đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș william-gillis-two-definitions-of-power.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:44:37. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Two Definitions Of Power Author: William Gillis Date: 13th November 2009 Language: en Topics: power Source: http://humaniterations.net/2009/11/13/two-definitions-of-power/
In our everyday language we often to use the term âpowerâ in very
different ways. This can lead to all manner of confusion. Worse, it can
hobble our own understanding of a situation and allow others to twist
and distort our capacity to call shit out. The Bolsheviks infamously
appropriated and distorted the decentralist, anti-state slogan âAll
Power to the Soviets!â into a rallying cry for centralized state
control. Today one can visit a demonstration and simultaneously see
âPower To The Peopleâ sprayed on walls while at the same time âFight The
Powerâ blasts out a stereo. In activist critiques talk of âempowermentâ
runs parallel to struggles to âabolish all power relations.â All of
these notions are clearly related, but the occasional dissonance between
them poses a danger worth addressing.
There are ultimately, I feel, two broad ways we think of and use the
term âpowerâ:
1. Power as capacity. The enhancement or expansion of oneâs options.
2. Power as control. The limitation or suppression of oneâs options.
With empowerment, aside from the abstract connotations of
self-actualization, whatâs really being said is: one has the capacity to
do something. When one has the âpower to lift somethingâ one has the
ability to lift it.
But with the strict sociological definition of power, we specifically
refer to control over another; coercion perhaps not conveyed in violence
or the threat of violence, but nevertheless a situation where one person
looses to some degree their own agency to become a extension of some
external will. Or, in the material case, where an objectâs behavior is
determined more fully by oneâs will. On a first glance this appears to
follow from the definition as capacity â when you control other people
that control can grant you the capacity to undertake vast projects, to
build pyramids and pick cotton.
We say that one individual has âpower over anotherâ when they can
determine that individualâs actions/thoughts. However that same phrase
can be â and often is â read as having more power than another. Thus
power might simply be a quantity. A substance, the unequal distribution
of which between the two individuals is the source of the determination
of the otherâs thoughts/actions. This is the classical Marxist position,
often directly referring to the distribution of resources. One person
âhasâ more resources and these resources lend them the capacity to take
certain actions with a varying degree of force. Between two individuals
the one with the most material capacity can win any contention between
wills, and thus has control over the other because they have more
capacity. Further this control, once obtained, can grant the controlling
party the capacity to do even more. Capacity, being the root concept in
this model, often appears to be the subject best deserving the
recognition of the term âpower.â
But is this really so?
We can easily conceive of a situation where, despite equal allocations
of capacity, both individuals are capable of coercing one another. Even
further, occasions where they do_._ Two people can assert a high degree
of control over one another without either acquiring any additional
capacity â with, in fact, such control limiting both of them.
This is not just a specific hypothetical, this is the most common case._
_
One might be intelligent and manipulative while the other might be
strong and brutal. Both individualâs wills would be constrained by the
otherâs conditions. The brute may intimidate the conman while
simultaneously be in turn manipulated by him. The conmanâs agency
constrained by the ever-present threat of the bruteâs fury on some
areas, while the brute may be beguiled into certain forms of behavior.
One might object that this only demonstrates the existence of different
kinds of power. But we can, with a little more thought, replicate the
same phenomenon with two conmen or two brutes. While in a contest of
wills neither party will triumph in achieving their goal, both parties
find themselves constrained. Even if one party finally triumphs, the
extra exertion is limiting.
The contest of wills itself is constraining. And yet neither party would
consider the other powerless. In fact both would likely consider the
other to be exerting power over them. The conmen in particular may find
themselves ever more deeply wrapped in a relationship they are unable to
escape, their thoughts ever more dominated by reactive calculations.
In short, both parties capacities are reduced while we do not say the
same of their power. Power thus seems to operate as âcontrol.â In
everyday use we donât run across situations where one speaks of âhaving
powerâ in a situation of high capacity and low control. But there are
situations where one âhas powerâ with high control and low capacity.
Weâre reminded of the classic image of a king becomes a slave to his own
throne. He has power â control â but is controlled himself by the
maintenance of it.
Power then â despite some sloppy thinking â is best referenced in the
social realm not as a quantity of capacity but rather a relationship of
control. Often to some degree mutual control.
Power is a psychosis. Our goal as Anarchists is not to equalize power
and give everyone the same 5.3 milliHitlers of oppression each. Unlike
the Marxists our goal is not to attempt some balancing of the books.
Itâs to overcome the very premise of our existing social relations.
âIt seems to me that the truly American Revolution would be to abolish
power.â
âKarl Hess.