hills—all places where man can flee his humanity and

gently liberate himself from himself. But everything here calls for

solitude and the blood of young men. Goethe on his deathbed calls

for light and this is a historic remark. At Belcourt and Bab-el-Oued

old men seated in the depths of cafes listen to the bragging of

young men with plastered hair.

Summer betrays these beginnings and ends to us in Algiers.

During those months the city is deserted. But the poor remain, and

the sky. We join the former as they go down toward the harbor and

man’s treasures: warmth of the water and the brown bodies of

women. In the evening, sated with such wealth, they return to the

oilcloth and kerosene lamp that constitute the whole setting of their

life.

In Algiers no one says “go for a swim,” but rather “indulge in a

swim.” The implications are clear. People swim in the harbor and

go to rest on the buoys. Anyone who passes near a buoy where a

pretty girl already is sunning herself shouts to his friends: “I tell

you it’s a seagull.” These are healthy amusements. They must

obviously constitute the ideal of those youths, since most of them

continue the same life in the winter, undressing every day at noon

for a frugal lunch in the sun. Not that they have read the boring

sermons of the nudists, those Protestants of the flesh (there is a

theory of the body quite as tiresome as that of the mind). But they

are simply “comfortable in the sunlight.” The importance of this

custom for our epoch can never be overestimated. For the first time

in two thousand years the body has appeared naked on beaches.

For twenty centuries men have striven to give decency to Greek

insolence and naivete, to diminish the flesh and complicate dress.

Today, despite that history, young men running on Mediterranean

beaches repeat the gestures of the athletes of Delos. And living

thus among bodies and through one’s body, one becomes aware

that it has its connotations, its life, and, to risk nonsense, a

psychology of its own.[33] The body’s evolution, like that of the

mind, has its history, its vicissitudes, its progress, and its

deficiency. With this distinction, however: color. When you

frequent the beach in summer you become aware of a simultaneous

progression of all skins from white to golden to tanned, ending up

in a tobacco color which marks the extreme limit of the effort of

transformation of which the body is capable. Above the harbor

stands the set of white cubes of the Kasbah. When you are at water

level, against the sharp while background of the Arab town the

bodies describe a copper-colored frieze. And as the month of

August progresses and the sun grows, the white of the houses

becomes more blinding and skins take on a darker warmth. How

can one fail to participate, then, in that dialogue of stone and flesh

in tune with the sun and seasons? The whole morning has been

spent in diving, in bursts of laughter amid splashing water, in

vigorous paddles around the red and black freighters (those from

Norway with all the scents of wood, those that come from

Germany full of the smell of oil, those that go up and down the

coast and smell of wine and old casks). At the hour when the sun

overflows from every corner of the sky at once, the orange canoe

loaded with brown bodies brings us home in a mad race. And

when, having suddenly interrupted the cadenced beat of the double

paddle’s bright-colored wings, we glide slowly in the calm water

of the inner harbor, how can I fail to feel that I am piloting through

the smooth waters a savage cargo of gods in whom I recognize my

brothers?

But at the other end of the city summer is already offering us,

by way of contrast, its other riches: I mean its silence and its

boredom. That silence is not always of the same quality, depending

on whether it springs from the shade or the sunlight. There is the

silence of noon on the Place du Gouvernement. In the shade of the

trees surrounding it, Arabs sell for five sous glasses of iced

lemonade flavored with orange-flowers. Their cry “Cool, cool” can

be heard across the empty square. After their cry silence again falls

under the burning sun: in the vendor’s jug the ice moves and I can

hear its tinkle. There is the silence of the siesta. In the streets of the

Marine, in front of the dirty barbershops it can be measured in the

melodious buzzing of flies behind the hollow reed curtains.

Elsewhere, in the Moorish cafes of the Kasbah the body is silent,

unable to tear itself away, to leave the glass of tea and rediscover

time with the pulsing of its own blood. But, above all, there is the

silence of summer evenings.

Those brief moments when day topples into night must be

peopled with secret signs and summons for my Algiers to be so

closely linked to them. When I spend some time far from that

town, I imagine its twilights as promises of happiness. On the hills

above the city there are paths among the mastics and olive trees.

And toward them my heart turns at such moments. I see flights of

black birds rise against the green horizon. In the sky suddenly

divested of its sun something relaxes. A whole little nation of red

clouds stretches out until it is absorbed in the air. Almost

immediately afterward appears the first star that had been seen

taking shape and consistency in the depth of the sky. And then

suddenly, all consuming, night. What exceptional quality do the

fugitive Algerian evenings possess to be able to release so many

things in me? I haven’t time to tire of that sweetness they leave on

my lips before it has disappeared into night. Is this the secret of its

persistence? This country’s affection is overwhelming and furtive.

But during the moment it is present, one’s heart at least surrenders

completely to it. At Padovani Beach the dance hall is open every

day. And in that huge rectangular box with its entire side open to

the sea, the poor young people of the neighborhood dance until

evening. Often I used to await there a moment of exceptional

beauty. During the day the hall is protected by sloping wooden

awnings. When the sun goes down they are raised. Then the hall is

filled with an odd green light born of the double shell of the sky

and the sea. When one is seated far from the windows, one sees

only the sky and, silhouetted against it, the faces of the dancers

passing in succession. Sometimes a waltz is being played, and

against the green background the black profiles whirl obstinately

like those cut-out silhouettes that are attached to a phonograph’s

turntable. Night comes rapidly after this, and with it the lights. But

I am unable to relate the thrill and secrecy that subtle instant holds

for me. I recall at least a magnificent tall girl who had danced all

afternoon. She was wearing a jasmine garland on her tight blue

dress, wet with perspiration from the small of her back to her legs.

She was laughing as she danced and throwing back her head. As

she passed the tables, she left behind her a mingled scent of

flowers and flesh. When evening came, I could no longer see her

body pressed tight to her partner, but against the sky whirled

alternating spots of white jasmine and black hair, and when she

would throw back her swelling breast I would hear her laugh and

see her partner’s profile suddenly plunge forward. I owe to such

evenings the idea I have of innocence. In any case, I learn not to

separate these creatures bursting with violent energy from the sky

where their desires whirl.

In the neighborhood movies in Algiers peppermint lozenges are

sometimes sold with, stamped in red, all that is necessary to the

awakening of love: (1) questions: “When will you marry me?” “Do

you love me?” and (2) replies: “Madly,” “Next spring.” After

having prepared the way, you pass them to your neighbor, who

answers likewise or else turns a deaf ear. At Belcourt marriages

have been arranged this way and whole lives been pledged by the

mere exchange of peppermint lozenges. And this really depicts the

childlike people of this region.

The distinguishing mark of youth is perhaps a magnificent

vocation for facile joys. But, above all, it is a haste to live that

borders on waste. At Belcourt, as at Bab-el-Oued, people get

married young. They go to work early and in ten years exhaust the

experience of a lifetime. A thirty-year-old workman has already

played all the cards in his hand. He awaits the end between his

wife and his children. His joys have been sudden and merciless, as

has been his life. One realizes that he is born of this country where

everything is given to be taken away. In that plenty and profusion

life follows the sweep of great passions, sudden, exacting, and

generous. It is not to be built up, but to be burned up. Stopping to

think and becoming better are out of the question. The notion of

hell, for instance, is merely a funny joke here. Such imaginings are

allowed only to the very virtuous. And I really think that virtue is a

meaningless word in all Algeria. Not that these men lack

principles. They have their code, and a very special one. You are

not disrespectful to your mother. You see that your wife is

respected in the street. You show consideration for a pregnant

woman. You don’t double up on an adversary, because “that looks

bad.” Whoever does not observe these elementary commandments

“is not a man,” and the question is decided. This strikes me as fair

and strong. There are still many of us who automatically observe

this code of the street, the only disinterested one I know. But at the

same time the shopkeeper’s ethics are unknown. I have always

seen faces around me filled with pity at the sight of a man between

two policemen. And before knowing whether the man had stolen,

killed his father, or was merely a nonconformist, they would say:

“The poor fellow,” or else, with a hint of admiration: “He’s a

pirate, all right.”

There are races born for pride and life. They are the ones that

nourish the strangest vocation for boredom. It is also among them

that the attitude toward death is the most repulsive. Aside from

sensual pleasure, the amusements of this race are among the

silliest. A society of bowlers and association banquets, the three-

franc movies and parish feasts have for years provided the

recreation of those over thirty. Algiers Sundays are among the

most sinister. How, then, could this race devoid of spirituality

clothe in myths the profound horror of its life? Everything related

to death is either ridiculous or hateful here. This populace without

religion and without idols dies alone after having lived in a crowd.

I know no more hideous spot than the cemetery on Boulevard Bru,

opposite one of the most beautiful landscapes in the world. An

accumulation of bad taste among the black fencings allows a

dreadful melancholy to rise from this spot where death shows her

true likeness. “Everything fades,” say the heart-shaped ex-votos,

“except memory.” And all insist on that paltry eternity provided us

cheaply by the hearts of those who loved us. The same words fit all

despairs. Addressed to the dead man, they speak to him in the

second person (our memory will never forsake you); lugubrious

pretense which attributes a body and desires to what is at best a

black liquid. Elsewhere, amid a deadly profusion of marble flowers

and birds, this bold assertion: “Never will your grave be without

flowers.” But never fear: the inscription surrounds a gilded stucco

bouquet, very time-saving for the living (like those immortelles

which owe their pompous name to the gratitude of those who still

jump onto moving buses). Inasmuch as it is essential to keep up

with the times, the classic warbler is sometimes replaced by an

astounding pearl airplane piloted by a silly angel who, without

regard for logic, is provided with an impressive pair of wings.

Yet how to bring out that these images of death are never

separated from life? Here the values are closely linked. The

favorite joke of Algerian undertakers, when driving an empty

hearse, is to shout: “Want a ride, sister?” to any pretty girls they

meet on the way. There is no objection to seeing a symbol in this,

even if somewhat untoward. It may seem blasphemous, likewise,

to reply to the announcement of a death while winking one’s left

eye: “Poor fellow, he’ll never sing again,” or, like that woman of

Oran who bad never loved her husband: “God gave him to me and

God has taken him from me.” But, all in all, I see nothing sacred in

death and am well aware, on the other hand, of the distance there is

between fear and respect. Everything here suggests the horror of

dying in a country that invites one to live. And yet it is under the

very walls of this cemetery that the young of Belcourt have their

assignations and that the girls offer themselves to kisses and

caresses.

I am well aware that such a race cannot be accepted by all.

Here intelligence has no place as in Italy. This race is indifferent to

the mind. It has a cult for and admiration of the body. Whence its

strength, its innocent cynicism, and a puerile vanity which explains

why it is so severely judged. It is commonly blamed for its

“mentality”—that is, a way of seeing and of living. And it is true

that a certain intensity of life is inseparable from injustice. Yet here

is a rate without past, without tradition, and yet not without

poetry—but a poetry whose quality I know well, harsh, carnal, far

from tenderness, that of their very sky, the only one in truth to

move me and bring me inner peace. The contrary of a civilized

nation is a creative nation. I have the mad hope that, without

knowing it perhaps, these barbarians lounging on beaches are

actually modeling the image of a culture in which the greatness of

man will at last find its true likeness. This race, wholly cast into its

present, lives without myths, without solace. It has put all its

possessions on this earth and therefore remains without defense

against death. All the gifts of physical beauty have been lavished

on it. And with them, the strange avidity that always accompanies

that wealth without future. Everything that is done here shows a

horror of stability and a disregard for the future. People are in haste

to live, and if an art were to be born here it would obey that hatred

of permanence that made the Dorians fashion their first column in

wood. And yet, yes, one can find measure as well as excess in the

violent and keen face of this race, in this summer sky with nothing

tender in it, before which all truths can be uttered and on which no

deceptive divinity has traced the signs of hope or of redemption.

Between this sky and these faces turned toward it, nothing on

which to hang a mythology, a literature, an ethic, or a religion, but

stones, flesh, stars, and those truths the hand can touch.

To feel one’s attachment to a certain region, one’s love for a

certain group of men, to know that there is always a spot where

one’s heart will feel at peace these are many certainties for a single

human life. And yet this is not enough. But at certain moments

everything yearns for that spiritual home. “Yes, we must go back

there—there, indeed.” Is there anything odd in finding on earth that

union that Plotinus longed for? Unity is expressed here in terms of

sun and sea. The heart is sensitive to it through a certain savor of

flesh which constitutes its bitterness and its grandeur. I learn that

there is no superhuman happiness, no eternity outside the sweep of

days. These paltry and essential belongings, these relative truths

are the only ones to stir me. As for the others, the “ideal” truths, I

have not enough soul to understand them. Not that one must be an

animal, but I find no meaning in the happiness of angels. I know

simply that this sky will last longer than I. And what shall I call

eternity except what will continue after my death? I am not

expressing here the creature’s satisfaction with his condition. It is

quite a different matter. It is not always easy to be a man, still less

to be a pure man. But being pure is recovering that spiritual home

where one can feel the world’s relationship, where one’s pulse-

beats coincide with the violent throbbing of the two-o’clock sun. It

is well known that one’s native land is always recognized at the

moment of losing it. For those who are too uneasy about

themselves, their native land is the one that negates them. I should

not like to be brutal or seem extravagant. But, after all, what

negates me in this life is first of all what kills me. Everything that

exalts life at the same time increases its absurdity. In the Algerian

summer I learn that one thing only is more tragic than suffering,

and that is the life of a happy man. But it may be also the way to a

greater life because it leads to not cheating.

Many, in fact, feign love of life to evade love itself. They try

their skill at enjoyment and at “indulging in experiences.” But this

is illusory. It requires a rare vocation to be a sensualist. The life of

a man is fulfilled without the aid of his mind, with its backward

and forward movements, at one and the same time its solitude and

its presences. To see these men of Belcourt working, protecting

their wives and children, and often without a reproach, I think one

can feel a secret shame. To be sure, I have no illusions about it.

There is not much love in the lives I am speaking of. I ought to say

that not much remains. But at least they have evaded nothing.

There are words I have never really understood, such as “sin.” Yet

I believe these men have never sinned against life. For if there is a

sin against life, it consists perhaps not so much in despairing of life

as in hoping for another life and in eluding the implacable

grandeur of this life. These men have not cheated. Gods of summer

they were at twenty by their enthusiasm for life, and they still are,

deprived of all hope. I have seen two of them die. They were full

of horror, but silent. It is better thus. From Pandora’s box, where

all the ills of humanity swarmed, the Greeks drew out hope after

all the others, as the most dreadful of all. I know no more stirring

symbol; for, contrary to the general belief, hope equals resignation.

And to live is not to resign oneself. This, at least, is the bitter

lesson of Algerian summers. But already the season is wavering

and summer totters. The first September rains, after such violence

and hardening, are like the liberated earth’s first tears, as if for a

few days this country tried its hand at tenderness. Yet at the same

period the carob trees cover all of Algeria with a scent of love. In

the evening or after the rain, the whole earth, its womb moist with

a seed redolent of bitter almond, rests after having given herself to

the sun all summer long. And again that scent hallows the union of

man and earth and awakens in us the only really virile love in this

world: ephemeral and noble.

(1936)

The Minotaur or The Stop In Oran

**for PIERRE GALINDO**

This essay dates from 1939. The reader will have to bear this in

mind to judge of the present-day Oran. Impassioned protests from

that beautiful city assure me, as a matter of fact, that all the

imperfections have been (or will be) remedied. On the other hand,

the beauties extolled in this essay have been jealously respected.

Happy and realistic city, Oran has no further need of writers: she is

awaiting tourists.

(1953)

There are no more deserts. There are no more islands. Yet there

is a need for them. In order to understand the world, one has to turn

away from it on occasion; in order to serve men better, one has to

hold them at a distance for a time. But where can one find the

solitude necessary to vigor, the deep breath in which the mind

collects itself and courage gauges its strength? There remain big

cities. Simply, certain conditions are required.

The cities Europe offers us are too full of the din of the past. A

practiced ear can make out the flapping of wings, a fluttering of

souls. The giddy whirl of centuries, of revolutions, of fame can be

felt there. There one cannot forget that the Occident was forged in

a series of uproars. All that does not make for enough silence.

Paris is often a desert for the heart, but at certain moments

from the heights of Pere-Lachaise there blows a revolutionary

wind that suddenly fills that desert with flags and fallen glories. So

it is with certain Spanish towns, with Florence or with Prague.

Salzburg would be peaceful without Mozart. But from time to time

there rings out over the Salzach the great proud cry of Don Juan as

he plunges toward hell. Vienna seems more silent; she is a

youngster among cities. Her stones are no older than three

centuries and their youth is ignorant of melancholy. But Vienna

stands at a crossroads of history. Around her echoes the clash of

empires. Certain evenings when the sky is suffused with blood, the

stone horses on the Ring monuments seem to take wing. In that

fleeting moment when everything is reminiscent of power and

history, can he distinctly heard, under the charge of the Polish

squadrons, the crashing fall of the Ottoman Empire. That does not

make for enough silence either.

To be sure, it is just that solitude amid others that men come

looking for in European cities. At least, men with a purpose in life.

There they can choose their company, take it or leave it. How

many minds have been tempered in the trip between their hotel

room and the old stones of the Ile Saint Louis! It is true that others

have died there of isolation. As for the first, at any rate, there they

found their reasons for growing and asserting themselves. They

were alone and they weren’t alone. Centuries of history and

beauty, the ardent testimony of a thousand lives of the past

accompanied them along the Seine and spoke to them both of

traditions and of conquests. But their youth urged them to invite

such company. There comes a time, there come periods, when it is

unwelcome. “It’s between us two!” exclaims Rasti-gnac, facing the

vast mustiness of Paris. Two, yes, but that is still too many!

The desert itself has assumed significance; it has been glutted

with poetry. For all the world’s sorrows it is a hallowed spot. But

at certain moments the heart wants nothing so much as spots

devoid of poetry. Descartes, planning to meditate, chose his desert:

the most mercantile city of his era. There he found his solitude and

the occasion for perhaps the greatest of our virile poems: “The first

[precept] was never to accept anything as true unless I knew it to

be obviously so.” It is possible to have less ambition and the same

nostalgia. But during the last three centuries Amsterdam has

spawned museums. In order to flee poetry and yet recapture the

peace of stones, other deserts are needed, other spots without soul

and without reprieve. Oran is one of these.

The Street

I have often heard the people of Oran complain: “There is no

interesting circle.” No, indeed! You wouldn’t want one! A few

right-thinking people tried to introduce the customs of another

world into this desert, faithful to the principle that it is impossible

to advance art or ideas without grouping together.[34] The result is

such that the only instructive circles remain those of poker-players,

boxing enthusiasts, bowlers, and the local associations. There at

least the unsophisticated prevails. After all, there exists a certain

nobility that does not lend itself to the lofty. It is sterile by nature.

And those who want to find it leave the “circles” and go out into

the street.

The streets of Oran are doomed to dust, pebbles, and heat. If it

rains, there is a deluge and a sea of mud. But rain or shine, the

shops have the same extravagant and absurd look. All the bad taste

of Europe and the Orient has managed to converge in them. One

finds, helter-skelter, marble greyhounds, ballerinas with swans,

versions of Diana the huntress in green galalith, discus-throwers

and reapers, everything that is used for birthday and wedding gifts,

the whole race of painful figurines constantly called forth by a

commercial and playful genie on our mantelpieces. But such

perseverance in bad taste takes on a baroque aspect that makes one

forgive all. Here, presented in a casket of dust, are the contents of a

show window: frightful plaster models of deformed feet, a group

of Rembrandt drawings “sacrificed at 150 francs each,” practical

jokes, tricolored wallets, an eighteenth-century pastel, a

mechanical donkey made of plush, bottles of Provence water for

preserving green olives, and a wretched wooden virgin with an

indecent smile.

(So that no one can go away ignorant, the

“management” has propped at its base a card saying: “Wooden

Virgin.”) There can be found in Oran:

1) Cafes with filter-glazed counters sprinkled with the legs and

wings of flies, the proprietor always smiling despite his always

empty cafe. A small black coffee used to cost twelve sous and a

large one eighteen.

2) Photographers’ studios where there has been no progress in

technique since the invention of sensitized paper. They exhibit a

strange fauna impossible to encounter in the streets, from the

pseudo-sailor leaning on a console table to the marriageable girl,

badly dressed and arms dangling, standing in front of a sylvan

background. It is possible to assume that these are not portraits

from life: they are creations.

3) An edifying abundance of funeral establishments. It is not

that people die more in Oran than elsewhere, but I fancy merely

that more is made of it.

The attractive naivete of this nation of merchants is displayed

even in their advertising. I read, in the handbill of an Oran movie

theater, the advertisement for a third-rate film. I note the adjectives

“sumptuous,” splendid, extraordinary, amazing, staggering, and

“tremendous.” At the end the management informs the public of

the considerable sacrifices it has undertaken to be able to present

this startling “realization.” Nevertheless, the price of tickets will

not be increased.

It would be wrong to assume that this is merely a manifestation

of that love of exaggeration characteristic of the south. Rather, the

authors of this marvelous handbill are revealing their sense of

psychology. It is essential to overcome the indifference and

profound apathy felt in this country the moment there is any

question of choosing between two shows, two careers, and, often,

even two women. People make up their minds only when forced to

do so. And advertising is well aware of this. It will assume

American proportions, having the same reasons, both here and

there, for getting desperate.

The streets of Oran inform us as to the two essential pleasures

of the local youth: getting one’s shoes shined and displaying those

same shoes on the boulevard. In order to have a clear idea of the

first of these delights, one has to entrust one’s shoes, at ten o’clock

on a Sunday morning, to the shoe-shiners in Boulevard Gal-lieni.

Perched on high armchairs, one can enjoy that peculiar satisfaction

produced, even upon a rank outsider, by the sight of men in love

with their job, as the shoe-shiners of Oran obviously are.

Everything is worked over in detail. Several brushes, three kinds of

cloths, the polish mixed with gasoline. One might think the

operation is finished when a perfect shine comes to life under the

soft brush. But the same insistent hand covers the glossy surface

again with polish, rubs it, dulls it, makes the cream penetrate the

heart of the leather, and then brings forth, under the same brush, a

double and really definitive gloss sprung from the depths of the

leather. The wonders achieved in this way are then exhibited to the

connoisseurs. In order to appreciate such pleasures of the

boulevard, you ought to see the masquerade of youth taking place

every evening on the main arteries of the city. Between the ages of

sixteen and twenty the young people of Oran “Society” borrow

their models of elegance from American films and put on their

fancy dress before going out to dinner. With wavy, oiled hair

protruding from under a felt hat slanted over the left ear and

peaked over the right eye, the neck encircled by a collar big

enough to accommodate the straggling hair, the microscopic knot

of the necktie kept in place by a regulation pin, with thigh-length

coat and waist close to the hips, with light-colored and noticeably

short trousers, with dazzlingly shiny triple-soled shoes, every

evening those youths make the sidewalks ring with their metal-

tipped soles. In all things they are bent on imitating the bearing,

forthrightness, and superiority of Mr. Clark Gable. For this reason

the local carpers commonly nickname those youths, by favor of a

casual pronunciation, “Clarques.”

At any rate, the main boulevards of Oran are invaded late in the

afternoon by an army of attractive adolescents who go to the

greatest trouble to look like a bad lot. Inasmuch as the girls of Oran

feel traditionally engaged to these softhearted gangsters, they

likewise flaunt the make-up and elegance of popular American

actresses. Consequently, the same wits call them “Marlenes.” Thus

on the evening boulevards when the sound of birds rises skyward

from the palm trees, dozens of Clarques and Marlenes meet, eye

and size up one another, happy to be alive and to cut a figure,

indulging for an hour in the intoxication of perfect existences.

There can then be witnessed, the jealous say, the meetings of the

American Commission. But in these words lies the bitterness of

those over thirty who have no connection with such diversions.

They fail to appreciate those daily congresses of youth and

romance. These are, in truth, the parliaments of birds that are met

in Hindu literature. But no one on the boulevards of Oran debates

the problem of being or worries about the way to perfection. There

remains nothing but flappings of wings, plumed struttings,

coquettish and victorious graces, a great burst of carefree song that

disappears with the night.

From here I can hear Klestakov: “I shall soon have to be

concerned with something lofty.” Alas, he is quite capable of it! If

he were urged, he would people this desert within a few years. But

for the moment a somewhat secret soul must liberate itself in this

facile city with its parade of painted girls unable, nevertheless, to

simulate emotion, feigning coyness so badly that the pretense is

immediately obvious. Be concerned with something lofty! Just see:

Santa-Cruz cut out of the rock, the mountains, the flat sea, the

violent wind and the sun, the great cranes of the harbor, the trains,

the hangars, the quays, and the huge ramps climbing up the city’s

rock, and in the city itself these diversions and this boredom, this

hubbub and this solitude. Perhaps, indeed, all this is not

sufficiently lofty. But the great value of such overpopulated islands

is that in them the heart strips bare. Silence is no longer possible

except in noisy cities. From Amsterdam Descartes writes to the

aged Guez de Balzac: “I go out walking every day amid the

confusion of a great crowd, with as much freedom and tranquillity

as you could do on your garden paths.”[35]

The Desert in Oran

Obliged to live facing a wonderful landscape, the people of

Oran have overcome this fearful ordeal by covering their city with

very ugly constructions. One expects to find a city open to the sea,

washed and refreshed by the evening breeze. And aside from the

Spanish quarter,[36] one finds a walled town that turns its back to

the sea, that has been built up by turning back on itself like a snail.

Oran is a great circular yellow wall covered over with a leaden

sky. In the beginning you wander in the labyrinth, seeking the sea

like the sign of Ariadne. But you turn round and round in pale and

oppressive streets, and eventually the Minotaur devours the people

of Oran: the Minotaur is boredom. For some time the citizens of

Oran have given up wandering. They have accepted being eaten.

It is impossible to know what stone is without coming to Oran.

In that dustiest of cities, the pebble is king. It is so much

appreciated that shopkeepers exhibit it in their show windows to

hold papers in place or even for mere display. Piles of them are set

up along the streets, doubtless for the eyes’ delight, since a year

later the pile is still there. Whatever elsewhere derives its poetry

from the vegetable kingdom here takes on a stone face. The

hundred or so trees that can be found in the business section have

been carefully covered with dust. They are petrified plants whose

branches give off an acrid, dusty smell. In Algiers the Arab

cemeteries have a well-known mellowness. In Oran, above the

Ras-el-Ain ravine, facing the sea this time, flat against the blue

sky, are fields of chalky, friable pebbles in which the sun blinds

with its fires. Amid these bare bones of the earth a purple

geranium, from time to time, contributes its life and fresh blood to

the landscape. The whole city has solidified in a stony matrix. Seen

from Les Planteurs, the depth of the cliffs surrounding it is so great

that the landscape becomes unreal, so mineral it is. Man is

outlawed from it. So much heavy beauty seems to come from

another world.

If the desert can be defined as a soulless place where the sky

alone is king, then Oran is awaiting her prophets. All around and

above the city the brutal nature of Africa is indeed clad in her

burning charms. She bursts the unfortunate stage setting with

which she is covered; she shrieks forth between all the houses and

over all the roofs. If one climbs one of the roads up the mountain

of Santa-Cruz, the first thing to be visible is the scattered colored

cubes of Oran. But a little higher and already the jagged cliffs that

surround the plateau crouch in the sea like red beasts. Still a little

higher and a great vortex of sun and wind sweeps over, airs out,

and obscures the untidy city scattered in disorder all over a rocky

landscape. The opposition here is between magnificent human

anarchy and the permanence of an unchanging sea. This is enough

to make a staggering scent of life rise toward the mountainside

road.

There is something implacable about the desert. The mineral

sky of Oran, her streets and trees in their coating of dust—

everything contributes to creating this dense and impassible

universe in which the heart and mind are never distracted from

themselves, nor from their sole object, which is man. I am

speaking here of difficult places of retreat. Books are written on

Florence or Athens. Those cities have formed so many European

minds that they must have a meaning. They have the means of

moving to tears or of uplifting. They quiet a certain spiritual

hunger whose bread is memory. But can one be moved by a city

where nothing attracts the mind, where the very ugliness is

anonymous, where the past is reduced to nothing? Emptiness,

boredom, an indifferent sky, what are the charms of such places?

Doubtless solitude and, perhaps, the human creature.

For a certain race of men, wherever the human creature is

beautiful is a bitter native land. Oran is one of its thousand capitals.

Sports

The Central Sporting Club, on rue du Fondouk in Oran, is

giving an evening of boxing which it insists will be appreciated by

real enthusiasts. Interpreted, this means that the boxers on the bill

are far from being stars, that some of them are entering the ring for

the first time, and that consequently you can count, if not on the

skill, at least on the courage of the opponents. A native having

thrilled me with the firm promise that “blood would flow,” I find

myself that evening among the real enthusiasts.

Apparently the latter never insist on comfort. To be sure, a ring

has been set up at the back of a sort of whitewashed garage,

covered with corrugated iron and violently lighted. Folding chairs

have been lined up in a square around the ropes. These are the

“honor rings.” Most of the length of the hall has been filled with

seats, and behind them opens a large free space called “lounge” by

reason of the fact that not one of the five hundred persons in it

could take out a handkerchief without causing serious accidents. In

this rectangular box live and breathe some thousand men and two

or three women—the kind who, according to my neighbor, always

insist on

“attracting attention.” Everybody is sweating fiercely.

While waiting for the fights of the “young hopefuls” a gigantic

phonograph grinds out a Tino Rossi record. This is the sentimental

song before the murder.

The patience of a true enthusiast is unlimited. The fight

announced for nine o’clock has not even begun at nine thirty and

no one has protested. The spring weather is warm and the smell of

a humanity in shirt sleeves is exciting. Lively discussion goes on

among the periodic explosions of lemon-soda corks and the tireless

lament of the Corsican singer. A few late arrivals are wedged into

the audience when a spotlight throws a blinding light onto the ring.

The fights of the young hopefuls begin.

The young hopefuls, or beginners, who are fighting for the fun

of it, are always eager to prove this by massacring each other at the

earliest opportunity, in defiance of technique. They were never

able to last more than three rounds. The hero of the evening in this

regard is young “Kid Airplane,” who in regular life sells lottery

tickets on cafe terraces. His opponent, indeed, hurtled awkwardly

out of the ring at the beginning of the second round after contact

with a fist wielded like a propeller.

The crowd got somewhat excited, but this is still an act of

courtesy. Gravely it breathes in the hallowed air of the

embrocation. It watches these series of slow rites and unregulated

sacrifices, made even more authentic by the propitiatory designs,

on the white wall, of the fighters’ shadows. These are the

deliberate ceremonial prologues of a savage religion. The trance

will not come until later.

And it so happens that the loudspeaker announces Amar, “the

tough Oranese who has never disarmed,” against Perez,

“the

slugger from Algiers.” An uninitiate would misinterpret the yelling

that greets the introduction of the boxers in the ring. He would

imagine some sensational combat in which the boxers were to

settle a personal quarrel known to the public. To tell the truth, it is

a quarrel they are going to settle. But it is the one that for the past

hundred years has mortally separated Algiers and Oran. Back in

history, these two North African cities would have already bled

each other white as Pisa and Florence did in happier times. Their

rivalry is all the stronger just because it probably has no basis.

Having every reason to like each other, they loathe each other

proportionately. The Oranese accuse the citizens of Algiers of

“sham.” The people of Algiers imply that the Oranese are rustic.

These are bloodier insults than they might seem because they are

metaphysical. And unable to lay siege to each other, Oran and

Algiers meet, compete, and insult each other on the field of sports,

statistics, and public works.

Thus a page of history is unfolding in the ring. And the tough

Oranese, backed by a thousand yelling voices, is defending against

Perez a way of life and the pride of a province. Truth forces me to

admit that Amar is not conducting his discussion well. His

argument has a flaw: he lacks reach. The slugger from Algiers, on

the contrary, has the required reach in his argument. It lands

persuasively between his contradictor’s eyes. The Oranese bleeds

magnificently amid the vociferations of a wild audience. Despite

the repeated encouragements of the gallery and of my neighbor,

despite the dauntless shouts of

“Kill him!”,

“Floor him!”, the

insidious “Below the belt,”

“Oh, the referee missed that one!”, the optimistic

“He’s

pooped,” “He can’t take any more,” nevertheless the man from

Algiers is proclaimed the winner on points amid interminable

catcalls. My neighbor, who is inclined to talk of sportsmanship,

applauds ostensibly, while slipping to me in a voice made faint by

so many shouts: “So that he won’t be able to say back there that

we of Oran are savages.”

But throughout the audience, fights not included on the

program have already broken out. Chairs are brandished, the police

clear a path, excitement is at its height. In order to calm these good

people and contribute to the return of silence, the “management,”

without losing a moment, commissions the loudspeaker to boom

out “Sambre-et-Meuse.” For a few minutes the audience has a

really warlike look. Confused clusters of com-batants and

voluntary referees sway in the grip of policemen; the gallery exults

and calls for the rest of the program with wild cries, cock-a-

doodle-doo’s, and mocking catcalls drowned in the irresistible

flood from the military band.

But the announcement or the big fight is enough to restore

calm. This takes place suddenly, without flourishes, just as actors

leave the stage once the play is finished. With the greatest

unconcern, hats are dusted off, chairs are put back in place, and

without transition all faces assume the kindly expression of the

respectable member of the audience who has paid for his ticket to a

family concert.

The last fight pits a French champion of the Navy against an

Oran boxer. This time the difference in reach is to the advantage of

the latter. But his superiorities, during the first rounds, do not stir

the crowd. They are sleeping off the effects of their first

excitement; they are sobering up. They are still short of breath. If

they applaud, there is no passion in it. They hiss without animosity.

The audience is divided into two camps, as is appropriate in the

interest of fairness. But each individual’s choice obeys that

indifference that follows on great expenditures of energy. If the

Frenchman holds his own, if the Oranese forgets that one doesn’t

lead with the head, the boxer is bent under a volley of hisses, but

immediately pulled upright again by a burst of applause. Not until

the seventh round does sport rise to the surface again, at the same

time that the real enthusiasts begin to emerge from their fatigue.

The Frenchman, to tell the truth, has touched the mat and, eager to

win back points, has hurled himself on his opponent. “What did I

tell you?” said my neighbor; “it’s going to be a fight to the finish.”

Indeed, it is a fight to the finish. Covered with sweat under the

pitiless light, both boxers open their guard, close their eyes as they

hit, shove with shoulders and knees, swap their blood, and snort

with rage. As one man, the audience has stood up and punctuates

the efforts of its two heroes. It receives the blows, returns them,

echoes them in a thousand hollow, panting voices. The same ones

who had chosen their favorite in indifference cling to their choice

through obstinacy and defend it passionately. Every ten seconds a

shout from my neighbor pierces my right ear: “Go to it, gob; come

on, Navy!” while another man in front of us shouts to the Oranese:

“Anda! hombre!” The man and the gob go to it, and together with

them, in this temple of whitewash, iron, and cement, an audience

completely given over to gods with cauliflower ears. Every blow

that gives a dull sound on the shining pectorals echoes in vast

vibrations in the very body of the crowd, which, with the boxers, is

making its last effort.

In such an atmosphere a draw is badly received. Indeed, it runs

counter to a quite Manichean tendency in the audience. There is

good and there is evil, the winner and the loser. One must be either

right or wrong. The conclusion of this impeccable logic is

immediately provided by two thousand energetic lungs accusing

the judges of being sold, or bought. But the gob has walked over

and embraced his rival in the ring, drinking in his fraternal sweat.

This is enough to make the audience, reversing its view, burst out

in sudden applause. My neighbor is right: they are not savages.

The crowd pouring out, under a sky full of silence and stars,

has just fought the most exhausting fight. It keeps quiet and

disappears furtively, without any energy left for post mortems.

There is good and there is evil; that religion is merciless. The band

of faithful is now no more than a group of black-and-white

shadows disappearing into the night. For force and violence are

solitary gods. They contribute nothing to memory. On the contrary,

they distribute their miracles by the handful in the present. They

are made for this race without past which celebrates its

communions around the prize ring. These are rather difficult rites

but ones that simplify everything. Good and evil, winner and loser.

At Corinth two temples stood side by side, the temple of Violence

and the temple of Necessity.

Monuments

For many reasons due as much to economics as to metaphysics,

it may be said that the Oranese style, if there is one, forcefully and

clearly appears in the extraordinary edifice called the Maison du

Colon. Oran hardly lacks monuments. The city has its quota of

imperial marshals, ministers, and local benefactors. They are found

on dusty little squares, resigned to rain and sun, they too converted

to stone and boredom. But, in any case, they represent

contributions from the outside. In that happy barbary they are the

regrettable marks of civilization.

Oran, on the other hand, has raised up her altars and rostra to

her own honor. In the very heart of the mercantile city, having to

construct a common home for the innumerable agricultural

organizations that keep this country alive, the people of Oran

conceived the idea of building solidly a convincing image of their

virtues: the Maison du Colon. To judge from the edifice, those

virtues are three in number: boldness in taste, love of violence, and

a feeling for historical syntheses. Egypt, Byzantium, and Munich

collaborated in the delicate construction of a piece of pastry in the

shape of a bowl upside down. Multicolored stones, most vigorous

in effect, have been brought in to outline the roof. These mosaics

are so exuberantly persuasive that at first you see nothing but an

amorphous effulgence. But with a closer view and your attention

called to it, you discover that they have a meaning: a graceful

colonist, wearing a bow tie and white pith helmet, is receiving the

homage of a procession of slaves dressed in classical style.[37] The

edifice and its colored illustrations have been set down in the

middle of a square in the to-and-fro of the little two-car trams

whose filth is one of the charms of the city.

Oran greatly cherishes also the two lions of its Place d’Armes,

or parade ground. Since 1888 they have been sitting in state on

opposite sides of the municipal stairs. Their author was named (

ain. They have majesty and a stubby torso. It is said that at night

they get down from their pedestal one after the other, silently pace

around the dark square, and on occasion uninate at length under the

big, dusty ficus trees. These, of course, are rumors to which the

people of Oran lend an indulgent ear. But it is unlikely.

Despite a certain amount of research, I have not been able to

get interested in Cain. I merely learned that he had the reputation

of being a skillful animal-sculptor. Yet I often think of him. This is

an intellectual bent that comes naturally in Oran. Here is a

sonorously named artist who left an unimportant work here.

Several hundred thousand people are familiar with the easygoing

beasts he put in front of a pretentious town hall. This is one way of

succeeding in art. To be sure, these two lions, like thousands of

works of the same type, are proof of something else than talent.

Others have created “The Night Watch,” “Saint Francis Receiving

the Stigmata,” “David,” or the Pharsalian bas-relief called “The

Glorification of the Flower.” Cain, on the other hand, set up two

hilarious snouts on the square of a mercantile province overseas.

But the David will go down one day with Florence and the lions

will perhaps be saved from the catastrophe. Let me repeat, they are

proof of something else.

Can one state this idea clearly? In this work there are

insignificance and solidity. Spirit counts for nothing and matter for

a great deal. Mediocrity insists upon lasting by all means,

including bronze. It is refused a right to eternity, and every day it

takes that right. Is it not eternity itself? In any event, such

perseverance is capable of stirring, and it involves its lesson, that

of all the monuments of Oran, and of Oran herself. An hour a day,

every so often, it forces you to pay attention to something that has

no importance. The mind profits from such recurrences. In a sense

this is its hygiene, and since it absolutely needs its moments of

humility, it seems to me that this chance to indulge in stupidity is

better than others. Everything that is ephemeral wants to last. Let

us say that everything wants to last. Human productions mean

nothing else, and in this regard Cain’s lions have the same chances

as the ruins of Angkor. This disposes one toward modesty.

There are other Oranese monuments. Or at least they deserve

this name because they, too, stand for their city, and perhaps in a

more significant way. They are the public works at present

covering the coast for some ten kilometers. Apparently it is a

matter of transforming the most luminous of bays into a gigantic

harbor. In reality it is one more chance for man to come to grips

with stone.

In the paintings of certain Flemish masters a theme of

strikingly general application recurs insistently: the building of the

Tower of Babel. Vast landscapes, rocks climbing up to heaven,

steep slopes teeming with workmen, animals, ladders, strange

machines, cords, pulleys. Man, moreover, is there only to give

scale to the inhuman scope of the construction. This is what the

Oran coast makes one think of, west of the city.

Clinging to vast slopes, rails, dump-cars, cranes, tiny trains ...

Under a broiling sun, toy-like locomotives round huge blocks of

stone amid whistles, dust, and smoke. Day and night a nation of

ants bustles about on the smoking carcass of the mountain.

Clinging all up and down a single cord against the side of the cliff,

dozens of men, their bellies pushing against the handles of

automatic drills, vibrate in empty space all day long and break off

whole masses of rock that hurtle down in dust and rumbling.

Farther on, dump-carts tip their loads over the slopes; and the

rocks, suddenly poured seaward, bound and roll into the water,

each large lump followed by a scattering of lighter stones. At

regular intervals, at dead of night or in broad daylight, detonations

shake the whole mountain and stir up the sea itself.

Man, in this vast construction field, makes a frontal attack on

stone. And if one could forget, for a moment at least, the harsh

slavery that makes this work possible, one would have to admire.

These stones, torn from the mountain, serve man in his plans. They

pile up under the first waves, gradually emerge, and finally take

their place to form a jetty, soon covered with men and machines

which advance, day after day, toward the open sea. Without

stopping, huge steel jaws bite into the cliff’s belly, turn round, and

disgorge into the water their overflowing gravel. As the coastal

cliff is lowered, the whole coast encroaches irresistibly on the sea.

Of course, destroying stone is not possible. It is merely moved

from one place to another. In any case, it will last longer than the

men who use it. For the moment, it satisfies their will to action.

That in itself is probably useless. But moving things about is the

work of men; one must choose doing that or nothing.[38] Obviously

the people of Oran have chosen. In front of that indifferent bay, for

many years more they will pile up stones along the coast. In a

hundred years—tomorrow, in other words—they will have to

begin again. But today these heaps of rocks testify for the men in

masks of dust and sweat who move about among them. The true

monuments of Oran are still her stones.

Ariadne’s Stone

It seems that the people of Oran are like that friend of Flaubert

who, on the point of death, casting a last glance at this

irreplaceable earth, exclaimed:

“Close the window; it’s too

beautiful.” They have closed the window, they have walled

themselves in, they have cast out the landscape. But Flaubert’s

friend, Le Poittevin, died, and after him days continued to be added

to days. Likewise, beyond the yellow walls of Oran, land and sea

continue their indifferent dialogue. That permanence in the world

has always had contrary charms for man. It drives him to despair

and excites him. The world never says but one thing; first it

interests, then it bores. But eventually it wins out by dint of

obstinacy. It is always right.

Already, at the very gates of Oran, nature raises its voice. In

the direction of Canastel there are vast wastelands covered with

fragrant brush. There sun and wind speak only of solitude. Above

Oran there is the mountain of Santa-Cruz, the plateau and the

myriad ravines leading to it. Roads, once carriageable, cling to the

slopes overhanging the sea. In the month of January some are

covered with flowers. Daisies and buttercups turn them into

sumptuous paths, embroidered in yellow and white. About Sant-

Cruzz everything has been said. But if I were to speak of it, I

should forget the sacred processions that climb the rugged hill on

feast days, in order to recall other pilgrimages. Solitary, they walk

in the red stone, rise above the motionless bay, and come to

dedicate to nakedness a luminous, perfect hour.

Oran has also its deserts of sand: its beaches. Those

encountered near the gates are deserted only in winter and spring.

Then they are plateaus covered with asphodels, peopled with bare

little cottages among the flowers. The sea rumbles a bit, down

below. Yet already the sun, the faint breeze, the whiteness of the

asphodels, the sharp blue of the sky, everything makes one fancy

summer—the golden youth then covering the beach, the long hours

on the sand and the sudden softness of evening. Each year on these

shores there is a new harvest of girls in flower. Apparently they

have but one season. The following year, other cordial blossoms

take their place, which, the summer before, were still little girls

with bodies as hard as buds. At eleven a.m., coming down from the

plateau, all that young flesh, lightly clothed in motley materials,

breaks on the sand like a multicolored wave.

One has to go farther (strangely close, however, to that spot

where two hundred thousand men are laboring) to discover a still

virgin landscape: long, deserted dunes where the passage of men

has left no other trace than a worm-eaten hut. From time to time an

Arab shepherd drives along the top of the dunes the black and

beige spots of his flock of goats. On the beaches of the Oran

country every summer morning seems to be the first in the world.

Each twilight seems to be the last, solemn agony, announced at

sunset by a final glow that darkens every hue. The sea is

ultramarine, the road the color of clotted blood, the beach yellow.

Everything disappears with the green sun; an hour later the dunes

are bathed in moonlight. Then there are incomparable nights under

a rain of stars. Occasionally storms sweep over them, and the

lightning flashes flow along the dunes, whiten the sky, and give the

sand and one’s eyes orange-colored glints.

But this cannot be shared. One has to have lived it. So much

solitude and nobility give these places an unforgettable aspect. In

the warm moment before daybreak, after confronting the first

bitter, black waves, a new creature breasts night’s heavy,

enveloping water. The memory of those joys does not make me

regret them, and thus I recognize that they were good. After so

many years they still last, somewhere in this heart which finds

unswerving loyalty so difficult. And I know that today, if I were to

go to the deserted dune, the same sky would pour down on me its

cargo of breezes and stars. These are lands of innocence.

But innocence needs sand and stones. And man has forgotten

how to live among them. At least it seems so, for he has taken

refuge in this extraordinary city where boredom sleeps.

Nevertheless, that very confrontation constitutes the value of Oran.

The capital of boredom, besieged by innocence and beauty, it is

surrounded by an army in which every stone is a soldier. In the

city, and at certain hours, however, what a temptation to go over to

the enemy! What a temptation to identify oneself with those

stones, to melt into that burning and impassive universe that defies

history and its ferments! That is doubtless futile. But there is in

every man a profound instinct which is neither that of destruction

nor that of creation. It is merely a matter of resembling nothing. In

the shadow of the warm walls of Oran, on its dusty asphalt, that

invitation is sometimes heard. It seems that, for a time, the minds

that yield to it are never disappointed. This is the darkness of

Eurydice and the sleep of Isis. Here are the deserts where thought

will collect itself, the cool hand of evening on a troubled heart. On

this Mount of Olives, vigil is futile; the mind recalls and approves

the sleeping Apostles. Were they really wrong? They nonetheless

had their revelation.

Just think of Sakyamuni in the desert. He remained there for

years on end, squatting motionless with his eyes on heaven. The

very gods envied him that wisdom and that stone-like destiny. In

his outstretched hands the swallows had made their nest. But one

day they flew away, answering the call of distant lands. And he

who had stifled in himself desire and will, fame and suffering,

began to cry. It happens thus that flowers grow on rocks. Yes, let

us accept stone when it is necessary. That secret and that rapture

we ask of faces can also be given us by stone. To be sure, this

cannot last. But what can last, after all? The secret of faces fades

away, and there we are, cast back to the chain of desires. And if

stone can do no more for us than the human heart, at least it can do

just as much.

“Oh, to be nothing!” For thousands of years this great cry has

roused millions of men to revolt against desire and pain. Its dying

echoes have reached this far, across centuries and oceans, to the

oldest sea in the world. They still reverberate dully against the

compact cliffs of Oran. Everybody in this country follows this

advice without knowing it. Of course, it is almost futile.

Nothingness cannot be achieved any more than the absolute can.

But since we receive as favors the eternal signs brought us by roses

or by human suffering, let us not refuse either the rare invitations

to sleep that the earth addresses us. Each has as much truth as the

other.

This, perhaps, is the Ariadne’s thread of this somnambulist and

frantic city. Here one learns the virtues, provisional to be sure, of a

certain kind of boredom. In order to be spared, one must say “yes”

to the Minotaur. This is an old and fecund wisdom. Above the sea,

silent at the base of the red cliffs, it is enough to maintain a

delicate equilibrium halfway between the two massive headlands

which, on the right and left, dip into the clear water. In the puffing

of a coast-guard vessel crawling along the water far out bathed in

radiant light, is distinctly heard the muffled call of inhuman and

glittering forces: it is the Minotaur’s farewell.

It is noon; the very day is being weighed in the balance. His

rite accomplished, the traveler receives the reward of his liberation:

the little stone, dry and smooth as an asphodel, that he picks up on

the cliff. For the initiate the world is no heavier to bear than this

stone. Atlas’s task is easy; it is sufficient to choose one’s hour.

Then one realizes that for an hour, a month, a year, these shores

can indulge in freedom. They welcome pell-mell, without even

looking at them, the monk, the civil servant, or the conqueror.

There are days when I expected to meet, in the streets of Oran,

Descartes or Cesare Borgia. That did not happen. But perhaps

another will be more fortunate. A great deed, a great work, virile

meditation used to call for the solitude of sands or of the convent.

There were kept the spiritual vigils of arms. Where could they be

better celebrated now than in the emptiness of a big city

established for some time in unintellectual beauty?

Here is the little stone, smooth as an asphodel. It is at the

beginning of everything. Flowers, tears (if you insist), departures,

and struggles are for tomorrow. In the middle of the day when the

sky opens its fountains of light in the vast, sonorous space, all the

headlands of the coast look like a fleet about to set out. Those

heavy galleons of rock and light are trembling on their keels as if

they were preparing to steer for sunlit isles. O mornings in the

country of Oran! From the high plateaus the swallows plunge into

huge troughs where the air is seething. The whole coast is ready

for departure; a shiver of adventure ripples through it. Tomorrow,

perhaps, we shall leave together.

(1939)

Helen’s Exile

The mediterranean sun has something tragic about it, quite

different from the tragedy of fogs. Certain evenings at the base of

the seaside mountains, night falls over the flawless curve of a little

bay, and there rises from the silent waters a sense of anguished

fulfillment. In such spots one can understand that if the Greeks

knew despair, they always did so through beauty and its stifling

quality. In that gilded calamity, tragedy reaches its highest point.

Our time, on the other hand, has fed its despair on ugliness and

convulsions. This is why Europe would be vile, if suffering could

ever be so. We have exiled beauty; the Greeks took up arms for

her. First difference, but one that has a history. Greek thought

always took refuge behind the conception of limits. It never carried

anything to extremes, neither the sacred nor reason, because it

negated nothing, neither the sacred nor reason. It took everything

into consideration, balancing shadow with light. Our Europe, on

the other hand, off in the pursuit of totality, is the child of

disproportion. She negates beauty, as she negates whatever she

does not glorify. And, through all her diverse ways, she glorifies

but one thing, which is the future rule of reason. In her madness

she extends the eternal limits, and at that very moment dark

Erinyes fall upon her and tear her to pieces. Nemesis, the goddess

of measure and not of revenge, keeps watch. All those who

overstep the limit are pitilessly punished by her.

The Greeks, who for centuries questioned themselves as to

what is just, could understand nothing of our idea of justice. For

them equity implied a limit, whereas our whole continent is

convulsed in its search for a justice that must be total. At the dawn

of Greek thought Hera-clitus was already imagining that justice

sets limits for the physical universe itself:

“The sun will not

overstep his measures; if he does, the Erinyes, the handmaids of

justice, will find him out.”1 We who have cast the universe and

spirit out of our sphere laugh at that threat. In a drunken sky we

light up the suns we want. But nonetheless the boundaries exist,

and we know it. In our wildest aberrations we dream of an

equilibrium we have left behind, which we naively expect to find

at the end of our errors. Childish presumption which justifies the

fact that child-nations, inheriting our follies, are now directing our

history.

A fragment attributed to the same Heraclitus simply states:

“Presumption, regression of progress.” And, many centuries after

the man of Ephesus, Socrates, facing the threat of being

condemned to death, acknowledged only this one superiority in

himself: what he did not know he did not claim to know. The most

exemplary life and thought of those centuries close on a proud

confession of ignorance. Forgetting that, we have forgotten our

virility. We have preferred the power that apes greatness, first

Alexander and then the Roman conquerors whom the authors of

our schoolbooks, through some incomparable vulgarity, teach us to

admire. We, too, have conquered, moved boundaries, mastered

heaven and earth. Our reason has driven all away. Alone at last,

we end up by ruling over a desert. What imagination could we

have left for that higher equilibrium in which nature balanced

history, beauty, virtue, and which applied the music of numbers

even to blood-tragedy? We turn our backs on nature; we are

ashamed of beauty. Our wretched tragedies have a smell of the

office clinging to them, and the blood that trickles from them is the

color of printer’s ink.

This is why it is improper to proclaim today that we are the

sons of Greece. Or else we are the renegade sons. Placing history

on the throne of God, we are progressing toward theocracy like

those whom the Greeks called Barbarians and whom they fought to

death in the waters of Salamis. In order to realize how we differ,

one must turn to him among our philosophers who is the true rival

of Plato. “Only the modern city,” Hegel dares write, “offers the

mind a field in which it can become aware of itself.” We are thus

living in the period of big cities. Deliberately, the world has been

amputated of all that constitutes its permanence: nature, the sea,

hilltops, evening meditation. Consciousness is to be found only in

the streets, because history is to be found only in the streets—this

is the edict. And consequently our most significant works show the

same bias. Landscapes are not to be found in great European

literature since Dostoevsky. History explains neither the natural

universe that existed before it nor the beauty that exists above it.

Hence it chose to be ignorant of them. Whereas Plato contained

everything—nonsense, reason, and myth—our philosophers

contain nothing but nonsense or reason because they have closed

their eyes to the rest. The mole is meditating.

It is Christianity that began substituting the tragedy of the soul

for contemplation of the world. But, at least, Christianity referred

to a spiritual nature and thereby preserved a certain fixity. With

God dead, there remains only history and power. For some time

the entire effort of our philosophers has aimed solely at replacing

the notion of human nature with that of situation, and replacing

ancient harmony with the disorderly advance of chance or reason’s

pitiless progress. Whereas the Greeks gave to will the boundaries

of reason, we have come to put the will’s impulse in the very

center of reason, which has, as a result, become deadly. For the

Greeks, values pre-existed all action, of which they definitely set

the limits. Modern philosophy places its values at the end of

action. They are not but are becoming, and we shall know them

fully only at the completion of history. With values, all limit

disappears, and since conceptions differ as to what they will be,

since all struggles, without the brake of those same values, spread

indefinitely, today’s Messianisms confront one another and their

clamors mingle in the clash of empires. Disproportion is a

conflagration, according to Heraclitus. The conflagration is

spreading; Nietzsche is outdistanced. Europe no longer

philosophizes by striking a hammer, but by shooting a cannon.

Nature is still there, however. She contrasts her calm skies and

her reasons with the madness of men. Until the atom too catches

fire and history ends in the triumph of reason and the agony of the

species. But the Greeks never said that the limit could not he

overstepped. They said it existed and that whoever dared to exceed

it was mercilessly struck down. Nothing in present history can

contradict them.

The historical spirit and the artist both want to remake the

world. But the artist, through an obligation of his nature, knows his

limits, which the historical spirit fails to recognize. This is why the

latter’s aim is tyranny whereas the former’s passion is freedom. All

those who are struggling for freedom today are ultimately fighting

for beauty. Of course, it is not a question of defending beauty for

itself. Beauty cannot do without man, and we shall not give our era

its nobility and serenity unless we follow it in its misfortune. Never

again shall we be hermits. But it is no less true that man cannot do

without beauty, and this is what our era pretends to want to

disregard. It steels itself to attain the absolute and authority; it

wants to transfigure the world before having exhausted it, to set it

to rights before having understood it. Whatever it may say, our era

is deserting this world. Ulysses can choose at Calypso’s bidding

between immortality and the land of his fathers. He chooses the

land, and death with it. Such simple nobility is foreign to us today.

Others will say that we lack humility; but, all things considered,

this word is ambiguous. Like Dostoevsky’s fools who boast of

everything, soar to heaven, and end up flaunting their shame in any

public place, we merely lack man’s pride, which is fidelity to his

limits, lucid love of his condition.

“I hate my time,” Saint-Exupery wrote shortly before his death,

for reasons not far removed from those I have spoken of. But,

however upsetting that exclamation, coming from him who loved

men for their admirable qualities, we shall not accept responsibility

for it. Yet what a temptation, at certain moments, to turn one’s

back on this bleak, fleshless world! But this time is ours, and we

cannot live hating ourselves. It has fallen so low only through the

excess of its virtues as well as through the extent of its vices. We

shall fight for the virtue that has a history. What virtue? The horses

of Patroclus weep for their master killed in battle. All is lost. But

Achilles resumes the fight, and victory is the outcome, because

friendship has just been assassinated: friendship is a virtue.

Admission of ignorance, rejection of fanaticism, the limits of

the world and of man, the beloved face, and finally beauty—this is

where we shall be on the side of the Greeks. In a certain sense, the

direction history will take is not the one we think. It lies in the

struggle between creation and inquisition. Despite the price which

artists will pay for their empty hands, we may hope for their

victory. Once more the philosophy of darkness will break and fade

away over the dazzling sea. O midday thought, the Trojan war is

being fought far from the battlefields! Once more the dreadful

walls of the modern city will fall to deliver up—“soul serene as the

ocean’s calm”—the beauty of Helen.

(1948)

Return To Tipasa

You have navigated with raging soul far from the paternal
home, passing beyond the sea’s double rocks, and you now inhabit
a foreign land.
—Medea

For five days rain had been falling ceaselessly on Algiers and

had finally wet the sea itself. From an apparently inexhaustible

sky, constant downpours, viscous in their density, streamed down

upon the gulf. Gray and soft as a huge sponge, the sea rose slowly

in the ill-defined bay. But the surface of the water seemed almost

motionless under the steady rain. Only now and then a barely

perceptible swelling motion would raise above the sea’s surface a

vague puff of smoke that would come to dock in the harbor, under

an arc of wet boulevards. The city itself, all its white walls

dripping, gave off a different steam that went out to meet the first

steam. Whichever way you turned, you seemed to be breathing

water, to be drinking the air.

In front of the soaked sea I walked and waited in that

December Algiers, which was for me the city of summers. I had

fled Europe’s night, the winter of faces. But the summer city

herself had been emptied of her laughter and offered me only bent

and shining backs. In the evening, in the crudely lighted cafes

where I took refuge, I read my age in faces I recognized without

being able to name them. I merely knew that they had been young

with me and that they were no longer so.

Yet I persisted without very well knowing what I was waiting

for, unless perhaps the moment to go back to Tipasa. To be sure, it

is sheer madness, almost always punished, to return to the sites of

one’s youth and try to relive at forty what one loved or keenly

enjoyed at twenty. But I was forewarned of that madness. Once

already I had returned to Tipasa, soon after those war years that

marked for me the end of youth. I hoped, I think, to recapture there

a freedom I could not forget. In that spot, indeed, more than twenty

years ago, I had spent whole mornings wandering among the ruins,

breathing in the wormwood, warming myself against the stones,

discovering little roses, soon plucked of their petals, which outlive

the spring. Only at noon, at the hour when the cicadas themselves

fell silent as if overcome, I would flee the greedy glare of an all-

consuming light. Sometimes at night I would sleep open-eyed

under a sky dripping with stars. I was alive then. Fifteen years later

I found my ruins, a few feet from the first waves, I followed the

streets of the forgotten walled city through fields covered with

bitter trees, and on the slopes overlooking the hay I still caressed

the bread-colored columns. But the ruins were now surrounded

with barbed wire and could be entered only through certain

openings. It was also forbidden, for reasons which it appears that

morality approves, to walk there at night; by day one encountered

an official guardian. It just happened, that morning, that it was

raining over the whole extent of the ruins.

Disoriented, walking through the wet, solitary countryside, I

tried at least to recapture that strength, hitherto always at hand, that

helps me to accept what is when once I have admitted that I cannot

change it. And I could not, indeed, reverse the course of time and

restore to the world the appearance I had loved which had

disappeared in a day, long before. The second of September 1939,

in fact, I had not gone to Greece, as I was to do. War, on the

contrary, had come to us, then it had spread over Greece herself.

That distance, those years separating the warm ruins from the

barbed wire were to be found in me, too, that day as I stood before

the sarcophaguses full of black water or under the sodden

tamarisks. Originally brought up surrounded by beauty which was

my only wealth, I had begun in plenty. Then had come the barbed

wire—I mean tyrannies, war, police forces, the era of revolt. One

had had to put oneself right with the authorities of night: the day’s

beauty was but a memory. And in this muddy Tipasa the memory

itself was becoming dim. It was indeed a question of beauty,

plenty, or youth! In the light from conflagrations the world had

suddenly shown its wrinkles and its wounds, old and new. It had

aged all at once, and we with it. I had come here looking for a

certain “lift”; but I realized that it inspires only the man who is

unaware that he is about to launch forward. No love without a little

innocence. Where was the innocence? Empires were tumbling

down; nations and men were tearing at one another’s throats; our

hands were soiled. Originally innocent without knowing it, we

were now guilty without meaning to be: the mystery was

increasing with our knowledge. This is why, O mockery, we were

concerned with morality. Weak and disabled, I was dreaming of

virtue! In the days of innocence I didn’t even know that morality

existed. I knew it now, and I was not capable of living up to its

standard. On the promontory that I used to love, among the wet

columns of the ruined temple, I seemed to be walking behind

someone whose steps I could still hear on the stone slabs and

mosaics but whom I should never again overtake. I went back to

Paris and remained several years before returning home.

Yet I obscurely missed something during all those years. When

one has once had the good luck to love intensely, life is spent in

trying to recapture that ardor and that illumination. Forsaking

beauty and the sensual happiness attached to it, exclusively serving

misfortune, calls for a nobility I lack. But, after all, nothing is true

that forces one to exclude. Isolated beauty ends up simpering;

solitary justice ends up oppressing. Whoever aims to serve one

exclusive of the other serves no one, not even himself, and

eventually serves injustice twice. A day comes when, thanks to

rigidity, nothing causes wonder any more, everything is known,

and life is spent in beginning over again. These are the days of

exile, of desiccated life, of dead souls. To come alive again, one

needs a special grace, self-forgetfulness, or a homeland. Certain

mornings, on turning a corner, a delightful dew falls on the heart

and then evaporates. But its coolness remains, and this is what the

heart requires always. I had to set out again.

And in Algiers a second time, still walking under the same

downpour which seemed not to have ceased since a departure I had

thought definitive, amid the same vast melancholy smelling of rain

and sea, despite this misty sky, these backs fleeing under the

shower, these cafes whose sulphureous light distorted faces, I

persisted in hoping. Didn’t I know, besides, that Algiers rains,

despite their appearance of never meaning to end, nonetheless stop

in an instant, like those streams in my country which rise in two

hours, lay waste acres of land, and suddenly dry up? One evening,

in fact, the rain ceased. I waited one night more. A limpid morning

rose, dazzling, over the pure sea. From the sky, fresh as a daisy,

washed over and over again by the rains, reduced by these repeated

washings to its finest and clearest texture, emanated a vibrant light

that gave to each house and each tree a sharp outline, an astonished

newness. In the world’s morning the earth must have sprung forth

in such a light. I again took the road for Tipasa.

For me there is not a single one of those sixty-nine kilometers

that is not filled with memories and sensations. Turbulent

childhood, adolescent daydreams in the drone of the bus’s motor,

mornings, unspoiled girls, beaches, young muscles always at the

peak of their effort, evening’s slight anxiety in a sixteen-year-old

heart, lust for life, fame, and ever the same sky throughout the

years, unfailing in strength and light, itself insatiable, consuming

one by one over a period of months the victims stretched out in the

form of crosses on the beach at the deathlike hour of noon. Always

the same sea, too, almost impalpable in the morning light, which I

again saw on the horizon as soon as the road, leaving the Sahel and

its bronze-colored vineyards, sloped down toward the coast. But I

did not stop to look at it. I wanted to see again the Chenoua, that

solid, heavy mountain cut out of a single block of stone, which

borders the bay of Tipasa to the west before dropping down into

the sea itself. It is seen from a distance, long before arriving, a

light, blue haze still confused with the sky. But gradually it is

condensed, as you advance toward it, until it takes on the color of

the surrounding waters, a huge motionless wave whose amazing

leap upward has been brutally solidified above the sea calmed all

at once. Still nearer, almost at the gates of Tipasa, here is its

frowning bulk, brown and green, here is the old mossy god that

nothing will ever shake, a refuge and harbor for its sons, of whom I

am one.

While watching it I finally got through the barbed wire and

found myself among the ruins. And under the glorious December

light, as happens but once or twice in lives which ever after can

consider themselves favored to the full, I found exactly what I had

come seeking, what, despite the era and the world, was offered me,

truly to me alone, in that forsaken nature. From the forum strewn

with olives could be seen the village down below. No sound came

from it; wisps of smoke rose in the limpid air. The sea likewise

was silent as if smothered under the unbroken shower of dazzling,

cold light. From the Chenoua a distant cock’s crow alone

celebrated the day’s fragile glory. In the direction of the ruins, as

far as the eye could see, there was nothing but pock-marked stones

and wormwood, trees and perfect columns in the transparence of

the crystalline air. It seemed as if the morning were stabilized, the

sun stopped for an incalculable moment. In this light and this

silence, years of wrath and night melted slowly away. I listened to

an almost forgotten sound within myself as if my heart, long

stopped, were calmly beginning to beat again. And awake now, I

recognized one by one the imperceptible sounds of which the

silence was made up: the figured bass of the birds, the sea’s faint,

brief sighs at the foot of the rocks, the vibration of the trees, the

blind singing of the columns, the rustling of the wormwood plants,

the furtive lizards. I heard that; I also listened to the happy torrents

rising within me. It seemed to me that I had at last come to harbor,

for a moment at least, and that henceforth that moment would be

endless. But soon after, the sun rose visibly a degree in the sky. A

magpie preluded briefly, and at once, from all directions, birds’

songs burst out with energy, jubilation, joyful discordance, and

infinite rapture. The day started up again. It was to carry me to

evening.

At noon on the half-sandy slopes covered with heliotropes like

a foam left by the furious waves of the last few days as they

withdrew, I watched the sea barely swelling at that hour with an

exhausted motion, and I satisfied the two thirsts one cannot long

neglect without drying up—I mean loving and admiring. For there

is merely bad luck in not being loved; there is misfortune in not

loving. All of us, today, are dying of this misfortune. For violence

and hatred dry up the heart itself; the long fight for justice exhausts

the love that nevertheless gave birth to it. In the clamor in which

we live, love is impossible and justice does not suffice. This is why

Europe hates daylight and is only able to set injustice up against

injustice. But in order to keep justice from shriveling up like a

beautiful orange fruit containing nothing but a bitter, dry pulp, I

discovered once more at Tipasa that one must keep intact in

oneself a freshness, a cool wellspring of joy, love the day that

escapes injustice, and return to combat having won that light. Here

I recaptured the former beauty, a young sky, and I measured my

luck, realizing at last that in the worst years of our madness the

memory of that sky had never left me. This was what in the end

had kept me from despairing. I had always known that the ruins of

Tipasa were younger than our new constructions or our bomb

damage. There the world began over again every day in an ever

new light. O light! This is the cry of all the characters of ancient

drama brought face to face with their fate. This last resort was

ours, too, and I knew it now. In the middle of winter I at last

discovered that there was in me an invincible summer.

I have again left Tipasa; I have returned to Europe and its

struggles. But the memory of that day still uplifts me and helps me

to welcome equally what delights and what crushes. In the difficult

hour we are living, what else can I desire than to exclude nothing

and to learn how to braid with white thread and black thread a

single cord stretched to the breaking-point? In everything I have

done or said up to now, I seem to recognize these two forces, even

when they work at cross-purposes. I have not been able to disown

the light into which I was born and yet I have not wanted to reject

the servitudes of this time. It would be too easy to contrast here

with the sweet name of Tipasa other more sonorous and crueler

names. For men of today there is an inner way, which I know well

from having taken it in both directions, leading from the spiritual

hilltops to the capitals of crime. And doubtless one can always rest,

fall asleep on the hilltop or board with crime. But if one forgoes a

part of what is, one must forgo being oneself; one must forgo

living or loving otherwise than by proxy. There is thus a will to

live without rejecting anything of life, which is the virtue I honor

most in this world. From time to time, at least, it is true that I

should like to have practiced it. Inasmuch as few epochs require as

much as ours that one should be equal to the best as to the worst, I

should like, indeed, to shirk nothing and to keep faithfully a doubl

memory. Yes, there is beauty and there are the humiliated.

Whatever may be the difficulties of the undertaking, I should like

never to be unfaithful either to one or to the others.

But this still resembles a moral code, and we live for something

that goes farther than morality. If we could only name it, what

silence! On the hill of Sainte-Salsa, to the east of Tipasa, the

evening is inhabited. It is still light, to tell the truth, but in this light

an almost invisible fading announces the day’s end. A wind rises,

young like the night, and suddenly the waveless sea chooses a

direction and flows like a great barren river from one end of the

horizon to the other. The sky darkens. Then begins the mystery, the

gods of night, the beyond-pleasure. But how to translate this? The

little coin I am carrying away from here has a visible surface, a

woman’s beautiful face which repeats to me all I have learned in

this day, and a worn surface which I feel under my fingers during

the return. What can that lipless mouth be saying, except what I am

told by another mysterious voice, within me, which every day

informs me of my ignorance and my happiness:

“The secret I am seeking lies hidden in a valley full of olive

trees, under the grass and the cold violets, around an old house that

smells of wood smoke. For more than twenty years I rambled over

that valley and others resembling it, I questioned mute goatherds, I

knocked at the door of deserted ruins. Occasionally, at the moment

of the first star in the still bright sky, under a shower of

shimmering light, I thought I knew. I did know, in truth. I still

know, perhaps. But no one wants any of this secret; I don’t want

any myself, doubtless; and I cannot stand apart from my people. I

live in my family, which thinks it rules over rich and hideous cities

built of stones and mists. Day and night it speaks up, and

everything bows before it, which bows before nothing: it is deaf to

all secrets. Its power that carries me bores me, nevertheless, and on

occasion its shouts weary me. But its misfortune is mine, and we

are of the same blood. A cripple, likewise, an accomplice and

noisy, have I not shouted among the stones? Consequently, I strive

to forget, I walk in our cities of iron and fire, I smile bravely at the

night, I hail the storms, I shall be faithful. I have forgotten, in truth:

active and deaf, henceforth. But perhaps someday, when we are

ready to die of exhaustion and ignorance, I shall be able to disown

our garish tombs and go and stretch out in the valley, under the

same light, and learn for the last time what I know.”

(1952)

The Artist And His Time

I. As an artist, have you chosen the role of witness?

This would take considerable presumption or a vocation I lack.

Personally I don’t ask for any role and I have but one real vocation.

As a man, I have a preference for happiness; as an artist, it seems

to me that I still have characters to bring to life without the help of

wars or of law-courts. But I have been sought out, as each

individual has been sought out. Artists of the past could at least

keep silent in the face of tyranny. The tyrannies of today are

improved; they no longer admit of silence or neutrality. One has to

take a stand, be either for or against. Well, in that case, I am

against. But this does not amount to choosing the comfortable role

of witness. It is merely accepting the time as it is, minding one’s

own business, in short. Moreover, you are forgetting that today

judges, accused, and witnesses exchange positions with exemplary

rapidity. My choice, if you think I am making one, would at least

be never to sit on a judge’s bench, or beneath it, like so many of

our philosophers. Aside from that, there is no dearth of

opportunities for action, in the relative. Trade-unionism is today

the first, and the most fruitful among them.

II. Is not the quixotism that has been criticized in your recent

works an idealistic and romantic definition of the artist’s role?

However words are perverted, they provisionally keep their

meaning. And it is clear to me that the romantic is the one who

chooses the perpetual motion of history, the grandiose epic, and the

announcement of a miraculous event at the end of time. If I have

tried to define something, it is, on the contrary, simply the common

existence of history and of man, everyday life with the most

possible light thrown upon it, the dogged struggle against one’s

own degradation and that of others.

It is likewise idealism, and of the worse kind, to end up by

hanging all action and all truth on a meaning of history that is not

implicit in events and that, in any case, implies a mythical aim.

Would it therefore be realism to take as the laws of history the

future—in other words, just what is not yet history, something of

whose nature we know nothing?

It seems to me, on the contrary, that I am arguing in favor of a

true realism against a mythology that is both illogical and deadly,

and against romantic nihilism whether it be bourgeois or allegedly

revolutionary. To tell the truth, far from being romantic, I believe

in the necessity of a rule and an order. I merely say that there can

be no question of just any rule whatsoever. And that it would be

surprising if the rule we need were given us by this disordered

society, or, on the other hand, by those doctrinaires who declare

themselves liberated from all rules and all scruples.

III. The Marxists and their followers likewise think they are

humanists. But for them human nature will be formed in the

classless society of the future.

To begin with, this proves that they reject at the present

moment what we all are: those humanists are accusers of man.

How can we be surprised that such a claim should have developed

in the world of court trials? They reject the man of today in the

name of the man of the future. That claim is religious in nature.

Why should it be more justified than the one which announces the

kingdom of heaven to come? In reality the end of history cannot

have, within the limits of our condition, any definable significance.

It can only be the object of a faith and of a new mystification. A

mystification that today is no less great than the one that of old

based colonial oppression on the necessity of saving the souls of

infidels.

IV. Is not that what in reality separates you from the intellectuals of the left?

You mean that is what separates those intellectuals from the

left? Traditionally the left has always been at war against injustice,

obscurantism, and oppression. It always thought that those

phenomena were interdependent. The idea that obscurantism can

lead to justice, the national interest to liberty, is quite recent. The

truth is that certain intellectuals of the left (not all, fortunately) are

today hypnotized by force and efficacy as our intellectuals of the

right were before and during the war. Their attitudes are different,

but the act of resignation is the same. The first wanted to be

realistic nationalists; the second want to be realistic socialists. In

the end they betray nationalism and socialism alike in the name of

a realism henceforth without content and adored as a pure, and

illusory, technique of efficacy.

This is a temptation that can, after all, be understood. But still,

however the question is looked at, the new position of the people

who call themselves, or think themselves, leftists consists in

saying: certain oppressions are justifiable because they follow the

direction, which cannot be justified, of history. Hence there are

presumably privileged executioners, and privileged by nothing.

This is about what was said in another context by Joseph de

Maistre, who has never been taken for an incendiary. But this is a

thesis which, personally, I shall always reject. Allow me to set up

against it the traditional point of view of what has been hitherto

called the left: all executioners are of the same family.

V. What can the artist do in the world of today?

He is not asked either to write about co-operatives or,

conversely, to lull to sleep in himself the sufferings endured by

others throughout history. And since you have asked me to speak

personally, I am going to do so as simply as I can. Considered as

artists, we perhaps have no need to interfere in the affairs of the

world. But considered as men, yes. The miner who is exploited or

shot down, the slaves in the camps, those in the colonies, the

legions of persecuted throughout the world—they need all those

who can speak to communicate their silence and to keep in touch

with them. I have not written, day after day, fighting articles and

texts, I have not taken part in the common struggles because I

desire the world to be covered with Greek statues and

masterpieces. The man who has such a desire does exist in me.

Except that he has something better to do in trying to instill life

into the creatures of his imagination. But from my first articles to

my latest book I have written so much, and perhaps too much, only

because I cannot keep from being drawn toward everyday life,

toward those, whoever they may be, who are humiliated and

debased. They need to hope, and if all keep silent or if they are

given a choice between two kinds of humiliation, they will be

forever deprived of hope and we with them. It seems to me

impossible to endure that idea, nor can he who cannot endure it lie

down to sleep in his tower. Not through virtue, as you see, but

through a sort of almost organic intolerance, which you feel or do

not feel. Indeed, I see many who fail to feel it, but I cannot envy

their sleep. This does not mean, however, that we must sacrifice

our artist’s nature to some social preaching or other. I have said

elsewhere why the artist was more than ever necessary. But if we

intervene as men, that experience will have an effect upon our

language. And if we are not artists in our language first of all, what

sort of artists are we? Even if, militants in our lives, we speak in

our works of deserts and of selfish love, the mere fact that our lives

are militant causes a special tone of voice to people with men that

desert and that love. I shall certainly not choose the moment when

we are beginning to leave nihilism behind to stupidly deny the

values of creation in favor of the values of humanity, or vice versa.

In my mind neither one is ever separated from the other and I

measure the greatness of an artist (Moliere, Tolstoy, Melville) by

the balance he managed to maintain between the two. Today, under

the pressure of events, we are obliged to transport that tension into

our lives likewise. This is why so many artists, bending under the

burden, take refuge in the ivory tower or, conversely, in the social

church. But as for me, I see in both choices a like act of

resignation. We must simultaneously serve suffering and beauty.

The long patience, “The strength, the secret cunning such service

calls for are the virtues that establish the very renascence we need.

One word more. This undertaking, I know, cannot be

accomplished without dangers and bitterness. We must accept the

dangers: the era of chairbound artists is over. But we must reject

the bitterness. One of the temptations of the artist is to believe

himself solitary, and in truth he bears this shouted at him with a

certain base delight. But this is not true. He stands in the midst of

all, in the same rank, neither higher nor lower, with all those who

are working and struggling. His very vocation, in the face of

oppression, is to open the prisons and to give a voice to the

sorrows and joys of all. This is where art, against its enemies,

justifies itself by proving precisely that it is no one’s enemy. By

itself art could probably not produce the renascence which implies

justice and liberty. But without it, that renascence would be

without forms and, consequently, would be nothing. Without

culture, and the relative freedom it implies, society, even when

perfect, is but a jungle. This is why any authentic creation is a gift

to the future.

(1953)

[1] From the point of view of the relative value of truth. On the other hand,

from the point of view of virile behavior, this scholar’s fragility may well make

us smile.

[2] Let us not miss this opportunity to point out the relative character of this

essay. Suicide may indeed be related to much more honorable considerations—

for example, the political suicides of protest, as they were called, during the

Chinese revolution.

[3] I have heard of an emulator of Peregrinos, a post-war writer who, after

having finished his first hook, committed suicide to attract attention to his work.

Attention was in fact attracted, but the book was judged no good.

[4] But not in the proper sense. This is not a definition, but rather an

enumeration of the feelings that may admit of the absurd. Still, the enumeration

finished, the absurd has nevertheless not been exhausted.

[5] Apropos of the notion of exception particularly and against Aristotle.

[6] It may be thought that I am neglecting here the essential problem, that

of faith. But I am not examining the philosophy of Kierkegaard or of Chestov or,

later on, of Husserl (this would call for a different place and a different attitude

of mind); I am simply borrowing a theme from them and examining whether its

consequences can fit the already established rules. It is merely a matter of

persistence.

[7] I did not say “excludes God,” which would still amount to asserting.

[8] Let me assert again: it is not the affirmation of God that is questioned

here, but rather the logic leading to that affirmation.

[9] Even the most rigorous epistemologies imply metaphysics. And to such

a degree that the metaphysic of many contemporary thinkers consists in having

nothing but an epistemology.

[10] A.—At that time reason had to adapt itself or die. It adapts itself. With

Plotinus, after being logical it becomes aesthetic. Metaphor takes the place of

the syllogism.

B.—Moreover, this is not Plotinus’ only contribution to phenomenology.

This whole attitude is already contained in the concept so dear to the

Alexandrian thinker that there is not only an idea of man but also an idea of

Socrates.

[11] I am concerned here with a factual comparison, not with an apology of

humility. The absurd man is the contrary of the reconciled man.

[12] Quantity sometimes constitutes quality. If I can believe the latest

restatements of scientific theory, all matter is constituted by centers of energy.

Their greater or lesser quantity makes its specificity more or less remarkable. A

billion ions and one ion differ not only in quantity but also in quality. It is easy

to find an analogy in human experience.

[13] Same reflection on a notion as different as the idea of eternal

nothingness. It neither adds anything to nor subtracts anything from reality. In

psychological experience of nothingness, it is by the consideration of what will

happen in two thousand years that our own nothingness truly takes on meaning.

In one of its aspects, eternal nothingness is made up precisely of the sum of lives

to come which will not be ours.

[14] The will is only the agent here: it tends to maintain consciousness. It

provides a discipline of life, and that is appreciable.

[15] What matters is coherence. We start out here from acceptance of the

world. But Oriental thought teaches that one can indulge in the same effort of

logic by choosing against the world. That is just as legitimate and gives this

essay its perspectives and its limits. But when the negation of the world is

pursued just as rigorously, one often achieves ( in certain Vedantic schools)

similar results regarding, for instance, the indifference of works. In a book of

great importance, Le Choix, Jean Grenier establishes in this way a veritable

“philosophy of indifference.”

[16] In the fullest sense and with his faults. A healthy attitude also includes

faults.

[17] At this point I am thinking of Moliere’s Alceste. Everything is so

simple, so obvious and so coarse. Alceste against Philinte,

[18] It is curious to note that the most intellectual kind of painting, the one

that tries to reduce reality to its essential elements, is ultimately but a visual

delight. All it has kept of the world is its color. (This is apparent particularly in

Leger.)

[19] If you stop to think of it, this explains the worst novels. Almost

everybody considers himself capable of thinking and, to a certain degree,

whether right or wrong, really does think. Very few, on the contrary, can fancy

themselves poets or artists in words. But from the moment when thought won

out over style, the mob invaded the novel. That is not such a great evil as is said. The best are led to make greater demands upon themselves. As for those who succumb, they did not deserve to survive.

[20] Malraux’s work, for instance. But it would have been necessary to deal

at the same time with the social question which in fact cannot be avoided by

absurd thought (even though that thought may put forward several solutions,

very different from one another). One must, however, limit oneself.

[21] “Stavrogin: ‘Do you believe in eternal life in the other world?’ Kirilov:

‘No, but in eternal life in this world.’”

[22] “Man simply invented God in order not to kill himself. That is the

summary of universal history down to this moment.”

[23] Boris de Schloezer.

[24] Gide’s curious and penetrating remark: almost all Dostoevsky’s heroes

are polygamous.

[25] Melville’s Moby Dick, for instance.

[26] It is worth noting that the works of Kafka can quite as legitimately be

interpreted in the sense of a social criticism (for instance in The Trial). It is

probable, moreover, that there is no need to choose. Both interpretations are

good. In absurd terms, as we have seen, revolt against men is also directed

against God: great revolutions are always metaphysical.

[27] In The Castle it seems that “distractions” in the Pascalian sense are

represented by the assistants who “distract” K. from his anxiety. If Frieda

eventually becomes the mistress of one of the assistants, this is because she

prefers the stage setting to truth, everyday life to shared anguish.

[28] This is obviously true only of the unfinished version of The Castle that

Kafka left us. But it is doubtful that the writer would have destroyed in the last

chapters his novel’s unity of tone.

[29] Purity of heart.

[30] The only character without hope in The Castle is Amalia. She is the one

with whom the Land Surveyor is most violently contrasted.

[31] On the two aspects of Kafka’s thought, compare “In the Penal Colony,”

published by the Cahiers du Sud (and in America by Partisan Review—

translator’s note): “Guilt [‘of man’ is understood] is never doubtful” and a

fragment of The Castle (Momus’s report): “The guilt of the Land Surveyor K. is

hard to establish.”

[32] What is offered above is obviously an interpretation of Kafka’s work.

But it is only fair to add that nothing prevents its being considered, aside from

any interpretation, from a purely aesthetic point of view. For instance, B.

Groethuysen in his remarkable preface to The Trial limits himself, more wisely

than we, to following merely the painful fancies of what he calls, most

strikingly, a daydreamer. It is the fate and perhaps the greatness of that work that

it offers everything and confirms nothing.

[33] May I take the ridiculous position of saying that I do not like the way

Gide exalts the body? He asks it to restrain its desire to make it keener. Thus he

comes dangerously near to those who in brothel slang are called involved or

brain-workers. Christianity also wants to suspend desire. But, more natural, it

sees a mortification in this. My friend Vincent, who is a cooper and junior

breast-stroke champion, has an even clearer view. He drinks when he is thirsty,

if he desires a woman tries to go to bed with her, and would marry her if he

loved her (this hasn’t yet happened). Afterward he always says: “I feel better”—

and this sums up vigorously any apology that might be made for satiety.

[34] Gogol’s Klestakov is met in Oran. He yawns and then: “I feel I shall

soon have to be concerned with something lofty.”

[35] Doubtless in memory of these good words, an Oran lecture-and-

discussion group has been founded under the name of Cogito-Club.

[36] And the new boulevard called Front-de-Mer.

[37] Another quality of the Algerian race is, as you see, candor.

[38] This essay deals with a certain temptation. It is essential to have known

it. One can then act or not, but with full knowledge of the facts.

Home