đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș william-gillis-debt-the-possibilities-ignored.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:41:39. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Debt: The Possibilities Ignored Author: William Gillis Date: October 7th, 2014 Language: en Topics: book review, debt Source: https://c4ss.org/content/24459
Itâs no secret that economists and libertarians have developed a bad
habit of assuming things about history and other societies on first
principle without actually checking archaeological or anthropological
findings. On occasion the divide can be quite stark. David Graeberâs
Debt: The First 5000 Years gets a lot of momentum by attacking a widely
circulated economic fable purporting to explain the origin of currency
wherein coinage precedes credit. It shouldnât be a surprise that the âI
need a blanket and all I have to barter with are five chickens but
everyone in my village likes cowry shellsâ dilemma at the start of
elementary economics textbooks has no clear historical basis; thereâs
little evidence small tribes or villages needed to invent physical
currency to facilitate market exchange internally because reputation and
credit are far more natural and flexible.
To say this is sympathetic territory for me would be an understatement.
In my longest essay in Markets Not Capitalism I emphasized the role
reputation and goodwill play in relationships as more fundamental and
foundational than property titles and critiqued the recurring assumption
that property titles are inherent to all societies. Even though my
conclusion was a full-throated defense of property titles, albeit
repositioned as a looser, less absolute, second order derivation from
goodwill and reputation, you might be forgiven for expecting a strictly
positive review of Graeberâs breakout book. Certainly many of my
colleagues did. And there is a lot to be found of value in Debt for
libertarians and anarchists of all stripes. It is a refreshingly
audacious work hearkening towards the kind of grand theory building
radicals used to do and Iâve found myself handing it out to young
activists hungry for something of more audacity and scope than
Gelderloos or Bonanno. Itâs been far too long since a work of anarchist
theory topped bestseller lists. And anything that so flusters and
discombobulates liberals, marxists, and vulgar libertarians alike is
surely of value.
However Debt is not without its flaws, some of them quite vexing.
Perhaps the greatest thing about anthropology is its capacity to
demonstrate that often unexamined norms we consider universal are but a
tiny sliver in the phase space of cultural and societal configurations
that have existed throughout human history. Anthropology helps serve as
a reminder of the paucity of our imagination. Yet it is important not to
blindly take history as a constraint. Two hundred thousand years of homo
sapiens is simply too few iterations, too tightly correlated to truly
explore the expanse of what is possible.
Sadly, if there is one underlying failure coursing through Graeberâs
bestseller itâs his reactionary instincts in the face of such
possibility.
Debt sets out a long and winding exploration of how notions of the
interpersonal or economic obligations characterized as âdebtâ have
morphed over the last five thousand years and how these changes
correlated to the presence of state violence and the development of
currency.
Graeber suggests that the first currencies were direct markers of honor,
status, or social goodwill only incidentally exchanged for goods and
commodities. Coinage and specie currency were sharp deviations from this
norm, invented so religious institutions could keep internal accounts of
goods but quickly adopted by states to quantify penal codes, collect
taxes, and pay marauding soldiers. Coinage, Graeber argues, was an
invention imposed by the state to dissolve the complexity of informal
bonds between individuals into relations as universal and
interchangeable as its own scope. In this context debt tended towards
outright slavery and the specific game theoretic dynamics that
characterize statism grew increasingly hegemonic. When your honor or the
value you held to others was simplified to the widely interchangeable
gold in your pouch, throat-slitting became suddenly quite appealing.
Surrounding this historical transition the wild array of dynamics and
social mores at play in various societies became increasingly framed in
terms of person-to-person exchanges (theoretically repayable) rather
than standing before the community or as matters of hierarchically
ritualized benefaction. And in turn, through its persistent creep as a
metaphor to frame human relations as exchanges (implicitly between
equals or should-be-equals), debt came to signify an unnatural
perturbation of baseline equality. While on the one hand the word
âfreedomâ has its roots in Sumerian debt-cancellation, that same
moralistic language of obligation to oneâs debts was frequently adopted
by the oppressed and those with grievances. Amid all of this communities
on the periphery played games with notions of perpetual debt to denote
and enforce ties of fraternity, but on the whole debt increasingly came
to connote a sinful state of inequality and injustice. âŠExcept with
things so tangled that exactly who is in the wrong is never entirely
clear and consistent rules never really hashed out. Thus, Graeber
concludes, we arrived at the ridiculousness of our present situation
where for instance plutocratic plunder and the vast subsidy of
historical violence are seen as prompt for charity, but the notion of
cancelling the supposed debt incurred to oneâs explicit oppressors is
unthinkable.
Though certain chapters are resplendent with crowing at the repeated
close confluence of money, markets and the atrocities of state power, to
his credit as an intellectually honest academic Graeber doesnât flinch
away from recognizing situations where state power has withered and
markets blossomed.
There have, certainly, been times and places when a kind of free market
populism has emerged, where markets began operating independently of
governments, at least to some degree â Medieval Islam is one famous
example, and later, Ming Chinaâbut in such cases, they tended to operate
in very different ways than the kind of markets weâre now familiar with,
less about competition, much more about creating and maintaining
relations of interpersonal trust, or for instance, profit-sharing
operations instead of interest, etc etc.
âŠHistory shows that you basically need a state to create a situation
where people are willing to sign on basically as rent-a-slaves to other
people.
That many observers, some with horror, have read these asides as
validation of left market anarchist theory is unsurprising. We are of
course totally right. About everything. Obviously. But Graeber is less
than enthused to see these confessions extend beyond proving the
unsustainability of capitalism in the absence of state violence. Free
market populism, in his framework, is still an ultimately confused state
of affairs, championed by the well-meaning but insufficiently
far-seeing. Useful perhaps as a half measure for the US and a few other
contexts where anarcho-communist alternatives are beyond culturally
alien, but not an ideal goal. For Graeber markets and currency cannot
shed the incredibly suspicious stain of their inception through state
violence. Currency in particular.
Lest we get too lost in the default rhetorical devices of radicals, let
us remind ourselves that if Hitler popularized consensus process or the
refrigerator it wouldnât invalidate either. But in fact history and
prehistory are almost certainly more complicated than the selection
Graeber presents in his tale. Mass societies have been around for a hell
of a long time and so has trade in obsidian, grain, cattle and copper.
Things werenât nearly as simple as one day villages and the next day
Mesopotamian scribes keeping accounts in silver; we know thereâs a ton
of history lost before the proliferation of writing. Gift economies are
empirically known to scale poorly, and itâs obvious that when thereâs
too many people to personally keep track of the approaches that work for
villages and tribes start to break down. If cities nine thousand years
ago like the famous ĂatalhöyĂŒk werenât characterized by intense
statismâand thereâs less than no reason to suspect they wereâfolks very
likely faced double incidence of wants on a regular basis. In particular
the five thousand years of mass society before Graeber starts his
account saw many profound social changes, my favorite tale of which is
this:
On a certain day 9200 years ago the manorial houses at the north side of
the large square in ĂayönĂŒ were burnt down, and this happened so fast
that the owners were not able to save any of their treasures. The temple
was torn down and burnt, and even the floor was ripped open, the stone
pillars around the free space were taken down and the taller of them
were broken up. The place itself â previously maintained and kept
meticulously clean for more than 1000 years â was converted into a
municipal waste dump. After a short chaotic transition all houses had
been torn down. The slums in the west disappeared for good, but only a
few steps away from the spot where the ruins of the manorial houses had
burnt the new ĂayönĂŒ was erected. The new houses were comparable in size
to the old manors but there were no more houses or shacks built to an
inferior standard. In all houses, work was done and all hints to social
differences were erased.
âŠNot only did the revolutionaries of those remote times succeed in
overthrowing a regime thousands of years old, bloody and exploitative â
moreover, they also succeeded in developing their own alternative
society, devising and realizing it. An egalitarian, classless society
arises in which women and men are equal, a society which rapidly spreads
over the whole of Anatolia and almost simultaneously over the Balcans
and which endures for 3000 years.
When Mesopotamian scribes finally pick up the pen to give us more direct
accounts we are not glimpsing the first steps, but a very particular
product of a richly storied past we have only fleeting access to.
Sure, when credit is feasible thereâs no need for the convoluted dance
of boots into obsidian or grain and then back into chickens, but when
thereâs thousands of teeming peopleâwhen people have options outside a
tightly controlled tribe, neighborhood, or casteâcredit frequently
becomes less secure and/or efficient than spot transactions. We know
from the North American Great Plains that even when the land wonât
support it longer than a few weeks, people will still often struggle to
form mass societies when and where they can to take advantage of the
benefits such provides in novelty, culture and general opportunity.
Hereâs an alternative postulate to Graeberâs: Early mass societies arose
and iterated through very different forms and there were many avenues by
which they tackled the limits of gift economies. Some mass societies
simply preserved the village model internally by subdividing (or
remaining divided) into neighborhoods, clans and castes where gift
economies could be retained internally while they continued to trade
with one another externally, but the danger of losing excommunication as
the ultimate sanction required these divisions to still be policed
relatively tightly lest individuals start abandoning their ties and
debts for greener pastures. Some mass societies with more idealic roots,
either as cultural loci or the result of slave uprisings that shrugged
off ruling castes leaving behind a single relatively unsubdivided mass
of individuals, were obliged to turn more strongly to barter. Lastly
still other mass societies, possibly where the maintenance of clans,
castes or even polycentric associations had become problematic, resorted
to the sort of centralized arbitration and accounting that eventually
fueled the fires of empire seen thousands of years later in Mesopotamia
where Graeber blithely starts his tale.
But even after his launching point there are systemic biases against
anarchistic mass societies in the historical record that he should be
damn well aware of. No, in the absence of pharaohs and emperors we donât
tend to erect giant edifices to our glory or stamp millions of coins,
but that doesnât mean freer societies left no trace. By focusing on the
classical states of antiquity and then, upon arriving at more recent
ages, pointing out that the more free market societies that arose
afterward arose afterward, Graeber occludes numerous points any other
anarchist historian would place front and center. The gist of which is
that freer societies have certainly existed in a great multitude between
the gaps in the statistâs saga of war and empire. Some, like the
Harappans, major contemporaries of Mesopotamian tyranny, left no signs
of priests or leaders, no palaces, temples or monuments. A flourishing
trader and artisan society they likely had a spectrum of social respect
or at least a diversity of focuses (visible through differences in
adornment) while at the same time capital was egalitarianly distributed.
They led advancements in the purity of metallurgy, docks, wheeled
transport and adopted uniform weightsâtestaments to how central trade
and quantified exchange were to their society. Despite their intense
noteworthiness in size, accomplishment and impact, popular history has
largely dismissed them for not making reference in any major wars. (And,
most deliciously, certain scholars have dismissed them as obviously
having a state because they had plumbing.)
I think itâs intuitively obvious that credit and debt preceded
currencies focused on coordinating goods. And the introduction of
universal metal coinage has both the unmistakable scent of the stateâs
drive to universalize and the gangsterâs need for contextless cash. But
the notion that the concerns found in widespread barter only arose as an
occasional byproduct of the statist imposition of markets and central
currencies as means of accounting is simply unsubstantiatable. Neither
Graeber nor I have a time machine and the most relevant particulars to
that kind of claim take place before he even begins his story. In the
absence of young upstart mass societies just developing in the wilds of
Brazil, say, the evidence is scant. Thankfully we can at least get
somewhere modeling these kinds of things and that is precisely what
economists have done with extensive consideration and mathematical
modeling.
Which brings us to a particularly irksome current in Debt. If the bookâs
systemic failure is not recognizing the breadth of the possible,
Graeberâs weakest and at times most embarrassing arguments by far stem
from his assertion that a critical distinction between good obligations
and bad ones is whether or not anyoneâs gotten rigorous or considered
about it. In his worst moments he blames mathematics, and indeed
elevates it as a comparable evil as you know, loan sharks bludgeoning
people to death:
Debt is just a perversion of a promise. It is a promise corrupted by
both math and violence.
Of course whatâs actually happening is not an issue with mathematics or
even arithmetic and quantification, itâs an issue with violently imposed
universal simplifications of richly complicated or localized dynamics.
The problem is the state and the legalistic impulse that underpins it
here, not the innate tendency of human minds to geek out and analyze
shit in pursuit of precision and efficiency. Mathematical analysis unto
itself in no way implies oversimplification or misrepresentation. And
while there are often limits to what we can know and calculate in a
given context, especially when dealing with other minds, such
limitations are themselves mathematical dynamics. There is just as much
to be gained from augmenting our interactions with awareness of these
limitations as there is from using mathematical modeling directly when
and where it can clarify dynamics and expand our agency.
Distinctions between what can and canât be quantified substantively in
different dynamics and contexts have long been core to modern
libertarian analysis, both in the pragmatically mathematical Hayekian
sense and the more analytic Praxeological sense. Certainly the legal
codification of remuneration for honor violations in units of Irish
slave girls, as per one example from Debt, fails virtually every
economic and libertarian precept imaginable. That said, there is
something quite interesting and fresh in Graeberâs implicit attack on
the valuation of gold as a near-universal mediator of social debts. The
loss of nuanced social information happening when you can exactly
ârepayâ a friend for their kindness in precious metals is surely stark.
Or at least it is when such repayment isnât a trust-building exercise
and a product of their subjective desire via some fresh negotiation that
validates both parties as human beings with unknowable subjectivities,
but an exchange in which one or both parties can merely default on
static universal standards with little to no consideration of the other
as a complex individual. The very notion of going back to âsquare oneâ
strangerhood through repayment, of erasing the accounts containing the
context of prior interactions, is only possible when tracking and
conveying a particular personâs trustworthiness is impossible, where
there are no true currencies available, just dumb commodities like gold
that donât even have a public ledger.
Yet it should be obvious that such situations are not a product of
quantification! The impulse seen in the use of coinage to dismiss rich
context or make declarations about the objective comparative value of
incredibly complex and situational things like favors is clearly sloppy
at best and dangerous as hell at worst. But thatâs completely different
from using a measuring cup when loaning your neighbor rice (or gold) so
thereâs no lingering misperceptions, disagreements or wasteful default
biases. Artificially simplifying universal norms are only sustainable
when thereâs coercion backing them on some level. The issue is whether
debts are enforced through the violent suppression of contextual
awareness or the voluntary maximization of it through reputation, trust
networks, and risk conveyance. By the time there are kings, chiefs,
governments, oligarchs, or central committees remotely capable of
revoking debt, things have obviously gone too far and the whole system
can be assumed rotten. But the imposition of universal simplifications
certainly doesnât satiate anyoneâs drive for precision and informed
agency save the rulers, indeed it acts to suppress precision and complex
analytic depth at play in our relationships and calculations with regard
to one another. The sort of debts Graeber conveys are not, as he puts
it, the collaboration of violence and math but rather the suppression of
math by violence.
You may ask why I dwell so strongly on this theme within Debt. The
misuse of something as richly descriptive and human as mathematics to
refer to arithmetic and artificially simple quantification is irritating
to be sure, yet I feel this framing belies something deeper than
mischosen words. Graeber makes quite a lot to turn on the distinction
between quantified and unquantified interactions but in his writing he
rarely stays content with such, expanding this theme to decry the
âimpersonalismâ of mathematics and reason. Now one might say math and
reason are defined by their search for global symmetries in a world of
messy particulars, something that can momentarily disregard those
particulars, but in application math and reason have infinitely rich
descriptive capacity. I canât help but smell an anti-intellectual
current in Graeberâs language thatâs sadly all too common among the left
wherein intelligence or analytic rigor is implicitly conceded as
inherently sociopathic at high values. Where measuring, modeling or
keeping accounts of things inherently implies hostile or untoward
intent. In this inversion of any sane or coherent ethics vigilance
itself becomes suspect. We cannot afford to examine, measure or analyse
our social or interpersonal dynamics too closely because that way lies
sociopathy! Iâm well aware that through centuries of misappropriation
math and reason now strike many as the devilâs sign. But I shudder to
think of what it must be like to live in such a world, that openly
swallows the premise of our enemies that humane relations are only
possible through ignorance and then reacts by embracing ignorance!
Of course I doubt that Graeber is so quite explicit with himselfâand we
are all sometimes subject to cognitive dissonancesâbut Debt contains so
many arguments or implications from association (even just loose
etymology) it risks Glenn Beck territory at points. And, as such, it
poses dangers within the wider left and radical discourse. While the
scattershot explorations can be enjoyably bracing, itâs embarrassing to
see the most powerful and popular anarchist work of this century get
mired in weak arguments. Leaping from historical association to
causation is the same shit pulled by primitivists to critique
refrigerators. Indeed many of Graeberâs fans would be shocked to stop
and actually dwell on lines like this:
not only do existing technologies necessarily mean a society based on
alienation and oppression, which is hard to deny, since existing
technologies have been developed in that context
I mean that is just some pretty extreme faulty reasoning.
For example the more significant dynamic contemporaneous with the advent
of large scale states and widely accepted currency is not quantification
but writing. Let us remember that bureaucratic account keeping and laws
imposing universal prices are direct result of the technology to save
memories to papyrus or stone and convey them. We know that the
introduction of persistence, of nonnegotiable historical accounts, is
always a huge cultural event in any society. Further at the time writing
sharply pushed back against prior diseconomies of scale, enabling the
growth of cancerous social hierarchies in China, India and the
Mediterranean. Until full-fledged alphabets were invented by Semetic
slaves in Egypt writing retained a steep learning curve that was
critical alongside the sword in preventing the technologyâs diffusion to
the periphery. The major event contemporaneous to the downfall of
ĂayönĂŒ? The nearby invention of writing in the form of the VinÄa signs.
Yet aside from John Zerzan and the occasional wingnut no anarchists
reject writing as inherently implying âa society based in alienation and
oppressionâ. We correctly realize that despite its sharp and profound
dangers in certain contexts, writingâs even sharper positive potential
outweighs them. âŠJust as the danger from Einsteinâs insights making
possible nuclear bombs is profound, but the value to better
understanding the world around us is even greater still.
In exactly the same sense markets and dastardly evil of measuring cups
can be extraordinarily useful.
While priorities vary wildly between each person and over time, human
beings have always sought precision in their crafts and interpersonal
communications. Even determining what oneâs priorities or preferences
are in a situation is a calculation, often requiring extensive
consideration and measurement. Freed from the oppressive tensions of
capitalism we would surely prefer to turn such focus on say crafting
baskets or writing poems rather than neurotically calculating and
re-calculating the weekâs remaining expenses or the quickest trip across
town, but even in a world where our everyday stopped being a hustle to
merely survive there would still be necessary calculations. The
abolition of the artificial scarcities that plague our world does not
imply the triumph over scarcity in general. You could no more triumph
over entropy. And many of the passions we develop free of survival
concerns involve a great deal of complexity and coordination of scarce
goods. So long as human beings have dreams and desires in a finite
environment there will be coordination and calculation problems to be
solved. While the extent of the possible is vast there are limits; you
canât shuffle around loaves and fishes under some cups and magically end
up with more loaves and fishes. Sure, much of modern economics is
infected with neoliberalism, but there are nevertheless strong
mathematical constraints to our interactions with the material universe
and each other. Markets provide an array of extraordinarily useful tools
for solving these coordination problems; indeed they denote the only
phase space where solutions can be found for problems past a certain
complexity. Whereas the inherency of subjective knowledge, experience,
and desire in our individual brains and the tiny bandwidth of human
language place strong limits on communist alternatives, decentralized or
not.
While thereâs much to critique on many levels to current norms of
currency (and the surrounding economic, political, and cultural
context), double-incidence of wants is a real phenomenon with important
implications. The value of currency of some form in facilitating the
cosmopolitan mass society we so desire clearly outweighs the dangers.
Indeed setting our sights slightly further, thereâs a very potent point
only somewhat obscured by Graeberâs instincts in his own pages, which is
that the evidence doesnât show prohibiting usury makes for positive
markets, but rather merely the violent enforcement of usury. âUnder
genuine free market conditions loans at interest will become effectively
impossible to collect,â Graeber writes, but while they would surely be
much harder to collect, I highly doubt all instances will disappear
because there are occasionally quite valid reasons to ask for and accept
it. Instead, defanged of the threat of violence one would expect
quantified debts to collapse more directly and organically to the full
human relations and contexts that underpin them⊠including risks and
opportunity costs. My British syndicalist friends obsessed with policing
the borders of mutualism and individualist anarchism might gasp to hear
me suggest it but, in the absence of physical violence or a broadly
coercive context like capitalism, voluntary agreements should be free to
involve interest in recognition of subjective costs. Because when
reputation is the only enforcement mechanism the stateâs mercenary
coinage is not positioned as the ultimate good, instead goodwill is. To
remove violent enforcement from the equation puts an immediate release
valve on any potentially metastasizing power relations and grounds
people directly in their social context. The main benefit and promise of
mass society is having more degrees of freedom with which to respond to
cancerous social forms. If usury or wage labor were to completely
overrun a society and catalyze a shift from centrifugal tendencies on
wealth to accumulative ones weâd surely consider that society a failure.
But interest, like credit, often reflects and models important realities
of uncertainty and subjectivity that weâd be likewise insane to always
ignore.
The problem in all these situations isnât modeling, but cognitive
simplicity and/or the wrong models. Our tools should not simplify or
ignore dynamics but give us more awareness of, options in, and leverage
over them.
It is precisely through not simplifying our desires into a form parsable
by CEOs, politicians, and general assemblies, but instead embracing
their infinite diversity and potency that we can begin to make traction
against the forces that need visibility and human interchangeability to
control us. Yet our desires will always map onto material realities in
one way or anotherâwith ordinal preferencesâand scarcities of elements,
energy, etc. will always exist. Coordinating their allocation with any
remote efficiency is not always hyper important, but for desires and
considerations of any complexity they will be. I hear tell itâs hard to
build a good radio telescope without at least rounding up both string
and coconuts. Hayekian calculation problems are no trivial concern and
as hardbaked into the universe as entropy or cryptography. Social forms
that donât prioritize individual agency in the allocation of goods that
affect them will lose tons of information. Conversely no matter how
complex individualsâ subjective desires, autonomous direct action can
maximally convey the relevant underlying information through revealed
preference. Unless we all retreat to the most tame of land projects and
meditation regimes anyone seeking to build a freer society will need to
adopt market forms to some degree.
At the same time anarchists should also be the first to point out the
dangers in simplifying these motivations. Problems arise when we lose
sight of the roots of our reasons for utilizing markets. One of the most
fascinating considerations in Debt is the way popular frameworks of
ethics have changed over time as religious, ideological or radical
movements got knotted up appealing to the dominant language in their
society.
When people start fetishizing the act of exchange as a foundation for
ethical analysisâinternalizing strategic oughts as full blown
motivations unto themselvesâdanger arises.
Graeber has a complicated and tumultuous affair with the notion of
reciprocity throughout Debtâs pages. On the one hand he wants to point
to debt as the source of positive currents in societies, lending weight
to his abhorrence for quantification by showing how some use a mesh of
debts that are never precisely resolved to build ties of community and
brotherhood. On the other hand he wants to reject that in favor of the
âEveryday Communismâ of community members giving to one another (whether
salt or accurate directions) without a second thought. Where accounting
is never undertaken and human relations are artificially assumed to be
permanent:
the understanding that, unless people consider themselves enemies, if
the need is considered great enough, or the cost considered reasonable
enough, the principle of âfrom each according to their abilities, to
each according to their needsâ will be assumed to apply.
I sympathize strongly with the impulse here, but not the terms of the
solution Graeber presents. In trying to seize the pragmatic high ground
by abandoning foundational conceptual considerations and speaking
instead in terms of groupable existing cultural practices, Graeber
inherently blocks himself from anything more robust or potent than the
most mundane casual kindness.
âFrom each according to their abilities to each according to their
needsâ is nice as a very abstract guiding light but when applied to any
non-trivial particulars it rapidly falls apart. Human needs are simply
unfathomably complex. Aside from some base considerations like food,
water and shelter that could be easily universally assured by merely
toppling the state and capitalism, the vast majority of our needs or
desires are in no sense objective or satisfyingly conveyable. Measuring
exactly whose desire is greater or more of a ânecessityâ is not just an
impossibility but an impulse that trends totalitarian. The closest we
can get in ascertaining this in rough terms is through the decentralized
expression of our priorities via one-on-one discussions and
negotiations. The market in other words. Communism through praxis rather
than the attempted omniscience of committees and general assemblies. But
a communism in which individuals must proactively stand up for
themselves and give voice to the desires and complexities that only they
have access to. A communism in which whenever our knowledge of another
personâs needs and preferences grows hazy we solve the calculation
through a conversation of comparisons with our own. A communism in which
we are constantly looking for opportunities to build trust (through
tests like exchange and loans) outside our immediate circles so that our
conversations can spread wealth faster and dynamics of distrust can be
countered.
(Donât be distracted by the fact that sociopathic wars of all against
all can likewise take place in a decentralized one-on-one fashion of
hostile discussions and negotiations. In a different environment with
different cultural instincts and different, more advanced social
organisms, intentions that slide towards the sociopathic can be
recognized and organized against before such contagion gains the
strength to seriously self-compound.)
In contrast to the communist potential of the market Graeberâs notion of
Everyday Communism in which âno accounts are takenâ is capable of
sliding by in only a tiny region of possible circumstances. I donât know
about you but a communism thatâs only maintainable through our ignorance
of details sounds awfully unsatisfying, and certainly unstable. Granted,
we all instinctively relax a bit at the prospect of any relief from the
constant stressful calculations weâre forced to preform under
capitalism, where precarity disrupts our thoughts with a blaring
hyper-awareness of every last penny, every last contact, every last
risk. But that trauma shouldnât lead to overreaction in blind pursuit of
carthesis. The problem is not that accounts are taken, that
relationships are mapped, or trust flows established more rigorously,
but that we are forced to pay constant attention to a small and crude
subsection of these. That our other desires and preoccupationsâsome
involving extraordinary attention to detailâare suppressed. The problem
is not the availability of tools and knowledge, but the infrastructure
that denies us a choice in them. Keeping accounts of all the details of
our interactions with extraordinary degrees of precision, or merely
being able to, do not equate always paying attention to those details.
As active minds with desires we will always geek out and stress out
about things, and the coordination of goods will always remain one.
Similarly Graeberâs exhalation to delude ourselves into assuming
infinite persistence (in relationships, in societies, etc) is obviously
incredibly dangerous and conducive to oppressive situations. Moralizing
in favor of ignorance is a dumb strategy for communism and certainly not
pragmatic. The dynamics at play in trivial situations like passing the
salt to one another and not giving people false directions, while
positive, are not scalable blueprints for a better world.
I want to be absolutely clear here. By rejecting Graeberâs âeveryday
communismâ I am not advocating the secondary moral framework he
implicitly sets up as competitor or fallback. There are deep issues with
ethics built on notions of exchange. Indeed my greatest critique of
âeveryday communismâ is that it doesnât go far enough in rejecting the
ethic of reciprocity. The internalization of the useful strategy of
exchange or tit-for-tat into a core motivating obligation is a cognitive
error with nasty consequences. In short reciprocity would be recognized
and denounced by millennialist rebels throughout history as a respecter
of persons; it differentiates the world according to who has done what
for us personally rather than who could best benefit. This is fine for
many strategic considerations but awful as a motivational framework.
Empathy and compassion are not strategic, they are prior to strategy.
Theyâre what set the goals. The oughts of ethical motivations arise when
our identity, our selfhood becomes blurred across time and space. To
future versions of oneâs âselfâ whoâd be irritated if today one didnât
take out the trash, but also to other fountainheads of creativity and
inquiry embedded in different contexts, different bodies. Itâs not that
we in some sense owe them, itâs that we in some sense are them. Albeit
subjectively closed from their full context. Such oughts are not
external obstacles or dynamics but direct expressions of our selfhood.
Our communist motivations precede the realm of strategies and market
exchanges, and will on occasion overwrite the heuristics we adopt in
those contexts. As in the case of âintellectual propertyâ where thereâs
no reason to persist in strategies adopted to deal with actual
scarcities.
Graeber is not unaware of the dangers to reciprocity as an idea and he
tries to stretch it as far as the concept can go without breaking, but
what he conjures as an idealic reciprocity in a broad sense is still not
enough:
What is equal on both sides is the knowledge that the other person would
do the same for you, not that they necessarily will.
This falls dramatically short of empathy as a foundation for an ethical
outlook in two respects, 1) it requires knowledge of the other personâs
motivations and 2) it restricts my obligation to merely those who share
the same ethos as me. Now Iâm not saying that those arenât strategically
important considerations. But most of us would fight to save people from
genocide regardless of whether our ethnic or social circles overlapped
enough for us to know a damn thing about their motivations. And weâd
fight to save them if even we knew they wouldnât do the same for us.
Indeed, as anarchists putting our lives on the line to fight oppressions
that the vast majority of the world silently tolerates or endorses, this
is no rarefied academic issue. Itâs one that anarchists have grappled
with for as long as there have been anarchists. Tensions between egoist
theory and altruistic consequentialist practice rivet every single nook
and cranny of our movementâs history. Yet as bad as this supposed
dissonance has been, many of the grand solutions weâve flirted with have
been even worse. If Kropotkinâs attempt to play realist by embracing
mutual aid as âhuman natureâ condemned the anarchist movement to a
century of luddism and the natural fallacy run rampant, Graeber is on
the verge of canonizing the present generationâs mistakes in which the
anarchist decides to play realist by valorizing anti-intellectualism,
social capital, and reciprocity.
There are major problems lurking here. We are not ânational anarchistsâ
content with a retreat to tribes, with smaller states more attentive in
their oppression. Rwanda proved that just as decentralization is always
more efficient than centralization, decentralized fascism can be more
efficient than centralized fascism. Informal power dynamics matter and
must be countered. As do material constraints. A society incapable of
complex economic calculation is a society that will leave Einsteins
stifling in the fields and the blind without restorative implants.
Itâs not enough to merely identify that there are currents of a better
world coursing through our veins. Weâve long known this. What should
preoccupy us is less what has worked in the past, but what else is
possible going forward. Graeber, like all academics, trapped in the land
of liberals and sneering marxist dinosaurs, is loathe to commit or
substantively consider beyond the most shallow of prescriptions: Abolish
the debt. Well of fucking course. Even Chomsky starts to look radical
from that position.
Engaging with what is possibleâand how to work backward from there to
attacks on the existingârequires an analysis deeper than clustered
associations from anecdotes. I would love to see left market anarchists
and radicals more broadly seriously take up the challenges raised in
Debt.
What would currency look like in a freed society? We donât know, but
itâs safe to say it would no more look like the current economy with US
treasury notes replaced by silver coins than businesses in the absence
of the state would look like Walmart.
Thereâs been a paucity to our imaginations here too. And mapping out the
possibilities, much less learning through praxis which array best meet
our situational needs, is sure to be a huge task. Iâve been studying,
writing and having conversations about this since 2003 and so too have
many mathematicians, economists and computer scientists (âcurrencyâ
obviously sitting within a much wider phase space of trust and protocol
dynamics). Thereâs interesting work being published on the arXiv, in
books and monographs by activist economists like Thomas Greco, and amid
the deluge of cryptocurrencies. Indeed the popular explosion of
cryocurrencies immediately following the publication of Debt is perhaps
one of the most interesting examples of convergent historical pressures,
and has seen both truly out there proposals as well as studiously
primordial experiments like Ripple and Etherium.
Amusingly a good many libertarians are still kicking themselves today
for disregarding Bitcoin thanks to Austrian orthodoxy pretty much rooted
in a cobwebbed few paragraph aside by Mises in Human Action. If only
theyâd paid attention to the man considered by far to be the most likely
creator of Bitcoin, Nick Szabo, who wrote extensively on the history and
nature of money as a social relation a decade before Debt. Szabo
launched off Dawkinâs summary that âmoney is a formal token of delayed
reciprocal altruismâ and expanded it into a more rigorous examination,
explicitly laying out many of the motivations for Bitcoin:
Collectibles augmented our large brains and language as solutions to the
Prisonerâs Dilemma that keeps almost all animals from cooperating via
delayed reciprocation with nonkin. Reputational beliefs can suffer from
two major kinds of errors â errors of about which person did what, and
errors in appraising the value or damages caused by that act. Within
clans (the small and immediately local kin group, or extended family,
which formed a subset of a tribe), our large brains could minimize these
errors, so that public reputation and coercive sanctions superceded the
limited motivation provided by the counterpartyâs ability to cooperate
or defect in the future as the main enforcer of delayed reciprocation.
In both homo sapiens neanderthalis and homo sapiens sapiens, with the
same large brain size, it is quite likely that every local clan member
kept track of everybody other local clan memberâs favors. The use of
collectibles for trade within the small local kin group may have been
minimal. Between clans within a tribe both favor tracking and
collectibles were used. Between tribes, collectibles entirely replaced
reputation as the enforcer of reciprocation, although violence still
played a major role in enforcing rights as well as being a high
transaction cost that prevented most kinds of trade.
To be useful as a general-purpose store of wealth and means of wealth
transfer, a collectible had to be embedded in at least one institution
with a closed-loop cycle, so that the cost of discovering and/or
manufacturing the object was amortized over multiple transactions.
Furthermore, a collectible was not just any kind of beautiful decorative
object. It had to have certain functional properties, such as the
security of being wearable on the person, compactness for hiding or
burial, and unforgeable costliness. That costliness must have been
verifiable by the recipient of the transfer â using many of the same
skills that collectors use to appraise collectibles today.
Of course as a vision of an ideal world Bitcoin is problematic in many
respects. The environmental cost of the energy consumption is nowhere
near as high as has been insinuated but is still arguably unnecessary.
The trust model has insufficiently examined weaknesses when it comes to
the proliferation of future protocol updatesâeven just the ratio of core
developers to users inherently introduces weaknesses the government has
been eager to pressure. And the implicit goal of One Big Currency is
just as unreasonable as One Big Union. Any flat global currency will
radically fail to match the topologies of trust, reputation, and other
diverse human realities it floats on top of â lurking instabilities are
inherent. Introducing parallel competing currencies all modeled on the
dream of a universal standard hardly solves the problem. My own
inclination is that exchange facilitating human reputation systems will
trend towards a rhizomatic federative model with every community,
collective or congealing association floating their own âcurrencyâ in a
sense, built to be dynamically recognfigured, and with routing protocols
fluidly negotiating the network topology on the fly for individual
transactions while retaining far more directed information regarding
lines of trust and repute. And indeed Bitcoin has already set off a vast
cornucopia of such developments from things like color coins, side
chains, and meta coins, to communities like the Lakota nation and
Catalonia launching their own alt coins (Catalonia even working on a
scheme to bake in basic universal income). Of course itâll be a while
before this development process or praxis achieves everything we want.
But in the meantime, in the non-prefigurative actually-existing world of
violence distorted markets, weâre having a hard time holding onto even
the precondition of a decentralized internet. Itâs not just an analogy
to note that while the anarchist ideal may be a rich ecology of mesh
networks, weâre anemic enough that net neutrality is better than
DisneyComcast. And in that context Bitcoin and its variations, must be
acknowledged as holding immense practical utility when compared to the
current regime. The CNT was a clusterfuck but it did get some good shit
done.
And there are a number of things Bitcoin gets right. Whatever sloppily
imposed tale of grand historical cycles Graeber cares to conjure, many
of the attributes of specie currency are of great utility to resistance
movements. If we are to make a serious push back through direct action
against global power structures we need the same fungible currencies
that gave (and give) lifeblood to pirate utopias and enable millions to
hustle out survival under the table. At the same time Bitcoin is caught
in a tension with prefiguration by quirk of mathematics which forces
every transaction into a public ledger to its satisfy proof of work
scheme. This trait was seen as a bug rather than a feature by many
Libertarians (and there are a few elaborate schemes in progress to
overcome it), but history arguably shows that public ledgers are the
more natural framework for currency, from necklaces to clay tablets to
marked sticks. The most famous and direct example being the islanders of
Yap who carved giant stone coins hundreds of miles away, rafted them
home and then simply publicly declared changes of ownership without ever
moving them. When a coin was accidentally dropped into the sea on its
way to Yap the islanders shrugged and continued to exchange title to it
since its physical location was ultimately unimportant. Bitcoin has
merely used mathematics to extend the number of parties to such
consensuses while freeing our brains to remember and think about other
things. (Interestingly this ease has also facilitated an explosion of
social gifting which currently constitute the majority of Bitcoin
transactions.)
Of course even when itâs possible there can be problems with simply
scaling up tools and approaches that work well on the tribal level, just
because we can get around Dunbarâs limit on some dynamics doesnât mean
we can for all interrelated dynamics, and to grab onto solutions that
have worked before ignoring changes in context is dangerous in the
extreme. If a technologyâlike a currencyâcan facilitate a liberatory
mass society it should be built around enhancing agency and giving folks
broader and more fluid choices.
That said, while a great number of problems can be solved by automating
the grunt work involved in protocol negotiation, routing, map-learning,
stock predictions, etc., even the most furturist general AI will still
be starkly limited by Hayekian subjectivity. Unless we buy into the
capitalist and state communist vision of limited, controllable desires
we will still have to at some point, at some level engage. Even the most
advanced tool canât intuit our needs, or, for example assume a threat or
trust model for us. We have to declare our ever changing preferences and
contextual considerations, we have to make decisions, we have to
actively judge. And itâs here that the issue of what exactly do we want
to pay attention to arises. Markets can exist only wherever attention is
placed. And some people feel deeply annoyed when huge amounts of
attention is placed in areas by others that they donât want to likewise
pay attention to. What should we have markets in? What should we
calculate with precision? How can we, in wildly varying situations,
mediate between those who for various reasons want to obsess over a
dynamic and those who would rather not give a fuck? These are questions
often cloaked in combative, reactive rhetoric, but are worth bringing to
the fore.
Obviously we shouldnât just retire human inquiry away at some level of
awareness, start some land project and seek no further, but we do
occasionally reach plateaus in human computational capacity with
diminishing returns. In the absence of a higher-bandwidth language or
telepathy, micromanaging our relationships can become counterproductive.
When I was a teen I felt horrified and betrayed to overhear a cluster of
anarchafeminists bitterly complaining about their sensitive partners
checking in about consent on every little action in bed, but the point
is actually valid. Over-resolution in a specific realm when it becomes
normative can be constraining to those with other priorities in
exploration. That said there is of course, ultimately no such thing as
over-resolution in our collective striving for understanding in every
arena. Thereâs no area or level to which we all should flinch from
examinationâregardless of whether we decide we want to live at that
granularity in our everyday lives with boring old non-transhuman homo
sapiens brains.
We have many problems to solve, from the feedback loops in social
capital that drive informal power relations to means for survivors of
secret rapists to find one another and coordinate in an untrustworthy
environment. A wishful longing for ignorance of historical accounts is
not a productive or workable ideal. If thereâs one thing I hope readers
take away from Debt itâs a calling to geek out on particulars and tackle
these dynamics. This isnât unchartered territory, thereâs a lot of
really great work going on and tools being forged by heroes. The next
chapter on debt, in which many of its forms arenât abolished from on
high but dissolved from below, has still yet to be finished.
So what then to say in conclusion?
I think this summary of Graeberâs is supremely illustrative of the
mistakes creeping into his account:
All human interactions are not forms of exchange. Only some are.
Exchange encourages a particular way of conceiving human relations. This
is because exchange implies equality, but it also implies separation.
Itâs precisely when the money changes hands, when the debt is cancelled,
that equality is restored and both parties can walk away and have
nothing further to do with each other.
Yet there are no such thing as unseparated human beings! Every human
relationship is deeply predicated upon separation. Until brain-to-brain
technology matures and radically scales up the bandwidth of our
potential communication even the closest of lovers face strong limits
from the subjectivity inherent to individual existence. For some
relationships and situations Gift of the Magi style catastrophes are a
tolerable bullet to bite, but only ever to a certain degree. And as we
shake off the shackles of capitalism and let our desires stretch such
confusions and logjams will become even less cute.
Further, the notion that âequality is restoredâ wildly ignores what
social currency was about imperfectly declaring: standing and
trustworthiness, realities that donât have to be hierarchical and
assessments thereof that donât have to be collectively managed. When the
neighbor returns precisely one cup of rice and maybe a little more as
agreed on, that doesnât have to cancel the relationship, it can enhance
it by proving trustworthiness. I am freeing you to have agency in your
association with me, so that our friendship might be richer for the
knowledge that we are not bound by material considerations. Only with
such knowledge can we be capable of developing real affinities. A
consensual society should be built off knowing we can reconfigure our
social relations at any moment. That their substance lies not in
ossified roles or identities but in empathy.
In an understandable but dangerous rush to paint a clean picture David
Graeber ignores a host of other possibilities and paints an all-too-cute
historical progression and taxonomy in which all human societies mix
different degrees of hierarchical, communistic, and market oriented
dynamics. But markets, in his tale, are primarily a confused state of
affairs in which any permanence or substance to human relations is
dissolved and everything is quantified. And the unquantified,
unexamined, unmapped ignorance of communism is bliss.
I disagree.
Whatever moralistic language may sometimes cling to them, markets
themselves are not rooted in cultural confusion but in inescapable
material and game theoretic realities. Currency resolves an important
issue in mass societies and while it can have problems they can be
solved with more mathematical nuance not less.
We should be incredibly suspicious of valorizing alternatives like
Maussian gift economies that embrace interpersonal power dynamics rather
than working to negate them. And Graeberâs
communism-as-a-deliberate-state-of-ignorance hardly serves any better.
If we really care about one another, if we really want to build a freer
world from an orientation of empathy and compassion, if weâre really
concerned about the crystalization of hierarchies, we owe it to
ourselves to be maximally vigilant, to seize every tool at our disposal
and remain unpetrified of exploring root dynamics.
It is the interplay of desire and math that ultimately shapes what is
possible, not sweeping historical impressions or awkward taxonomies of
cultural dynamics. Debt: The First 5,000 Years is an exhilarating storm
of anecdotes and with many insightful themes, but it flounders in many
respects when it seeks to draw lessons from history.
The past is no cage for the future.