đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș philippe-chanial-proudhon-sociologist.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:14:12. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Proudhon, Sociologist and Activist of the Autonomy of the Social Author: Philippe Chanial Date: 2017 Language: en Topics: Sociology, Proudhon Source: âProudhon, sociologue et militant de lâautonomie du socialâ Revue de la SociĂ©tĂ© P.-J. Proudhon, no. 3 (2017): 9â16. Source in French: [[https://www.proudhon.net/philippe-chanial-proudhon-sociologue-et-militant-de-lautonomie-du-social/]] Notes: Translated by Shaun Murdock.
If Proudhon can and should be read as a forerunner of sociology, is it
not above all because he was one of the first to have systematically
hypothesised the autonomy of its very object, the âsocialâ? As everyone
knows, this hypothesis is foundational to sociology. The late Pierre
Ansart reminded us that the heart of Proudhonâs sociological thesis is
an âessential heterogeneity of the social relative to the
individualâ.[1] Before him, the Durkheimian CĂ©lestin BouglĂ© emphasised
that if Proudhonâs work pertains to sociological theory, it is because
it shares the premise that âthe meeting of individual entities generates
an original reality, something greater than and different to their mere
sumâ. And, he continued, âarguably no thinker has made greater use of
this premise than Proudhonâ because âhe constantly opposes, to purely
individual phenomena, the notions of collective force, collective being
and collective reasonâ.[2]
However, this theory of the irreducibility of the social â of the
collective â to the individual does not exhaust this hypothesis of the
autonomy of the social. It raises another question: that of the
relationship between the social, the political and the economic. In the
war of the sciences, sociology was only able to assert itself as an
autonomous science by rejecting the self-proclaimed status of both
political philosophy and political economy as the science of society.[3]
It did so by refusing that the mystery of the social order â the fact
that there is, among or between people, something rather than nothing
(chaos, arbitrary violence, war of all against all, etc.) or, to put it
another way, the fact that people manage to give a lasting form to their
coexistence â can be resolved either by identifying society with a
system of power, as if the heteronomy of its political establishment,
even if it were legitimate, were the absolute condition for the
possibility of human coexistence; or by reducing it to a market, as if
commercial ties alone were sufficient to make society. But is it not
this double refusal that also defines the unique anarchism and socialism
of Proudhon? Is is not this hypothesis of an autonomy of the social that
enables both sociology as a scientific discipline, and socialism or
anarchism as paths for emancipation?
Let us therefore attempt to unravel some of the simultaneously
sociological and normative questions raised by this Proudhonian plea for
an autonomy of the social.
In his Carnets of 1852, Proudhon said: âI do politics to kill it. To put
an end to politics.â This confession summarises, in a particularly
polemical tone, his well-known critique of governmentalism. But this
desire to end the âgovernmental biasâ should not be reduced to a purely
negative injunction to abolish all powers. It is also an invitation to
accede to a âconstitution of societyâ that is no longer based on the
hierarchy of political powers but on the free organisation of social
forces. It is in Confessions of a Revolutionary, written, as Pierre
Ansart also recalled, âin a sort of anger after the failure of a
hoped-for social revolutionâ[4], that Proudhon makes this fundamental
distinction:
âIn every society I find the distinction between two kinds of
constitution, one of which I call the social constitution and the other
the political constitution; the first, inherent to humanity, liberal,
necessary, the development of which consists above all in weakening and
gradually eliminating the second, which is essentially factitious,
restrictive and transitory. The social constitution is nothing but the
equilibrium of interests founded upon free contract and the organisation
of economic forces, which are in general: Labour, Division of Labour,
Collective Force, Competition, Commerce, Money, Machines, Credit,
Property, Equality in transactions, Reciprocity of guarantees, etc. The
political constitution has authority as its principle. Its forms are:
Class Distinctions, Separation of Powers, Administrative Centralisation,
Judicial Hierarchy [...]. These two constitutions are [...] of utterly
different and even incompatible naturesâ.[5]
This fit of anger is also a theoretical and normative act of force, as
if society could â and should â no longer be established on the basis of
political heteronomy but on the autonomy of the social, on the mutual
guarantee of the liberty of all by all, which on the contrary allows us,
under the supreme law of justice and contract, to do without any
government. By this radical gesture, Proudhon can thus be interpreted,
inseparably, as a pioneer of anarchism but also of sociology. Indeed,
while Proudhon constantly suggests that it is necessary to âproceed
[...] to social reform through the extermination of power and politicsâ,
such a reform, in all its radicality, assumes a science of the social
(which he calls for as early as The Celebration of Sunday in 1839)
capable of asserting that the social order â and Proudhon also continues
to advocate for order â is an immanent order: an order that precedes the
political order, and that cannot therefore proceed from it. In this
sense, this new science requires dethroning political philosophy in its
age-old ambition to constitute âtheâ science of society, in order to
better assert the primacy of the âsocial constitutionâ over the
âpolitical constitutionâ.
It is reasonable to assume that this hypothesis of an autonomy of the
social, with its own constitution and consistency, results from an
optimism characteristic of pre-Marxist socialisms. This idea of an order
created spontaneously in humanity, without the intervention of a
coercive power, is especially reminiscent of the Fourierist utopia. As
Miguel Abensour stressed, what distinguishes these master dreamers is
first and foremost their desire to subvert modern society precisely by
preventing the State from embodying the One or the universal. Indeed, he
said, where does the utopian strategy start from, if not civil society
and âthe multiple centres of socialisation that it carries within
itselfâ? And what is its aim, if not to substitute a âsociety of
societiesâ for the exteriority of power and State violence? In this
sense, he said again:
âDecentralisation, the multiplication of places of socialisation [âŠ], an
invitation to plurality, dissemination, a call for communication between
groups, series constantly being made and unmade, the proliferation on
the same territory of micro-experimental communities âbehind the backâ
of State unification: such are utopiaâs ways of allowing a new way of
living together to be establishedâ.[6]
But, paradoxically, does this hypothesis of an autonomy of the social
not also shape the thesis defended by the liberal economists, whereby
the natural harmony of interests is sufficient to produce such an order?
And besides, would Proudhon not suggest that the solution to the social
problem should not lie with the public authorities, but precisely with
the âidentity of interestsâ, to the point of defining himself as a
financier? In one of his last texts, War and Peace in 1861, he wrote:
âWhat governs the world [...] is not the Gospel, nor the Koran, nor
Aristotle, nor Voltaire; no more is it the constitution of 1852 or that
of 1793. It is the Great Ledger, whose pages carry only two words in
large letters: on one side Debit, on the other, Credit.â[7] It is
therefore not without reason that C. Bouglé could characterise the
sociology of the author of The Stock Exchange Speculatorâs Manual as a
âsociology of an economist and an accountantâ.
However, despite his fascination with political economy and what he
called âbanking solutionsâ, and also his provocations against the
âsentimental socialismâ of his age, for Proudhon it is a question of
identifying other laws: laws other than economic laws alone, laws apt to
found this autonomy of the social not only against political heteronomy,
but also against âeconomic insolidarityâ, the ârespect for parasitesâ,
the ânecessity of povertyâ, and even the âhomicidal Providenceâ promoted
by the economists. Such laws are those of the Collective Being, laws
that come only from itself. And it is up to the new science of society
mentioned as early as 1839 to identify them. In specifying that this
science must be discovered, not invented, Proudhon invites us to
consider that there is an intelligence of the social which is specific
to it and which must be explained from within. This social intelligence
is manifested in particular in the subtle âbalancingâ of individual
forces which produces a collective force, a distinct power generated by
the association of people. And it is through this collective force that
the sui generis reality that constitutes the Collecting Being is
manifested; in short, any social group, whether it is the ensemble
constituted by the famous workers erecting the Luxor obelisk, a
workshop, an orchestra, an academy, an army or âsocietyâ.
In this sense, the inner essence of society is, in his words, âorganicâ
in nature â the order it embodies results from and is manifested in
cooperation (and conflict) among the immanent forces of which it is
composed â not âmechanicalâ, in the sense of an artificial or
conventional order that comes from outside. On the contrary, the order
of social order comes from within. It emerges from social practices
themselves. Thus the bond â or solidarity â that unites its different
members is not the artificial result of an external constraint, but
inherent in the spontaneity and creativity of social life. Thus, while
the Collective Being is a sui generis reality, it is not a transcendent
reality.
However, people, whether willingly or by force, constantly project such
transcendent instances through a process that Proudhon calls
âexternalisationâ, by giving themselves a religion, subordinating
themselves to a power, or surrendering themselves to the âhomicidal
Providenceâ of the economistsâ supposed laws; in short, by attributing
to what is only a human work the capacity to create social reality.
Considering the autonomy of the social thus opens up to a critical point
of view these forms of alienation and domination, from which society
must extricate itself so that it can in some way ârecaptureâ itself and
retrieve its âinherent, secular constitutionâ.
But what can this capacity of the social to capture or recapture itself
be supported? On which lever? What is the pivot, the axis of a society
restored to itself, master of itself? For Proudhon, this lever, this
axis, this pivot is, as everyone knows, the idea of justice. Through
justice, Proudhon proposes to recognise a normativity immanent to the
Collective Being. The social is not a normative no manâs land, a simple
play of forces: the very texture of social reality is, as he put it,
âideo-realistâ. This assumes that justice is not an abstract ideal, a
transcendental implant, but a practical reality, an âidea-forceâ in
Alfred FouillĂ©eâs sense, enshrined in interpersonal practices and
relations, a manifestation of what I have called the intelligence of the
social.
Here we see the emergence of Proudhonâs sociological, Durkheimian
argument: within social reality itself there is a distinct force of
obligation, which in some way renders any external constraint parasitic
(hence his criticisms of Hobbes): a force of obligation which links
people together and which they are linked to, which holds them together
and which they hold on to. For this reason, the imperative of justice â
which for Proudhon can alone freely oblige people to one another â is
indeed the condition of the autonomy of the social. Conversely, this
means that any unjust order can only be heteronomous. And as everyone
knows, it is on this pivot â because for Proudhon everything revolves
around justice â that Proudhon defends his mutualism and then his
federalism.
However, it is first and foremost at the heart of the most anodyne
interpersonal relations that he emphasises the socialising and
individualising force of this free obligation of justice. Thus in
Justice he opposes the âobliqueâ look, cast âfrom top to bottomâ, that
of contempt, inherent in the relationship between superior and inferior,
with the respect, the âequality of considerationâ, manifested in the
greeting exchanged between two people who look at each other
face-to-face, in the eyes, as equals. Justice thus means equal and
reciprocal respect for the dignity of each person. This means for us
that the autonomy of the social presupposes the reciprocal and
egalitarian quality of interpersonal relations that we find in simple
greetings. But, more broadly, for Proudhon, it is society as a whole
that takes shape through these transactions, reciprocal exchanges, pacts
of mutual respect, all of which respond to justice.
However, we should not misunderstand the meaning of the imperative of
reciprocity which, for Proudhon, ratifies interpersonal relations under
the seal of the contract. The âregime of contractsâ that he calls for,
as the concrete form of the âsystem of immanenceâ that he opposes to the
âsystem of transcendenceâ, is not, of course, the reign of interest. If
he sees in the contract the exclusive expression of a realistic justice,
his contract-based rhetoric is in part misleading. Social life cannot be
exhausted in the strict accounting of a generalised system of
give-and-take. Referring to the mutualist organisation, he writes:
âWhich private or social virtue will you accuse men of lacking who
reciprocally promise each other everything, who, without granting
anything for nothing, guarantee each other everything, assure each other
everything, give each other everything: Education, Work, Trade,
Property, Wealth, Security?â[8]
âGiving everything without granting anything for nothingâ: this phrase
is striking as it recalls the very logic of the Maussian gift[9], the
subtle articulation between generosity or unconditionality (âgiving
everythingâ) and reciprocity or conditionality (âwithout granting
anything for nothingâ). In short, if we need to know how to calculate,
we also need to know how to give everything. Thus the moral dimension of
Proudhonian sociology appears more clearly, and thereby how much the
autonomy of the social requires the social order to be understood as a
moral order. This is why the Proudhonian âregime of contractsâ in which
this autonomy is achieved in practice is based less on the calculation
of well-understood interests than, first of all, on the capacity of
people to oblige each other reciprocally. Or, to express it another way,
because the law of justice is immutable and objective, the contracts
that implement it â or approximate it â are, for Proudhon, irrevocable
by their very nature. Their model is much more that of the oath, the
promise, the pact of trust:
âMen, having made a pact of probity, loyalty, guarantee and honour
between themselves, cannot say in separating from each other: we were
wrong; now we will become liars and rascals again; we will gain more
that wayâ.[10]
In short, he concludes later, âone does not go back on a pact, on a
profession of faith, as with the mutualist profession of faith, as with
the federative pactâ.[11] It is this fidelity to the pact (and the
conjugal pact should also be included, but that is another matter),
whatever the price, and if necessary against oneâs own interests, that
sums up the Proudhonian law of justice. And it is justice that, on the
model of the conditional unconditionality of the Maussian gift, enables
this self-institution, both performative and normative, of the social.
This performative and instituting dimension of the imperative of justice
deserves to be measured in all its radicality. It implies that the
social order can no longer be based on any form of authority, on any
form of traditional consensus, or even on shared beliefs, but on justice
and equality alone as the internal requirement for social practices and
relations. Here, Proudhonian anarchism curiously meets the sociology of
Durkheim. For the latter, because the forms of mechanical solidarity of
past societies are now behind us, what has become necessary is a very
different form of social solidarity that does not depend on the
authority of collective beliefs, but rather on a shared commitment to
equality in participation and reciprocity in cooperation; in short, on
justice. This is the historical condition of the autonomy of the social.
And this was the conclusion of The Division of Labour in Society:
âThe task of the most advanced societies may therefore be said to be a
mission for justice. [...] Just as the ideal of lower societies was to
create or maintain a common life as intense as possible, in which the
individual was engulfed, ours is to inject an even greater equity into
our social relationships, in order to ensure the free deployment of all
those forces that are socially useful. [...] Just as ancient peoples had
above all need of a common faith to live by, we have need of justice. We
can rest assured that this need will become ever more pressing if, as
everything leads us to foresee, the conditions that dominate social
evolution remain unchanged.â[12]
Neither Durkheim nor Proudhon believed, as the conservatives of their
time did, that the problems confronting modern societies came from a
growing division of labour or the development of individualism, eroding
tradition. For Durkheim, they result from the fact that we continue to
think and act as if authority and consensus were essential, when they
have in fact been replaced by justice and equality as prerequisites for
implementing new forms of cooperation between people. Moreover, as
Durkheim shows â and Proudhon, through his distinction between social
constitution and political constitution, could only share its analysis â
modern societies still too often seek to rely on the authority of formal
systems that can no longer create ties. On the contrary, a new form of
spontaneous social order must be created to challenge this type of
authority by developing and consolidating itself from the bottom up.
Ultimately, the problem of modern societies results from the inability
to recognise that individual freedom is possible only in a certain
social context, and under the condition of a certain quality â
egalitarian and reciprocal â of interpersonal relations, and from the
resulting failure to implement the justice needed to fully achieve it.
As such â and this lesson of sociology is of course valid for our
contemporary societies â do Durkheim and Proudhon not concur in showing
that only by consolidating this autonomy of the social â the reciprocal
quality of social relations that Marcel Mauss, a socialist activist and
Durkheimâs nephew, would designate under the concept of gift[13] â can
we achieve freedom and justice for all?
[1] Ansart, P., Sociologie de Proudhon, Paris, PUF, 1967, p. 18.
[2] Bouglé, C., Sociologie de Proudhon, Paris, A. Colin, 1911, p. XIII.
[3] Cf. Chanial, Ph., La sociologie comme philosophie politique. Et
réciproquement [Sociology as Political Philosophy and Vice Versa],
Paris, La DĂ©couverte, 2011, particularly the introduction.
[4] Op. cit.
[5] Confessions dâun rĂ©volutionnaire, Paris, Editions Tops/Trinquier,
1997, p. 173.
[6] Abensour, M., « Le procĂšs des maĂźtres rĂȘveurs » [The Trial of the
Master Dreamers], in Libre, no. 4, Paris, Payot, 1978, p. 226.
[7] La guerre et la paix, in Ćuvres complĂštes de P.-J. Proudhon
[Complete Works of P.-J. Proudhon], Paris, Marcel RiviĂšre, 1927, p. 463.
[8] De la capacité des classes ouvriÚres [Political Capacity of the
Working Classes], in Ćuvres complĂštes de P.-J. Proudhon, Paris, Marcel
RiviĂšre, 1924, p. 224.
[9] Mauss, M., « Essai sur le don » [Essay on the Gift], in Sociologie
et anthropologie, Paris, PUF, 1989.
[10] Ibid., p. 195.
[11] Ibid., p. 222.
[12] Durkheim, Ă., De la division du travail social, PUF, Paris, 1991,
p. 381.
[13] Cf. Chanial, Ph., La délicate essence du socialisme [The Delicate
Essence of Socialism], Lormont, Le Bord de lâeau, 2009.