💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › c-l-james-anarchism-and-malthus.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 23:12:56. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

⬅️ Previous capture (2023-01-29)

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism and Malthus
Author: C. L. James
Date: 1910
Language: en
Topics: economics, population, progress, William Godwin
Source: Retrieved on 31 August 2010 from http://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t/text/pageviewer-idx?c=labadie&cc=labadie&idno=2917581
Notes: Mother Earth Publishing Association210 East 13th Street, New York

C. L. James

Anarchism and Malthus

John Stuart Mill, who knew little about the difference between Anarchism

and Socialism, but sympathized with both, as far as he understood them,

has left on record the sentiment that the Malthusian theory, long

considered the fatal objection to Socialism, might prove the strongest

argument in its favor. Being much of that opinion myself, I have long

desired Malthus, a writer of whom everybody talks and whom nobody reads,

to be more generally understood. His life and character strike me as

very irrelevant to his reasonings; but since prejudice always insists on

getting them in, and generally tells lies about them, here is the truth.

Daniel Malthus was the friend and executor of Rousseau. It need not be

said, he was a radical. He was also an author to whom some literary

merit is attributed; but he always wrote anonymously. His social grade

was that of an English “gentleman,” living on an income derived from

some sort of stock. That he was pretty rich, and that he met with

financial reverses, may be inferred from the facts that he passed

through the University of Cambridge as a student in the most expensive

class; but his son, Thomas Robert Malthus, the economist, was sent there

on a cheaper plan; at which time we also find that the family, though

increased, had moved into a smaller house than that where he was born.

Here, during the winter of 1797, the father and son had some arguments

about the merits of Political Justice, a book recently published by

William Godwin (husband of Mary Wollstonecraft, and father-in-law of

Percy Bysshe Shelley). Godwin was an Anarchist of that early

unscientific type which preceded Marx and Proudhon. Like his French

contemporary, Condorcet, he vaguely enertained those ideas to which

Saint Simon about twenty-four years later, gave precision. That

prodigious increase of wealth-producing arts which marked the last

quarter of the eighteenth century was transforming military into

industrial organization. The trades of the soldier, the legislator, the

judge, the jailer, the sovereign, and the hangman, would soon be

discarded as useless by a generation whom commerce was bringing to

understand human solidarity. Commerce itself, by its effect in

cheapening the means of life, would be obliged to make way for

Communism. The Golden Age, the Paradisiacal State, was not only before,

instead of behind us — it was at the door. The courageous optimism which

could think so whein the greatest of popular revolutions was, after

fearful bloodshed, in the act of transformation into a conquering

military despotism, does credit to Godwin’s heart, and his imagination;

and the elder Malthus was delighted. But the younger pointed out

difficulties. In Godwin’s Utopia, life was to be maintained so easily

that the “struggle for existence” (a phrase used by Malthus) would have

ceased; and population, naturally, would increase fast. For things had

by no means come to that in the United States, where the settlers were

still killing Indians and working negro slaves; where they had fought

seven years against a tax, and were in the act of domestic rebellion for

cheap whiskey. Yet even in the United States living was so easy, that

population, aside from immigration, doubled every twenty-five years. No

such rate of increase could possibly continue. As this is a point on

which ignorant critics of Malthus continually blunder, we will try to

get it clear. The ignorant critics speak about destructive effects of

this increase as if these were equally remote with the earth’s falling

into the sun, or the extinction of the sun itself. But anyone who can

use a table of logarithms may convince himself in five minutes that the

progeny of one Adam and Eve, doubling every twenty-five years, would

pack like oranges in a box, not after geologic aeons, but in a few

centuries. Of course no such result is possible. Yet it would evidently

happen but that something hinders. What does? Increase of the

death-rate. This comes in various forms, all horrible to contemplate.

Densely peopled countries, India, China, Egypt, Ireland, are mostly very

liable to famine. Those happier in this respect have had dire experience

that crowding and pestilence go together. Even where these destroying

angels spare to smite for the sins of the people, the mortality of

cities, notwithstanding all their opulence and knowledge, is invariably

higher than that of the poorer, ruder country. But above all other

things, war has been not only a check on over-population, but a proof

that even very ignorant people know a check is needed. That they may not

starve, cannibals fight and eat each other. Shepherds, indeed, cannot

starve while their flocks are fed; for the flocks increase faster than

the men.[1] But the flocks must have food as well as the men; and,

because they increase faster, they reach the limit beyond which they

cannot be supported, sooner. Then the shepherd-peoples also resort to

war. They sweep across three continents under the black banner of

Mahomet, or, perhaps, they are defeated, and almost annihilated, in a

battle like that of Aqua Sextiae, by the richer and more civilized

neighbors whose territories they have invaded. Either way, the problem

of over-population is solved for some time, so far as they are concerned

with it. In agricultural countries, war is less popular. But when a

government able to suppress it through a wide region arises, famine

takes its place, unless the birth-rate be reduced at the same time. A

great object-lesson of the kind had recently been seen in India. The

first of her recorded famines on a large scale occurred under

Aurungzebe, — the first sovereign who really ruled all India. And

observe, this could be attributed to nothing but cessation of war,

which, when famine threatened, had previously offered a more hopeful way

of dying; for, except cessation of war, there had been no important

change in the customs of India to account for so terrible a change in

the results. The alternative of war or famine is likewise so generally

understood that, though backward agricultural peoples are less

pugnacious than the cattle-breeders, war was everywhere, always, the

principal fact in their history, till it ended, as war normally does, in

extensive conquests like those of the Great Moguls. In the highest state

of civilization, where there are important manufactures and extensive

commerce, there is less war than anywhere else. But even so typically

modern a country as England had been at war fifty years in the preceding

hundred, and if we clear our minds of cant about “rights,”

“international law,” “the balance of power,” and other diplomatic

flimflam, we shall find that the true object of a modern war is a

commercial advantage, that nations get ready to fight for a commercial

advantage when the pressure of increasing population makes the advantage

sufficiently necessary, that increase of the population is the

fundamental cause of war, — “teterrima causa belli” — as it always was.

Now, Mr. Godwin is witness that war is the cause of government, slavery,

serfdom, laws, punishments, unequal distribution of wealth. If,

therefore, his Utopia, which is to banish all such things, were

established, it could not last, and we should soon have them all back,

unless a way be found of checking propagation. But, in truth, too much

is conceded in supposing his Utopia established at all. Since men were

cannibals, some slow approaches to it have, indeed, been made. The

tortoise of industry may be tiring out the hares of lust and plunder;

but Mr. Godwin himself shows us that they are a long way ahead of her

still; and to imagine them laid asleep by his Arcadian rhetoric is to

show ignorance of human nature. All which led Malthus Jr. to another

series of reflections. What he called Positive Checks on population —

those which increase the death-rate-are inevitable, if propagation goes

on at American speed, which, under Utopian conditions, it should

surpass. But, generally speaking, it does not go on so fast. There are,

then, Checks on population, of a different sort — Preventive — those

which diminish the birth-rate. It is evident that there are many checks

of this kind — among them vicious practices. But on these, Malthus, a

clergyman, had no mercy. He classed them as Positive Checks, — appearing

to hold, rather dogmatically, that they restrain increase as much by

raising the death-rate as by lowering the birth-rate; nor did he

withhold this censure from the least injurious among them, such as those

afterwards proposed by the Malthusian Socialist, Robert Owen.[2] The

only check which Malthus would admit to be truly Preventive, or

Prudential, is continence. This check is, certainly, far from

inefficacious. The lowest savages, who graze like apes, know, indeed,

nothing about it. But in the stage of hunting nomadism, a young man is

not allowed to marry till the cruel rites of barbarian confirmation have

proved him fit for his father’s trade of war. If he cannot pass, he is

good for nothing but a priest; and where priests do not fight (as

sometimes they do) the general rule is that they are celibates. Among

cattleraising nomads, polygamy prevails; and men who are not smart

enough to acquire stock can get no wives. In the agricultural state, and

still more the commercial, it is mere commonplace that to marry without

the means of supporting a family is imprudent. Thus, from the lowest

conditions of man to the highest, we find celibacy increasing uniformly

with civilization, except as superstition sometimes intervenes to cause

a factitious increase, which, we may suspect of being rather apparent

than real. In that increasing celibacy whose causes are economic, much,

no doubt, is loose; but much is genuine. It requires some force of

character, some foresight, some judgment, to do what Jacob did for

Rachel. Yet this is what many young men do in all social states, from

the nomadic shepherd’s upwards, but increasingly. If the qualities they

show be among those which make success in the battle of life, as they

very clearly are, has not Godwin’s materialistic philosophy confounded

effect with cause? Is it not this improvement of habits which has made

increase in wealth and knowledge? If the latter fails, as we see it has

so far failed, to “substitute the industrial régime for the military,”

is not that because the improvement of habits is by no means as general

as are some of its superficial effects? A beggar may be made more

comfortable in London than a king in Darkest Africa; but there is no

making- a fool anything else than a fool, or saving him from being

pushed to the worst place among competitors wherever he may happen to

live.

From these discussions sprang the famous essay of Malthus which was

published in 1798. The prodigious sensation which it immediately

produced caused five editions to follow during the author’s life. The

second, and most important, appeared in 1803. This book, with

expansions, revisions, replies to critics, — in short, the subject of

this book, variously handled — is coextensive with Maithus’ literary

activity. (He had, indeed, written an earlier pamphlet called The

Crisis, in defense of Pitt’s administration; but, by his father’s

advice, he kept it out of print.) The first edition of the Essay

described its topic as the Principle of Population viewed with relation

to, the Future Improvement of Mankind. The motive of a critique on

Godwin’s Political Justice was still in Malthus’ mind. He had also

another reason for introducing his study in this way. Professing to be a

Christian, and having recently taken holy orders, he knew well enough

that he would be attacked on the ground of impugning the Divine

goodness; and that no one would be so savage as his fellow-priests for

this and other reasons. He, therefore, must have his theory about the

future improvement of mankind, which, if not so rose-colored as

Godwin’s, must be sufficient for the pious purpose of vindicating the

ways of God to man. Malthus professes, accordingly, to desire the future

improvement of mankind as much as Godwin can desire it. The only

question between them is about practicable. means. Having argued as

above that Godwin’s Utopia, if set up, would fall; and, moreover, that

it could not be set up, without a radical change in regard to an

important relation which Godwin had forgotten to mention; Maithus

proceeds to contend that his law of population, though it may seem hard

to rebellious flesh, is in truth, the law of human progress from the

brute state of the lowest savage upwards. As distinctly as his most

illustrious pupil, Darwin, does Malthus perceive that “the struggle for

existence” is what makes us progressively better fitted to exist. It is

also what makes us more worthy. Terrible as have been the struggles, it

is to them we owe it that we are not picking worms out of rotten trees,

or ranging the sea-shore for carrion. It is because our ancestors were

cannibals that they have, everywhere except in the most inaccessible

jungles and islands, exterminated those weaker brothers of theirs who

could be content with wild fruits or dead fish. That, as here, so at

every later step in the struggle, whether between nations or

individuals, the world has been made better by the success of the

strongest, bravest, and shrewdest, can scarcely, indeed, be disputed,

but it will not be adequately understood without our realizing that the

improvement has been moral, no less than physical and intellectual. On a

general view, it seems evident enough that the vices — sloth, cowardice,

conceit, spite, envy, vanity, ill-temper, gluttony, lasciviousness, —

are decided handicaps in the struggle, which must be, and are, wearing

down, through the ill-success of those in whom they principally prevail.

Of two only — avarice and falsehood — can it be pretended that they help

anyone to outdo competitors. But too much is allowed in granting that

they generally do. They may help an individual on a pinch. But compare

nations, classes, sects, parties, whose lives are longer than those of

individuals — nay, compare, not two but many, individuals — and it will

be clear enough that neither piggishness nor rascality pays; that

cunning, though an advantage in itself, is no such advantage as a

reputation for veracity; that though generosity is often imprudent, it

is not prudent to lack generosity. And thus the cynical saying that

prudence is the only virtue God rewards, may be transfigured into this

reverent sentiment that all the virtues can be deduced from the premises

of one who will grant a sure reward to even prudence. Thus the actual

causes of past improvement guide us to the process of future. The

general direction is that in which Godwin can see no obstacles. War,

slavery, punishments, inequalities of fortune and station, and the

passions which cause them, are very bad things, to be avoided by every

man, for himself, no less than for the sake of humanity. The man who

will not fight if he can help it, is wiser than the bully. But it does

not do to forget that the best-tempered men will fight for life and

those things without which life is worthless; that it is the direction

of advantage in such necessary strife which has displaced those who

thought fighting a sufficient end by those who very reluctantly adopt it

as a means; that the one great error, of imprudence in giving life

before providing material to support life, will continue, as long as

committed, to make the struggle for existence inevitable. In the second

edition of the Essay, all this elaborate Theodice disappears.[3] So do

many rhetorical passages, chief among them the famous one about

“Nature’s mighty feast,” which all the world quotes, and generally

garbles. There was a reason for this change. Malthus was now a famous

man. Attacks on his doctrines from the side of superstition had come, of

course; but they did not amount to as much as he expected; and he had

ceased to care for them.[4] By Socialists, if the term at this early

date be proper, his work had been rather well received than otherwise —

Godwin particularly using expressions which implied that he had learned

by it; as, from his life and associations we should infer, he easily

might. The day when demolishing Malthus appeared a part of every

radical’s appointed task, did not come till Ricardo (died 1823) had

drawn certain inferences from the theory of Malthus, about which more

anon. Of more interest to Malthus’ scientific mind were criticisms on

statistical and other positive grounds. He determined, therefore, in

revising his Essay, to keep strictly within facts. Even the title was

altered accordingly. His subject is declared to be, not the future

improvement, but the past history and present prospects of mankind. In

the substance of his reasoning there was one modification which his

opponents naturally worked for all it was worth. In the edition of 1798

he had described the positive checks on population as “Vice and Misery,”

the preventive as based upon “the fear of them.” A criticism, in which

he admitted force, was that he had said nothing about hope. Ambition,

the desire of improving one’s condition, is certainly a chief cause of

continence, and this is something more than fear of vice and misery for

oneself or his posterity. Acknowledging this, the tone of theorizing is

certainly more optimistic than before. This change in Malthus’ language,

rather than his meaning, together with the confession that he should

have been more explicit at first, is the basis of the criticism often

made by Coleridge and others, that the theory is a truism from which

nothing can be inferred. That it is no truism, but an extremely

complicated equation, may certainly be inferred from the facility with

which critics misunderstand it, the multiplicity of ways in which they

manage to do that, and the oft-recurring argument ad verecundum — it is

very strange that Menu, Confucius, Moses, Solon, Cato, even the ascetic

Roman Catholic publicists, should have held up increasing the species as

a sacred duty; and that discovering the direful results of doing so

should have been reserved for Malthus![5] Of the four subsequent

editions, nothing need be said here, except that they become

progressively more statistical, comprehensive, and bald, until even

friendly critics thought he would have been clearer for taking less

pains to be clear.

Amidst all these changes, which quite amount to making the book a new

one, there is no wavering about the “main principle,” as Malthus termed

it. The “main principle,” or Malthusian Theory, properly so-called, may

be boiled down to this, that increase of the Positive Check (premature

deaths) can be averted only by increase of the Prudential Check (fewer

births). Its arithmetical self-evidence needs no further exposition, if

the American figures, on which it was founded, be correct. In this

respect it is characteristic of the author. Malthus was not a very

consecutive thinker or lucid writer, though in his youth he was a florid

one; but figures were his strong point (he came out of Cambridge with

the high mathematical rank of Ninth Wrangler). His description of human

increase in America as “geometrical” and increase of food as

“arithmetical” has been pronounced affectedly technical by one of his

few really competent reviewers (Mill); but it is not without

justification. Population, doubling every twenty-five years, does not

increase in a very rapid geometric ratio, like the pennies paid for

nails in the problem of the horse’s shoes. Let such a population live,

as long as it can, on flocks and herds, grain, commissions in exchange,

or what you will; all, except perhaps the last, also increase in a

geometric ratio, and faster than men, thus making their increase at the

old rate practicable — true; while there is vacant land to be exploited;

but how long will that be? The increase of land in pasture; of grain,

under the intensest culture; of commerce, while the continents are being

developed, is not, for want of land, at a geometrical rate — we put it

high in supposing it arithmetical, thus: —

Evidently, too, the principle is highly important. Not to mention “the

future improvement of mankind,” if their “present prospect” be that

forbearance from unchecked indulgence in an appetite they share with

brutes is the only alternative from the double agony of unwelcome births

and premature deaths: if “their past history” have for its key-note

excessive births, necessitating premature deaths, by sacrifice to

Moloch, as in Syria; legal infanticide, as at Rome; illicit infanticide,

as in China;[6] abortion; famine; pestilence; war; the miseries and

disgraces of slavery, which, in all its forms, is the result of war;

between which propositions the first is mathematically demonstrable, and

the other historically notorious; then recalcitration against the moral

is the mark of a brute; the laws which still do in some measure

encourage masculine sensuality, feminine dependence, and their hideous

consequences, are the brutal laws of barbarians, who wanted food for

powder because, like other men, they sought to gratify their desires

with the least exertion, and because plunder is, in the barbarous state,

the easiest way to live; nor can the voluble individual who, in our

time, praises their polity, escape being deemed a brute on any ground

but the contemptuous one that he is only an ignorant sensationalist.

Most assuredly, the whimper that Malthus attributes “vice and misery to

a natural instinct with which are linked the purest and sweetest

affections,” deserves no sympathy from one whose estimate of women’s

rights and duties is at all above the Rooseveltian standard.

Men, however, are not easily convinced of what they do not wish to

believe. The windows of heaven have rained refutations upon Malthus for,

now, a hundred and ten years. That the refutations do not refute is

shown by the fact that they continue to rain. But though the shower

gives no sign of slackening, originality in making the missiles was

exhausted long ago. The modern student not only keeps his refutations of

Malthus on the same shelf with his reconciliations of Genesis and

geology, but knows, as soon as he looks into one, on what part of the

shelf to put it.

Among refuters of Malthus we have specified two kinds, those who say the

theory is a truism, and those who arraign it on some such a priori

ground as impiety; being “dangerous to morals”; being pessimistic; being

a stock argument of Tories and the privileged classes, — concerning

which we shall say more.[7] A third class of refuters, probably as

numerous as the rest put together, are the eclectics, who reproduce all

the arguments of previous anti-Malthusians, without perceiving that they

contradict each other. There are also many who attempt a reductio ad

absurdum, and succeed triumphantly — in making themselves absurd. Such

are those who accuse Malthus of representing vice and misery as rather

good things than otherwise; of supposing we are in danger of an actual

squeeze (!) of recommending infanticide, against which we have seen that

he discovered a new argument; of being refuted by all the wisdom of

antiquity. These are not always easy to distinguish from the a priori

critics; but there is this important difference that Messrs. a priori

fairly understand what Malthus meant, while the reducer to absurdity

always misunderstands him grossly. A common case, which also illustrates

the complexity of his alleged truism and the ease with which it can be

misunderstood, is that of the man who asks for proof that population

does increase, and reminds us of fishers washing their nets upon the

rock of Tyre, or jackals howling among the ruins of Babylon. Now,

Malthus never said that population on the whole did increase — not that

I doubt it, but I might, without contradicting Malthus. He said that

there was a powerful human instinct which tends to increase population;

and therefore (which is an important point) that it must increase —

unless the Positive Check or the Prudential hinders. But he was not so

ignorant of what either can do as to be unaware that celibacy like that

of the Roman Empire, especially after it became Christian, or a

visitation like the Black Death, may diminish population very fast.

The theory of Malthus has, a good long while ago, converted all writers

worthy to be called economists, all biologists, and all historians. Its

first victories were among those emphatically to be designated as the

men of his own time. The great party which had ruled England without

intermission from 1715 to 1760, was breaking in the vortex of the French

Revolution. Those among the Old Whigs who followed Burke and Pitt soon

came to be indistinguishable from the Tories, whose ashes were warmed

into life by a sympathetic reign and by the extinction of their evil

genius, the exiled House of Stuart. Malthus’ place as a politician was

among the New Whigs, whose importance began when the Napoleonic wars

were over — with those who abolished slavery; repealed the Corn Laws;

put an end to imprisonment for debt; took away the political

disabilities of Jews, Catholics, and Dissenters; reformed the

representative system; swept away the Draconian penal code; established

the policy of peace. He deserves to be called a Liberal, because he was

in favor of everything good which was ripe enough to be done during his

own literary period; from the Peace of Amiens, in 1802, to the Reform

Bill, thirty years later, and shortly before his death. But his

celebrity, of course, is mainly in connection with political economy;

his importance is known to ordinary readers chiefly on this account,

that political economy was the especial field of England during the

nineteenth century. The Manchester School, till lately dominant, looks

to Malthus as its second founder; and, since schisms have arisen in that

school, it is to the specific views of Malthus that there has been a

reversion, from those of the long-idolized Ricardo.

David Ricardo, supposed, till Mill openly seceded from among his pupils,

to have placed political economy on a basis of all-comprehensive

demonstration, was six years younger than Malthus, who long outlived

him. They were intimate friends, their disputes were always in perfect

good temper; and since Ricardo continued to be read, but Malthus did

not, very few people, until lately, knew how much they differed. It is

from Malthus’ supposed law of population that Ricardo deduced his famous

law of rent, which George has made familiar to everybody, and on which

Marx founded his “scientific Socialism.” Population increases beyond the

capacity of land, in use, to support it; other land, therefore, must be

taken up; since men seek to gratify their desires with the least

exertion, the best land will be improved first; between its yield and

that of the inferior land intervenes a constantly increasing margin of

rent, which is what makes the difference between rich and poor. It

reduces wages to the minimum obtainable from the poorest land (the Iron

Law of Wages, Lasalle called this). Yet worse remains. Since cultivation

extends, this minimum is not a stationary but a diminishing quantity.

True, the cost of living is diminished, and the laborer’s real wages do

not, therefore, fall as fast as the nominal, but they do fall, for those

commodities the laborer chiefly wants are those most directly derived

from the soil; and they are not being cheapened, but the contrary.[8]

Ricardo is thus the true founder of “the Dismal Science.” The extreme

pessimism and determinism of his views, which have been compared to

those of Calvin, did not prevent their “taking” with English

capitalists, who, during the Corn Law battle, found in them a weapon

against English landlords. But Ricardo also furnished Socialism with a

weapon against both. Except the Anarchists, all Socialists who make any

pretensions to scientific economic reasoning, begin with Ricardo. Their

common burden is that government must, and, when these things become

better understood, a democratic government certainly will, confiscate

rent for the common good, and, they usually add, assume control of

business. How their idol, the government, will, after all, manage to

keep people from finding it harder to live as the Law of Diminishing

Returns keeps shortening the result of their labor, these reformers do

not, indeed, make quite as clear as could be wished. But here is where

their prejudice against Malthus began. His name became associated,

though Ricardo’s rather should be, with the Law of Diminishing Returns.

It is, therefore, a fact of extreme interest that Malthus decidedly

rejected Ricardo’s improvements on his system. The difference between

Anarchism and Socialism, as we usually understand the latter term, is

the difference between Malthus and Ricardo. Malthus, we remember, had

never said that population necessarily increases. Under the existing

conditions, he believed population to be limited by the willingness of

capitalists to employ labor; nor is there much doubt that this is

substantially correct; though the “wage-fund doctrine” of Senior,

McCulloch, and other Ricardians,[9] overdoes it. Now Malthus observed,

nor could Ricardo deny,[10] that capital will not take up waste land

unless it can get from such land as much as from those institutions

which borrow and lend money for speculative enterprises. Except, then,

as improved methods bring up the profit on waste land to the current

rate of interest, there will be no rise of rent. Experimental

cultivation by government, philanthropists, theorists, or communists,

produces no such effect: — it must be business cultivation yielding

profit and also wages up to rate. For one of Malthus’ most striking

doctrines, in pronounced contradiction to Ricardo and all his followers,

is that real wages never fall. Malthus studied history and society,

which Ricardo, in his theorizing a mere formal logician and

mathematician, did not. Ricardo, then, might vaguely think (for here, as

often, he is not clear) that capital indemnifies itself for rent by

cutting wages; but Malthus knew how tenacious labor is of every

advantage it has gained in the war with parasites. He believed such

gains to be continuous. He had a theory of their origin, which, if

rather empirical, is sufficiently comprehensive, and, as usual, savors

very much of Darwin.

What, with Fate-like persistency, has raised real wages since they

consisted in the daily find of toads or lizards, which may take up all a

Digger Indian’s time, is, in Malthus’ language, “accidents.” Some of

these accidents were blessings very terribly disguised. One of the most

important was the Black Death, which killed serfdom throughout the

greater part of Europe, by reducing the number of laborers, and exciting

such competition for their services that they could no longer be kept

from migrating in search of high wages. Such “accidents” would do the

laborer no permanent good, if he were quite the shiftless being which

some bourgeois writers represent him. But, though generally ignorant and

stupid, he has certain “strong instincts and plain rules,” which serve

his turn. He will not work for less (real) wages than he is used to

getting. Even down to the state of chattel slavery we can see this.

Coolies may work for rice gruel; but it would never do not to make negro

slaves more comfortable than many white men are. The “standard of

comfort” among laborers, raised, from time to time, by “fortunate

accidents,” and kept from falling by strikes, peasant insurrections,

increase of continence, in short by the laborer’s determination to keep

it up at whatever hazard, has been the guarantee of progress; for it is

these struggles which increase knowledge.

Examples of the “accidents” are numerous. The breaking up of the Roman

Empire killed chattel slavery, which requires extradition not to be

obtained under the loose rule of the Barbarians. The restoration of

slavery, though favored by circumstances in the colonies, had been

stoutly withstood, and, in Malthus’ time, was evidently failing. The

discovery of America, by relieving pressure in Europe, raised the

standard of comfort there; and legalization of Trades’ Unions is

evidence that it will not fall. The French Revolution made the peasants

landowners, and the restored Bourbon dared not rob them; etc. Evidently,

Malthus’ economy is not a dismal science. Believing a high standard of

comfort the condition of social improvement, he was no prophet of

“parsimony.” He encouraged, indeed, saving by retrenchment of expenses

upon the lower appetites; but with a view to enjoyment, not mere

money-making. The English proletaire who denies himself gin, if at all,

that he may have good clothes, a furnished house, a lease, a library, is

wiser than the French peasant who lives on black bread that he may buy

more land. Malthus went further than perhaps any economist reckoned

“orthodox” in recognition of the great truth that exchange is the chief

source of riches and that starving to get ahead of each other, like the

Coolies and the Jews in many places, makes all the people absolutely

poor whomever it makes relatively rich. Thus his view of “progress and

poverty” differed from Ricardo’s, it has been said, as Arminianism from

Calvinism. Malthus refers everything to the individual, Ricardo to

certain institutions, such as land ownership, which he took for granted.

In the minds of Socialists, Ricardo’s principles tend to passive

reliance on the Omnipotent Goodness of the State, those of Malthus to

repudiation of the State, or Anarchism.

Ricardo’s positive dogmatism, plausible syllogizing, and coherent style,

gave his writings an advantage over those of Malthus. As concerns

conservatism they were equal, or rather Ricardo’s superabundant

acknowledgment of indebtedness to Malthus made the latter appear to the

generation which did not read him more conservative than the former

really was.[11]

The Seniors, McCullochs, Benthams, Macaulays, Mills, Leckys, Martineaus,

Marcets, and other orthodox exponents of Ricardo, contemporary with the

Socialistic upheavals and panics between 1848 and 1871, but little aware

to what purposes Marx and Proudhon were turning their instructor,

deduced from Ricardo, whom they represented as the greater pupil of

Malthus, notwithstanding the real difference, that labor depended for

support on the wage-fund; that to lessen the wage-fund by frightening

capital was to do laborers the worst of injuries; that the admitted

harshness of the social state was due principally to a “natural

monopoly” which government did not make and could not destroy; that

artificial monopolies were, indeed, wrong and pernicious, for which

reason a liberal government was preferable to a monarchy or oligarchy;

but Anarchy, of course, would be the worst of anything, and Socialistic

interference with the natural laws of production fostered Anarchy by

promising impossibilities and causing disappointment; for which reason

authority should be strictly upheld and Utopianism discouraged; above

all that the only real remedies were parsimony and continence (a queer

jumble, which shows how little these public instructors themselves

understood the true relation of Malthusian economy to Ricardian). There

was just enough truth in all this to be timely for conservative

purposes. The fact, in direct contradiction to what Macaulay often says

on the subject, is that great expropriations, like those of the monks by

Henry VIII., of the Church and the nobles during the French Revolution,

of the slave owners during our Civil War, have always, in the long run,

conferred great benefits on the poor; but that, at first, they always

cause increased hardship to the poor, not because there is any such

thing as a wage-fund which supports productive laborers, but because a

large part of the poor are unproductive laborers, whom panic among the

rich at once deprives of their jobs, while time is required for the

productive class to gain anything by fall of an unproductive: which

immediate consequences of insecurity are so well known to the often

unemployed proletaire that he is afraid of attempts at expropriation,

and will not promote them unless his oppressors have first driven him to

the wall. The unpopularity of Socialism, for there can be no doubt that

on the whole it is unpopular, is due to this fear, addressed on two

sides; by the conservative Ricardians, as stated; by the Ricardian

Socialists, like Engel and Lassalle, because they talked of legislative

expropriation. Amidst the fulminations of Ricardian orthodoxy the few

critics who pointed out (like Richard Jones) that Ricardo’s best-known

theories are arbitrarily deductive, and bear no clear relation to

visible facts,[12] were dinned and flashed away, with the inevitable

valediction that “they had failed to understand Ricardo.” But the

cocksureness of the Epigoni, as economists of this period have been

called, did not quite go the length of imputing ignorance to John Stuart

Mill. If there was anything he did not know, it was what they knew still

less. The reaction began, accordingly, when he, originally, like his

father, a Ricardian, decidedly rebelled. The Malthusian direction of

this movement has been very inadequately acknowledged. The Optimistic

school of Carey and Bastiat builds on Malthus’ law that real wages never

fall. The Historical Economist, now the most influential among those

reckoned orthodox, follows the line of investigation which Malthus laid

down, but to which he could not hold Ricardo. On the Socialistic side of

the fence, Ricardianism is sure to age in proportion as it does on the

other. How far the new Socialistic economy of Anarchism is indebted to

Malthus, we have yet to see. But the affinities of American and Russian

Anarchism with his thought are as clear as those of Marx and Proudhon

with Ricardo’s.

Though Malthus’ writings were neglected during the fifty years or so of

Ricardo’s pontificate, his name lived. As the demonstrator of a

principle evidently revolutionary, therefore of transcendent importance,

not only to Economy, but Biology, History, Ethics, and Religion, he was

known, by reputation, to students of all these subjects. For want of

reading him, they often misunderstood, but they had tolerably clear his

“main principle,” that unrestricted propagation means a high death-rate,

involving a “struggle for existence,” which hitherto has been the

determinator of progress: though “moral restraint” on propagation would

be better.

The anatomical and physiological affinities of higher animal and vegetal

types with lower had, before Malthus’ time, suggested to Buffon,

Monboddo, and a few others, the idea that species arise by Evolution.

But their theories on the subject were mere guesses, which commanded

little attention from the scientific world. The glory of placing organic

development on the positive basis of Heredity, Natural Selection, and

Sexual Selection, belongs to Darwin. The fact that species do arise by

evolution has been experimentally demonstrated by Haeckel; and the world

no longer contains a naturalist who disputes it; though there continues

to be controversy upon such minor points as whether post-natal

variations are hereditary.[13]

History, by right the greatest among sciences, since it supplies

material for all which require the use of records, was in a wholly

empirical condition before the epochmaking work of Buckle: — for the

so-called philosophic history of an earlier time did not, as Macaulay

remarked, rise above the level of essay-writing on the philosophy of

history. Fragmentary and in some matters of detail incorrect as Buckle’s

writings are, they forever establish the method, which is entirely

Malthusian. That social progress depends on substitution of Preventive

for Positive Checks on population; which, in turn, depends on

substitution as incentives to action, of more varied desires for the

simple animal appetites of food and sex, and this again on leisure, in

which such desires germinate; that ignorance, and its most legitimate

offspring, superstition, are the great standing obstacles to this happy

change, operating to dull the new desires and content men with their

barbarous ancestors’ ways; these propositions, indeed, involve somewhat

more than the “main principle” of Malthus; but they are all among his

authentic statements, not the innovations of Ricardo and others. Since

Buckle’s time, they have constituted the great working hypothesis by

which all historic phenomena have been elucidated.[14] Ethics, previous

to that evolutionary philosophy in which Malthus was the first wise

master-builder, presented a ruinous chaos, in which the blind forces of

tyranny and superstition essentially hostile to each other but foes to

knowledge, met in refluent eddies like infernal rivers. Private

experience had taught men that sensual and other excesses are haunted by

Remorse. Superstition, seeking to escape this phantom, but without a

guide, has always tended to Asceticism. Even those forms which we call

immoral — the glorification by some religions of prostitution and still

more nauseous vice, of mutilation, drunkenness, human sacrifice, war,

appealed, as is well known among comparative students of human error,

not to the lusts of the flesh themselves, but that despair and rage

which springs from deception by these tempters — it was really ascetic

self-torture which was glorified, and the “consecrated” persons whose

houses Hezekiah took away from the Temple were holy because they served

the appetites of others in ways not agreeable to themselves. On the

other hand, governments, military institutions, designed to serve the

purposes of man’s most violent passions, as rapacity, lust, and

vengeance, invariably encouraged sensuality to breed fighters, invested

war with the glamour of heroism, and cultivated that view of commerce

which makes exchange a disguised robbery. Hence the muddled and

inconsistent ideas of morality given us by two sets of teachers thus

radically opposed, but of whom one was in a measure coerced or bribed by

the other. Except for naturally arising conflicts among themselves,

their only use of logic has been to invent reasons why the king has a

right to govern wrong, why wives should obey their husbands, how it can

be an Englishman’s duty to kill a Frenchman, and equally the Frenchman’s

to kill him.[15] Malthus taught even governments that hungry and

dependent numbers are a source of weakness, not strength.[16] His name

is so familiar that Race Suicide speeches and bills to put a tax on

celibacy have none but humorous effect. It was he who convinced the

rulers that, much as they feared educating the ruled, they had no

choice. Though the “Mercantile” economy, and its practical corollary,

Protection, received their fatal wound from Adam Smith, the root whence

they spring remains in his Wealth of Nations; and the stump-puller

destined to eradicate it was constructed by Malthus. The root is the

doctrine that parsimony enriches. The stump-puller is the Malthusian

proof that it can enrich only individuals, and this only on condition of

having neighbors less parsimonious than themselves — that exchange is

what principally causes increase of wealth; that if a people are all

parsimonious, like the “Jewtown” Hebrews, they must be poor. But the

ultimate services of Malthus to ethics were more radical than this. The

advice of Bacon to treat ethics as an inductive science — to ascertain,

by observation and experiment, what effects are actually produced on

character by heredity, education, example, society, solitude, religious

belief, the civil law, by the indulgence of particular habits, the

reading of particular books, the following of particular trades, — a

sort of knowledge whence we might expect to learn something about how

undesired propensities can be corrected and others cultivated — had been

neglected for three centuries while the doctors continued to dispute as

usual about whether Revelation, Moral Sense, or Expediency furnished the

readiest method of making out perfect the foolish institutions of their

respective countries — all this, chiefly, because they lacked a guide

into the better way. The first height on which the light of positive

discovery began to shine was the effect upon morals of Heredity. The

point of radiation was the Darwinian Theory, and the Darwinian Theory,

in the express words of its originator, only applies Malthus’ doctrine

to the whole animal and vegetable kingdom.

In religious speculation, we have already seen what the original

Theodice of Malthus was. It is the one which has become fashionable.

That it is much more simple, affecting, and sublime, than the grotesque

myths which preceded it, has become commonplace. But of more importance

is the fact that it dissipates the most odious and most unfailing trait

of merely subjective piety — its intolerance. Sin is always stupidity:

it is, therefore, a sin (an injustice) in the sinner who counts himself

partially reformed to be angry with the thicker-headed fellow-sinner who

is not reformed at all: and thus, too, sin vindicates its character as

stupidity; for being angry with sinners is not at all the right way

either to reform them or to prevent others from following their example.

Thus far-reaching has been the influence of Malthus. Expounding it

should serve to illustrate the absurdity of attempting his refutation by

rehashing arguments all of which have long been commonplace. A fortress

like Gibraltar is not to be overthrown with a pop-gun. A structure as

lofty and secure as that which has arisen upon the foundation laid by

Malthus must be “rockrooted in the crust of the earth, and buttressed

with the everlasting hills.”

Refutations continue to rain, however. Of these criticisms which show

only the writer’s limited acquaintance with his subject (and they are

the immense majority) it is unnecessary to say more. There are, however,

two kinds not uncommonly heard from persons who know what they are

talking about. One disputes the validity of the geometric and

arithmetical ratios.[17] A sufficient reply was given by Mill. The

increase of unchecked population is geometrical. That of food may be

more than arithmetical. But what is the use of talking about increase of

food when geometrical increase of population, if it did not bring back

the Positive Check in other ways, as, of course, it would, must soon

restore that Check in the inexorable form of crowding? The other

criticism, much more practical, is perhaps intended only as a criticism,

not a refutation; but if this be meant the critics ought to say so, —

first, in order to clear themselves of identification with the Sadlers,

Godwins, Coleridges, De Quinceys, Georges, and others whose refuted

refutations ring hollow down the corridors of time; secondly, that they

may avoid exercising a pernicious influence upon readers less informed

than themselves. The criticism is based on the. obvious fact that since

Malthus wrote, wealth, at least in England, has increased much faster

than population — a fact from whose significance the one word emigration

takes a great deal — but here become possible suggestions which make

this criticism a phase of the others — we do not know what intenser

cultivation may effect — the actual habits of mankind are not such as to

bring in the Positive Check, etc., etc. “Speak unto us smooth things;

prophesy unto us deceits!” We do know that intenser cultivation will

never banish need for the Prudential Check: and the habits of mankind

are such as to invite the Positive when they are such as to invite wars

for a harbor or a diamond mine every few years. I am sorry to say that

Kropotkin’s Fields, Factories and Workshops, contains passages which are

adapted (I cannot believe intended) to encourage in careless readers the

loose idea that “everything is lovely” except certain human institutions

(which, saving only the subjection of women, are not causes but

effects).

To conclude the story of Malthus. One of the lies is that he had

thirteen children! He had three, of whom only two survived him. His wife

came from a part of England which he is known to have visited many years

before. It is probable there was a long engagement. Malthus certainly

was a good deal older at marriage than the average. His life and

teachings appear, therefore, to have been entirely consistent. Among the

many attempts to refute him one was by suggesting that man in his

developed state might be above the desire of sex, and that the need for

propagation might be superseded by terrestrial immortality! Malthus

treated this fully as respectfully as it deserved. He said that, while

bondage to the desire was a potent source of vice and misery, the desire

itself was a principal source of the moral virtues and of happiness,

with which it would be by no means desirable, if it were credible, that

mankind in general should dispense. The effect of these discussions on

Godwin’s active imagination may be seen on comparing his famous novels.

Caleb Williams (1794) gives no hint of anything supernatural. It is a

powerful arraignment of “Things As They Are.” In St. Leon (1832) the

hero attains terrestrial immortality, and, like the Wandering Jew, finds

it the greatest of all imaginable curses; but, pervading the story is

the subthought of Godwin’s invincible Optimism — a Salathiel, a St.

Leon, would not be miserable in a world where all the people were

immortal. The time which Godwin chose for his attempt at refuting

Malthus is also significant — it was in 1820, when Ricardo was deducing

from the Malthusian theory corollaries whose legitimacy no one then

seems to have disputed except Malthus himself. Malthus died, from

disease of the heart, in 1834, the sixty-eighth year of his age. Godwin

followed on the 7^(th) of April, 1836. Of the two, Malthus had best

maintained his philosophic dignity. The Anarchist Godwin stooped to

accept a sinecure office from the Liberal administration of Earl Grey.

Malthus declined the tardy favor offered by government to him. “In their

death,” says the best biographer of Malthus, “they were still divided;

but, si quis piorum animis locus, they are divided no longer, and think

hard thoughts of each other no more.”

Before the eyes of both there was growing up a power unobserved of

either, but predestined to solve their problem. Commerce could never

cheapen itself out of existence while population, varying with cheapness

of food, kept up the struggle for existence: nor, though commerce which

cannot do that teaches solidarity, could it prevent recurrence of those

crises when “the eyeless I howls in darkness.” But increase of the

Prudential Check on population has always kept up with, or rather it has

gone before and been the source of, economic progress. Its increase has

depended on that of hope, this on increase of liberty, increase of

liberty on those “accidents” by which Providence has from time to time

interfered to give men intent on enslaving each other and themselves

another call to reflection. If, then, there be a tendency in the

bourgeois system which brings liberty and hope to women; from that we

really may expect revolutionary changes. For the female is the less

amorous sex. The last proposition, which certainly does sound rather

like a stock assertion, may have been unknown to both Godwin and

Malthus. But no reader of Darwin can help knowing that it has been

demonstrated by exhaustive application to every animal species and been

found the clue to progress through heredity. Women have never chosen to

breed food for gunpowder. They have submitted to do so only because they

could not help themselves. Now there is in the bourgeois system a

tendency which, by bringing liberty and hope to women, promises far more

energetic restraint on propagation than the world has ever known, — a

tendency which capitalists view with indifference; reactionaries, and

Socialists not infrequently, with alarm; judicious friends of humanity,

with unmixed satisfaction. The wages paid directly to women in the

factories first afforded to proletarian women, unprotected by

settlements and other contrivances of the rich, a means to live which

was not easily taken from them. True to the maxim that it is not misery

but hope which works improvement, they, who till now had been well

enough content not to own themselves, became refractory the moment the

had something to lose. The entire modern movement for the property

rights of married women, equality of pay with men for all working women,

opening of all the trades to women, political equality of the sexes,

easy divorce, began with employment of women as breadwinners, which came

in as a necessity of the bourgeois situation. That complete emancipation

of women, defect in food for gunpowder, cessation of war, the downfall

of those appliances for plunder which war created, are all threatened by

this movement, there can be no occasion for me to prove. Mr. Roosevelt

will show you that — and afterwards gnash his teeth. The Malthusian

Theory is the fatal objection to every form of Socialism, even if called

Anarchism, which encourages man to think that he can enslave women and

escape the most righteous retribution of being a slave himself. It is

the strongest possible argument for that kind of Socialism or Anarchism

which proposes, through complete emancipation of women, to abolish the

fundamental tyranny from whence all others spring.

 

[1] This is one of Henry George’s arguments to show that population may

increase indefinitely — an argument utterly idiotic, as the next

sentence shows.

[2] If he were wrong in this, he at least had something to say. Under

the Roman Empire celibacy, of course, as a rule, impure, which, even

under the Republic, had become a common way of avoiding the pecuniary

pressure, increased to immense proportions. This saved the Roman peace

from ending in famine, like the Mogul. But it did not avert dissolution

of the Empire. Malthus would have been quite in the ordinary way of

thinking if he attributed Roman misfortunes to Roman vice; and

maintained that a chaste celibacy might have had better results.

[3] George says that the Malthusian theory did not originally involve

the idea of progress. Referred even to the later editions of Malthus,

this is incorrect; but for the first it is ridiculous, and shows at once

that George never read what Malthus wrote in 1798.

[4] Those acquainted with Malthus in after life say he was one of the

gentlest and most amiable of men; which we are also told about Ricardo

and Adam Smith. But there are letters of his tutor extant, from which it

appears that he had been a most pugnacious boy; and a phrenologist,

reading his works with knowledge of their occasions, would find ground

on every page for saying: “Firmness and combativeness, Large!” Malthus

said that the charges of discouraging benevolence, and commending

infanticide and abortion, etc., etc., gave him pain, when they were

honest misunderstandings; but, considered as polemical tricks, he had

learned to despise them, and got over answering.

[5] George, whose “refutation of Malthus” is useful because it gives in

epitome those of every one else, with exquisite consistency, suggests

both these views; sometimes wondering ironically that this great truth

never was discovered before; sometimes intimating that it does not

amount to a great truth, because everybody knows all the truth there is

in it, and governs himself accordingly. That Malthus actually stated all

the truth there is in this, would never be suspected by a reader of

George.

[6] Malthus, whose eye surveyed the world, did not, of course, overlook

so huge a fact as infanticide. From a moral point of view, his judgment

on it may be anticipated; but from an economic, he reasoned that it

rather increased population than otherwise, being looked forward to,

wherever tolerated, as a resort, before children are born; while, after

that, parental affection limits it to a last resort.

[7] Much the best criticism of this kind was made by Karl Marx. The

capitalists, he says, have regular employment for a limited number of

proletaires. What they call the surplus is an excess over that number.

They are quite insincere in affecting a desire to reduce it, for it is

the reserve of their army. Out of this “surplus” come the “scab,” the

strike-breaker, the policeman, the common soldier where there is no

conscription. This is true enough; and it is a good reply to hypocrites

who find in the Malthusian Theory a “parry to demands for reform.” But

what it has to do with the truth of the theory I do not see; nay, if we

must be polemical, the fact that neglect of Malthus breeds

strike-breakers seems to me an excellent reason why Socialists should be

Malthusians.

[8] This is important. George repeatedly assures us that ability to

create any kind of wealth is ability to create as much of any other

kind. But if the Law of Diminishing Returns from Agricultural Lands be

correct, this is not correct for the most important kind of wealth.

[9] By making an actual sum out of the “wage-fund,” which in the works

of Adam Smith and Malthus, is only a rhetorical phrase.

[10] This was reserved for George. Ricardo, a practical man of business,

knew too much about the comparative incomes of landlords and

capitalists, under varying conditions of time and place, to say that

Rent was swallowing all which labor and capital ought to get from land

above the poorest.

[11] Thus Henry George, whose premises are taken straight out of

Ricardo, thinks it necessary to refute Malthus, of whose real relation

to Ricardo he knew very little. Extension of cultivation is, according

to Ricardo, the cause of rent. Its own cause (George supposes) is, for

Malthus apud Ricardo, increase of population. To save Ricardo without

adopting Malthus, George ingeniously argues that it is not increase, but

concentration, of population which extends cultivation. The truth is,

Malthus had not said it was either.

[12] No disrespect at all is meant Ricardo by anything said here. He

greatly advanced knowledge by establishing the true relation of rent to

price, which Adam Smith misunderstood, and by showing that when the

price of bullion is said to rise it is really that of paper money which

falls. His maxim that, under free competition labor buys labor, is the

basis of Marx’ theory concerning Surplus Value and of philosophic

Socialism. Like Ptolemy in astronomy and Galen in medicine, he long had

the ill-luck to be influential largely through his mistakes; but that

any man can be that is the measure of his abilities.

[13] Bourgeois writers have seized upon the doctrines of Malthus and

Darwin as upon an argument against co-operation, almsgiving, and above

all, anything like communism. The struggle for existence, they tell us,

is the source of progress. For the strong to assist the feeble in

living, but above all propagating, is to weaken the social organism, as

well as to raise impracticable expectations and increase misery by

adding disappointment to its pains. This is unquestionably true for

compulsory charity. It is true for all voluntary charity whose final

result is to encourage dependence. And in the present general condition

of dependence, all almsgiving has a tendency to do that. But two things

are overlooked. First, co-operation is not charity, but trade: — for

benefits given, benefits are expected. Secondly, the pauperizing effect

of charity depends on a previous degradation of the recipient. No man is

morally worse for the helping hand of a fellow-worker. Every man is, for

the beaming condescension of a patron. Socialistic writers, who

generally know too much to attempt refuting Darwin, attempt instead to

show that the conflict by which the world has advanced was a conflict of

species, not individuals of the same species, among whom co-operation,

not competition, has been the rule. Among those who have secured this

side of the matter due attention, Kropotkin is the most distinguished.

Whether he has contracted anything like a prejudice by the way, may be

inquired later. It is hardly deniable that with men, the struggle has

been very largely between nations and often individuals.

[14] To illustrate, it was a favorite subject of controversy among

writers who, like Montesquieu, made any attempt at philosophic history,

whether the ancient world were more or less populous than the modern? We

may not know much about the world; but, on Malthusian principles, it is

absurd to suppose that France, for example, could have had anything like

her present population when her soil was mainly covered by forests

supporting only half-wild cattle and hogs; when Paris was a village, and

Lyons a rural oppidum, when silk was unknown and wine imported at such

prices as a slave for a jar. A phenomenon which these early writers

noticed, was that, after a great migration of barbarians, like the

Scythians or Northmen, their countries remained quiet for many years.

The explanation was that they were “biding their time” — living,

probably, on ice and air. It is, now, that, until the principle of

population restored their numbers, none were left at home but children

and old people.

[15] James Fitz James Stephen (the crazy snoozer who tried Mrs.

Maybrick) says, in his Liberty, Equality and Fraternity, a reply to

Mill’s Liberty, that there is no absurdity about this paradox. If he had

not said so, we might perhaps have imagined that there was.

[16] Pitt, next to Napoleon the chief modern anthropophagus, had

actually prepared a bill for a bounty on children; but withdrew it in

deference to the arguments of Dr. Parr and others among Malthus’

earliest converts.

[17] To illustrate again the facility with which these things may be

misunderstood, dependent on the complexity of that relation which some

try to evade by calling it a truism — I have said here, in the name of

Malthus, too, that what enables a high rate of propagation to go on is

increase of the death-rate. But the death-rate, from all causes and in

all places of statistical census taken together, has decreased notably

since we began to have reliable returns (which is only since about 1700

A. D.); and what little we know about earlier times indicates that the

death-rate has always decreased, on the whole, since men emerged from

the grazing state of savagery, where the average duration of life is

said to be only thirteen years. How do these statements agree? Simply

enough. Who said propagation had gone on unslackened? The reasoning of

Malthus, and mine, has all been to the effect that the Prudential Check

has gained on the Positive almost continuously since men emerged from

utter barbarism, except where increased facility of living has, for a

time, caused it to be neglected. Wherever that happens — as when a

prairie changes into a Chicago — we may see that the death-rate does

increase as soon as that facility of living which relaxed the Prudential

Check encourages propagation sufficiently to recall the Positive.