💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › tarjei-straume-anthropos-anarchos.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:23:40. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: ANTHROPOS ANARCHOS
Author: Tarjei Straume
Language: en
Topics: spirituality, anarcho-anthroposophy
Source: https://www.uncletaz.com/anthranark.html

Tarjei Straume

ANTHROPOS ANARCHOS

What is anarcho-anthroposophy or anthroposophical anarchism? There is a

lot of disagreement going around about who have the right to call

themselves anarchists and who don't. In such discussions the claim has

occasionally been made that dialectical materialism is the only

acceptable belief for anarchists.

This excludes every religious coloring, including Tao anarchism,[1] the

philosophy of Gandhi,[2] and Christos Anarchos.[3] Although all

anarchists reject the Communist dictatorship of the proletariat, there

are a few who cling to an almost mandatory atheism. There is little room

for spiritual freedom in their utopia. This is an important point of

departure when we are going to approach Rudolf Steiner's Anthroposophy

as a branch of anarchist philosophy.

Even though Steiner was a declared enemy of economic liberalism, he

appears to be a libertarian individualist with special sympathies for

rabid egoists like Max Stirner and Benjamin Tucker. Because of his

spiritually oriented world view, he displayed a certain distaste for

Marxism. This was in spite of, or perhaps precisely because, Steiner

himself had his roots in the proletariat, and never became a wealthy

man. It was his conviction that what he had to offer the working class

was a liberation of each individual through self-consciousness, while

the socialists lulled the workers to sleep with their materialistic

propaganda and their dictatorial party platforms.

"Rudolf Steiner was a child of poor people," writes Christoph

Lindenberg. "He never made big deal out of his parents' poverty; he

usually only mentions in passing the humble conditions he gew up in. But

one time, during a discussion in 1919, when a person who knew poverty

only through what he had heard, began to lecture about how low-paid

postal employees lived, Steiner burst out: 'I have learned to understand

the proletarians by living with them myself, by having grown out of the

proletariat, by having learned to starve with proletarians.'"[4]

Rudolf Steiner

Rudolf Steiner was born on February 27 1861 in Kraljevec, a small

bordertown on the island Murr in Hungary (later Yugoslavia, then

Croatia), and grew up in Austria. After the breakup from the

Theosophical Society, he founded the Anthroposophical Society in 1913 in

Dornach, Switzerland, where he died in his study on March 30 1925.

"Anthroposophically oriented spiritual science" is very comprehensive

and constitutes the background for Waldorf schools, the theory about the

Threefold Social Order, biodynamic farming, alternative medicine, and an

obscure New Age religiosity that has influenced a number of poets and

authors. Many anarchists find such a supersensible conception of reality

difficult to digest, especially because Anthroposophy is the most

misunderstood of all "New Age" varieties.

The core of anthroposophical philosophy is thoroughly anarchistic. This

is not so easy to discern, because Rudolf Steiner's basic view can be

very challenging to get to the bottom of. Most anthroposophists choose

what appeals to them and suppress the rest. Most overlooked of all is

the anarchism. This is why we have seen so many authority-loving and

power-hungry bourgeois anthroposophists who have not discovered that

they are sitting on a revolutionary megabomb.

Rudolf Steiner's works comprise over 340 volumes in the German original.

Most of these consist of short hand transcripts from his approximately

6000 lectures. This work can mainly be divided into two groups: First

his written philosophical works from the 1880's and the 1890's, among

these his pioneering "The Philosophy of Freedom" (1894), which he

claimed 30 years later would survive all his other works, and which lays

the foundation for esoteric (spiritual-philosophical) anarchism.

The second group of his works consists of everything he communicated

after the turn of the century, i.e. from 1900 until 1925, and which

makes up over 90 per cent of anthroposophical literature.

Steiner's critique of Marx and Engels and their dialectical materialism

has a central place in anarchist anthroposophy. This dialectical

materialism did not only exert its influence on Communism, but in a

camouflaged manner also on latter-day capitalism (because of its

relationship to social Darwinism). In addition, it has been a strong

factor in socialist-anarchist thinking and is therefore the main reason

for the tension between atheist-collectivist anarchist thinking on the

one hand and freedom-individualistic anarchism on the other.

When evaluating Steiner in the light of the history of anarchism, it is

necessary to put special weight upon his major philosophical work The

Philosophy of Freedom. It is only the second group of Steiner's

communications, i.e. his books and lectures after the turn of the

century, that are often ridiculed or are experienced as offensive

because of their controversial character. This was when he had decided

to speak up openly about the supersensory knowledge he had acquired as a

result of his inborn highly unusual states of consciousness.

Anthroposophical literature originating from the period 1900-1925

requires a spiritual orientation, or cast of mind, where every concept

of faith in the traditional sense is sacrificed in favor of results

yielded by scientific research, while at the same time powers of

cognition with religious characteristics beyond the intellect are

applied. It is very difficult for someone who does not possess this cast

of mind to accept Rudolf Steiner's anthroposophically oriented spiritual

science. Steiner encourages trust in terms of an open and at the same

time critical mind, but he cautions very strongly against regarding his

person as an authority or his communications as authoritative. The

cultivation of Rudolf Steiner as an authority among super-bourgeois and

subservient anthroposophists is, ipso facto, in violation of the

principles of freedom inherent in Anthroposophy.

We are here in touch with the most vulnerable paradox for

anthroposophists with regard to critical objections. The whole thing is

about an enormously rich body of knowledge which is the result of Rudolf

Steiner's occult research. Steiner emphasizes expressly on repeated

occasions that nothing must be accepted on authority alone in our time.

Everything must be scrutinized and verified empirically. How is this

possible, we must ask, when the research itself requires supersensory

organs, powers, and abilities that Rudolf Steiner alone and nobody else

did or does possess?

This objection is so weighty and sensible that most bourgeois

anthroposophists get cold feet when they are confronted with a problem

of this nature. They either explain it all away by denying the paradox

completely, or they renounce any identification with Steiner's

representation, especially in the religious field. Anthroposophy leads

not only to anarchism, but also to esoteric Christianity and to

Buddhism. Because of this, the tragicomical situation arises when in

public debates, one frequently gets clearer and more accurate

descriptions of Anthroposophy from atheist or Christian opponents than

from the anthroposophists themselves, who do everything in their power

to explain away and befog the whole thing.

With the fact in mind that the undersigned considers himself an

anarcho-anthroposophist, an approximate response to the objection

mentioned above may be in order. In the first place, it should be

pointed out that although Steiner did not want to be regarded as an

authority, he did accept that many viewed him as a guide or light

bearer. Immediately following the turn of the century, he published his

observations from the so-called Akasha Chronicle in a magazine of his

own that he called Luzifer-Gnosis, or The Light Bearer's Wisdom. He

pointed out that the prostrate propensity among most people to submit

themselves to authorities of all kinds represents a serious obstacle to

the development of freedom in our time. It is understandable, therefore,

that many anthroposophists don't understand the difference between a

guide and a source of information on the one hand, and an authority on

the other.

One question arising here is to what extent anarchists should permit

themselves to have guides at all. We are living in a complex

entanglement of mutually dependent relationships, and as long as each

individual evaluates freely the credibility and sensibility of every

single source, there is no question of authority. For an anarchist,

therefore, Steiner can be as relevant as Bakunin, Proudhon, Stirner, or

Tolstoy.

As guide, Steiner claimed that anybody could expand the abilities he or

she already possessed. To this end, he published a series of books with

detailed exercises and advice. There are yet many reasons to believe

that Steiner may have overestimated his contemporaries in several

fields.

Steiner thought the claims he presented as occult facts could be

followed up and tested to a certain extent without advanced claivoyance,

or "initiation." Inner experiences cultivated with sharpened powers of

thought, observations of external phenomena that most people overlook,

historical documents, etc. - all this could be used to affirm or

invalidate Steiner's communications. When one developed real occult

abilities later, e.g. by working with the guide's communications, one

could do one's own research as well, also in unknown territories.

The Philosophy of Freedom and the epistemology of anarchism

Epistemology is the science about the origin and boundaries of human

knowledge, and which methods we use to reach it. It is a branch of

research that traditionally belongs to the realm of philosophy.

Steiner's doctoral thesis, which was published in Weimar in 1892 with

the title, Truth and Knowledge: An Introduction to "The Philosophy of

Freedom," presents an epistemological critique of Kant. With German

idealists like Fichte, Schiller, Hegel, Goethe, and to a certain degree

also Nietzsche, editing of Darwin, plus critique of Bacon, Newton,

Copernicus og Galileo as his point of departure, Steiner wished to

establish a solid epistemological foundation for everything he

communicated after the turn of the century, first as Theosophy, later as

Anthroposophy.

In The Philosophy of Freedom, Steiner challenges the dualists and argues

that a realistic epistemology must lead to an unequivocal monism. The

most influential dualist in the German speaking world was Immanuel Kant,

who divided existential reality in two by alleging that a reality

existed which could not be experienced and which would forever have to

remain hidden from human powers of cognition. This type of dualism is

still making deep tracks in our culture and in mainstream philosophical

orientation. With dualism as our point of departure, we speak about "the

unknown," "the beyond," "God," "aliens," etc. Kant called this unknown

"the thing in itself" and postulated that the real essence of natural

phenomena was located in a hidden world that nobody had experienced or

could ever experience.

Steiner alleged that this beyond unknown was the product of sheer

superstition. He argued that the philosophical sciences could take only

one reality into consideration, namely the empirical one. This was what

he called monism. He found the most reliable point of departure for this

monism in Charles Darwin's natural science, which at that time was being

elaborated further by Ernst Haeckel. Furthermore, he had discovered that

Goethe's research in botanics, biology, anatomy, light, and color was

pioneering and demonstrated among other things that Isaac Newton's

theory of color had been a sidetrack. This monism still represents

cultural heresy in philosophy and in natural science alike.

The Philosophy of Freedom aims to demonstrate that monism is an absolute

presupposition for perfect, unencumbered spiritual freedom. If we shall

be capable of liberating ourselves completely from all coercion and

authority, internal and external, physical and metaphysical, we cannot

remain in a dualistic world that hides ghosts we can never approach. We

must call on monism's help to tear down those limitations that the

dominant dualistic culture has enforced upon human cognition like some

kind of occult permanent boundary.

In this way, monism wishes to enable the development of unencumbered

free will as well as the cognition that the potential of human

empiricism is unlimited. The Philosophy of Freedomhas as its goal,

therefore, to define the presuppositions for free action.

In order to develop the "free spirit," Steiner argued that one would

have to liberate onself from inner and outer tyranny alike. In the tenth

chapter, Freedom - Philosophy and Monism, Steiner defines the difference

between "naïve realism" and "metaphysical realism." Naïve realism is

bound by sensory authorities:

"The naïve man, who acknowledges as real only what he can see with his

eyes and grasp with his hands, requires for his moral life, also, a

basis for action that shall be perceptible to the senses. He requires

someone or something to impart the basis for his action to him in a way

that his senses can understand. He is ready to allow this basis for

action to be dictated to him as commandments by any man whom he

considers wiser or more powerful than himself, or whom he acknowledges

for some other reason to be a power over him. In this way there arise,

as moral principles, the authority of family, state, society, church and

God, as previously described. A man who is very narrow minded still puts

his faith in some one person; the more advanced man allows his moral

conduct to be dictated by a majority (state, society). It is always on

perceptible powers that he builds. The man who awakens at last to the

conviction that basically these powers are human beings as weak as

himself, seeks guidance from a higher power, from a Divine Being, whom

he endows, however, with sense perceptible features. He conceives this

Being as communicating to him the conceptual content of his moral life,

again in a perceptible way - whether it be, for example, that God

appears in the burning bush, or that He moves about among men in

manifest human shape, and that their ears can hear Him telling them what

to do and what not to do."[5]

Perhaps it may seem a little odd that Steiner puts so much emphasis on

such things as hands, eyes, ears, etc. in relation to inner images. In

the course of his years, he often spoke about the necessity of

developing "sensefree thinking," i.e. a more flexible kind of mental

activity that is less dependent upon the grey braincells. (It ought to

be taken note here of the fact that Anthroposophy views the brain as a

sense organ, so that thoughts are perceived by the brain just like

sounds are perceived by the ear.) Many of his utterances appear absurd

when they are approached with a thinking that is spellbound by the

physical brain because they aim to give the listener inner pictures that

do not reflect anything sensory, and thereby contribute to the

development of sensefree thinking.

The metaphysical realist does not think any more sensefree than the

naïve realist is doing. He only projects physical concepts to a

metphysical plane:

"The highest stage of development of naïve realism in the sphere of

morality is that where the moral commandment (moral idea) is separated

from every being other than oneself and is thought of, hypothetically,

as being an absolute power in one's own inner life. What man first took

to be the external voice of God, he now takes as an independent power

within him, and speaks of this inner voice in such a way as to identify

it with conscience.

"But in doing this he has already gone beyond the stage of naïve

consciousness into the sphere where the moral laws have become

independently existing standards. There they are no longer carried by

real bearers, but have become metaphysical entities existing in their

own right. They are analogous to the invisible "visible forces" of

metaphysical realism, which does not seek reality through the part of it

that man has in his thinking, but hypothetically adds it on to actual

experience. These extra-human moral standards always occur as

accompanying features of metaphysical realism. For metaphysical realism

is bound to seek the origin of morality in the sphere of extra-human

reality."[6]

Steiner argued that dialectical materialism made freedom impossible

because it enslaved thinking in a mechanical universe. He continues:

"If the hypothetically assumed entity is conceived as in itself

unthinking, acting according to purely mechanical laws, as materialism

would have it, then it must also produce out of itself, by purely

mechanical necessity, the human individual with all his characteristic

features. The consciousness of freedom can then be nothing more than an

illusion. For though I consider myself the author of my action, it is

the matter of which I am composed and the movements going on in it that

are working in me. I believe myself free; but in fact all my actions are

nothing but the result of the material processes which underlie my

physical and mental organization. It is said that we have the feeling of

freedom only because we do not know the motives compelling us."[7]

After that, Steiner confronts spiritualistic dualism. Today, this

variety is better known as religious fundamentalism:

"Whereas the materialistic dualist makes man an automaton whose actions

are only the result of a purely mechanical system, the spiritualistic

dualist (that is, one who sees the Absolute, the Being-in-itself, as

something spiritual in which man has no share in his conscious

experience) makes him a slave to the will of the Absolute. As in

materialism, so also in one-sided spiritualism, in fact in any kind of

metaphysical realism inferring but not experiencing something

extra-human as the true reality, freedom is out of the question.

"Metaphysical as well as naïve realism, consistently followed out, must

deny freedom for one and the same reason: they both see man as doing no

more than putting into effect, or carrying out, principles forced upon

him by necessity. Naive realism destroys freedom by subjecting man to

the authority of a perceptible being or of one conceived on the analogy

of a perceptible being, or eventually to the authority of the abstract

inner voice which it interprets as 'conscience'; the metaphysician, who

merely infers the extra-human reality, cannot acknowledge freedom

because he sees man as being determined, mechanically or morally, by a

'Being-in-itself'."[8]

The core in Rudolf Steiner's monism is the sovereign independence of the

single individual in thinking as well as in doing. The human being

itself and nothing else is the determining factor with regard to moral

behavior:

"The moral laws which the metaphysician who works by mere inference must

regard as issuing from a higher power, are, for the adherent of monism,

thoughts of men; for him the moral world order is neither the imprint of

a purely mechanical natural order, nor that of an extra-human world

order, but through and through the free creation of men. It is not the

will of some being outside him in the world that man has to carry out,

but his own; he puts into effect his own resolves and intentions, not

those of another being. Monism does not see, behind man's actions, the

purposes of a supreme directorate, foreign to him and determining him

according to its will, but rather sees that men, in so far as they

realize their intuitive ideas, pursue only their own human ends.

Moreover, each individual pursues his own particular ends. For the world

of ideas comes to expression, not in a community of men, but only in

human individuals. What appears as the common goal of a whole group of

people is only the result of the separate acts of will of its individual

members, and in fact, usually of a few outstanding ones who, as their

authorities, are followed by the others. Each one of us has it in him to

be a free spirit, just as every rose bud has in it a rose."[9]

Charles Darwin's theory of evolution holds a central position in Rudolf

Steiner's philosophy. For him, the moral development of the soul was the

most important aspect of evolution, and for this reson, he was confident

that human beings would develop their free spirits through the

experiences of life.

Steiner writes on:

"Monism knows that Nature does not send man forth from her arms ready

made as a free spirit, but that she leads him up to a certain stage from

which he continues to develop still as an unfree being until he comes to

the point where he finds his own self.

"Monism is quite clear that a being acting under physical or moral

compulsion cannot be a truly moral being. It regards the phases of

automatic behavior (following natural urges and instincts) and of

obedient behavior (following moral standards) as necessary preparatory

stages of morality, but it also sees that both these transitory stages

can be overcome by the free spirit. Monism frees the truly moral world

conception both from the mundane fetters of naïve moral maxims and from

the transcendental moral maxims of the speculative metaphysician. Monism

can no more eliminate the former from the world than it can eliminate

percepts; it rejects the latter because it seeks all the principles for

the elucidation of the world phenomena within that world, and none

outside it."[10]

Steiner's anarchist milieu. Tucker and Mackay.

Between 1890 and 1897 Steiner lived in Weimar, and at this time he

became interested in Max Stirner's radical individualistic-anarchist

writings. He had written a book about Nietzsche, but ended up preferring

Stirner's crystal clear thoughts and courage for freedom.

During the fall of 1898, when living in Berlin, Steiner became

acquainted with the Scottish-German poet and Stirner-biographer John

Henry Mackay and his friend Benjamin Ricketson Tucker. A very good

friendship developed among Steiner, Mackay, and Tucker.

Magazin für Literatur was banned in Russia because the editor Rudolf

Steiner was a friend of the anarchist John Henry Mackay. The situation

did not exactly improve when Steiner wrote in his column that he

regarded himself as an individualistic anarchist:

"Until now, I have myself always avoided using the words

'individualistic' or 'theoretical anarchism' to describe my world view.

Because I care very little for such labels. But if I, to the extent it

is possible to determine such things, should say if the word

'individualistic anarchist' can be applied to me, I would have to answer

with an unequivocal 'yes'."[11]

Mackay's theoretical anarchism had many features in common with The

Philosophy of Freedom. Steiner believed, however, that he had shown in

his book that thinking was a spiritual activity and that the human

spirit could create free actions only through a developed thinking. It

is probable that Mackay could not understand this concept of Steiner -

there was in fact nobody who understood it at that time - but he seems

to have been closer to Steiner in other areas.

Mackay had political ambitions with his theories, and he wanted

Steiner's support and cooperation. It was a time when Steiner presented

his ethical individualism as a political ideal, and it looks as if he

felt tempted to use his own philosophy as a platform for Mackay's

political dreams. His description of this episode in his autobiography

30 years later makes it clear that he experienced the inclination as a

temptation or spiritual trial:

"Through my experience with J.H. Mackay and Stirner, my destiny caused

me once more to enter a world of thought where I had to go through a

spiritual test. Ethical individualism, as I had elaborated it, is the

reality of moral life experienced purely within the human soul. Nothing

was further from my intention in elaborating this conception than to

make it the basis for a purely political view. But at this time, about

1898, my soul with its conception of ethical individualism, was to be

dragged into a kind of abyss. From being a purely individual experience

within the human soul, it was to become something theoretical and

external. The esoteric was to be diverted into the exoteric."[12] From

then onward, he decided to tread his own paths.

Bourgeois Steiner-biographers describe this period as a little sidestep,

as a passing flirt with anarchism, and they interpret the last quote as

a goodbye between Steiner and anarchism. This is where the

anarcho-anthroposophists protest. Because it is just as correct to

present Anthroposophy as the next stage in the evolution of anarchism

and to claim that Steiner is the one who makes anarchism a real

possibility with The Philosophy of Freedom. The

anarcho-anthroposophists' argument is, therefore, that the genuine

anarchism is to be found precisely in Anthroposophy, which is and

remains a heretical counter-culture and a rebellious dropout-society,

regardless of how various members of the fine-cultural super-bourgeoisie

wish to decorate the situation.

When one takes the anthroposophical theism into consideration, i.e. the

entire doctrine about the supersensory hierarchies, the Christology,

etc. that dominates the second part of Rudolf Steiner's comprehensive

life work, it may seem puzzling that he embraced Darwinism, which in

many ways has become the basic philosophy of modern atheism. When the

spiritual worlds, with all their gods, demons, departed souls, etc., lay

wide open for Rudolf Steiner from his earliest childhood, we must allow

ourselves to ask: Is it possible at all for a person like that to

appreciate atheism, to understand it?

Human freedom, the inviolable sovereignty of the individual - this was

Steiner's basic philosophical point of departure. It was precisely on

the premises of freedom that he praised Nietzsche, Stirner, and Tucker.

Steiner claimed, paradoxically enough for many people, that traditional

religious ideas in terms of theology and the like, belong to a bygone

age and must yield to self-dependent thinking, totally independent of

external or internal authority.

The paradox here is Steiner's considerable contribution to Christian

theology, which was, however, a result of special requests. Even his

theism is thoroughly anarchistic. The innumerable gods are man's

creators, but they have now withdrawn their authority so that we shall

become mature and self-dependent enough to make it on our own. The gods

are in other words anarchists. The free spirit in man, the anarchist

soul, is the goal and purpose of creation.

Steiner's theism may seem self-contradictory in relation to monism,

which takes only the empirical world into consideration. This was no

problem for the initiated occultist, considering the fact that all his

statements were based upon supersensory research. Traditional religion,

on the other hand, is dualistic because phenomena beyond man's empirical

potential become objects of blind faith.

Collision with Marx

Rudolf Steiner could never accept Marxism, which spread like fire in a

haystack at the turn of the century. Jens Bjørneboe did call himself an

anarchist, Marxist, and anthroposophist and is supposed to have claimed

that no contradiction existed between Steiner and Marx, but in that

case, he was thoroughly mistaken. Steiner criticized Karl Marx on many

points on different occasions, especially with regard to his

dialectical-materialistic interpretation of history.

When Steiner was working primarily with the idealism of freedom and

anarchism together with Tucker and Mackay, he wrote an article where he

critically confronted the problem of power: "Of all forms of power, what

is being striven for by social democracy, is the worst."[13] By "social

democracy" was meant the Communist ideology at that time.

Six months later, Steiner received a request from the administration of

Arbeiterbildungsschule in Berlin (founded by the Marxist Wilhelm

Liebknecht) to take over the history classes. He threw himself into the

task with great enthusiasm, in spite of the fact that the school could

only afford to pay him a fee that was so extremely modest that they

doubted he could accept the request.

In his autobiography, Steiner tells as follows: "I made it clear to the

directors that if I accepted the task I would present history according

to my own views of mankind's evolution and not according to the Marxist

interpretation as was now customary in Socialist circles. They still

wished me to give the courses."

"These people knew physical work and the results it produces. But they

had no idea of the spiritual powers that guide mankind forward through

history. That was why they so readily accepted Marxism and its

'materialistic interpretation of history.' Marxism maintains that the

only forces at work in history are material and economic, that is,

forces produced through physical work. Any 'spiritual, cultural factors'

are considered to be a byproduct arising out of the material-economic

sphere, a mere ideology.

"Added to this was the fact that for a long time the workers had felt a

growing eagerness for education. But the only means available for

satisfying this need was the popular materialistic literature on

science. It was the only literature slanted to the workers' outlook and

reasoning. Anything else was written in a style the workers could not

possibly understand. Thus the unspeakably tragic situation arose that

while the growing proletariat had an intense craving for knowledge, this

could be satisfied only through the grossest form of materialism."[14]

History was a "special child of sorrow" to Arbeiterbildungsschule. The

students became rapidly bored with the way the subject was taught, and

most of them ceased to attend - whereupon the lecturers usually gave up.

Steiner, however, made success with the students. Later on he went on to

lecture on German literature, on Indian, Persian and Arabic culture, on

the history of philosophy, chemistry, and the history of industrialism.

He also offered instruction in public speaking, and corrected all papers

submitted to him with such care that many of the students really

accomplished things which previously could never have been expected of

them.[15]

In his autobiography, Steiner explains the phenomenon in this way:

"It must be remembered that there are partial truths in the

materialistic ideas on economy which are absorbed by the workers through

Marxism as 'material history.' And these partial truths are just waht

can easily be understood by the workers. Had I simply ignored them and

taught history from an idealistic point of view, the workers would have

sensed that what I said was not in agreement with the partial truths

they knew.

"So I started from a fact that was understandable to my listeners. I

explained why it is nonsense to speak of economic forces dominating

history prior to the sixteenth century, as Karl Marx does. I also showed

that economic life did not take on a form that can be understood in a

Marxistic sense until the sixteenth century, and that this process

reached its climax in the nineteenth century.

"This made it possible for me to speak quite factually about the

spiritual ideals at work in the preceding epochs of history, and I could

show that in more recent times these impulses have weakened, in contrast

to the material-economic ones.

"Thus the workers gradually arrived at concrete ideas about the

spiritual impulses in history, religion, art and morality, and ceased to

regard them as mere ideology. It would have been useless to enter into a

controversy about materialism; I had to let idealism arise out of

materialism."[16]

After five years, the whole thing came to a close when the Party

leadership put an end to Steiner's tuition. He encountered strongest

opposition each time he spoke about freedom. "To speak of freedom seemed

extremely dangerous," he said thirteen years later. The socialist

leaders planted four of their members in a meeting with hundreds of

students where Steiner defended spiritual values, and these made sure

that he was driven out by making it impossible for him to continue. When

Steiner said, "If people wish socialism to play a part in future

evolution, then liberty of teaching and liberty of thought must be

permitted," one of the stooges sent by the party leadership declared:

"In our party and its schools there can be no question of freedom, but

only of reasonable constraint."

To this remark, Steiner added the following comment: "One must not

imagine that the modern proletariat is not thirsting for spiritual

nourishment! It has an insatiable craving for it. But the nourishment

which it is offered is, in part, that in which it firmly believes,

namely positivism, scientific materialism, or in part an indigestible

pabulum that offers stones instead of bread!"[17]

One of these students, Emil Unger-Winkelried, remembered Steiner as

teacher 30 years later: "For us students, especially us working class

students, he was an sacrifice-willing friend who taught at the workers'

school two evenings a week through approximately five years. A so

many-faceted gifted man like Steiner most certainly did not stay with

this tiresome teaching because of the lousy fee, but because it gave him

joy, and the students adored him."[18]

Bourgeois Anthroposophy

Bourgeois philosophy dominates anthroposophical culture to a remarkable

degree. This is an incredibly paradoxical phenomenon, because as we have

seen, The Philosophy of Freedomis nothing short of pure anarchism. In

this connection, something crucial about Rudolf Steiner should be

mentioned, namely that he never disavowed anything he had expressed

earlier. When he wrote in his magazine in 1898 that he was n

individualistic anarchist, it means that this is precisely what he was -

through his whole life!

In 1897, he met with his friends in the restaurant Zur Alten

Künstnerklause in Berlin, where he frequently ended up sitting far into

the morning hours. Max Halbe recalls "Steiner's external image, his

coalblack hair, his flashing black eyes, the hollow-cheeked face, the

skinny buttoned-up shape, kind of black in black altogether in the

strange mixture of adept and daemon."[19]

This description alone makes of Steiner a striking representative for

the black flag of anarchism. F. W. Zeylmans van Emmichoven's portryal of

his meeting with Steiner in 1920, when the man was almost sixty years

old, is almost neckbreaking:

"The eyes recede deeply under the shadow of the heavy brows. One might

say that these eyes are dark brown, but that would tell very little of

their true nature. How can we describe them? Sometimes they appear

unfathomable. One looks into them as into an abyss, standing dazzled at

the brink. At other times it is a depth like a dark night, when no stars

are visible, yet their presence is felt."[20]

Rudolf Steiner was himself never in the military, and when his

architectural masterpiece Das Goethanum was arsoned on New Year's Eve

1922 (probably by the hostile opponents of the movement) and burned to

the ground, he insisted that the misdeed should not be reported or

investigated. He spoke on several occasions about how spiritually free

people of the future will learn to refrain from reacting to evil or

infringements. He did not wish, however, to combine his ethical

individualism with a socio-political or moral set of rules.

The Ordinary Rudolf Steiner

Serious opposition against Rudolf Steiner and his work occurred early,

but the antagonism increased considerably after the first world war,

when Steiner spoke about social Threefolding. The strongest and best

organized opposition came from nationalist quarters, especially in

England and Germany.

Rudolf Steiner made himself guilty of a kind of cultural heresy that has

never been forgiven him, neither by his own time nor by posterity.

Principally speaking, this heresy is no different from e.g. Galileo

Galilei's efforts to demonstrate his vision of the planetary orbits

around the sun. Steiner wished that spiritual science, or Anthroposophy,

should achieve the status of an acknowledged science on par with

chemistry, botany, geology, etc. In his own time, he was met with direct

attacks, while posterity has stonewalled him with silence. He is not

only conspicuous by his absence in most philosophical, scientific, and

religious reference works, but also in most New Age bibliographies.

There is only one aspect of Steiner that has proven to be unassailable,

and that is his personal character. The collection of letters and other

documentation convey a portrait of an imensely good and warm human being

who in an unselfish manner made limitless demands upon himself. It

probably appears incomprehensible for many people that a man who argued

that a free spirit had to liberate itself even from the tyranny of

conscience could be a thoroughly good and selfless person. A major

argument against anarchism is that it will entail unencumbered evil and

egoism. Throughout his years, Steiner placed a lot of emphasis on laying

the foundation for the development of "moral impulses" and "moral

imagination." By this he meant that the really free spirit would gain

increasingly greater inner freedom by using the imagination for loving

and self-sacrificing actions. He believed in the best in humanity

because he had discovered this within himself.

This is where we find anarchism in its highest form.

Tarjei Straume

[1] Zen & taoisme, frihetlige filosofier fra øst, Gateavisa no. 146.

[2] Mahatma Gandhi - den myke revolusjonære, Gateavisa no. 149.

[3] i.e.. Christian anarchism (Christos Anarchos) Gateavisa no. 151.

[4] Die soziale Frage, GA #328, s. 167, Rudolf Steiner mit

Selbstzeugnissen und Bilddokumenten dargestellt von Christoph

Lindenberg.

[5] Die Philosophie der Freiheit 1894, GA #4: kap. 10:

Freiheitsphilosophie und Monismus.

[6] Ibid.

[7] Ibid.

[8] Ibid.

[9] Ibid.

[10] Ibid.

[11] Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Kultur- und Zeitgeschichte 1887-1901, GA

31, p. 261.

[12] Mein Lebensgang, GA #28, ch. 28.

[13] Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Kultur- und Zeitgeschichte 1887-1901, GA 31

[14] Mein Lebensgang, GA #28, ch. 28.

[15] Stewart Easton: Rudolf Steiner, Herald of a New Epoch, p. 101.

[16] Mein Lebensgang, GA #28, ch. 28.

[17] Geschichtliche Symtomatologie, 6. lecture, GA #185.

[18] Emil Unger-Winkelried, 1934.

[19] Max Halbe: Jahrhundertwende, Danzig 1942, p. 183.

[20] Journal for Anthroposophy #44, An Encounter with Rudolf Steiner, p.

24. Zeylman's book was published in Holland in 1932.