💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › ervin-szabo-marx-and-bakunin.gmi captured on 2023-01-30 at 01:13:59. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

⬅️ Previous capture (2023-01-29)

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Marx and Bakunin
Author: Ervin SzabĂł
Date: June 2005
Language: en
Topics: Karl Marx, Mikhail Bakunin, first international
Source: Retrieved on 2nd March 2021 from https://libcom.org/history/ervin-szab%C3%B3-marx-bakunin
Notes: Introduction by the Barricade Collective

Ervin SzabĂł

Marx and Bakunin

Nowadays the class struggles and within these the viewpoint of some

groups are alarmingly insular minded. These groups throw the experiences

of the past – which have already been accumulated – away, and focus only

on present times. This thing wouldn’t be surprising if we could fight

this struggle in unity against the ruling class and after in bed of

roses we would enjoy the bearings of communism. Who would be that

foolish person that time dealing with the spirit of the past… But we are

living in capitalism and our class is very devided, which thing has very

arborescent reasons – from the scarcity of class-solidarity to the

abscence of class cosciousness. Not long ago we have sent a text to a

libertarian communist activist, who after reading that text has asked

why we are dealing with such an old text. (It was written in the

nineteenth century.) We have answered in our letter: „What have changed

between now and then connected to capitalism and proletarian struggles?”

We cast everything away which rejects dialectic and throws our struggles

to the space and wrest them from their historical context. We don’t want

to argufy but go to blazes those banzai self-advertising actionism and

other craps, which make only press-material for media and enhance

capital’s terror which thing could go with imprisonment and liquidation

of thousands of comrades. Of course, we are not against the organised or

spontaneous street fightings or looting, sabotage, demonstration,

strike. We just want to emphasize, that the most important thing is to

do these actions in organised form and orderly in case if these have

spontaneous aspects to avoid defeat.

For us there is no „past” and „present” divided into two different

parts, just the whole of the struggle in its continuity. Therefore it’s

important to integrate „preterite struggles” as the experiences for the

future. This is the reason why we publish this text.

Ervin SzabĂł had an especial walk of life. His writing which is published

here shows great perspicacity. At first he makes a wild rush at social

democracy with which he was arguing all along his life and condemns its

personalities and its hatred of anarchism. On the one hand this conflict

can originate to Marx and Engels. On the other hand Bakunin and the

anarchists were responsible for the dividing of the revolutionary

movement. He has written this article to establish the unity. It’s

important to point out this because at present working class is divided

at many walks of bourgeois „life”, despite of their common interests.

Because of this, we think it’s necessary for proletarians living in the

West to get to know the writing of comrade SzabĂł.

Szabó shows in his article that the „two tendencies” agreed in most of

the principles of the First International, the only difference between

them was in the question of centralization/decentralization. Marx

supported the centralization against Bakunin’s federalism but this is

only a half-truth, because Bakunin and his associates established a

centralized communist organization with the forming of Alliance. Its

statues had romantic elements but other parts of it compose an integral

part of the communist platform. At the same time the two tendencies

accused each other with authoritarianism, and personal remark empoisoned

the atmosphere. This irresponsible trifling have divided the

revolutionary working-class movement. Thus we have to argue and explain

the basic differences between communism and bolshevism as well as

anarchism and liberalism yet again.

We do not agree with some of the author’s false statements – for example

the partition of „scientist and fighter”, the considering of social

democracy as a part of socialism. After all, social democracy had never

maintained the struggle of the proletariat but it had tried to

inactivate it. Altogether the article is progressive for our struggle

because it tries to enhance unity despite of its ambiguous parts.

Ervin SzabĂł was born in 1877. From 1899 he admits himself anarchist, in

after years Marxist. The Russian revolutionists and the Hungarian-German

social democracy had great affect on his viewpoint. With the latter he

encountered soon after – because of its reformism. He was publishing

regularly all along his life and was all attention to the revolutionary

movement in which he was taking part, too. It’s due to him that

socialist pieces have become accessible in the public libraries in

Hungary. Cultural orientation had a great importance his whole lifelong

through. He made an important role in translating, publishing

Marx-Engels’ selected works and wrote divine forewords. He was forming

connections with Italian and Russian anarcho-syndicalists but he has

never been touched by the waves of nationalism. The experience of

syndicalism hurt him, namely he become syndicalist in 1909. In the next

year he wrote the manifesto of the syndicalist propaganda-group (in his

syndicalism he always rejected the unions and attended to independent

workers’ organizations). He wrote his paper named „The struggle between

Capital and Labour” in 1911 and along about the first world war he had

been the determinant theoretican of the Hungarian „Zimmerwaldists” and

Revolutionary Socialists, but had kept himself in the background. He had

been writing internationalist pamphlets, had been giving piece of advice

connected to conspiracy. Anarchists and communists had been working

together inside this group, they had had no divergencies. Later the

Hungarian Communist Party was formed from this movement, which had been

appropriated by Kun and his associates afterwards and made an advance to

bolshevism. Ervin Szabó couldn’t see this because he died in 1918. He

was waiting for the revolution his whole lifelong through, he saw

expectantly the revolution in Russia but he avoided bolshevism because

he had a flair for this and due to his non-Leninist Marxism. Truly Ervin

Szabó had never been eclectic – although he tried a lot within the

spectrum of the working-class movement. He was an anarcho-Marxist whom

both liberalism and bolshevism tried to appropriate. We are sorry he

died before the proletarian revolution of 1919 in Hungary which he was

fighting actively for.

Barricade Collective, 2005 June

---

Every nation and every generation has its favorite legendary epoch into

which it projects its yearnings and ideals in the form of extremely

enlarged realities-enlarged and exaggerated-because only such

unconscious self-delusion can ever compensate for the misery of the

present, a present upon which desires get shipwrecked, in which the most

beautiful principles shrivel into commonplace facts.

What the heroic age was for warlike peoples and the era of the martyrs

for the Christians, that is the era of the International for the

socialists of Western Europe. That was the legendary age when the

bourgeoisie and the rulers of all Europe were trembling at the sight of

this international spectre, which was in high fever burning and

consuming itself in the rivalry of the titans, Marx and Bakunin. The

Inaugural Address was the first public docu-ment issued by the first

international organization of the working class.

Today we know that the International Working Men’s Association was far

from being the awe-inspiring power the bourgeoisie imagined it to be,

terror-stricken as it was by revolutions and counterrevolutions and as

it still is in the less developed countries. The workers of any minor

country today could throw larger masses and greater force into the

struggle than the entire international camp that the International was

able to muster. It could hardly have been otherwise: the working class

was much less devel-oped in some countries, much less conscious in

others. It was not its actual power that rendered the International

truly great and awe-inspiring, but rather its clear under-standing of

basic principles and the guidance it was able to provide the workers’

movement. This guidance was precisely what was least appreciated at the

time, by the working and by the ruling classes alike. The attention of

contemporaries was drawn to immediate goals, to occasional tactics, and

to devices meant to shock. Very few were able to recognize the essence,

the great principles of liberation.

Perhaps today we are better able to appreciate the true significance of

the International, the fact that it emphasized certain principles more

clearly and more consciously than any of its predecessors: “that the

liberation of the working class can be accomplished only by the working

class itself,” “that every kind of servitude is social misery,” “that in

consequence the economic liberation of the working-class is the major

goal, and all the political movements must be subordinated to it,” and

“that the liberation of work is not a local or national problem, but a

social one, which extends to every modernized country.” All these

principles are eminently up-to-date, relevant, and weighty even now.

They contain everything that we recognize as the basic principles of

contemporary socialist movement. In fact, many wordy party programs say

no more, but take longer to say it less well.

In order correctly to evaluate the theoretical and practical

significance of the International, I would like to deal with a

superstition derived from its internal struggles and which still has an

impact on socialist movements in certain countries. In those countries

where “German Marxism” prevails, that is, mainly in the German Empire

itself, in Austria, Hungary, Russia, and the Balkans, social democrats

are stubbornly convinced that the International was destroyed not

because it came before its time, but because of personality clashes,

particularly the disruptive activity of Bakunin, in other words, that

Bakunin, the true father of anarchism, was the enemy of every kind of

organization and that the true objective of anarchism to this day is

disorganization. Consequently, there can be no more irreconcilable

contradiction than the one between anarchism and socialism; anarchists

and socialists are not brothers, but enemies.

Every improvement in organizing the proletariat is a step towards its

liberation, and every obstacle to its organization is a step backwards.

Those friends of the proletariat who would weaken its solidarity for its

own alleged benefit are actually much more dangerous enemies than the

opponents who would destroy the proletarian organizations by force. No

tendency has advanced further along this line than that of Bakunin. This

is why Marxists are waging a merciless war against it.

Thus wrote Karl Kautsky, the leading theoretician of so-called orthodox

revolutionary Marxism, only a few years ago. The declaration of a Dutch

social democrat at the 1904 international congress in Amsterdam, that

“the anarchists are our greatest enemies,” likewise went unchallenged.

Furthermore, in the above mentioned countries, the anarchists are

frequently accused of being spies for the police or agents provocateurs.

The history of the International sheds light on the origin of these

arguments and accusations. The roots can be found particularly in the

polemical writings with which Marx fought against the growing influence

of Bakunin and which ultimately led to the latter’s exclusion from the

International. These writings not only distort Bakunin’s theoretical

statements to the point where they appear totally muddled or absurd, but

also include grave accusations against his personal and political

integrity. Even Kautsky admits that these charges were entirely without

foundation: “It is impossible to deny,” he wrote in 1902, “that in the

heat of the struggle against Bakunin and his followers Marx and his

friends overshot their mark and resorted to any number of baseless

accusations.” Nevertheless, only two years later, a German social

democrat wrote a rather successful book about the International in which

the followers of Bakunin were, in the words of Kautsky, “occasionally

labeled liars, demagogues, and even criminal characters.” Another social

democrat has, in utter bad faith, distorted the teachings of Bakunin in

a pamphlet that has been translated into every European language. The

party newspapers and agitators make sure that the poison of libel

spreads everywhere. On the other hand, certain anarchists seem to

believe in the same bad faith that they can best serve their cause by

raising similar charges against Marx, Engels, and social democracy in

general.

Under these circumstances it seems appropriate to preface the Hungarian

translation of the first document of the International so as to head off

a possible attempt to embitter the already sharp actual conflicts with

further myths invented in our own country. Hence I will do my best,

insofar as that is possible within the framework of an introduction, to

make an objective comparison of the

theories of Marx and Bakunin and to determine their relationship to each

other.

Bakunin’s Theories and Marxism

It cannot be claimed that Bakunin was one of the great masters of style.

Predisposed to oral agitation and to action, engaged in constant and

almost superhuman activity, Bakunin could not possibly have taken up the

pen with the serenity and objectivity which is required for lucid

writing. With few exceptions, his writings are occasional pieces about

the initiation or justification of some action or polemical tracts. We

know how easily a writer becomes dominated by his temperament in such

cases, how he stresses certain points which might otherwise have

remained in the background, and how he sharpens certain arguments to

harm his adversary rather than to serve the cause of justice. All of

Bakunin’s writings are of this nature, written in the heat of combat. No

wonder his opponents have had no difficulty culling contradictions from

them or pointing out his many sloppy formulations in order to

demonstrate his ignorance and confusion.

Were one to approach his works not with a view to detecting

contradictions at all cost, but rather with the realization that the

work of an agitator, bent to influence whole countries and generations,

must be forceful and single-minded, one would discover something

entirely different in the works of Bakunin. One would discover that the

father of anarchism was far from being a representative of idealistic

philosophical speculations or of the fantastic individualism of the

post-Hegelian period. Rather, Bakunin was, in every respect, the

disciple of the nineteenth-century school of positive sociology.

So how could he possibly be cast as the theoretical opponent of Marx?

Bakunin himself claimed to be a disciple of Marx. “I am your disciple,”

he wrote to him in one of his letters, “and I am proud of it.” He

declared this to others as well. When Herzen urged him to respond in

kind to Marx who had spread rumours about his being a paid agent of the

Russian government, Bakunin replied:

As far as Marx is concerned, I know as well as you do that he is guilty

towards us like so many others; what is more, that he is the author and

instigator of the ignominies attributed to us. Why have I praised him,

then? For two reasons... First, for the sake of justice. No matter how

despicably he behaved towards us, I for one will not pass over his

outstanding merits regarding socialism; he has been ahead of us by

serving the cause for almost twenty-five years intelligently,

dynamically, and faithfully... Second, for political reasons: Marx is

one of the surest, most influential and most intelligent pillars of

socialism in the International, and one of the most solid dams against

penetration by any kind of bourgeois tendency. And I would never forgive

myself were I to annihilate or diminish his un-questionably beneficial

influence for the sake of the satisfaction of my personal desire for

vengeance.

Bakunin had not spoken in such glowing terms of any of his predecessors

or contemporaries even though, like most persons with an impulsive

character, he was inclined to exaggerate the virtues and merits of

others. Still, he does not mention Proudhon in such favorable colors,

though Proudhon was the only truly significant theoretician of socialism

next to Marx and undoubtedly shared some of Bakunin’s ideas. Even less

does Bakunin praise the person who is sometimes described as the true

father of anarchism (although his influence was quite limited), Max

Stirner, or anybody else, for that matter. Actually Bakunin felt himself

closest to Marx, both in theory and in practice. Bakunin was the first

to translate the Communist Manifesto into Russian, and he began to

translate Capital as well, while it never occurred to him to translate

the works of any other west European socialist.

Nevertheless, we cannot refer to him as simply a disciple of Marx or as

a Marxist. Even if we mean no more by Marxism than Marx’s method of

research – historical materialism – and the concomitant principle of

action – class struggle – and exclude from it everything that is not a

generally valid sociological thesis but merely an observation applicable

to a specific period such as capitalism, or to a specific field, such as

political economy, even then we would still have to concede that the

basic theories of Bakunin and Marx are not completely identical. Not

because Bakunin rejected historical materialism, nor because he did not

proclaim and practice class struggle, but because, in his reading of

these Marxian notions, alien elements had crept in which often

interfered with their consistent application.

His general views on social philosophy predisposed Bakunin to Marxism.

Some of its opponents like to pretend that anarchism is an extension of

bourgeois liberalism, the cult of ultimate individualism and of absolute

personal freedom. This is not the place to discuss the untruth of these

assertions, but I can marshal any number of quotations to demonstrate

that Bakunin was not an individualist. He was far from interpreting

historical progress as the work of arbitrary individual will, or from

considering social existence as the death of, or even a barrier to,

individual liberty. He was far from satisfied with the vapid and

superficial formulations of the principle of individual liberty which

states that the only limit to the freedom of the individual is the

freedom of other individuals. This was the principle upon which the most

typical and most outstanding master of the liberal school of sociology,

Herbert Spencer, would have based the society of the future. This

definition matches almost word for word the principle of liberty

enunciated by Rousseau, and that was precisely the target of Bakunin’s

sharpest attacks. For him social life is as much determined by

implacable laws as nature is. The universal law of causality reigns in

one domain just as in the other; the same unseverable connection and

fateful ineluctability prevails in one sphere as in the other. It is

impossible to revolt against the natural laws, because they surround us

and penetrate our every movement, our every thought, regulate our every

action, and even when we think we are disobeying the laws of nature we

do no more than proclaim their omnipotence. With respect to these laws

man can have but one freedom: to recognize them and to use them

increasingly along the road to collective and individual liberation and

humanization on which he is advancing.

Man has reached this road thanks to his understanding, thanks to his

capacity for abstraction. But are abstractions and ideas the springs of

historical development? According to the idealists, yes. They claim that

certain ideas and feelings are innate in humans. Nothing can be further

from the truth. What humans bring with them-selves at the moment of

their birth-at various stages of their evolution and to different

degrees-is nothing but the material or formal capacity to feel, think,

shape, and develop ideas. These capacities are strictly formal. What

gives them content? Society does.

How did the first concepts or ideas come about in history? The only

thing we can say is that they were not created autonomously, in

isolation, by the miraculously enlightened minds of certain inspired

individuals. They were the outcome of collective effort, something that

passed mostly unnoticed by sections of society and by the minds of

individuals. The geniuses, the outstanding individuals of a given

society, are only the most fortunate spokesmen of this collective

effort. Every person of genius is like Voltaire: “He took the best

wherever he found it.” In other words, it was the collective mind of

primitive society that created the first ideas.

Thus man is a social being, both physically and intellectually. To the

idealists a la Rousseau man was free and immortal at the beginning, and

became mortal and a slave only in society. He surrendered the freedom of

his immortal and infinite soul in order to satisfy the needs of his

finite and imperfect body. Social life, therefore, is the surrender of

the infinite and of freedom.

The concept of freedom held by materialists, realists, and collectivists

is precisely the opposite. Human beings become human only within

society, and it is only by the collective action of all society that

they attain the consciousness and realization of their humanity. Only

social or collective work is able to convert the surface of the earth

into an area conducive to human development and liberate men from the

yoke of nature. Without this material liberation, moral and intellectual

liberation would remain impossible. Nor is it possible to free oneself

from the yoke of one’s own inner nature; that is, one cannot subordinate

the instincts and movements of one’s body to the direction of a more

developed intellect except by education and culture. Both processes of

liberation are social manifestations par excellence. Outside of society

man would have forever remained a wild animal... The isolated individual

would not even have awoken to the realization of his freedom. To be free

means that others, all human, recognize one as free, and deal with one

accordingly. Thus freedom is not a factor of isolation, but mutual

reflections; not of exclusion, but of contact. The freedom of every

individual is nothing but the reflection of his humanity and his human

rights in the consciousness of others. It is only in the presence of

others, and vis-á-vis others, that one can claim to be and actually be

free.

The progress of society amounts to the widening of the sphere of human

liberty. What does this widening mean? It means that man learns the laws

of nature better and better and thereby becomes master over them. The

road to civilization and to freedom is one and the same.

A thinker who regarded individual freedom and will to be thus dependent

on the social environment can certainly not be accused of individualism.

When Bakunin emphasizes that “liberty is not at the beginning of

history, but at its end,” because “the true, great, objective and final

goal of history is the actual and total emancipation of every

individual,” then he is in concert with Engels who had stated that

“Socialism is humanity’s leap from the kingdom of necessity into the

kingdom of freedom.”

We have seen that Bakunin places the origin of ideas in society and

makes freedom dependent on social progress. Only one step separates this

interpretation from historical materialism. And Bakunin took this final

step. In the pamphlet aimed at the German school of socialism (Sophismes

Historiques de l’Ecole Doctrinaire des Communistes Allemands), he once

again contrasted the idealists with the materialists:

While they derive all aspects of history, including material progress

and the development of various sectors of economic organization, from

ideas, the German communists, on the contrary, see in all history, in

the most ideal manifestations of collective and individual life, in the

intellectual, moral, religious, metaphysical, scientific, artistic,

political, legal, and social changes in the past and at the present,

nothing but the reflections of economic factors or necessary reactions

to them. While the idealists claim that ideas precede facts and even

create them, the communists... on the other hand, claim that facts give

birth to ideas and that the latter are nothing but the ideal expression

of discrete events. The communists claim that the economic, the material

world are the facts par excellence; these are the ones that create the

main base, the essential foundation, while all other factors,

intellectual or moral, political or social, are merely inevitable

consequences.

Who is right: the idealists or the materialists? Once the question has

been posed in this way, our answer cannot be hesitant. Without a doubt

the idealists are mistaken, only the materialists are right. Yes, the

facts do precede ideas. Yes, the ideal, as Proudhon said, is but a

flower, its roots are the material conditions. Yes, the entire

intellectual, moral, political, and social history of mankind is the

reflection of its economic history. Every branch of serious and

disinterested modern science can be cited to support this great,

decisive truth.

We can see that Bakunin was not only able precisely to explain

historical materialism, but actually accepted it in its full expanse,

though he himself proceeded to limit its applicability right away. Given

the gaps in his training in economics one could hardly expect that at

times he should not perceive other factors as dominant; the objective

view of things, the consistent derivation of the facts of mental life

from the objectified outside world, was incompatible with his active

fighting spirit. Thus Bakunin easily forgot what he had often argued

regarding the social origin of ideas; next to the economic factor he

placed two bio-psychological factors – the ability to think and the

capacity and need to revolt – as complementary aspects of social

evolution. He refers to these two capacities as the negative factors of

progress, whereas the economic is the positive one.

Obviously Bakunin in the same breath has cited two elemental and general

factors of the organic world and a specifically social factor. For the

capacity to think and revolt is not an exclusively human trait, but

merely the mental expression and subjective reflection of that great

elemental force to which all living creatures owe their life: the

struggle for survival. Every struggle is a revolt, the same for the

tiger, the caterpillar, the fir tree, the moss, as it is for man.

Historical materialism does not deny this in the least. But the person

who uses social science as a method of research has to restrict himself

to social facts and seek nothing more than the specific means humanity

uses in its social struggle and hence finds that the existence of

humanity is shaped by the development and forms of its economic

activities. In other words, the complex manifestations of society are to

be reduced to the most basic social activity. That this basic social

activity is founded on even more basic natural conditions is not a

matter for the social scientist but pertains to the domain of the

natural sciences.

We would be inordinately strict with Bakunin, however, if we were to bar

him from the ranks of the adepts of historical materialism simply on the

grounds that he has mixed biological and psychological factors into the

basic factors accounting for social developments or because at moments

he attributed greater importance to ideas. Any number of thinkers who

had no greater familiarity with the genuine essence of historical

materialism than Bakunin were counted as true Marxists to the end of

their life. A whole school of thinkers has identified the examination of

economic factors, that is, the derivation of social manifestations from

the means of production, simply with economic interest; they have

reduced it to a purely psychological category. Engels himself – after

Marx’s death – made significant allowances for the subjective tendency.

Others have confused historical with philosophical materialism. The

problem of historical materialism is not simple, and Bakunin is not the

only Marxist who used the concept mistakenly.

It is undeniable, however, that Bakunin never fell into extremes; when

examining specific social problems he perceived, along with the basic

economic aspect, the concomitant intellectual, moral, religious, and

other factors; nevertheless, in the critique of ideologies and the

struggle against them he never neglected the social bases of ideas.

Among his most deeply rooted tendencies was his antagonism to religion

and to the church. In each one of his works he ends up by discussing God

and religion. Nevertheless, he writes about the propaganda activity of

free thinkers:

Only social revolution, and not the propaganda of free thinkers, will be

able to extirpate religion from the bosom of the people. To be sure,

that propaganda is quite useful. It is even indispensable as a means of

converting the more progressive individuals; but it can-not affect the

masses, because religion is not simply a slip or dislocation of the

mind, but rather and particularly the protest of the live and active

character of the masses against the miseries of actual existence. The

people go to church for the same reason as they go to the tavern-to be

drugged, to forget their misery, and to think of themselves, at least

for brief moments, as equal, free, and happy. Let him have a human life

and he will no longer go to either pub or church. This human existence

can and will be provided for him only by social revolution.

Some Marxists claim that to attribute decisive significance to human

understanding in social development or to attempt the transformation of

society by means of legislation is compatible with the economic

perception of society. Bakunin’s reply to these social scientists was

completely in accord with the spirit of historical materialism.

Society is ruled by morals and customs, never by laws. Individual

initiatives, rather than the thought or will of the legislator, drive it

slowly along the road of progress. There are laws which govern it

unconsciously, but these are natural laws, inherent to the social body,

just as the physical laws are inherent to material bodies. The better

part of these laws is unknown to this day, and yet they have ruled

society since its beginnings, independent of the thought and will of the

persons constituting it; from which it follows that we must not confuse

them with political and juridical laws.

This sounds very much like the opening sentences in Marx’s famous

preface to the Critique of Political Economy.

Bakunin’s Practical Principles and Marx

Thus far I have endeavored to show the proximity between the general

social philosophies of Bakunin and Marx. I have placed greater stress on

this than I shall in the next section, in which I compare their

political and tactical views, their praxis. Yet it was not about

theories that they clashed in the International but rather about

questions of tactics and organization. Admittedly these matters are much

more important than theories. They mean action, life, actual history; at

most, theories provide an account of the extent to which historical

events have registered in the heads of individual persons. If I have

dealt at length with theories, it was because, while the writings of

Marx and of the social democrats, most of which were in German, are

easily accessible, the works of Bakunin and the anarchists, mostly in

French and Italian, remain largely inaccessible to Hungarian readers.

The inevitable consequence of this has been that our working class has

gained a totally one-sided view of the significance of both tendencies

of the socialist movement and has accepted uncritically all the bona (or

mala) fide errors of the German social democrats.

I believe the passages from Bakunin quoted above should make everyone

more cautious in regard to the usual accusations; and it should no

longer be easy to pretend that the contradiction between Bakunin and

Marx is like the one between the working class and the bourgeoisie;

moreover, it will not be possible to deny that Bakunin and Marx are

related by close theoretical ties.

This kinship seems even closer when it comes to the politics of the

working class and the socialist movement. While studying objectively the

history of the International, one is bound to feel that the mutual

accusations, insofar as they had some basis in reality, were either

eminently premature or simply pretended, and farfetched conflicts. There

was but one serious source of conflict: whether the organization of the

International should be centralized or federalized; whether the General

Council sitting in London should be an organization controlling the

local sections, or merely a correspondence office transmitting their

communications. Because of his temperament, his inclination to

authoritarianism, and his personal vanity, Marx was inclined to

centralism whereas Bakunin was swept towards the opposite point of view

by his temperament and his unbridled desire for action.

Yet all this relates solely to the internal organization of the

International. Not a word was said about applying the principles of

organization of the International to either the workers’ movement on the

whole, or to its national, political, and economic subdivisions. After

all, every section and, what is more, every single member belonged to

the association not via some central national organ, but directly.

However, as today, almost forty years after the Hague congress at which

Bakunin was excluded from the organization, the central organ of the

international social democratic movement, the Bureau Socialiste

Internationale in Brussels, is simply that – a bureau, an office, rather

than a higher forum – we must conclude that time has vindicated Bakunin.

As to the basic points of the program of the International, Bakunin was

in total agreement with Marx. What were these points? The program

specified class organization and politics of the working class in total

independence from other classes and of bourgeois parties; a halt to the

monopoly of the means of production as a basic condition of the liberty

of the working class, hence the subordination of the political movement

to the economic struggle; finally, the assertion of the international

nature of the workers’ movement.

The contradictions that have arisen in these matters do not refer to the

essence, but to the inconsequential details or to conclusions that were

not at all relevant in that primitive stage of the working-class

movement, such as parliamentarianism and participation in government or

the problem of the organization of future society-all of which were

entirely academic matters at the time. It is fairly obvious, however,

that it was precisely the Bakuninists who stuck rigidly to the basic

principles of the International, which, as we know, were formulated by

Marx, whereas those who stood by Marx during the controversies (it is

not possible to refer to them invariably as Marxists) were often mere

politicians who made concessions to the early times and the undeveloped

conditions out of political opportunism. That is, they have acted much

the same way as Bakunin had been justly accused of acting in his Russian

policy. The economic and social conditions in Russia were incomparably

more primitive than those of Western Europe at the time, for industry

and an industrial working class simply did not exist; hence the only

possible politics were aristocratic or liberal. In Western Europe, on

the contrary, it was not possible to do anything except pure

working-class politics. This was all Marx insisted on, as was clearly

stated in the program of the International. Bakunin and his disciples

wanted the same; and so it happened that each time Marx opposed Bakunin,

he ended up by opposing himself. Mutual recriminations are mostly what

we get in these matters.

We can see this immediately in the issue of class consciousness. Bakunin

was accused of being petit bourgeois; Bakunin said the same about the

socialists and workers in Germany:

In Germany though the socialist paper kept insisting on awakening within

the proletariat a feeling and consciousness of its necessary

contradiction vis-a-vis the bourgeois (Klassenbewusstsein,

Klassenkampf), the workers and peasants remain part of the network of

the bourgeoisie whose culture surrounds them completely, and whose

spirit permeates the masses. And these same socialist writers, who are

thundering against the bourgeoisie, are themselves bourgeois from top to

bottom; they are the propagandists and apostles of the bourgeoisie, and,

although unwittingly for the most part, they have become the defenders

of bourgeois interests against the proletariat.

Accordingly, Bakunin took the most determined stand against the

bourgeoisie, as well as against the so-called bourgeois socialists or

reform socialists, who are intent on purely political reform by means of

charity, moral preaching, or government assistance: helping the lower

classes, but only through initiatives taken by the upper class. He

fought them particularly in Italy, where he had most room for practical

action,but elsewhere as well. In this regard Bakunin’s attitude was not

a bit less determined than that of Marx. In general he claimed that the

bourgeoisie, “this class which at one time was so powerful, enlightened,

and flourishing and which today slowly but inevitably heads towards

decline is already dead as regards its reason and morals. It no longer

has faith, or ideas, or any spirit of endeavor. It does not want to and

cannot turn back, yet it dares not look forward either.” “The character

of contemporary bourgeoisie is to appreciate the beautiful only in the

past, and to adore in the present only that which is profitable and

useful.” Hence Bakunin kept reiterating that the working class should

not count on the bourgeoisie. No one could have expressed more clearly

and pointedly the contradiction separating the concept of the two

classes regarding the means of progress. One of the two classes, having

developed its economic forces, can increase its power only by means of

political power, whereas the other can develop the forces latent in its

social situation only through the struggle against this power.

The bourgeois see and understand nothing that is not part of the state

or of the means regulated by the state. The maximum of their ideal, of

their imagination, and of their heroism is the revolutionary

exaggeration of the power and function of the state in the name of

general interest. But I have already shown that the activity of the

state cannot save... France... I am the absolute enemy of revolution par

decrets, the consequence and application of the principle of the

revolutionary state; that is, of the kind of revolution which bears only

the outward appearance of revolution. I confront the system of

revolutionary decrees with the system of revolutionary acts, the only

truly effective, consistent, and true one.

Let no one think, however, that Bakunin naively believed it would be

sufficient to make a revolution and a collective society would be ready

right away. He often stressed that the bourgeois world still has more

material means and organized and educated government forces at its

disposal than we would wish. In the sequence of historical periods in

which cannibalism was replaced by slavery, slavery by serfdom, and

serfdom by wage-labor “there will come the terrible day of judgment

which in turn will be followed, much, much later, by the era of

brotherhood.” Bakunin claimed, however, that society cannot be shaken by

words and resolutions: actions are needed, but an act deserves the name

of action only if it changes the world in some way. Undeniably he was

inclined to overestimate the value of violent revolts and to greet every

violent uprising as an action; but no one can pretend that he felt that

individual action was the only possible one, or that the organization of

the masses was superfluous. In some Italian cities where Bakuninism was

especially strong he had thousands of adherents organized by trade, in

accordance with his principle that “it is not enough to be merely

conscious of the truth; it is necessary to organize the forces of the

proletariat...” because “without prior organization even the most

powerful forces remain impotent and nil.” The first congress of

Bakuninists decided in this spirit, when it proposed to all its members

the establishment of trade unions and of strike funds.

In fact, this was not what separated the two nuances of the

International. It was not a matter of whether organization was necessary

or not, but rather whether the basis of socialist organization should be

unions by trade or purely political organizations. One of Marx’s most

faithful disciples, Jung, in an official letter addressed to one of the

leaders of the Swiss Bakuninists, James Guillaume, on behalf of the

General Council of the International, wrote:

You believe that the trade unions will be the ones to obtain the

liberation of the workers? You are wrong. We use trade unions as one

kind of tool among many, but not as an end in themselves. The trade

unions are the expression of economic struggle. They will never

transform society, however; they may initiate social revolution, but

could never finish it. In order to change society, in order to complete

the social revolution, the workers will be obliged to seize political

power.

It is also an unquestionable fact that all the social democratic

parties, and especially those that consider themselves the bastions of

orthodox Marxism, remained for a long time completely indifferent

towards the trade union movement, crediting it with little or uncertain

value. The force of reality, the tremendous growth and impact of

economic organizations as compared to the political movement, was

necessary to finally convince some Marxists of our day that the economic

movement was at least as important as the political one in the struggle

for the liberation of the working class. On the other hand, the

International had proclaimed the great significance of the economic

organizations some forty years ago, while still under the influence of

Marx. As early as in 1864, the first congress held in Geneva stated

that:

…unconsciously to themselves, the Trades’ Unions were forming centres of

organisation of the working class, as the mediaeval municipalities and

communes did for the middle class. If the Trades’ Unions are required

for the guerrilla fights between capital and labor, they are still more

important as organized agencies for superseding the very system of wages

labor and capital rule.

It is the International itself that describes trade unions as the

organized vehicles against wage-labor and capital. Hence, when the

Bakuninists were stressing the economic movement at whatever cost,

surely they could not be accused of acting against the spirit of Marx.

Therefore, the Bakuninists and the Marxists clashed not about matters of

organization, but rather whether it was seizure of political power or

economic struggle that would lead to socialism in the long run. In the

early period of the workers’ organizations this question was undoubtedly

premature; theoretically speaking, as far as it refers to their

teachings about the state, the issue did not imply any fundamental

difference between Marx and Bakunin.

True, antistatism was Bakunin’s most pronounced tendency. It is hardly

necessary to quote him to prove the point. We can see it as a red thread

running through each and every one of his writings and actions. The

state, everything that is referred to as political power, must be

destroyed, both in theory and in practice. As long as there is political

power there will be rulers and subjects, masters and servants,

exploiters and exploited. “Once political power has been destroyed, it

has to be replaced by organizations of the forces of production and

economic institutions.” Each of his arguments was directed against the

claim that the democratic state and its prerequisite, universal

suffrage, could, if it only tried, change the economic and social

predicament of the working class. The state is necessarily a

class-state, under all circumstances, because when it is not the

propertied classes which use it as their tool of exploitation, then it

is those interested in the maintenance of political power: the state

officials, the bureaucracy. Consequently the state is the natural enemy

of every truly revolutionary act, because it trusts only itself and

feels insecure in face of the free movements and spontaneous actions of

the masses as they can turn against the state at any moment. But because

the free collective society can emerge only from the free and

spontaneous action of the masses, any participation in politics is

detrimental, since it enhances the confidence in the state and

contributes to its strength. The state has to be eradicated and society

liberated.

But those who would resort to these tenets to construct an unbridgeable

gap between Bakunin and Marx neglect the fact that while Marx made all

kinds of concessions to the state and to democracy in practice, he was

just as much an enemy of the state in principle and imagined the

political structure of the future society in the same way as Bakunin. In

a hundred places in his works Marx condemns with ruthless irony those

who see in the state the organization of public interest, an impartial,

unprejudiced, and ethical power above class or group interests. The

state is the powerful weapon of the ruling classes by which they

violently ensure their power; as long as there are classes, the state is

a class-state and will remain so. Since the objective of the struggle of

the working class is the elimination of classes, the state must perish

along with class society. In 1847 Marx asked:

Does this mean that after the fall of the old society there will be a

new class domination culminating in a new political power? No.

The condition for the emancipation of the working class is the abolition

of all classes, just as the condition for the emancipation of the third

estate, of the bourgeois order, was the abolition of all estates and all

orders. The working class, in the course of its development, will

substitute for the old civil society an association which will exclude

classes and their antagonism, and there will be no more political power

properly so-called, since political power is precisely the official

expression of antagonism in civil society.

Thirty years later, in his critique of the German party’s Gotha program,

he spoke with sharp irony of state-socialistic tendencies in the

program.

The German workers’ party strives for “the free state”. Free state –

what is this? It is by no means the aim of the workers, who have got rid

of the narrow mentality of humble subjects, to set the state free. In

the German Empire the “state” is almost as “free” as in Russia. (...)

The German workers’ party (...) shows that its socialist ideas are not

even skin-deep (...) it treats the state rather as an independent entity

that possesses its own autonomous intellectual and ethical bases.(...)

But the whole program, for all its democratic clang, is tainted through

and through by the Lassallean sect’s servile belief in the state, or,

what is no better, by a democratic belief in miracles, or rather it is a

compromise between these two kinds of belief in miracles, both equally

remote from socialism.

After all this, it is not surprising that in the face of Bakunin, Marx

came to the defence of anarchy itself, and gave the concept a broadly

socialist interpretation.

All socialists see anarchy as the following programme: once the aim of

the proletarian movement, i.e., abolition of classes is attained, the

power of the State, which serves to keep the great majority of producers

in bondage to a very small exploiter minority, disappears, and, the

functions of government become simple administrative functions.

When compared with these quotations, which we could continue ad

infinitum, the debate between the followers of Bakunin and the followers

of Marx on whether the organization of future society should be

collectivist or communist, pales into insignificance. How insignificant

these distinctions were is clearly demonstrated by the fact that in

those times it was the disciples of Bakunin who referred to themselves

as collectivists and to Marx’s friends as communists, whereas nowadays

it is mostly the anarchists who call themselves communist, and

collectivism is the ideal of the social democrats. In any case, we are

still far from the day when the different principles of organization of

socialist society will be on the agenda of the struggling working class.

The struggle of the working class will continue for a long time to come

within the framework of the present state, and the immediate problem

facing it is not the philosophy of the present or, if you prefer, of the

future state, but whether the power of the state can be used in its

everyday struggle. While this issue could hardly have been brought up at

the time of Marx and Bakunin, because of the embryonic development and

organization of the working class, today, as a result of its strong

representation in parliament, this has become the most burning issue

among those issues which played a role in the contest between the two

leaders of the International.

It seems to be that the best guideline on this issue is to be sought in

a synthesis of the views of Marx and Bakunin. Although Marx believed in

parliamentary action, he was far from enthusiastic about it. He followed

the activity of bourgeois as well as social democratic parliamentary

parties with sarcasm and never ceased reminding the workers that truly

constructive action takes place not in parliament, but in society, in

the economy and in the movement of the masses. He referred to this

involvement with parliaments as parliamentary cretinism, a disorder

which penetrates its unfortunate victims with the solemn conviction that

the whole world, its history and future, are governed and determined by

a majority of votes in that particular representative body which has the

honor to count them among its members, and that all and everything going

on outside the walls of their house-wars, revolutions,

railway-constructing, colonizing of whole new continents, Californian

gold discoveries, Central American canals, Russian armies, and whatever

else may have some little claim to influence upon the destinies of

mankind-is nothing compared to the incommensurable events hinging upon

the important question, whatever it may be, just at that moment

occupying the attention of the honorable House.

Bakunin, on the other hand, argues that even in the most democratic

states such as the United States and Switzerland, while the people may

appear to be omnipotent, self-government by the masses is pure fiction,

and it is a minority who rules. Nevertheless, he comes down in favor of

democracy.

Let no one think that when we criticize democratic government we are

speaking in favor of monarchy. We are firmly convinced that the most

imperfect republic is worth a thousand times more than the most

enlightened monarchy, because in a republic there are at least moments

when the people, although continuously exploited, are not oppressed,

whereas in a monarchy the oppression is continuous too. Moreover, a

republican government educates the masses little by little to gain an

understanding of public affairs, which the monarchy never does. But

though we prefer a republic, it must be admitted and announced that no

matter what the form of government, as long as human society is divided

into classes as a result of the inequality of professions and trades, of

fortune, of culture, and of rights, it shall always remain in the hands

of the few, and a minority will inevitably exploit the majority.

My description of the internal struggles of the International, of the

battles fought with poisoned arrows, in which I attempted to stop short

of evoking the insults exchanged, might be concluded at this point. I

deliberately allowed the two antagonists to speak for themselves more

and more and to let them stand next to each other in order to let

everyone acquire a direct view of them. Nevertheless, as we well know,

this view cannot be complete. My chief endeavor was to show the

similarities between these two leaders, and I had to relegate into the

background other traits which might have underlined the differences.

Yet, in the face of so much intentional or unintentional falsification,

in the face of all the malevolent and fanatical distortions obfuscating

the true history of the International Working Men’s Organization, I

believe I am justified in emphasizing the similarities. From these

everyone can see that both Bakunin and Marx served enthusiastically and

unselfishly the great cause of the working class, albeit with differing

temperaments, with differing estimates of the real and practical

opportunities. Undoubtedly, the differences between them were profound.

But my presentation should make it clear that the distinctions must be

sought not so much in their teachings, but in that each represented a

different type of human being. One was a thinker, the other a doer; one

a scientist, the other a fighter. The conditions of the emerging and

undifferentiated workers’ organizations particularly demanded the unity

of theory and practice. Under these circumstances two such different

characters, yet equally born leaders, were bound to clash: their

personalities made it impossible for them to express the needs of the

parturient movement of the working class in the same terms, though they

were certainly its most outstanding representatives.

From the passages quoted it should be obvious that the unbridgeable gap

which certain social democrats perceive between anarchism and socialism

exists only as a figment of their imagination, not in reality. Even less

is this gap to be found in the writings of Marx and Bakunin, although

they were cited most often by the disciples of each tendency. Anarchism

is one species of socialism, as is social democracy itself. Socialism

and social democracy are by no means identical. The essence of socialism

is the common ownership of the means of production and the achievement

of this community through the struggle of the organized forces of the

working class. All the anarchist leaders agree with this, except for a

few individualistic anarchists who have never found roots among the

workers. And this is all that matters. Everything else is but a means to

an end, and not the end in itself. It cannot be denied that the

advocates of revolutionary action have at least as much right to refer

to Marx for the justification of the means of the fanatics of

parliamentarianism and peaceful transformation. It is not the advocates

of revolutionary action who are attempting to free them-selves from the

heritage of Marx today, but rather those who advocate parliamentary

action. And those whom the advocates of parliamentary action would so

lightly label anarchists are increasingly sounding off the old slogan:

back to Marx!

Those who continue to feel, even after the death of the two leaders,

that they should fight with poisoned pens against the memory of these

men as well as against their heirs and disciples, might like to read and

assimilate what may have been Bakunin’s last pronouncement before his

death: “Try to introduce into your contacts with new people with whom

you want to establish closer relationships as much justice, sincerity,

and kindness as your nature allows. You must understand that it is not

possible to construct anything live and solid on Jesuitic mischief, that

the success of revolutionary activity must not reside in base and low

passions, and that no revolution will triumph without higher ideals. It

is in this direction and in this sense that I sincerely bid you

success.”