đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș colin-ward-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 23:42:37. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âŹ…ïž Previous capture (2023-01-29)

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism
Author: Colin Ward
Date: February 2004
Language: en
Topics: introductory
Source: Retrieved on 31st August 2021 from http://www.revoltlib.com/anarchism/anarchism-a-very-short-introduction/view.php

Colin Ward

Anarchism

Foreword

Anarchism is a social and political ideology which, despite a history of

defeat, continually reemerges in a new guise or in a new country, so

that another chapter has to be added to its chronology, or another

dimension to its scope.

In 1962 George Woodcock wrote a 470-page book, Anarchism, which,

continually reprinted as a Penguin Book and translated into many

languages, became probably the most widely read book on the subject in

the world. Woodcock wrote a series of updating postscripts until his

death in 1995.

In 1992 Peter Marshall wrote a book of more than 700 pages called

Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism (HarperCollins) which

seems likely to overtake the earlier book in global sales. Woodcock was

greatly relieved: ‘I now have a book,’ he wrote, ‘to which I can direct

readers when they ask me how soon I intend to bring my Anarchism up to

date.’ Like all his other readers, I have been very grateful for Peter

Marshall’s capacity for summarizing complex ideas and for exploring the

by-ways of anarchist history.

For decades, when in search of a fact or an opinion, I would telephone

Nicolas Walter, who died in the year 2000. I greatly value his neat

little pamphlet About Anarchism, which is part of the global treasury of

anarchist literature stocked by the Freedom Press Bookshop in London.

My task has been one of selection: simply an attempt to introduce the

reader to anarchist ideas in a very few words and to point to further

sources. In this rich field the emphases are bound to be my own.

C. W. February 2004

Chapter 1. Definitions and ancestors

The word ‘anarchy’ comes from the Greek anarkhia, meaning contrary to

authority or without a ruler, and was used in a derogatory sense until

1840, when it was adopted by Pierre-Joseph Proudhon to describe his

political and social ideology. Proudhon argued that organization without

government was both possible and desirable. In the evolution of

political ideas, anarchism can be seen as an ultimate projection of both

liberalism and socialism, and the differing strands of anarchist thought

can be related to their emphasis on one or the other of these.

Historically, anarchism arose not only as an explanation of the gulf

between the rich and the poor in any community, and of the reason why

the poor have been obliged to fight for their share of a common

inheritance, but as a radical answer to the question ‘What went wrong?’

that followed the ultimate outcome of the French Revolution. It had

ended not only with a reign of terror and the emergence of a newly rich

ruling caste, but with a new adored emperor, Napoleon Bonaparte,

strutting through his conquered territories.

The anarchists and their precursors were unique on the political Left in

affirming that workers and peasants, grasping the chance that arose to

bring an end to centuries of exploitation and tyranny, were inevitably

betrayed by the new class of politicians, whose first priority was to

reestablish a centralized state power. After every revolutionary

uprising, usually won at a heavy cost for ordinary populations, the new

rulers had no hesitation in applying violence and terror, a secret

police, and a professional army to maintain their control.

For anarchists the state itself is the enemy, and they have applied the

same interpretation to the outcome of every revolution of the 19^(th)

and 20^(th) centuries. This is not merely because every state keeps a

watchful and sometimes punitive eye on its dissidents, but because every

state protects the privileges of the powerful.

The mainstream of anarchist propaganda for more than a century has been

anarchist-communism, which argues that property in land, natural

resources, and the means of production should be held in mutual control

by local communities, federating for innumerable joint purposes with

other communes. It differs from state socialism in opposing the concept

of any central authority. Some anarchists prefer to distinguish between

anarchist-communism and collectivist anarchism in order to stress the

obviously desirable freedom of an individual or family to possess the

resources needed for living, while not implying the right to own the

resources needed by others.

Anarcho-syndicalism puts its emphasis on the organized industrial

workers who could, through a ‘social general strike’, expropriate the

possessors of capital and thus engineer a workers’ take-over of industry

and administration.

There are, unsurprisingly, several traditions of individualist

anarchism, one of them deriving from the ‘conscious egoism’ of the

German writer Max Stirner (1806–56), and another from a remarkable

series of 19^(th)-century American figures who argued that in protecting

our own autonomy and associating with others for common advantages, we

are promoting the good of all. These thinkers differed from free-market

liberals in their absolute mistrust of American capitalism, and in their

emphasis on mutualism. In the late 20^(th) century the word

‘libertarian’, which people holding such a viewpoint had previously used

as an alternative to the word ‘anarchist’, was appropriated by a new

group of American thinkers, who are discussed in Chapter 7.

Pacifist anarchism follows both from the anti-militarism that

accompanies rejection of the state, with its ultimate dependence on

armed forces, and from the conviction that any morally viable human

society depends upon the uncoerced goodwill of its members.

These and other threads of anarchist thought have different emphases.

What links them all is their rejection of external authority, whether

that of the state, the employer, or the hierarchies of administration

and of established institutions like the school and the church. The same

is true of more recently emerging varieties of anarchist propaganda,

green anarchism and anarcha-feminism. Like those who believe that animal

liberation is an aspect of human liberation, they claim that the only

ideology consistent with their aims is anarchism.

It is customary to relate the anarchist tradition to four major thinkers

and writers. The first was William Godwin (1756–1836), who in his

Inquiry Concerning Political Justice, published in 1793, set out the

anarchist case against government, the law, property, and the

institutions of the state. He was the partner of Mary Wollstonecraft and

the father of Mary Shelley, and was an heir of both the English

tradition of radical nonconformity and of the French philosophes. His

book brought him instant fame, soon followed by hostility and neglect in

the political climate of the early 19^(th) century, but it had an

underground life in radical circles until its rediscovery by the

anarchist movement in the 1890s.

The second of these pioneers was Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809–65), the

French propagandist who was the first one to call himself an anarchist.

He became famous in 1840 by virtue of an essay that declared that

‘Property is Theft’, but he also claimed that ‘Property is Freedom’. He

saw no contradiction between these two slogans, since he thought it

obvious that the first related to the landowner and capitalist whose

ownership derived from conquest or exploitation and was sustained only

through the state, its property laws, police, and army; while the second

was concerned with the peasant or artisan family with an obvious natural

right to a home, to the land it could cultivate, and to the tools of a

trade, but not to ownership or control of the homes, land, or livelihood

of others. Proudhon was criticized for being a mere survivor of the

world of peasant farmers and small artisans in local communities, but he

had a ready response in setting out the principles of successful

federation.

The third of the classical anarchist luminaries was the Russian

revolutionary Michael Bakunin (1814–76), deservedly famous for his

disputes with Marx in the First International in the 1870s, where, for

his successors, he predicted with remarkable accuracy the outcome of

Marxist dictatorships in the 20^(th) century. ‘Freedom without

socialism,’ he said, ‘is privilege and injustice, but socialism without

freedom is slavery and brutality.’ His elaborations on this perception

are cited in innumerable books published since the collapse of the

Soviet Union, and subsequently of the regimes it imposed on its

satellites. Typical of Bakunin’s observations was a letter of 1872 in

which he remarked:

I believe that Herr Marx is a very serious if not very honest

revolutionary, and that he really is in favor of the rebellion of the

masses, and I wonder how he manages to overlook the fact that the

establishment of a universal dictatorship, collective or individual, a

dictatorship which would create the post of a kind of chief engineer of

world revolution, ruling and controlling the insurrectionary activity of

the masses in all countries, as a machine might be controlled – that the

establishment of such a dictatorship would in itself suffice to kill

revolution and warp and paralyze all popular movements ...

The last of these key thinkers was another Russian of aristocratic

origin, Peter Kropotkin (1842–1921). His original reputation derived

from his work as a geographer, and in a long series of books and

pamphlets he sought to give anarchism a scientific basis. The Conquest

of Bread (1892) was his manual on the self-organization of a

post-revolutionary society. Mutual Aid (1902) was written to confront

those misinterpretations of Darwinism that justified competitive

capitalism, by demonstrating from the observation of animal and human

societies that competition within species is far less significant than

cooperation as a precondition for survival.

Fields, Factories and Workshops (1899) was Kropotkin’s treatise on the

humanization of work, through the integration of agriculture and

industry, of brain work and physical work, and of intellectual and

manual education. The most widely read on a global scale of all

anarchist authors, he linked anarchism both with subsequent ideas of

social ecology and with everyday experience.

Some anarchists would object to the identification of anarchism with its

best-known writers. They would point out that everywhere in the world

where anarchist ideas have arisen, there is a local activist conspiring

to get access to a printing press, aware of the anarchist undercurrent

in every uprising of the downtrodden all through history, and full of

ideas about the application of anarchist solutions to local issues and

dilemmas. They point to the way in which anarchist aspirations can be

traced through the slave revolts of the ancient world, the peasant

risings of medieval Europe, in the aims of the Diggers in the English

Revolution of the 1640s, in the revolutions in France in 1789 and 1848,

and the Paris Commune of 1871. In the 20^(th) century, anarchism had a

role in the Mexican Revolution of 1911, the Russian Revolution of 1917,

and most notably in the revolution in Spain that followed the military

uprising that precipitated the civil war in 1936. The part played by the

anarchists in these revolutionary situations is described in the

following chapter.

In all these revolutions the fate of the anarchists was that of heroic

losers. But anarchists do not necessarily fit the stereotype of

believers in some ultimate revolution, succeeding where all others had

failed, and inaugurating Utopia. The German anarchist Gustav Landauer

declared that:

The state is not something which can be destroyed by a revolution, but

is a condition, a certain relationship between human beings, a mode of

human behavior; we destroy it by contracting other relationships, by

behaving differently.

Moreover, if the anarchists have not changed society in the ways that

they hoped were possible, the same is true for the advocates of every

other social ideology of the past century, whether socialist or

capitalist. But, as I stress in Chapter 8, they have contributed to a

long series of small liberations that have lifted a huge load of human

misery.

Anarchism has, in fact, an enduring resilience. Every European, North

American, Latin American, and Asian society has had its anarchist

publicists, journals, circles of adherents, imprisoned activists, and

martyrs. Whenever an authoritarian and repressive political regime

collapses, the anarchists are there, a minority urging their fellow

citizens to absorb the lessons of the sheer horror and irresponsibility

of government.

The anarchist press reemerged in Germany after Hitler, in Italy after

Mussolini, in Spain after Franco, in Portugal after Salazar, in

Argentina after the generals, and in Russia after 70 years of brutal

suppression. For anarchists this is an indication that the ideal of a

self-organizing society based on voluntary cooperation rather than upon

coercion is irrepressible. It represents, they claim, a universal human

aspiration. This is illustrated by the way that people from non-European

cultures took Western anarchist ideas and concepts and linked them to

traditions and thinkers from their own countries.

Anarchist ideas were brought to Japan by Kotuku Shusui in the very early

years of the 20^(th) century. He had read Kropotkin’s writings while in

prison during the Russo-Japanese War of 1904–5. When released he visited

California, making contact with the militant anarcho-syndicalists of the

Industrial Workers of the World (IWW), and returned to Japan to publish

an anti-militarist journal, Heimen. Kotuku claimed that there was always

an anarchist undercurrent in Japanese life, deriving from both Buddhism

and Taoism. He was one of 12 anarchists executed in 1911, accused of

plotting against the Emperor Meiji. All through the first half of the

century, a series of successors continued propaganda and industrial

action against militarism, and were suppressed by government, to

reappear in a changed climate after the horrors of the Second World War.

Chinese anarchism emerged at much the same time, through the influence

of students who had been to Tokyo or to Paris. Those who studied in

Japan were influenced by Kotuku Shusui, and stressed the links with a

long-established stream in Chinese life. As Peter Marshall explains,

Modern anarchism not only advocated the Taoist rural idyll, but also

echoed the peasant longing embedded in Chinese culture for a frugal and

egalitarian millennium which had expressed itself in peasant rebellions

throughout Chinese history. It further struck a chord with two

traditional concepts, Ta-t’ung, a legendary golden age of social

equality and harmony, and Ching-t’ien, a system of communal land tenure.

Those young Chinese who studied in Paris were attracted by the writings

of Bakunin and Kropotkin, as well as by Darwinian evolutionary theory.

They rejected attempts to link anarchism with Lao Tzu’s Taoism and with

agrarian history. With the fall of the Manchu dynasty in 1911, both

anarchist factions thought that their hour had come. But in fact the

revolutionary ideology that slowly triumphed in the turbulent history of

20^(th)-century China was that of the Marxist-Leninists. And as we shall

see in Chapter 2, the programs imposed by force on the Chinese were a

dictatorial parody of anarchist aspirations.

Korea, too, has an anarchist tradition linked with 19^(th)-century hopes

for peasant communism, but due to 35 years of Japanese occupation

fiercely resisted by the anarchists, among other political factions,

their reputation is that of patriots in a country where the North is a

Marxist dictatorship while the South is a model of American-style

capitalism.

In India the history of the first half of the 20^(th) century, and the

struggle to end British rule, was dominated by Mohandas K. Gandhi, who

built a unique ideology of nonviolent resistance and peasant socialism

from a series of semi-anarchist sources and linked them with Indian

traditions. From Tolstoy he evolved his policy of nonviolent resistance,

from Thoreau he took his philosophy of civil disobedience, and from a

close reading of Kropotkin his program of decentralized and autonomous

village communes linking agriculture with local industry. After

independence was achieved, his political successors revered his memory

but ignored his ideas. Later in the century Vinoba Bhave’s Sarvodaya

movement sought a nonviolent land-based revolution, rejecting the

politics of central government.

In Africa, Mbah and Igarewey the authors of a study of the failure of

state socialism imposed by governments draw attention to the

seemingly endemic problem of ethnic conflicts across the continent; the

continued political and economic marginalization of Africa at the global

level; the unspeakable misery of about 90 percent of Africa’s

population; and, indeed, the ongoing collapse of the nation state in

many parts of Africa.

They argue that:

Given these problems, a return to the ‘anarchic elements’ in African

communalism is virtually inevitable. The goal of a self-managed society

born out of the free will of its people and devoid of authoritarian

control and regimentation is as attractive as it is feasible in the long

run.

The reader may wonder why, if ideas and aspirations similar to those of

the anarchists can be traced through so many cultures around the world,

the concept is so regularly misunderstood or caricatured. The answer is

to be found in a very small episode in anarchist history.

There was a period, a century ago, when a minority of anarchists, like

the subsequent minorities of a dozen other political movements, believed

that the assassination of monarchs, princes, and presidents would hasten

popular revolution. Sad to say, the most deserving victims, Mussolini,

Franco, Hitler, or Stalin, were well protected, and in terms of changing

the course of history and ridding the world of its tyrants the

anarchists were no more successful than most subsequent political

assassins. But their legacy has been the cartoonist’s stereotype of the

anarchist as the cloaked and bearded carrier of a spherical bomb with a

smoking fuze, and this has consequently provided yet another obstacle to

the serious discussion of anarchist approaches. Meanwhile, modern

political terrorism on an indiscriminate scale is the monopoly of

governments and is directed at civilian populations, or is the weapon we

all associate with religious or nationalist separatism, both of them

very far from the aspirations of anarchists.

In the entry for ‘Anarchism’ that Kropotkin wrote in 1905 for the

11^(th) edition of the Encyclopedia Britannica, he began by explaining

that it is

the name given to a principle or theory of life and conduct under which

society is conceived without government – harmony in such a society

being obtained, not by submission to law, or by obedience to any

authority, but by free agreements, concluded between the various groups,

territorial and professional, freely constituted for the sake of

production and consumption, as also for the satisfaction of the infinite

variety of needs and aspirations of a civilized being.

Implicit in this definition is the inevitability of compromise, an

ordinary aspect of politics which has been found difficult by

anarchists, precisely because their ideology precludes the usual routes

to political influence.

Chapter 2. Revolutionary moments

In the course of the revolutionary outbreaks that spread across Europe

in 1848 the Prefect of Police in Paris is said to have remarked of the

anarchist Michael Bakunin, ‘What a man! On the first day of the

revolution he is a perfect treasure; but on the next day he ought to be

shot.’ His observation epitomizes both the role and the ultimate fate of

the anarchists and their precursors in a long series of European popular

uprisings.

Chroniclers of all political movements invariably discover antecedents

from the past, and the anarchists found ancestors in the slave revolts

of the Roman Empire and in all subsequent revolutionary upheavals of the

downtrodden. They have similarly identified precursors in such risings

as the Peasants’ Revolt that began in England in 1391, in the

insurrection of the Taborites in Bohemia in 1493 and that of the

Anabaptists a century later.

In the English Revolution of the civil war years leading up to 1649, the

anarchist element was illustrated by the activities of the Diggers,

Ranters, and Levelers, who, having helped to ensure Cromwell’s success,

were described by one pamphleteer as ‘Switzerising anarchists’ and were

rapidly eliminated once the Protector was securely in power, only to be

followed by the eventual return of the monarchy. But the people who

dared to remove a king had opened the way to more radical thoughts on

the relationship between the individual and the community and between

society and the state. The American and French revolutions of the

following century brought a message beautifully expressed in Thomas

Paine’s Common Sense in 1776:

Society in every state is a blessing, but government even in its best

state is but a necessary evil; in its worst state an intolerable one;

for when we suffer, or are exposed to the same miseries by a government

which we might expect in a country without a government, our calamity is

heightened by reflecting that we furnish the means by which we suffer.

Government, like dress, is the badge of lost innocence: the palaces of

kings are built on the ruins of the bowers of paradise.

Political ideas crossed the Atlantic almost as rapidly in the 18^(th)

century as in the 21^(st), and the American Revolution made the French

Revolution inevitable. Jefferson, Paine, and Franklin had a role in

both, while William Godwin in his Inquiry Concerning Political Justice

was arguing the anarchist case from first principles. Meanwhile, a

series of brave opponents of the new French state, known as the Enragés

and gathered around Jacques Roux and Jean Varlet, opposed the new

rulers. Varlet, who actually survived the Terror, observed that

Despotism has passed from the palace of kings to the circle of a

committee. It is neither the royal robes, nor the scepter, nor the

crown, that makes kings hated, but ambition and tyranny. In my country

there has been only a change in dress.

Anarchism reappeared in the European revolutions of 1848. In the

following year, after the failure of the revolution in Dresden, Bakunin

was imprisoned, condemned to death, and after a year handed over to the

Austrians, condemned again, but in the next year handed over to the

Russians. After six years in the Peter-and-Paul fortress at St

Petersburg he was exiled to Siberia, whence he eventually escaped to

London by way of Japan, San Francisco, and New York. After the

Franco-Prussian War of 1870, Proudhon’s federalist ideas shaped the

short-lived Paris Commune and its ‘Manifesto to the French People’ of

April 1871, which urged:

The absolute autonomy of the Commune extended to all the localities of

France, assuring to each its integral rights and to every Frenchman the

full exercise of his aptitudes, as a man, a citizen, and a worker. The

autonomy of the Commune will have for its limits only the equal autonomy

of all other communities adhering to the contract; their association

must assure the liberty of France.

(Needless to say, although the Commune had an admired anarchist heroine,

Louise Michel, its Manifesto did not extend these rights to

Frenchwomen.)

In the major revolutions of the 20^(th) century there were recognizable

anarchist elements, but in each of them the anarchists were victims of

the new rulers. In Mexico, Ricardo Flores Magon and his brothers had in

1900 begun publication of an anarcho-syndicalist newspaper RegeneraciĂłn,

building up opposition to the dictator Porfirio Diaz, slipping across

the border into California when publication became too difficult. With

the fall of Diaz, Magon established contact with the peasant

revolutionary Emiliano Zapata in the state of Morales in the South,

fighting the efforts of large landowners to annex the land of poor

growers. Magon is said to have made Zapata literate through reading and

discussing Kropotkin’s The Conquest of Bread. Zapata was ambushed and

killed in 1919, while Magon was jailed in the United States and was

murdered in Leavenworth Penitentiary in 1923. Ironically, both men are

celebrated in the Rotunda of Illustrious Men in Mexico City. The

contemporary EZLN (Zapatista Army of National Liberation) is Mexico’s

modern incarnation of Zapata’s campaign, as is, for example, the MST

(Movement of Landless Rural Workers) in Brazil. Both of these are

campaigns of dispossessed peasants for communal control of land seized

by large-scale cattle-ranching oligarchies.

In the Russian Revolution of 1917 the Bolshevik seizure of power was

pushed through with anarchist slogans like ‘Bread and Freedom’ and ‘All

Power to the Soviets’, which were very far from daily experience in the

new regime. The anarchist hero of the revolution was the Ukrainian

peasant Nestor Makhno, organizing peasant land seizures and defending

them from both the Bolsheviks and the Whites. Returning Russian exiles

included Emma Goldman and Alexander Berkman, deported from the United

States, and Kropotkin, who had been obliged to live abroad for 40 years.

Kropotkin addressed critical letters to Lenin and wrote a Letter to the

Workers of Western Europe describing for them the lessons of the Russian

Revolution. His funeral in 1921 was the last occasion when the Russian

anarchists were at liberty until the slow releases from Stalin’s prison

camps after 1956.

Goldman and Berkman tried to tell the truth about Lenin’s Russia when

they left the country, but found that the political Left in the West

rejected their message, seeing it as ‘counter-revolutionary’. The same

kind of exclusion by the political Left faced continual anarchist

attempts to reveal the truth about the Soviet Union, while Stalinist

infiltration destroyed the integrity of a long series of workers’

organizations in the West.

Italy’s anarchist tradition began when Bakunin settled there in 1863,

recommended to fellow revolutionaries by Garibaldi and Mazzini, whose

nationalism he actually opposed in the name of communal autonomy and

federalism. To this period of Bakunin’s life belong his polemics against

Marx which, accurately and uniquely, foresaw the evolution of Marxist

dictatorships in the 20^(th) century. His disciple Errico Malatesta, who

died under house arrest in Mussolini’s Italy, initiated streams of

anarchist propaganda in Italy and Latin America, which still flow to

this day in the form of an impressive spread of publications and

campaigns.

In the Far East, the habit of sending young men from affluent families

to complete their education in Europe led to a string of revolutionary

students bringing back to China from Paris the anarchist message of

Kropotkin in his propagandist books The Conquest of Bread, Mutual Aid,

and especially Fields, Factories and Workshops. Many of the shifts and

turns of Communist Party policy in China in the 1950s and 1960s have

recognizable links with Kropotkin’s agenda, although, of course, they

were imposed with the utmost indifference to human suffering. The

celebrated novelist Pa Chin (Li Pai Kan) saw Emma Goldman as his

‘spiritual mother’ and constructed his pseudonym from one syllable each

of the names Bakunin and Kropotkin. Needless to say, he was subjected to

‘reeducation’ several times, and, in 1989, at the age of 84, was

arrested because of his support for the demonstrators in Tiananmen

Square.

But the country where anarchism put down its deepest roots was Spain,

which in the 1930s had both a mass anarcho-syndicalist trade union, the

CNT (ConfederaciĂłn Nacional del Trabajo), and the FAI (FederaciĂłn

Anarquista Iberica), an anarchist body which emerged periodically from

an underground existence. The revolution of 19 July 1936 in Spain

illustrates another gulf between the anarchist account of events and the

way they are perceived and described by more influential voices.

On 18 July 1936, Spain had three Popular Front governments in the course

of a single day, debating how to oppose the military revolt from the

generals in Morocco, which was moving into mainland Spain, and usually

concluding that resistance was futile. Meanwhile in several cities and

regions, not only were the weapons of the military garrisons and the

civil guards seized, but CNT members took control of factories,

transport, and land. The following day marked the beginning, not only of

a war against Franco’s insurrection, but of a popular revolution.

Franco’s rebellion was aided by weapons, troops, and bomber aircraft

from Mussolini’s Italy and Nazi Germany, but the Non-Intervention

Agreement upheld by the British and French governments limited the

supply of arms for the anti-Fascist forces to those provided (at the

cost of Spain’s gold reserves) by the Soviet Union. A further heavy

penalty was paid for Soviet support. Stalin’s foreign policy required

the repudiation of the Spanish revolution in the interests of the

‘Popular Front’ concept. In the effort to resist growing Soviet

influence, anarchist and syndicalist militants actually became ministers

both in the Catalan government in Barcelona and in the central

government in Madrid.

The war in Spain wound down to its desolate conclusion in April 1939,

after immense loss of life. In August that year the non-aggression pact

between Stalin and Hitler was signed, and in September the Second World

War began. Franco’s regime in Spain survived until the dictator’s death

in 1975. The collapse of opposition brought a relentless campaign of

vengeance against those who dared to oppose Franco. There were untold

numbers of executions and the prisons were filled. Millions of Spaniards

lived out their lives in exile.

From the point of view of the anarchists, Spain thus provided terrible

ironies. In terms of the collectivization of agriculture and industry,

it gave a living and inspiring example of Kropotkin’s theories about the

seizure of control by the workers. In those parts of the country that

had not been seized by army units supporting Franco there were

large-scale seizures of land. Spain was a predominantly agricultural

country, in which 67% of the land was owned by 2% of landowners. At the

same time many smallholdings were too small to feed a family. Gerald

Brenan, in his classic book The Spanish Labyrinth, explained that ‘the

only reasonable solution through wide tracts of Spain is a collective

one’.

In 1936 it was estimated that in those parts of Spain not overrun by

Franco’s troops, about three million men, women, and children were

living in collectivized communes. Observers from the time similarly

reported on the collectivization of factories in Catalonia and of the

reorganization of public services, transport, telephones, gas, and

electricity in Barcelona.

The American philosopher of language Noam Chomsky remembers reading

about these achievements as a boy in New York, in the Yiddish-language

anarchist journal Fraye Arbeter Shtime. There stayed in his mind a

report on a poverty-stricken Spanish town, Membrilla, in whose miserable

huts eight thousand people lived, with ‘no newspaper, no cinema, neither

a cafĂ© nor a library’. But the villagers shared food, clothing, and

tools, and took in a large number of refugees. ‘It was, however, not a

socialization of wealth but of poverty ... Membrilla is perhaps the

poorest village of Spain, but it is the most just.’ Chomsky comments

that

An account such as this, with its concern for human relations and the

ideal of a just society, must appear very strange to the consciousness

of the sophisticated intellectual, and it is therefore treated with

scorn, or taken to be naive or primitive or otherwise irrational. Only

when such prejudice is abandoned will it be possible for historians to

undertake a serious study of the popular movement that transformed

Republican Spain in one of the most remarkable social revolutions that

history records.

By now the serious studies have been made, and Chomsky has stressed

their significance and their lessons for the future, since, as he says,

What attracts me about anarchism personally are the tendencies in it

that try to come to grips with the problems of dealing with complex

organized industrial societies within a framework of free institutions

and structures.

The Spanish experience hardly met the second of his criteria, but the

events of 1936 amply justified his comments. These achievements were

barely noticed in the news media of Western Europe outside the journals

of anarchism and the noncommunist far Left, and when George Orwell, back

from Spain, attempted to puncture the conspiracy of silence in his

Homage to Catalonia in 1937, his book had sold a mere 300 copies before

being remaindered to the anarchist bookshop in 1940. Many decades later,

Ken Loach’s film Land and Freedom (1995) was rapturously received in

Spain for dramatizing a key episode in the civil war, hitherto almost

unknown in Spain itself.

Needless to say, in the years of exile, those anarchists who had

survived both the war and Franco’s revenge devoted endless debate to the

fatal decision of the leaders of the CNT to become part of government in

an effort to combat Soviet dominance. Since every variety of anarchism

has opposed the structure of politics and the political system, this

decision was seen as a compromise that brought no advantage and much

discredit. Those anarchists who have explored the issue tend to agree

with the comment of the veteran French anarchist SĂ©bastien Faure: ‘I am

aware of the fact that it is not always possible to do what one should

do; but I know that there are things that on no account can one ever

do.’

Meanwhile, decades later, a new series of popular uprisings rediscovered

anarchist slogans in heroic defiance of Stalin’s apparently monolithic

empire. Suppressed aspirations emerged on the streets of Hungarian and

Polish cities in 1956 and on those of Czechoslovakia in 1968. They were

harbingers of the subsequent bloodless collapse of the Soviet Union,

after decades of appalling suffering for those who, usually

inadvertently, failed to please their rulers.

As the regimes of their jailers collapsed around them, there was some

comfort for the surviving anarchists, with their black flags of protest

against the new capitalism steered into being by their old oppressors.

They were still monotonously right and their priorities remained the

same.

Chapter 3. States, societies, and the collapse of socialism

There is a vital distinction, stressed by anarchists, between society

and the state. It has been obvious for centuries, and although many

political thinkers have ignored this distinction, it was as clear, for

example, to such 20^(th)-century academics as Isaiah Berlin or G. D. H.

Cole as it was in the 18^(th) century to Thomas Paine, cited in the

previous chapter. However, accompanying the collapse of the Soviet

Empire there has been a rediscovery by political enquirers of ‘civil

society’.

The philosopher Martin Buber was the friend and executor of the German

anarchist Gustav Landauer, whose observation about the nature of the

state as a mode of human behavior is discussed in Chapter 1. In his

capacity as a professor of sociology, Buber provided a striking

polarization of the two principles of human behavior involved: the

political and the social. He saw the characteristics of the political

principle to be power, authority, hierarchy, and dominion, while the

social principle was visible to him in all spontaneous human

associations built around a common need or common interest. The problem

that arose was that of identifying the reason for the continual

ascendancy of the political principle. Buber’s answer suggested that

the fact that every people feels itself threatened by the others gives

the state its definite unifying power; it depends upon the instinct of

self-preservation of society itself; the latent external crisis enables

it to get the upper hand in internal crises ... All forms of government

have this in common: each possesses more power than is required by the

given conditions; in fact, this excess in the capacity for making

dispositions is actually what we understand by political power. The

measure of this excess ... represents the exact difference between

administration and government.

Buber described this excess, which he admitted could not be computed

exactly, as the ‘political surplus’, and observed that

its justification derives from the external and internal instability,

from the latent state of crisis between nations and within every nation.

The political principle is always stronger in relation to the social

principle than the given conditions require. The result is a continuous

diminution in social spontaneity.

Social spontaneity is highly valued by anarchists but is not on the

agenda of the politicians involved in dismantling the British postwar

welfare state, and recommending the virtues of profit-making private

enterprise. Anarchists are frequently told that their antipathy to the

state is historically outmoded, since a main function of the modern

state is the provision of social welfare. They respond by stressing that

social welfare in Britain did not originate from government, nor from

the postwar National Insurance laws, nor with the initiation of the

National Health Service in 1948. It evolved from the vast network of

friendly societies and mutual aid organizations that had sprung up

through working-class self-help in the 19^(th) century.

The founding father of the NHS was the then member of parliament for

Tredegar in South Wales, Aneurin Bevan, the Labor Government’s Minister

of Health. His constituency was the home of the Tredegar Medical

Society, founded in 1870 and surviving until 1995. It provided medical

care for the local employed workers, who were mostly miners and

steelworkers, but also (unlike the pre-1948 National Health Insurance)

for the needs of dependents, children, the old, and the non-employed:

everyone living in the district.

It was

sustained through the years by voluntary contributions of three old

pennies in the pound from the wage-packets of miners and steelworkers

... At one time the society employed five doctors, a dentist, a

chiropodist and a physiotherapist to care for the health of about 25,000

people.

A retired miner told Peter Hennessy that when Bevan initiated the

National Health Service, ‘We thought he was turning the whole country

into one big Tredegar.’ In practice, the Health Service has been in a

state of continuous reorganization ever since its foundation, but has

never been submitted to a local and federalized approach to medical

care. A second reflection on the story of Tredegar is that when every

employed worker in that town paid a voluntary levy to extend the local

medical service to every resident, the earnings of even highly skilled

industrial workers were below the liability to income tax. But ever

since full employment and the system of PAYE (automatic deduction of tax

as a duty of employers) was introduced during the Second World War, the

central government’s Treasury has creamed off the cash that once

supported local initiatives. If the pattern of local self-taxation on

the Tredegar model had become the general pattern for health provision,

this permanent daily need would not have become the plaything of central

government financial policy.

Anarchists cite this little, local example of an alternative approach to

the provision of health care to indicate that a different style of

social organization could have evolved. In British experience, another

variety was to be found in the 1930s and 1950s in what became known as

the Peckham Experiment in south London, which was essentially a family

health club where medical care was a feature of a social club providing

sporting and swimming facilities. These and much more recent attempts to

change the relationships in meeting universal social needs exemplify the

urgency of the search for alternatives to the dreary polarity of public

bureaucracy on the one hand and private profit on the other. I have

myself heard the former chief architect to the Ministry of Health admit

that the advice he gave for years on hospital design was misguided, and

have heard similar confessions from management consultants, expensively

hired to solve the NHS’s organizational problems.

A century ago, Kropotkin noted the endless variety of ‘friendly

societies, the unities of odd fellows, the village and town clubs

organized for meeting the doctor’s bills’ built up by working-class

self-help; as part of his evidence for Mutual Aid: A Factor of

Evolution, and in a later book, Modern Science and Anarchism, he

declared that ‘the economic and political liberation of man will have to

create new forms for its expression in life, instead of those

established by the State’. For he saw it as self-evident that ‘this new

form will have to be more popular, more decentralized, and nearer to the

folk-mote self-government than representative government can ever be’.

He reiterated that we will be compelled to find new forms of

organization for the social functions that the state fulfills through

the bureaucracy, and that ‘as long as this is not done, nothing will be

done’.

It is often suggested that as a result of modern personal mobility and

instant communications, we all live in a series of global villages and

that consequently the concept of local control of local services is

obsolete. But there is confusion here between the concepts of

communities of propinquity and communities of interest. We may share

concerns with people on the other side of the world, and not even know

our neighbors. But the picture is transformed at different stages in our

personal or family history when we have shared interests with other

users of the local primary school or health center, and the local shop

or post office. Here there is, as every parent will confirm, an intense

concern with very local issues.

Alternative patterns of social control of local facilities could have

emerged, but for the fact that centralized government imposed national

uniformity, while popular disillusionment with the bureaucratic welfare

state coincided with the rise of the all-party gospel of managerial

capitalism. Anarchists claim that after the inevitable disappointment,

an alternative concept of socialism will be rediscovered. They argue

that the identification of social welfare with bureaucratic

managerialism is one of the factors that has delayed the exploration of

other approaches for half a century. The private sector, as it is

called, is happy to take over the health needs of those citizens who can

pay its bills. Other citizens would either have to suffer the minimal

services that remain for them, or to re-create the institutions that

they built up in the 19^(th) century. The anarchists see their methods

as more relevant than ever, waiting to be reinvented, precisely because

modern society has learned the limitations of both socialist and

capitalist alternatives.

A once-famous book, James Burnham’s The Managerial Revolution, traced a

shift in power in companies from shareholders to managers. But another

more recent change in the power structure of public services of every

kind has been felt, for example, all through the education system. It is

the rise to dominance of professional managers who are the new

unassailable masters of every kind of institution. Middle-class

professionals in, say, public health, environmental planning, schools

and universities, and the social services have found themselves

subjected to the same kind of managerial Newspeak that used to outrage

working-class trade unionists. Mastery of its grotesque jargon has

become the prerequisite for appointment and promotion throughout the job

market, except in the submerged economy of hard repetitive work, where

the old assumptions of insecurity, long hours, and low pay remain true.

The new managerialism has such insubstantial foundations and has aroused

such resentment among people proud of their professional skills (as was

also true of skilled workers displaced by globalization) that it is

bound to be challenged by a new breed of advocates of workplace

democracy. Already the authors of alternative textbooks of management

are borrowing the language, if not the intentions, of the anarchists,

for example with a manual entitled Managing Without Management, and

another called Action and Existence: Anarchism for Business

Administration.

It seems inevitable that anarchist concepts will be reinvented or

rediscovered continually, in fields never envisaged by the propagandists

of the past, as people in so many areas of human activity search for

alternatives to the crudities and injustices of both free-market

capitalism and bureaucratic managerial socialism. It is possible to

discern four principles that would shape an anarchist theory of

organizations: that they should be (1) voluntary, (2) functional, (3)

temporary, and (4) small.

They should be voluntary and functional for obvious reasons. There is no

point in advocating individual freedom and responsibility if we go on to

set up organizations in which membership is mandatory, or which have no

purpose. There is a tendency for bodies to continue to exist after

having outlived their functions. They should be temporary precisely

because permanence is one of those factors that hardens the arteries of

any organization, giving it a vested interest in its own survival, or in

serving the interests of its office-holders rather than performing its

ostensible functions. Finally, they should be small because in small,

face-to-face groups the bureaucratizing and hierarchical tendencies

inherent in all organizations have least opportunity to develop.

The 20^(th) century experienced or witnessed every variety of state

socialism, and learned that if its rulers are ruthless enough, they can

impose, for a while, the most bizarre regimes and describe them as

socialism. As socialism has been grossly misrepresented, so anarchism

suffers from the widely held view that it is simply another variety of

millenarianism, the belief in the eventual arrival, ‘after the

revolution’, of a period of ultimate happiness when all the problems

that beset humanity will have been solved, permanently.

The 19^(th)-century anarchist propaganda, in common with other varieties

of socialist propaganda, frequently implied this, but I have seldom met

20^(th)-century anarchists who admitted to this simple faith. As for the

great 20^(th)-century tragedy of the Soviet Union, promising earthly

paradise for future generations earned by today’s sacrifice, the

anarchist inquest on it was written as long ago as 1847 by Bakunin’s

friend, the Russian populist Alexander Herzen:

If progress is the goal, for whom then are we working? Who is this

Moloch who, as the toilers approach him, instead of rewarding them,

draws back, and as a consolation to the exhausted multitudes shouting,

‘We, who are about to die, salute thee!’, can only give the mocking

answer that after their death all will be beautiful on earth. Do you

really wish to condemn human beings alive today to the mere sad role of

caryatids supporting a floor for others one day to dance upon? Of

wretched galley slaves who, up to their knees in mud, drag a barge with

the humble words ‘Future Progress’ on its flag?

A goal which is infinitely remote is not a goal at all, it is a

deception. A goal must be closer – at the very least the laborer’s wage

or pleasure in the work performed. Each epoch, each generation, each

life has had, and has, its own experience, and en route new demands

grow, new methods.

Socialism in the 20^(th) century promised ‘jam tomorrow’ so regularly,

and the promise remained so often unfulfilled, that as Herzen insisted,

new generations will have to evolve their own more immediate social

aims, which, the anarchists hope, will be structured around styles of

social organization other than the machinery of the state.

But because it is frequently suggested that anarchism is simply

inappropriate for the scale of modern society, the concept of federalism

is vital for any attempt to build an anarchist theory of organization.

Anarchist approaches to federalism are fully discussed in Chapter 9.

Chapter 4. Deflating nationalism and fundamentalism

The anarchists claim that popular self-organization could provide those

new forms of social organization which, as Kropotkin put it in an

observation I have cited earlier, would undertake ‘those social

functions that the state fulfills through the bureaucracy’. However,

these are not the only issues that are raised when skeptics dismiss

anarchism as a primitive ideology that is simply not relevant to the

modern world. They have a different reason, as they observe the modern

nation state and the intense hostilities and rivalries arising between

the government of any major state and others. Or, indeed, the lethal

hatreds visible among different factions within one territory that has

been designated as a state, and the frightening antagonisms that emerge

between the adherents of different religions. They may notice especially

the poisonous legacy of European imperialism to the territories that the

empire-building powers seized and colonized.

It is probably still important to remind the British, French, Belgians,

Germans, Spanish, Portuguese, Italians, Dutch, Austrians, Greeks, Turks,

Russians, and Americans, among others, that most of the intractable

disputes around the globe today are a direct result of the imperialist

policies of their one-time rulers, with their fatal fascination for

seizing some other part of the world, and their cynical application of

the slogan ‘Divide and Rule’. All around the world people are suffering

today as a result of the activity of the empire-builders, and militant

attitudes usually succeed in making matters worse. For nationalist

movements, as Avi Shlaim has expressed it,

have an in-built tendency towards extremism and xenophobia, towards

self-righteousness on the one hand and demonizing the enemy on the

other. History is often falsified and even fabricated to serve a

nationalist political agenda.

It is hard to see how the anarchists, with an absolute hostility to both

religious rivalries and territorial politics, can engage in these

disputes, beyond the direct rejection of imperialism, except to wish

that they were in the past. Abstention itself can be a perilous, though

necessary, attitude, and we have all observed around the globe instances

when the zealots have turned their most vicious attention to those who

dare to attempt an accommodation with the people on ‘the other side’.

Martin Buber, who, half a century ago, made some valuable contributions

to an assessment of anarchism, warned his fellow Zionists as long ago as

1921 that if the Jews in Palestine did not live with the Arabs as well

as next to them, they would find themselves living in enmity with them.

When he died, 44 years later, the obituarists noted that his advocacy of

bi-nationalism caused him to be ostracized by the orthodox as ‘an enemy

of the people’.

These 20^(th)-century responses were certainly not anticipated by the

19^(th)-century anarchists. Their classical statement on religion as a

social phenomenon came from the most widely circulated work of the

Russian anarchist Michael Bakunin, God and the State. In this fragment,

written in 1871, he deplores the fact that belief in God still survived

among the people, especially, as he put it, ‘in the rural districts,

where it is more widespread than among the proletariat of the cities’.

He thought this faith in religion was all too natural, since all

governments profited from the ignorance of the people as one of the

essential conditions of their own power; while weighed down by labor,

deprived of leisure and of intellectual intercourse, the people sought

an escape. Bakunin claimed that there were three routes of escape from

the miseries of life, two of them illusory and one real. The first two

were the bottle and the church, ‘debauchery of the body or debauchery of

the mind; the third is social revolution’. Social revolution, he

asserted,

will be much more potent than all the theological propagandism of the

freethinkers to destroy to their last vestige the religious beliefs and

dissolute habits of the people, beliefs and habits much more intimately

connected than is generally supposed.

Bakunin then turned to the powerful, dominant classes in society who,

while too worldly-wise to be believers themselves, ‘must at least make a

semblance of believing’ because the simple faith of the people was a

useful factor in keeping them down. Finally, in this particular

statement of his attitudes, Bakunin turns to those propagandists for

religion who, when you challenge them on any specific absurdity in their

dogma, relating to miracles, virgin births, or resurrection, loftily

explain that they are to be understood as beautiful myths rather than

literal truths, and that we are to be pitied for our prosaic questions,

rather than them for propagating mythology as truth.

Bakunin’s opinions were much the same on this matter as those of his

adversary Karl Marx, one of whose best-known phrases was his description

of religion as the ‘opium of the people’. And the historians of ideas

would categorize liberalism, socialism, communism, and anarchism all as

products of the period known as the Enlightenment, the result of the Age

of Reason, the ferment of ideas and the spirit of inquiry between the

English Revolution of the 1640s and the American and French revolutions

of the 1770s and 1780s.

In parochial English terms, one slow, grudgingly conceded result of the

Enlightenment was religious toleration. We tend to forget that England

has a state church, founded because of a row that Henry VIII had with

the Pope over one of his divorces. It too claimed its martyrs, as the

long history of the suppression of dissenters reminds us, as does the

continual struggle for religious freedom. It wasn’t until 1858 that

legal disabilities were lifted from believing Jews, and not until 1871

that people who could not subscribe to the 39 Articles of the Church of

England were admitted to the ancient universities. The Church of England

may be an irrelevance to the majority of the British people, but it is a

reminder of an important social and political fact. One result of the

Enlightenment was that the people who wrote the constitutions of many

states sought to learn the lessons of history and the horrors of

religious wars by insisting on the absolute separation of religious

practices from public life. Religion was to be a private affair.

This was true of the founding fathers of the United States of America,

whose ancestors had fled religious persecution in Europe; it was true of

the French Republic, and consequently of those countries which, with

immense loss of life, liberated themselves from French imperialism. And

it is true of many new republics similarly founded as a result of the

collapse of imperialism in the 20^(th) century. Some key examples are

the republics of India, Turkey, Egypt, Algeria, and Israel.

Now, all over the world, the secular state is under threat. Secular

political regimes in North Africa and the Middle East are confronted by

militant religious movements, and there is a growing fundamentalist

threat to the secular constitution of the United States. This isn’t what

Bakunin or Marx, or any other political thinker of the 19^(th) century,

from Alexis de Tocqueville to John Stuart Mill, predicted.

The unexpected and unwelcome change in the religious atmosphere which we

call fundamentalism arose from a trend in religious revivalism in the

United States after the First World War, which insisted on belief in the

literal truth of everything in the Bible. The use of the term has spread

to describe trends in the Jewish, Muslim, Hindu, Sikh, and Shinto

religions which, to outsiders, present similar features. They are a

threat not only to the hard-won concept of the secular state, which

anarchists may not feel to be important, but to the hard-won freedoms of

every citizen. The anarchist and secularist propagandist Nicolas Walter

urged us to take this threat seriously, stressing that

Fundamentalist Christians are trying to suppress the study of evolution

and the practice of contraception and abortion in the West and the Third

World. Fundamentalist Jews are trying to incorpoate the whole of

Palestine into Israel and to impose the halachah, the traditional law of

Judaism. Fundamentalist Muslims are trying to establish Muslim regimes

in all countries with Muslim populations (including Britain) and to

impose the sharia, the traditional law of Islam. And fundamentalists of

all faiths are using assassination and terror all over the world to

suppress freedom and discussion of such matters.

This is an absolute tragedy for that majority of citizens in any country

who are simply concerned with the ordinary business of living, feeding a

family, and enjoying the daily pleasures of life, as well as for those

who aspire to improve conditions through community action and social

justice.

Governmental suppression of religion never works. The Soviet Union

witnessed 70 years of state hostility, sometimes violent and sometimes

benign, to religious activity. When the regime collapsed, there was a

huge revival of the Orthodox faith and a happy hunting ground for

American Protestant evangelists. In Soviet Central Asia, Malise Ruthven

suggests,

the local elites, attached to Islamic customs and recognizing a degree

of affinity between Islamic and social values, cheated on their

anti-religious activities as assiduously as they faked their

cotton-production figures. Gatherings of old men reading the Koran would

be described to zealots of the Society for Scientific Atheism as

meetings of Great Patriotic War veterans.

In Turkey, Kemal Ataturk, who also shared Bakunin’s views on religion,

embarked on a dictatorial policy of what we might call

‘de-Islamification’. His current successors are prevented from

instituting even a façade of democracy precisely because of the threat

of the return of religion. On a different time-scale, the Shah of Iran,

who was a ruthless Westernizer, was succeeded by a fundamentalist regime

that no one predicted. Egypt and Algeria are torn apart by rival elites

of the secular or religious state. In the United States the most

powerful of all political lobbies is that of the Christian Coalition,

with a growing influence in the Republican Party. It denies any

responsibility for the murder of the last doctor to perform an abortion

in the American South.

It is disappointing and unexpected for secularist anarchists, who

thought that wars of religion belonged to the past, now to have to

confront issues of the recognition of difference, while they are trying

to move on to the issues that unite rather than divide us. One approach

they can take is that of the anarchist propagandist Rudolf Rocker, a

century ago, in the Jewish community of Whitechapel in east London. Some

secularist allies had chosen the propaganda of provocative behavior on

Sabbath mornings outside the synagogue in Brick Lane. Asked his opinion

of these demonstrations, Rocker replied that the place for believers was

the house of worship, and the place for nonbelievers was the radical

meeting. But the scene has changed. For the same building that has seen

many faiths come and go, as a Huguenot church, a dissenting

meeting-house, and a Jewish synagogue, is now a mosque. Anyone harassing

the emerging worshipers today is not a secularist Bangladeshi but an

English racist, menacing and heavy, bent on instilling fear and making

trouble.

It has been said, for example, of the Bharatiya Janata (‘Indian

People’s’) Party (BJP) in India, who succeeded in spreading communal

violence into parts of the Punjab where different communities had

previously lived in harmony together, that the name of the disease is

not fundamentalism but ethnic nationalism. This view fits other parts of

the globe, and in such instances, including many areas of the Islamic

world, we can again choose to blame the endless humiliations and

devaluations of the local culture inflicted by Western imperialism.

The fear and terror induced by the overscale images of ‘terrorism’ and

‘fundamentalism’ – call them the figures of an international or

transnational imagery made up of foreign devils – hastens the

individual’s subordination to the dominant norms of the moment. This is

as true in the new post-colonial societies as it is in the West

generally and the United States particularly. Thus to oppose the

abnormality and extremism embedded in terrorism and fundamentalism – my

example has only a small degree of parody – is also to uphold the

moderation, rationality, executive centrality of a vaguely designated

‘Western’ (or otherwise local and patriotically assumed) ethos. The

irony is that far from endowing the Western ethos with the confidence

and secure ‘normality’ we associate with privilege and rectitude, this

dynamic imbues ‘us’ with a righteous anger and defensiveness in which

‘others’ are finally seen as enemies, bent on destroying our

civilization and way of life.

Edward W. Said, Culture and Imperialism

(London: Chatto and Windus, 1993)

Edward Said’s difficult diagnosis (see box below) envelops big truths.

The countries of the Near and Middle East were for centuries subjected

to one imperialism or another, their cultures ridiculed or patronized,

and even their boundaries formed by lines drawn on the map by European

governments and business. They are valued today according to their oil

resources or as potential markets, while they are awash with weapons

left over from Cold War bribes. The Western secular religion of

conspicuous consumption was readily adopted by Middle Eastern rulers,

but they offered nothing but frustrated hopes to the poor majority of

their subjects.

Another vital issue was raised by the Moroccan scholar Fatima Mernissi,

when she was asked to provide a preface for the English translation of

her book on Women and Islam.

When I finished writing this book I had come to understand one thing: if

women’s rights are a problem for some modern Muslim men, it is neither

because of the Koran, nor the Prophet, nor the Islamic tradition, but

simply because those rights conflict with the interests of a male elite.

The elite faction is trying to convince us that their egotistical,

highly subjective and mediocre view of culture and society has a sacred

basis.

In common with all the other left-wing factions of the late 19^(th) and

early 20^(th) centuries, the anarchists saw territorial and religious

separatism as irrelevant preoccupations that human society had outgrown.

Their only possible message is the hope that zealotry will lose its

impetus when its leaders find they have no followers, as people discover

more interesting, more enjoyable, or at the very least less lethal,

issues to discuss with their neighbors.

Chapter 5. Containing deviancy and liberating work

From the fall of the Bastille in 1789, which actually released only

seven prisoners, to the death of Stalin in 1953, which slowly liberated

millions, the anarchists, through personal experience, provided an

impressive literature on the defects of the penal system. Kropotkin’s

first book was his account of his experiences In Russian and French

Prisons (1887), and Alexander Berkman’s was his Prison Memoirs of an

Anarchist (1912).

It was Kropotkin who first used the phrase ‘prisons are the universities

of crime’, and his observation remains true in the sense that the first

imprisonment of any offender becomes a guarantee that he, like the

people with whom he shares a cell, will learn in jail a long series of

more sophisticated criminal techniques than the petty larceny that

started off his prison career. Kropotkin claimed in 1886 that a society

built around cooperation rather than competition would, for that very

reason, suffer less from antisocial activity. He argued that

Peoples without political organization, and therefore less depraved than

ourselves, have perfectly understood that the man who is called

‘criminal’ is simply unfortunate; that the remedy is not to flog him, to

chain him up, or to kill him on the scaffold or in prison, but to help

him by the most brotherly care, by treatment based on equality, by the

usages of life among honest men.

It could be claimed that the best service the British and American

governments in the two world wars of the 20^(th) century could have

provided to the cause of penal reform was the imprisonment of

war-resisters. The jailed objectors, beyond the appalling hardships that

befell some of them in the First World War, had several important

attributes. They tended to be literate people and keen observers of

their surroundings and of their fellow prisoners. They also had a useful

sense of moral superiority over their jailers, seeing the humiliations

they suffered as a reflection, not of their own situation, but of that

of the good citizens who had chosen to incarcerate them.

These observers recognized and publicized what a handful of

19^(th)-century reformers had already pointed out: that many of their

fellow prisoners, serving the current prison sentence for a lifetime

career of petty theft, petty violence, drug-dealing, or drunken idiocy,

came from a background that made their offenses and incarceration almost

inevitable. Many of us, learning the cost to the citizen of keeping any

individual in jail, and realizing that it is far more than our own

incomes, could fervently wish that we had taken heed of the warnings of

the penal reformers, who had sought to draw our attention to the common

factors in the lives of the people we imprison. Frequently, for example,

inmates have a background of institutional childhood, of mental

instability, or of educational failure. They are also, overwhelmingly,

male.

Recognition of these factors was one of the influences at the end of the

19^(th) century leading to the establishment in both Britain and America

of the probation service, in which, as an alternative to prison, a

probation officer was charged with the task of becoming the friend and

adviser of the offender, and with helping him to lead a normal working

and family life. Through much of the 20^(th) century there was a slow

humanization of the penal system, so far as this was possible, inspired

by the reformers who had been inmates and observers in the war years,

despite frequent opposition from the staff of penal establishments.

Practitioners of various therapeutic approaches gained access,

sporadically, to the penal system, with the support of some prison

governors, with significant results. They urged the prison staff that

their own status and job satisfaction would be enhanced if their work

was perceived as curative rather than custodial. Many anarchists were

skeptical about these efforts to civilize the penal system, and so, of

course, was the popular press, which regularly described open prisons as

holiday camps (revealing their journalists’ ignorance of both). In the

decades following the Second World War, many countries witnessed a

steady decline in the prison population. (Notable exceptions were the

Soviet Union and the nations whose governments it influenced.) David

Cayley explained that

The Netherlands set the standard, bringing a rate of 90 prisoners per

100,000 of population after the war down to a remarkable 17 per 100,000

in 1975 ... Reductions in imprisonment had been brought about by what

Dutch criminologist Willem de Haan once called the ‘politics of bad

conscience.’

But from the late 1970s onwards, the politics of bad conscience were

replaced by the contrasting approach described by the criminologist

Andrew Rutherford as ‘a politics of good conscience about imprisonment’.

Criminal statistics are notoriously difficult to interpret, because they

reflect simply the number of arrests for a range of offenses that any

police force is expected to record. But penal statistics are readily

available and tell a terrifying story. David Cayley reported in 1998

that

To help house the 1.5 million Americans currently in prison, 168 new

state prisons and 45 new federal prisons were built between 1990 and

1995 alone, but these were still not enough to accommodate the numbers

of new prisoners ... The United States has now exposed so many of its

citizens – especially its Black and Hispanic citizens – to the

brutalizing effects of its prisons that a self-fulfilling prophecy has

been set in motion. The more Americans who are manhandled by the

criminal justice system, the more there are whose behavior seems to

justify and demand this treatment.

By the year 2000, prisons in the United States had received their

two-millionth inmate. The sociologist David Downes remarked at a

conference on crime at New York University that no other nation in

history has ever put a bigger proportion of its citizens in jail. The

judicial system also ensures that African-American men have a 1 in 4

chance of going to prison during their lifetimes, while the chance is 1

in 23 for their white fellow citizens. Professor Downes was asked

whether Europe would be affected by the American example. He replied

that ‘The components of a steep rise in imprisonment in Europe have

already been assembled.’ His answer was correct, and Britain leads

Europe in the proportion of its citizens that it incarcerates.

Alternative approaches, shared by the anarchists with other penal

reformers, have been rejected by the politicians and their public. This

does not persuade reformers to change their opinions, but merely to

await an eventual shift in public attitudes.

There is just one field of law-breaking and law-enforcement in which a

policy of decriminalization is gaining advocates, and which would

greatly reduce the prison population. This concerns the imprisonment of

drug users and drug traders. Everyone agrees this policy is an expensive

failure that, as David Cayley observes, ‘has fostered evils far worse

than those it was supposed to eliminate’. It has the additional irony

that many users find the drugs of their choice are more easily available

inside prison than on the outside. Here it is worth noting the opinions

of the anarchist Errico Malatesta, as far back as 1922, long before our

parents or grandparents imagined that we had a drug problem.

<quote>

It is the old mistake of legislators, in spite of experience invariably

showing that laws, however barbarous they may be, have never served to

suppress vise or to discourage delinquency. The more severe the

penalties imposed on the consumers and traffickers of cocaine, the

greater will be the attractions of forbidden fruits and the fascination

of the risks incurred by the consumer, and the greater will be the

profits made by the speculators, avid for money.

It is useless, therefore, to hope for anything from the law. We must

suggest another solution. Make the use and sale of cocaine free from

restrictions, and open kiosks where it would be sold at cost price or

even under cost. And then launch a great propaganda campaign to explain

to the public, and let them see for themselves, the evils of cocaine; no

one would engage in counter-propaganda because no one could exploit the

misfortune of addicts.

Certainly the harmful use of cocaine would not disappear completely,

because the social causes which create and drive those poor devils to

the use of drugs would still exist. But in any case the evil would

decrease, because nobody could make profits out of its sale, and nobody

could speculate on the hunt for speculators. And for this reason our

suggestion either will not be taken into account, or it will be

considered impractical and mad. Yet intelligent and disinterested people

might say to themselves: Since the penal laws have proved to be

impotent, would it not be a good thing, as an experiment, to try out the

anarchist method?

Errico Malatesta in UmanitĂ  Nova, 2 September 1920,

reprinted in V. Richards (ed.), Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas

(London: Freedom Press, 1965)

In two European cities, Zurich and Amsterdam, local authorities have

boldly sought to implement such a policy, and in Britain, by the

beginning of the 21^(st) century, at least two chief constables have

expressed a similar point of view, earning sensational headlines but

little practical support.

Politicians of the major parties in Britain won popular acclaim with

rhetoric about giving offenders a ‘short, sharp shock’ or sending them

to ‘Boot Camps’, and by circumscribing the efforts of the probation

service to keep released offenders out of jail. Even the staccato,

single-syllable language of these programs indicates that the intention

was not to cope with the problem of crime but to satisfy the

headline-writers of the popular press, the real determinants of penal

policy. In the United States, the Republican Party’s electoral success

is seen to be related to its ability to portray its opponents as ‘soft

on crime’.

Meanwhile, suicides grew among young prisoners jailed for offenses that

were a nuisance, rather than a threat, to society. Moreover, it is

perfectly obvious that prison does nothing to reduce the crime rate. As

Lord Waddington, Home Secretary to Margaret Thatcher, put it, ‘Prison is

a very expensive way of making bad men worse’. Even the politicians no

longer believe in the policies they administer. This is hardly

surprising when you consider the statistics. In 2003 it was reported

that 84% of young people released from custodial sentences in Britain

rapidly reoffend. Figures from the United States would exceed this

record.

But the issues raised by the anarchists, among the ranks of the penal

reformers, will not disappear. They are made more intractable by

society’s assumptions, as manipulated by the popular press.

Another crucial question, which arose early in the history of anarchism,

concerned its application to the world of work, especially since the

anarchist pioneers tended to have links with the emerging trade union

movement. They identified with the radical end of the union spectrum,

proclaiming anarcho-syndicalism (from the French syndicat, meaning

union), which saw every local industrial struggle as a step towards a

general strike, when the collapse of capitalism would lead to a

take-over by the workers.

In France the Confédération Générale du Travail (CGT) and in Spain the

ConfederaciĂłn Nacional del Trabajo (CNT) became large-scale mass

movements, as, for a time, did the Industrial Workers of the World (IWW)

in the United States. There were, of course, inbuilt conflicts within

syndicalist unions, between those members who were willing to fight and

sometimes win little local battles over small issues, and the militants

who hoped to turn every small dispute into the final struggle to seize

control of the means of production and thus ‘expropriate the

expropriators’, continuing production under workers’ control.

But the fading away of the aim of liberating work has little to do with

the gulf between reformers and revolutionaries in the workers’

organizations. It has a far closer connection with the new, ultimate

weapon in the hands of employers against the claims of workers: ‘accept

our conditions or we will transfer our activities and your jobs to

South-east Asia or Latin America, where the labor force will be

delighted to work on our terms.’ The owners of capital remain in the

rich world, but the providers of labor are now in the developing world,

and if they should demand a larger share of the products of their work,

the employers simply shift to a cheaper labor force in another country.

Meanwhile, the rich world has a concealed labor force of its own.

Agricultural work in the picking and packing of fruit and vegetables is

undertaken by gang-masters with their teams of illegal immigrants, East

European public employes waiting for wages in their own countries,

students, and migrants. Another underclass copes with telephone and

Internet inquiries, operating in call centers from provincial Britain to

Bangalore in India.

A century ago, the ‘new unionism’ in Britain and the IWW in America set

about organizing and representing the unskilled and uncounted workers on

the fringes of the official economy, and succeeded. At the same time,

the anarchist Kropotkin was addressing a British audience which assumed

that Britain was the workshop of the world, and that for ever more the

whole globe would depend on textiles from Lancashire, coal from

Newcastle, and ships from the Clyde. In 1899, when he wrote his Fields,

Factories and Workshops, one of his aims was to demonstrate that, while

the politicians and economists thought in terms of vast factories, the

greater part of industrial production was actually carried out in small

workshops and little local enterprises. Electricity and modern transport

had decentralized production, and Kropotkin urged that this liberated

not only the location of work but the individual’s choice of occupation.

It was now possible to combine brain work and manual work, which was his

industrial ideal.

Anarchists are seldom to be found in the diminishing world of career

employment in formal industry or bureaucracy. They tend to find their

niche in the informal or small-scale economy. This is not surprising,

since industrial psychologists frequently report that satisfaction in

work is directly related to the ‘span of autonomy’ it offers, meaning

the amount of the working day or week in which the workers are free to

make their own decisions. In this post-industrial world of work, the

only serious study of the small businessman finds him to be not a

Thatcherite hero, but a creative rebel against the compulsion to be

either an employer or an employee. Paul Thompson reports that

It turns out that far from being an especially purposeful breed of men,

Samuel Smiles’ heroes a hundred years on, many small businessmen are

closer to a kind of drop-out. They disliked the whole modern capitalist

ethic, and especially being employed by others; instead they preferred

to feel the satisfaction of providing a ‘service’ and ‘doing a good

job’. Quite often it was a mere chance that allowed them to find their

present vocation. Moreover, they will not provide the basis for our next

industrial revolution, because they don’t want to expand: that would

imply employing people and losing the personal relationships they like

to have with a small number of workers.

Findings like these are far from the expectations of the

anarcho-syndicalists, who envisaged a triumphant take-over of the

factory by its workers, but they indicate clearly that anarchist

aspirations are close to the dreams of vast numbers of citizens who feel

trapped by the culture of employment.

Chapter 6. Freedom in education

The editors of a well-known anthology of anarchist writings remark that,

from the school prospectus issued by William Godwin in 1783 to Paul

Goodman’s book of 1964 on Compulsory Miseducation, ‘no other movement

whatever has assigned to educational principles, concepts, experiments

and practices a more significant place in its writings and activities’.

Godwin’s tract was published as An Account of the Seminary that will be

Opened on Monday the Fourth Day of August, at Epsom in Surrey, for the

Instruction of Twelve Pupils. It failed to convince enough parents, and

the school never opened. In this pamphlet he declared that

modern education not only corrupts the heart of our youth, by the rigid

slavery to which it condemns them, it also undermines their reason, by

the unintelligible jargon with which they are overwhelmed in the first

instance, and the little attention that is given to accommodating their

pursuits to their capacities in the second.

And he added that

there is not in the world a truer object of pity than a child terrified

at every glance, and watching with anxious uncertainty the caprices of a

pedagogue.

A later book of Godwin’s, The Enquirer (1797), contains, as his

biographer rightly says, ‘some of the most remarkable and advanced ideas

on education ever written’. Its opening words are the splendid

affirmation that ‘The true object of education, like that of every other

moral process, is the generation of happiness’. And it goes on to assert

the rights of the child against the automatic assumptions of authority

by the adult world. For example, he observed that

Children, it is said, are free from the cares of the world. Are they

without their cares? Of all cares, those that bring with them the

greatest consolation are the cares of independence. There is no more

certain source of exultation than the consciousness that I am of some

importance in the world. A child usually feels that he is a nobody.

Parents, in the abundance of their providence, take good care to

administer to them this bitter recollection. How suddenly does a child

rise to an enviable degree of happiness, who feels that he has the honor

to be trusted and consulted by his superiors?

Between these two resounding manifestos came Godwin’s best-known book,

his Inquiry Concerning Political Justice (1793). In the course of this

book he diverged sharply from progressive opinion in Britain and from

the Enlightenment philosophers Rousseau, Helvetius, Diderot, and

Condorcet, all of whom put forward schemes for national systems of

schooling, postulating an ideal state, which in Godwin’s view was a

contradiction in terms. He outlined his three major objections thus:

The injuries that result from a system of national education are, in the

first place, that all public establishments include in them the idea of

permanence ... public education has always expended its energies in the

support of prejudice ... This feature runs through every species of

public establishment; and even in the petty institution of Sunday

schools, the chief lessons to be taught are a superstitious veneration

for the Church of England, and to bow to every man in a handsome coat

...

Secondly, the idea of national education is founded in an inattention to

the nature of mind. Whatever each man does for himself is done well;

whatever his neighbors or his country undertake to do for him is done

ill. It is our wisdom to incite men to act for themselves, not to retain

them in a state of perpetual pupilage ...

Thirdly, the project of a national education ought uniformly to be

discouraged on account of its obvious alliance with national government.

This is an alliance of a more formidable nature than the old and much

contested alliance of church and state. Before we put so powerful a

machine under the direction of so ambitious an agent, it behooves us to

consider well what we do. Government will not fail to employ it to

strengthen its hand and perpetuate its institutions ... Their views as

instigators of a system of education will not fail to be analogous to

their views in their political capacity ... [Even] in the countries

where liberty chiefly prevails, it is reasonably to be assumed that

there are important errors, and a national system has the most direct

tendency to perpetuate those errors and to form all minds on one model.

Some admirers of Godwin’s thought have been embarrassed by this

rejection of ‘progressive’ opinion. They recall the hard struggle to

achieve free, universal, compulsory education for all in both Britain

and the United States after 1870. (There is a confusing similarity of

educational language in Britain and the United States. In the United

States ‘public’ schools are the primary and secondary schools provided

at the public expense. In Britain ‘private’ and ‘public’ are the words

used to describe the junior and senior schools funded by affluent

parents for their privileged children; the schools described as ‘state’

schools are actually administered by local government authorities.) In

Britain, a centenary publication from the National Union of Teachers in

1970 explained that ‘apart from religious and charitable schools,

‘‘dame’’ or common schools were operated by the private enterprise of

people who were often barely literate’, and it dismissed the widespread

working-class hostility to the School Boards of the 19^(th) century with

the remark that ‘parents were not always quick to appreciate the

advantages of full-time schooling against the loss of extra wages’.

But more recently historians have seen this resistance to state

schooling in a quite different light. Stephen Humphries found that, by

the 1860s, working-class private schools (as opposed to what is meant

today by private schools) were providing an alternative education to

that of the charitable or religious ‘National’ or ‘British’ schools for

about one-third of all working-class children, and he suggests that

This enormous demand for private as opposed to public education is

perhaps best illustrated by the fact that working-class parents in a

number of major cities responded to the introduction of compulsory

attendance regulations not by sending their children to provided state

schools, as government inspectors had predicted, but by extending the

length of their children’s education in private schools. Parents favored

these schools for a number of reasons: they were small and close to home

and were consequently more personal and more convenient than most

publicly provided schools; they were informal and tolerant of irregular

attendance and unpunctuality; no attendance registers were kept; they

were not segregated according to age and sex; they used individual as

opposed to authoritarian teaching methods; and, most important, they

belonged to and were controlled by the local community rather than being

imposed on the neighborhood by an alien authority.

Humphries’ remarkable observation was reinforced by a mass of

contemporary evidence exhumed by Philip Gardner in his book on The Lost

Elementary Schools of Victorian England. This researcher concluded that

these working-class schools

achieved just what the customer wanted: quick results in basic skills

like reading, writing and arithmetic, wasted no time on religious

studies and moral uplift, and represented a genuinely alternative

approach to childhood learning to that prescribed by the education

experts.

In the view of the historian Paul Thompson, the price of eliminating

these schools through the imposition of the national education system

was

the suppression in countless working-class children of the appetite for

education and ability to learn independently which contemporary

progressive education seeks to rekindle.

Radically different as it is from the history of education as taught to

student teachers, this approach helps us to locate the anarchist

thinkers in the spectrum of educational ideas. These include, for

example, the speculations of Leo Tolstoy on the school he started at

Yasnaya Polyana, and those of Francesco Ferrer (1859–1909), the founder

of the ‘Modern School’ movement. Ferrer opened his first school in

Barcelona in 1901, aiming at a secular, rationalist education. He

inspired emulators in several countries and aroused the enmity of the

church. When the Spanish government called for conscription in Catalonia

for its war in Morocco in 1909, Ferrer was held responsible for street

battles in Barcelona in which 200 demonstrators were killed, even though

he was not present. He was executed, but his campaign for secular

education did not die. After the revolution of 19 July 1936, at least

60,000 children in Catalonia attended Ferrer schools.

It is interesting to see how their approach led a variety of anarchists

to offer educational opinions in anticipation of the progressive

propagandists of a century later. For example, Bakunin, in a mere

footnote to a polemic on a different topic, envisaged the school as a

lifelong resource for us all:

They will be schools no longer; they will be popular academies, in which

neither pupils nor masters will be known, where the people will come

freely to get, if they need it, free instruction, and in which, rich in

their own experience, they will teach in turn many things to the

professors who shall bring them knowledge which they lack. This then

will be a mutual instruction, an act of intellectual fraternity.

He was writing in 1870, and if his argument is familiar this is

precisely because identical aspirations were expressed a century later

by people like Ivan Illich and Paul Goodman in America, or in Britain by

Michael Young, and by Professor Harry RĂ©e. In 1972 RĂ©e told an audience

of young teachers that

I think we are going to see in your lifetime the end of schools as we

know them. Instead there will be a community center with the doors open

twelve hours a day, seven days a week, where anybody can wander in and

out of the library, workshops, sports center, self- service store and

bar. In a hundred years time the compulsory attendance laws for children

to go to school may have gone the same way as the compulsory laws for

attendance at church.

His prophecy is unlikely to be fulfilled, for within ten years of his

address, an incoming government was blaming the collapse of the British

manufacturing industry on, of all unlikely scapegoats, the schools.

There followed a new regime of unprecedented intervention by central

government in the management and curriculum of primary and secondary

schools, which in Britain are provided by local authorities. These

included the imposition, for the first time, of a National Curriculum by

the central government, a continuous program of testing children at

particular ages, and an avalanche of form-filling for teachers. (This

endless assessment proved beyond doubt that schools in affluent

districts achieve higher marks than schools in poor areas with a

majority of children whose native language is not English. These are

social facts that most people already knew.)

By 1995, Her Majesty’s Chief Inspector of Schools was declaring that the

real impediment to the development of a better educational system in

Britain was ‘a commitment to particular beliefs about the purposes and

conduct of education’, and that what was needed was ‘less learning by

doing and more teaching by telling’. He was repudiating a hundred years

of progressive influence on the official, compulsory education system,

fitfully moving up the age-range from the nursery to the secondary

school. One irony about the rejection of ‘progressive’ education by

politicians of the political Right is that the educational aims of many

anarchists would be completely acceptable to them. Michael Smith, the

historian of The Libertarians and Education, remarks that Proudhon

was always conscious of the fact that the children he was talking about

were the children of workers. Work was going to be their life when they

grew up. Proudhon saw nothing wrong with this. The work a man did was

something to be proud of, it was what gave interest, value and dignity

to his life. It was right, therefore, that school should prepare the

young for a life of work. An education that was divorced from the world

of work, that is, an education that was entirely bookish or

grammar-schoolish in conception, was valueless from the point of view of

ordinary working-class children. Of course, an education that went too

far in the other direction, which brought up children merely to be

fodder for factories, was equally unacceptable. What was required was an

education which would equip a child for the workplace but would also

give him a degree of independence in the labor market. This could be

achieved by giving him not just the basis of a trade but, as well, a

whole range of marketable skills which would ensure that he was not

totally at the mercy of an industrial system which required

specialization of its workers and then discarded them when the

specialization was no longer of interest to the firm. Thus Proudhon was

led to the idea of an education that was ‘polytechnical’.

Readers will have guessed, correctly, that Proudhon was concerning

himself solely with the education of boys, but this was not true of such

successors as Kropotkin, with his hopes for the integration of brain

work and manual work, not only in education but in life; nor of such

heroes as Francesco Ferrer in Spain, whose approach was similarly that

of an education for emancipation, as opposed to what he saw as education

for subservience. Michael Smith’s most interesting pages for the English

reader describe ‘Integral Education’ in practice, through the experience

of the French anarchist Paul Robin and the school he ran from 1880 to

1894 at Cempius. It was based upon workshop training and the abandonment

of the classroom in favor of what we would now call the resource center.

Cooking, needlecraft, carpentry, and metalwork were undertaken by both

sexes, while ‘the Cempius children, both girls and boys, were among the

first children in France to go in for cycling’.

Co-education, sexual equality, and atheism brought down Robin’s school,

but another celebrated French anarchist, SĂ©bastien Faure, ran a famous

school called La Ruche (‘The Beehive’). Michael Smith comments that

‘Faure had learned one very significant lesson from Robin’s downfall:

stay completely out of the state system and thus be assured of complete

independence.’ But in Britain there has been a continual effort to

introduce the approaches of libertarian education into the school system

funded by all citizens. Another historian, John Shotton, has traced the

history of these attempts, and of similar efforts to help all those

children who have been excluded by the official system.

A century of progressive experiments have had a profound effect on every

school, most evidently the primary schools. The role of the teacher has

changed from that of fearsome martinet to that of friendly guide, while

corporal punishment, once the mainstay of the school system, has been

legally outlawed. There is, however, a distinction to be made between

‘progressive’ education and ‘libertarian’ education, which in practice

revolves around the issue of compulsory or voluntary attendance at

lessons. Foremost among the libertarians was A. S. Neill, who for many

decades ran Summerhill School in Suffolk, which survives to this day,

led by his daughter Zoë Readhead.

Neill could not stand the high-minded and manipulative progressives. By

the 1930s he was writing to Dora Russell of Beacon Hill School that she

and he were ‘the only educators’. As one of his mentors, Homer Lane, put

it:

‘Give the child freedom’ is the insistent cry of the New Educators, but

then its exponents usually devise a ‘system’ which, although based on

the soundest of principles, limits that freedom and contradicts the

principle.

Lane was echoing the opinion of William Godwin in The Enquirer, when he

found that Rousseau, even though the world was indebted to him ‘for the

irresistible energy of his writings and the magnitude of his

speculations’, had fallen into the common error of manipulating the

child:

His whole system of education is a series of tricks, a puppet-show

exhibition, of which the master holds the wires, and the scholar is

never to suspect in what manner they are moved.

The anarchist approach has been more influential in education than in

most other fields of life. It may be contested and deplored by

authoritarians, with their own nostalgia for an idealized past, but it

is difficult to conceive that young people will tolerate in the future

the educational regime to which the grandparents of their rulers were

subjected.

In some parts of the world, the battle for the freedom of the young is

in the past. In others, it has still to be won. Some of the attempts in

Britain to provide an alternative experience for the young people who

are excluded from the official education system are described in Chapter

8.

Chapter 7. The individualist response

For a century, anarchists have used the word ‘libertarian’ as a synonym

for ‘anarchist’, both as a noun and an adjective. The celebrated

anarchist journal Le Libertaire was founded in 1895. However, much more

recently the word has been appropriated by various American free-market

philosophers – David Friedman, Robert Nozick, Murray Rothbard, and

Robert Paul Wolff – so it is necessary to examine the modern

individualist ‘libertarian’ response from the standpoint of the

anarchist tradition.

In approaching this theme, one obstacle to circumnavigate is the German

advocate of ‘conscious egoism’, Max Stirner. He was born Johann Caspar

Schmidt (1806–56) and his book, published in 1845, Der Einzige und sein

Eigentum, was translated into English in 1907 as The Ego and His Own. I

have made several efforts to read this book, but have continually found

it incomprehensible. I used to excuse myself with the comment that the

cult of the ‘Ego’ seemed to me as distasteful as Nietzsche’s ‘Superman’,

but anarchist admirers of Stirner assure me that his approach is quite

different from Nietzsche’s. They argue that Stirner’s ‘conscious egoism’

does not in any way deny the human tendency towards altruistic behavior,

precisely because our own self-image is gratified by the way we perceive

ourselves as social beings. They also draw my attention to Stirner’s

anticipation of the later perception by Robert Michels of an ‘iron law

of oligarchy’, diagnosing an inbuilt tendency of all human institutions

to ossify into oppressive bodies, which have to be opposed in the name

of individual liberty.

Far more typical than Stirner of the anarchist individualist current was

a long series of American activists and innovators, predating the

vigorous history of anarchist propaganda among numerous immigrant groups

of the late 19^(th) and early 20^(th) centuries: German, Russian,

Jewish, Swedish, Dutch, Italian, and Spanish. Such guidebooks as James

J. Martin’s Men Against the State (which first appeared in 1953) and

David DeLeon’s The American as Anarchist: Reflections on Indigenous

Radicalism (which first appeared in 1978) provide a rich and varied

history in the United States of inventive individual and social

anarchist argument and experiment.

The immigrant tradition was of social and collective ventures rapidly

growing into deeply rooted organizations for welfare and conviviality.

It included workers’ unions, schools, and cooperatives. The indigenous

tradition was far more individualistic but its protagonists have had a

remarkable range of impacts on American life. Their chroniclers

distinguish between the ideologies of these libertarians of the Left,

and that of the libertarians of the Right. As David DeLeon separates

them: ‘While the libertarians of the Right despise the state because it

hinders the freedom of property, Left libertarians condemn the state

because it is a bastion of property.’

The first of these luminaries was Josiah Warren (1798–1874) who,

disappointed by the failure of Robert Owen’s cooperative colony of New

Harmony, set up a Time Store in Cincinnati, whose customers bought goods

in return for ‘labor notes’ promising the trader an equivalent product

or service. This was followed by a cooperative Village of Equity in

Ohio, the long-lived ‘mutualist’ village of Utopia, and the community of

Modern Times on Long Island that similarly retained its cooperative

character for at least 20 years. Warren’s belief in the importance of

the individual led him to advocate communal kitchens, to ‘relieve the

females of the family from the full, mill-horse drudgery to which they

otherwise are irretrievably doomed’.

Lysander Spooner (1808–87) wanted an America of self-employed

individuals sharing equal access to credit. He argued, too, that

if a man has never consented or agreed to support a government, he

breaks no faith in refusing to support it. And if he makes war on it, he

does so as an open enemy, and not as a traitor.

Stephen Pearl Andrews (1812–86) similarly accepted that the sovereignty

of the individual applied to every individual. Consequently, as Peter

Marshall explains,

He consistently opposed slavery and tried to free the state of Texas by

raising money to buy off all of its slaves but the war with Mexico

intervened. He also argued that sexual behavior and family life should

be matters of personal responsibility beyond the control of Church and

State.

Like that of Warren, the individualism of S. P. Andrews led him to

recommend communal nurseries, infant schools, and cooperative

cafeterias, in order to liberate women.

Benjamin R. Tucker (1854–1939) was, in his day, the best-known of the

American individualist anarchists, since his journal Liberty lasted a

quarter of a century, until his Boston printing shop was burned down in

1907. He was also the pioneer translator of Proudhon and Bakunin.

But among the American libertarians of the 19^(th) century, the most

individual and the best remembered is Henry David Thoreau (1817–62). His

famous book Walden is an account of the two years he spent seeking

self-sufficiency in the hut he built for himself near Concord,

Massachusetts. This did not imply a withdrawal from American life, for

the man who declared that the soldier’s natural enemy is the government

that drills him was his country’s most forthright subversive. One of his

essays, usually called ‘On the duty of civil disobedience’, though

originally published in 1849 as ‘Resistance to civil government’,

attracted no attention at the time, but subsequently influenced both

Tolstoy and Gandhi (who read it in prison in South Africa). Martin

Luther King read it as a student in Atlanta, and recalled that,

Fascinated by the idea of refusing to cooperate with an evil system, I

was so deeply moved that I reread the work several times. This was my

first intellectual contact with the theory of nonviolent resistance.

Thoreau’s essay on civil disobedience, originating in his sense of

outrage at the United States’ government’s Mexican War and at the

continuance of black slavery, began its history as a lecture to his

fellow citizens at the Concord Lyceum in 1848. When the abolitionist

John Brown took up arms against the United States in 1859 and was

condemned to death, Thoreau, against some opposition, delivered an

address in the Town Hall called ‘A Plea for Captain John Brown’. Many

decades later Havelock Ellis remarked that Thoreau was ‘the one man in

America to recognize the greatness of the occasion and to stand up

publicly on his side’.

Another remarkable American individualist, Randolph Bourne (1886–1918),

invented a famous phrase during the First World War, as he observed the

process by which his country was manouevred into participating in that

war. ‘War is the health of the state’, he claimed, and he explained that

The State is the organization of the herd to act offensively or

defensively against another herd similarly organized. War sends the

current of purpose and activity flowing down to the lowest level of the

herd, and to its most remote branches. All the activities of society are

linked together as fast as possible to this central purpose of making a

military offensive or military defense, and the State becomes what in

peacetime it has vainly struggled to become ... The slack is taken up,

the cross-currents fade out, and the nation moves lumberingly and

slowly, but with ever accelerated speed and integration, towards the

great end, towards that peacefulness of being at war ...

His perception of the way that 20^(th)-century governments have been

able to manufacture and manipulate opinion is amply demonstrated by

events in the 90 years since he was writing. American anarchist

individualist protesters have lobbied in the streets against the

policies of the United States government ever since. One was Ammon

Hennacy, always described as ‘the one-man revolution’, who maintained a

continual individual protest against United States imperialism, from the

East Coast to the Southwest, and another was Dorothy Day of the Catholic

Worker Movement, who testified for many decades of the 20^(th) century

to her faith in self-organizing cooperative communities, which in

political terms has to be described as anarchism.

Some time later, in the 1970s, a series of books, from academics rather

than activists, proclaimed a different style of American libertarianism.

They were Robert Paul Wolff’s In Defense of Anarchism; Robert Nozick’s

Anarchy, State and Utopia; David Friedman’s The Machinery of Freedom;

and Murray Rothbard’s For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto. This

phalanx of authors have provided the ‘ideological superstructure’ of the

swing to the Right in federal and local politics in the United States,

and in British politics for the aim of ‘rolling back the frontiers of

the State’, which was actually a cloak for increased subservience to

central decision-making. Robert Paul Wolff claimed that ‘philosophical

anarchism would seem to be the only reasonable belief for an enlightened

man’. Robert Nozick is said by the historian Peter Marshall to have

‘helped to make libertarian and anarchist theory acceptable in academic

circles’ – no small achievement; while David Friedman has popularized

for an American readership the argument of Friedrich von Hayek that

welfare legislation is the first step on The Road to Serfdom.

Peter Marshall sees the economist Murray Rothbard as the most aware of

the actual anarchist tradition among the anarcho-capitalist apologists:

He was originally regarded as an extreme right-wing Republican, but went

on to edit La BoĂ©tie’s libertarian classic Of Voluntary Servitude and

now calls himself an anarchist. ‘If you wish to know how the

libertarians regard the State and any of its acts,’ he wrote in For a

New Liberty, ‘simply think of the State as a criminal band, and all the

libertarian attitudes will logically fall into place.’ He reduces the

libertarian creed to one central axiom, ‘that no man or group of men may

aggress against the person or property of anyone else.’ Neither the

State nor any private party therefore can initiate or threaten the use

of force against any person for any purpose. Free individuals should

regulate their affairs and dispose of their property only by voluntary

agreement based on contractual obligation.

Rothbard is aware of a tradition, but he is singularly unaware of the

old proverb that freedom for the pike means death for the minnow. For

the bleak facts about the United States economy are that 10% of its

citizens possess 85% of the nation’s net wealth, and that this minority

are also the people who benefit from every reduction in the nation’s

social welfare budget.

The libertarians of the Right have, nevertheless, a function in the

spectrum of anarchist discussion. Every anarchist propagandist finds

that the audience or readership is perplexed by the very idea that it

might be possible to organize human life without government. That is why

Kropotkin, as a libertarian of the Left, as we saw in Chapter 3,

insisted that anarchist propagandists should identify new forms of

organization for those functions that the state now fulfills through

bureaucracy.

Murray Rothbard was one of the founders of a Libertarian Party in the

United States, seeking, as Peter Marshall explains, to abolish ‘the

entire Federal regulatory apparatus as well as social security, welfare,

public education and taxation’, and urging the United States ‘to

withdraw from the United Nations and its foreign commitments, and to

reduce its military forces to those required for minimal defense.’

Beyond an aspiration to repeal all ‘victimless crime’ laws, we did not

learn about any commitment to a change in the United States penal

system, which now imprisons a larger proportion of the population than

any other nation that keeps reliable records. But in any case, the other

philosophers of the new libertarian Right seem to have a less sweeping

agenda. Robert Paul Wolff, for example, in the 1998 reprint of his book

In Defense of Anarchism, suggests that ‘a system of in-the-home voting

machines be set up’, each of them ‘attached to the television set’, to

decide social and political issues. He asserts that ‘social justice

would flourish as it has never flourished before’.

Most anarchists would see this as a rather pathetic evasion of the

issues raised by the anarchist criticism of American society, and would

prefer to commemorate a far richer heritage of dissent in the United

States, exemplified by a long series of well-remembered propagandists,

from Thoreau in one generation and Emma Goldman in another, down to Paul

Goodman, who bequeathed an intriguing legacy to his anarchist

successors. In his last article in the American press, he suggested that

For me, the chief principle of anarchism is not freedom but autonomy,

the ability to initiate a task and do it one’s own way. The weakness of

‘my’ anarchism is that the lust for freedom is a powerful motive for

political change, whereas autonomy is not. Autonomous people protect

themselves stubbornly but by less strenuous means, including plenty of

passive resistance. They do it their own way anyway. The pathos of

oppressed people, however, is that, if they break free, they don’t know

what to do. Not having been autonomous, they don’t know what it’s like,

and before they learn, they have new managers who are not in a hurry to

abdicate ...

The 19^(th)-century American individualists were busy creating communes,

cooperatives, alternative schools, local currencies, and schemes for

mutual banking. They were busy social inventors exploring the potential

of autonomy, including women’s liberation and black equality. Their

experience, in the social climate of America, illustrates Martin Buber’s

insistence, cited in Chapter 3, on the inverse relationship between the

social principle and the political principle. The practice of autonomy

generates the experience that enlarges the possibility of success. Or as

the American anarchist David Wieck expresssed it: ‘The habit of direct

action is, perhaps, identical with the habit of being free, prepared to

live responsibly in a free society.’

The American ‘libertarians’ of the 20^(th) century are academics rather

than social activists, and their inventiveness seems to be limited to

providing an ideology for untrammeled market capitalism.

Chapter 8. Quiet revolutions

The gulf between anarchist aspirations and the actual history of the

20^(th) century could be seen as an indication of the folly of

impossible hopes, but for the concurrent failure of other political

ideologies of the Left. Which of us was not profoundly relieved by the

collapse of Soviet communism, even though we have had little reason to

rejoice in subsequent regimes? As the penal settlements slowly emptied

of their survivors, the true believers were obliged to question their

assumptions.

Many years ago, the American journalist Dwight Macdonald wrote an

article on ‘Politics Past’ which included a long footnote that he later

told me was the most-quoted paragraph he had ever written. His footnote

said:

The revolutionary alternative to the status quo today is not

collectivized property administered by a ‘workers’ state’ whatever that

means, but some kind of anarchist decentralization that will break up

mass society into small communities where individuals can live together

as variegated human beings instead of as impersonal units in the mass

sum. The shallowness of the New Deal and the British Labor Party’s

postwar regime is shown by their failure to improve any of the important

things in people’s lives – the actual relationships on the job, the way

they spend their leisure, and child- rearing and sex and art. It is mass

living that vitiates all these today, and the State that holds together

the status quo. Marxism glorifies ‘the masses’ and endorses the State.

Anarchism leads back to the individual and the community, which is

‘impractical’ but necessary – that is to say, it is revolutionary.

In a partial, incomplete, but visible way, several of the revolutions he

sought have already transformed the surface of life. To take an example

that is by definition superficial, one that is obvious and visible but

seldom discussed, consider the revolution in dress in the second half of

the 20^(th) century. Fifty years ago in Britain, the social class of

men, women, and children could be recognized from their clothing. Today

this is no longer true, except for the tiny minority who can read the

signs of expensive and exclusive dress. This is usually attributed to

the growth of mass production and the fact that the garment trade is the

first route to the global economy for a low-paid workforce in the

‘developing’ world. But it has more to do with the relaxation of dress

codes, pioneered all through the 20^(th) century by the radical

nonconformists’ rejection of fashion.

The ignoring of dress codes based on occupation or social class was a

small and personal rebuff to convention. But of course a far more

significant revolution, gaining ground all through the century, has been

the women’s movement, rejecting the universal convention of male

dominance. Among its anarchist pioneers was Emma Goldman, with her

trenchant pamphlet on The Tragedy of Women’s Emancipation, arguing that

the vote, which had failed to liberate men, was not likely to free

women. Emancipation, she argued, must come from the woman herself,

First, by asserting herself as a personality, and not a sex commodity.

Second, by refusing the right to anyone over her body; by refusing to

bear children, unless she wants them; by refusing to be a servant to

God, the State, society, the husband, the family etc., by making her

life simpler, but deeper and richer. That is, by trying to learn the

meaning and substance of life in all its complexities, by freeing

herself from the fear of public opinion and public condemnation. Only

that, and not the ballot, will set women free ...

It was among the anarchists that the habit began of what were called

‘free unions’ as opposed to marriages licensed by church or state. Today

these are almost as common as regular marriages, with the result that

the stigma once associated with illegitimacy has, during the century,

disappeared. This change was, of course, accelerated by the

pharmacological revolution of the contraceptive pill.

Alex Comfort (1920–2000) was a physician, novelist, poet, and anarchist.

His lectures to meetings of the London Anarchist Group in the late 1940s

gave rise to his book Barbarism and Sexual Freedom, published by Freedom

Press in 1948 at a time when no ‘respectable’ publisher would issue such

a book. This in turn led to his Sexual Behavior in Society and to his

phenomenally successful manuals on sex. In his book More Joy: A

Lovemaking Companion to The Joy of Sex (1973), he included an anarchist

account of the connection between sexuality and politics. He asserted

that

acquiring the awareness and the attitudes which can come from good

sexual experience does not make for selfish withdrawal: it is more

inclined to radicalize people. The anti-sexualism of authoritarian

societies and the people who run them does not spring from conviction

(they themselves have sex), but from the vague perception that freedom

here might lead to a liking for freedom elsewhere. People who have

eroticized their experience of themselves and the world are, on the one

hand, inconveniently unwarlike, and on the other, violently combative in

resisting political salesmen and racists who threaten the personal

freedom they have attained and want to see others share.

Comfort hoped that his books would provide both reassurance and

liberation, and that they would be a contribution to another

20^(th)-century revolution: that of the relationships between parents

and children. It is hard to imagine in today’s Western Europe the

punitive behavior of parents towards children that was taken for granted

a century ago.

The same is true of the relationships between teachers and children. The

recollections of people who were schoolchildren in the first decade of

the 20^(th) century are full of accounts of the physical punishment they

received or that they continually feared. In the century’s last decade a

law in Britain banned corporal punishment in schools. This was not a

sudden legal decision. It reflected the influence of a handful of

‘progressive’ schools on general educational thinking.

Many observers claim that the school system has failed to prepare for

the dilemmas that came in the wake of the abandonment of physical

punishment. The teacher is deprived of the weapon that was seen as the

ultimate sanction of the school. This has resulted in increased numbers

of children being excluded from school because teachers have declined to

have them in the class. Anyone who has observed how one disruptive

member of the class can make learning impossible for the whole group has

no criticism to make of those teachers (especially since their employers

put pressure on them not to upset statistics).

In the 1960s and 1970s an intriguing situation arose in several British

cities: London, Liverpool, Leeds, and Glasgow. Groups of enthusiasts

found empty buildings and set up ‘free schools’ to provide an informal

education for children who were either excluded from school or had

excluded themselves through truancy. (One of them, White Lion Free

School in London, lasted from 1972 to 1990.) The regime of these schools

was consciously modeled on the experience of the progressive school

movement. I asked a veteran of those experiments why the idea had not

been revived among the new generation of excluded children at the start

of the new century. She gave me two reasons: first, the legal

requirement in Britain for all schools to teach the National Curriculum

introduced during the Thatcher regime and retained by its successors;

and second, the difficulty of finding premises that would meet the

safety and sanitary regulations prescribed for schools. However, it is

hard to imagine returning to the regime of fear that governed schools a

century ago. The quiet revolution in education can only move forward.

Two other changes in Britain from the 1960s also seem irreversible. One

is the removal of the fear of criminal prosecution for homosexuality.

This had been recommended in a government report commissioned from John

Wolfenden and published in 1957, but years of argument and agitation

were needed to engineer a change in the law. The other was the ending of

capital punishment in 1965. On the eve of the debate that brought this

change, the anarchist publishers Freedom Press presented every Member of

Parliament with a copy of their edition of Charles Duff’s devastating

book, A Handbook on Hanging, which took the form of an enthusiastic

manual for executioners. Only very humorless observers would complain

that support for campaigns to end barbaric laws was a contradiction of

the anarchist anti-parliamentary stance.

Taken together, the social changes in Britain that I have listed are an

indication that while the anarchists have made little progress towards

the large-scale changes in society that they hoped to bring about, they

have contributed to a long series of small liberations that have lifted

a huge load of human misery.

Several anarchist groups sought to link together these struggles for

human liberation into a conscious campaign with a wider relevance. In

the Netherlands, the Provos introduced games and playful alternatives to

ridicule the official city management. Their most famous ploy was to

litter Amsterdam with white bicycles for public use, to demonstrate that

cars were unnecessary. They were followed by the Kabouters, or gnomes,

forerunners of the Green movement. One of them, Roel van Duyn, made the

same links between anarchism and cybernetics, the science of control and

communication systems, that had been suggested by the founder of

cybernetics, the neurologist Gray Walter. He had pointed out that

We find no boss in the brain, no oligarchic ganglion or glandular Big

Brother. Within our heads our very lives depend on equality of

opportunity, on specialization with versatility, on free communication

and just restraint, a freedom without interference. Here too, local

minorities can and do control their own means of production and

expression in free and equal intercourse with their neighbors.

Among French attempts to sharpen the widespread vaguely libertarian

trends were the Situationists, notably Raoul Vaneigem with his manifesto

on The Revolution of Everyday Life (1967). As Peter Marshall puts it:

The way out for the Situationists was not to wait for a distant

revolution but to reinvent daily life here and now. To transform the

perception of the world and to change the structure of society is the

same thing. By liberating oneself, one changed power relations and

therefore transformed society ...

The Situationists, like the Kabouters, have passed into history without

managing to transform society, but France and the Netherlands, like

Britain, have seen a series of modest gains in civilization.

Then the quiet revolution became noisier as, thanks to the Internet, the

anarchists were linked to a variety of anti-capitalist protesters in a

series of large-scale demonstrations whenever global bodies met to

advance their interests. George Monbiot, in his book Captive State,

describes how

In April 1998, a ragged band of protesters inflicted the first of a

series of defeats on a coalition of the most powerful interests on

earth. The 29 richest nations had joined forces with the world’s biggest

multinational companies to write ‘the constitution of a single global

economy’. Proposed and drafted by businessmen, secretly discussed by

governments, the Multilateral Agreement on Investment would, had it

succeeded, have granted corporations the right to sue any country whose

laws restricted their ability to make money. The treaty was, its

opponents claimed, a charter for the corporate takeover of the world.

Monbiot explains how the leaking of this secret treaty in 1997 led to

objectors posting the details on the Web, guaranteeing demonstrations

wherever the governmental negotiators might meet. Public pressure and

internal disputes obliged the global leaders to abandon their

negotiations, only to revive them under the auspices of the World Trade

Organization. Its negotiators met in Seattle in November 1999, but the

talks there collapsed as tens of thousands of people from around the

world protested outside, in the name of the poor countries and the

planet’s environment.

In the string of demonstrations that began at Seattle, the techniques

adopted by the Provos and Kabouters were used to ridicule the forces of

law and order. Sean Sheehan, in his account of contemporary anarchism,

describes the scene in Prague, a year after Seattle, where in

demonstrations against the International Monetary Fund,

mini armies of protesters came dressed as fairies and armed with feather

dusters to tickle the ranks of heavily clothed, armed police. At such

protests, lines of transport tend to be blocked not so much by burning

barricades and street battles but by giant contraptions like the

Liberation Puppet, capable of snarling up a major highway.

But after five days of protest had brought a World Trade Organization

conference close to collapse, the heavily armed police responded. As

Sheehan reports,

That the size and organization of the protests spooked the police into

frenzied and blatantly illegal behavior was confirmed by the fact that

of the 631 arrests, only 14 ever went to trial.

Having started gently and humorously, the big international

demonstrations of opposition to global capitalism are no longer quiet

revolutions. There seems to have been a pact between the world’s police

forces to escalate the violence of their response to demonstrators. Sean

Sheehan goes on to record that

‘Normal’ police violence at Seattle escalated at the anti-capitalism

protest in Gothenburg in June 2001 to the issuing of live ammunition to

the police with three people shot. When another anti-capitalist protest

was mounted in Genoa in July, the event turned into a violent riot, with

armored vans driving at speed into crowds of protesters and a

late-night, cold-blooded and very violent assault by the police on a

building where media activists and their material were lodged.

One young anarchist was killed at Genoa, and his death prompted a

renewed discussion of strategies of protest. Maybe there are subtler

ways of undermining global capitalism? The quiet revolutionaries who

transformed the culture of Western countries in the 20^(th) century have

not yet discovered them.

Chapter 9. The federalist agenda

A frequent criticism of anarchism is that it is an ideology that fits a

world of isolated villages, small enough to be self-governing entities,

but not the global, multi-national society that we all inhabit in real

life. But in fact the major anarchist thinkers of the past: Proudhon,

Bakunin, and Kropotkin, had a federalist agenda that was a foretaste of

modern debates on European unity.

That minority of children in any European country who were given the

opportunity of studying the history of Europe as well as that of their

own nations learned that there were two great events in the 19^(th)

century: the unification of Germany, achieved by Bismarck and the

Emperor Wilhelm I; and the unification of Italy, won by Cavour, Mazzini,

Garibaldi, and Vittorio Emanuale II. These triumphs had been welcomed by

the whole world (which in those days meant the European world) because

Germany and Italy had left behind all those silly little principalities,

republics, papal provinces, and city states, to become nation states,

empires, and, of course, conquerors.

They had become like France, whose little local despots were finally

unified by force, first by Louis XIV with his majestic slogan ‘L’État

c’est moi’, and then by Napoleon, heir to the Grande Revolution, just

like Stalin in the 20^(th) century, who built up the administrative

machinery of terror to ensure that the slogan was true. Or they had

become like England, whose kings (and its one republican ruler, Oliver

Cromwell) had conquered the Welsh, Scots, and Irish, and sought to

dominate the rest of the world outside Europe. The same thing was

happening at the other end of Europe. Ivan IV, appropriately named ‘The

Terrible’, conquered central Asia as far as the Pacific, and Peter I,

known as ‘The Great’, using the techniques he had learned in France and

Britain, took over the Baltic, most of Poland, and the west of Ukraine.

Advanced opinion throughout Europe welcomed Germany and Italy to the

gentleman’s club of national and imperial powers. The eventual results

in the 20^(th) century were appalling adventures in conquest, with the

devastating loss of life among young men from the villages of Europe in

the two world wars, and the rise of populist demagogues like Hitler and

Mussolini, as well as their endless imitators to this day, who claim

L’État c’est moi. Consequently, although we have had all too few

politicians arguing for the breakdown of nations, we have a host of them

of every persuasion who have sought European unity: economic, social,

administrative, or, of course, political.

Needless to say, in efforts for unification promoted by politicians we

have a multitude of administrators in Brussels issuing edicts about

which varieties of vegetable seeds, or what constituents of beefburgers

or ice cream, may be sold in the shops of member nations. The newspapers

joyfully report all this trivia. The press gives far less attention to

another undercurrent of pan-European opinion, evolving from the views

expressed in Strasbourg from people of every political hue, claiming the

existence of a ‘Europe of the Regions’, and daring to argue that the

nation state was a phenomenon of the 16^(th) to 19^(th) centuries, which

will not have any useful future in the 21^(st) century. The forthcoming

pattern of administration in the federated Europe that they are

struggling to discover is a link between, let us say, Calabria, Wales,

Andalusia, Aquitaine, Galicia, or Saxony, as regions, rather than as

nations, seeking their regional identity, economically and culturally,

which has been lost in their incorporation in nation states, where the

center of gravity is elsewhere.

In the great tide of nationalism in the 19^(th) century there was a

handful of prophetic and dissenting voices, urging the alternative of

federalism. It is interesting, at least, that those whose names survive

were the three best-known anarchist thinkers of that century. The

political Left as it evolved in the 20^(th) century has dismissed their

legacy as irrelevant. So much the worse for the Left, since the debate

is now monopolized by the political Right, which has its own agenda in

opposing both federalism and regionalism.

First among these anarchist precursors was Proudhon, who devoted two of

his books to the idea of federation in opposition to that of the nation

state. They were La FĂ©dĂ©ration et l’UnitĂ© en Italie of 1862, and in the

following year his Du Principe Fédératif. Proudhon was French, a citizen

of a unified, centralized nation state, with the result that he was

obliged to become a refugee in Belgium. And he feared the unification of

Italy on several different levels. In his book De la Justice of 1858, he

had forecast that the creation of the German Empire would bring only

trouble both to the Germans and to the rest of Europe, and he pursued

this argument into the political history of Italy.

On the bottom level was history, where natural factors like geology and

climate had shaped local customs and attitudes. ‘Italy’, he claimed,

is federal by the constitution of her territory; by the diversity of her

inhabitants; in the nature of her genius; in her mores; in her history.

She is federal in all her being and has been since all eternity ... And

by federation you will make her as many times free as you give her

independent states.

It was therefore unnatural for Italy to become a nation state.

He understood that Cavour and Napoleon III had agreed to make a federal

Italy, but he knew they would rely on a vainglorious princeling from the

House of Savoy who would settle for nothing less than a centralized

constitutional monarchy. And beyond this, he profoundly mistrusted the

liberal anti-clericalism of Mazzini, not through any love of the Papacy

but because he recognized that Mazzini’s slogan ‘Dio e popolo’ could be

exploited by any demagogue who could seize the machinery of a

centralized state. He saw that the existence of this administrative

machinery was an absolute threat to personal and local liberty. Proudhon

was almost alone among 19^(th)-century political theorists to perceive

this:

Liberal today under a liberal government, it will tomorrow become the

formidable engine of a usurping despot. It is a perpetual temptation to

the executive power, a perpetual threat to the people’s liberties. No

rights, individual or collective, can be sure of a future.

Centralization might, then, be called the disarming of a nation for the

profit of its government ...

Everything we now know about the 20^(th)-century history of Europe,

Asia, Latin America, or Africa supports this perception. Nor does the

North American style of federalism, so lovingly conceived by Thomas

Jefferson and his friends, guarantee the removal of this threat. One of

Proudhon’s English biographers, Edward Hyams, comments that

it has become apparent since the Second World War that United States

Presidents can and do make use of the Federal administrative machine in

a way which makes a mockery of democracy.

And his Canadian translator Richard Vernon paraphrases Proudhon’s

conclusion thus:

Solicit men’s views in the mass, and they will return stupid, fickle and

violent answers; solicit their views as members of definite groups with

real solidarity and a distinctive character, and their answers will be

responsible and wise. Expose them to the political ‘language’ of mass

democracy, which represents ‘the people’ as unitary and undivided, and

minorities as traitors, and they will give birth to tyranny; expose them

to the political language of federalism, in which the people figures as

a diversified aggregate of real associations, and they will resist

tyranny to the end.

This observation reveals a profound understanding of the psychology of

politics. Proudhon was extrapolating from the evolution of the Swiss

Confederation, but Europe has other examples in a whole series of

specialist fields. The Netherlands has a reputation for its mild or

lenient penal policy. The official explanation of this is the

replacement in 1886 of the Code Napoleon by ‘a genuine Dutch criminal

code’ based upon cultural traditions like ‘the well-known Dutch

‘‘tolerance’’ and tendency to accept deviant minorities’. I am quoting

the Netherlands criminologist Dr Willem de Haan, who cites the

explanation that Dutch society

has traditionally been based upon religious, political and ideological

rather than class lines. The important denominational groupings created

their own social institutions in all major public spheres. This process

... is responsible for transforming a pragmatic, tolerant general

attitude into an absolute social must.

In other words it is diversity and not unity that creates the kind of

society in which you and I can most comfortably live. And modern Dutch

attitudes are rooted in the diversity of the medieval city states of

Holland and Zeeland, which demonstrates, as much as Proudhon’s

regionalism, that a desirable future for all Europe lies in an

accommodation of local differences.

Discussions about European integration in the 1860s prompted a skeptical

reaction from Proudhon:

Among French democrats there has been much talk of a European

confederation, or a United States of Europe. By this they seem to

understand nothing but an alliance of all the states which presently

exist in Europe, great and small, presided over by a permanent congress.

It is taken for granted that each state will retain the form of

government that suits it best. Now since each state will have votes in

the congress in proportion to its population and territory, the small

states in this so-called confederation will soon be incorporated into

the large ones ...

Swallowing up neighboring countries may be unfashionable nowadays, but

we can see Proudhon’s misgivings being realized in the way debates and

decisions of the European Community are dominated by the large states at

the expense of the smaller member nations.

The second of my 19^(th)-century mentors, Michael Bakunin, demands our

attention for a variety of reasons. He was almost alone among that

century’s political thinkers in foreseeing the horrors of the clash of

modern nation states in the First and Second World Wars, as well as

predicting the results of centralizing Marxism in the Russian Empire. In

1867 Prussia and France seemed to be poised for a war about who should

control Luxembourg and this, through the network of interests and

alliances, ‘threatened to engulf all Europe’. A League for Peace and

Freedom held its congress in Geneva, sponsored by prominent people from

various countries, such as Giuseppe Garibaldi, Victor Hugo, and John

Stuart Mill. Bakunin seized the opportunity to address this audience,

and published his opinions under the title Fédéralisme, Socialisme, et

Anti-Théologisme. This document set out 13 points on which, according to

Bakunin, the Geneva Congress was unanimous.

The first of these points proclaimed

That in order to achieve the triumph of liberty, justice and peace in

the international relations of Europe, and to render civil war

impossible among the various peoples which make up the European family,

only a single course lies open: to constitute the United States of

Europe.

His second point argued that this aim implied that states must be

replaced by regions, for it observed

That the formation of these States of Europe can never come about

between the States as constituted at present, in view of the monstrous

disparity which exists between their various powers.

His fourth point claimed

That not even if it called itself a republic could any centralized,

bureaucratic and by the same token militarist State enter seriously and

genuinely into an international federation. By virtue of its

constitution, which will always be an explicit or implicit denial of

domestic liberty, it would necessarily imply a declaration of permanent

war and a threat to the existence of neighboring countries.

Consequently his fifth point demanded

That all the supporters of the League should therefore bend all their

energies towards the reconstruction of their various countries, in order

to replace the old organization founded throughout upon violence and the

principle of authority by a new organization based solely upon the

interests, needs and inclinations of the populace, and owning no

principle other than that of the free federation of individuals into

communes, communes into provinces, provinces into nations, and the

latter into the United States, first of Europe, then of the whole world.

The vision thus became bigger and bigger, but Bakunin was careful to

include the acceptance of secession. His eighth point declared that

Just because a region has formed part of a State, even by voluntary

accession, it by no means follows that it incurs any obligation to

remain tied to it for ever. No obligation in perpetuity is acceptable to

human justice ... The right of free union and equally free secession

comes first and foremost among all political rights; without it,

confederation would be nothing but centralization in disguise.

Bakunin refers admiringly to the Swiss Confederation, ‘practicing

federation so successfully today’, as he put it, and Proudhon too

explicitly took as a model the Swiss supremacy of the commune as the

unit of social organization, linked by the canton, with a purely

administrative federal council. But both remembered the events of 1848,

when the Sonderbund of secessionist cantons were compelled by war to

accept the new constitution of the majority. Proudhon and Bakunin agreed

in condemning this subversion of federalism by the unitary principle.

There must be a right of secession.

Switzerland, precisely because of its decentralized structure, was a

refuge for numerous political refugees from the Austro-Hungarian,

German, and Russian empires. One Russian anarchist was even expelled

from Switzerland: he was too much even for the Swiss Federal Council.

This was Peter Kropotkin, whose ideas connect 19^(th)-century federalism

with 20^(th)-century regional geography.

Kropotkin’s youth was spent as an army officer in geological expeditions

in the Far Eastern provinces of the Russian Empire. His autobiography

tells of the outrage he felt to see how central administration and

funding destroyed any improvement of local conditions, through

ignorance, incompetence, and universal corruption, and through the

destruction of ancient communal institutions which might have enabled

people to change their own lives. The rich got richer, the poor got

poorer, and the administrative machinery was suffocated by boredom and

embezzlement. There is a similar literature from any other empire or

nation state.

In 1872 Kropotkin made his first visit to Western Europe, and in

Switzerland was intoxicated by the air of democracy, even a bourgeois

one. In the Jura hills he stayed with the watch-makers, a community of

self-employed craftsmen. His biographer Martin Miller describes his

reactions:

Kropotkin’s meetings and talks with the workers on their jobs revealed

the kind of spontaneous freedom without authority or direction from

above that he had dreamed about. Isolated and self-sufficient, the Jura

watchmakers impressed Kropotkin as an example that could transform

society if such a community were allowed to develop on a large scale.

There was no doubt in his mind that this community would work because it

was not a matter of imposing an artificial ‘system’ such as had been

attempted by Muraviev in Siberia but of permitting the natural activity

of the workers to function according to their own interests.

His stay in the Jura hills was a turning point for Kropotkin. The rest

of his life was, in a sense, devoted to gathering the evidence for

anarchism, federalism, and regionalism.

Kropotkin’s approach is not simply a matter of academic history. In a

study of Un federalista Russo, Pietro Kropotkin (1922), the Italian

anarchist Camillo Berneri quotes the ‘Letter to the Workers of Western

Europe’ that Kropotkin handed to the British Labor Party politician

Margaret Bondfield in June 1920. In the course of it he declared that:

Imperial Russia is dead and will never be revived. The future of the

various provinces which composed the Empire will be directed towards a

large federation. The natural territories of the different sections of

this federation are in no way distinct from those with which we are

familiar in the history of Russia, of its ethnography and economic life.

All the attempts to bring together the consituent parts of the Russian

Empire, such as Finland, the Baltic provinces, Lithuania, Ukraine,

Georgia, Armenia, Siberia and others, under a central authority are

doomed to failure. The future of what was the Russian Empire is directed

towards a federation of independent units.

Today we can see the relevance of this opinion, ignored for 70 years. As

an exile in Western Europe, Kropotkin had close contact with a range of

pioneers of regional thinking. The relationship between regionalism and

anarchism has been handsomely delineated by the geographer Peter Hall,

when director of the Institute of Urban and Regional Development at

Berkeley, California, in his book Cities of Tomorrow (1988). There was

Kropotkin’s fellow anarchist geographer ElisĂ©e Reclus, arguing for

small-scale human societies based on the ecology of their regions. There

was Paul Vidal de la Blache, another founder of French geography, who

argued that ‘the region was more than an object of survey; it was to

provide the basis for the total reconstruction of social and political

life’. For Vidal, as Professor Hall explains, it was the region, not the

nation, which

as the motor force of human development; the almost sensual reciprocity

between men and women and their surroundings, was the seat of

comprehensible liberty and the mainspring of cultural evolution, which

were being attacked and eroded by the centralized nation-state and by

large-scale machine industry.

Finally there was the extraordinary Scottish biologist Patrick Geddes,

who tried to encapsulate all these regionalist ideas, whether

geographical, social, historical, political, or economic, into an

ideology of reasons for regions, known to most of us through the work of

his disciple Lewis Mumford.

Professor Hall pointed out that

many, though by no means all, of the early visions of the planning

movement stemmed from the anarchist movement, which flourished in the

last decades of the nineteenth century and the first years of the

twentieth ... The vision of these anarchist pioneers was not merely of

an alternative built form, but of an alternative society, nether

capitalist nor bureaucratic-socialist: a society based on voluntary

cooperation among men and women, working and living in small

self-governing communities.

Those 19^(th)-century anarchist thinkers were a century in advance of

their contemporaries in warning the peoples of Europe of the

consequences of not adopting a regionalist and federalist approach.

After every kind of disastrous experience in the 20^(th) century, the

rulers of the nation states of Europe have directed policy towards

several kinds of supranational entities. The crucial issue that faces

them is whether to conceive of a Europe of States or a Europe of

Regions.

To do them justice, the advocates of a united Europe have developed a

doctrine of ‘subsidiarity’, by which governmental decisions outside the

remit of the supranational institutions of the European Community should

be taken by regional or local levels of administration, rather than by

national governments. A resolution has been adopted by the Council of

Europe, calling for national governments to adopt its Charter for Local

Self-Government, ‘to formalize commitment to the principle that

government functions should be carried out at the lowest level possible

and only transferred to higher government by consent.’

This precept is an extraordinary tribute to Proudhon, Bakunin, and

Kropotkin and the ideas that they were alone in voicing (apart from some

interesting Spanish thinkers like Pi y Margall or Joaquin Costa). Of

course it is one of the first aspects of pan-European ideology that

national governments will choose to ignore, though there are obvious

differences between various nation states in this respect. In many of

them, for example Germany, Italy, Spain, and even France, the machinery

of government is considerably more devolved than it was 50 years ago.

The same is true of the former Soviet Union.

One anarchist thinker from the Netherlands, Thom Holterman, has set out

the criteria which anarchists would see as the prerequisites for a free

united Europe. His warning is precisely that the obstacle to a Europe of

the Regions is the existence of nation states. Another is that because

the thinking and planning of the future of Europe is in the hands of

governmental bureaucracies, they are all preparing for a Europe of the

bureaucrats.

Kropotkin used to cite the lifeboat institution as an example of the

kind of voluntary and non-coercive organization envisaged by anarchists

that could provide a worldwide service without the principle of

authority intervening. Two other examples of the way in which local

groups and associations could combine to provide a complex network of

functions without any central authority are the post office and the

railways. You can post a letter to Chili or China, confident that it

will get there, as a result of freely-arrived-at agreements between

different national post offices, without there being any central world

postal authority at all. Or you can travel across Europe and Asia over

the lines of a dozen different railway systems, public and private,

without any kind of central railway authority. Coordination requires

neither uniformity nor bureaucracy.

Chapter 10. Green aspirations and anarchist futures

When Kropotkin’s Fields, Factories and Workshops first appeared in 1899,

the precursors of the Green movement found it an inspiration, since its

author stressed the productivity of small-scale decentralized industry,

and of a ‘horticultural’ approach to food production, for its immense

output. When his book was re-issued at the end of the First World War,

an added preliminary note observed that: ‘It pleads for a new economy in

the energies used in supplying the needs of human life, since these

needs are increasing and the energies are not inexhaustible.’

In those days this was a rare recognition of the limits to growth. Today

we have a vast literature on the problems of resource depletion and

environmental destruction. The difficulty for environmental activists,

trying to enlist the support of fellow citizens, is one of priorities:

which campaign most urgently needs a helping hand? Capitalism roams the

globe, seeking the least protected labor market and the least protected

physical environment, in order to stimulate, and to win, an ever-growing

market for its goods. It describes this process as ‘consumer

sovereignty’ and thus evades any responsibility for its ruthless

exploitation of poor people and weak economies. The richer we are, the

more we are inclined to shrug off our share of this responsibility.

For many years now, we in the rich economies have had a series of

movements and campaigns described in general terms as ‘environmental’,

‘conservationist’, or ‘green’, or even ‘ecological’, drawing our

attention to the crises of the environment, global warming, and the

depletion of finite resources. Critics of these campaigns in the rich

world point out that they do not always include an awareness of the

plight of the rich world’s poor. Amartya Sen remarked on the paradox

that ‘In the poor world the poor are thin and the rich are fat. In the

rich world the rich are thin and the poor are fat.’ He is the author of

a famous study of who eats and who starves, and of what they eat, with a

theory of ‘entitlements’, defining these as the set of ‘alternative

commodity bundles which a person can command’. His observation is a

reminder that in every society there are several simultaneous food

cultures, ultimately determined by levels of poverty and affluence. In

the poor world the powerful and wealthy and their military elites live

grandly, while the poor are ill-nourished and sometimes starving. In the

rich world a significant poor minority lives on the ‘junk food’ that the

affluent can afford to despise. In Britain the number of children

growing up in poverty trebled between 1968 and 1998.

Any discussion of environmental issues has to start with the fact of

malnutrition in a world of plenty, and then proceed to examine the high

cost of the rich world’s ‘cheap’ food. Kropotkin’s arguments included

the claim that a densely populated small country like Britain could feed

itself from its own land, an idea regarded as absurd even though it was

based on European experience. A century later I had the pleasure of

meeting Jac Smit, president of the Urban Agriculture Network and

coauthor of the United Nations report on Urban Agriculture: Food, Jobs

and Sustainable Cities, who explained how in Chinese cities 90% of

vegetables are locally grown, and that

Hong Kong, the densest large city in the world, produces within its

boundaries two-thirds of the poultry, one-sixth of the pigs, and close

to half the vegetables eaten by its citizens and visitors.

The best-known examples of urban intensive food production are provided

by the vast cities of South-East Asia. Singapore’s 1,500 hectares of

‘agro-technology parks’ are famous. As their admirer Geoff Wilson points

out,

The inescapable logic is that while rural agriculture can need up to

eight fossil fuel energy units to produce one food energy unit sold in

supermarkets, urban agriculture can provide up to eight food energy

units for every one fossil fuel energy unit.

Tim Lang, a professor of food policy who has been concerned for years

with the implications of findings like these, reminds us that

Supermarket distribution systems are totally dependent upon cheap

energy. Far from being more convenient, hypermarkets are actually making

us make more, not less, shopping trips. The average number increased by

28 percent between 1978 and 1991. Shoppers also have to go further: the

distance rose by 60 percent between 1978 and 1991 ... The common factor

to all this is the food retailers’ use of centralized distribution

systems. Each firm has its own regional distribution centers (RDCs). All

food goes to the RDC and thence to the shops. As a result the food

travels much further ...

This is known as the food-miles issue. It has been extended to even more

bizarre lengths by the policies of the giant food retailers, searching

the globe for suppliers who are cheapest, regardless of the diversion of

local water supplies from meeting traditional local needs. In my nearest

town in East Anglia I can buy Mexican carrots, Australian onions,

African mange-tout peas, and Peruvian asparagus. This fact contributes

far more to global warming than my careless use of electricity.

Professor John Houghton, Chairman of the Royal Commission on

Environmental Pollution and of the United Nations Advisory Panel on

Climate Change, thought there was something absurd in the fact that he

had eaten delicious new potatoes for his lunch. They had been delivered

by a 40-tonne lorry to his local hypermarket after being flown by

superjet to England. And, as he commented, ‘I could have grown them in

my own back garden.’

His remark was important because it illustrates the gulf between our

green aspirations and our actual behavior. In exploring this gap, the

work of the American anarchist Murray Bookchin has been significant and

influential. He, like Rachel Carson, had been a propagandist on

environmental issues in the 1950s and 1960s, and this gave him the same

kind of forerunner status in the emerging American Green movement. He

linked this with the homegrown American anarchist tradition. ‘What we

are trying to do’, he explained,

is to redeem certain aspects of the American Dream. There are, of

course, several American dreams: one is the John Wayne tradition of the

cowboy going out to the West, and the whole notion of pioneering

individualism; another is the immigrant American dream, this being the

land of opportunity where the streets are made of gold. But there is a

third American dream, which is the oldest of the lot, dating back to

Puritan times, which stresses community, decentralization,

self-sufficiency, mutual aid and face- to-face democracy.

This is where Bookchin came into conflict with yet another American

dream. As ecological awareness spread among the children of the

affluent, the national guilt over the genocide of indigenous peoples led

to an exaltation of the Noble Savage, and a distaste for ordinary

mortals who hadn’t got the Message. What was seen as ‘Deep Ecology’

became fashionable among those affluent enough to ‘get away from it all’

and pursue every kind of mystical belief, so long as the checks kept

flowing into their bank accounts. Many of Bookchin’s fellow citizens

shifted from an involvement in social issues to a sentimental and

privileged idealization of ‘wilderness’ and the natural environment,

with a consequent misanthropy towards their fellow humans.

Bookchin’s vigorous repudiation of these approaches has sought to

confront the abandonment of social concerns in an increasingly divided

America, re-asserting the claims of ‘Social Ecology’ and aiming, as he

said, to advance ‘a serious challenge to society with its vast,

hierarchical, sexist, class-ruled, state apparatus and militaristic

history’.

Most anarchists would take it for granted that an ecologically viable

society is incompatible with capitalism and its demand for continually

expanding markets, achieved through the invention of wants and the

built-in obsolescence of consumer goods. At the same time, most of us

feel that in seeking more ecologically viable ways of living, we cannot

wait until the downfall of the capitalist system. The Green movement has

been in existence long enough for its adherents to learn which

approaches are most relevant for them.

In the 1970s I was lucky enough to be employed to start a journal for

teachers and students called the Bulletin of Environmental Education

(BEE). One of its most stimulating mentors was an inventive young man

called Peter Harper, who in 1975 went to Wales to join a group of

enthusiasts who were starting the Center for Alternative Technology

(CAT) at Machynlleth, in an old quarry in a landscape of industrial

dereliction. By the end of the century that enterprise (operating as a

workers’ cooperative of 28 members) was being visited by about 80,000

people every year, including 20,000 children, and is world-famous as a

demonstration site for environmentally friendly power generation,

building construction, and sewage disposal. I am told that it generates

90% of its own energy requirements in renewable form from sun, wind, and

water.

Since he has long practical experience in this field, I take Peter

Harper’s conclusions seriously. He told interviewers in 1998 that

The craze for self-sufficiency and small-is-beautiful has passed. Don’t

try to do it all yourself. Start where you are strong, not where you are

weak ... Don’t try to make your energy: try to save your energy. Most of

the action is going to be in cities, where the majority of humans will

soon be living and where, contrary to our old Arcadian assumptions,

sustainable modern lifestyles are more easily achieved.

His continual probing of the environmental consciousness of our fellow

citizens has led him to make a different distinction from that between

Deep Ecologists and Social Ecologists. Peter Harper divides us into

Light Greens (with more money than time) and Deep Greens (with, perhaps,

more time than money). The Light Greens, he suggests, are involved with

the new technology of solar heating, fuel-efficient lightweight motor

cars, and sustainable consumption, while the Deep Greens believe in

small, insulated houses, bicycles and public transport, homegrown food,

repair and recycling, local currency schemes, and barter.

Meanwhile, the rest of society will continue to belong to the culture of

MORE! For, as he observes,

People aspire to greater convenience and comfort, more personal space,

easy mobility, a sense of expanding possibilities. This is the modern

consumerist project: what modern societies are all about. It is a

central feature of mainstream politics and economics that consumerist

aspirations are not seriously challenged. On the contrary, the implied

official message is ‘Hang on in there: we will deliver.’ The central

slogan is brutally simple: MORE!

Some of us, Peter Harper noted in his Schumacher Lecture at Bristol in

2001, have apocalyptic visions of uncontrollable catastrophes in the

future resulting from indiscriminate economic activity. He, as an

optimist, and from his own experience as an environmental activist, has

a different expectation. He thinks that as life gradually gets worse for

everyone else, the Deep Greens (the people he calls the recessive genes

of the sustainability movement) will be found to have solved what he

calls the great riddle of reconciling modernity and sustainability:

‘They will quite visibly be having a good time: comfortable, with varied

lives and less stress, healthy and fit, having rediscovered the

elementary virtues of restraint and balance.’

Twenty-five years of offering environmental choices to fellow citizens

who came to the Center for Alternative Technology with a variety of

motives have led Peter Harper to adopt his relaxed approach to the task

of convincing us all that our lifestyles have to change. Murray Bookchin

would probably react differently, but many years earlier he posed the

same issues in discussing the nature of a liberatory technology, one

which frees rather than enslaves us. Can we imagine, he asked, that an

ecologically viable economy could be based on a centralized nation state

and its bureaucratic apparatus? He urged that, from the standpoint of

the viability of the planet and all living things on it, anarchist

concepts are not merely desirable, they are necessary:

What was once regarded as impractical and visionary has now become

eminently practical ... If community face-to-face democracy, a

humanistic, liberatory technology, and decentralization are conceived of

merely as reactions to the prevailing state of affairs – a vigorous

‘nay’ to the ‘yes’ of what exists today – a compelling, objective case

can be made for the practicability of an anarchist society.

Environmental and ecological concerns have been advocated long enough

for us to recognize peaks and troughs in the support they receive from

the general, uncommitted public, whose involvement is vital for the

manipulators of change. There are fashions in crisis-consciousness, as

in most other aspects of our communal life. A comforting thought for

anarchists is the reflection that a society advanced enough to accept

the environmental imperatives of the 21^(st) century will be obliged to

reinvent anarchism as a response to them.

For a very strong case has been made by such authors as Murray Bookchin

and Alan Carter that anarchism is the only political ideology capable of

addressing the challenges posed by our new green consciousness to the

accepted range of political ideas. Anarchism becomes more and more

relevant for the new century.

References

Chapter 1

Peter Marshall (ed.), The Anarchist Writings of William Godwin (London:

Freedom Press, 1986)

Stewart Edwards (ed.), Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon

(London: Macmillan, 1969)

K. J. Kenafick (ed.), Marxism, Freedom and the State (London: Freedom

Press, 1984)

Paul Avrich (ed.), The Conquest of Bread (London: Allen Lane, 1972

[1892])

Colin Ward (ed.), Fields, Factories and Workshops (London: Allen and

Unwin, 1974; London: Freedom Press, 1985 [1899])

John Hewetson (ed.), Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution (London: Freedom

Press, 1987 [1902])

The passage quoted from Landauer is from Martin Buber, Paths in Utopia

(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1949).

F. G. Notehelfer, Kotuku Shusui: Portrait of a Japanese Radical

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971)

Robert A. Scalapino and George T. Yu, The Chinese Anarchist Movement

(Bristol: Drowned Rat Publications, 1985)

Hai Ki-Rak, History of the Korean Anarchist Movement (Tuega, Korea:

Anarchist Publishing Committee, 1986)

Adi Doctor, Anarchist Thought in India (Bombay: Asia Publishing House,

1964)

Geoffrey Ostergaard and M. Currell, The Gentle Anarchists (Oxford:

Clarendon Press, 1971)

Sam Mbah and I. E. Igarewey, African Anarchism: The History of a

Movement (Tucson, Arizona: See Sharp Press, 1997)

For the extent of anarchist involvement in assassinations, see Charles

Townshend, Terrorism: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2002)

Kropotkin’s article on anarchism for the 11^(th) edition of the

Encyclopedia Britannica is reprinted in Peter Kropotkin, Anarchism and

Anarchist Communism (London: Freedom Press, 1987)

Chapter 2

Thomas Paine, Common Sense (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1971 [1776]) J.

Varlet, quoted in George Woodcock, Anarchism (Harmondsworth: Penguin,

1963)

Paris Commune, cited in Woodcock op. cit.

John Womack, Zapata and the Mexican Revolution (London: Thames and

Hudson, 1972)

John Ross, The War Against Oblivion: The Zapatista Chronicles (Monroe,

Maine: Common Courage Press, 2000)

Sue Branford and Jan Rocha, Cutting the Wire: The Story of the Landless

Movement in Brazil (London: Latin American Bureau, 2002)

Paul Avrich, The Russian Anarchists (New Jersey: Princeton University

Press, 1967)

Carl Levy, ‘Italian anarchism 1870–1926’, in For Anarchism: History,

Theory and Practice, ed. David Goodway (London: Routledge, 1989)

Gerald Brenan, The Spanish Labyrinth (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 1943).

Pierre Broué and Emile Témine, The Revolution and the Civil War in Spain

(London: Faber, 1970)

Burnett Bolloten, The Spanish Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of

North Carolina Press, 1979)

Noam Chomsky, American Power and the New Mandarins (New York: Random

House, 1967)

S. Faure, cited in Vernon Richards, Lessons of the Spanish Revolution

(London: Freedom Press, 1953; 3^(rd) edn. 1983)

Chapter 3

M. Buber, ‘Society and the State’, in World Review, July 1951, reprinted

in M. Buber, Pointing the Way (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1957)

Colin Ward, Social Policy: An Anarchist Response (London: London School

of Economics, 1996; Freedom Press, 2000) James Burnham, The Managerial

Revolution (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1944)

Richard Koch and Ian Godden, Managing Without Management (London:

Nicholas Brealey, 1996)

Pierre Guillet de Monthoux, Action and Existence: Anarchism for Business

Administration (Chichester: John Wiley, 1983)

A. Herzen, From the Other Shore (London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 1956;

Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979)

Chapter 4

Avi Schlaim, in The Guardian, 29 March 2003

M. Buber, Israel and Palestine (London: East and West Library, 1952)

M. Bakunin, God and the State, in Bakunin on Anarchy, ed. Sam Dogloff

(London: Allen and Unwin, 1973)

N. Walter, cited in Colin Ward, ‘Fundamentalism’, in The Raven, 27, Vol.

7, No. 3 (London: Freedom Press, 1994)

Malise Ruthven ‘Phantoms of ideology’ in Times Literary Supplement, 19

August 1994

R. Rocker, cited in W. J. Fishman, East End Jewish Radicals 1875–1914

(London: Duckworth, 1975)

E. W. Said, Culture and Imperialism (London: Chatto and Windus, 1993)

Fatima Mernissi, Women and Islam: An Historical and Theological Inquiry

(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991)

Chapter 5

Peter Kropotkin, In Russian and French Prisons (New York: Schocken

Books, 1971 [1887])

Alexander Berkman, Prison Memoirs of an Anarchist (New York: Schocken

Books, 1970 [1912])

David Cayley, The Expanding Prison: The Crisis in Crime and Punishment

and the Search for Alternatives (Toronto: Anansi, 1998) David Downes,

‘The Macho Penal Economy: Mass Incarceration in the United States. A

European Perspective’, Lecture at New York University, February 2000.

Errico Malatesta, in UmanitĂ  Nova, 2 September 1920, reprinted in V.

Richards (ed.), Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas (London: Freedom

Press, 1965)

David Waddington, on BBC Radio 4, 19 February 2003 Geoffrey Ostergaard,

The Tradition of Workers’ Control, ed. Brian Bamford (London: Freedom

Press, 1997)

Paul Thompson, Why William Morris Matters Today: Human Creativity and

the Future World Environment (London: William Morris Society, 1991)

Chapter 6

William Godwin, An Inquiry Concerning Political Justice (Harmondsworth:

Penguin, 1976 [1793]); *Uncollected Writings *(1785–1822), eds J. W.

Marken and B. R. Pollin (Gainsville, Florida: Scholars’ Facsimiles,

1968)

Paul Goodman, Compulsory Miseducation, 2^(nd) edn. (Harmondsworth:

Penguin, 1971)

National Union of Teachers, The Struggle for Education (London: NUT,

1970)

Stephen Humphries, Hooligans or Rebels? An Oral History of Working-Class

Childhood and Youth 1889–1939 (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981)

Philip Gardner, The Lost Elementary Schools of Victorian England

(London: Croom Helm, 1984)

Paul Thompson, ‘Basic Skills’, in New Society, 6 December 1984

Francesco Ferrer, see Paul Avrich, The Modern School Movement: Anarchism

and Education in the United States (New Jersey: Princeton University

Press, 1980)

Michael Bakunin, God and the State (London: Freedom Press, 1910; New

York: Dover, 1970)

Harry RĂ©e, reported in The Teacher, 8 April 1972

H. M. Chief Inspector of Schools, interviewed in The Times, 1 February

1995, and reported in The Times Educational Supplement, 27 January 1995

Michael Smith, The Libertarians and Education (London: Allen and Unwin,

1983)

John Shotton, No Master High or Low: Libertarian Education and Schooling

1890–1990 (Bristol: Libertarian Education, 1993)

Jonathan Croall, Neill of Summerhill: The Permanent Rebel (London:

Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983)

Jonathan Croall (ed.), All the Best, Neill: Letters from Summerhill

(London: André Deutsch, 1974)

Chapter 7

Max Stirner, The Ego and His Own, tr. Steven Byington (New York:

Libertarian Book Club, 1963 [1907])

James J. Martin, Men Against the State (Colorado Springs: Ralph Myles,

1970)

David DeLeon, The American as Anarchist: Reflections on Indigenous

Radicalism (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978)

Henry David Thoreau, in Carl Bode (ed.), The Portable Thoreau

(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1979)

Randolph Bourne, War and the Intellectuals: Collected Essays 1915– 1919

(New York: The Resistance Press, 1964)

Ammon Hennacy, The Autobiography of a Catholic Anarchist (New York:

Catholic Worker Books, 1954)

Dorothy Day, The Long Loneliness (New York: Harper and Row, 1952)

Robert Paul Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (New York: Harper Colophon,

1976)

Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: Blackwell, 1974)

David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper, 1975)

Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto (New York:

Collier, 1978)

F. von Hayek, The Road to Serfdom (London: Routledge, 1944)

Paul Goodman, ‘Politics within Limits’, reprinted in Taylor Stoehr

(ed.), *Crazy Hope and Finite Experience: Final Essays of Paul Goodman

Chapter 8

Dwight Macdonald, ‘Politics Past’, in Encounter, April 1957

Emma Goldman, ‘The Tragedy of Women’s Emancipation’, in Anarchism and

Other Essays (New York: Dover, 1969 [1911])

Alex Comfort, More Joy: A Lovemaking Companion to The Joy of Sex

(London: Quartet, 1973)

Charles Duff, A Handbook on Hanging (London: Freedom Press, 1965)

Rudolf de Jong, Provos and Kabouters (Buffalo, NY: Friends of Malatesta,

no date)

Raoul Vaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday Life, rev. edn. (London:

Rebel Press, 1983)

George Monbiot, Captive State (London: Macmillan, 2000)

Sean M. Sheehan, Anarchism (London: Reaktion Books, 2003)

Chapter 9

Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, The Principle of Federation, tr. Richard Vernon

(Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1979)

Edward Hyams, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (London: John Murray, 1979)

Willem de Haan, The Politics of Redress (London: Unwin Hyman, 1990)

Arthur Lehning (ed.), Bakunin: Selected Writings (London: Jonathan Cape,

1973)

Martin Miller, Kropotkin (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976)

Camillo Berneri, Peter Kropotkin: His Federalist Ideas (London: Freedom

Press, 1942 [1922])

Peter Hall, Cities of Tomorrow (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988)

Council of Europe, ‘The Impact of the Completion of the Internal Market

on Local and Regional Autonomy’ (Council of Europe Studies and Texts,

Series No.12, 1990)

Thom Holterman, ‘A Free United Europe’, in The Raven, 31, Vol. 8, No. 3

(London: Freedom Press, 1995)

Chapter 10

<biblio> Amartya Sen, Poverty and Famine (Oxford: Oxford University

Press, 1981)

Jac Smit et al., Urban Agriculture: Food, Jobs and Sustainable Cities

(New York: United Nations Development Program, 1996)

Tim Lang, in Ken Worpole (ed.), Richer Futures: Fashioning a New

Politics (London: Earthscan, 1999)

John Houghton, cited in The Raven, 43, Vol. 11, No. 3 (London: Freedom

Press, 2001)

Murray Bookchin, Post-Scarcity Anarchism (London: Wildwood House 1974)

Peter Harper, interviewed in W. & D. Schwartz Living Lightly: Travels in

Post-Consumer Society (Oxford: Jon Carpenter 1998), and ‘Natural

Technology’, lecture to the Schumacher Society, Bristol 2001

Alan Carter, A Radical Green Political Theory (London: Routledge, 1999)

</biblo>

Further reading

An earlier interpreter of anarchism remarked that ‘anarchism is like

blotting-paper: it soaks up everything’, and, like most political

ideologies, it can be given a variety of emphases. Beyond the general

histories described in the Foreword, there are several books I should

mention, providing alternative or additional interpretations extending

those explored in this volume.

Max Blechman (ed.), Drunken Boat: Art, Rebellion, Anarchy (Brooklyn, NY:

Automedia; and Seattle, WA: Left Bank Books, 1984)

Murray Bookchin, Post-Scarcity Anarchism (London: Wildwood House, 1974)

Alan Carter, A Radical Green Political Theory (London: Routledge, 1999)

Howard J. Ehrlich (ed.), Reinventing Anarchy, Again (Edinburgh and San

Francisco: AK Press, 1996)

Clifford Harper, Anarchy: A Graphic Guide (London: Camden Press, 1987)

George McKay (ed.), DIY Culture: Party and Protest in Nineties Britain

(London: Verso, 1998)

Jon Purkis and James Bowen (eds), Twenty-First Century Anarchism:

Unorthodox Ideas for a New Millennium (London: Cassell, 1997)

Sean M. Sheehan, Anarchism (London: Reaktion Books, 2003)