đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş andrew-robinson-why-deleuze-still-matters.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 21:31:27. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ď¸ Previous capture (2023-01-29)
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Why Deleuze (still) matters Author: Andrew Robinson Date: 2010 Language: en Topics: Deleuze, Guattari, Philosophy, anti-state Source: https://ceasefiremagazine.co.uk/in-theory-deleuze-war-machine/
The usefulness of Deleuzian theory for social transformation will vary
with the selection of which conceptual contributions one chooses to
appropriate. Studying Deleuzian theory is complicated by characteristics
of Deleuze and Guattariâs philosophical method. In What is Philosophy?,
they define the function of theory in terms of proliferating concepts â
inventing new conceptual categories which construct new ways of seeing.
In common with many constructivists, they take the view that our
relationship to the world is filtered through our conceptual categories.
Distinctively, they also view agency in terms of differentiation â each
person or group creates itself, not by selecting among available
alternatives, but by splitting existing totalities through the creation
of new differences. This approach leads to a proliferation of different
concepts which, across Deleuze and Guattariâs collaborative and
individual works, total in the hundreds.
Instead of seeking to trim their conceptual innovations and neologisms
(new words) for simplicity and necessity (an efficiency model of theory
â âjust in timeâ, like modern production), they multiply concepts as
tools for use, which, although possibly redundant in some analyses, may
be useful for others (a resilience model of theory â âjust in caseâ,
like indigenous and autonomous cultures). They encourage readers to pick
and choose from their concepts, selecting those which are useful and
simply passing by those which are not. This has contributed to the
spread of diverse Deleuzian approaches which draw on different aspects
of their work, but also makes it easy for people to make incomplete
readings of their theories, appropriating certain concepts for
incompatible theoretical projects while rejecting the revolutionary
dynamic of the theory itself. As a result, a large proportion of what
passes for Deleuzian theory has limited resonance with the general gist
of Deleuze and Guattariâs work, which is not at all about reconciling
oneself to the dominant system, but rather, is about constructing other
kinds of social relations impossible within the dominant frame. The
proliferation of concepts is intended to support such constructions of
other ways of being. Another effect of the proliferation of concepts is
to make Deleuzian theory difficult to explain or express in its
entirety.
In this article, I have chosen to concentrate on the conceptual pairing
of states and war-machines as a way of understanding the differences
between autonomous social networks and hierarchical, repressive
formations. Deleuze and Guattari view the âstateâ as a particular kind
of institutional regime derived from a set of social relations which can
be traced to a way of seeing focused on the construction of fixities and
representation. There is thus a basic form of the state (a âstate-formâ)
in spite of the differences among specific states. Since Deleuze and
Guattariâs theory is primarily relational and processual, the state
exists primarily as a process rather than a thing. The state-form is
defined by the processes or practices of âovercodingâ, âdespotic
significationâ and âmachinic enslavementâ. These attributes can be
explained one at a time. The concept of despotic signification, derived
from Lacanâs idea of the master-signifier, suggests that, in statist
thought, a particular signifier is elevated to the status of standing
for the whole, and the other of this signifier (remembering that
signification is necessarily differential) is defined as radically
excluded. âOvercodingâ consists in the imposition of the regime of
meanings arising from this fixing of representations on the various
processes through which social life and desire operate. In contrast to
the deep penetration which occurs in capitalism, states often do this
fairly lightly, but with brutality around the edges. Hence for instance,
in historical despotic states, the inclusion of peripheral areas only
required their symbolic subordination, and not any real impact on
everyday life in these areas. Overcoding also, however, entails the
destruction of anything which cannot be represented or encoded.
âMachinic enslavementâ occurs when assembled groups of social relations
and desires, known in Deleuzian theory as âmachinesâ, are rendered
subordinate to the regulatory function of the despotic signifier and
hence incorporated in an overarching totality. This process identifies
Deleuze and Guattariâs view of the state-form with Mumfordâs idea of the
megamachine, with the state operating as a kind of absorbing and
enclosing totality, a bit like the Borg in Star Trek, eating up and
assimilating the social networks with which it comes into contact.
Crucially, while these relations it absorbs often start out as
horizontal, or as hierarchical only at a local level, their absorption
rearranges them as vertical and hierarchical aggregates. It tends to
destroy or reduce the intensity of horizontal connections, instead
increasing the intensity of vertical subordination. Take, for instance,
the formation of the colonial state in Africa: loose social identities
were rigidly reclassified as exclusive ethnicities, and these
ethnicities were arranged in hierarchies (for instance, Tutsi as
superior to Hutu) in ways which created rigid boundaries and oppressive
relations culminating in todayâs conflicts.
According to this theory of the state-form, states are at once
âisomorphicâ, sharing a basic structure and function, and heterogeneous,
differing in how they express this structure. In particular, states vary
in terms of the relative balance between âaddingâ and âsubtracting
axiomsâ (capitalism is also seen as performing these two operations). An
axiom here refers to the inclusion of a particular group or social logic
or set of desires as something recognised by a state: examples of
addition of axioms would be the recognition of minority rights (e.g. gay
rights), the recognition and systematic inclusion of minority groups in
formal multiculturalism (e.g. Indian âscheduled castesâ), the creation
of niche markets for particular groups (e.g. âethnic foodâ sections in
supermarkets), and the provision of inclusive services (e.g. support for
independent living for people with disabilities). It is most marked in
social-democratic kinds of states. The subtraction of axioms consists in
the encoding of differences as problems to be suppressed, for example in
the classification of differences as crimes, the institutionalisation of
unwanted minorities (e.g. âsectioningâ people who are psychologically
different), or the restriction of services to members of an in-group
(excluding âdisruptiveâ children, denying council housing to migrants).
This process reaches its culmination in totalitarian states. It is
important to realise that in both cases, the state is expressing the
logic of the state-form, finding ways to encode and represent
differences; but that the effects of the two strategies on the freedom
and social power of marginalised groups are very different.
The state is also viewed as a force of âantiproductionâ. This term is
defined against the âproductiveâ or creative power Deleuze and Guattari
believe resides in processes of desiring-production (the process through
which desires are formed and connected to objects or others) and social
production (the process of constructing social âassemblagesâ or
networks). Desiring-production tends to proliferate differences, because
desire operates through fluxes and breaks, overflowing particular
boundaries. The state as machine of antiproduction operates to restrict,
prevent or channel these flows of creative energy so as to preserve
fixed social forms and restrict the extent of difference which is able
to exist, or the connections it is able to form. Hence, states try to
restrict and break down the coming-together of social networks by
prohibiting or making difficult the formation of hierarchical
assemblages; it operates to block âsubject-formationâ in terms of social
groups, or the emergence of subjectivities which are not already encoded
in dominant terms. Take for instance the laws on âdispersalâ, in which
the British state allows police to break up groups (often of young
people) congregating in public spaces. Absurdly, the state defines the
social act of coming-together as anti-social, because it creates a space
in which different kinds of social relations can be formed. The state
wishes to have a monopoly on how people interrelate, and so acts to
prevent people from associating horizontally. Another example of
antiproduction is the way that participation in imposed activities such
as the requirement to work and the unpaid reproductive labour involved
in families, leaves little time for other kinds of relationships â
people donât have time to form other assemblages either with other
people or with other objects of desire. Hakim Bey has argued that this
pressure to restrict connections is so strong that simply finding time
and space for other forms of belonging â regardless of the goal of these
other connections â is already a victory against the system.
So what, in Deleuzian theory, is the alternative to the state? Deleuze
and Guattari argue for a type of assemblage (social group or cluster of
relations) which they refer to as the âwar-machineâ, though with the
proviso that certain kinds of âwar-machinesâ can also be captured and
used by states. This should not be considered a militarist theory, and
the term âwar-machineâ is in many respects misleading. It is used
because Deleuze and Guattari derive their theory from Pierre Clastresâ
theory of the role of ritualised (often non-lethal) warfare among
indigenous groups. Paul Patton has suggested that the war-machine would
be better called a metamorphosis-machine, others have used the term
âdifference engineâ, a machine of differentiation, and there is a lot of
overlap with the idea of autonomous groups or movements in how the
war-machine is theorised. We should also remember that âmachineâ in
Deleuze and Guattari simply refers to a combination of forces or
elements; it does not have overtones of instrumentalism or of mindless
mechanisms â a social group, an ecosystem, a knight on horseback are all
âmachinesâ. The term âwar-machineâ has the unfortunate connotations of
brutal military machinery and of uncontrollable militarist apparatuses
such as NATO, which operate with a machine-like rigidity and inhumanity
(c.f. the phrase âmilitary-industrial complexâ).
For Deleuze and Guattari, these kinds of statist war-machines are also
war-machines of a sort, because they descend from a historical process
through which states âcapturedâ or incorporated autonomous social
movements (particularly those of nomadic indigenous societies) and made
them part of the state so as to contain their subversive power. Early
states learned to capture war-machines because they were previously
vulnerable to being destroyed by the war-machines of nomadic stateless
societies, having no similar means of response. Hence, armies are a kind
of hybrid social form, containing some of the power of autonomous
war-machines but contained in such a way as to harness it to state
instrumentalism and inhumanity. Captured in this way, war-machines lose
their affirmative force, becoming simply machines of purposeless
destruction â having lost the purpose of deterritorialisation (see
below), they take on the purpose of pure war as a goal in itself.
Deleuze and Guattari argue that state-captured war-machines are
regaining their autonomy in a dangerous way, tending to replace limited
war in the service of a stateâs goals with a drive to total war. This
drive is expressed for instance in the âwar on terrorâ as permanent
state of emergency. There was a recent controversy about Israeli
strategists adopting Deleuzian ideas, which reflects the continuities
between state war-machines and autonomous war-machines, but depends on a
selective conceptual misreading in which the drive to total war
denounced by Deleuze and Guattari is explicitly valorised. The Israeli
army is a captured war-machine in the worst possible sense, pursuing the
destruction of othersâ existential territories in order to accumulate
destructive power for a state. For Deleuze and Guattari, it is not the
Israeli army but the Palestinian resistance which is a war-machine in
the full sense.
The autonomous war-machine, as opposed to the state-captured
war-machine, is a form of social assemblage directed against the state,
and against the coalescence of sovereignty. The way such machines
undermine the state is by exercising diffuse power to break down
concentrated power, and through the replacement of âstriatedâ
(regulated, marked) space with âsmoothâ space (although the war-machine
is the âconstituent element of smooth spaceâ, I shall save discussion of
smooth space for some other time). In Clastresâ account of Amazonian
societies, on which Deleuze and Guattariâs theory is based, this is done
by means of each band defending its own autonomy, and reacting to any
potential accumulation of power by other bands. One could similarly
think of how neighbourhood gangs resist subordination by rival gangs, or
how autonomous social movements resist concentrations of political
power. Autonomous social movements, such as the European squattersâ
movement, the Zapatistas, and networks of protest against summits, are
the principal example Deleuze and Guattari have in mind of war-machines
in the global North, though they also use the concept in relation to
Southern guerrilla and popular movements such as the Palestinian
intifada and the Vietnamese resistance to American occupation, and also
in relation to everyday practices of indigenous groups resisting state
control.
One could also argue that the âwar-machineâ is implicit in practices of
everyday resistance of the kind studies by James Scott. Marginal groups,
termed âminoritiesâ in Deleuzian theory, often coalesce as war-machines
because the state-form is inappropriate for them.
According to Deleuze and Guattari, war is not the aim of the war-machine
(except when it is captured by the state); rather, war-machines tend to
end up in a situation of war with states because of the
incommensurability of the war-machine with the state and with striated
space. War-machines end up in conflict with states because their goal is
the âdeterritorialisationâ of the rigid fixities of state space, often
to create space for difference or for particular ways of life. Think for
instance of squattersâ movements: in themselves they do not aim for
conflict, but rather, seek different kinds of arrangements of space by
forming new combinations of unused geographical spaces with otherwise
âspacelessâ social groups. Yet such movements are often forced into
conflict with the machinery of state repression because the state
ignores, or refuses to recognise these new articulations. As I write
this, the JB Spray squat in Nottingham is continuing a campaign of
resistance to reoccupation by state forces acting on behalf of
capitalist owners who have no intent of putting the space to use. This
is a struggle I would very much encourage readers to support (see this
article and related links for details; contact 07817493824 or email
jbspray[at]hotmail.co.uk). It is also a clear, local example of how
autonomous social movements are forced into conflict by the stateâs
drive to repress difference.
War-machines are also associated with the formation of special types of
groups which are variously termed âbandsâ, âpacksâ and âmultiplicitiesâ.
These groups are seen as operating as dense local clusters of
emotionally-intense connections, strongly differentiated from the
âmassâ, which is a type of group based on large scale, lack of intensity
and vertical integration. âPacksâ or âbandsâ instead form as unstable
groups, avoiding fixed hierarchies (any leaders emerging are subject to
rapid succession), usually with small numbers, and dispersed through
space rather than concentrated in particular sites. Their diffusion is
enabled by a multiplicity of objectives which resonate through
horizontal, molecular connections rather than being represented in
overarching structures. They tend to detach materials from the
connections in which they are inserted in the dominant system, instead
reconstructing different âuniversesâ or perspectives around other ways
of seeing and relating. One can think for instance of the way groups of
children reconstruct urban spaces as spaces of play, finding new,
dissident uses for objects such as shopping trollies. For Deleuze and
Guattari, the process of forming âbandsâ or âpacksâ is necessarily
dangerous, risking the self-destructive implosion of small groups, but
also offering hopeful possibilities of forming ways of relating which
are more open to difference than those prevalent in the dominant system.
Deleuze and Guattariâs usefulness for radical activism is by no means
limited to this particular pair of concepts, but this way of thinking
about social transformation raises useful questions and provides
insights into how autonomous groups differ from dominant hierarchical
forms of social collectivity. For instance, this theory points towards
the need to avoid duplicating statist ways of relating within autonomous
spaces, and to avoid coalescing in formal organisations which ultimately
lead back into the state-form (albeit usually through the addition of
axioms). It also suggests the inevitability of antagonism between
radical movements and the state, even when the goal of a radical
movement is simply to defend or express its own difference.
Strategically, therefore, autonomous activists need to be prepared to
âward offâ the state, both within movements (by challenging statist ways
of thinking and acting) and in relation to the wider context (by
resisting state repression). According to Deleuze and Guattari, there is
a basic incompatibility between state âantiproductionâ and the
flourishing of difference, and this requires overcoming the former. This
requires attention to the creation and defence of autonomous spaces, in
full awareness of their underlying transformative potential.