đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș jan-waclaw-machajski-state-socialism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:38:32. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: State Socialism Author: Jan WacĆaw Machajski Date: 1900 Topics: State socialism Source: Retrieved on April 21, 2012 from http://libcom.org/library/state-socialism
The following essay by the Polish revolutionary Jan WacĆaw Machajski
(1866â1926) is part of a larger work, âScientific Socialismâ, written in
1900. Machajski refers to this work as a âbrochureâ although it is
almost book-length; it is an extended critique of Volume II of Marxâs
Capital.
In âState Socialismâ Machajski quotes extensively from the writings of
Karl Johann Rodbertus (1805â1875), especially his âSocial Lettersâ to
Julius von Kirchmann (1802â1884). These two Prussian conservatives
carried on a debate about the foundations of political economy in
1850â1854. The fourth of Rodbertusâs âlettersâ was actually published
separately as a book under the name âDas Kapitalâ. A caustic but
detailed account of this debate can be found in Rosa Luxemburgâs The
Accumulation of Capital (Chapters 15â17). Rodbertus defended the labour
theory of value but, despite indulging in a lot of hand-wringing about
the plight of the workers, drew reactionary conclusions from his
analysis. Machajski found Rodbertusâs discussion of the capitalist
economy, especially at the national level, to be similar to Marxâs;
however, the particular issues Machajski wished to discuss are more
transparent in Rodbertus than in Marx â or in Engels, Kautsky, and
Plekhanov.
Machajskiâs page references to nineteenth century editions of the works
of Rodbertus have been replaced by references to the four-volume edition
of his works published in 1972. All endnotes are by the translator.
It is believed this is the first substantial piece of writing by
Machajski to appear in the English language. Alexandre Skirda has
published a French translation in his collection Le socialisme des
intellectuels (1979/2001) but it is considerably abridged. Nevertheless
Skirdaâs translation has been useful in finding proper translations of
the technical terms used in Machajskiâs essay. Skirda himself credits
Maxmilien Rubel for helping him with this problem.
â Malcolm Archibald, January 2011
According to classical economic doctrine[1], the development of the
capitalist mode of production is synonymous with the development of
national wealth, and the growth of the ânet national incomeâ and the
ânet national profitâ.
It is the size of the latter which determines the âstrength of a nationâ
and its culture; the ânet national profitâ represents the fund which
provides the upkeep for all non-productive labour, i.e. for the whole of
educated society.
It would seem that the more the source of profit becomes manifest, the
more exposed to scrutiny should become the ânet national profitâ.
However âscientific socialismâ, working from theoretical premises which
I have examined previously[2], takes a completely different approach to
this matter.
The concept of ânet national profitâ, established by the classical
economists, cannot be found in any of Marxâs economic works. It has
disappeared without a trace.
Profit, considered as the fund drawn upon by the privileged classes for
consumption, exists in Marxist doctrine only for the consumption of a
ârelatively small number of capitalists and large-scale landownersâ. It
constitutes only a portion of the value which is extracted from the
working class. The remaining portion is accumulated by the capitalists
and transformed into constant capital â into a continually increasing
quantity of the means of production. This is a manifestation of
capitalismâs intrinsic striving for unlimited development of the forces
of production â the characteristic which embodies its progressive
aspect.
So the wealth of a nation is not expressed by the growth of its ânet
national profitâ in the form of the fund for the consumption needs of
the whole of privileged society, but rather by the increase of the
productive forces of the country, which has no connection whatsoever
with consumption. This why it frequently happens that the national
wealth rises at the same time that the ânationalâ consumption falls.
Thus, even though it is functioning progressively, capitalism finds
itself in a obvious contradiction which implies its inevitable demise.
This characteristic contradiction under capitalism between national
production and ânational consumptionâ has long been noted by scientific
socialism. But despite this obvious contradiction, capitalism quietly
goes on thriving. The main thing is that those who predicted a quick
death for capitalism because of this contradiction sooner or later
become convinced of capitalismâs vitality which will ensure it a
prolonged existence. The most ardent Russian brains state as fact that
in Russia there is not the slightest force capable of shaking the
capitalist system (BeltovâPlekhanov)[3]. The most ardent Russian hearts
exclaim with enthusiasm: âCapitalism shall lead us to the Divine Lightâ
(Novoye Slovo [The New Word][4]). This dogma is pronounced at the same
time as Russia is ravaged by famines. Apparently the latter either do
not accurately express the contradictions between capitalist production
and consumption, or they are still too insignificant and have not
attained that degree of development which would allow them to overwhelm
the whole âprogressiveness of capitalist contradictionsâ.
Those whom capitalism has failed to âlead to the Divine Lightâ are
beginning, at last, to pose the question: why does capitalismâs
âprogressiveâ contradiction neglect to manifest itself, to declare its
âhistorical missionâ? Why does it not reveal itself as âthe incessant
and inexhaustible source of change of social formsâ?
If capitalismâs contradiction is so splendidly compensated for by its
own progressiveness, it is because, apparently, it satisfies the real
interests of certain people. Scientific socialism explains that the
progressiveness of capitalism consists in its development of the
productive forces until they become incompatible with the capitalist
system, thereby creating the preconditions for social forms which are
more just. Apparently this capitalist progressiveness satisfies the
interests of humanity in general. But humanity has not yet arrived at a
state where the action of interests of this kind can be seen to be
coming into play. Up till now the only real forces are those which
represent class interests.
The growth of capitalist progress is inconceivable without the growth of
educated society and the intelligentsia, of the army of intellectual
workers. Even those whose interests it is to call this class a
propertyless, educated proletariat, cannot conceal the fact that the
intelligentsia in its standard of living approaches the bourgeoisie
(Kautsky), i.e. that just like the bourgeoisie it enjoys a privileged
remuneration. Consequently, the growth of capitalism signifies the
growth of a ânew intermediate social orderâ which attains in its
developed form a bourgeois standard of living.
The more that this contradiction of capitalism, identified by Marxism as
âprogressiveâ, fails to be effective, the more the proletariat will
become conscious that this contradiction does not lead to the downfall
of capitalism precisely because its progressive feature satisfies the
real economic interests of educated society. The profits extracted by
the capitalists provide for the parasitical existence not just of a
âhandful of capitalists and large-scale landownersâ. It also allows the
possibility for the whole of educated society to possess a bourgeois
standard of living. Educated society, the whole army of intellectual
workers, is a consumer of the ânet national profitâ.
As the proletariat becomes conscious of this fact, it will become more
and more aware of that social force which up to now has diligently
concealed its own nature from the eyes of the proletariat, indeed has
identified itself with the proletariat: that force is the intellectual
worker. The proletariat will realize that it has been too trusting in
its relations with this force, which has joined it in attacking capital,
but for reasons of its own. For the attack on capital of the
intellectual workers consists in the demand for a âjustâ distribution of
the national profit for the benefit of educated society, a distribution
which is resisted by a handful of plutocrats, the âfeudal lords of
industryâ. The intellectual workers are struggling to attain legal
status in the class system, the sort of status which has always been
enjoyed by scholars, indeed anyone possessing knowledge. Increasingly
the proletariat will cease to view the army of intellectual workers as
allies, but rather see this army as a privileged class exercising power
over it. And increasingly the proletariat will modify those socialist
doctrines which originated in the period when there was complete trust
in the âintellectual workersâ. It is clear that during that period of
the struggle when the enemy was regarded as a friend, the exploitation
of the working class, as well as the basis of class rule and the goal of
the struggle, could only be understood in a manner which did not harm
the special interests of the intellectual worker.
The ultimate goal of proletarian struggle has been established by
scientific socialism as the transformation of commodity production into
socialist production by means of the transfer of land and all the means
of production into social property.
In Kautskyâs writings the reader will find in many places where he
explains that socialist thought was bogged down for a long time in
utopianism, before arriving at the scientific conclusion according to
which the eradication of exploitation does not require the removal of
objects of consumption from the sphere of personal ownership (as assumed
in primitive communism), but only the means of production. Following
this logic, one can only suppose that the âCommunist Manifestoâ, when it
proclaimed the abolition of personal property in general, was not yet
expressing the âultimate goalâ in its most mature form.
In what way does this just mentioned formula take into account the
special interests of the intellectual worker? Straightforward
discussions of this question are not to be found, of course, in
social-democratic literature which is intended to serve as propaganda
for the working class. This literature already serves a purpose in that
it is able to deflect the proletariat from examining the special
interests of the intellectual workers, which it claims are of no
importance. The proletarians are told that the intelligentsia is not
implicated in exploitation and lives by selling its own intellectual
work power. This is a popularization of that abstract economic doctrine
which declares inviolable the possessions of educated society.
But scientific socialismâs âinfallibleâ formula is virtually identical
with the socialist formula of Rodbertus. The latter, itâs true,
preferred to use the expression âthe transfer of the ownership of
capital into the hands of the stateâ rather than âthe transfer of
ownership of the means of production into the hands of societyâ.
Nevertheless, the reader will find both expressions used by Rodbertus.
Since he relates the socialist formula to educated society, we will find
in his work direct indications as to how this formula satisfies the
special interests of the intellectual workers.
In the Second Social Letter we read[5]:
â... The judge, ... the physician, ... the teacher ... receive incomes
for the creation of which they did not expend their own labour, incomes
which undoubtedly do not constitute the product of their own labour. But
all these persons receive their incomes from what the economists call
âthe second division of wealthâ, from the incomes of others who
participate in âthe first division of wealthâ. The former receive
incomes from the latter either directly or through the intermediary of
the state as compensation for services rendered to society, services
which may be onerous, indispensable, or useful. But there are also
people in society who take part in the first distribution of wealth, who
draw their incomes from it, and yet neither participate in generating
this wealth nor render any other equivalent service... Among these
people we find the landowner who does nothing in exchange for his
income, who hands over his piece of land to another to cultivate while
pocketing the rent. Then there is the capitalist who receives a
comfortable income in the form of dividends. And the entrepreneur who
uses hired managers to run his business.â
Itâs possible some social-democrats will find the tone of this passage
offensive. But they must admit that its content corresponds in detail to
the content of the Erfurt Program, according to which the only
ânon-workersâ in contemporary society are capitalists and large-scale
landowners. And this passage is completely in agreement with the general
doctrine of social-democracy according to which the intelligentsia are
non-participants in exploitation and live by the realization of their
own labour power. Rodbertus deals with this question as follows:
âIf I assert that the institution of personal ownership in land and
capital is the cause of the workers being deprived of part of their
output, I am by no means suggesting that the ability to make use of a
certain amount of capital to employ a large number of workers in
productive activity is not a public service which deserves to receive
compensation. Common sense tells us otherwise. Not only knowledge, but
also moral strength and moral action are required to successfully
supervise a large group of workers in a productive enterprise...
Services of this kind, however, are not rendered by the productive
workers themselves and by the nature of their occupations they are
unable to render such services. But these services are absolutely
necessary for national production. Therefore, since a claim can be made
for compensation for any social service, no one should question that
capitalists, landowners, entrepreneurs, and managers of enterprises can
also demand compensation for themselves for the above-mentioned useful
and necessary services with as much right as anyone else making claims
for services provided... such as, for example, a minister of trade or
public works, assuming that he fulfills his duties. Furthermore, these
services, just like the services of judges, teachers, physicians, etc.,
can receive their compensation only from the output of the workers, for
there is no other source of material wealth.â[6]
Rodbertus, starting from the basic position of social-democracy
according to which the intelligentsia is a non-participant in capitalist
exploitation, follows social-democracyâs logic which leads him to a
defense of... hard-working business owners. But is Rodbertus really
transgressing the scientific aspect of scientific socialism? Not in the
least. His socialist science is characterized by precision just like any
other science. In the case at hand, science defends the truth that
stripping away the means of production from the owners of land and
capital does not require depriving them of the fruits of their
intellectual labour, any more than it does in the case of intellectual
workers. The business owner is an exploiter so long as he delegates the
running of his enterprise to his own manager. But if he personally
manages his business and demands a salary no higher than that of, for
example, âComradeâ Millerand[7] , then he is as an intellectual worker
realizing his own special talents and abilities (as Kautsky says), or
his own skill at bossing a large bunch of workers (as Rodbertus crudely
expresses it).
If this explanation helps in the peaceful resolution of the âsocial
questionâ between âentrepreneursâ and âproletariansâ of the Millerand
type, it by no means addresses the social question which relates to the
situation of the âproductive workersâ. No matter what socialist
transformations take place, the latter are unable, by the nature of
their occupations, to render such âservicesâ as their âcomradesâ of the
Millerand type. From the point of view of proletarian socialism, one can
object strenuously to the state socialism of Rodbertus, which ârequires
work from anyâ member of society, only where he deals with that
exploitation to which the proletarian, i.e. the worker performing
physical labour, is subject, at the hands of educated society, i.e. at
the hands of the intellectual worker.
In the Fourth Social Letter, this question is discussed as follows:
âTo that part [of the national product] which is distributed in the form
of income to individuals, has a claim not only, for example, the worker
who grinds the point of a needle over and over, but also anyone who is
occupied with scientific or artistic work, or who carries out continuous
or intermittent managerial functions which are nowadays regarded as a
regular job. For in the general division of labour, the latter is as
much a worker as the former; and if the producers of material goods
enjoy the products of scholars and artists (and are therefore able to
devote themselves exclusively to the production of material goods), so
scholars and artists can commit themselves exclusively to the creation
of scholarly and artistic masterpieces because they have available the
objects of consumption created by others. The objects of consumption are
available to everyone, but the production of objects of consumptions,
and the labour involved in producing them, remains specialized.â[8]
Concerning the great happiness of the needle grinder in being able to
help (thanks to his specialized slave labour) in the development of the
arts and sciences, concerning his great honour to participate (thanks to
that specialization) in a heart-warming collaboration with scientists
and artists â concerning all this the economist, taking note of the
âsocializationâ of labour, speaks with the same crudity and arrogance as
the classical economists, who regarded the capitalist system as eternal.
This is the manner in which true socialist science interprets the
social-democratic doctrine that âknowledge is labour powerâ. The
possessors of this labour power â scholars â who provide the needle
grinder with so much pleasure and delight with their products of science
and the arts, are at the same time his co-workers â comrades in the
division of labour.
In the place just cited Rodbertus makes the following interesting
comment:
âThis relationship has given rise to an impulse to extend the field of
political economy in an unwarranted fashion to include the division of
labour in general (in society) which results in the abasement of
non-material goods to the level of economic goods. But ... although the
field of political economy concerns itself with the material goods
destined for producers of non-material goods, it nevertheless does not
deal with the services rendered in exchange for the latter.â[9]
This definition of political economy is acknowledged, of course, not
only by Rodbertus. It is acknowledged by all the economists, including
those who, as Rodbertus wittily notes, speak in the prefaces of their
books about the equivalency, in economic terms, of physical and
intellectual labour, while in fact the entire content of these books,
which never mention a word about the products of intellectual labour,
proves just the opposite. This observation can also be applied to Marxâs
treatise, if it is true as affirmed by the Sombarts and Ratners[10] that
Marx considered intellectual labour to be âproductiveâ, on a level with
physical labour. On the other hand, the only factor which accounts for
the existence of political economy is the value of labour power. The
calculation of this constant by the economists is realistic enough, for
it is a measure of the wage rate maintained by the ruling classes at a
certain level which they deign necessary to sustain the existence of
labour power. In obtaining this constant, the economists, while drawing
on their observations of reality, limit its existence to the field of
production of âmaterial goodsâ, i.e. to the field of physical labour.
Thus the science of political economyâand as a science it has claims of
universal applicabilityâprotests against any attempt at the âabasement
of non-material goods to the level of economic goodsâ; it protests
against any attempt to abase the âproducers of non-material goods to
such a degree that it is possible to apply to them the category of the
value of labour powerâ; and it protests against any demand requiring
them to account for the services they render in exchange for the
compensation received by them in the form of material goods.
It is appropriate to ask a scientific socialist, continually complaining
that the capitalists always deprive the intelligentsia of the authority
which it possesses in other forms of society, if he can point out to us
even one violation of the rules of political economy by capitalist
economists. No, the imagination of those who protest so eloquently
against the âabasement of intellectualsâ â an imagination which is so
passionate, so sensitive to the sufferings of intellectuals who were
raised for cushy jobs but are unable to occupy them because of the
anarchy of production â this imagination gives rise only to illusions
which make it impossible for the scientific socialist to demonstrate
that capitalist economists violate political economy.
The afore-mentioned detailed explanation given by Rodbertus to educated
society occupies in his first work of 1842 a very small place, which
reduces to the following:
âThe greater the sum of rents (surplus value), the greater the number of
people who can live without engaging in productive (in a strictly
economic sense) labour, and devote themselves to other occupations.
However the magnitude of the sum of rents depends... on the productivity
of labour. Thus we see how closely connected the higher spheres of
political life are with economic activity. The higher the productivity,
the richer can be the intellectual and artistic life of the nation; the
lower the former, the more impoverished the latter.â[11]
How forthright this passage is! It does not obfuscate the issue in the
manner of the Marxists, according to whom the accumulation of profits
only augments the means of production, which cannot be consumed by
anyone. However, Rodbertus avoids establishing a direct connection
between rents and the intellectual life of the nation, because
specifying this relation might evoke in the reader the following image,
stripped of any embellishment: the higher the national profit, the
greater the consumption fund of privileged educated society. It is not
only capitalists who are interested in the exploitation of the
proletariat and the size of profits, but also the whole of educated
society. For the workers are exploited not only so a handful of
capitalists can live in idleness, but also for the parasitical existence
of the whole of educated society, the producers of ânon-material goodsâ.
The standard of living of the workers is reduced to the minimum required
to sustain existence so that the âintellectual workersâ can receive
incomes with no fixed limit for the ârealizationâ of âtheir special
talents and abilitiesâ. The workers cannot enjoy the fruits of increased
productivity, because this increase only serves to improve the life
style of privileged educated society.
If the principles developed by Rodbertus (which are essentially a
âstrictly scientificâ consequence of the Erfurt Program[12]) are applied
to the planning of a communist society, then the following picture is
obtained:
âThis system need not be communistic to the extent that private property
is excluded in general. Private property is completely excluded only in
the case where in dividing up the national income the principle of
social distribution depends exclusively on a single social will,
governed only by considerations of practicality. In this case a
communist âdistributorâ is required; this role can be filled by a St.
Simonian pope[13] â a proletarian dictator â or take the form of a
social directory. On the other hand, individual property will exist if
the principle of distribution is independent of any such single social
will, and results from some legal principle, i.e. from a principle
associated with the exercise of individual freedom. In the latter case
such a âdistributorâ is not necessary. So it is quite possible to
introduce communism in the possession of the land and capital of the
nation without communism in relation to distribution. In such a case
only property which bears rent is abolished, and not property generally.
On the contrary, property is then just reduced to its essential
principle â to labour â and reduces to the individual ownership by the
worker of the entire value of the product of his labour.â (Fourth Social
Letter)[14].
Social-democracy takes the position that any discussions about the
âfuture orderâ over and above the general demand for the transfer into
the hands of society of the land and the means of production would only
be utopian fantasying. Social-democracy rejects any examination, not
only of the details of this âfuture orderâ (such an exercise would just
be a waste of time, of course), but also any analysis of the âlegal
principleâ which âsocialistâ educated society would like to see applied
as the basis for the nationalization of land and the means of
production. Encouraging the workers to indulge in fanciful dreams of the
âfuture orderâ, âsocialistâ educated society more and more restricts its
own socialist plans, its own âsocialist idealâ, conforming to its own
interests, and in this manner arrives at a âscientific idealâ. We have
already mentioned that the demand of the Communist Manifesto for the
âabolishment of private propertyâ has been reduced, with the development
of scientific socialism, to the demand for nationalization of the means
of production alone. The âsocialist idealâ in this form is undoubtedly
âscientificâ, because even a non-social-democratic scholar like
Rodbertus recognizes the necessity of such nationalization. Judging by
what we have quoted above, Rodbertus would no doubt have warmly
applauded Deville[15], who declared in the Chamber of Deputies in 1897
that terrible slanders were being spread about the socialists, accusing
them of wishing to abolish private property. Rodbertus would surely also
have recognized his own thought in the following statement of Kautsky in
The Agrarian Question:
âThe goal [of social-democracy] is not the abolition of private
property, but the elimination of the capitalist mode of production. We
are striving to eliminate the former only to the extent that this is
necessary for the abolishment of the latter.â[16]
It is clear that that legal principle which Rodbertus posits as the
basis of his communist order is a generalized deduction from his
doctrine about the âvarious social servicesâ which was cited above. This
doctrine defends the absolute right of doctors, teachers, judges, and
ministers to the incomes they receive today, in view of the absolute
necessity and usefulness of the services they provide. This doctrine
demonstrates the absolute impossibility of transferring these services
to âproductive workersâ, and that the existence of the arts and sciences
is possible only because at the other pole of social life there is the
specialized occupation of the grinder of needles.
When Rodbertus states that in his communist system âthe social law
stipulates not only what sort of social demands must be satisfied, but
also how many individual producers should be assigned to meet these
demandsâ (ibid., p. 136), it is clear that this social law in practice
would never âlower the income of the producers of non-material goods to
the level of income of the producers of material goodsâ. If in his
system âproperty is ... reduced to its essential principle â to labourâ,
and if this principle amounts to the âindividual ownership by the worker
of the entire value of the product of his labourâ, then the âlegal
principleâ decides beforehand that all the income currently received by
all the âintellectual workersâ, i.e. by the whole of educated society,
is its inalienable property since it is its undeniable reward for its
labour, for its âspecial talents and abilitiesâ. To sum up, this âlegal
system with communism in land and capital and private ownership by the
individual of the value of the product of his labourâ[17] is a class
system featuring the direct rule (direct in the sense of not involving
plenipotentiaries) of the educated possessors of culture over the
remaining majority, which is condemned for its inherent inability to
render ânon-material servicesâ. The age-old oppression of the majority
of humanity, doomed to life-long manual labour, has not been destroyed
at all. However, the capitalist system no longer exists,
capitalist-exploiters have disappeared, and âcommodity exchange
inevitably ceasesâ[18]. If this scenario were to come to pass, it would
apparently be in accordance with the statement of Kautsky cited above,
that âwe are striving to eliminate private property only to the extent
that this is necessary for the abolishment of the capitalist means of
productionâ.
How would this socialist ideal of educated society be put into practice?
âIn such a society the division of labour can be retained in that form
which it has assumed at the present time, under the regime of private
property in land and capital... All current enterprises would continue
to produce the same goods, under the condition that the transformation
of private property in land and capital into social property proceeds in
such a way that rents, rather than being paid to the former owners, are
transferred to the social budget. Then so long as the private owners of
land and capital are not abolished without compensation, but rather
bought out, then at the beginning the consumption of goods would
continue in the same form and on the same scale as previously. And only
gradually, in tune with the rising national income and consumption of
the labouring classes, would the content of the national product be
modified... But if the abolishment of private ownership of land and
capital were to proceed without compensation, i.e. with the sudden,
complete loss of rents, the whole of national production would be
delivered into a state of destructive disarray.â[19]
In the event of âthe sudden, complete loss of rentsâ the national profit
would be exposed to great danger which â who knows? â could result in
total ruin. Thus the only possible way to salvage the institution of the
socialist ideal is posited to be the gradual transfer of ownership into
the hands of society with compensation for the owners. For in this case
profit is not eliminated, but rather preserved â it is transformed from
personal to national â and its existence is assured by the whole force
of the law and the power of the state.
Engels mentioned somewhere that Marx very often in conversation with him
expressed the opinion that the cheapest way to bring about
ânationalizationâ would be by buying out the band of capitalists. Ever
since then, many social-democrats, ânot wishing to be more Catholic than
the Popeâ (social-democracy adhered to this principle long before it was
formulated by Bernstein) began finally to favour the buy-out as the only
scientific method of nationalizing. Kautsky, for example, says in his
own âErfurt Programâ that it is ânot knownâ and âimpossible to predictâ
whether nationalizing will take the form of buy-outs or
confiscation.[20] This ânot knownâ, however, actually means âdoesnât
matterâ. In his polemic with Bernstein, when he is required to give a
clear answer to the question as to whether nationalizing would require
âa general, simultaneous, and violent expropriation, or rather a gradual
change, organized and legalâ, Kautsky with the feigned naivety of a
child replied that âas far as the capitalists are concerned, it does not
make any difference if they are expropriated simultaneously or one after
the other, nor whether this happens in an organized manner according to
law or in some other way â this is also of little interest to themâ.
Since it is in no way possible to ascribe to Kautsky such towering
stupidity that his naivety could be considered as genuine, then,
apparently, his polemical style in this case takes the form of
expressing in his distinctive fashion the view that there is no
difference between nationalizing by means of forced expropriation, by
means of âgradual change by virtue of organization and lawâ, or by means
of buy-outs. Therefore on this question there can be no serious
difference of opinions between Bernstein and Kautsky.
Thus, while the workers are encouraged to dream about how
social-democracy, having attained its goals, will transform human
society into one big family where fraternal communist relations will
prevail, in the meantime social-democratic science is cooking up an
error-free, strictly scientific method of nationalization, thanks to
which in the âfuture orderâ âconsumption of the labouring masses remains
on the whole at its previous levels, rising only slowly and graduallyâ.
With the nationalization of the means of production, the national
profit, preserved by the above-described means, ends up in Rodbertusâs
socialist system in the hands of its legal owners.
âAs was said earlier [Rodbertus has in mind his theory of value,
according to which the value of all goods is equal to the directly
expended labour + past labour expended in creating the means of
production], land rent and profit on capital are the product not only of
whoever has tilled the field, but also to some degree or other the
product of the labour of whoever, many years ago, dug up the field; and
the product not only of whoever is running the mill today, but also of
those who built the mill many years ago. Two points of contention only
arise: in the first place, should land rent or profits be received by
people who did not actually dig up the field or build the mill, or are
not the legal successors of the people who did so? (I am here assuming
the law of inheritance and other legal means for the free disposition of
private property.) In the second place, does land rent and the profit on
capital constitute appropriate compensation for the labour of digging up
the field and building the mill?â[21] (Third Social Letter)
Elsewhere in the same essay Rodbertus writes: âThe right of
inheritance... is as sacred in the eyes of the law as private property
itselfâ.[22]
One can scarcely imagine a more emphatic and solemn enunciation of the
inviolability, indeed the permanence, of the right of inheritance than
the preceding words of âa scholar who acknowledges the possibility of
nationalizing the economyâ. And yet the Marxists, so often seeking to
distance Rodbertus from Marx, have never given any answer to the
question about the âsacrednessâ of inherited property. Indeed it never
occurs to them that the âPrussian-monarchist barracksâ envisaged by
Rodbertusâs social system is the direct and inevitable consequence of
recognizing inherited property as inviolable. For the inviolability of
the right of inheritance in conjunction with the nationalization of the
means of production implies no less than the inviolability in the
nationalized economy of the special privileges of educated society: the
inviolability of the hierarchy of rulers and bureaucrats and the
necessity of a barracks regime for the labouring masses, paid âaccording
to the wage scale established by the governmentâ (Kautsky on Rodbertus).
The demand for the âabolition of all rights of inheritanceâ which was
set forth in the Communist Manifesto and which, for the elimination of
servitude, must be formulated as the abolition of family property â this
demand has apparently become simply âobsoleteâ for Marxists, just like
the vague and unscientific demand for the elimination of private
property generally. At the present time no Marxist party is going to be
so utopian as to revive this demand. Incidentally such a revival would
be counter to the practical activity of Marx himself in the
International. Marx, while putting forward resolutions at congresses of
the International about the need to nationalize private property in
land, mines, and communications, considered it necessary at the Basel
congress (1869) to reject Bakuninâs resolution about the abolition of
the right of inheritance. He justified himself on the ground that
Bakunin was only trying to revive the teachings of Saint-Simon (report
of the Hague Commission about the matter of Bakunin). But it is clear
the rejection of Bakuninâs resolution was not so much a blow struck
against Saint-Simonâs utopianism as a gesture of reassurance in the
direction of Rodbertus, concerned about his sacrosanct inherited
property.
At the present time Marxism â in the person, for example, of Kautsky â
by teaching that socialism demands the elimination of private property
only to the extent necessary for the transfer of the means of production
into the hands of society, encourages its followers to regard the
inviolability of family property as a matter of individual preference.
Since the Marxists share with Rodbertus his basic position that
socialism repudiates only private property in land and the means of
production, they may be said to have in common with him to a greater or
lesser degree the general âsocialist idealâ. Therefore they are
compelled to regard his practical activity, distinguished, as is well
known, by an extreme conservatism[23], as a retreat from this ideal
which is inconsistent from their point of view with the true state of
affairs, a residuum of the class interests of his aristocratic milieu
which he found himself unable to abandon, in spite of his socialism. The
Marxists are quite incapable of understanding that this scholar, ârock
solidâ in his own convictions, devised his socialist plans, his
socialist ideal, in accord with the class interests of privileged
society â class interests which the Marxists believe he defended only in
his practical, but not his theoretical, activity.
âDespite all his efforts to be unbiased,â wrote Valentinov in 1882 in
Otechestvennye Zapiski[24], âhe, Rodbertus, could never raise himself to
that level of impartiality which would have compelled him to make a
final break with traditions which were obsolete, indeed condemned by
history.â Although he displayed âprofound theoretical thoughtâ,
âtheoretical insightâ, and âacknowledged in theory the possibility of
nationalizing the economy,â said Kautsky, âRodbertus remained too
conservative to recognize the plight of the propertyless producer as his
own concern.â
Sanin, considering it his historical mission to deepen the Marxist class
point of view more than all the Marxists who have preceded him, finds
himself dissatisfied (in Nauchny Oboz. [The Scientific Observer],
1899)[25] not only with Valentinov, but also with Kautsky. For the
latter, in expressing his opinion about Rodbertusâs âtheoretical
thoughtâ, deviated from a consistent application of a strictly class
point of view. Sanin explains Rodbertusâs vacillations between the
âsocialist idealâ and bourgeois aspirations as a reflection of the
situation of the whole class of feudal aristocrats embedded in the
bourgeois system. A âmore profound class point of viewâ gives the
following analysis of Rodbertus:
âAlthough [Rodbertusâs ideal] smacks a little of the Prussian-monarchist
barracks, ... nevertheless this ideal is based on the notion of
ânationalizationâ. In any case, his ideal expresses to the highest
degree his intransigence towards the appropriation of surplus labour in
any form and his desire to eliminate any social relations which give
rise to, or at least make possible, exploitation. However Rodbertus, the
ideologue of the feudal proprietor, is unable to maintain his thought on
the dizzying heights of this utopian anti-bourgeois ideal, and exhibits
an irrepressible urge to come down from the clouds to the mundane world
of the purely bourgeois form of life.â
The reader has probably noticed by now that a deepening of the Marxist
point of view by Russian Marxists inevitably turns out to be a more
dexterous juggling of balls labeled âclass struggleâ, âproletarian point
of viewâ, etc. And so it is in the present case. Kautskyâs more
superficial class point of view at least reminds us that the socialist
ideal of Rodbertus, while involving ânationalizationâ, is nevertheless a
âbarracksâ system; while Saninâs âmore profound class point of viewâ
states bluntly that Rodbertusâs ideal implies the unconditional
ânegationâ of exploitation and all forms of the appropriation of surplus
labour.
The dizziness referred to by Sanin clearly affects not Rodbertus, but
the Marxists. Rodbertus unceasingly points his finger at that
exploitation which is the key to constructing his socialist ideal. But
his âpupilsâ, âfinding themselves on the heights of European scienceâ,
and dumbfounded by Rodbertusâs prediction of the disappearance of the
kulaks, come up with their analysis of Rodbertus âfrom the proletarian
point of viewâ, namely that âthis is the absolute negation of
exploitation and the appropriation of surplus labourâ.
âHereditary property is as sacred as individual property.â The socialist
system of Rodbertus takes this eternal institution of human society as
its starting point. With the complete nationalization of the means of
production, all private capital disappears, only to be transformed into
social national capital. This means: private persons surrender to the
State their right to draw profits from their own capital, i.e. the
function of maintaining the workersâ wages at the level required for the
sustenance of their labour power is fulfilled now by the social group
which rules over the workers; the will of this social group is codified
in law and it takes on the role previously exercised by private
capitalists. The constant replacement of social capital takes place on
the assumption of the accumulation in the hands of the dominant social
group â acting through the State â of the whole sum of that wealth
produced at each given moment which remains after deducting the wages of
the âproducers of material goodsâ, i.e. that sum which incessantly grows
in accord with the rising productivity of labour.
But society no longer includes capitalists and their lackeys; âany
possibility of exploitation has been suppressedâ. The ruling clique now
includes only some workers from the army of intellectual workers who
have no other means of obtaining their incomes than by the expenditure
of âtheir own labour powerâ. Their labour power, as Kautsky explains, is
their knowledge, their special talents and abilities. This labour power
has a value which vulgar political economy does not even dare to
discuss; it cannot be subject to any kind of critique.
Individual property is sacred and so is the sum of the income reserved
for the intellectual workers by virtue of their âspecial talents and
abilitiesâ. As the national profit grows with each step in the
development of technology, so this national profit is distributed
âaccording to the will of the peopleâ among the whole of educated
society, in the form of honorariums and pumped-up salaries, creating a
whole hierarchy of state employees.
Inherited property is sacred. However, as a result of that elemental
sentiment innate to humans which obliges them to love and nurture their
own children, educated society transmits its own special talents and
abilities, all its own knowledge, only to its own offspring â Rodbertus
has no doubts about this. Educated society without question will
reproduce itself through its descendants in the same form â the army of
intellectual workers who are learned, capable, and talented and who have
concentrated in their own persons the whole of human knowledge.
On the other hand, the remaining millions of individuals will reproduce
descendants who will already be ignorant, lacking in any talents, and
quite âincapable of rendering immaterial services to human societyâ.
These millions, generation after generation, will only be capable of
engaging in manual labour, only capable of toiling and admiring the
magnificent talent and genius generated uniquely in the higher society
which rules over them; they find themselves condemned to a life of
slavish, mechanistic labour.
The socialist system of Rodbertus is far from being the complete
negation of exploitation as the Marxists claim. In fact he offers us in
its purest form that foundation of the State and servitude on which
rests our contemporary class system. Indeed Rodbertus says himself that
he described his communist system not in order to oppose it to the
existing system as a better alternative, but rather in order to better
understand the existing system.
The goal of the proletarian global struggle is to overthrow the basis of
contemporary domination which regards state socialism as sacred, to
overthrow the economic basis of the class system which transmits the
entire heritage of humanity into the hands of the ruling educated
society. This heritage allows educated society to prepare its own
progeny from generation to generation as the sole, hereditary possessors
of the whole of human knowledge, of the whole of civilization and
culture. Meanwhile the remaining millions are turned into hereditary
slaves, condemned to hard physical labour.
The proletariat, through global conspiracy and dictatorship, will seize
control of the state machinery, but not in order to extricate it from
its difficulties â from the anarchy and bankruptcy of an economic system
which is incapable of coping with productive forces which are outgrowing
the constraints of current ownership relations... The proletariat will
strive to seize power in order to seize the resources of the dominant
educated society, the property of the world of knowledge, in order to
wrest the heritage of humanity from the hands of the minority which
holds it. Then, having abolished hereditary family property as well as
private funds and educational facilities, it will use the confiscated
resources to organize public education â to âsocialize knowledgeâ. For
only this conquest, achieved by means of the âuncompromising assault of
the proletariat on the right of private propertyâ â that is, by the
violent manifestation of its will â will annihilate the basic law of the
class system, defended by million-strong armies, by virtue of which all
the members of the privileged minority are destined from birth to accede
to power, while the descendants of the minority are condemned to
slavery.
The transfer of the means of production into the hands of society,
without disturbing any of the other sacred rights of property, is the
socialist ideal of the âintellectual workersâ, of educated society. And
it is to this ideal that social-democracy has reduced the goal of
proletarian struggle, thereby transforming its brand of socialism into
state socialism. Marxâs economic doctrine, as we showed in the preceding
chapter[26], is completely compatible with this goal.
The âscientific socialist idealâ, according to the affirmations of
radical socialist educated society, is already being realized at the
present time in the West European democracies in the form of
âmunicipalizationâ and ânationalizationâ of those enterprises which
âyield the highest profitsâ and which are currently âripe to be taken
over by the Stateâ, or, as the Marxist say, have been âprepared by the
capitalist system itselfâ for the socialist economy.
Orthodox Marxist social-democracy rejects the various individual cases
of nationalization in Germany, because in its opinion they were done
âfor tax purposesâ and the âconcentration of political and economic
oppression in one set of handsâ only reinforces the present system. But
in such countries as England and Switzerland, âindividual instances of
nationalization have undoubtedly weakened the existing order, its
oppression, and its exploitationâ (see the articles of Kautsky in Neue
Zeit, 1893, on the subject of state socialism)[27]. In those countries
state socialism is not on the agenda, orthodox Marxism assures us; the
municipalizations and nationalizations being carried out in the âtrue
democraciesâ at the present time must be seen, apparently, as the first
steps in the âgradual nationalization of the means of productionâ.
But in reality the practice of contemporary nationalizations in France,
England, and Switzerland shows that the less the workers are
enthusiastic about this âsocialismâ (in the opinion of the âsocialist
intelligentsiaâ this deficit of enthusiasm is indicative of the
political immaturity of the workers who even in a democratic setting
have not been able to grasp the âsocialist idealâ), and the more the
workers are indifferent to the achievement of these âsocialist stepsâ,
the better it is for them. For they can receive major concessions with
respect to their working conditions from the new owners (nations,
municipalities) which, depending on the will of the people, are
compelled to count on the workersâ votes to institute their
nationalizations. But once installed, the new owners become just as
inaccessible as the old ones.
âIndividual nationalizationsâ reinforce the contemporary class system in
Switzerland just as much as in Germany. In both countries this means one
and the same thing: the transfer of the source of profit from private
hands to the ownership of the nation, i.e. of privileged society.
Capital and exploitation are now protected by a new boss â the âwill of
the peopleâ. If social-democracy considers that ânationalizingâ in
Germany is a tax grab, while in Switzerland the same phenomenom is a
reduction of exploitation, it is only because in Germany the income of
the state, augmented by this nationalization, is received primarily by
the highest levels of privileged society; while in Switzerland it is
distributed âmore equitablyâ among the whole of privileged educated
society. It is for this sole reason, according to the teaching of
Kautsky, that one and the same reform reinforces the class system in
Germany and undermines it in Switzerland.
Social-democracy declares that democracy cannot accomodate state
socialism of the Rodbertus type, which implies that the socialist
practice of social-democracy in a democratic state reduces to the quest
for state socialism (response of Kautsky to Vollmar in the articles
cited earlier). In other words, the socialism of social-democracy is
state socialism which realizes itself in a democracy. This is confirmed
by the tactics of the English, French, and Swiss Marxists, rejecting any
illegal methods of struggle and formulating as their goal the gradual
taking over by the state of individual branches of industry wherever
possible, and insofar as concentration has taken place. By doing so they
are able to draw into their own ranks the radicals, the
socialist-chauvinists, and outright counter-revolutionaries like the
Fabians, creating from all these elements a âpurely proletarianâ
social-democracy.
The workers do not share this ideal because of their own class
interests. The proletarian movement defends people condemned to servile
physical labour. Its goal is liberation from this slavery. Proletarian
socialism is therefore diametrically opposed to the socialism of the
intellectual workers, which consists of socializing capital â
transforming it from private into socialist, national capital â into
constant social capital.
[1] Machajski means the mainly British school of economics which
flourished from 1750â1830 and is associated with such names as Adam
Smith and David Ricardo.
[2] Machajski is referring to his work The Evolution of
Social-Democracy, published in its final form in 1905 in Geneva.
[3] The leading Russian Marxist theoretician Georgi Valentinovich
Plekhanov (1857â1918) published his famous book The Development of the
Monist View of History under the pseudonym âBeltovâ.
[4] Novoye Slovo was a journal of so-called âlegal Marxismâ; Plekanov
published in it, but under the name âKamenskyâ.
[5] Machajski actually quotes from the â Third Social Letterâ: Johann
Karl Rodbertus, Gesammelte Werke und Briefe, Abteilung I, Band I
(Osnabruck, 1972), p. 456.
[6] Ibid., pp. 561â562.
[7] Alexandre Millerand (1859â1943), French politician, was the first
socialist to accept a cabinet position in a bourgeois democracy (in
1899). As labour minister he pushed through a law reducing the working
day to 11 hours.
[8] Rodbertus, op. cit., Abteilung I, Band II, pp. 88â89.
[9] Ibid., p. 89(fn).
[10] The German sociologist and Marxist academic Werner Sombart
(1863â1941) was the author of Sozialismus und soziale Bewegung (1896);
the Russian Jew Mark Ratner (1871â1917) was one of the leaders of the
Socialist Jewish Workers Party, and the author of Marxist analyses of
the peasant question in the Russian empire.
[11] Rodbertus, op. cit., Abteilung I, Band I, p. 110. Rodbertus defines
ârentâ as âall income obtained without personal exertion, solely by
virtue of possessionâ (Gesammelte Werke, Abteilung I, Band I, p. 392).
Thus it includes both land-rent and profit on capital.
[12] The Erfurt Program was adopted by the Social Democratic Party of
Germany at its 1891 congress in Erfurt. Karl Kautsky, who helped to
draft the Program, wrote an official commentary on it, The Class
Struggle, which came to be regarded as an exposition of the doctrine of
âorthodoxâ Marxism or, as some would say, âvulgarâ Marxism.
[13] The utopian socialist Henri de Saint-Simon (1760â1825) founded a
social movement loosely modelled on the Catholic Church.
[14] Rodbertus, op. cit., Abteilung I, Band II, pp. 117â118.
[15] The French socialist deputy Gabriel Deville (1854â1940) was the
author of a number of theoretical works of Marxism. He approved of
Millerandâs entry into a bourgeois government (see note 7).
[16] Karl Kautsky, Die Agrarfrage, (Hannover, 1966; reprint of the 1899
edition), p. 333.
[17] Rodbertus, op. cit., Abteilung I, Band II, p. 118.
[18] Ibid., p. 123.
[19] Ibid., pp. 118â119.
[20] Kautskyâs comments are found in The Class Struggle (see note 12):
âThe program of the Socialist Party has nothing to say about
confiscation. It does not mention it, not from fear of giving offense,
but because it is a subject upon which nothing can be said with
certainty... In what way this transfer from private and individual into
collective ownership will be effected, whether this inevitable transfer
will take the form of confiscation, whether it will be a peaceable or a
forcible one â these are questions no man can answer...â [p. 129 in the
Norton edition: New York, 1971].
[21] Rodbertus, op. cit., Abteilung I, Band I, p. 451.
[22] Ibid., p. 567.
[23] Rodbertus once served as Prussian Minister of Education and Public
Worship. Although his term of office lasted only 14 days, it sufficed to
destroy any notion that he was progressive.
[24] Valentinov, âThe economic theory of Karl Rodbertus-Jagetsovâ,
Otechestvennye Zapiski [Notes of the Fatherland], â 9, 10 (1883).
Valentinov was another pseudonym used by G. V. Plekhanov; Otechestvennye
Zapiski was a monthly literary-scientific-political journal published in
St. Petersburg in 1839â1884. Its contributors included Herzen, Belinsky,
Turgenev, and Bakunin. Plekanovâs book-length essay on Rodbertus is more
readily accessed in his collected works: G. V. Plekanov, Sochinenia,
Vol. 1 (Moscow, 1922). The passage quoted by Machajski is on page 338.
Jagetsov is the name of an estate purchased by Rodbertus.
[25] It has not been possible to locate this rather obscure reference.
However, Alexei Alexeievich Sanin was a Russian social-democrat based in
Samara, who was regarded as a talented theoretician and whose work was
cited with approval by Lenin in The Development of Capitalism in Russia.
[26] Machajski is referring to his essay âMarxâs Theory of Social
Constant Capitalâ.
[27] Machajski is referring to Kautskyâs polemic with George von Vollmar
on state socialism, carried out in the pages of Neue Zeit in 1892â1893:
Karl Kautsky, âVollmar und der Staatssozialismusâ, Neue Zeit (1892), pp.
705â713; George von Vollman, âZur Streitfrage ĂŒber den
Staatssozialismusâ, Neue Zeit (1893), pp. 196â210; Karl Kautsky, âDer
Parteitag und der Staatssozialismusâ, Neue Zeit (1893), pp. 210â221.