đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș ron-tabor-a-look-at-leninism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:46:18. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: A Look at Leninism Author: Ron Tabor Date: 1988 Language: en Topics: Leninism, anti-Bolshevism, critique Source: Retrieved on 2nd December 2020 from https://libcom.org/library/look-leninism-ron-taber
THE book in your hands was originally written as a series of articles in
the Torch/La Antorcha, a newspaper published by the Revolutionary
Socialist League, in 1987 and early 1988, The ideas presented in these
articles had been germinating in my mind for quite some lime. They were,
in particular, an offshoot of work on a previous book, Trotskyism and
the Dilemma of Socialism (with Christopher Z. Hobson), a history of
Trotskyism and a critique of Leon Trotskyâs theory of the nature of the
Soviet Union, During the course of writing that book, it became dear to
me that Trotskyâs tendency to lay the blame for the totalitarian
evolution of the Soviet regime solely at die hands of Joseph Stalin, and
to exonerate Lenin of any responsibility, was, at the very least,
one-sided. The question: What role did Bolshevik Party founder and
leader, V,l, Lenin, and his theories and practical activity play in the
establishment or that oppressive society which we call state
capitalism)?âthus presented itself.
The result was a considerable amount of additional reading on the
October Revolution, the Civil War and its aftermath, various
philosophical questions, and a re-reading of a number of works of Lenin
himself. Partial conclusions from this program were recorded in a number
of rough drafts of documents intended for internal discussion in the
Revolutionary Socialist League and in a talk presented at the 1986
convention of that organization. I was not satisfied with any of these
presents! ions or my conclusions, however.
At a certain point in my reevaluation of Leninism, it occurred to me
that the fundamental outlook and mentality of Lenin and the Bolshevik
Party as a whole were overwhelmingly authoritarian, and I could no
longer square my acceptance of Leninism with my more fundamental
commitment to a revolutionary libertarian socialism. As a major leader
of the RSL. I could not in good conscience
keep this conclusion to myself. The series of articles now compiled in
this book was my attempt to explain and motivate my thinking.
Since they were written over a period of 13 months, for a newspaper and
hence for a fairly broad audience, and often under the pressure of
deadlines, the articles are occasionally repetitive, while some issues
are covered somewhat simplistically. Moreover, a number of topicsâthe
attitude of Lenin toward the peasantry, for exampleâ were omitted for
reasons of time and space Despite this, the articles represent an
accurate enough presentation of my current evaluation of Leninism to
warrant re-publication in book form. It is hoped that whatever
weaknesses the resulting book exhibits do not prevent it from being of
some value for those looking for a political outlook and strategy that
are both revolutionary and anti-authoritarian.
I would particularly like to thank Bruce Kala for his time and patience
both in typesetting the original articles and inserting the various
minor editing changes made since then. All errors, of course, are solely
my responsibility.
IN the discussion that follows, Leninism is taken 10 mean the theory and
practice of the political tendency/faction/party within the Russian
revolutionary movement led by V.I. Lenin, from around 1900, through the
October Revolution of 1917, to the early years of the Bolshevik regime.
Although other individuals played prominent roles in various phases of
the Bolshevik tendency, Lenin was by far the dominant personality, as
theoretician, organizer and overall leader. Bolshevism was
overwhelmingly his idea. And while Leninâs ideas and policies changed
during the course of his political career, there is sufficient unity and
continuity among them to justify describing and analyzing them as
Leninism.
This series is not meant to he a complete work on Leninism, Nor is it
intended to be a âbalance sheet,â a careful weighing of pluses and
minuses. Having considered ourselves Leninists for the length of our
history as a tendency, our task now is not to look at the positive but,
in the interests of an insightful analysis, to focus on the negative, to
look for the weaknesses in Leninism. A discussion of the pluses â in the
light of the negatives â and a balance sheet can come later.
Our unifying theme, though, is not negativity per se, but a particular
question or problem. This can be described roughly as follows: What
responsibility does Leninism /Bolshevism have for the social system, and
the crimes, of what we have- loosely called Stalinism and more
accurately labelled stale capitalism?
As most readers of the Torch/La Antorcha are aware, we do not believe
that the social systems that exist in Russia. China, Cuba, Eastern
Europe. Vietnam, etc.. are socialist, moving toward socialism, workersâ
states or even progressive. Instead, we consider them to be highly
stratified variants of capitalismâstate capitalism. In these societies,
the workers and other oppressed people, deprived of political rights and
power over the state, are exploited by a bureaucratic elite built around
the party/state economic, political and military apparatus.
I do not intend to argue for, let alone try to prove, this position
here, (We have discussed it many times elsewhere.) It is a premise of
the series. Taking it as a starting point, I am particularly interested
in the establishment of the very first state capitalist regimeâ that in
Russiaâwhich was the outcome of the October (Bolshevik) Revolution of
17. This revolution and regime were not only the inspiration and mode!
for I he revolutions and processes that established the other stale
capitalist systems. In addition, because of the nature of the October
Revolution itself, the insurrection and the Bolshevik regime it
established have been key factors supporting the illusion that the state
capitalist regimes are socialist.
We believe that the October Revolution was, to a considerable degree, a
revolution carried out by the working class and supported by the
peasantry. The Bolshevik Party, which led the revolution (along with the
Left Social Revolutionaries and various anarchist organist ions} had won
majorities in the soviets (workersâ councils set up by the workers
themselves after the revolution in February), the factory committees and
other mass organizations. Most of these soviets had passed resolutions
calling for âAll Power to the Sovietsâ some weeks before the revolution.
The uprising itself was effected by a fairly broad number of workersâ,
soldiersâ and sailorsâ organisations, most of which were not part of the
Bolshevik Party or even under its firm control. Moreover, after i( had
occurred, the insurrection was approved by an All-Russian Congress of
Soviets and by other mass organisations. (The insurrection was also
supported de factoâindeed, made possibleâby the mass of peasants, who
rose up and seized and divided the landed estates during the summer and
fail of 1917,)
The October Revolution, in other words, was not simply a Bolshevik coup
dâetat, carried out against the wishes and behind the backs of the
workers and peasants.
Despite the popular nature of the insurrection, however, the regime that
finally emerged from the revolution, the Civil War and Stalinâs
consolidation of power was a frightful totalitarian dictatorship that
had deprived the workers of any control over the factories, had taken
the land back from the peasants, had deprived both of them of control
over the state, as well as virtually ail political rights, and had
killed millions of people in the process.
In the past, we tended to pin the responsibility for [his development
on 1) Joseph Stalin, who look over the leadership of the Bolshevik
(Communist) Party after Leninâs illness and death, and 2) objective
conditions. In other words, paraphrasing Leon Trotskyâs analysis, we
believed that certain objective conditionsâthe failure of workers in
other countries to carry out successful revolutions, the
counter-revolutionary attempts and imperialist interventions in Russia,
Russiaâs historical backwardness and poverty, along with the disruption
and devastation brought about by World W*r I, the revolutions and Civil
Wat â prevented the Bolshevik government from evolving into a healthy
proletarian dictatorship {ââa state that is already becoming a
non-state.â a âCommune-type state,â etc.). Instead, they enabled a
bureaucracy, led and organized by Stalin, to seize power, eliminate the
last vestiges of workersâ control over the economy and state, smash the
peasants and consolidate itself as a state capitalist ruling class.
Vet, is this the whole story? Is it realty possible to place the
responsibility/blame solely on objective conditions and Stalin, and to
leave the Bolsheviks and Lenin blame-free? I donât think so.
There arc a number of questions whose very posing suggests that the
Bolsheviks themselves (meaning Lenin and the party as a whole prior to
Stalin establishing his stranglehold over it) have at least some
responsibility for what happened. For one thing, how did Stalin get to
be the head of the party? Why was a man like that in the party in the
first place? What kind of party would enable someone like Stalin to
thrive in it, be a major leader for many years and finally establish
himself as its key leader?
Why did Lenin appoint Stalin to the Organization Bureau and Secretarial
of the Party, let alone appoint him, or allow him to become, General
Secretary of the Party? Why did so many Bolsheviks line up with Stalin
against Trotsky and against, so it would seem, the original ideals of
Bolshevism? What enabled Stalin so easily to don the mantle of Leninism?
Why didnât more Bolsheviks organize to stop Stalin? Why did they allow
themselves to be âliquidatedââ by him without a serious struggle?
AH these questions suggest, at least to me, that there was something in
the theory and practice of the Bolshevik Party, its politics and
methods, its atmosphere and âethosâ that ]) gave rise to Stalin and 2)
helped create the circumstances that allowed him to consolidate state
capitalism in Russia,
Holding Lenin and the Bolsheviks (and Leninism) at least partially
responsible for the establishment of state capitalism flows not just
from the above questions about Stalin and the party, but even more from
an objective took at the state and society that had been established in
Russia at the conclusion of the Civil War (when Lenin was still alive
and well).
By this time, the Soviet government was a one-party regime, run totally
by the Bolsheviks, The party dominated the soviets, which had become
little more than vehicles for carrying out policies the Bolsheviks
decided rather than the arena in which the workers determined policies
and chose and controlled their leadership. Nor did the workers run the
factories or any other part of the economy. The factory committees had
long been superseded by âone-man managementâ â Bolshevik appointees in
no way elected or controlled by, or responsible to, the workers.
Almost all other political parties were either outlawed or barely
tolerated (until 1922 when they were outlawed) and harassed by the Cheka
(political police). After the ban on internal factions in the Bolshevik
Party was adopted in March 1921, the Cheka hounded opposition forces
even within the party. The trade unions were almost exclusively arms of
the state and while some strikes were legal under the NEP (New Economic
Policy, adopted in 1921), strikes were strongly discouraged and
strikers, and especially strike leaders, were harassed and arrested.
More broadly, the Bolshevik Party was isolated from the popular classes,
including the overwhelming majority of the workers and peasants. This is
indicated by the Bolsheviksâ suppression of the uprising at the
Kronstadt naval fortress, the mass peasant uprisings in a number of
provinces (e.g., Tambov) and the near general strike in Petrograd, which
had long been the Bolsheviksâ chief political baseâall of which occurred
at the close of the Civil War in early 1921. In short, while the Soviet
state was nowhere near the Stalinist nightmare it was to become, by
1922, the foundations of a state capitalist regime had been constructed,
replete with censorship (libraries were periodically purged to eliminate
âoffensiveâ material, including outdated Bolshevik writings), secret
police, labor camps, etc.
The point here is not that the post-Civil War regime in Russia was fully
state capitalist and totalitarian. Nor is it that the Bolsheviks were
totally responsible for the establishment of such a regime and therefore
the Bolsheviks were nothing but a state capitalist political force. (1
think the question is more complicated than this.) It is to indicate
that an objective loo]; at the problem suggests that the Bolsheviks have
to be held at least partially responsible for the establishment of state
capitalism, and the Stalinist hell-hole, in Russia. {Hopefully, just how
responsible will emerge from the series.)
Why is the question of Leninism and its relation to Stalinism/ state
capitalism so important to us. There are two interrelated reasons. 1}
When the Revolutionary Socialist League was founded, we defined
ourselves essentially as âorthodox Trotskyistsâ with a slate capitalist
position on the nature of Russia and the other so-called âsocialist
countries.â Our Trotskyism included a belief in an orthodox Leninism and
Marxism, more or less as defined by Trotsky. We rarely posed it
precisely this way, but this is what we meant when we defined Trotskyism
as the âcontinuityâ of Marxism and Leninism.
Unlike other left groups, however, we were not content to define
ourselves In a certain âorthodoxâ way and then leave our politics alone.
For a variety of reasons (one of which was the impact of the womenâs and
the lesbian and gay liberation movements), we subjected our politics to
a continual questioning. In particular, we began to investigate
Trotskyism in some detail.
A key impetus for this process was internal to our theory. Specifically,
we began to realize that if Trotsky had been wrong about the nature of
Russia, this error was not likely to have been an isolated one, without
effect on other aspects of his politics and methods, Among other things,
we recognised that in addition to what we saw as the positive,
pro-socialist aspects of Trotskyâs politics (leading hint ultimately lo
call for a revolution against Stalin and to advocate a multi-party
democracy under a workersâ state), there were what we called âstate
capitalistâ aspects or tendencies, tendencies that justified or implied
state capitalism, it was these tendencies that led Trotskyâs followers
in the Fourth International, after the expansion of state capitalism
into Eastern Europe following World Wat II, lo capitulate and become
apologists for stale capitalism. (As this suggests, the most obvious
stale capitalist aspect of Trotskyism was Trotskyâs position that Russia
under Stalin was a âdegenerated workersâ state,â and its implied
corollary that a state can be a workers* state even though it is not
controlled byâindeed, actually oppressesâthe workers.)
In short, we decided that there were definite state capitalist aspects
to Trotskyism and that we should discard those, retain the
âpro-socialistâ aspects, modify the others as needed, and generally move
away from an âorthodoxâ (formalistic, dogmatic) conception of politics
toward a more synthetic (some might say eclectic) approach. The latter
includes looking at, and borrowing from, other left-wing political
traditions, such as anarchism.
As part of our developing critique of Trotskyism, we began to pay
special attention to the period from the October Revolution, through the
Civil War, to Leninâs incapacitation and de facto retirement in late
1922â23. This was the period, according to Trotsky, in which the
Bolshevik regime was a relatively healthy workersâ state (it had
âbureaucratic distortions,â in Leninâs phrase). It became clear to us,
however, that this was far from the case, especially if viewed from the
Marxist ideal of a state already beginning to wither away, etc.
As has already been indicated, the soviet regime by this time was
significantly bureaucratized (stale capitalist), and much of this was
the direct result of the measures taken by the Bolsheviks themselves:
centralizing economic and political power in their own hands,
eliminating direct workersâ control of the factories, suppressing other
political tendencies, requisitioning grain from the peasants by force,
establishing a secret police, building an army along
hierarchical/bourgeois lines, etc. However much these measures were
taken in reaction to the equally harsh, if not harsher, measures taken
by the Bolsheviksâ opponents, they were nevertheless extremely
bureaucratic, coercive and brutal. In addition, the Bolsheviks justified
and even glorified them, and made no serious effort lo reverse them
(except for forced requisitions), after the Civil War was over.
Most important, these measures, for whatever reason they were taken,
whether justified or not, involved the de facto destruction of the
workersâ control over the economy and state. A consideration of this
fact at least posed the question that I am now proposing to discuss: How
much responsibility for state capitalism lies with Leninism; or, how
much state capitalism is there in Leninism?
There is a more general reason for our concern with the question of
Leninism, and it is something that has motivated our theoretical
interest from before the foundation of the RSL. This is another
question: How did revolutionary socialism, a world-view and movement
that claim to be for the liberation of humanity through a revolution by
its most oppressed classes, wind up creating one of the more oppressive,
less liberatory social systems the world has seen? Whatever the
achievements of the state capitalist countries (which we donât propose
to dispute or discuss here), these gains have come at the suffering and
deaths of millions of people, (The estimates of the people who died as a
result of Stalinâs forced âcollectivizationâ and the resulting famine,
along with the massive purgesânot counting deaths in World War IIârange
upward from 20 million. See Robert Conquest, The Honest of Sorrow,
Oxford, 1986, and The Great Terror, Macmillan, 1968. Estimates of those
who died in Maoâs Great Leap forward and the Cultural Revolution in
China run in the many millions.)
Moreover, the results of this incredible human sacrifice are not dynamic
and prosperous social systems in which people live in abundance and
security, (With one exception, these countries are now stagnating; the
exception, China, is saving itself from stagnation, at least for now, by
adopting free market, i.e., traditional capitalist, policies.) Nor are
these countries models of, or even moving toward, socialist democracy.
These facts are something that revolutionary socialists, particularly
those who consider themselves Leninists, must face up to and take
responsibility for. It will not do to pretend that the Stalinist/ Maoist
atrocities didnât happen, to downplay their extent and gravity, to
consider them merely temporary âaberrations,â or to fool oneself into
believing that they cannot happen again. To those with open eyes and
open minds, the problem remains: The concrete historical result of the
program of socialist revolution has not led to what it promised;
instead, it has resulted in a stupendous human tragedy, (The relatively
benign character of the Cuban and Sandinista revolutions should not
blind us to the realities of Russia, China and,.. Kampuchea.)
Whatever the rest of the left may do, we in the Revolutionary Socialist
League feel we have a deep political, and moral, responsibility lo
investigate as thoroughly as we can why this happened. How can we
propose a way forward for workers and other oppressed groups, or say we
have a solution to their problems and to the crisis of world capitalism,
without investigating the reasons for the historic failure of
revolutionary socialism? It is easy to be against thingsâpoverty, racism
and sexism, the waste and brutality of capitalism, the destruction of
tremendous human resources and the environment, the moral corruption,
etc.âwithout doing much theorizing. But to advocate a profound social
transformation and the creation of a new social system, and lo do this
in a responsible manner, one ought to have done a great deal of thinking
about what it is one is for and whether and under what circumstances it
will work- Simply appealing to âhistorical lawsâ or the âscienceâ of
historical materialism is the same as the Pope appealing to âfaithâ and
ârevelation,â and equally dangerous.
IN this installment of our series, we will focus on the question of
broad strategy, particularlyâwhat kind of revolution did the Bolsheviks
advocate and prepare themselves for during the period prior to the
October Revolution?
Most people not very familiar with Marxist history tend to assume that
people and organizations that call themselves Marxist or Communist
always advocate and try to carry out socialist revolutions^ revolutions
to overthrow capitalism and establish socialism Yet, while such
revolutions have usually been declared the ââultimate goalâ of such
groups, Marxian socialists in so-called âunderdevelopedâ countries have
generally advocated bourgeois (capitalist) revolutions as the âfirst
Stageâ of the revolutionary process in their respective countries. The
Russian Marxists were no exception. Up until April, 1917, the entire
Marxist movement, including Lenin and the Bolsheviks, advocated and
sought to carry out a bourgeois (âbourgeois democraticâ) revolution in
Russia.
This position was consistent with, and an essential part of, what was
considered to be âorthodox Marxismâ at the time. This orthodoxy was
largely defined by the major theoretician of the international Marxist
movement of the time (the Second, or Socialist. International), Karl
Kautsky.
Based on a mechanical reading of the major texts of Marxism and a
generally formalistic mode of thought, this orthodoxy insisted that each
and every country in the world had to go through all of what were
considered to be the necessary stagesâmodes of productionâof human
society between primitive communism and social ism/communism. These were
ancient slave society, feudalism, and capitalism.
Russia around the turn of the century clearly did not have a developed
form of industrial capitalismâthere was a king, the Tsar, a landed
nobility, peasants only recently freed from serfdom and still bound to
the land by debts, a lack of political rights, etc. The Marxists of the
period considered Russian society to be, or to have just emerged from, a
form of feudalism. And the revolution they felt the country was moving
toward, and which they advocated and readied themselves for, was a
bourgeois one. That is, the revolution would overthrow the Tsar, destroy
the landed gentry, free the peasants and set up some kind of bourgeois
democratic political system that would guarantee political rights,
including the rights to strike and form political parties, freedom of
the press, etc.
Not least, the revolution would pave the way for the fullest development
of capitalism. Only after a period of capitalist development of
undetermined length, during which the country would be industrialized
and the working class would grow, organize itself and become conscious
of its position in society and of the need to establish its own rule,
would a second, socialist revolution take place. Since, according to
Marxist theory, socialism requires modern industry and material
abundance, and a socialist revolution could only be carried out by a
modern working class, the Marxists in Russia, ironically, found
themselves advocates of a bourgeois revolution and... capitalism.
With almost no exceptions (Leon Trotsky, after 1905, was one), the
entire Marxist movement in Russia subscribed to one form or another of
this theory. They not only believed it themselves, but argued vehemently
against â that is, denounced â those who disagreed with them, including
anarchists and populists, who after 1902 were organized in the Social
Revolutionary Party. Marxism, the âscience of society,â âscientific
socialismââthey contendedâ deemed that Russia, feudal, semi-feudal, or
recently emerged from feudalism, could not âjump overâ the âhistorical
stageâ of capitalism. And anyone who said it could was a dreamer, a
muddle-head or, worse, a utopian. The coming revolution in Russia was
going to be, and had to be, a bourgeois one.
In all the debatesâpolemicsâLenin carried out with other individuals,
tendencies and parties, up to 1917, he never called the bourgeois nature
of the Russian revolution into question. For example, in Leninâs debates
with his main Marxist opponents, such as the âEconomistsâ and the
Mensheviks, the question of the fundamental (bourgeois) nature of the
coming revolution was never explicitly at issue.
In Leninâs various books and articles on the âagrarian question,â on
which Lenin was an expert, one of his main aims was to advocate measures
that would guarantee the greatest development of capitalist relations in
agriculture. Significantly, in much of the period between 1905 and 1917,
the Bolsheviksâ main agitational slogans (directed toward the âbroad
massesâ), known as the âthree whalesâ were, roughly, the eight-hour day,
land to the peasants, and a democratic republic. These are all
bourgeois-democratic demands.
It was only in early 1917, after the February Revolution had overthrown
the Tsar, that the Bolsheviks adopted the point of view that the
revolution they sought to carry out would be a socialist one. (Some have
argued that Lenin had come to this position as far back as late 1914.
While Leninâs thinking changed significantly beginning at that timeâthe
outbreak of World War I and the collapse of the Second Internationalâit
is not clear that his view of the revolution had changed prior to late
1916-carly 1917, In any case, Lenin was isolated from most of his
followers during this period and the changes in his thinking were not
likely to have affected many Bolsheviks prior to his. and their, return
Lo Russia after the February Revolution.)
I do not wish to argue the substance of the question here, that is,
whether the Russian Marxists were right or wrong in their conception.
The point I wish to stress is that throughout the entire formative
period of Bolshevism as a political tendency/movement/party, it
advocated and sought to implement not a socialist revolution, but a
bourgeois one. Given this, is it really very surprising that the
revolution that the Bolsheviks did carry out in Russia, when judged in
terms of its long-term outcome, was basically a bourgeois one, that is,
it created a kind of capitalist society, not a socialist one?
I donât mean to be playing with words here, or to be making cheap
arguments. I am making a fundamental point. A political movement is
defined not only by its long-term proclaimed goal but also, and even
more so, by what it organizes itself around in the present and the near-
and middle-term future. What it does is more important than what it sags
it is âultimatelyâ for.
Revolutionary Marxists, including Leninists, have always recognized the
validity of this point when applied to the parties of the Second
International. Although these parties advocated socialism in the long
run, by and large, their day-to-day functioning was that of reformist
socialist organizations. They ran the trade unions and other mass
organizations, Fought for pro-labor and other progressive legislation in
parliament, etc. Socialism was primarily for speeches on May Day and
oilier working class holidays.
Thus, while Lenin was surprised when the Second International collapsed
at the beginning of World War I (most of its constituent parties
supported the predatory war aims of âtheirâ respective ruling classes,
instead of opposing the war as a whole), we, looking back, can see that
this was the most likely development. And some astute contemporary
observers, such as Rosa Luxemburg, long a left-winger in the German
Social Democratic Party (the SPD), had realized the true nature of the
majority of the movement as early as 1910.
If the argument is valid vis-a-vis the Social Democracy, why does it
suddenly become false when applied to the Bolsheviks? For most of their
history, I repeat, they advocated and prepared themselves lo carry out a
bourgeois revolution. Is this significant?
The question is not whether the Bolsheviks were really reformists rather
than revolutionaries, but what kind of revolutionaries they were,
socialist or bourgeois. If we are to be consistent with our analysis of
the Second International, I think we have to answer, or at least be open
lo the idea, that the Bolsheviks were a kind (a special kind, to be
sure), of bourgeois revolutionary!
I am not raising this argument here to prove that the Bolsheviks were
really bourgeois rather than socialist revolutionaries, bur to establish
the plausibility of the contention, To me, the fact that throughout
virtually their entire history prior to the October Revolution they
advocated and prepared themselves to carry out a kind of bourgeois
revolution is highly suggestive. Among other things, it makes the
apparent paradox of how socialist revolutionaries wound up creating a
form of bourgeois society less paradoxical.
A number of arguments can be raised against the point i am trying lo
establish- One is that the composition of the Bolshevik
tendency/movement/party was primarily working class. Actually, this was
only true in certain limes, such as revolutionary upheavals. At other
times, the âclass characterâ of the movement cannot simply be considered
to be proletarian. It had members from the working class, but it also
had many members who were part of the intelligentsia, a stratum of
intellectuals from different backgrounds, roughly the equivalent of the
modern middle class. There is also the question of what to consider
someone from a working class background who is a full-time party
functionary. On balance, throughout much of its history the class
character of the Bolshevik movement would have to be considered as
declasse, that is, as outside the class structure of Russia.
In any case, the nature of a political movement/party is not primarily
defined by the class its members and supporters arc part of. Most of the
members of the Democratic Party in the United States today, for example,
are probably workers, but that doesnât make the party a working class
party.
Another argument against my hypothesis that the Bolsheviks were (despite
themselves) bourgeois revolutionaries is that they thought of themselves
as Marxists, studied Marxism, made it clear to the workers that they
were socialists, recruited people to be socialists, etc. But calling
yourself a Marxist doesnât automatically make you one. Nor does being a
Marxist automatically make you a socialist, in the revolutionary
libertarian meaning of the term.
Most tendencies which today call themselves Marxist we consider to be
state capitalist, and their vision of socialism really a form of state
capitalism. How do we know what the Bolsheviksâ vision of socialism was?
Perhaps they did recruit people to be socialists, hold study sessions,
etc. on socialism. But if their vision of socialism was to any
significant degree contaminated by state capitalist ideas â for example,
that one party (theirs) will make the decisions for the workersâtheir
advocacy of what they called socialism does not make them socialists.
In fact, it is not clear how much discussion of, or education about, the
nature of socialism the Bolsheviks regularly conducted. The Bolsheviks,
like the entire Marxist movement going back to Marx and Engels, were
impatient with discussions or investigations about what socialism would
concretely look like. This was in part a reaction lo the utopian
socialists, Robert Owen. St. Simon, Fourier, etc., who drew up detailed
plans (down to who would live where) about what the ideal society would
look like, and, in some cases, actually tried to set up such
communities, Correctly sensing the totalitarian nature of such projects
(the people in those communities donât decide how the community will be
set up; it is decided beforehand, by someone else), Marx and Engels
eschewed elaborating, or even discussing very much, their vision of
socialism.
This bent was also motivated by a conviction (with its own totalitarian
implications, as we will discuss later) that socialism was the necessary
(inevitable) outcome of history; since socialism was going to happen,
there was no point in figuring out what is would look like.
For whatever reason, then, the Marxist movement Up to and through the
period we are discussing did not generally discuss or elaborate its
conception of socialist society. Given the Bolsheviksâ contention that
the revolution âon the agendaâ in Russia was a bourgeois one, and given
the fact that for most of their history they were an illegal, persecuted
group, it is not likely that they had many in-depth, detailed
discussions about the concrete nature of a socialist society,
A third argument against the contention that the Bolsheviksâ advocacy of
a bourgeois revolution in Russia was a significant, defining element of
Bolshevism is that the Bolsheviks did, prior to the October Revolution,
explicitly discuss and change their conception of the nature of the
revolution they aimed to lead. This refers to the discussion held in the
Bolshevik Party after Leninâs arrival in Russia in early April, 1917,
and to the decision of the party, adopted at the so-called âApril
Conference,â a few weeks later, to seek to seize state power at the head
of a working class socialist revolution, based on the soviets (the
workersâ councils established by the workers during and after the
February Revolution), They did, of course, have this discussion and make
such a decision, among others. But, how deep or thorough was this
discussion?
How long did it go on?
Lenin arrived in Russia after his long exile in Western Europe on April
3 (old-style Russian calendar), a little over a month after the February
Revolution, Prior to his arrival, most Bolsheviks (there were a handful
who disagreed), believed that the Bolsheviksâ main strategic task was to
carry the bourgeois revolution to completion, not to carry out a
socialist revolution. And when Lenin first arrived he shocked most
Bolsheviks who heard him (again, minus a handful) with his new position,
expressed in his âApril Theses,â that (he Bolsheviks should seek to
carry out a socialist revolution. This was considered by almost ail
Bolsheviks, particularly the longtime members, the âOld Bolsheviks,â to
be very unorthodox, heresy, even anarchism.
By the end of April, however, the Bolshevik Party conference (April
24â29) voted overwhelmingly to endorse Leninâs point of view, The
discussion over Leninâs (unorthodox and heretical) point of viewâ took
all of... three weeks. What kind of discussion could they have had in
this time? Could it have been very deep? Could it have been very
thorough? Could the Bolsheviks have even begun lo discuss what the new
position really entailed? Did they use the months between April and the
October Revolution (October 25) to continue this discussion on an
ever-deepening basis? I think the answers to these questions must be
âno.â
The Bolsheviks were in the middle of a political and social maelstrom
and had a million things to do; they were undoubtedly spending most of
their time feverishly agitating and organizing in the midst of hectic
conditions, Lenin did, during this period (he was in hiding,
mid-July-late October), write a number of works, mostly short pamphlets,
explaining what a Bolshevik government based on the Soviets would look
like and what it would do. In particular, during this period Lenin wrote
what many consider to be his greatest work, The Slate and Revolution,
which discusses his view of the nature of the dictatorship of the
proletariat, the withering away of the state, etc. Yet, given the
complexity of these issues, these investigations were really not very
detailed. Equally important The State and Revolution was never finished
and was not published until the following year. It is quite unlikely,
therefore, that the Bolshevik Party had a full discussion of either The
State and Revolution or Leninâs pamphlets.
In short, I believe the Bolsheviks never had a thorough discussion of
the change of position adopted at the April Conference; what it really
meant, what a society based on the soviets would look like, what would
be the relationship between the soviets, factory committees and trade
unions, for example, a question that was to loom very large soon after
the October Revolution, And the course of the revolution, specifically
the success of the October insurrection, seemed to make such a
discussion irrelevant.
Probably the strongest argument that might be leveled against the tine
of thought I am outlining here is the fact that throughout most of their
history prior to 1917 the Bolsheviks did not advocate a âtypicalâ
bourgeois revolution, that is, one led by the capitalists and their
representatives among the intellectuals, etc. Instead, beginning around
1905, the Bolsheviks advocated a bourgeois-democratic revolution that
was lo be carried out by the workers and peasants against the Tsar, the
landed gentry and (paradoxically) the capitalists (the bourgeoisie).
As a result, this argument would run, since the Bolsheviks had, since
1905, advocated a revolution carried out by the workers and peasants
against the capitalists, as well as the Tsar, landlords, etc., and had
always tried to build a base among the working class, to build a working
class party, to make the workers class conscious, etc., the switch in
strategic conceptions in 1917 was not such a big deal. Indeed, some have
argued, this fact goes a long way to explain why Lenin could change the
partyâs mind, so to speak, on this question so easily.
On one level, this appears to be a substantial argument. Yet, a careful
look at the issues involved will, I believe, support and even strengthen
my contention. Letâs look at the question more closely.
Although almost all Russian Marxists agreed that the revolution they
advocated and felt was coming would be a bourgeois-democratic one, they
disagreed over the roles different classes would play in the revolution
and specifically over the tasks Social Democrats should seek to
accomplish, (They all called themselves Social Democrats then; Lenin and
the Bolsheviks took up the older name Communists in 1917,) In fact,
after questions of organization, it is fair to say that the major
differences between Bolsheviks and Mensheviks through most of their
history were disagreements over the configuration of the
(bourgeois-democratic) revolution in Russia and the role Marxists should
play in it.
(For those who donât know, or remember, the terms Bolshevik and
Menshevik come from the Russian words Bolâshinstvo and Menâshinstvo,
meaning majorityites and minorityites, respectively. At the Second
Congress of the Russian Social Democratic Labor Party, the official name
of the Marxist organization, in 1903, the delegates to the congress
split into two hostile factions, largely over questions of party
organization, questions we will get to later. On one of the crucial
votes, the forces led by Lenin won a majority. As a result, Lenin and
his followers were called, and called themselves, Bolsheviks. Those who
had lost the vote were called Mensheviks. This split was never healed,
and the Marxist movement in Russia largely consisted of two factions,
with often separate newspapers and structures, coexisting uneasily. The
two factions were formally in the same party until 1912, when the
Bolsheviks formed their own party. It is typical of Leninâs genius, and
the Mensheviks ineffectiveness, that Lenin and his supporters kept the
name Bolsheviks, which implies strength, while the Mensheviks were
saddled with a name denoting weakness, even though the Menshevik faction
was often larger than the Bolshevik.)
The key differences between the Mensheviks and the Bolsheviks on the
question of bourgeois-democratic revolution in Russia centered on the
role they expected the Russian bourgeoisie to play in the revolution
and, therefore, the attitude the working class and Marxists should take
toward it,
A mechanical, formalistic conception of a bourgeois-democratic
revolution would entail the view that, by definition, a
bourgeois-democratic revolution will be led by the bourgeoisie.
Specifically, the bourgeoisie, which by nature and class interests
prefers a democratic republic, will lead the other progressive forces,
including the peasants, the workers and the middle class, in a struggle
against the monarch (king, queen, Tsar or whatever), the landed nohiiity
and other feudalist forces, [t would aim to do away with feudal
privileges and all forms of servitude, to set up a democratic republic
and to establish the conditions for the fullest and freest development
of capitalism.
This was essentially the view of the Mensheviks. They therefore
advocated that the chief role of the working class and the Social
Democrats was to help the bourgeoisie carry out such a revolution, to
push ii from behind, as it were. Although advocating the independent
organisation of the workers in unions, a social democratic party and,
during the 1905 revolution, soviets (there is some evidence that the
Mensheviks were the first political group to call for a mass, city-wide
strike committee in St, Petersburg, which eventually became the
Petersburg Soviet), the Mensheviks basically felt that the workers
should subordinate themselves to the bourgeoisie, that the latter should
have overall leadership of the revolution. Some even warned of the
danger of the workers pushing loo hard (e.g., striking loo much for
higher wages, threatening to take over and run the factories, etc.),
that this would frighten the bourgeoisie and make ti pull back from a
militant struggle against the Tsar, gentry, etc.
The Bolsheviks, while accepting the bourgeois-democratic character of
the revolution, saw things differently. Instead of starting from an
abstract model of the bourgeois revolution, Lenin began with a concrete
analysis of the economic, social and political situation in Russia at
the time. He was particularly aware of certain âpeculiaritiesâ of
Russian historical development: 1) The Russian state, certainly since
around 1500, had been very strong and tended to dominate Russian
society, 2) Since the Lime of Peter the Great, roughly 1700, the state
had sought to encourage economic development, through borrowing
technology from Western Europe, as a means of defending itself, 3} As a
result, much of Russian industry was built by and/or with the support of
the state, and much was state-owned, 4) Russian industry tended lo be
concentrated in huge enterprises, often employing thousands of workers
(such as the giant Pulilov metalworking plant in St. Petersburg),
The result of these factors was that the Russian bourgeoisie tended to
be small, weak and greatly dependent upon the Tsarist state, while the
working class, in contrast, was proportionately large and
well-concentrated. Consequently, Lenin reasoned, rather than leading the
bourgeois-democratic revolution against the Tsar, the bourgeoisie, at
the first sign of independent and militant mobilisation of the workers
and peasants, would side with the Tsar and the nobility against the
workers and peasants and the revolution as a whole, (Although the
capitalists were frightened of the large, concentrated and oppressed
working class, they also feared the millions upon millions of even more
oppressed peasants, waiting to wreak vengeance upon the landlords and
seize the and, and quite willing to set fire to large portions of the
countryside to do so. This is what they did in 1917.)
The leadership of the revolution, Lenin concluded, would fall lo the
working class and, to a lesser degree, the peasants. It would be they
who would carry out the bourgeois-democratic revolution, not only
against the Tsar and the landlords, bat also the bourgeoisie.
In the eyes of the Bolsheviks, then, the bourgeois-democratic revolution
was defined primarily by the tasks that needed to be carried out. e.g.,
overthrowing the Tsar, seizing the [and from the landlords, establishing
a democratic republic, etc., rather than by being led by the
bourgeoisie.
The specific vehicle for carrying out these tasks would be what Lenin
called the ârevolutionary democratic dictatorship of the proletariat and
peasantry.â This was to be, roughly, a centralized, revolutionary
government, made up of parties representing the workers and peasants
respectively, and based on and supported by the masses of workers and
peasants. This dictatorship would be established by armed insurrection.
(The Bolsheviks actually attempted such an uprising during the 1905
revolution, in Moscow in December of 1905.)
Although Lenin devoted many of his writings to various aspects of the
bourgeois-democratic revolution in Russia, aside from a very broad
sketch, he never put forward a worked out conception of what the
ârevolutionary democratic dictatorshipâ would look like. His failure, or
refusal, to do so appears to have been motivated mostly by the belief
that it would be impossible to predict precisely what would happen in
the course of the revolution, that revolutionaries should not try to
cram the class struggle into some narrowly-conceived mold and that, in
any case, the Bolsheviks should remain flexible.
Yet, in light of the detail Lenin wont into on questions of program
(e.g., the âagrarianâ and ânationalâ questions), party structure (he
called for a reorganization of the party during 1905), and tactics (a
major focus of Bolshevikâ activity during 1905 was the formation of
armed squads of workers), the failure to elaborate the structure of the
ârevolutionary democratic dictatorshipâ is significant. It is
particularly noteworthy that the relationship between the political
parties, supposedly ârepresentingâ the proletariat and the peasantry on
the one hand, and the mass organizations of these classes on the other,
was never seriously raised or investigated.
Lenin was also not very clear about what would happen to this
dictatorship once it had âcarried the bourgeois-democratic revolution
through to completion,â to paraphrase the Marxist language of the
period. He seems to have had two scenarios in mind, both of which can be
inferred from 71vo Tactics of Social Democracy in the Democratic
Revolution, a major work devoted to his conception of the
bourgeois-democratic revolution in Russia.
In one, the ârevolutionary democratic dictatorshipâ would carry out
various steps (e.g.. overthrowing the Tsar, seizing the land from the
landlords, enacting the eight-hour workday) on its own initiative, after
which it would organize for elections, based on direct universal
suffrage, to a Constituent Assembly. Once this assembly had gathered,
approved the revolutionary measures already taken and drawn up a
constitution for a (bourgeois) democratic government, the parties
constituting the ârevolutionary democratic dictatorshipâ would step
down, in favor of a newly-elected parliament and government. That Lenin
took this scenario seriously is suggested by various of his writings on
the agrarian question in which he advocates the relatively long-term
development of Russian agriculture on U-S.-style (small, independent
capitalist farmer) rather than on Prussian (commercial landed estates)
lines.
The second scenario follows the first, up to a point. Very tentatively,
and using only the most general terms, Lenin in Two Tactics writes that
if the bourgeois-democratic revolution in Russia were preceded,
accompanied, or soon followed by one or more socialist revolutions in
Western Europe, the revolutionary parties making up the revolutionary
democratic dictatorship should seek to retain power and begin taking up
socialist tasks, e.g., expropriating the capitalists, etc.
In other words, Lenin raises, very gingerly to be sure, the possibility
that under certain circumstances the bourgeois-democratic revolution in
Russia might begin to âgrow overâ into a socialist revolution. Although
this conception would later (during Stalinâs fight against Trotsky in
the 1920b) become recognized âBolshevikâ orthodoxy, from the lime it was
written to early 1917, it had hardly even been considered by the
majority of Bolsheviks.
Our point in discussing Leninâs conception of the ârevolutionary
democratic dictatorshipâ was to assess to what degree this weakens my
argument that the Bolsheviks had generally advocated and prepared
themselves to carry out a bourgeois revolution, and that this had a
crucial impact in determining the politics and methods of the Bolshevik
Party.
Specifically, it can be argued that since the Bolsheviks had, since
1905, advocated a particular version of a bourgeois-democratic
revolution, that is, one led by the workers and peasants against the
bourgeoisie, it is not quite true to say that they had always planned to
carry out a bourgeois revolution in Russia.
Indeed, it can be argued that the bourgeois-democratic revolution as
conceived by the Bolsheviks was a lot closer to a conception of a
socialist revolution than a bourgeois one. This is why, so Trotsky
insisted, the Bolshevik Party was won so easily to Leninâs new
perspective in April, 1917.
t would contend, however, that the stronger arguments go in the other
direction: 1) That despite the new elements in Leninâs perspective of
1917 what he advocated remained largely within the framework of his
earlier conception, in other words, a bourgeois-democratic revolution
that, under certain circumstances, âgoes beyondâ the
bourgeois-democratic âphaseâ; and 2) that what the Bolsheviks actually
did, looking at not just 1917, but the entire period from 1917 to 1921,
was to implement a version of the ârevolutionary democratic dictatorship
of the proletariat and peasantry,â that is, to carry out a very
specific, and very radical, kind of bourgeois-democratic revolution.
As we know, in late October, 1917, the Bolsheviks, in alliance with the
Left Social Revolutionaries, seized political power at the head of a
workersâ insurrection (made possible by the peasantsâ spontaneous
seizure of the land), and set up a centralized dictatorship. Although
this revolutionary government at first rested on and was supported by
the workersâ and peasantsâ mass organizations, it was not actually
controlled by them. Believing that they were going beyond the
bourgeois-democratic revolution, the Bolsheviks sanctioned the workersâ
seizure of the factories and then expropriated the capitalists
altogether. They dispersed the Constituent Assembly and, after the Left
SRs revolted against the terms of the Brest-Litovsk peace treaty,
concentrated all power into their own hands. They also, in June, 1918,
launched a campaign against the so-called âmiddle peasantsâ in the name
of extending the class struggle to the countryside. In this sense, they
did go beyond the âtypicalâ bourgeois-democratic revolution. But they
did not succeed in creating a true proletarian dictatorship, that is, a
government actually run by the workers for themselves. Instead, the
Bolsheviks built a government they believed was acting âin the
interestsâ of the workers, which is by no means the same thing.
It may have rested upon the organizations of the workers, but in its
methods, e.g., its commitment to extreme centralization, its use of a
secret police to hunt counterrevolutionaries, and in its conception of
regimented, centrally-controlled economy run by decree from the top, it
was far closer to a Jacobin dictatorship (the dictatorship of
Robespierre and the Committee of Public Safety, supported by the
oppressed âsans culottesâ of Paris during the most radical phase of the
French Revolution) than to a true workersâ government.
The fallacy in the Bolsheviksâ theory and practice, it seems to me, is
that (even within the framework of Marxism) the methods and structure of
a socialist revolution are not merely the logical extension of the
structure and methods of the bourgeois-democratic revolution. The
dictatorship of the proletariat, supported by the peasantry, is not
merely the ârevolutionary dictatorship of the proletariat and the
peasantryâ going beyond the limits of the bourgeois-democratic
revolution.
Concretely, in a bourgeois-democratic revolution, the tasks âappropriate
toâ that revolution can be carried out by a party, or parties, that
claim to represent the ânon-feudalâ classes, the bourgeoisie, the
peasants and the workers, if they exist. A government of revolutionary
intellectuals, for example, as long as it is supported by mobilized
masses (sans culottes, peasants, workers) can eliminate a monarchy,
sanction the peasantsâ seizure of the land, the establishment of the
eight-hour day, the calling of a constituent assembly, etc.
In this sense, [his government, and the parties participating in it, if
there are any, can be said to represent the progressive classes. Once
âfeudalâ or âsemi-feudalâ institutions arc dismantled or significantly
weakened, once the major obstacles to commodity production and the
accumulation of capital are eliminated, capitalism develops
spontaneously, ensuring the ultimate defeat of the reactionary forces.
Thus, during the French Revolution, many if not most of the radical
measures taken were not implemented by the bourgeoisie, per se, but by
essentially middle class intellectuals, supported by the peasants and
sans culottes, acting independently of the bourgeoisie, And despite the
fact that the Jacobins were eventually overthrown and (he monarchy
restored, the period of reaction was temporary; capitalism continued to
develop and the monarchy was eventually overthrown.
But in a socialist revolution, it is not sufficient for a party that
claims to represent (he working class to enact measures that are
supposedly in the workersâ interests and to concentrate ail power in its
own hands, it is not, in other words, sufficient for a dictatorship of
one party to be supported by members of the class in whose interests it
claims to be acting, i.e., to rest on the mass organizations of the
workers, such as soviets,
This government, if it is to remain or, better, become, a true
proletarian dictatorship, must increasingly come under the control of
the mass, democratic organizations of the workers. Instead, the
Bolsheviks believing they represented the interests of the workers,
subordinated the soviets (and the factory committees} to themselves,
without recognizing what this meant. The result was not a revolutionary
democratic dictatorship of the proletariat and peasantry moving toward
being (he dictatorship of the proletariat, but the revolutionary
democratic dictatorship that consolidated its own power over and above
the classes it claimed to lead.
Unlike the Jacobins, the Bolsheviks managed to fight off the
counterrevolution externally and internally, and also to defeat the
efforts of the workers and peasants to free themselves from the
dictatorship that claimed lo represent them {Kronstadt, the Petrograd
strikes, the peasant uprisings of 1921). The result, in other words, was
a kind of permanent Jacobin dictatorship, a permanent ârevolutionary
dictatorship of the proletariat and the the peasantry,â rather than the
dictatorship of the proletariat or the triumph of the old reactionary
classes.
Thus, a deeper look at the third and best argument against my
proposition (the anti-bourgeois nature of Leninâs ârevolutionary
democratic dictatorshipâ) in fact reinforces my main point, that the
Bolsheviks advocated and sought to carry out a bourgeois revolution
throughout most of their history, and that this perspective remained the
Bolshevik de facto strategy even after the April Conference in 1917.
So, we return to our main starting point, F believe it is correct to say
that throughout the overwhelming part of its history prior to the
October Revolution, the Bolshevik faction /party advocated and planned
to carry out a bourgeois revolution and that, despite Leninâs new
perspective of 1917 and the discussions in the party, this never really
changed. Moreover, I would argue that the fundamental nature of the
party, its methods, ethos and style, were consistent with, if not
determined by, this. As we have discussed, the party was never truly
prepared to carry out a socialist revolution, not just in the sense of a
working class seizure of power but the construction of a true workers*
state; it never even had a serious discussion of the question.
More concretely, the partyâs advocacy of a bourgeois-democratic
revolution had to have affected its composition. How many people were
attracted to the party specifically because they wanted to carry out a
bourgeois-democratic, rather than a proletarian, revolution? (To put it
the other way around, how many people were alienated from the
Bolsheviks, as well as the Mensheviks, because of their insistence that
the revolution had to be bourgeois-democratic; how many people joined
the various populist organizations, such as the SRs, or the anarchists,
because these advocated a full socialist, or âsocial,â revolution?)
How many people joined the Bolsheviks because they were basically for
economic growth and industrialization, which they perceived to be the
way to solve Russiaâs poverty and backwardness, and never gave two hoots
about a truly worker-run society? How many people were attracted merely
by the thought of having power and prestige, something that was totally
closed off to them in Tsarist Russia? How many had their vision of
socialism distorted, at the very least, by the failure of the Bolsheviks
(and the Mensheviks) to elaborate a conception of a revolutionary
democratic socialist society? How many people joined the Bolshevik
Party, remained active in it through the October Revolution and the
Civil War, participated in the post-war reconstruction, and joined in
the persecution of Trotsky, only to perish at Stalinâs hands because
they were never clear about what was the difference between a workersâ
state and a dictatorship of revolutionary intellectuals believing they
are acting âin the interests ofâ the workers and peasants?
The point is not to try to answer these questions specifically. The
point is lo recognize that the Bolsheviksâ program, what it included and
what it excluded, had lo have had an impact on who was attracted to the
party, who remained with it, who got power in it, etc. If we keep these
questions and the point they imply in mind, we can begin to get some
answers to some of the questions raised in the First installment, such
as, how did Stalin get to be General Secretary of the Party? why was he
able to stand under Leninâs mantle? why did so few Bolsheviks oppose
him? etc., etc.
The answer, I think, lies in the recognition that the Bolsheviks
ultimately carried out what they had planned to ...a unique, very
radical type of bourgeois revolution.
THE subject of this article is the question of socialist consciousness,
the revolutionary party and the working class, and the relationship
among them. We will specifically focus on some of the conceptions put
forward in What Is To Be Done?, one of Leninâs most important writings
and a major âtextâ of Leninism/Bolshevism. It is true that Lenin
discussed the issues raised in What Is To Be Done? in other writings and
even wrote things that appear to contradict major ideas in the book. We
will lake up this question below, but for now, we will direct our
attention to What Is To Be Done?
To understand what Lenin is getting at in his book, especially in
relation to our chief interestâsocialist consciousness, the working
class, and the revolutionary partyâit is essential to understand the
context in which the work appeared, what Lenin was trying to accomplish
and what those who disagreed with him were saying.
What Is To Be Done?, published in early 1902, was a crucial part of the
debate among Russian Marxists over how to build a revolutionary party,
specifically, the Russian Social Democratic Labor Party (RSDLP), in the
Russian empire in the early years of the current century. To build such
a party was not so easy, since virtually all political activity, and
certainly anything liberal, let alone revolutionary, was outlawed.
Revolutionaries of all persuasions were subject to arrest, imprisonment,
and exile in remote, forbidding places.
At the time What Is To Be Done? was written, a revolutionary Marxist
party did exist, but only in name, in reality, the Russian Marxist
movement remained what it had been for nearly ten years, a melange of
local committees. These were mostly study circles and groups devoted to
carrying out âeconomic*â agitation, that is, distributing material
focusing on the workersâ wages, working conditions, etc., and supporting
various strikes. They were generally isolated from each other and
carried out their activities autonomously. In essence, the movement at
this time was a milieu, not a party.
Earlier, four years before What Is To Be Done? was written, an attempt
had been made to remedy this situation. At the so-called First Congress
of the RSDLP, held in Minsk in March 1898, a manifesto was adopted, a
structure was decided upon, leaders were elected and a decision to
publish a party newspaper was made. But the Tsarist political police
(the Okhrana) arrested (he participants of the congress soon afterwards
and, as a result, the state of the movement remained virtually
unchanged. (None of the nine delegates to that First Congress played a
major role in later Russian events.)
This attempt to organize a party occurred against the background of a
growing wave of workersâ strike activity. Beginning in the early 1890s,
the still small and very young working class in the Russian empire
launched strike struggles that eventually shook the major cities,
Working conditions were terrible: hours were dreadfully long, pay was
hardly existent, maiming accidents were common, the workers were subject
to fines for âpoor workâ and other infractions, the overseers were
brutal, etc. Spurred in part by an economic upturn in the 1890s,
desperate workers went out on strike to improve their conditions. These
strikes were âspontaneous,â insofar as they were not planned or led by
organized revolutionaries, although individual revolutionaries
undoubtedly look pan.
It was in (his situation that a young (25 years old) Lenin had played
his first major role in the Russian Marxist movement. In 1895 he and
Julius Martov, the future leader of the Mensheviks, put together a
22-person group that soon called itself the Si. Petersburg League of
Struggle for the Emancipation of Labor. Lenin urged his immediate
colleagues and other Marxists to orient toward the workersâ mass strike
movement, writing broad agitational literature directed at the workers.
(Prior to this, most Marxist activity had consisted of study circles
among a very small number of âworker-intellectuals,â some of whom
opposed the orientation to mass agitation.)
In December 1895 Lenin and nine others in the group were arrested and
tried. Lenin was sentenced to one year in prison followed by three years
in Siberia. He was released in January 1900 and went into exile in
Western Europe. There he met with the âfounding fathersâ of Russian
Marxism, specifically G.V. Plekhanov, Vera Zasulich, and Paul Akselrod,
in order to win them over to his plan to rebuild the RSDLP following the
disastrous aftermath of the First Congress.
Leninâs plan, first put forward publicly in some articles in 1900, had a
number of aspects. Probably most important, he proposed to rebuild the
RSDLP around an âAll-Russianâ newspaper. This was to be a newspaper
directed to all the nationalities and regions of the Russian empire, in
contrast to local journals directed toward single cities. This paper
would be written and published abroad, in the safety of exile, and
smuggled into Russia by various means. Such a newspaper would provide
the Marxists in Russia and those others who read it with a national (in
fact, transnational, since Russia consisted of many nations) point of
view, rather than a local one.
Equally, this All-Russian newspaper would provide the basis to build an
organizational structure, an apparatus, around which to rebuild the
RSDLP. Specifically, Lenin proposed [hat this apparatus focus on
smuggling the paper into Russia and distributing it to the workers and
other interested people. The nuclei of this network would be local
committees, all of whose members would be underground, that is, without
legal identity, and would be paid, meagerly to be sure, by the party.
This network/apparatus would be as centralized as possible and united by
an âiron disciplineâ (firm adherence to agreed-upon rules of operation).
Overall national (All-Russian) positions on various political and
programmatic questions would be determined by periodic delegated
congresses and, between these gatherings, by elected leaders living
abroad, not by local and regional committees.
Lenin was particularly concerned to build a strong, well-functioning
organization that could resist Tsarist repression. He attributed the
failure to build a party up to that point to what he considered the
âamateurishnessâ of the Russian Marxists, including parochialism, sloppy
methods, lack of a serious division of labor, etc. To counter this, he
called for âprofessionalismâ and a party of professional
revolutionaries. This was meant in two distinct but interrelated senses.
One was the general meaning of professionalâ using unified, tested
methods, training experts in various phases of revolutionary activity.
The second sense of âprofessionalismâ was narrower and quite literal. As
we noted, the party, at least initially, would consist exclusively of
underground operatives, full-time people, paid by the party and living
clandestinely.
An additional aspect or Leninâs strategy was that the All-Russian
newspaper, and the party as a whole, would emphasize what Lenin called
ââpolitical agitationâ: articles and exposes addressed primarily to
political, a$ opposed to âeconomicâ issues (wages, working conditions,
strike struggles), A focus on political questions, Lenin argued, would
tend to raise the workersâ consciousness from its current level (the
workers were, after all, already carrying out spontaneous strikes over
local âeconomicâ issues) to a higher, more political level, and at the
same time encourage them to think in terms of the whole Russian empire,
not just their own locality.
With the support of Plekhanov, Akselrod and Zasulich, Lenin, Martov and
V, Potresov launched this All-Russian newspaper, called Iskra (Spark) in
December 1900, and began to build a following, and an apparatus. A
companion theoretical journal, Zarya (Dawn), was launched in April 1901.
Of course, not all of the people, committees, etc,, in the Russian
Marxist movement agreed with Leninâs conception. To simplify, we can
note that the opposition to the ideas of the Zarya-ists focused on two
points. One was that the Iskra-ists ignored the âeconomicâ struggle â
the workersâ struggles over wages, working conditions, etc. The other
was that the Iskra-ist emphasis on centralized structure and
decision-making violated the autonomy of the local committees, (hat is.
that it was undemocratic.
We do not wish to debate here the merits and demerits of the
Lenin/Iskra-istsâ strategy nor of the arguments of their opponents. Our
concern is to sketch the context in which What Is To Be Done? was
written and within which its contents must be understood, What Is To Be
Done? was an attempt to defend the ideas behind the Iskraistsâ strategy
and to win supporters to it; a second congress of the RSDLP was being
planned for the following year and Lenin fell very strongly (as he did
about nearly everything), that the approach he advocated was the only
way to build, and maintain, a truly revolutionary Marxist party in
Russia. What Is To Be Done?, then, was both a defense of his
strategic/organizational conception for building the RSDLP and an
elaboration of it.
Typical of the Marxist polemics of this period (and most others),
Leninâs arguments about how to build the party are buttressed by
discussions of fundamental theoretical questions, such as the nature of
socialist consciousness and how it is created, to which we now turn.
(Incidentally, the name of the book, What Is To Be Done?, comes from the
title of a famous novel, written by the Russian populist N.G.
Chernyshevsky in 1362, considered one of the key manifestos of Russian
populist thought.)
For other purposes, the chief import of What Is To Be Done? is that it
elaborates a conception of the political consciousness of the working
class and how it develops, and the role of a revolutionary party in that
process, that had a fundamental, indeed defining, impact on the
development of Leninism/Bolshevism, Although, as we mentioned, Lenin
occasionally said other things about the question, the theory elaborated
in What Is To Be Done? represented a major ideological assumption of
Bolshevism, underpinning the Bolsheviksâ conception of the nature of the
party, its relationship to the working class, its strategy, tactics and
methods. This conception, moreover, remained central despite the various
changes in Leninâs/the Bolsheviksâ ideas. And, I would argue, this
conception has a fundamentally totalitarian/state capitalist
implication.
The relevant passage from What Is To Be Done? is as follows:
We have said that there could not yet be Social-Democratic consciousness
among the workers. It could only be brought to them from without. The
history of all countries shows that the working class, exclusively by
its own effort, is able to develop only trade union consciousness, i.e.,
the conviction that it is necessary to combine in unions, fight the
employers and strive to compel the government to pass necessary labour
legislation, etc, (Trade unionism does not exclude âpolitiesâ
altogether, as some imagine- Trade unions have always conducted some
political |but not Social-Democratic] agitation and struggle.) The
theory of Socialism, however, grew out of the philosophic, historical
and economic theories that were elaborated by the educated
representatives of the propertied classes, the intellectuals.
There are two distinct, but related, points here. One is that the
working class, by itself, meaning the mass of workers in the absence of
an organ nation of Marxist revolutionaries, is only capable of
developing trade unionist consciousness, e.g., understanding the need to
organize unions, 10 organize and strike for higher wages, better working
conditions and other benefits. By themselves, in other words, I he
majority of workers will not, and cannot, come to socialist conclusions,
that is, recognize the need to unite as a class and to rise up,
overthrow capitalism and build a socialist society.
The second key point is that âsocial democraticâ consciousness, what we
call revolutionary socialist consciousness, something developed and
maintained by socialist intellectuals, must be brought to the workers
from âwithout,â from a party that stands on these ideas, that is, a
Social Democratic Party.
Before proceeding to our discussion of the state capitalist implications
of these theses, it is worth making a number of preliminary comments
about them. First, these ideas were not unique to Lenin, As he himself
said, this was the conception of the major theoretical leader of the
international Marxist movement of that time, Karl Kautsky, Lenin,
seeking to convince the majority of Russian Marxists of his strategic
and organizational ideas, sought to justify them with arguments of the
most âorthodoxâ of Marxists. Whether or not ail, or even most, members
of the Social Democratic movement agreed with Kautsky is a different
matter. It was convenient to quote from the âPope of Marxism,â
Second, we doubt that Karl Marx would have agreed precisely with
Kautskyâs formulation. Although Marx well knew how much work socialist
intellectuals (particularly himself) had put into elaborating socialist
ideas and theory, I suspect he fell that what he had done was to
recognize, elaborate and put into writing something that was happening,
or would happen, independently of his consciousness, that is, among the
working class Itself, But this is a point for another, much larger,
discussion.
Third, there is some truth in what Kautsky/Lenin wrote. During
non-revolutionary periodsâ that is, outside of mass revolutionary
upheavals, most workers are not revolutionary socialist (we are
accepting, for the moment, the equation between âsocial democraticâ and
ârevolutionary socialistâ).
During ânormalâ times, most workers are trade unionist, if they are
that, and many workers may not even recognize that they are members of a
common social stratum, (In the U.S. most workers probably consider
themselves part of an amorphous âmiddle class.â) At best, only a small
number of workers consider themselves revolutionary socialists and they
are, by and large, outside the ongoing life of the majority of workers.
Insofar as they, along with middle class revolutionaries, convince other
workers to be revolutionary socialists, they are bringing socialist
consciousness to the workers â from without.â Even in revolutionary
periods, the revolutionary consciousness that many workers develop may
not be âtrulyâ revolutionary, in the Marxist sense. It might be
anarchist, anarcho-syndicalist. revolutionary populist, or some other
kind of consciousness that most Marxists have considered to be not
âproletarian.â
Fourth* a!though the conception that Lenin defends has strong state
capitalist/totalitarian implications* it does have a positive, that is,
democratic and even libertarian, aspect as well. (This is probably one
of the things that has helped obscure the state capitalist implications
for many people, including this writer.) This is the idea that
socialists should be open and straightforward about what they believe.
They should try to convince people (workers and others) to be
revolutionary socialists, openly and honestly. They should not hide
their ideas, pretend to be something else, and come up with some trick
or scheme that will convince people to be socialists in the absence of
dialogue and rational argument. In this sense, revolutionary socialists
do, and should, bring socialist consciousness to the workers. As Leon
Trotsky said, revolutionaries should âsay what is,â i.e., tell the truth
to the workers.
This is in contrast to other approaches which are, Tn fact, dishonest
and manipulative, One of these is the reformist approach Lenin argued
against in What Is To Be Done?, that if the workers are just encouraged
to fight reform struggles they will automatically come to socialist
conclusions. In this conception, there is no need for socialists to
argue openly and explicitly for (perhaps unpopular) socialist ideas, and
to convince people. Rather they should pretend to be simply âmilitant
unionistsâ or militant whatevers, that is, something other than what
they are. (In fact, if you cease to advocate socialism and function like
a reformist, you become a reformist, regardless of what you call
yourself.) Not only is this dishonest, it winds up strengthening
reformist ideas among the workers and building a reformist workersâ
movement, not a revolutionary one. In this sense Leninâs conception was
superior to that of his reformist (âEconomistâ) opponents.
Another approach which doesnât argue openly for socialism motivates many
people who pursue a terrorist strategy. People are asleep, this
reasoning often goes, numbed by the mass media, habit, fast food or
ârepressive desublimationâ (in the conception of Herbert Marcuse), and
the job of revolutionaries is lo wake them up. Hence, the use of bombs.
One doesnât argue for socialism, one tries to âgalvanizeâ the people.
Both these approaches* in failing to openly argue for socialist ideas,
failing to âbring socialist consciousness to the working classâ (using
these words loosely) are dishonest and manipulative. They too have a
state capitalist implication: the workers are too stupid to be
convinced; an elite has to trick them into fighting for socialism.
All this being said, we now turn to the question of the state
capitalist/totalitarian implications of Leninâs formulations on
socialist consciousness and the role of the party in What Is To Be Done?
By state capitalist/totalitarian implications we mean explicit or hidden
conceptions and/or tendencies that imply, point to, or justify state
capitalismâthe rule of an elite over the working class in the name of
socialism.
Perhaps the best way to approach this is to list a number of
interrelated ideas that follow from the What Is To Be Done?
formulations. If the workers are able, by themselves, to come only to
trade union consciousness, and socialist consciousness must be brought
to them from âwithout,â by revolutionary intellectuals/the revolutionary
party, then:
socialist intellectuals/the revolutionary party, not the working class.
state power is seized by the revolutionary party; the bottom line of
what constitutes socialism/the dictatorship of the proletariat is that
the slate is ruled by a revolutionary party.
the revolutionary party is right, and the party has the right, even the
duty, to rule âin the name of,â âin the interests of,â the working
class.
Prior to the seizure of power by a revolutionary party, these state
capitalist/totalitarian implications are not very clear; they represent
a kind of hidden potential. After all, the party is trying to âreachâ
the working class, carry out propaganda and agitation, form various
organizations, etc.âin general, trying to create socialist consciousness
among the workers. If the workers donât care to listen, if they refuse
to be socialists, the party remains relatively isolated and small.
Moreover, one can conceive, in theory, of a relationship between the
working class and the revolutionary party, during and after the seizure
of power, in which the party does not rule over the working class, but
provides the leadership for the class rule of the workers.
But things are always more complicated in reality than in theory.
Socialist theory, in particular, has a tendency to assume that the
workersâ âtrueâ or âappropriateâ consciousness (truly âproletarian
consciousnessâ) is socialist ideology. This leads directly to the idea
that once the working class becomes socialist, certainly once a working
class insurrection is carried out. the workers will not have any
fundamental disagreements with the revolutionary party.
But what if this isnât true? What if, after certain developments
following a workersâ insurrection, the workers no longer fully support
the revolutionary party? What if they cease being revolutionary? What if
they remain revolutionary, but their notion of being revolutionary
differs from that of the revolutionary party? What if workers and the
party remain in basic agreement, but develop strategic, tactical or
organizational differences, which in conditions of upheaval, can become
divisive and quite bitter?
In all these circumstances, the logic of Leninâs formulations in What Is
To Be Done? implies, points toward, and justifies, the rule of the party
over the workers. In other words, it implies, points toward, and
justifies state capitalism. In shorty the state capitalist/totalitarian
implications of these formulations can become explicit once a working
class insurrection takes place.
This is not inevitable. As we noted, one can conceive of a
democratic/socialist relationship between the working class and one
revolutionary party during and after the seizure of power. But a state
capitalist outcome is highly probable.
This is especially true if the party has been built around the idea that
it, and only it, is the true repository and guarantee of socialist
consciousness, and that every other political organization is, at
bottom, ultimately bourgeois and counterrevolutionary. Unless the
revolution goes almost perfectly and is beset by few obstacles (and this
is not likely), almost all the training and ways of thinking and acting
of its members will push that party toward ruling âin the name of,â âin
the interests of,â the working class.
In fact, the state capitalist/totalitarian implications of the ideas in
What Is To Be Done? go deeper than this. While What Is To Be Done? says
that the revolutionary intellectuals/the revolutionary party is the
source of socialist consciousness, it also defines the revolutionary
party as âprofessional revolutionaries,â the full-time party apparatus.
Adding this thought into the hopper, we get the additional implication
that the ultimate source, repository and guarantee of socialist
consciousness is the party apparatus, the functionaries. And, by logical
extension, after the seizure of power, the only guarantor of the
proletarian or socialist nature of the state is the rule of the party
apparatus, the bureaucrats.
This implies that when conflicts develop between the party and the mass
organizations of the working class {the workersâ councils (soviets),
factory committees, trade unions, workersâ militia, etc.). the party is
right and takes precedence. It has the right to make the decisions and
rule over the working class. And, in turn, when conflicts develop
between the party apparatus and other sections of the party, the party
apparatus is right and takes precedence. It has the right to make the
decisions and rule over the rest of the party (and, of course, the
working class). This is what happened in Russia after the October
Revolution.
One does not need to argue that Lenin explicitly held and defended the
state capitalist/totalitarian conceptions that are implied in What Is To
Be Done? (He probably thought that once the workers had become
socialists and had followed the party in carrying out the revolution,
the issue of the party ruling over the workers would never even arise.)
For now, all we need to note is that the formulations in What Is To Be
Done? do contain such implications.
In fact, Lenin elsewhere wrote things that implied the direct opposite
of the passages in What Is To Be Done? In an article called The
Reorganization of the Party, written in late 1905, just after the most
radical events of the (unsuccessful) 1905 Revolution, Lenin wrote: âThe
working class is instinctively, spontaneously social democratic,â (Once
again, this meant revolutionary socialist, since Lenin and the
Bolsheviks still called themselves Social Democrats). This article was
written to argue for admitting workers âat the benchâ (workers who had
normal jobs, like in factories) into the party, and reorganizing and
broadening the party accordingly, Lenin was trying to overcome the
resistance of some party members who were afraid that admitting members
who were not full-time, paid functionaries would dilute the
revolutionary character of the party.
That Lenin would write something the the sentence cited above during the
1905 Revolution makes perfect sense. There was a revolution going on and
the workers, without any help from the revolutionary organizations, had
become quite militant and revolutionary. (All the revolutionary
organizations, including the Bolsheviks, were small and relatively
marginal to the revolutionary goings on. Leon Trotsky played an
important role as chairman of the St. Petersburg soviet, but as an
individual figure, not as a member of a party-type organization.)
The Bolsheviks at this time were still organized as an underground
apparatus of professional operatives. Hence Leninâs proposal to open up
the party to ânon-professionals.â Hence, Loo, his argument against those
who resisted his proposal, in essence, âthe workers are already
revolutionary.â
Despite this article, the conception put forward in What Is To Be Done?
remained, I would contend, the dominant one among the Bolsheviks. What
Is To Be Done? was essentially the founding document of the Bolshevik
faction/party, with elaborate discussions of fundamental issues in
socialist theory and practice. The Reorganization of the Party was in no
way comparable; it was a minor piece. While we do not know for sure, we
can guess that new members of the Bolshevik faction/party were urged,
probably required, to read What Is To Be Done? soon after, maybe even
before, joining. Older members probably went back and reread it, to
refresh their memories. It is almost certain, however, that this was not
true of The Reorganization of the Party.
Maybe even more important, central leaders of the Bolshevik Party,
including many âOld Bolsheviksâ such as Joseph Stalin, were trained in
the ideas and practices of What Is To Be Done? Some went back to the
original Iskra period and the period from the Second Congress of the
RSDLP in 1903 to the 1905 Revolution. Others were trained in the years
after 1905â06 when the workers became politically quiescent and
conservative and all the revolutionary organizations shrank drastically.
The Bolsheviks, as much by necessity as by choice, became little more
than a professional underground apparatus, and sometimes barely this.
This remained the case roughly until the outbreak of the February
Revolution in 1917.
Later Bolshevik leaders, recruited and seasoned under these conditions,
would almost automatically agree with the conceptions in What Is To Be
Done? And all would be prone to act according to its implications
before, during and after the October Revolution.
The most convincing evidence of the impact of the state
capitalist/totalitarian implications of the ideas in What Is To Be Done?
is what actually happened after the October Revolution, particularly
during the Civil War. As we have mentioned the Bolsheviks centralized
all political power in their own hands. This included subordinating the
soviets, factory committees, unions, militias, and other mass
organizations {where these had not been disbanded) to their direct
control and âdiscipline.â These measures were certainly taken under
specific conditions, including internal counterrevolutionary uprisings,
foreign intervention, incredible devastation and poverty.
And perhaps the Bolsheviks would have preferred not to have taken them
(although many of the measures were praised, even glorified, by N.I.
Bukharin, the partyâs major theoretician).
Yet, the steps taken were totally consistent with the conceptions put
forward in What Is To Be Done? They were justified by leading
Bolsheviks, including the not very âOld Bolsheviksâ Leon Trotsky and
Karl Radek.
The party [is] entitled to assert its dictatorship even if that
dictatorship temporarily clashes] with the passing moods of the workersâ
democracy It is necessary to create among us the awareness of the
revolutionary, historical birthright of the party. The parry is obliged
to maintain its dictatorship, regardless of temporary wavering in the
spontaneous moods of the masses, regardless of the temporary
vacillations even in the working class. (Trotsky)
The Party is the politically conscious vanguard of the working class.
We are now at a point where the workers, at the end of their endurance,
refuse any longer to follow a vanguard which leads them into battle and
sacrifice. Ought we to yield to the clamours of workingmen who have
reached the limit of their patience but who do not understand their true
interests as we do? Their state of mind is frankly reactionary. But the
Party has decided that we must not yield, that we must impose our will
to victory on our exhausted and dispirited followers. (Radek)
And needless to say, these steps were warmly embraced by Stalin and
other âOld Bolsheviksâ who took the ball and kept running. Is this
purely a coincidence?
IN this article, 1 will discuss what might be called the âethosâ of
Bolshevism, By âethos,â I mean the overall outlook, attitudes and
styleâthe culture, roughlyâof the faction and party that has come to be
known as Bolshevik. âEthosâ is a somewhat vague term. Nevertheless,
there are certain fairly definite characteristics of the Bolsheviks,
both as individuals and as a tendency/party, and of their political
outlook, that can be discerned.
One of the most salient aspects of the ethos of the Bolshevik tendency
is what might be called the cult of the âhards.â The Bolsheviks prided
themselves on their toughness. They even referred to themselves as âthe
hards.â This was in contrast to what they derided as the âsoftnessâ of
the Mensheviks. As the Bolsheviks saw it, they were strong, tough and
unhesitating: the Mensheviks weak, soft and indecisive. The Bolsheviks
prided themselves on their skill in functioning âundergroundâ and on
their willingness to endure the hardships this entailed. They considered
the Mensheviks as less capable of working under conditions of
clandestinity and too anxious to function legally, no matter what
restrictions this entailed. The Bolsheviks also saw themselves as more
proletarian than the Mensheviks, whom they considered more middle class
(even when this was not strictly true).
Even more important, the Bolsheviks viewed themselves as being more
politically intransigent than the Mensheviks, more hostile to the Tsar,
landlords and capitalists, more suspicious of the bourgeois liberals.
This intransigence, or political âhardness,â referred both to political
stance and to the question of methods. In general, the Bolsheviks*
political program was more radical than the Mensheviks; they had a more
radical position on the agrarian question, one of the main issues in
Russia.
The Bolsheviks were also more willing to advocate and use violent
tactics. During the 1905 Revolution, for example, one of the Bolsheviks*
main emphases was on organizing armed fighting squads with the idea of
carrying out an armed insurrection.
In this cull of âhardness,â political position and personai style,
faction policies and personal characteristics, were considered
integrally connected, even if this was not true of every individual in
the faction. (For example, Grigorii Zinoviev, a leading Bolshevik, was
well-known among the Bolsheviks for his vacillating temperament and even
cowardice.)
However true or false this conception was in general, it did tend to
reflect the personal characteristics of the main leaders of the
Mensheviks and Bolsheviks, Yuri Martov and V.I. Lenin, respectively,
Martov appeared to be physically weak, somewhat slovenly, overly
cautious politically and an undisciplined thinker and speaker. Lenin, on
the other hand, gave the impression of personal strength and energy; he
was also neat, very decisive politically and an incisive thinker and
speaker.
The Bolsheviks* conception of themselves as the âhardsâ reflected their
ideal, or model. This was, as we discussed in our last article, the
professional, full-time revolutionary. He (and, by and large, he was a
he) was illegal. He lived and worked âunderground,â without permanent
home, hiding and often running from the police. He subsisted on very
little and could look forward to periods of jail and exile. He was
totally devoted to his work. He was a professional, a skilled operative.
Almost anybody who survived such an existence for any period of lime had
to be, or had to become, âhard,â or tough. (The Bolsheviks, by the way,
tended to wear black leather jackets and coats, which became kind of a
badge with them.)
There are two aspects of the question of âhardnessâ that are worth
noting. One is the question of âdiscipline.â This was meant both in a
political or party sense, and in a personal and Individual sense.
Discipline in the political sense meant a total commitment to the
principles and the policies of the party. Whatever one might think of
these, even if one had disagreements with the policies, or âline,â of
the party, one firmly defended them and carried them out. Raising oneâs
differences was reserved for specific periods, and even then, solely
within the party or faction. The Bolsheviks often used the term âiron
disciplineâ as something to strive for.
Another aspect of âdiscipline*â consisted of personal dedication and
single-mindedness. This included a kind of asceticism, a pride in being
able to do without luxuries and things most people take for granted,
including family and a social life.
This asceticism was not something we merely point to in hindsight; it
was explicitly held up as an ideal, Lenin was known for his frugality,
his lack of affectation and a willingness to live without luxuries. {He
did live considerably better than mast peasants and workers, however.)
Significantly, the name of Leninâs book What Is To Be Done?, as we
mentioned, was borrowed from the title of a book by N.G, Chernyshevsky.
Written in solitary confinement in 1862, this book was virtually the
bible of the young, mostly middie-class and upper-class radicals of the
1860s who âwent to the peopleâ (the peasants) to bring them
enlightenment and radical ideas. A striking figure in the book is a
young man, Rakhmetov. Of plebeian origins, Rakhmetov is a tower of
strength. He believes only in the cause and is totally devoted to the
âpeople,â Not least, he prepares himself for the coming struggle
(implicitly, a vast upheaval) by sleeping on a bed of nails and
otherwise toughening his body and mind. The connection between
Rakhmetovâs style and that of the Bolsheviks was no accident. Now, there
is much that is positive about the Bolsheviksâ stress on âhardness,â
both politically and personally. It is good for revolutionaries to be
radical, intransigent, decisive and loyal to oneâs organization and its
policies. It is also positive to be dedicated, skillful and willing to
endure hardships, lo suffer for the cause. âHardness,â in this sense, is
one of the things that enabled the Bolsheviks to survive the stresses of
Tsarist repression and the revolution, to lead the October Revolution
and prevail during the Civil War. Certainly, any serious revolutionary
organization needs a good dose of this.
Yet, âhardnessâ can be taken loo far. And a cult of âhardnessâ can lead
to serious distortions. On a minima! level, it can become a kind of
revolutionary puritanism which condemns even modest common comforts as
luxuries and frivolities, and sneers at people who want lo live normal
lives, not totally dedicated to the cause. It may also entail a
hostility toward the âloo openâ expression of the âpositiveâ
emotionsâlove, joy, happiness, etc. âand to a denigration of pleasurable
activities as âdecadentâ or âbourgeois.â It can thus become very
âmacho,â implicitly or explicitly looking down on women, gay people, and
on anything we might call sexual liberation.
A cult of âhardnessâ can also lead to a willingness to advocate, even
prefer, brutal, coercive methods, and to an insensitivity to human
suffering.
Had ââhardnessâ remained a question of individual style or altitude, or
had it been part of an ethos of a party that remained out of power, a
cult of âhardnessâ might not amount to much. What makes a cult of
âhardnessâ in a political organization potentially dangerous is the
possibility that it becomes part of a state ideology.
If a party priding itself on its âhardnessâ becomes the sole political
power in a state, the party may tend to impose its hardness on everybody
else. Then what started out as the personal puritanism of members of a
faction or party before the revolution becomes a kind of state
puritanism, imposed by the various means at the disposal of a state
afterward. The result can be regimentation and a punitive attitude
toward classes, groups and individuals who oppose or do not fully agree
with the goals and methods of the ruling party.
More generally, just as the âpuritan ethicâ of the 16^(th) and 17^(th)
centuries reinforced the capitalist dictum âaccumulation for the sake of
accumulationâ on the part of individual capitalists, so does a state
puritanism lend itself to the same dictum on the part of the state.
This, in fact, is the ethic of state capitalism.
Most ominously, a state cull of âhardnessâ can lead quite logically to
the idea that if brutal coercive methods are justified before and during
a revolution, they are also justified afterwards. But the ability to
utilize such methods will have been enormously increased, since the
party now has the vast power of the state (police, prisons, armies,
etc.) at its disposal. Thus, if it is okay to sacrifice individuals in
the name of the cause, it is also okay, and possible to justify
sacrificing even more people, perhaps whole classes, if it serves the
interests of the great cause of socialism and the liberation of
humanity.
Another aspect of the âethosâ of Bolshevism worthy of note is what can
be called a cult of centralism and centralization.
Generally speaking, the Bolsheviks strongly favored centralism over
decentralism, which they saw in a negative light. This attraction to
centralism had a number of roots, not all of which are clear. As an
organizational principle for their faction/party, the Bolsheviks
advocated what they called âdemocratic centralism.â This was, in fact, a
necessity largely imposed on them by the circumstances under which they
operated for most of their historyâ: they were an outlawed group,
subject to arrest, imprisonment, exile, etc., if caught. To build a
strong organization that could resist repression, that is, survive, they
adopted centralism.
Yet, the Bolsheviks revered centralism far beyond the necessities of
underground existence. They seemed to have considered it not only
stronger organizationally than decentralism but also inherently more
democratic. Some of the Bolsheviksâ reverence for centralism appears to
have come from their admiration of capitalist-industrial technique and
structure. One of their main criticisms of Russia was its backwardness
âwhat we would call the underdeveloped character of its economy. The
Bolsheviks saw the capitalist factory, run on a centralized basis, as a
progressive institution, technically speaking.
Lenin, for example, constantly held up the highly centralized and
hierarchical German postal system and German industry as a whole as an
example for the Russians to adopt. Thus, after the October Revolution,
Lenin defined the creation of a highly centralized economic apparatus as
a major goal of the Soviet state.
The organization of accounting, the control of large enterprises, the
transformation of the state economic mechanism into a single huge
machine. into an economic organism that will work in such a sway as to
enable hundreds of millions of people to be guided by a single planâsuch
was the enormous organizational problem that rested on our shoulders,
(Political Report of the Central Committee to the Extraordinary Seventh
Congress of the RCP(B), delivered March 7. 1918. Collected Works, Vol.
27. pp. 90â91.)
Leninâs commitment to, virtual adoration of, centralism can be seen in
his fairly frequent recommendation that the economy, revolutionary army,
and soviet state be âsubordinated to a single willâ {presumably his, but
that, for the moment, is not the point we are stressing).
Here it is worth citing a fairly long passage in order to get a
relatively broad feel of Leninâs thinking on the question.
...it must be said that large-scale machine industryâwhich is precisely
the material source, the productive source, the foundation of socialism
â calls for absolute and strict unity of wilt, which directs the joint
labours of hundreds, thousands and tens of thousands of people. The
technical, economic and historic necessity of this is obvious, and all
those who have thought about socialism have always regarded it as one of
the conditions of socialism. But how can strict unity or will be
ensured? By thousands subordinating their will to the will of one.
Given ideal class-consciousness and discipline on the part of those
participating in the common work, this subordination would be something
like the mild leadership of a conductor of an orchestra, II may assume
the sharp forms of a dictatorship if ideal discipline and class
consciousness are lacking. But be that as it may, unquestioning
subordination to a single will is absolutely necessary for the success
of processes organised on the pattern of large-scale machine industry.
(âThe Immediate Tasks of the Soviet Governmentâ written March-April,
1918. Collected Works, Vol. 27, pp. 268â269.)
In the previous paragraph, Lenin writes âThere is, therefore, absolutely
no contradiction in principle between Soviet (that is, socialist)
democracy and the exercise of dictatorial powers by individuals.â [P.
268.]
Thus, in Leninâs view, extreme, even absolute, centralization was far
from being antithetical to socialist democracy. It was perfectly
compatible with it, in some sense, its perfect embodiment.
(t is not my point, here, to prove that a commitment to centralism,
seeing it as an intrinsically progressive and even proletarian form, is
per se state capitalist. But it is fairly easy to see that a political
party whose commitment to centralism became virtually a point of
principle would resort to extreme centralist measures (backed by âiron
disciplineâ) to preserve what it considered to be the dictatorship of
the proletariat. It is also easy to see why such a party would not
recognize that extreme centralism would eventually destroyâby choking
off real workersâ control and democracyâthe proletarian state they
thought they were defending. And why, later on, such a party would
revert to extreme centralist measures as the main way to industrialize
the country.
Part of the Bolsheviksâ cult of centralism was an infatuation with
(economic) planning. To the Bolsheviks, and to all too many Marxists,
the essence of socialism is economic planning. This is in contrast to
capitalism which, on the whole, is chaotic, working through the free, or
partially free market.
But there is planning and there is planning. It depends on who is doing
it and how it is done. Todayâs Russian economy is supposedly planned,
bu! anyone who knows anything about how it actually works knows that it
is an unplanned mass of chaos. What is âplannedâ and what happens have
little relation to each other. Planning by a bureaucratic state
capitalist class that exploits the working class is not the same as
democratic, socialist planning by the workers. The Bolsheviks were never
clear about this and tended to conflate the two ideas.
Part of the responsibility for this rests with Marx and Engels
themselves. They contrasted the chaos and anarchy of the capitalist
market to the supposedly planned nature of production inside the
factory.
Perhaps a small factory, the kind that Engels managed for many years, is
really planned. But a huge capitalist combine, such as General Motors,
has many divisions, sub-divisions, bureaucracies, etc., competing for
resources, recognition, etc.. While more planned than the market, it is
not truly planned. Like the modem Russian economy as a whole, such a
firm is closer to marginally managed chaos than real planning. And to
the degree any given Factory is planned, such planning is based on
brutal regimentation. A whole society built around the bureaucratic and
hierarchical principles of a capitalist corporation would not be
planned; it would be a stifling, bureaucratic nightmare.
Like Marx and Engels, the Bolsheviks tended to equate socialist planning
with the planning typical of capitalist firms. Planning was to be done
by economic expense in a supposedly âscientificâ manner, based on the
complete nationalization (centralization) of industry. It was not
supposed to be a question of politics subject to discussion and debate
by the workers.
As a result, workersâ control of factories and industry as a whole,
which the Bolsheviks advocated during 1917, was seen by them as a
stepping-stone, a transitional measure, lo something else, something
âmore socialistâ: nationalization of industry and so-called âsocialistâ
planning. The Bolsheviks did not conceive of socialist planning as being
compatible with the direct workersâ control of the factories, which they
saw as an anarchist idea. They were therefore for âworkersâ controlâ
during 1917 only insofar as it led âfurtherâ (and because during and
after the February Revolution the workers had occupied the factories and
established their control).
Thus, as soon as they were able, the Bolsheviks subordinated the factory
committees to other institutions (the trade unions) and ultimately
effectively did away with them altogether. They were replaced by
âone-man management.â While this has often been explained as motivated
by necessity (the onset of the Civil War, the drastic decline of the
economy, etc.), and this is true to a degree, it was also totally
consistent with the Bolsheviksâ pre-existent ideas and leanings,
particularly their idolization of centralism.
As we have mentioned, one source of the Bolsheviksâ commitment to
centralism was a belief in the inherent progressiveness of bourgeois
technology. Bourgeois technology, and its corollary, industrialization,
were also virtual cult objects on the part of the Bolsheviks.
Although they were fiercely opposed to traditional capitalism,
capitalist corporations and banks and individual capitalists, the
Bolsheviks were extremely fond of bourgeois technology, particularly the
techniques of capitalist industry.
But their attachment was not limited to merely the industrial processes,
as suchâ technology in the narrow sense of the termâ but to the overall
methods and even structure of capitalist industry. This included the
centralization, the hierarchical structure of management, piecework and
other facets of {bourgeois) âscientific managementâ (e.g., Taylorism).
Lenin actually believed that the overall structure and methods of
capitalist industry could be taken over, in total, by a proletarian
state. To Lenin, all that mattered to make this type of structure
proletarian was that it be controlled by a state based on soviets. Thus,
in May, 1918, Lenin wrote:
Here (in Germany) we have âthe last wordâ in modern large-scale
capitalist engineering and planned organization, subordinated to
Junker-bourgeois imperialism. Cross out the words in italics, and in
place of the militarist. Junker, bourgeois, imperialist state put also a
state, but of a different social type, of a different class content â a
Soviet slate, that is, a proletarian state, and you will have the sum
total of the conditions necessary for socialism. {ââLeft-wing*
Childishness and the Petty Bourgeois Mentality,â Collected Works, Vol.
27, p. 334.)
(It is worth noting that many of the arguments in Leninâs articles and
speeches we have cited, as well as others from the period, were intended
to refute those, both outside the Bolshevik party and inside it, who
disagreed with the course Lenin advocated. This is an indication that
not ail Bolsheviks agreed with Lenin, and that the specific aspects of
the Bolshevik ethos we have been discussing do not comprise the sum
total of Bolshevism.)
Lenin did not see that industrial technique, organizational structure
and methods are not purely scientific questions, politically neutral; he
did not realize that they have a definite class content. Specifically,
Lenin did not recognize that the German industry, and capitalist
industry as a whole, of his time, was a thoroughly bourgeois institution
in every facet. Merely subordinating a capitalist economic apparatus to
soviets (assuming the soviets are controlled by the workers), does not
automatically make the appparatus proletarian. It has to be thoroughly
revolutionized by the workers themselves.
It is understandable why the Bolsheviks would consider bourgeois
industry to be progressive in and of itself. From their position within
Tsarist Russia, the main problem was the poverty, ignorance, disease,
etc., of the workers and peasants. And this, it appeared to them, was
caused primarily by the economic, political and cultural backwardness of
Russia. Within this context, capitalist technology and capitalist
managerial techniques, etc., were easily seen as progressive per se.
What Russia needed, so it seemed, was a thorough-going economic
transformation, a basically capitalist industrialization.
This was one motivation for the view they held throughout most of their
history that the revolution on the order of the day in Russia was a
bourgeois one, not a socialist one. And, as we saw in the second
installment in this series, the main goal of this revolution would be to
dear the way for the fullest development of capitalism in Russia.
When the Bolsheviks altered their strategy in April, 1917, and oriented
themselves toward a working class revolution and the establishment of
what they saw as a proletarian dictatorship, their commitment to
bourgeois technology â industrial methods and managerial structureâdid
not really change. They felt: 1) since industry, etc., was now
controlled by a soviet government, that is, a workersâ slate, it ipso
facto served the interests of the working class (and peasants), 2) the
main task within Russia was to build up the industrial apparatus and the
economy in general, to industrialize the country. This would lay the
material basis for establishing socialism and, eventually, communism.
As a result, they became even more committed to the centralization,
hierarchy and discipline of capitalist industry, and paid no attention
at all to developing a system of direct working class control over the
economy. If anything, the fact that this industry was now under their
control, which they assumed meant the control of the working class, led
them to discard whatever objections to centralization, hierarchy and
dictatorial management they might have have had.
The Bolsheviks did not merely justify these steps by citing the
intensification of the economic crisis and [he onset of the Civil War in
1918. They also advocated, justified anti defended them as a point of
principle, as steps toward socialism. One of N.I. Bukharinâs main
theoretical works written during the Civil War, The Economics of the
Transition Period, was a virtual hymn to centralization, And Bukharin
was the Bolsheviksâ major theoretician.
Here we can see a direct basis for both the aims and the methods of
Stalinâs program of forced industrial teat ion. Once it became clear
that the post-war wave of workersâ revolutions had been defeated, and
since the working class as a whole had âshownâ that it lacked the
revolutionary will (the Kronstadt uprising, the Petrograd general
strike), it seemed logical that the chief task of the party was to force
the workers and peasants to industrialize the country.
Based on bourgeois technology and centralized planning,
industrialization, Stalin thought, would create abundance, the material
basis for communism, thus opening up the road to the next stage of human
society. But with the workers and soon the peasants deprived of any
control over the means of production, the cults of centralism and
bourgeois technology and, as we will soon discuss, coercive methods,
left them subordinated, exploited and decimated. Given Stalinâs
assumptions, many of which were taken over from Bolshevism, the result
was, and could only have been, a state capitalist industrialization.
An additional feature of the Bolshevik ethos was a belief in the
efficacy, even desirability, of coercive, brutal methods. I mentioned
this above in the section on the cult of hardness, but there are
additional points to be made.
When I refer to the Bolsheviksâ attraction to coercive methods, 1 am not
just repeating the standard bourgeois reproach of Marxism that â(he end
justifies the means.ââ (In fact, (he capitalists themselves believe that
the end, e.g., profits, the defense of capitalism, does justify the
means â injurious working conditions, the death penalty, chemical
warfare, nuclear weaponsâbut this is too long a discussion to embark
upon here.) Nor do I reject violent methods in total, I am not a
pacifist. In general, I accept Marxâs conception that a revolution
necessarily entails violence, but by and large this is, or should be,
the violence of the overwhelming majority against a very small minority
of exploiters and their agents. So, the problem is not one of
coercion/violence in the abstract.
There seems to me to be two issues involved. The first is whether those
who are resorting to coercive measures are aware that using them entails
a cost: that they can undercut the goal they are purportedly being used
to reach, and that at some point such measures can actually preclude the
reaching of that goal.
What I am getting at is that brutal methods tend to demoralize and
dehumanize those who employ them. It seems to me that if we seek to
build a more humane society than capitalism, then we should always
attempt to use methods that are more, rather than less, humane than
those of the capitalists.
The other issue involved in the question of the use of coercion/
violence by revolutionaries is: against whom are the coercive measures
directed? If the vast majority of workers and other oppressed people use
violence against the capitalists and their hangers-on, that is one
thing, if a relatively small minority of revolutionaries winds up
employing brutal methods against large numbers of workers, etc., then
this is something else.
All this being said, I would argue: 1) that the Bolsheviks were overly
inclined to advocate coercive/brutal methods, in general; 2) that they
seemed to be unaware that this might undermine the very goal they
claimed to be fighting for; and, 3) that, at least implicitly, these
coercive measures would logically wind up being directed against
members, even large sectors, of the working class, whose vanguard the
Bolsheviks claimed to be.
Since this is such a strong charge {and a charge typically raised by
opponents of socialism), it is worth citing some passages from Leninâs
writings and speeches to substantiate it, The three 1 have chosen were
written or spoken in April and May of 1918, This was after the October
Revolution but before the onset of the Civil War (which was really to
get underway in June, 1918).
In this period, the new Soviet government, consisting of the Bolsheviks
and the Left Social Revolutionaries, was faced with fairly rapid
economic decline and [he onset of social and economic chaos. The
government had also recently signed the onerous Brest-Litovsk treaty
with the Central Powers, which had entailed the loss of a great deal of
Russian territory and industry. We say this both to give the context of
Leninâs comments as well as to present them in the best possible light.
In âLeft-wingâ Childishness and the Petty Bourgeois Mentality (May 5,
1918 Collected Works, Vol. 27, p, 344) Lenin wrote: âAnother thing is
that the courts are not sufficiently firm, Instead of sentencing people
who take bribes to be shot, they sentence them to six monthsâ
imprisonment.â
Here. Lenin is demanding that people who take bribes be shot.
The death penalty for taking bribes certainly appears very harsh to me,
especially since it is not ipso facto an act of active
counter-revolutionary behavior.
Even more important, it is worth recognising that at this point in the
Russian Revolution, bribe-taking was pandemic to Russian society. (The
normal practices of peacetime had been greatly extended by the World
War, the revolution and a devastating economic crisis.) To shoot all
those who accepted bribes would be to execute a hell of a lot of people,
not all of who were actively counterrevolutionary or even bourgeois.
Moreover, it is reasonable to assume that Lenin thought similar
punishment should be meted out to other âpeople who infringe the
measures passed by the Sovietsâ (quote from the same passage). Well, by
this time, the soviets had outlawed private trade. But with the
breakdown of the economy, and the little time since the seizure of
power, the state trade network was very new and extremely inefficient.
In fact, it hardly existed. In this situation, many ordinary workers and
peasants engaged in private trade just to survive. So we can see that
Lenin is advocating, however implicitly, shooting a very, very large
number of people.
Perhaps Lenin thought such âfirmâ measures would actually suppress
bribe-taking. If so, he was only deluding himself. In conditions of
extreme scarcity and chaos, people will do what they have to do to eat
and feed their families, even if they face the supreme penalty if
caught. They did so in Russia.
So, here we see an example of Leninâs preference for brutal methods,
coupled with a belief in their effectiveness. Not only is his choice of
methods excessively brutal, it also entails coercion against workers and
peasants, not just a handful of oppressors. Even more frightening, such
measures have a tendency to create enemies of [hose who use them.
Thus in the above example, as I have indicated, most of those who look
bribes or engaged in private trade were not counterrevolutionaries. At
most, to use Bolshevik terminology, they were only âobjectivelyâ
counterrevolutionary.
But, I would argue, shooting people engaged in bribe-taking or private
trading is the surest way lo turn those not yet caught into âsubjectiveâ
counterrevolutionaries, And this is indeed what happened.
Beginning in the summer of 1918, the Bolsheviks âbrought the revolution
to the countrysideâ* (as they called it), and began the forced
requisitioning of grain front the so-called middle and rich peasants.
This measure turned millions of peasants against the new Soviet regime,
led to a vast contraction of cultivated land and food production, and a
consequent famine, and resulted in a bloodbath in the countryside.
Of course, the Bolsheviks were not solely to blame for this. The White
armies were probably even more brutal than the Bolsheviks, But the
Bolsheviksâ policy of trying to suppress all private trade shared a
great deal of the responsibility for what happened. It also made it
virtually certain that the vast majority of peasants would be, and would
remain, deeply hostile to the Bolshevik regime.
(The Bolsheviksâ agrarian policy, as well as others pursued by the
Bolsheviks in the early years of the revolution, is discussed and
criticized by the basically pro-Soviet Russian dissident historian, Roy
Medvedev, in his recent book, The October Revolution.)
Another passage from Leninâs writings and speeches in this period
illustrates the problem even more clearly.
In his speech in the Moscow Soviet of Workersâ, Peasantsâ and Red Army
Deputies, of April 23, 1918, Lenin said:
This country, which the course of history has advanced to the foremost
position in the arena of the world revolution, a country devastated and
bled while, is in an extremely grave situation and we shall be crushed
if we do not counter ruin, disorganisation and despair with the iron
dictatorship of the class conscious workers. We shall be merciless both
to our enemies and to all waverers and harmful elements in our midst who
dare to bring disorganisation into our difficult creative work of
building a new life for the working people. [Collected Works, Vol. 27,
p. 233.]
Here, two points are worth stressing. First, not only arc the Bolsheviks
to be âmercilessâ toward their enemies, they will also be so toward
âwaverersâ and âharmful elements in our midst.â âWaverersâ and âharmful
elementsâ arc very broad words and, in the circumstances of the time,
probably encompassed a lot of people.
And Lenin is not only threatening (at least implicitly) many ordinary
workers and peasants with Bolshevik mercilessness (probably execution),
he is also threatening those elements within the Bolshevik Party who
disagree with the need for this kind of âmercilessness.â This is merely
the broad version of Leninâs demand to shoot those caught taking bribes
and engaging in private trading.
Second, in this passage, Lenin advocates the âiron dictatorship of the
class conscious workers.â Here, in Leninâs mind, Marxâs conception of
the dictatorship of the proletariat (a dictatorship of the entire, or
almost the entire, working class), has become the dictatorship of part
of the proletariat, the âclass consciousâ workers, who are, by Leninâs
definition, the members of the Bolshevik Party.
And the task of these workers is to impose their âiron dictatorshipâ not
only on class enemies (capitalists, landlords, Tsarist officers, etc.),
but also on those workers who are not class conscious, as the Bolsheviks
define such consciousness. That is, on those workers who do not agree
with what they are for. That is, the rest of the working class.
Right here is the theoretical blueprint for what was to exist by the end
of the Civil War in early 1921. By that time, the Bolsheviks had imposed
their âiron dictatorshipâ on the rest of the working class, supposedly
in the interests of that class. But these workers did not agree about
who represented their true interests: in March, 1921, to show their
opposition to Bolshevik âmercilessness,â they paralyzed Petrograd, the
capital, with a general strike.
The next passage (a short one), I wish to cite poses Leninâs attitude
toward the question of methods quite succinctly. It is also from
âLeft-wingâ Childishness and the Petty Bourgeois Mentality,
â...we must not hesitate to use barbarous methods in fighting
barbarism.â (P. 340.)
To me, this pretty much sums up the issue underlying all the questions
we have been discussing. It sums up all too much of what I have called
the Bolshevik âethos.â And, it sums up what was, and I think could only
have been, the logical outcome of a revolution led by a party with that
âethos.â For, it seems to me, if one sets out to use barbarous methods
to fight barbarism, the result can only be...barbarism.
The main point I have been trying to establish is that there were many
aspects of the style and culture of the Bolshevik Party that pointed in
the direction of stale capitalism. These were tendencies that implied
the establishment of a dictatorship of a self-proclaimed socialist elite
over the workers and peasants âin the interests of* those classes and
âin the name ofâ socialism and communism.
It is not that objective conditionsâpoverty, the destruction of war and
revolution, political isolationâdid not play a part in the establishment
of such a dictatorship. They certainly did. But what the Bolsheviks
thought and did (and did veryâ aggressively), greatly contributed, in
the context of those conditions, to that same outcome.
For example, if one effect of the objective conditions is to undermine
(he institutions of workersâ control over the economy and state, then
what the Bolsheviks did in the context of those conditions worked to
further those tendencies rather than to counter them.
Moreover, once the dictatorship of the Bolshevik Party had been
established, it is not clear to me that, even had there been successful
workersâ revolutions in Western Europe, the Bolsheviks would have
reestablished real proletarian democracy, including legalizing other
left tendencies. Nor is it obvious that, given their infatuation with
centralization and âscientificâ planning, they would have tried to set
up real workersâ control of the factories and the economy as a whole. In
the past, 1 used to think so, Today, I am not so sure.
In sum, I believe that the Bolshevik ethos, and particularly the
mind-set of Lenin, its creator and major leader, was laced with
tendencies, altitudes and conceptions that pointed in the direction of
state capitalism. Even if they do not add up to state capitalism
entirely, they certainly helped lay the basis, and provided the
justification, for the direction Stalin took after Leninâs death.
In conclusion, let me quote, once again, from Leninâs writings from the
spring of 1918- (We have already cited a part of this passage.)
White the revolution in Germany is still slow in âcoming forth,â our
task is to study the state capitalism of the Germans, to spare no
effort, in copying it and not shrink from adopting dictatorial methods
to hasten the copying of it. Our task is to hasten this copying even
more than Peter (Tsar Peter the GreatâRi) hastened the copying of
Western Culture by barbarian Russia, and we must not hesitate to use
barbarous methods in fighting barbarism.
With or without the objective conditions, this looks to me like a recipe
for state capitalism.
THIS installment of our series on Leninism will focus on The State and
Revolution. Written in the summer of 1917 during the Russian Revolution
itself, this is one of Leninâs most important works.
In many ways, this installment is the most difficult for me to write.
The State and Revolution was one of the first, if not the first, of the
works of Lenin I ever read. This relatively small book had a profound
effect on a teenager coming of age in the early â60s.
While my family was radical (the word used then was âprogressiveâ), The
State and Revolution convinced me to become a Leninist and to want to be
a professional revolutionary âwhen I grew up.â Here, it seemed to me,
was a revolutionary and democratic vision worth devoting my life to. t
read The State and Revolution at least once a year for many years
thereafter.
And in many ways, The State and Revolution is Leninâs most libertarian
work. Here was Lenin breaking decisively with the reformist and statist
conceptions of the Second (Socialist) International, demanding a return
to the much more radical ideas put forward by Karl Marx in his writings
on the Paris Commune. Here was Lenin elaborating a notion of a
revolutionary society based on soviets (workersâ councils) and other
institutions of direct workersâ rule. Here was Lenin emphasizing that
the ultimate goal of proletarian revolution is the withering away of the
state.
For many years, The State and Revolution was the foundation stone on
which I elaborated my politics. It was what I pointed to in arguing
against liberal and reformist positions. It was what I used as the
starting point for fighting my own (and othersâ) illusions in the
so-called âsocialist countries.â And it was what I kept coming back to
in an attempt to develop a revolutionary, democratic conception of
socialism that remained within the overall framework of Leninism (via
Trotskyism, for example),
It was also the one work of Leninâs in which I had the most difficulty
discovering what I have been calling âstate capitalist tendencies.â The
book seemed so revolutionary, so anti-state, that for the longest time I
could not see any foreshadowings of Stalinism/state capitalism in it. It
was probably this, as much as anything else, that prevented me from
recognizing the role that Lenin (and Leninism) had in creating Stalinism
and state capitalism. After all, if Leninâs vision of 1917 was as
democratic and anti-state as it seemed, then it seemed logical to blame
what happened in Russia on âobjective conditionsâ â and on Stalin. That
is, on anybody and anything but Lenin.
Yet, recognizing the state capitalist tendencies in The State and
Revolution is crucial to coming up with a realistic assessment of
Leninism, if Leninism is significantly statist, it ought to be apparent,
or at least discernible, in this book. If it is not, then perhaps
Leninism isnât as statist as the anarchists, anti-authoritarians and
libertarians contend.
The often heard argument from many anarchists, libertarians, etc., that
Lenin stole the ideas in The State and Revolution from the anarchists
only muddies the waters, it accepts that the book is a truly libertarian
document and then avoids a serious analysis of how Lenin, the
arch-statist, could come up with it by claiming that he really didnât.
A meaningful analysis would at least attempt to show the different
degrees of continuity and discontinuity between The State and Revolution
and Leninâs other works. It would also analyze the circumstances that
would induce Lenin to write such a work and, most important, would
attempt to elucidate whatever slate capitalist tendencies are present in
the book, however modest or hidden they may be.
On its own terms, the argument that Lenin lifted much of The State and
Revolution from the anarchists seems implausible to me, I do not mean to
deny the possibility that Lenin might have been influenced by anarchist
ideas in this period (he certainly began to see the ulterior motives
behind the reformistsâ attacks on anarchism). But I donât think this
tells us much. Unfortunately, Lenin had little but contempt for
anarchism, the anarchist movement and anarchist thinking: he generally
debunked it as a form of petty bourgeois ideology, whatever he might
have thought of individual anarchist militants.
The genesis of The State and Revolution is more reasonably explained by
(wo factors:
World War I caused Lenin to take a very critical look at what had been
considered âorthodox Marxismâ at the time. In this rethinking, involving
a reading of some of the works of the philosophical forerunner of Marx,
G.W.F. Hegel, Lenin broke out of the mechanistic siage-ism of Social
Democracy.
He began to see Russia as a part of a world capitalist system that was
suffering a serious global crisis. This opened him up to the idea that
the Russian Revolution need not be limited to a bourgeois-democratic
stage until the victory of one or more socialist revolutions in Europe
and led him to think in terms of a worker-led revolution in Russia that
would be the first battle in an international socialist revolution.
revolutionary government that would emerge from it, was suggested by the
course of the class struggle itself. By the time Lenin arrived in Russia
in early April 1917, the workers and soldiers had not only
(spontaneously) toppled the Tsar. They had also set up mass democratic
institutions (soviets, factory committees, etc.), and were, to a
considerable extent, running Russian society through them. Between his
theoretical reconsiderations of basic questions of Marxism and the
imposing reality of the achievements of the Russian workers, Lenin did
not need to borrow, or steal, from the anarchists, to come up with The
State and Revolution, In my opinion, then, The State and Revolution is
the organic result of the development of Leninâs thinking. That it is as
libertarian as it is is a reflection of the libertarian impulse in
Marxism and the even greater libertarian impulse of masses of workers
attempting to carry out a social revolution.
Despite all this, however, there are state capitalist tendencies in The
State and Revolution. And those who want to evaluate Leninism from a
libertarian point of view ought to be able to reveal them and analyze
them.
One reason The Stare and Revolution appears to be so libertarian is that
it proclaims that the main goal of Marxists is the establishment of a
stateless and, of course, classless society. The goal of the socialist
revolution, Lenin insisted, was the establishment of communism, a
society without social classes and without a state of any kind. Nor was
this meant to be in the far distant future. Because of the world crisis
of imperialism, this goal was an immediate, practical one.
This may seem obviously Marxist to those who have read Marx and Engels.
But at the time, Leninâs assertion was seen as quite radical because the
Socialist International had quietly shelved such ideas (reserved for May
Day speeches, at best) as part of the âutopian â and unrealistic dreams
of Marx and Engels in their younger years. The actual goal of Social
Democracy was increasingly a democratic capitalist welfare stale. For
Lenin to resurrect and even to emphasize Marx and Engelsâ radical and
apparently anti-statist vision (and to call attention to the fact that
this was expressed as âlateâ as 1871 in Marxâs writings on the Paris
Commune) was almost heretical.
Despite how anti-statist the call for a revolution to establish a
classless and stateless society may sound, a careful reading of The
State and Revolution shows that the book is not nearly as anti-state as
it seems. In fact, it is quite pro-state, but in a hidden sort of way.
The source of this paradox is the notion of the withering away of the
state. In Marxist theory, the state, after a successful socialist
revolution, is not abolished. It withers away: it disappears gradually.
This flows, supposedly, from the very nature of the form of government
established by a successful proletarian uprising. The proletariat rises
up, smashes the old bourgeois state, and builds a new state based on
workersâ councils and other democratic institutions of the working class
and other oppressed classes. The job of this state is primarily to
defeat counterrevolutionary attempts, to complete the destruction of the
bourgeois slate, to finish suppressing the capitalist class and other
oppressor classes, and to draw the masses of workers and other oppressed
people into the day-to-day management of society. To the degree these
tasks are accomplished, and relative scarcity, the material basis of
class society and the state, is overcome, there is no need for such a
state and it will gradually wither away.
This flows from the nature of the state itself. Under class societies,
such as ancient slave systems, feudalism, capitalism, etc., the state is
an instrument of a tiny minority to maintain its rule over the exploited
majority. Given the disparity in the sizes of the oppressor and
oppressed classes respectively, this task requires a large and elaborate
apparatus ultimately based on coercion and consisting of âbodies of
armed men, prisons, etc.â
The stale after a successful proletarian revolution, on the 01 her hand,
is not an instrument of a tiny minority over the vast majority, but the
reverse. It is a weapon of the vast majority to suppress the former
ruling and exploiting minority. Thus, as its tasks are completed, it no
longer has any purpose and gradually disappears.
While this seems to make sense, in fact it contains a number of
fallacies. In order to SCO them, it is worth considering what this
conception of the nature of the revolutionary stale and its eventual
withering away means in terms of the tasks facing revolutionaries. In
other words, how would revolutionaries holding to this theory of the
slate and Its eventual elimination think of what they should do during
and after a revolution?
The practical application of this theory, it seems to me, is that the
key job of revolutionaries after a successful proletarian revolution is
not to do away with the state, but to build a new one. Moreover, in
order to suppress the bourgeoisie and the other exploiters most
efficiently, this state should be as strong and alt-embracing as
possible. Finally, since this new âproletarianâ state will âinevitablyâ
wither away once the exploiters and counterrevolutionaries are
suppressed and the workers are drawn into administering society, there
is no need to safeguard the workers, the revolution or the
revolutionaries themselves from âtheir ownâ state.
This is the crux of the paradox I mentioned above. The very
revolutionaries who claim that they are against the state, and for
eliminating the state, who say they are the only ones who can do away
with the slate, etc., see as their central task after a revolution to
build up a state that is more solid, more centralized and more
all-embracing than the old state.
This, it seems to me, is the key problem with The State and Revolution
and, in fact, the entire Marxist theory of the state. In this theory,
the key goal for one of them), the elimination of the state, supposedly
happens by itself; it is taken care of by the âhistoric process,â Human
beings donât have to worry about it; what they have to worry about is
building up a new state.
But what if the historic process doesnât work out as Marx and Engels and
Lenin thought it would? What if, instead of withering away, the
revolutionary slate sticks around? What if some individuals or groups of
individuals in powerful positions in that slate decide they donât want
the state, and their power, to wither away?
The result, even under optimal conditions, is likely to be a
ârevolutionaryâ society governed by a large, power fill and omnipresent
stale apparatus, which is justified by the absurd notion that the
purpose of such a state is to eliminate the state, We call this state
capitalism.
On one level, the underlying fallacy in the theory of the state put
forward in The State and Revolution can be described by the common
phrase âIt looks good on paper, but...â In other words, it is wishful
thinking; it assumes the best.
On a somewhat deeper level, the problem is the belief that the theory
has captured the full reality of the state, its essence, purpose, and
historical direction. And since the theory declares that the âlogicâ of
this essence, purpose and historical direction is that the state will
eventually be eliminated, ânegated,â âtranscendedâ via a âdialecticalâ
(apparently contradictory) process, this is what will inevitably happen.
The fallacy, in other words, is that the theory has reduced historical
development to a (dialectical) logic that it declares to be inevitable,
even if this may not be so.
Those who detect a criticism of Hegelian thinking here are correct. In
my view, the Marxist theory of (he state and its eventual withering away
is essentially Hegelian. Although Man: and Engels felt that they had
broken decisively with their philosophical mentor, the Marxist world
viewâfrom its conception of history, to Capital to its underlying
philosophical outlookâis fundamentally Hegelian, And even though Marx
and Engels described their viewpoint as a materialism, in contrast to
Hegelâs idealism, their world view remained, in my opinion, as
idealistic as Hegelâs, although unconsciously so.
The so-called âlaws of history,â as expressed in âhistorical
materialism,â are a kind of logic, or thought. And it is this logic that
ultimately determines human history. This is idealism.
Marx and Engels, or maybe just Engels, occasionally described what they
had done as turning Hegel on his head, or standing an upside-down Hegel
on his feet. But Hegel turned upside down or right side up is still
Hegel.
Leninâs (and Marx and Engelsâ) theory of the state, to repeal, is based
on the notion that the (dialectical) logic of the slate (and of history)
guarantees that (he slate under a revolutionary society will disappear.
But what if this dialectical logic is too neat? What if this view of the
state (and history, human society, etc.), ignores or defines our of
existence other aspects of the slate (and history, human society, etc.),
that are not reducible to logic {even dialectical logic)? If, however
brilliant it might be, the theory is not 100% correct {and no theory can
ever be 100% correct), the stage might just be set for Marxist
revolutionaries, fervently believing Marxist theory, and organized in an
extremely disciplined and well-organized party, to create a
âdictatorship of the proletariatâ that might not wither away as it was
supposed to.
1 think this is, at least in part, what happened after the October
Revolution. The Bolsheviks sought to build up a strong state apparatus,
based on the soviets, trade unions and factory committees. Convinced
that the stronger, more efficient and more centralized this apparatus
was, the easier it would be to smash the old state and ruling classes,
defeat the counterrevolutionary attempts and draw the workers into
administering society, and convinced that once these tasks were
accomplished and other revolutions had succeeded in the West, the state
would wither away, the Bolsheviks gave no thought to the other,
supposedly higher goal of doing away with the state. Although they
proclaimed their goal to be the elimination of the state, their de facto
goal was to build a new, more efficient, more centralized one. They
succeeded.
The point is not that the workers and other oppressed people should not
build up a strong set of organizations during and after a revolution to
manage the economy and society, defend their gains and suppress the
exploiters, etc. But they also need to take steps to prevent a new state
from arising and oppressing them. That is, they need to figure out
concretely how they arc going to build a stateless society.
The Marxist theory of the dictatorship of the proletariat, as elaborated
in The State and Revolution, âarmsâ the revolutionary party with the
need to build up a new, revolutionary state, but it disarms the workers
about the need to fight against a new state forming.
At this point (if they havenât already), someone will protest that
Lenin, citing Marx, talks about the dictatorship of the proletariat
being a state of the armed workers, the proletariat organized as the
ruling class, a state that is already beginning to wither away, a state
that is already in the process of becoming a non-state, etc.
Yes, someone else will say, and he also included detailed discussions of
various measures to maintain the workersâ control over their state, for
example, having the soviets combine legislative and executive powers,
having the workersâ delegates be subject to immediate recall, having all
mate officials receive no more than an average workerâs salary, etc.
This is certainly true, although how detailed these discussions are and
how effective the measures proposed would be can be disputed (leaving
aside the question of whether the Bolsheviks ever seriously tried to
implement them).
The problem, however, is not that Lenin gave no thought to how the
workers might control the new state apparatus, but that his very
conception of that apparatus was bourgeois. In the previous installment
of this series, I discussed Leninâs infatuation with bourgeois
technology, centralization, technocratic planning, etc. Lenin seemed to
assume that capitalist industry, managerial techniques, etc., were
class-neutral, that is. that what made them bourgeois was that they were
controlled by the bourgeoisie and were used to further its interests.
He therefore assumed that after a revolution, the workers could lake
over this industry, technology, etc., more or less as is, and put it to
work for themselves. Ail that was necessary, he thought, was that the
workers needed to be able lo control it (although by 1915, in my
opinion, he seemed to think that control by the Bolshevik party was
sufficient to guarantee working class control; in 1922â23, he seems to
have changed his mind, but by that time it was too late).
It did not occur to him that capitalist industry, technology, managerial
techniques, etc., are bourgeois through and through, in their very
structure. The same mistake is apparent in The State and Revolution.
To be specific: as we know, Lenin was very impressed with the German
postal system and believed that its class content did not reside in its
form of organization, but in the fact that it was subordinated to a
landlord-Junker state. This idea appears in The State and Revolution. It
is worth citing a passage at some length:
A wise German Social-Democrat of the seventies of the last century
called the postal service an example of the socialist economic system.
This is very true. At the present the postal service is a business
organised on the lines of a state-capitalist monopoly. Imperialism is
gradually transforming all trusts into organisations of a similar type,
in which, standing over the âcommonâ people, who are overworked and
Starved, one has the same bourgeois democracy. But the mechanism of
social management is here already to hand. Once we have overthrown the
Capitalists, crushed the resistance of these exploiters with the iron
hand of the armed workers, and smashed the bureaucratic machine of the
modem state, we shall have a splendidly-equipped mechanism. Freed from
the âparasite,â a mechanism which can very well be set going by the
united workers themselves, who will hire technicians, foremen and
accountants, and pay them all, as indeed all âstateâ officials in
general, workmenâs wages. Here is a concrete practical task which can
immediately be fulfilled in relation to all trusts, a task whose
fulfillment will rid the working people of exploitation To organise the
whole economy on the lines of the postal service... all under the
control and leadership of the armed proletariatâthis is our immediate
aim. This is the state and this is the economic foundation we need.
(Collected Works, Vol. 25, pp. 426â7, emphasis in original.)
Reading this in light of everything that has happened in the state
capitalist countries (and refusing to give Lenin the benefit of the
doubt, as I used to do), I find this passage truly frightening. Lenin
wanted to organize all society along the lines of the German postal
system, replete with bourgeois technicians, foremen, etc., under the
illusion that this structure could be effectively controlled by the
workers. Even if all the measures Lenin proposed were implemented, this
apparatus would eventually wind up dominating the workers rather than
the other way around.
This is because the apparatus itself, the way it is organized, its
structure, its mode of operation, etc., is bourgeois (the German postal
system was probably partly feudal). And as it operates, it reproduces
bourgeois social relations within it; this is the very condition of its
operation. Even granting Lenin the best intentions, an entire society
built along the lines he is describing looks more like a bureaucratic
nightmare than a society moving toward eliminating the state.
Unfortunately, this was the model Lenin and the Bolsheviks used to
reorganize Russian society in the spring of 1918 and after. It explains
why they subordinated the factory committees to the trade unions, why
they instituted one-person management, why they built a standing army
with traditional discipline, officered by Tsarist generals, etc., etc.
You cannot blame this all on the economic crisis, the counterrevolution,
the revolt of the Left SRs, etc. While the specific measures may have
been determined by these objective conditions, the overall bent, the
overall orientation, is present in The State and Revolution, written
when Lenin was optimistic about the Russian Revolution and the
international revolution.
A few other passages from The State and Revolution will help to flesh
out Leninâs vision of the revolutionary state/society.
âUntil the higher phase of communism arrives, the socialists demand the
strictest control by society and by the state over the measure of labour
and the measure of consumption...â (Page 470, emphasis in original.)
According to Lenin, the âvital and burning qustion of present-day
politicsâ is: âthe expropriation of the capitalists, the conversion of
at! citizens into workers and employees of one huge syndicateâ the whole
state...â (Page 470.)
A few pages later Lenin predicts: âThe whole of society will have become
a single office and a single factory....â (Page 474.)
To be sure, Lenin always emphasizes that the âcontrolâ must be exercised
ânot by a slate of bureaucrats, but by a state of armed workers.(page
470), that the work of the âsyndicateâ be completely subordinated âto a
genuinely democratic stale, the state of the Soviets of Workersâ and
Soldiersâ Deputiesâ (page 470), etc., etc.
But the point made earlier about the German postal system applies here
as well, if the institutions of the revolutionary society, such as the
economy, are organized along what are essentially bourgeois lines (one
huge factory, one huge office, with foremen, accountants and bourgeois
technicians), then that society will remain bourgeois. Ft will be only a
matter of time before the bourgeois social relations, continually
reproduced and reinforced within the very heart of society, will
undermine the control of the âarmed workersâ and the âSoviets of
Workersâ and Soldiersâ Deputies.â
At its best, the workersâ control that Lenin talks about is entirely
external to the apparatus. But if the workers continue to live and, even
more important, work in an environment, in a structure, that is
bourgeois, their own activity and their consciousness will revert to
being bourgeois. Although true social liberation cannot be achieved all
at once, it cannot be compartmentalized either.
If the workers arc to control the post-revolutionary society, they have
to control it at all levels, especially at the immediate levels of their
own lives. Lenin seems to believe the workers can continue to work under
what are essentially bourgeois conditions while somehow exercising
control over this bourgeois apparatus. This is, at best, wishful
thinking.
Although 1 think the theoretical point has been made, I cannot resist
the temptation to point out what kind of vision these passages suggest.
Although Lenin talks in democratic terms, his conception is very
hierarchical and very regimented. There is virtually no room for
individual difference and creativity, let alone people just goofing off-
With the whole of society organised as one big factory and one big
office, liberation is defined as being a disciplined member of an
industrial army.
This jibes with the infatuation with economic growth and modernization
that i discussed in our last installment as being central to the
Bolshevik ethos. It also points directly toward Stalinâs commitment to
industrialization âby any means necessary.â It is not yet, not
explicitly, as inhumane as Stalinâs, but it certainly gels the ball
rolling in that direction.
This brings me to the next slate capitalist aspect of The State and
Revolution that I wish to discuss here. This is the fact that although
Lenin talks about workersâ control, winning the battle for democracy,
the proletariat organized as the ruling class, uniting legislative and
executive functions in individual governing bodies, etc,, nowhere in the
work do we get an idea that the workers will discuss, decide and carry
out political decisions. If anything, Lenin seems to think that after
the revolution, the questions facing the workers will be overwhelmingly
administrative.
Accounting and control â that is mainly what is needed for the âsmooth
working.ââ for the proper functioning, of the higher phase of communist
society, (Page 473.)
When the majority of people begin independently and everywhere to keep
such accounts and exercise such control over the capitalists {now
converted into employees) and over the intellectual gentry who preserve
their capitalist habits, this control will really become universal,
general and popular-... (Pages 473â4.)
From the moment all members of society, or at least the vast majority,
have learned to ad minister the state themselves, have taken this work
into their own hands, have organised control over the insignificant
capitalist minority, over the gentry who wish to preserve their
capitalist habits and over the workers who have been thoroughly
corrupted by capitalismâfrom this moment the need for government of any
kind begins to disappear altogether. (Page 474. emphasis in original)
Throughout this lengthy passage, and throughout The State and Revolution
as a whole, there is no mention of the need for the mass of workers to
make political decisions. The workersâ tasks, it seems, are
predominantly to suppress and/or âcontrolâ the Former capitalists, the
gentry, etc., and to âkeep accounts.â These are basically administrative
tasks. Somehow, political decisions, political discussion and debate are
absent. Lenin seems to assume that once the dictatorship of the
proletariat is established, political discussion â political debate,
political conflict, politics period â is transcended, (Either that or
political decisions are reserved exclusively For the revolutionary
party, the truly class conscious workers.)
As with much of The State and Revolution, it is not obvious that Leninâs
conception is undemocratic. It looks democratic: he talks of workersâ
control, workers administrating the state, a state of the armed workers,
etc., etc., but the meat, the contentâworkers directly and immediately
running society, workers, not bourgeois specialists and political
leaders, making the political and economic decisions â is just not
there.
This helps to explain one of the outstanding features of The State and
Revolution, in this case an omission. There is no discussion of the
revolutionary party in this work, let alone of a multiparty system. 1
think this is very significant.
After all, Lenin spent most of his adult life building, or trying to
build, a revolutionary party. Building such a party was the central
strategic task of revolutionaries short of carrying out a successful
working class revolution. In fact, the existence of such a party was,
for Lenin, the necessary condition for such a revolution to succeed.
Moreover, it is the revolutionary party, we will remember, that is the
source and guarantor of socialist consciousness. Without the party,
Lenin wrote in What Is To Be Done?, the working class can only attain
trade unionist, reformist consciousness. For Lenin to omit a discussion
of the revolutionary party in as central a work as The State and
Revolution means something.
There are, among others, two plausible explanations for this. One, Lenin
felt that the revolutionary party would continue to exist and lead the
workers. Indeed, its authority would be undisputed, owing to the success
of the revolution, etc. Two, Lenin felt that the party would not be
needed and would dissolve.
I personally feel that the first explanation is the likely one. Given
Leninâs entire conception of consciousness and leadership, I do not
think he could conceive of the dictatorship of the proletariat without
the âleading roleâ of the revolutionary party.
But on some level, it really doesnât matter which explanation is more
plausible because they both imply the point made earlierâin Leninâs
conception the mass of workers do not make political decisions, either
because they are reserved for the party (the workersâ delegates can
âdiscussâ and approve party decisions in the soviets), or because they
no longer need to be made.
It is tempting to belabor this point, to try to prove it rather than
just suggest it. But I donât think it can be proven directly. Those who
fed that Lenin believed in true workersâ democracy, where the workers
discuss and carry out the political and economic decisions of society,
will read The State and Revolution in that light. After many readings of
the book, and much thought, I do not believe Lenin believed in what we
would call workersâ democracy. Direct workersâ control over the
factories and workersâ democracy are, to Lenin, stepping stones, part of
a transitional stage, toward a very abstract âhigher democracy,â what is
in fact a very centralized, hierarchical, bureaucratic, regimented
âdictatorship of the proletariat.â
This point can perhaps be better made the other way around. Lenin docs
not seem to recognize that the socialist revolution must involve, at its
very core, a change in social relations, a change in how people relate
to each other. This change has to start right from the beginning; it
cannot be delayed until some indefinite point in the future, say, the
so-called âhigher phaseâ of communism.
Under capitalism, people by and large relate to each other in a
competitive, alienated manner. Cooperation exists, of course, but it
tends to be subordinated to the competitive, hierarchical structure and
ethos of capitalism. Social ism is a society in winch cooperation â
people helping each other, trying to work together, trying to live
together â becomes predominant. People still compete, but this
competition is primarily constructive, it remains within the framework
of people cooperating.
During a revolution, the new. cooperative social relations have to begin
appearing among the workers and oppressed classes right away. The
workers have to learn how to relate to each other in this new way. They
learn this through reorganizing their work situations, and through
directly governing society at all levels, They have to learn how to
manage all of their affairs through cooperation. And they (we) can only
learn this by doing it directly.
This dimension of the socialist revolution seems to be totally lost on
Lenin. The socialist revolution, in his conception, is largely a change
in form. But much of the content of the old societyâbourgeois
technology, bourgeois managerial techniques, hierarchical structures,
factory discipline and, I would suggest, bourgeois social relations â
remains.
In fact, the whole human dimension is lacking from The State and
Revolution. True, Lenin is writing theory and theory is abstract. But
somehow his theory about what ought to be one of the profoundest
transformations of human society, of human social relations, of the
human personality is disturbingly flat, non-human. At times, Lenin seems
to get excited, but his vision is so abstract that it ail rings hollow
to me, at least now.
I suspect that this flatness reflects a far deeper problem in his
thinking and in much of Marxist theory in general. Somehow, people,
concrete human beings, are not quite real. The real reality is the
social and historical categories, social classes, states, forces and
relations of production, modes of production.
These categories may or may not be useful in analyzing history and human
society. But they are not themselves that history, that society, that
human reality. Human beings (and human history) cannot be reduced to
purely logical categories. They are more complicated than that, This is
what makes them interesting, unique, lovable, hateable, etc. And itâs
what makes human beings and human societies ultimately unpredictable-
Without this unpredictability, without the special dimension of people
that cannot be reduced to categories, to abstractions, there is no bfe.
The fundamental fallacy of The State and Revolution, much of Marxism and
much of most of what passes for sociology and social theory, then, is
that it takes itself too seriously. It believes that the abstractions,
the categories, the theories are the real reality, and the concrete, the
non-reducible, is some kind of epiphenomenon, something derivative and
not quite real. These theories may or may not be true (meaning, roughly,
approximately true), but they are not the reality. Concrete people,
concrete historyâlifeâis the reality,
Seeing Marxist theory as the underlying reality, Lenin, in The State and
Revolution and elsewhere, conceived of a vision of the revolutionary
society I hat constrains human beings and human life within what arc
ultimately dead abstractions. With a fundamental approach and mindset
like this, is it any wonder that the movement Lenin buiit and ted
created a society that squelches out life in the interest of dead
structures, categories and ideology?
By way of conclusion, I want to repeat a point Iâve made periodically. I
am not trying to prove that everything Lenin did or wrote is
undemocratic, state capitalist or totalitarian. Nor am I suggesting that
Lenin willfully, knowingly, was an undemocratic person (like, say, Adolf
Hitter, who knew exactly what he was doing). I think Lenin saw himself
as being very democratic, very committed to workersâ rule, etc. Yet, his
underlying conception and vision of the dictatorship of the proletariat,
or a worker-run society, were undemocratic.
A lot of the reason for this had to do with the fact that he was a
product of his lime and place; backward, undemocratic Russia of the late
19^(th) and early 20^(th) centuries, with a tiny, very young working
class surrounded by millions of illiterate peasants, etc. Part of the
reason had to do with Leninâs own upbringing and personality.
But I think most of the reason for Leninâs ultimately undemocratic
vision was his belief that Marxism was a science, which, to him, meant
that it was absolutely true. If the theory is True, and it says that a
workersâ revolution and a workersâ society will take such and such a
form and do such and such a thing, then there is no place for real
democracy. Since it is all inevitable, there is no room for choice or,
if there is choice, it is the prerogative of those who understand the
Science, who have access to the Truth, that is, the revolutionary party.
This will be the theme of the next installment.
IN this installment of our series on Leninism, I propose to take up
Leninâs conception of human knowledge and truth.
This is a complicated subject which would be very difficult to write
about even if I were an expert. Since I am not, and since I am writing
to an audience made up of readers with different levels of philosophic
(and other) knowledge, and since 1 am writing a newspaper article, not a
hook, my task is not easy. I say this by way of an apology right at the
outset: 1 am sorry if my discussion is not as lucid as it might be.
However, I really have no choice but to make the attempt to explain
these matters since I believe they are the heart of the problem this
series is meant to Investigate.
And this is, to repeat, to what degree is the theory and practice of
Leninism responsible for the establishment of state capitalism in
Russia? Or, putting the question somewhat differently, what aspects of
the theory and practice of Leninism point to, or presage, state
capitalism?
Contrary to my usual procedure, I will slate my conclusions first,
I am convinced that Lenin and the Bolshevik Party as a whole
believed: 1) that there is an absolute truth (I mean by this that
reality is determined and predictable); 2) that absolute knowledge, that
is, perfect knowledge of that truth, is possible; 3) that such truth and
knowledge exist in respect to human society and history; 4) that Marxism
is the knowledge of this truth; and 5) that within Russia, Lenin and the
Bolsheviks were the only real Marxists.
I am also convinced that these propositions are the philosophical
foundation of state capitalism, that they, when combined with the
Marxist call to carry out its program through the seizure of state
power, point directly to the establishment of state capitalism. I do not
insist that a party holding to these or similar propositions wilt
inevitably create state capitalism, only that if it does seize stale
power, it is highly probable that it will.
If there is one and only one (political! truth, and if your party, by
virtue of its ideology and program, is the sole possessor of that truth,
then you are not going to think very highly of political debate,
political pluralism, and the right of other parties and organizations to
exist, organize themselves and openly propagate their views. You might
not always be against these things, but they wilt never be the top
priority.
Since you already have the truth, politically and otherwise, you donât
need a dialogue/debate with other forces to obtain it. And if you have
seized power and things gel rough, political pluralism and debate will
seem like downright luxuries that can, and should, be done away with, if
âonly temporarily,â Which, to a great degree, was done by the Bolsheviks
under Leninâs leadership, not Stalinâs, in Russia.
! do not contend that Leninism and Marxism are the only world views that
hold to notions of absolute truth and knowledge. Probably most people in
the worldâcertainly in the West â believe in absolute truth and
knowledge, in the sense that there L? an absolute truth, and absolute
knowledge of that truth, at least in some domains, is possible.
I am also not arguing that a belief in absolute truth and knowledge
necessarily equals a totalitarian ideology. Albert Einstein, the author
of the theory of relativity, believed that the uni verse is
deterministic, (hat is, that there is an absolute truth in respect 10
the structure of the universe. He also believed that science is capable
of comprehending it, in other words, that an absolute knowledge of that
structure is possible. Yet, Albert Einstein was one of the least
totalitarian-minded people of lit is century.
I do suggest, however, that the belief in absolute truth and knowledge
is the kernel of a totalitarian ideology and that every world view or
ideology based on such a belief has a totalitarian potential.
The chief Western religions, Judaism, Christianity and Islam, are good
examples. They are al! based on a belief in both absolute truth and
absolute knowledge of this truth (not that they are always internally
consistent about this). And they all contain totalitarian
potentialities.
Look at Islam, not only in Iran, whose current rulers hold to a
particularly fundamentalist version of that religion, but elsewhere,
book at Judaism, not only right-wing fanatics, such as Meir Kahane, but
also mainstream Zionism. Look, too, at the fundamentalist Christian
groups in the U.S. which, taken as a whole, are very large, very rich
and very powerful and scare me to death: they want to impose their very
narrow and reactionary ideology on everybody in the country.
Not least, look at the Catholic Church. For a variety of reasons, the
totalitarian potential of Catholicism (which, as such, is neither
greater nor less than that of Protestantism, Islam or Judaism} is
particularly apparent. Catholicism has a dictator (the Pope, Godâs
representative), a very defined and narrow dogma and regulations, from
which dissent is not allowed (Pope John Paul II reminded U.S. Catholics
of this in his recent tour), a huge political apparatus, including
courts and a secret police.
In the past, the Church also attempted to set up actual totalitarian
societies. In Western Europe during the Middle Ages, it came quite close
to doing so, at least as close as one could get given the limited
technology available. It owned between 1/2 and 1/4 of the land and
exploited thousands of serfs. It imposed a nearly complete ideological
(religious) monopoly on the entire society. Jews were sometimes
tolerated (under special restriction), but often massacred, as during
the Crusades, Pagan traditions were snuffed out or coopted. And the
Inquisition, in its various versions, investigated, exposed, tortured
and killed heretics.
In fact, the Church, under the aegis of the arch fanatical Jesuits (the
Society of Jesus), did build a totalitarian society in Paraguay, where
it ruled over and exploited large numbers of the indigenous people (in
the interests of their salvation, of course).
These examples suggest, at least to me, that the belief in absolute
truth and knowledge is the underlying core of totalitarian worldviews.
In and of itself, however, such a belief does not necessarily add up to
totalitarianism, in order for a world view to be such, it must also
believe that absolute truth and knowledge are possible in respect to
human society, that is, economics and politics, that it (the particular
world view} itself embodies the sole knowledge of that truth, and that
this world view, and an economic, political and social program
reflecting it, should be imposed on society.
Although 1 believe all these characteristics pertain to Leninism, I
would particularly like to focus on one, Leninâs conception of truth and
knowledge.
Lenin, like most people of his day, believed in absolute truth and
knowledge, that is, that the world has a definite, determined structure,
and that precise, absolute knowledge of that truth is possible. He wrote
an entire book devoted to defending this proposition (although he hedged
his words), along with his interpretation of dialectical materialism,
which he considered to be the philosophy of Marxism.
The book is Materialism and Empirio-criticism, published in 1909, and it
is this work that I wish to discuss at some length.
Materialism and Empirio-criticism was written as a polemic against
Anatoly Bogdanov and Aleksandr Lunacharsky, two Bolsheviks who were
attracted to the ideas of Ernst Mach and Richard Avcnarius, Henri
Poincare and other scientists, mathematicians and philosophers who were
the precursors of a school of philosophy called logical positivism.
Bogdanov and Lunacharsky had been interested in the ideas of Ernst Mach
(the most influential of these thinkers) for some lime and in 1903
published a book that contained contributions from Mach and others.
Lenin went to London in that year, spent a lot of time studying the
literature and came out with Materialism and Empirio-criticism the
following year.
Although Lenin had expressed concern about Machâs influence earlier In
the decade, his decision to write a book attacking him was motivated
primarily by internal Bolshevik factional politics. (When Bogdanov and
Lunacharsky agreed with Leninâindeed, for a while they were his main
stalwartsâyou can be sure he did not publicly attack them for
philosophical heresy. It was only when they disagreed with him that he
did so. What this means about Leninâs methods I will leave to the
readerâs interpretation.)
The circumstances of the dispute were these. In the aftermath of the
Revolution of 1905, which was defeated, a great demoralization set in
among the working class and the revolutionary movement. The Bolsheviks
were not unaffected by this. Like the other groups, they lost their mass
base, were hit by mass defections and dwindled away almost to nothing.
The Bolsheviksâ underground apparatus almost ceased to exist.
During this period, Lenin sought to take advantage of whatever scraps of
legal activity the Bolsheviks could engage in. One of these was running
for and participating in the Duma, a semi-legislative body, elected in a
highly indirect and undemocratic manner, that Tsar Nicholas II had
conceded at the height of the revolution.
At first, Lenin opposed running in the elections for the Duma and
participating in its deliberations. The Mensheviks, who were still in
the same party, generally favored participation. Later, when it had
become dear that the revolution was over and a reactionary period had
sot in, Lenin changed his mind and wanted the Bolsheviks to participate
to gain whatever space for conducting revolutionary agitation this
allowed, no matter how limited.
Within the Bolshevik faction, Lenin was isolated, opposed by his former
allies, including Bogdanov and Lunacharsky. (There were a variety of
tendencies among the Bolsheviks on this issue. Some favored an
out-and-out boycott of the elections and the Duma itself. Some favored
participating in the elections, but then, after presenting some kind of
ultimatum, walking out. Later some wanted to recall the delegates that
had been elected. But the differences are not very significant, at least
not today.) Since Lenin fell strongly about the issue, the discussion
was heated.
In addition to their âboycottism,â Lunacharsky and Bogdanov, along with
others, including (he writer Maxim Gorky, were playing around with
creating a kind of proletarian religion, as a way of competing with the
established churches for the minds of the demoralised workers.
Lenin opposed this âGod-building,â along with âboycottism.â Writing
Materialism and Empirio-criticism was thus a convenient way to discredit
Bogdanov and Lunacharsky. It was also a good way lo defend what he saw
as Marxist orthodoxy and thus firm up the faithful during a particularly
rough period.
Although Materialism and Empirio-criticism is directed against a number
of thinkers, I would like to focus on Ernst Mach (1838â1916), since he
was probably the most important of Leninâs targets.
Mach was an Austrian scientist and philosopher, and the author of a
number of well-respected books on such topics as dynamics and optics.
Like most physical scientists of his day, Mach was particularly
concerned about a number of contemporary developments that violated the
strictures of the accepted physics of his era. In fact, these
developments were to lead to the collapse of the entire edifice of
classical physics (built up over a period of over three hundred years),
and a conceptual revolution in science, exemplified by the theories of
relativity and quantum mechanics.
Machâs proposal to deal with the developing crisis was to radically
apply what has long been a fundamental postulate of scientific thinking
â economy of thoughtâe.g., a simple theory is better than a complex one;
if a particular idea is not essential to explain something, discard it;
the less speculation the better, etc. (The French mathematician and
scientist Laplace, when asked by Napoleon why he had not included God in
his theory of planetary motions, replied that he âhad no need of that
hypothesis.â)
Mach proposed to take this dictum as far as possible, doing away with
all conceptions that were not capable of direct experimental
verification. He was, in fact, skeptical of all scientific laws, which
he considered at worst to be improvable metaphysical speculations, and,
at best, convenient devices for organizing data that the human mind was
too lazy to remember in any other way,
Mach was particularly critical of theoretical mechanical models, such as
the etherial continuums that were then used to explain the phenomena of
light, electricity and magnetism. Insofar as he accepted scientific
laws, these were mathematical/statistical models, such as the laws of
thermodynamics, which establish general relationships among observed
phenomena, without necessarily entailing a specific model of what
actually happens on the micro level.
Mach, for example, never accepted the atomic theoryâ of matter, since he
couldnât see atoms and their existence had not yet been experimentally
demonstrated. In this, he was to be proven dreadfully wrong.
However, Mach also rejected the idea of absolute space and time, a
fundamental tenet of classical (Newtonian) physics. The young Albert
Einstein was a follower of Mach and even though he eventually abandoned
Machâs approach, Mach had a profound influence on the development of the
theory of relativity. (Ironically but consistently, Mach never accepted
that theory.)
Philosophically speaking, what Machâs approach entailed was to establish
immediate sense experience, that is, what we sense, in the most
immediate and narrow terms, with our eyes, ears, senses of taste, smell
and touch (and, by extension, through experimental apparatuses), as the
only basis of real knowledge, the only reality that we are justified in
accepting or discussing. Since one canât truly know anything beyond our
immediate sense data, it is futile, indeed self-indulgent, to try to
conceptualize it.
The idea, however, leads to, or implies, that there is no reality beyond
what our senses immediately perceive. This, in turn, implies that being
and perceiving are inextricably linked. Put another way, Machâs approach
implies (hat nothing exists unless it is perceived, that there is no
objective reality separate and apart from a perceiving subject.
Now (his, in its essence, was the position of the Anglican Bishop,
George Berkeley, an 18^(th)-century cleric and philosopher, who based a
proof of the existence of God on it, (Nothing exists unless it is
perceived. Since there are clearly things that continue to exist when
human beings cease to look at them, this is the proof that there exists
an omnipresent perceiverâa mind that perceives everything, that is,
God.)
(It is worth noting, before we go on, that the idea that being and
perception are inexorably linked, that at least on the subatomic level
the act of perception determines to some degree what is being perceived
isârightly or wrongly, philosophically-spikingâa fundamental conclusion
of the most widely accepted interpretation âthe so-called âCopenhagen
interpretationââof quantum mechanics, one of the chief pillars of 20ih
century physics,
(It is also worth noting that in contemporary theoretical physics,
mathematical models have replaced mechanical ones. This is particularly
true of atomic physics: Werner Heisenberg, a major figure in (he
development of quantum mechanics, wrote in 1945: âThe atom of modem
physics can be symbolized only through a partial differential equation
in an abstract space of many dimensions. All its qualities are
inferential; no material properties can be directly attributed to it.
That is to say, any picture of the atom that our imagination is able to
invent is for that very reason defective,â [Quoted in A History of the
Sciences, by Stephen F, Mason, p, 502.]
(In short, whatever we may think of the philosophical implications of
Machâs ideas, they have become far more influential in 20^(th) century
science than Lenin could have surmised.)
The implied logic of Machâs ideas that I have sketched was, in fact, the
main target of Leninâs attack on him and the other âEmpirio-criticsâ
(the term was Avenariusâ) in Materialism and Empirio-criticism. Machâs
assertion that all (hat we can know is the immediate data of experience
(only the factsâ are real), Lenin argued, leads directly to the
rejection of objective reality (a reality that exists independently of a
perceiving subject âa fundamental proposition of Marxism) and to the
philosophy of Berkeley and religion (what Lenin calls âfideism,â from
Latin for âfaithâ). If one gives one inch of ground to (he ideas of
Mach, Avenarius and the others, Lenin insists, one abandons dialectical
materialism in favor of one or another variety of idealism and bourgeois
philosophy.
I believe Leninâs specific critique of Machâs position is basically
valid. Yet, in attacking Mach, Lenin goes too far in the opposite
direction. Where Materialismâs scientific laws only a pragmatic,
militarian validity (i.e., they are convenient for organizing the facts
or data), Lenin sets up scientific laws as virtually absolute, as
directly reflecting (or corresponding to) objective reality. Despite
many caveats and obfuscations, in other words, Lenin argues for the
possibility of absolute knowledge.
A careful reading of one of the key passages of Materialism and
Empirio-criticism will show this, the following paragraph (from VI.
Lenin, Collected Works, Vol 14, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1968, p.
326) is a kind of summation, a brief statement of what Lenin is
advocating in Materialism and Empirio-criticism and elsewhere:
Materialism in general recognises objectively real being (matter) as
independent of the consciousness, sensation, experience, etc., of
humanity. Historical materialism recognises social being as independent
of the social consciousness of humanity. En both eases consciousness is
only the reflection of being, at best an approximately true (adequate,
perfectly exact) reflection of it. From this Marxist philosophy, which
is cast from a single piece of steel, you cannot eliminate one basic
premise, ore essential pan, without departing from objective truth,
without falling a prey to a bourgeois-reactionary falsehood.
To me, the most striking thing about [his passage is its dogmatism.
Immediately after writing that consciousness (and hence, knowledge) can
only âat bestâ approximate âbeingâ (reality), Lenin pens what can
essentially be paraphrased as âand if you question one phrase of what I
have written here (that is, my interpretation of Marxism), you are
wrong, have departed from âobjective truthâ and are promoting
âbourgeois-reactionary falsehood.ââ In other words, while
consciousness/knowledge in general may be only approximately true,
Marxism (rather, Leninâs interpretation of it) is absolutely true. And
Materialism and Empirio-criticism as a whole is written to discourage or
prevent any questioning of Marxism in light of the developments in
physics that were to culminate in a profound revolution in scientific
though!. This, I argue, is the real message of the book. (In fact, there
is a lot wrong with Leninâs paragraph, even from a Marxist framework,
but we will get to that later.)
Elsewhere, Lenin lets the cat out of the bag: âHuman thought then by its
nature is capable of giving, and does give, absolute truth, which is
compounded of a sum-total of relative truths. Each step in the
development of science adds new grains to the sum of absolute truth, but
the limits of the truth of each scientific proposition are relative, row
expanding, now shrinking with the growth of knowledge.â (P. 135.) On the
next page, Lenin writes: âFront the standpoint of modern materialism,
i.e., Marxism, the limits of approximation of our knowledge to
objective, absolute truth are historically conditional, but the
existence of such truth is unconditional, and the fact that we are
approaching nearer to it is also unconditional,â
These passages are Leninâs attempts to elucidate a passage he has just
cited from Frederick Engelsâ Authority, Although our purpose here is not
to discuss Engelsâ (or Marxâs) views of truth and knowledge, it is worth
citing the critical passage at some length. What follows are Engelsâ
words as quoted by Lenin (Materialism and Empirio-criticism, same
edition, pp. 133â134):
âNow we come to the question whether any, and if so which, products of
human knowledge ever can have sovereign validity and an unconditional
claim {Anspntch) to truthâ (5^(th) German ed, p. 79). And Engels answers
the question thus:
âThe sovereignty of thought is realised in the cries of extremely
unsovereignty-thinking human beings; the knowledge which has an
unconditional claim to the truth is realised in a series of relative
errors: neither the one nor the other (i.e., neither absolutely true
knowledge, nor sovereign thought) can be fully realised except through
an unending duration of human existence.
âHere once again we find the same contradiction as we found above,
between the character of human thought, necessarily conceived as
absolute, and its reality in individual human beings, all of whom think
only limitedly. This is a contradiction which can only be (solved in the
infinite progress, in what isâat least practically for usâan endless
succession of generations of mankind- In this sense human thought is
only as much sovereign as not sovereign, and its capacity for knowledge
just as much unlimited as limited. It is sovereign in its disposition
(Antage), its vocal ion, its possibilities and its historical ultimate
goal; it is not sovereign and it is limited in its individual
realisation and in reality at each particular moment.â
Without analyzing this passage in any depth, it is necessary to note
that Engels, while admitting the possibility of absolute, âsovereignâ
knowledge, hedges his bets quite a bit. (In my opinion, he fudges the
question.) To say that absolute knowledge is possible through an
âunending duration of human existenceâ and/or the âendless succession of
generations of mankind,â or that âhuman thought is only as much
sovereign as not sovereignâ is not making a very decisive case. And is
quite a bit different from saying that âHuman thought then by its nature
is capable of giving, anti does give, absolute truth, which is
compounded of a sum-total of relative truths.â
Although Engels is pushed in the direction of saying that approaching
the truth âin the infinite progressionâ (that is, say, the way a
hyperbola approaches its asymptotes) eventually adds up to absolute
knowledge, he tries to hold himself back. Lenin, on the other hand, at
best gives Lip service to the idea that knowledge at any given time is
relative, and jumps over the âasymptotic gapâ as if it had no relevance
whatever,
Engels at least had an excuse for believing that knowledge could be
compared to a smooth curve, that it increasingly approached absolute
truth. He was living in the last stage of an era that had seen the
sciences expand more or less continuously and smoothly for a few hundred
years. Until the latter part of his life, and certainly during his
formative period, scientific developments seemed to fit neatly into the
general framework that had reached a polished and elegant form at the
time of Isaac Newton (1642â1727), Of course absolute knowledge, as the
gradual addition of relative truths, seemed possible.
Lenin, living at the time of a scientific revolution that would overturn
the old framework, had no such excuse. And despite this, his views are
less tempered than Engelsâ.
Further on, Lenin is even more explicit. In discussing the role of
practice, and after a typical caveat to the effect that practice can
never â...either confirm or refute any human idea completelyâ (his
emphasis), Lenin writes: âIf what our practice confirms is the sole,
ultimate and objective truth, then from this must follow the recognition
that the only path to this truth is the path of science, which holds the
materialist point of viewâ (p. 141).
And still further, denouncing Bogdanovâs willingness to recognize Marxâs
theory of the circulation of money as an objective truth only for âour
time,â and refusing to attribute to this theory a âsuperhistorically
objective truth,â Lenin tells the whole story (all emphasis is Leninâs):
The correspondence of this theory lo practice cannot be altered by any
future circumstances, for the same simple reason that makes it an
eternal truth that Napoleon died on May 5, 1821. But inasmuch as the
criterion of practice, i.e.. the course of development of all capitalist
countries in the last few decades, proves only the objective truth of
Maraâs whole social and economic theory in general, and not merely one
or the other of its parts, formula!ions, etc., It is clear that to talk
here of the âdogmatismâ of the Marxists is to make an unpardonable
concession to bourgeois economics. The sole conclusion to be drawn from
the opinion held by Marxists that Marxâs theory is an objective truth is
that by following the path of Marxian theory we shall draw closer and
closer to objective truth (without ever exhausting it); but by following
any other path we shall arrive at nothing but confusion and lies. (P.
143.)
This, I believe, should be enough Lo demonstrate that Lenin believed in
absolute truth (if the words themselves donât convince you, the tone
ought to), not only in general, but also that Marxism is the truth, in
particular.
IN our last installment or this series, I began to discuss the question
of absolute truth and knowledge and Leninâs attitude toward it. In
particular, I mentioned that I feel that a belief in absolute knowledge
represents a âtotalitarian kernel,â a potential for a totalitarian
ideology. And through a cursory sketch of Leninâs book on the question
of knowledge, Materialism and Empirio-criticism, I showed that despite
some hedging Lenin did believe in absolute truth and the possibility of
absolute knowledge.
What I would like to do in this installment is to discuss Leninâs theory
of knowledge, particularly its failure to recognize that the
mind/knowledge is active; sketch how this conception led him to
misunderstand, and in fact to oppose, the scientific revolution going on
at the time; and suggest how his belief in absolute knowledge {embodied,
at least as far as society and history are concerned, in Marxism) helped
pave the way for the establishment of state capitalism in Russia.
In Materialism and Empirio-criticism, Lenin puts forward a theory of
knowledge that, at least at that time, underlay his belief in absolute
truth and knowledge. This theory can be expressed in a few
propositions: 1) reality is nothing but matter in motion; 2) human
knowledge is a reflection of that reality and corresponds to it; 3) the
truth of any given thought, idea, theory, etc., is proven or disproven
through experiments that test predictions deduced from the theory, as
well as the general success of the theory in terms of developing
technology and furthering science.
Despite the apparent plausibility of this view (it is a kind of
common-sense viewpoint), it really canât stand up to a serious
investigation of the issue.
In the first place, it is contradicted by other ideas about knowledge
and consciousness that Lenin himself held. Lenin, like most
Marxists, believed in the notion of âfalse consciousness.ââ This is a
consciousness (a view of the world, a set of values, etc.), held by
certain people in society that does not âcorrespondâ to their class
position.
For example, to Marxists, the âtrueâ consciousness of members of the
working class, true âproletarian consciousness,â is Marxism, or at least
some commitment to revolution and socialism. Yet, most workers are not
revolutionary socialists; they do not have âproletarian consciousness.â
Instead, they share the world views of other, non-proletarian classes,
such as the ruling class or sections of the middle class. The workers
have âfalse consciousness.â
This is not just the result of the bourgeois media, bourgeois education,
etc., although they certainly contribute. It also is more than the
effect of the âhegemonyâ (a kind of cultural leadership) of the ruling
class, in the sense described by the Italian Marxist, Antonio Gramsci.
The workersâ âfalse consciousnessâ comes from the on-going reality of
their daily lives, that they are workers who work at such and such
workplaces, sell their labor-power for wages, etc., and enter into
certain relations with their co-workers, management, merchants,
representatives of the state and (more indirectly) other capitalists.
Their âfalse consciousnessâ flows out, is a part of, the web of
day-to-day social relations that they arc enmeshed in. Their
consciousness âreflectsâ these relations.
But this raises a bit of a problem. If âfalse consciousnessâ is a
reflection of (social) reality, how do we get knowledge, if it, too, is
a reflection of reality? Or, if knowledge is the result of the
reflection of reality in the mind, where does âfalse consciousnessâ come
from? Clearly, there is something missing, some âmiddle term,â in
Leninâs theory of knowledge. Lenin has two poles, reality and knowledge,
one of which reflects the other. But the nature of that reflection must
be different between true knowledge on the one hand and false knowledge
on the other. Why and how this happens have to be explained.
in fact, the theory of knowledge that Lenin puts forward is considerably
less sophisticated than that of Karl Marx, whose theory Lenin thought he
was propounding. (Leninâs conception is basically a throwback to the
French materialistsâDiderot, dâAlembert, for exampleâof the 18^(th)
century.)
To Marx, reality (natural or social) and consciousness/know ledge are
not two polar terms with nothing between them (one merely re-fleeting
the other). He saw them as different aspects, two facets, of a social
process (âpractice,â or âpraxisâ in Greek), in which humanity transforms
both itself and reality through work.
(Lenin talks about âpracticeâ in Materialism and Empirio-criticism, but
he tends to reduce it to a narrow form and to ignore its fundamental
content for Marx, the social process through which humanity creates
itself.)
In Leninâs presentation, reality is basically given, stolidly present;
human consciousness just reflects it. For all of his talk about
dialectical materialism, Lenin fails to see the âdialecticâ where it can
most truly be said to existâin the process of the reciprocal
transformation of humanity and nature through labor.
Marx, in contrast, realized that reality, natural as well as social, is
as changed by this process as human beings are. One aspect of this
change is obvious; society evolves, and as it does so the world/ nature
is transformed by the development of technology, the impact of human
society on nature (not always to the good, clearly), etc.
But there is another facet to this idea, one not so easily grasped. And
this is that nature, as it is present to human beings, as human beings
perceive and confront it, changes. The nature that primitive peoples
perceived, their image of it, is different from that of modern humanity.
Some of this change is immediately technical; the universe that
contemporary humanity perceives through modern instruments, including
radio telescopes, planetary probes, etc., is a lot different from the
universe primitive people could see with the naked eye.
But there is a social/cultural difference as well. The universe that was
populated and moved by specific gods and spirits is a different universe
from that conveyed by the idea that space is most accurately presented
as a non-Euclidean geometryâ and sub-atomic particles by a series of
partial differential equations.
It is not that the âultimate natureâ (whatever that might be) of the
universe has necessarily changed, only that nature, âreality,â is not
just givenâpresented in total and as it âreally isââto humanity, so that
the human mind simply reflects it. What Lenin didnât understand (at
least when he wrote Materialism and Empirio-criticism) is that the human
mind (human consciousness, knowledge), taken individually and socially,
is active. It does not just passively reflect reality; it changes how
reality is presented to it, how it perceives reality.
We can clarify this some more by looking at the question a bit
differently, Lenin says that the mind reflects reality, but a look at
how an individual (or a group of individuals) perceives reality at any
given level suggests that this view is simplistic.
Even if we assume that the mind is like a camera, in that it records
without alteration the (visual) information it receives, we can easily
see that it is not purely passive. A camera has to be pointed in a
certain direction; and, with all but primitive cameras, it also has to
be focused (manually or automatically). In other words, we have to
choose to look at something. We donât just open our eyes and take
everything in in 360 degrees, at all distances, etc. This choosing is
active. It is not purely passive, like a mirror.
In fact, this activity involves processes a lot more complicated than
aiming and setting a focal length. For example, the mind has to
interpret what it sees, to arrange the infinite amount of data that
enters it into patterns. A baby not only has to learn how to point
his/her eyes in a certain direction and to focus them, lie/she also has
to learn what the patterns of different colors and shapes mean, which of
those colors and shapes âbelong togetherâ (e.g., as a material object,
as a person, etc.).
Even after we have learned how to recognize patterns and shapes, there
always remains the question of relevance. At any given time and place,
we have to decide which of all the things we see are relevant to us. If
we are in a coffee shop and are sealed at a table, the styrofoam cup in
front of us is more important than the moving cars in the street
outside. But when we are crossing that street a bit later, weâd better
be paying more attention to the cars than to the styrofoam cup lying in
the gutter.
Just considering the question of one sense, that of sight, we can
recognize that a lot more is involved than the eye merely reflecting
reality. The visual function involves, requires, the selection and
interpretation of the data that impinges on the eye. This is an active
process, not a passive process of reflection.
In a recent discussion about his participation in a group of scientists
and others searching for fossils in East Africa, Stephen Jay Gould, the
Harvard paleontologist and science writer, expresses this point in a
somewhat different context. Explaining that while some searchers have a
sharp eye for fossil fragments and others can piece them together, he
only finds snails, Gould writes:
All field naturalists know and respect the phenomenon of âsearch
imageââthe best proof that observation is an interaction of mind and
nature, not a fully objective and reproducible mapping of outside upon
inside, done in the same way by all careful and competent people- In
short, you see what you are trained to viewâand observation of different
sorts of objects often requires a conscious shift of focus, not a total
and indiscriminate expansion in the hopes of seeing everything. The
world is too crowded with wonders for simultaneous perception of all; we
learn our fruitful selectivities. (Natural History, May, J9&7, p, 27.)
If the operation of a single sense is active, isnât it obvious that
processes as complex as consciousness and knowledge entail activity?
Scientists do not just take in all the data that present themselves to
them. They have to choose what data are relevant to them. At the
broadest level, this involves choosing the very field any given
scientist will study and investigate, or the given problem within the
field he/she will investigate.
More specific still, as they seek to investigate a specific phenomenon,
scientists have to choose a way of approaching the investigation. to
decide What kinds of experiments they will carry out to collect what
kind of data* And even when these experiments have been carried out and
the data recorded, the collected data does not in and of itself suggest
the new concept or theory that will explain the phenomenon under
investigation.
At this point what is required Is an intuitive leap, an inspired guess,
that posits a new conception, a new way of looking at the problem, no
matter how far-fetched, Albert Einstein described the process this way:
For the creation of a theory, the mere collection of recorded phenomena
never sufficesâthere must always be added a free invention Of the human
mind that attacks the heart of the matter. (The Cosmic Code, by Heini R.
Pageis, p 141.)
Now. science is a social process; it involves many people communicating
with each other, over extended periods of time. As such, it is subject
to social and cultural influences. Scientists, like the rest of us, live
in the societies of their time and place. They have been, by and large,
members of specific social classes, etc. And they live in, and to a
great extent are created by, specific cultures. All these influences
affect scientific knowledge.
Thus, it is not an accident that the physics (hat emerged from the
so-called Copernican Revolution envisaged the universe largely in
mechanical terms, as, say. a huge clock that was created and set going
by a Creator who then sat back to watch the clock work in a beautiful
simplicity and regularity. This particular physics was developed during
the early stages of the development of capitalism, itself based on the
creation and utilization of mechanical devices* The society, (he
technology and the science were part of a single, very complex social
process, each creating the means for the development of the others.
The conceptions of the sciences in that period did not just reflect
nature, they actively conceptualized nature in a certain way. Such
conceptualizations vary greatly in different times. Today, the dominant
conceptions of physics are no longer mechanical.
Specifically, by the latter part of the 19^(th) century, mechanistic
explanations of phenomena were no longer sufficient to answer the
problems that physicists confronted. A new revolution in physics took
place that to roughly changed the way scientists look at the universe.
As a result, today the predominant conceptions of physics are
mathematical, Space (Einstein called it space-time) is conceived as a
(non-Euclidean) geometry; the structure of the atom as a set of complex
mathematical equations.
The main point I am trying to establish here is that the mind, human
consciousness, taken individually and collectively, is active, not
passive. It chooses to look at /investigate certain things and not
others. It sees some things as more important, more relevant than
others, it interprets what it sees; indued, the very act of seeing
entails this interpreting. As a result, all knowledge has a degree of
subjectivity that cannot be eliminated.
This is why different people see reality differently (sec a âdifferent
realityâ). Older people, on balance, see reality differently from young
ones. Artists tend to see reality differently from scientists. People in
die ruling class see reality differently from working class people.
People whose goal in life is to make money see reality differently from
people who live for a cause. Not least, people from different countries
and cultures sec reality differently from each other.
Scientists, unlike artists, have a mutually agreed-upon method of
determining which theory, which interpretation, is right. This is
through experimentation and other forms of testing theory. As a result,
science often appears to embody or lo approach absolute knowledge (at
least until the next scientific revolution occurs). Nevertheless, even
in science, the subjective element of knowledge, I he effect of the fact
that the mind is active, is not eliminated.
If the mind/human consciousness is active in the sense 1 have discussed,
what does it mean to say, as Lenin does, that knowledge âreflectsâ
reality? Not a whole lot. Obviously, there is some connection, some
âcorrespondenceâ between reality and knowledge (otherwise, the human
race would probably be extinct). But it is certainly not mere
reflection. Lenin could put forward his view that knowledge was a simple
reflection of reality because he did not understand that the human mind,
individually and collectively, as consciousness in general and
specifically as science, is active.
Leninâs one-sided and mechanical conception of human
consciousness/knowledge (and his dogmatism) is what made him miss the
significance of the scientific developments that were going on at the
very time he was writing. Yes, he does have a chapter (Chapter Five) on
the ârecent revolution in natural scienceâ in Materialism and
Empirio-criticism. But Lenin denies that the revolutionary developments
in the natural sciences of his time in fact represent any real challenge
to traditional scientific conceptions.
Instead, he accuses those scientists grappling with Lite meaning and
implications of these new developments of failing, when they
philosophize, to abide by what Lenin considered to be the de facto
dialectical materialism they practice when they function as scientists.
In other words, Lenin charges them with a kind of failure of nerve.
Lenin basically believed that the philosophical answers to the problems
the physicists and other scientists were struggling with had already
been given (by dialectical materialism), and that if the scientists
stopped being tempted by idealism and âfideismâ everything would work
out fine. But it was precisely the traditional conceptions of science,
including Leninâs (and Frederick Engelsâ) notion of dialectical
materialism, that could no longer provide satisfactory answers to the
questions being posed by the latest scientific discoveries. As a result,
Lenin winds up denying the very existence of the revolution in the
natural sciences that he claims to be discussing.
That Lenin did not understand what was actually happening in physics al
Lite time is revealed by his attempts lo discuss them concretely.
Consider the following two sentences:
Natural science was seeking, both in 1872 and 1906, is now seeking, and
is discoveringâor least it is groping its way towardsâthe atom of
electricity, the electron, in interdimensional space. Science docs not
doubt that the substance it is investigating exists in three-dimensional
space and, hence, that the particles of that substance, although they be
so small that we cannot see them, must also ânecessarilyââ exist in this
three-dimensional space. (Materialism and Empirio-criticism, pp,
180â181.)
Leaving aside the question of âsubstance,â Lenin was as wrong as he
could be regarding the question of three-dimensional space, Lenin was
writing after Albert Einstein had published his paper on the Special
Theory of Relativity (1905) which posited the local-ness and variability
of time, thus establishing it as a kind of fourth dimension. (Locations
in spaceâwhat Einstein called space-timeâare defined mathematically by
four numbers, three representing the traditional dimensions plus a
fourth representing time.) Today, cosmologists, those who investigate
and speculate about the ultimate structure of the universe, are thinking
in terms of theories that posit that the universe has many more than
four dimensions. How about, say, 10?
(Is it perhaps unfair to berate Lenin for not being totally up-to-date
about the developments of physics of the time, particularly when
Einsteinâs theoryâ was relatively little known, unaccepted and in no way
confirmed? I donât think so. Who asked Lenin to write a book about
problems of philosophy in light of the scientific revolution then
underway? Lenin hangs himself because he raised the issue.)
Not accidentally, the person Lenin is polemicizing against with the
sentences quoted is none other than Ernst Mach, whom Einstein credited
as being one of his major early influences. Although 1 cannot do it
justice in so limited a space, it is worth looking at the issue more
closely. This is because the question Mach was raising was to become a
fundamental concern of 20^(th) century physics.
In this section of his book, Lenin is discussing Machâs rather hesitant
suggestion that physicists should question, and perhaps abandon, the
Newtonian conception of absolute space and time:
In modern physics, he [Mach] says, Newtonâs idea of absolute time and
space prevails (pp. 442â444), of time and space as such. This idea seems
âto usâ senseless, Mach continues..,. But in practice, he claims, this
view was harmless (S. 442) and therefore for a long time escaped
criticism. (Materialism and Empirio-criticism, p. 179.)
To Lenin, this suggestion is âharmfulâ and must be rejected. Why?
Because âMachâs idealist view of space and time... opens the door for
fideism and... seduces Mach himself into drawing reactionary
conclusions,â (Materialism and Empirio-criticism, p. 179.) Just what are
these reactionary conclusions?
For instance, in 1872 Mach wrote that âone does not have to conceive of
the chemical elements in a space of three dimensions.â (Erhattung dec
Arbeit, S. 19, repeated or S. 55.) To do so would be âto impose an
unnecessary restriction upon ourselves. There is no more necessity to
think of what is mere thought (das bloss Gcdachle) spatially, that is to
say, in relations to the visible and tangible, than there is to think of
it in a definite pitch.â (27) âThe reason why a satisfactory theory of
electricity has not yet been established is perhaps because we have
invariably wanted to explain electrical phenomena in terms of molecular
processes in a three dimensional spaceâ (20). (Materialism and
Empirio-criticism, p. 180.)
To Lenin this is an absurdity.
The argument from the standpoint of the straightforward and un-muddled
Machism which Mach openly advocated in 1872 is quite indisputable: if
molecules, atoms, in a word, chemical elements, cannot be perceived,
they are âmere thoughtâ (das bloss Gedachic). If so, and if space and
time have no objective reality. It is clear that it is not essential to
think of atoms spatially. Let physics and chemistry ârestrict
themselvesâ to a three-dimensional space in which mailer moves; for the
explanation of electricity, however, we may seek its elements in a space
which is not three-dimensional! (Materialism and Empirio-criticism, p.
130.)
In fact, wherever he was coming from philosophically, Machâs suggestion
(remember he writes âperhapsâ) that scientists not restrict themselves
to the traditional Newtonian conception of space and time was profoundly
prophetic. Today, it is a fundamental tenet of physics. The theory of
relativity, with its positing of time as a fourth dimension, was, as we
have said, directly influenced by Mach. In quantum dynamics and its
later embodiments (quantum electrodynamics, quantum chromodynamics)
atoms and their constituent parts cannot be conceived spatially, time is
reversible and traditional logic does not apply.
What would Lenin say?
The point is not that Maehâs philosophy was right and that Leninâs was
wrong. The point is:
natural scienceâ that he was writing about and which so concerned the
people he was politicizing against.
prevent him from even considering, let alone accepting, an idea (hat
would become a fundamental tenet of this centuryâs physics. Because, in
Leninâs view, Machâs view âopens the door for fideismâ and âseduces Mach
himself into drawing reactionary conclusions,â Lenin condemns
out-of-hand Machâs suggestion that scientists ânot restrict themselvesâ
to the traditional view of space and time and refuses even to consider
that reality might have other than three dimensions.
(I think this is the germ of the attempt to use ideology to tell
scientists what to do and how to think that would run rampant in Russia
under Joseph Stalin (with resultant punishment, including execution, for
those scientists who would not buckle under). If a given theory,
proposition or assumption is not consistent with (someoneâs conception
of) dialectical materialism and/or if it leads to âreactionary
conclusions,â it is a priori wrong and cannot even be considered. In the
name of science, ideology is raised above science and presumes to
dictate to it.)
(Whether Lenin himself ever tried to tell scientists how to think and
what to do is not relevant. What is, is that when a party with Leninâs
conception of philosophy and science comes to power, it is highly likely
that someone in that party will, sooner or later, try to tell scientists
what to do and how to think.)
But Leninâs comment about reality only having three dimensions involves
more than ignorance and (can I say it?) arrogance. It implies a certain
conception of the relation between knowledge and truth, theory and
reality.
This is a tendency toward what I like to call the âhypostatization of
theory,â By this huge word (I can barely pronounce it) I mean a tendency
to believe that theory, concepts, are more real, have more substance,
than the reality they purport to explain.
This is the opposite of the way Ernst Mach tended to lean, Mach thought
of scientific concepts and theories as âmere thought,â as kinds of
conveniences, ways for the human mind to organize sensations, or data;
the question of whether they were true or not, in the traditional sense
of the term, was irrelevant. The only meaningful question to ask isâDocs
a given theory organize the data conveniently? Or, negatively, does any
of the data fall outside the confines of the theory? This is a kind of
denigration of theory, a denial of the reality or truth of theory.
In contrast to this, Lenin tends to ascribe to theory a greater truth or
substantiality than it can reasonably claim. Once a given theory or
concept has been proven âtrue,â in Leninâs view, it has more truth to it
than the reality it is meant to describe.
This can be seen in his view that reality is, and can only be three
dimensional. That reality could have more than three dimensions seems
totally bizarre lo him. This is because Lenin doesnât realize that
dimensionality is a conceptâspecifically, a geometryâan invention of the
human mind.
(âOrdinaryâ reality, that is, reality that is generally present to human
beings, may be almost perfectly definable/explainable in terms of three
dimensions. But that doesnât mean that reality has, and can only have,
three dimensions. By the same token, the universe can today best be
described by the theory of relativity that describes space (spaec-time)
in terms of four dimensions, but that doesnât mean reality has, and can
only have, four dimensions.)
Lenin takes the concept (in this case, three dimensionality) and makes
it the reality; This tendency to âhvpostatize theoryâ can be also seen
in his comment, cited in our last installment, about Marxâs theoryâ of
money having an eternal truth comparable to the fact that Napoleon died
on May 5, 1821, (We shall leave aside a discussion of the question of
how well this latter âfactâ stands up in terms of the theory of
relativity: what was a specific date for the Earth and its vicinity was
many different dates for other parts of the universe. In some parts of
the universe, Napoleon has not yet died. In others, he has not yet been
born.)
Now, Marxâs theory of money is a brilliant theory (as is his analysis of
capitalism, in my opinion), but to claim it has an eternal truth, isnât
that going a bit too far? Even Marx, arrogant as he was, only claimed a
kind of âepochalâ truth for his theory, that is, that it is only valid
for a specific historical epoch.
But, assuming that Lenin basically meant that Marxâs theory of money is
absolutely true, I donât think this can be seriously maintained today,
For one thing, it has a philosophical content (about the nature of human
beings, that the existence or money reflects their alienation from each
other and this true nature), which can neither be proved nor disproved.
Far more important, I donât think the existence of absolute truth and
knowledge (which, of course, is what saying Marxâs theory of money has
eternal truth means) can be reasonably asserted.
This is suggested by one of the main achievements of physics in this
century, the theory of quantum mechanics, which has been very successful
in explaining and predicting atomic and sub-atomic phenomena. One of the
tenets of this theoryâ is that it is impossible simultaneously to
exactly measure the velocity and position of a sub-atomic particle, for
example, an electron (or a photon of electromagnetic radiation). The
more accurately one measures its position, the greater variability of
values for its velocity one gets. If one measured an electronâs velocity
exactly its position could not be measured at all.
This is not, according to the theory, simply something that results from
the limitations of our minds and our ability to measure. There is a
certain randomness, a certain indeterminism in the nature of atomic and
sub atomic phenomena. The more one attempts lo gain certainty about one
aspect, the less certain others become.
Another aspect of the theory is that sub-atomic particles have a
two-sided character. Some or their behavior can be explained by assuming
they are particulate, that they are simply particles. Other aspects of
their behavior arc explainable by assuming that they have wave
characteristics. Moreover, these distinct behaviors/characteristics are
not combinable. They either exhibit one form of behavior/characteristic
or the other; they never exhibit both at the same time. Which
characteristic is exhibited depends on the experiment one carries out to
look for it.
One explanation for this confusing situation, the one that seems to be
the most accepted by modern physicists (insofar as they conceptualize
these things: one can simply use the equationsâweâre talking high level
math hereâwithout worrying about what they âmeanâ), is that the wave
characteristics represent an indication of the probability of finding a
given particle there at any given time.
The main point is that at the atomic and sub-atomic level, there is a
degree of randomness or uncertainly about what goes or at any given
lime. At least at this level, reality is not determined. There is no
absolute truth; reality is not precisely this and not that. It can be
both and/or neither.
And where there is no absolute truth, in the sense that reality is not
precisely determined, there can be no absolute knowledge. Ail one can
have is approximate knowledge. One cannot know for certain what will
happen, all one can have is varying degrees of probability that
something will happen. This probability may be very high, but it is
always a question of probability, not certainly.
Now, while this to me implies that all of natural reality exhibits
probabilistic behavior and that knowledge of âmacroâ phenomena can also
only approximate (in many cases, the variability is too small to be of
practical impact), many physicists appear to compartmentalize reality.
On the sub-atomic level, there is indeterminism and probabilities. On
the supra-atomic level, there is determinism and absolute
predictability. Yet, in the past few years.
physics has become more concerned with the investigation of random
processes, processes that are inherently random and unpredictable,
âchaotic.â I suspect that over the next few years more and more
processes previously perceived as being determined and predictable will
wind up in the random or at least somewhat indescribable category.
What I am really trying to get at here is that between the undetermined,
probabilistic nature of reality and the initiations of our ability to
measure and our minds, all knowledge of the natural world is, at best,
approximate, probabilistic. There is no absolute knowledge. One gets
greater or lesser probabilities. In some cases, the probability is so
high as to be almost certain, but it is still not certain.
At the risk or simplifying, perhaps ii is better to say that reality is
always more complicated than any given theory. Reality entails change,
novelty. Theory, perhaps because of the nature of the human mind,
entails uniformity, or to use a term very much in vogue in physics these
days, symmetry. Now, there is clearly symmetry in nature, otherwise
scientific theories would no! be as successful as they have been.
But what if (as I suspect) reality is not totally symmetrical? What if
it is not uniform? What if at some basic level it is asymmetrical? Then,
there will always be some aspect of reality that will not be incorporate
into theories which, by their nature imply uniformity, symmetry, even if
it is a âbrokenâ one. If so, this means that at some point any given
theory, no mailer how successful in predicting phenomena, no matter how
perfect it may appear, will eventually come across some kind of
phenomenon which it has not explained or predicted and cannot do so. Or,
to put it the other way around, sooner or later scientists will discover
a phenomenon which is unexplainable by, and incompatible with, current
theory.
(If this is so. Leninâs hypostatization of theory is in fact a form of
that very idealism that Lenin hated so much. Theory is an idea, a
concept. To believe that scientific theories represent the real reality,
truer than the concrete reality we see, hear, and touch, is to believe
that ultimate reality is ideal, not material.
(Lenin says unite rial reality consists of â matter in motion,â But the
motions of this matter are governed by the âlaws of motionâ discovered
by science. In other words, the structure of this mailer, and the
structures that are comprised of mailer, are determined by those âlaws
of motion.â But these laws of motion are a kind of logic. To Lenin,
then, the real reality, the defining structure of reality, is the logic
defined by these âlaws of motion.â This is a form of objective idealism.
Unbeknownst to himself, Lenin was an idealist.)
Now, if on the level of natural reality, all knowledge is approximate,
probabilistic, are we to seriously think that absolute knowledge is
possible when it comes to social reality, to history, economics,
politics, etc.âin short, lo people? I donât think so. In fact, I think
the very idea is absurd.
It is precisely the development of the human mind/human consciousness,
which so greatly multiplies the complexity of motivation (including
doing things out of spite, out of sheer perversity, just for the hell of
it, etc.), that makes people so unpredictable. As a result, absolute
knowledge of human beings and human society is out of the question.
But Lenin did believe such a knowledge is possible, indeed, that it
existed...in the form of Marxism.
From this Marxist philosophy, which is cast from a single piece of
steel, you cannot eliminate one basic premise, one essential part,
without departing from objective truth, without falling prey to a
bourgeois-reactionarv falsehood. (Materialism and Empirio-criticism,
Collected Works* Vol. 13, p. 326.)
... the criterion of practice, i.e., the course of development of all
capitalist countries in the last few decades, proves only the objective
truth of Marxâs whole social and economic theory in general, and not
merely one or the other of its parts, formulations, etc (P. 143)
And this, as 1 wrote in our last issue, is the philosophical root of
state capitalism. If a party which believes that its ideology is the
absolute truth (and every other ideology is a âbourgeois reactionary
falsehoodâ) comes to power in an armed revolution, it will not put too
much of a priority on maintaining the democratic rights of other
political parties.
More than this, if the rule of that party is threatened, it will not set
too great a priority on maintaining the democratic rights of the class
that it claims to represent especially if or when members of that class
start to behave in a way they arc not âsupposed to.â After all, it is
that party that represents the âtrue consciousnessâ of the working
class. Thus, those workers who support other parties of organizations
will be âunder the influence of non-proletarian ideologies.â
And their political rights will have to be repressed in order to defend
the ârule of the working class.â
And if the entire working class ceases to support that party, the party
will politically disfranchise it in the name of the âhistoric interests
of the working class.â In other words, the ideal, abstract working class
of Marxist theory will be elevated above the concrete workers and will
become an instrument in the workersâ re-enslavement. This, in a
nutshell, is what 1 believe happened in Russia.
Postscript. During World War I, Lenin read Hegel, particularly his
Logic. While this study was to have a significant impact on Leninâs
thought, it is not likely to have lessened his belief in the possibility
of absolute knowledge. If anything, it probably strengthened it, Hegelâs
philosophy is centered around the idea that not only is absolute
knowledge possible, but that Hegelâs system is that absolute knowledge.
BY now, I suspect that my general assessment of Leninism is pretty
clear. While I believe that Leninism is not entirely, 100%
authoritarian, that is, that there are some truly liberatory and
democratic impulses, I believe these impulses are far outweighed by
those that point toward and imply state capitalism. Moreover, these
latter are so strong that they distort the democratic impulses
themselves, rather than merely overshadowing them. For example, the
advocacy of a classless and stateless society in The State and
Revolution is turned into its opposite by Leninâs conception of how to
achieve it, e.g., through braiding a strong centralized state modeled
after the German postal system.
Even though most of the series focused on the state capitalist elements
in Leninism, it is probably worth summarizing my views or them, i
believe that of the various tendencies within Leninism that point toward
state capitalism, the most import ant are three:
First is (he fact that although Leninism advocates (he establishment of
a stateless society, ii not only proposes to use the state to achieve
this goal, it sees the use of the state as the main way to accomplish
this. Not least, although this state is said to be a proletarian state,
a dictatorship of the proletariat, it is to be structured, with
relatively minor exceptions, along hierarchical and bureaucratic. that
is, capitalistic, principles. Given this, is it any wonder that the
outcome of the Bolshevik Revolution in 1917 was not classless, stateless
societies, but monstrous, class divided, stale-dominated, social
systems?
The second state capitalist tendency within Leninism that 1 believe to
be decisive is i|s advocacy of coercive, ruthless methods. While some
kind of armed force/coercion is inevitable in almost any revolution,
Lenin almost revels in it: the need to be â âruthless toward our
enemies,â ânot to shrink from the most ruthless measures,â lo âshoot and
shoot and shoot some more.â Since morality lies within, is immanent in,
history, that is, morality finds its fruition in the outcome of history
(as Marx, following Hegel, argues), there is no need to act morally,
there is no morality, in the sphere of politics. But outside of
Marxian/Hegelian (or any other comparable) metaphysics, how can moral
neutralism lead to a moral society? It canât and hasnât.
The third fundamental state capitalist tendency in Leninism, and tying
alt three together, is Leninâs belief in determinism and absolute
knowledge. Physical and social/historical reality is absolutely
determined, Marxism represents true knowledge of this reality (it ever
increasingly approaches this reality), the Bolshevik faction/ party
holds the only correct interpretation of Marxism âthese are fundamental
tenets of Bolshevik thinking. And they point directly toward the
establishment of a dictatorship of the party over the proletariat in the
name of the proletariat itself. If the Bolsheviks alone understand
Marxism, then only they have true proletarian socialist consciousness;
they are the spiritual representatives of the proletariat. When the
proletariat disagrees with the Bolshevik Party, it has come under the
influence of non-proletarian classes; it no longer is the true
proletariat. With this idea firmly engraved in their minds, the
Bolsheviksâ suppression of all opposition parties and the outlawing of
opposition factions even within the Bolshevik Party was almost
inevitable.
This last factor looms even larger when it is realized that this
attitude, this total belief that they and only they represent the
proletariat â history, morality and truth â was fundamental to the
mentality of the Bolsheviks. It created a psychological and moral
cultureâa ruthless, party-oriented fanaticismâthat engulfed everything
and drained of all content even the formally democratic aspects of
Bolshevik theory. It was from this culture that a man like Stalin
emerged, and it is because of this culture that the Bolshevik Party was
not able to stop him. While Stalin is of the past, the possibility of
new Stalins remains because the intellectual/moral culture of Leninism
remains what it has always been.
These three tendencies (along with the others discussed in previous
articles), explain what I believe to be the fundamental problem with the
strategy and tactics the Bolsheviks pursued after the October
Revolution. This was a failure to maintain, a failure even to try to
maintain, what I call the united front character of the Russian
Revolution.
The Russian Revolution, including the February Revolution and the one in
October, had a united front character. By this I mean that like ail
popular revolutions, it was the outcome of more or less distinct
movements of different classes, groups and political organizations that
joined forces to overthrow an oppressive regime and social order. The
main classes were the workers and the peasants. Many different
nationalities, e.g., Ukrainians, While Russians, Finns, Georgians, etc.,
etc., fought for freedom from Great Russian rule. Various socialist
organizations were involved.
While this was obviously true of the February Revolution, it was also
true of the October âBolshevikâ Revolution, While workers and soldiers
{mostly peasants in uniform) carried out the revolution in the cities,
the peasants, intensifying an uprising that had begun during the summer,
carried out the insurrection in the countryside, running out the
landlords, burning their estates and seizing the land. {The importance
of this part of the struggle is not always recognized.)
The revolution also entailed the continuation of the revolt of Live
oppressed nationalities. And the organized political forces that led the
revolution, insofar as it was led at all, consisted of not only the
Bolshevik Party, but the left wing of the Social Revolutionary Party
(the âLeft SRâsâ), and various other left socialist and anarchist
organizations.
Although it is not clear whether the revolutionary forces could have
held out, given the revolutionâs isolation, the poverty of the country,
etc.. the key to their survival, it seems to me now, lay in the
maintenance of the revolutionâs united front character, that is, its
character of being a kind of coalition of different classes,
nationalities, and organizations. This would have meant working out
certain rules for political functioning in the soviets, workersâ
councils, and other mass organizations. Most important, it would have
required a commitment on (lie part of the major political parties,
particularly the Bolsheviks, not to try to squeeze out or suppress the
other organizations.
Unfortunately, the Bolsheviks did not pursue such a policy. They didnât
even try lo pursue it. From virtually the very beginning, the Bolsheviks
worked to concentrate as much political power in their hands as
possible. Although they maintained the formal united front with the Left
SRâs for seven or eight months, ii seems to me that they expected this
alliance lo fall apart at some point and made little effort to keep it
together.
The first major dispute between the Bolsheviks and the Left SRâs was
over the signing of a peace treaty with the Germans and Austrians in [he
late winter of 1918. In the political debates within the Bolshevik Party
over signing a treaty (the party almost split over the issue), little or
no consideration was given, by Lenin or anyone else, over what the
impact would be on the Left SRâs, who opposed signing a treaty. In fact,
in Leninâs speeches and writings on the question, he virtually assumes
that the Left SRâs are irrelevant and that it is only a matter of time
before the alliance breaks down.
The Left SRâs were pretty sectarian themselves, however, and since the
whole question of whether to sign the treaty is problematical, how the
Bolsheviks behaved on this issue doesnât prove a great deal. But a lot
more can be said about the way the Bolsheviks related to the peasants in
the late spring and early summer of 1918.
As we noted above, the October Revolution was the outcome of a dual
struggle, carried out by the workers (about three million}, on the one
hand, and the peasants (many millions), on the other. The Bolsheviks
tried to cement this alliance right after the October insurrection by
decreeing that the land belonged to the peasants. (They really had no
choice. The peasants had seized the land themselves and the Bolsheviks
had almost no organization or base of support in the countryside.)
It seems to me that the only potential guarantee for the revolutionary
regime to survive was to maintain the alliance between the workers and
the peasants. But, beginning in June of 1918, the Bolsheviks, under the
guise of âbringing the revolution to the countryside,â launched a
broadside attack on the peasants. In the belief that the kulaks (the
better-off peasants, wealthy enough to hire other peasants as laborers),
were hoarding grain from the cities threatened with starvation, the
Bolsheviks led armed detachments of workers out to the villages to seize
supposedly hoarded grain by force. The Bolsheviks also believed that
there was a substantial layer of poor peasants (peasants who did not
have enough land and who, as a result had to hire themselves out as
laborers to the kulaks) who would support the Bolshevik policy. But in
fact, after the land seizures of late 1917, almost all the peasants were
so-called middle peasants (peasants who had enough land lo maintain
themselves and their families, but who were not wealthy enough to hire
outside help). There were virtually no kulaks or poor peasants,
The Bolsheviksâ policy, as ii turned out, was not to âbring the class
straggle to the countryside,â but an outright assault on the vast
majority of peasants and a severing of the alliance between the workers
in the cities and the peasants in the countryside, It was this tactic
that finally broke the Bolsheviksâ alliance with the Left SRâs and gave
the counterrevolutionary forces (at that point virtually defeated) a maw
base of support.
The result was a bloody civil war that lasted over two and a half years,
virtually destroyed the Russian economy, and devastated the countryside.
When the Bolsheviks finally won (the peasants preferred them, who at
least let them keep the land, to the White counterrevolutionaries who,
when they conquered a territory, took it away), they were hated by
almost everybody.
It has sometimes been argued that the Bolsheviks had no choice but to
seize the grain because the people in the cities were starving and had
nothing to sell to the peasants in exchange for the grain. But the
answer to this is that in 1921, after the civil war, after the country
was laid waste, when the cities had even less to offer the peasants in
exchange for the grain, the Bolsheviks, at Leninâs urging, adopted the
New Economic Policy (NEB) that allowed the peasants the right to trade
grain freely, after they had paid a âtax in kindâ to the state. Had this
policy been pursued in 1918, much if not most of the destruction of the
civil war would have been avoided! The counterrevolutionary forces would
have been without a substantial base of support.
In my view, the Bolsheviksâ course was not just an error. It followed
logically out of the Bolsheviksâ basic outlook and politics,
particularly the state capitalist tendencies mentioned above. The
Bolsheviksâ main concern after the October Revolution was not to
maintain the united front character of the revolution. Their main
interest was to consolidate as much political power in their bands as
possible and to hold onto it by any means necessary, whether or not such
means undermined the popular democratic character of the revolution
itself.
Since, in their view, the working class is the only consistently
revolutionary class, since only the Bolsheviks, with the only true
interpretation of Marxism, really represent the working class, since the
chief political task is the seizure and maintenance of state power, and
since brutal methods are not only allowed but preferred. the Bolsheviks,
after the October Revolution, subordinated every other concern to oneâto
maintain their hold over the state.
I used to believe that the main reason the Bolsheviks did what they did
was the result of external factors, particularly the poverty of the
country, the fact that there were no successful workersâ revolutions in
the more economically developed countries, etc. I now believe that had
there been such revolutions, the outcome, at least in Russia, would not
have been much different than it was. The country would not have been
destroyed and perhaps Bolshevik rule would have beer more benign. But
Russia would still have been ruled by the Bolsheviks and the social
system that would have been established would be state capitalism, not a
libertarian socialism. This is because the fundamental, underlying
politics of the Bolsheviks, particularly the focus on using the state
and their belief that they possessed absolute knowledge of history,
society and politics, were state capitalist.
It is one thing to analyze and criticize Leninism, however, it is
another to come up with a new set of political ideas, one that avoids
the regressive tendencies of the past. This new task that the
Revolutionary Socialist League faces is made a bit feasible if we
recognise one fundamental characteristic of the history and evolution of
our organ bat ion. This is the fact that while our politics have
evolved, the underlying set of values that our politics have been meant
to represent have remained the same, or to be more accurate, have
evolved at a far slower pace. To put it perhaps a bit simplisticaily, I
still believe, and I hope the RSL still believes, that world capitalism
is both an unjust and dangerous system that needs to be, and can only
be, eliminated by an international revolution carried out by the vast
majority of working and oppressed people. The goal of this revolution is
to set up a democratic and egalitarian social system, a society governed
directly and democratically by the members of the formerly oppressed
classes, that has eliminated the extremes of wealth characteristic of
previous social systems and in which the state and other authoritarian
institutions have been eliminated.
Up until two years or so ago, I believed that Leninâs interpretation,
theory and practice, of Marxism represented an embodiment of this ideal
that was both loyal to the ideal and also represented a practical means
of achieving it, I did not see Leninism as perfect, but given the
alternatives, as I understood them, it seemed to offer the best
foundation upon which to elaborate a consistent set of politics.
Such an elaboration is what I think the RSL has tried to do over the
last 15 years. In short, we sought to develop an interpretation of
Leninism (we never accepted anyone elseâs) that both represented our
fundamental ideals and yet stayed within the formal bounds of Leninism.
I donât think this was all wrong, totally inconsistent or ridiculous. It
is easy to look back after youâve been through some experiences and say
that what we used to believe was silly. But that type of thinking
ignores the very process of learning that has enabled one to transcend
the earlier ideas.
Given where we were coming from (in the sense of coming out of the
student movement of the 1960s), and the fact that there was no
significant organized libertarian trend (either revolutionary democratic
socialist or anarchist/anti-authoritarian), our political orientation
and evolution make a lot of sense. And our politics were, I still
believe, the best around. Perhaps if we had been political geniuses we
would have been able lo come up with a totally new set of politics that
went way beyond the political material that we had to work with. But
virtually no set of ideas evolves this way; even the greatest of
intellectual achievements is synthesized out of previous currents.
With the benefit of hindsight, 1 think out main theoretical error was to
misread Lenin in a revolutionary democratic direction. We tended to
overemphasize those elements in Leninâs outlook and practice (which do
exist) that point in a democratic direction and underplay or explain
away the authoritarian elements.
For example, we gave greater weight to The State and Revolution than it
actually had for the Bolsheviks themselves. We also tended to overlook
or downplay those aspects of that work that are authoritarian.
White this was, I now think, a misinterpretation of Leninism, it was not
totally without merit, methodologically speaking. Again, given where we
were coming from and what the apparent alternatives were, to try to
âbendâ the framework of our formal politics to accommodate an
increasingly consistent libertarian instinct is quite logical, even
prudent. Eventually, however, one must resolve contradictions that have
become ever more glaring. One must make some âlargeâ decisions. This is
how I think we should look at our political evolution.
If the RSLs history is seen in this light, 1 think certain things
follow: One, the way to proceed is not to throw everything up for grabs
and try to develop a set of politics totally from scratch.
There are a lot of things we have long believed and which I still
believe to this day.
As I mentioned above in a different form, I donât think capitalism is a
fair or very viable system. I donât think it can be reformed. I think
humanity needs and ought to try to establish a truly democratic,
cooperative and egalitarian social system.
If we sit down and think through the implications and ramifications of
these few sentences, 1 think weâll soon realize how much of our previous
politics we in fact retain. I would certainly describe them differently
than we have in the past and place ourselves differently in terms of
historical political currents. Hut if we look for it, I think we will
see a great deal of continuity in our political thinking and evolution.
I, for one. am not ready to become a Christian socialist or a pacifist,
even though 1 believe we have things to learn from and should be willing
to work with people in these currents.
The second point I think we should keep in mind as we redefine ourselves
is that we should resist moving to the right. Right now the political
climate in the United States and internationally is conservative,
although that is beginning to change.
(One of the reasons for this conservatism is that previous
rationalizations were based on ideologies, such as the various forms of
Leninism, that were in fact authoritarian and hence ultimately
conservative. The rationalizations thus laid the basis for their own
demise.)
In such a period, a political current like ours, especially when it
seeks to redefine itself, comes under great but often invisible pressure
to move right. This rightward pressure can affect a political tendency
in a number of ways. Since in periods like the one we are in. radical
and revolutionary ideas in general are in small favor, there is a lot of
pressure to discard maximal, âutopianâ visions and to advocate piecemeal
reforms. Since so few people today believe that a global classless and
democratic society is possible, it sometimes seems easier to agree with
people on the need for some ârealisticâ changes. In short, in limes such
as these there is a lot of pressure to become reformist, to lessen oneâs
revolutionary opposition to capitalism (as well as state capitalism). I
think we should resist this.
Given the crisis of AIDS, there Is also a strong pull to become more
conservative on sexual/gender questions and related issues that are
generally perceived as âcivil libertarian.â
Lastly, given the quiescence of the working class, especially the
poorest layers of especially oppressed groups (Latins, Blacks, women,
gays, the physically afflicted), it is easy to get influenced by the
(usually self-centered) fads of the middle class (New Age idiocy, an
obsession with personal health, the assault on smokers). Whatever
individuals think or however they want to live their lives, we should
resist having such concerns shift our focus away from the basic source
of social ills, capitalism, and the struggle to overthrow it.
The chief way to resist the pressure toward the right, in my opinion, is
to move the organization to the left. This is also consistent with our
revaluation of Leninism. In my view, the problem with Leninism is not
that it is too radical, too revolutionary, Itâs that it is not radical
or revolutionary enough. It makes too many compromises with capitalism,
embodies too many capitalist ways of thinking and acting lo be a truly
revolutionary force.
For example, although it claims to want to abolish the state in the long
run, it seeks to build it up and strengthen it in the short. It claims
to want to build a society that is democratic and cooperative, but
emphasizes methods that are authoritarian and coercive.
Most important, while it claims to wish to establish a truly free
society, it believes that its ideology, its interpretation of Marxism,
represents the sole correct interpretation of history (and everything
else), thus rejecting the ultimate foundation of freedom, the right lo
think and believe differentlyâintellectual and spiritual freedom, I
think the way to proceed in redefining ourselves politically is
three-fold. First, we should elaborate a vision of freedom, to develop
our conception of what a truly democratic, cooperative and egalitarian
society might look like, (including alternative solutions to various
problems).
In fact, we have done this throughout our history (e.g., our
achievements in the area of gender and sexual liberation), although we
have not always been conscious of what this has meant. More recently, we
have more consciously developed our vision of a libertarian society. We
should continue to develop our ideas in this area and to publicize them
in various ways.
This elaboration of a vision of a free society is quite definitely
anti-Marxist, In opposition to the so-called Utopian Socialists, Marx
and Engels refused to elaborate a vision of the future society. This was
primarily because, in their view, the future society would emerge out of
the class struggle: that society, to use philosophical jargon, is
immanent in history. This view was closely linked to Marx and Engelsâ
belief that history is determined and that the establishment Of
socialism is âhistorically necessary,â in the sense of being inevitable.
If it is, why bother to elaborate a vision?
Today, I no longer believe this. 1 do not believe history is determined
and even if it is, I donât believe we can know what it is that will
happen, lit other words, 1 donât believe I here is absolute knowledge.
Moreover, if history were determined and socialism inevitable. the
result would not be freedom, because inevitability, historical
necessity, does not result in freedom but enslavement to the
historically necessary. A free society can only be possible if there is
the possibility of choice, of humanity choosing to be free rather than
enslaved or annihilated.
The result of all this, it seems to me, is that socialists who believe
in a libertarian socialism, must believe in freedom, must believe that
there is choice ill history, that history is not determined or
ânecessary,â Socialism can only happen if the majority of humanity
decide to want such a society and consciously and democratically set out
to build it. The job of socialists^ therefore, ts to try to convince
workers and other oppressed people that they should fight to establish a
libertarian socialism. Essential to this is to develop a vision of such
a society that shows, as concretely as possible, how such a society
could be run, and how various problems bequeathed lo us by capitalism
might be solved.
The second part of redefining ourselves is to think through our
strategy, tactics, organizational principles and methods and modify them
so that they are consistent with our vision, in my opinion, the main
change that this involves vis-a-vis our former conception is in the
tactic of the united front. To Leninists, the united front, along with
the corresponding tactic of critical support, is meant to win over the
base of a rival political organization and to discredit and destroy the
rival political leadership. In other words, itâs a policy of trying to
stab some people in the back, in some cases, e.g., reformist
bureaucrats, this is warranted. But the Bolsheviks believed that only
they represented the true interests of the workers and therefore arty
rival organization, no matter how revolutionary, was ultimately an agent
of the bourgeoisie.
Today, since we no longer believe in absolute truth and that we, by
ourselves, have access to it, we should see the united front as a way to
work together with other organizations and individuals, to engage in a
dialogue with them, and to seek to learn from them. Perhaps we will team
more from them than vice versa.
Lastly, and flowing from the above, we should look for organizations,
groups and individuals who share our overall vision (defined relatively
broadly), and seek to develop on-going relations with them, trying to
build greater theoretical and practical unity over time. This may well
mean substantial changes in the form of our organization.
1 personally believe that most such groups and people will be found in
the anarchist/libertarian milieu rather than in the Marxist or social
democratic milieus. The latter are too burdened with statism, the belief
in the inherent progressiveness of nationalized property and stale
planning and various other baggage that points toward state capitalism.
A basic methodological rule of thumb is that our political work,
theoretical and practical, should avoid being determined by abstract
political categories. Just because some groups or persons define
themselves differently than we do or use a different political
terminology should not be a basis for rejecting entering into a dialogue
and joint work with them.
Or, conversely, just because people define themselves as we do and use
the same language should not mean we automatically agree. Intellectual
categories, especially political ones, can be misleading and
intellectually crippling- For years, we called ourselves
(Marxist-Leninist} Trotskyists, but did not agree with the fundamental
values, let alone the less important things, of the groups that called
themselves Trotskyists. This should be a lesson for us, in this light, I
donât see what 1 have been proposing that (he organization try to do as
a drastic âturnâ or reorientation of our politics, i see it as a kind of
continuation of the political search that has defined our existence from
(he very beginning. This search âa search for a road to freedomâhaft
taken us across (he boundaries of traditional political categories. The
search has been consistent and, in fact, more or less in the same
direction. It just hasnât let itself be determined, or at least not for
long, by other peopleâs categories,
Once, we were Marxists and Leninists, but not Trotskyists. For a while
we were Trotskyists who thought Trotsky was wrong, insufficiently
libertarian, about Russia. Now, in my opinion, we have passed the line
that demarcates Trotskyism and Leninism into something else, something
that we need to define. We should let other people remain imprisoned by
their categories and continue to determine our own, to he our own.
I think the main thing that has changed, the main thing that we have
learned, is that there is no absolute knowledge. Before, we looked for
some kind of system, some kind of ideology, that answered all questions.
Now we know that that doesnât exist and that systems and ideologies that
claim to embody absolute knowledge, to answer all the questions, are
inherently dangerous.
Today, we know that the (relative, changing) truth can only be found
through a dialogue, a discussion among different groups and individuals.
Humanity can only solve its problems if it can discuss them, talk about
them and arrive at democratic decisions. Lenin, following Marx (who in
turn followed Hegel), subsumed dialogue in the dialectic of history
(which eventually arrives at socialism) and an absolute knowledge of
that history, Marxism.
Although Lenin was subjectively for freedom, he helped snuff it out,
because he believed that historical truth was embodied in the Bolshevik
Party, We have to recognize that only a dialectic that never ceases, a
dialogue among human beings, can lead to freedom.