đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș scott-nicholas-nappalos-emergence-and-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:06:44. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Emergence and Anarchism
Author: Scott Nicholas Nappalos
Date: 2019
Language: en
Topics: philosophy, political philosophy, Political Theory
Source: https://libcom.org/library/emergence-anarchism-philosophy-power-action-liberation
Notes: Cover by: Natykos. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ or send a letter to Creative Commons, PO Box 1866, Mountain View, CA 94042, USA.

Scott Nicholas Nappalos

Emergence and Anarchism

Epigraph

“Happiness does not mean the attainment of a certain level of personal

or collective existence. It is rather the consciousness of marching

toward a welldefined goal to which one aspires and that one creates in

part through one’s own will. To develop the continents, the seas, and

rearrange and regulate the environment in order to promote each

individual plant, animal, and human life; to become fully conscious of

our human solidarity, forming one body with the planet itself; and to

take a sweeping view of our origins, our present, our immediate goal,

and our distant ideal—this is what progress means.” –ElisĂ©e Reclus,

1905[1]

Foreword

Mark Bray

Science and socialism. For most of us this pairing brings to mind the

“scientific socialism” of Marx and Engels that undergirded the ascension

of “historical materialism” to the forefront of socialist thought into

the twentieth century. Certainly “historical materialism” grew out of

the burgeoning social sciences, but the school of 19^(th) and early

20^(th) century socialist thought that most privileged the natural

sciences may have been anarchism.

Many anarchists of the era considered their doctrine to be the social

embodiment of the ‘truths’ of the natural world revealed through

scientific inquiry. ‘Nature’ was endowed with a redemptive transcendence

manifested through Darwinian and (especially) Spencerian understandings

of evolution. In that vein, the turn of the century Catalan anarchist

Joan Montseny, aka Federico Urales—father of Federica Montseny, argued

that “in the world there exists a law that is perfectly harmonious and

perfectly just: the law of evolution.”[2] Likewise, the Russian

anarchist geographer and scientist Pyotr Kropotkin grounded his

exposition of mutual aid, one of the most lasting and influential

anarchist concepts, in his studies not only of history but of the

importance of cooperation in the natural world. He even went so far as

to argue that anarchism ought to be considered one of the “departments”

of the natural sciences.[3] Francisco Ferrer’s early 20^(th) century

Modern School, which became the model of anarchist education over the

following decades, was allegedly “based solely upon the Natural

Sciences” which Ferrer considered to be the font of a unitary truth

applicable to all of existence including human relations.[4] The

prominent Spanish anarchist FermĂ­n Salvochea was so optimistic about the

potential of the revolution to unshackle scientific inquiry from

capitalist fetters that he speculated in 1888 that post-revolutionary

medicine could even discover the key to immortality.[5] For some late

19^(th) century anarchists, science was “our God.”[6]

As with just about every aspect of anarchism, there were those who

dissented. Nietzschean anarchists attacked the supremacy of rationalism

and science while the primitivists of the Parisian L’État naturel and

the prominent Spanish anarchist Ricardo Mella were some of the most

critical of positivism.[7] It should also be noted that anarchists were

no less enthusiastic about the emergence of social sciences like

sociology. Nevertheless, the majority of late 19^(th) and early 20^(th)

century anarchists adopted the positivist, rationalist, and modernist

optimism of their era.

If the confidence that these anarchists expressed in the ability of the

natural sciences to solve the ‘social question’ feels distant and

removed from present-day considerations of societal change, that’s

because it is. The horrors of the world wars and the Holocaust dashed

the 19^(th) century Western expectation of a clean upward ascent for

humanity. As the 20^(th) century advanced, movements for decolonization,

feminism, queer liberation, black liberation, and others revealed the

hypocrisy at the heart of the fundamentally imperial, patriarchal,

heteronormative, and white supremacist concept of Western ‘progress.’

While it would be unfair to lump turn of the century anarchists in with

imperialists, they were not entirely immune to the oppressive modes of

thought of their era. Likewise, post-structuralist critiques of

conceptions of truth, justice, and objectivity itself pushed many

radicals to examine discourses of power, analyze fragmented

subjectivities, and dissect socially reproduced layers of domination

rather than turn to the natural sciences as sources of liberation.

Inherent in this post-modern turn has been a widespread wariness of

master narratives and grand theoretical formulations across much of the

political spectrum after Fukuyama’s “end of history.”

The audacity of Scott Nicholas Nappalos’ Emergence and Anarchism lies in

its ability to step back from the fray of intellectual trends and taboos

to offer a clear and sober analysis of how we can start to answer some

of the most basic questions about social transformation while avoiding

the limitations and pitfalls of both modernist and postmodernist

thought. Fundamentally, Nappalos reaffirms the importance of theory,

philosophy, and metapolitics against antiintellectual and ‘pragmatist’

tendencies prevalent in some “horizontalist” movements that reduce

liberation to a technics of practices and tactics. In so doing, he

refuses to allow the positivist baggage of past attempts to utilize

science for socialist ends to prevent us from gleaning useful models

from the natural world to help solve social problems today.

Most profoundly, perhaps, his use of the scientific concept of emergence

to describe multi-causal events and developments whose outcomes are

“more than the sum of their parts,” so to speak, presents opportunities

to build bridges between post-structuralism and more recent perspectives

on social transformation and the natural sciences in a somewhat similar

vein to Deleuze and Guattari’s use of the botanical concept of the

rhizome. The plurality and polyvalence of emergence open up alternative

routes to put Foucauldian notions of power or broad conceptions of

intersectionality, for example, into conversation with scientific

insights in the pursuit of liberation.

Emergence and Anarchism adeptly explores the tensions and synergies

between individuals and collectivities at the heart of anarchism’s

attempt to synthesize personal and collective agency. By delving into

the inner workings of agency, it challenges one-dimensional distinctions

between what have been referred to as insurrectionary and mass

anarchism.

Recognizing the enormity of the project of re-orienting some of the

philosophical foundations of revolutionary thought, Nappalos

strategically scales back his main goal by entreating the reader to

recognize the necessity of theories for action and the inseparability of

method and philosophy. Emergence and Anarchism aspires to be a

foundational building block for future theorizing and conceptualizing.

It accomplishes this goal. Agree or disagree with its premises and

conclusions, it confronts us with a broad array of fundamental questions

at the very heart of social transformation that cannot be ignored. More

than offering us answers to such questions, Nappalos demands that we all

take it upon ourselves to think through how change occurs, for

“philosophy is the domain of all people irrespective of their

intelligence, gender, class, race, or position.” As a health care

worker, Nappalos directly challenges “the alienation of this activity”

from the majority of humanity through his words.

The true value of this work will only become clear in the future to the

degree that Nappalos’ appeals for re-conceptualizing theory,

metapolitics, and agency inspire others to pursue and build upon his

train of thought. Many questions remain unanswered about how to build a

new world free from hunger, war, and domination. Emergence and Anarchism

reminds us that to create such a world we must not only examine our

political positions but also their metapolitical foundations.

Acknowledgements

Throughout my attempts at writing I’ve been lucky enough to have people

willing to set aside some of their own time to help take rough ideas and

turn them into something valuable enough for others to read. A book is

always a product of cooperation and the hand of many individuals, even

if one person’s name ends up on the spine. I want to thank Nate

Hawthorne, Adam Weaver, Monica Kostas, Adam Kunin, Don Hamerquist,

Kingsley Clarke, and Luz Sierra for our years of collaboration and their

dedication to pour through my texts and make them better. Noel Ignatiev,

Mark Bray, Don Hammerquist, and Michael Staudenmaier provided me with

helpful edits and kind words for the book, and are excellent comrades

who have stimulated and inspired me over the years we’ve known each

other. Kevin Gonzalez and Marcos Restrepo gave me early comments on

drafts on this book that were important in its development.

Thanks goes to Mark T. for introducing me to the ideas of complex system

and emergence, who along with Sarah T. spent countless hours listening

and arguing with me years ago until the arguments of this text took a

more solid form. Scott G. and Dustin Shannon provided copy-editing

services that were sorely needed. I’m grateful for my mother, whose own

rebelliousness led her to the civil rights and anti-war movements, and

inspired me to question the world I grew up in. There are many others

who offered advice, open minds, and their time to discuss these issues

without which this work would not have been possible including the

generations who worked thanklessly for the cause of human freedom and

anarchism. Without their sacrifices, we would be lacking a voice and a

path for our actions.

Introduction

It’s a jarring experience to be confronted with the reality of the great

and overwhelming wrongs that exist today. Our history is filled with

avoidable evils like the genocide of the indigenous peoples of the

Americas, the centuries of barbarity against African peoples, global

environmental degradation, and the misery of people torn from their land

to become propertyless workers whose generations were murdered, abused,

raped, and wasted by successive rulers. The initial shock of discovering

these crimes sticks with you, and today the horrors constantly fill our

senses through an unending barrage of information that keeps those

experiences close. For those who do not withdraw or shut down in

despair, an old question lingers: What can we do about it all?

With all the years of resistance across the planet, it is surprising how

few answers there are to some very basic problems. If the problems of

the world are not permanent, inherent, and natural to humanity, but are

in fact contingent, changeable, and driven by specific causes, then

there are specific things that can be done to correct injustice. Yet the

number of people both aware of these issues and willing to commit

themselves to a process of social change is generally small. That

minority of people must find ways to act against the weight of the

dominating system to create a better world. In the process people who

are not yet active have to somehow shift from otherwise going about

their lives to become thinking and acting agents of social change and

join the effort to liberate humanity. The goal is a better possible

world brought about from a society with the forces of domination in

control.

Perhaps surprisingly, the traditions that tried to dismantle domination

and exploitation have provided few answers for basic elements of radical

social change. It is a frequent and frustrating experience to discover

the lack of responses to fundamental questions, such as: How is

revolution possible? How can someone become radicalized? What means

allows a revolutionary minority to because a majority? How is the rule

of all people possible?

Paradoxes of Struggle

Years ago, I was involved in the union at my job where we organized a

strike in a social service facility. In the lead-up to the strike there

was a series of fairly brutal workplace injuries that happened largely

because of unsafe staffing with a patient population suffering from

severe mental health issues. Management claimed they had no money to pay

for more staff, while at the same time they were giving out raises to

administrators of over 25% at a nonprofit serving children who were

largely victims of abuse. The staff, battered and ignored, overall were

withdrawn. A majority of the workers didn’t even bother turning up to

the strike vote. The organizing committee, which I was a member of, was

pretty worried, but things had come to a head and we were resolved to

move forward and stop work. I expected a real fight to build support and

for many to cross the picket line.

The day of the strike the vast majority of all the workers walked out

while half the organizing committee of longtime union activists crossed

the picket line and became entrenched scabs for the life of the strike.

Once on the picket line, workers who had previously been cold, shut

down, and abused were literally crying with joy and outpacing the union

bureaucracy’s plans by attacking the vehicles of the bosses driving into

the job site. Virtual strangers began not only fighting for themselves,

but also questioning the class divisions at work, the role of the

government in their work and lives, and even the system itself.

Conversations on the picket line went much further than the union wanted

and that any of the few radicals involved had imagined.

That transformation stuck with me. The opening that came with taking

action altered the way I thought about social change and ultimately

shifted the course of my life. It was puzzling. How did it happen? How

does a fighting force come together to stay planted on sidewalks for

three months in the winter without much money or support from the

outside world? Why did the organizers so quickly betray the strike,

while those who ignored the union became its staunchest supporters?

After the strike people largely went their own ways and returned to

their daily lives, though a minority carried their experiences into new

activities and activism. Those events and tensions were far from rare.

Similar dynamics play out in all conflicts where the agency of people

struggling is shifted in ways that don’t neatly line up with how they or

their leaders think about it.

Throughout the history of workers’ movements new struggles emerged and

forms innovated that went beyond the norms of their days and generally

in opposition to the unions and political parties that drew their

strength from the support of the working class. During World War II US

workers at the same time voted for unprecedented (at the time) pledges

for labor peace with no-strike agreements, and then unleashed one of the

largest and most militant strike waves in our history. They did so

against the leadership of the unions and the Democratic Party drumming

up nationalist support for the “good war”, and even against the

Communist Party who sought to rally support to save Soviet Russia under

attack.[8]

Workers similarly shook things up for the Unidad Popular (UP), or

Popular Unity, government in Allende’s Chile. The UP had sought to

nationalize industries slowly and strategically and coordinate workers’

activity via structures of the State as part of populist reforms. The

workers interpreted the victory of the left-wing parties differently,

seeing it as a green light to take on directly the deepest problems

affecting them. Land seizures, factory occupations, and selfdefense

structures against police, employers, and the right sprung up that were

organized by the workers in opposition to the directions of the UP

functionaries. While the vision of socialist policy makers was limited

to social welfare and State ownership, the workers began to take matters

into their own hands by taking over their workplaces and neighborhoods

to be used to their own ends.[9] These initiatives outside the

officialdom would provide the only serious resistance to the horrific

coup and tragedy that would come as the UP systematically disarmed

itself against an open and immanent threat from the military and radical

right which ultimately led to indiscriminate killing, torture, and

immiseration for decades thereafter.

The dominant script of history is colored by the habit of viewing things

through the lens of those in charge; a perspective that systematically

misses exactly the dynamic that bursts open on picket lines, barricades,

and protests. These days there’s a fair deal of debate around the

Spanish Civil War (largely because of the growing influence of anarchist

ideas broadly), and the various positions and moves by heads of the

different factions. Augustin GuillamĂłn, in his detailed study of the

neighborhood defense committees of the Spanish anarchist union the

ConfederaciĂłn Nacional del Trabajo (CNT), or National Confederation of

Labor, reminds us how the insurrection and following war almost was not

a thing at all. The Republican government, socialists, communists, and

trade union leaders were nearly ready to abdicate after Franco’s coup

emerged. The militants of the anarchist CNT on the other hand had

prepared in the years leading up to the events. Worker militants

organized by their districts studied their areas and sought to find what

would be necessary to disarm the military and begin creating anarchist

society should a revolution occur. Decades of urban class warfare (which

saw workers and union activists frequently assassinated, tortured, and

abused by paramilitary forces of the State and employers) and aborted

insurrections (dubbed “revolutionary gymnastics” by the CNT) provided

collective memory and skills for the workers who lived through an

institutionalized culture of resistance to violent repression and

poverty. At a critical moment at the outset of the coup, a generalized

workingclass force rallied behind the defense committees, which

represented one of the only real bodies organized to oppose the fascist

revolt. Only thereafter did the civil war become possible and did the

vying factions step back into the fray saved by the popular response

that moved into the opening that had developed.[10]

Agency and Emergence

There are two central problems embedded within these examples: the

problem of agency and the problem of emergence. Emergence is a concept

that originally came from philosophy dating at least to the 19^(th)

century, but has been taken up by various sciences in the past fifty

years to look at complex systems like living organisms, ecosystems,

societies, and weather patterns. In these systems new things emerge out

of the interaction of vast numbers of components that together produce

something novel that is greater than the sum of its parts. Ants produce

emergent hive behavior with intelligence that doesn’t exist in any

individual colony member; neurons create conscious thought that does not

share properties of the chemical reactions inside our cells; and cities

create systematic patterns of growth and decay created by people merely

going about their days. The second section of this text takes on

emergence and its related issues.

People by their nature are agents. We take action and think about what

to do or what not to do. Seeking social change is one kind of agency.

One aspect of the struggle for a better world is choosing what we do as

individuals and coordinating with others. The change itself happens on

another level of organization. Like all social things, it arises out of

the actions of millions and a larger context. What can be a surprise is

how these two elements often do not match up. Based on everything we

knew as organizers, we did not expect for our co-organizers to become

scabs and the silent majority to become militants. Since then, there’s

been a number of other surprises like the Arab Spring, Madison, Occupy,

Brazil’s anti-World Cup and Olympics protests, and Black Lives Matter

responses in Ferguson, Baltimore, and Chicago, amongst others. The

complexities of social movements within a globalized world keep

expanding. Since 2001 at least a series of financial crises have plagued

the advanced capitalist countries, international relations have been

rocked by the breakdown of the Washington Consensus and the rise of

competitive powers of the BRIC (Brazil Russia India China) countries

amongst others; previously stable lines of political division have

gradually blurred.

The second factor in my exploration of agency and emergence was my

introduction to the life sciences through professional training as a

nurse. Biology explores causality in a fundamentally different manner

from what I had been used to. The life sciences and medicine study

adaptive living systems with staggering complexity organized into

different levels, each with their own logic, properties, and issues.

Working in hospitals brings health care practitioners into contact with

that reality as they try to navigate individuals in front of them with

their own composition and reality, and connect that to the more abstract

science of populations, diseases, and treatments. It’s one thing to

understand statistical trends from data of populations; it’s another

thing altogether to apply that knowledge to people who as individuals

can vary substantially.

From the outset parallels between the biological world and the political

world were obvious. Biology provides fodder for political metaphors,

such as the spread of cancers, how the immune system uses memory and

exposure to evolve defenses to unknown dangers, and the self-organized

order that emerges out of reproduction. Health care is not only a source

of analogies, but is viscerally political. Attempts to solve social

problems of health through individual initiative and agent-level change

are notoriously inefficient. The greatest public health victories

utilized collective intervention through the community and the

restructuring of urban space in a holistic way. The reduction of

tuberculosis was largely won before antibiotics were discovered due to

public health campaigners’ understanding of social organization and

emergent disease. The ridiculous state of American health care makes any

tensions between the biological and political more acute for health care

workers. Recontextualized away from disease, the issues and potential

solutions to social problems have at least a parallel to the social

nature of disease, its reproduction, and treatment.

This work is primarily a work of philosophy and metapolitics. Its

contents spell out a general philosophical picture of the world,

specifically about the lives of individuals and social systems, but

particularly from the perspective of developing further tools for

understanding and engaging in political struggles. Although the inquiry

is philosophical in nature, the approach arises from issues in the

biological sciences, history, and real problems in our lives as

thinking, desiring, and intentional beings in societies of solidarity,

conflict, and injustice. Though it draws on biological and complexity

science, I am not a scientific researcher and this is not a work of

empirical scientific research or hypotheses. The goal is to use lessons

from the discussion to further our capacity for social change and

thought.

Politics of Liberation

There are basic assumptions for this project that won’t be explored: a

critique of existing society as unjust and unnecessarily oppressive, as

well as a belief in the possibility of a fundamentally better world.

This is to say that things have been different, they can be changed, and

it is worth working for a different way to live. Social problems like

crime, violence, war, poverty, abuse, and alienation are not eternal or

inevitable, but rather are specific products of our society. For

example, before modern capitalism, work was limited by the cycles of

agriculture or hunting. Societies were structured on these rhythms and

allocated downtime for personal and cultural uses. With the growth of

capitalism, potential work time exploded. Long hours, overtime, and the

consumption of life by stupefying work is not a permanent fixture of

human life, but rather they are recent and avoidable symptoms of modern

capitalism. Nor are they merely incidental or sorted out by a minor fix,

but instead they are systematically produced by a system built to

maintain wealth and power in the hands of certain minorities and out of

reach of the bulk of the population. This perspective is built into the

project. The questions of agency, living systems, and emergence are

explored in the service of a politics of liberation.

Part of the historical shifts in our era have been driven by a loss in

faith in many political traditions globally. For nearly a century the

dominant leftist tendencies centered on a methodological and theoretical

framework that has suffered from a significant loss of credibility

worldwide. Marxism went unchallenged in its dominance in liberatory

thinking from perhaps the Second World War until recently. The pillars

of this thought centered on a number of variants on dialectics,

historical materialism, and Marxist visions for obtaining communist

society. Each of these pieces has since suffered a crisis of legitimacy.

Marxism’s main competitor was a liberalism that sought to improve

capitalism and expand the powers of the State in the service of an

abstract conception of rights and property, while defending the central

institutions of power through seeking to minimize their damage.

Prior to the Second World War anarchism was a global revolutionary

movement, largely of the laboring classes, that stretched from the

Americas to East Asia. In many areas outside Europe, anarchist movements

obtained dominance as the leading light for generations of

revolutionaries. A number of factors shifted the field for anarchist

movements including the rise of the USSR and Soviet-allied movements,

changed patterns of migration and assimilation, nationalism, revolutions

in capitalist production in industries dominated by anarchists, and the

spread of fascism and dictatorships in its strongholds in the 1920s-30s.

Anarchism in most of the West (with some notable exceptions like

Bulgaria and Spain for example) became a shadow of its former self and

too often retreated into a more passive role as the mere moral

conscience of the left when eclipsed by the Marxist-state-building

project earlier in the century. Anarchism lived on however as an active

practice through the Second World War especially in Korea, Eastern

Europe, Cuba, and the Southern Cone of South America.[11] In Uruguay,

Argentina, Chile, and Brazil anarchists retained key influences over

struggles and revolutionary thinking up to the dictatorships in the

1970s. In some cases, there is continuity through to the present.[12]

As thinking has shifted away from the Marxism of the previous generation

towards libertarian alternatives, gaps remain. One way to look at the

approach in this text is as an anarchist framework for revolutionary

thought and action once we have left dialectics, the Marxist vision of

revolution, and historical materialism behind. This isn’t to say there

aren’t things to learn from Marxism. In fact, the case is quite the

opposite. The focus here, however, is to put forward new foundations

rather than to discuss the failures of those traditions, produce more

exegesis of texts, or try to renovate or explore critiques of Marxism in

depth. A book critiquing interpretations of texts is much less valuable

than independent arguments aimed at our own time, especially given how

rare that is for these topics in spite of the popularity of libertarian

thought today.

The core argument of this text is that those seeking liberation face

particular challenges as agents. We are tasked with moving from

minorities committed to acting against powerful forces stacked against

us, while seeking to spread and propagate revolutionary ideas and

actions in a society built to contain and diffuse them. To do so

involves wrestling with large-scale social powers that are beyond our

grasp, difficult to anticipate, and yet crucial for our actions to have

an effect. A path forward can be found in adopting an analysis of our

context in terms of emergence, societies as exhibiting behaviors

characteristic of living systems, and a concept of power that links our

agency to the world of social relationships. These elements taken

together provide tools for interpreting our world and guiding our

actions that may open up new possibilities.

There are four sections in this book. The first part states the case for

the universality and use of philosophy, and explores broad issues around

the theoretical foundations of revolutionary politics. The second

section is the bulk of the work and lays out the theory of emergence,

its life in the sciences, and its application to social and political

thought. In the third section, those ideas are applied to power as a

central aspect of our mental lives and a unique concept that bridges the

world of agency and social emergence. In the fourth section, power and

emergence are used to understand the possibility of revolutionary action

and the problem of agency.

In the past few decades understanding of complex systems has exploded.

Advances in mathematical modeling of complex systems established the

foundations for modeling emergence. Computer scientists used these tools

to help physicists test theories of weather, friction, and electrical

networks. Biologists began describing swarms, hives, and evolution in

terms of complexity and emergence.[13] Social scientists developed new

concepts of the behavior of economic markets, internet communication

networks, self-organization in cities, and the evolution of language

norms through emergence.[14]

The growth of complexity science has led to the creation of tools to

analyze societies that previously were ignored. This work is quite new

and there’s much less exploration of the political implications of

understanding societies as living systems than you would imagine. This

is particularly true for revolutionary politics. Recently, the media has

reported on scientists and think-tanks using complex adaptive systems

modeling to predict riots from food prices,[15] national security

threats from climate change,[16] and regional conflicts in a multi-polar

world.[17] Strange results have emerged with scientists calling for

revolution,[18] IT gurus proposing stateless societies, and capitalist

managers questioning the need for managing workers.[19] This is not

accidental. Emergence confronts us with a change in thinking from what

we are used to—and one that has not yet fully played out. It is not

simply a new theory, but rather sets of theories describing new

phenomena. This carries with it the potential for changes in our

behavior, interpretations of events, and thoughts on political reality.

The framework of emergence is an attempt to give us tools to describe

the world then; but more importantly it is theory with implications for

transforming our situation.

What impact on our actions does emergence have? Theories surrounding

collective liberation specifically hinge on relationships of individual

agents to collectivities, yet theories around the individual’s world and

society have been disjointed. Too often individuals get treated as gods,

directly causing changes in society or society mysteriously moving along

aloof from the individuals within. The Great Man theory of history

popularized in the 19^(th) century has managed to hang on despite early

damning criticisms that undermined its intellectual foundations. The

theory sought to explain historical periods and events in terms of

exceptional individuals who altered the course of their days, and was

elaborated famously by Thomas Carlyle in his work On Heroes,

Hero-Worship and the Heroic in History.[20] Herbert Spencer famously

critiqued this view arguing that notable figures of different periods

were mere productions of the whole social environment that produced

them, drawing from his interpretations of Darwin.[21]

Interestingly William James, one of the pioneers of the concept of

emergence, along with other pragmatist philosophers such as John Dewey,

expressed a critique of both Carlyle’s and Spencer’s theories of the

role of individuals in history in favor of a complex interaction between

the actor and their environment. James argued that individuals are both

influenced by and influence their environment in a complex interaction

across the vast web of causes and reactions throughout society.[22] This

starting point demonstrates a basic emergence approach to understanding

what role individuals can play within social networks of immense

complexity, and takes us beyond turning actors into mere puppets or

superheroes who have mysterious powers. It changes the landscape as we

know it through opening up the possibility of explaining both the

contribution of countless individuals and the separation of society from

them. It is a potentially unifying framework for people who want to

change the world through their actions and understand the social forces

beyond their reach.

The existing literature on emergence from the perspective of a politics

of social change and critique is scanter than one might imagine. It

should be said that since I am not a scholar, there are likely to be

gaps in my own knowledge and research capacity to dig for sources. In

fact, the bulk of this book was written before I discovered thinkers who

had engaged this issue. The sources and historical references were

included at the frequent requests of different readers over the years to

try and situate the ideas better for readers unfamiliar with the

territory. A historian or social scientist by trade could likely produce

something more systematic and encompassing than I have done here (with

the limitations of my abilities and restrictions due to my aims to

blame). In general, the bulk of work on the social aspects of emergence

have been purely academic and descriptive in nature. Contemporary

sociologists seek to use new perspectives on emergence as a means to

better model and explain social phenomena in their studies. One of the

most famous systems theorists, Niklas Luhmann, was notoriously morally

agnostic about the impact of his theories and clung to observation

distanced from any practical lessons for action.

In fact, Luhmann’s ideas were an attack on the notion of agency and any

kind of predictability in trying to make change. His framework was

largely conservative and attempted to justify law, governance, and

existing social relationships, while the theory itself called into

question the ability of the State and law to cleanly impose an order on

the world.[23] The questioning ends there, however, and does not

investigate or propose further critiques of the State or

institutionalized forms of hierarchy despite the weaknesses that Luhmann

and systems theorists identified in its attempt to enforce its order.

Likewise, he fails to propose alternatives—natural lines of questioning

arising from the inherent weaknesses Luhmann and systems theorists

demonstrate in the ability of centralized structures to impose their

will directly.

Contemporary critical political thought in general has not shifted

significantly from more traditional liberal and dialectic narratives

towards emergence. The few theorists who uphold radical critique and

emergence at the same time have tended to use it as an explanatory tool

for traditional left ideologies rather than an approach in its own

right. Biological theorists Richard Lewontin and Richard Levins, for

example, have used emergence as a way to explore dialectics. Emergence

is a tool for the authors to explore political concepts and events

without opening up the implications of those theories to their

underlying basic frameworks and political models.[24] Dialectics,

however, is fundamentally about contradiction between opposites— theses

and anti-theses which oppose each other until transformed through

synthesis. This has no parallel in the world of social emergence and

complexity in which social causes are numerous or multi-polar and can’t

be reduced to the abstract binary opposites. Thus even for radical

critics of present society, emergence has provided an instrument for

explanation, but has not received an in depth attempt at extracting its

own unique implications for revolutionary theory, nor to assess its

potential to replace prior political starting points including Luhmann’s

conservative anti-humanism, liberal free agency, and Marxian dialectics.

There is then a distinct absence of proposals or debates about the

potential or effect of emergence on how we do politics, or its

implications for our basic views about the social world: power, the

State, social change, and the role of organized individuals in mass

action. This isn’t to say that emergence hasn’t played a subtler and

more hidden role within thought about social change. As an undercurrent,

emergentist ideas get frequent play in justifying shifts in political

discourse from participatory democratic experiments to revolts.[25]

Within the anarchist tradition there remains an untapped current of

emergence. Anarchist ideas and methods operate with an understanding of

the world in which the decentralized order constructed by individuals in

cooperation produces new powers and possibilities simultaneously

harnessed and repressed by the society of the State. Anarchism, as a

broad tradition spread across the globe, has adherents who have adopted

many different approaches including utopian, liberal, and dialectical

interpretations of anarchist thought. Still within the core of the

tradition anarchist thinkers have often made use of emergence to develop

their politics.

Peter Kropotkin, famed Russian evolutionary biologist and anarchist

theorist, and Elisée Reclus, a radical anarchist thinker and

foundational geographer, both wrote about natural phenomena in terms

that today we would call ecological and complexity based. Their views of

the world were complex and adaptive with emergent order produced by the

interaction from the bottom up forming their biology and geography,

respectively, yet leaving a mark on their anarchist thinking that was

distinct from the dialectics, humanist, and liberal thought of their

day.[26] Other thinkers, such as Australian anarchosyndicalist and

ecologist Graham Purchase, have looked to complexity and emergence to

provide critiques of the State and capital and a scientific description

of how anarchist society could produce better human organization.[27]

Noam Chomsky perhaps implicitly uses similar ideas in his critique of

media in Manufacturing Consent. One way to read those arguments is that

they provide a model in which unified propaganda is produced throughout

media organizations without having overt censorship. Chomsky charts how

power flows through these organizations as a complex and dynamic system

producing emergent propaganda.[28]

As much as these ideas were present as an undercurrent there is a lack

of explicit work to explore emergence on its own and put it at the core

of a libertarian approach to social transformation. Likewise, there’s a

parallel with power when the anarchist tradition innovated by making

power central, distinguishing it from other revolutionary traditions of

its time, and yet direct discussion of theories of power can sometimes

be difficult to find.[29] This is an attempt to lay out the groundwork

for such a politics, rather than to give immediate solutions. To address

that lacuna, the focus here is developing bases for social

transformation—drawing out the connections between agency, cognition,

power, and emergence for a broad theory of a revolutionary process and

action. These chapters are a stepping off in that unfinished direction.

Part 1: Philosophy

For Philosophy

With much of the world upended, to turn to philosophy might seem like a

strange move. Philosophy, the most abstract and seemingly out of touch

of all intellectual disciplines, appears a strange bedfellow for a time

when small fires are coming out of the ground here and there: Egypt,

Chile, China, Southern Europe, India, and even the United States. For

decades there’s been a philosophical slumber in the political world; a

cautious balance of traditions guarded by academia and a drift across

vast oceans swimming away from all the tumult raging ashore.

It’s precisely in times of great change that people turn again to

philosophy. Today we stand at crossroads in world history again with the

global flows of capital reorganizing, the loss of the “stability” of

Western and formerly Sovietaligned powers, new struggles arising around

the world, and an uncertain future both for liberation and survival at

least in the world as we’ve known it. With the breakdown of the previous

geopolitical balance of forces, agreements, and models, the dominant

forms of thought, too, are under fire. The failures of the powerful to

organize society have raised many questions about the ability of

existing philosophies to account for history’s sour turns. When matters

like environmental catastrophe, the potential for massive wars (and

expanding areas of conflict), economic collapse, and so on are on the

table, key sectors within the liberatory political landscape return to

philosophy to reevaluate and seek new ways forward. The surprising

popular success of Marx’s Capital in bookstores during the throes of

world financial crisis explained thusly makes perfect sense. Fundamental

questions are being raised, and people who normally do not engage in

that kind of activity are going back to the basics and picking up

whatever tools they’re aware of.

Part of the struggle for a more just society is our understanding,

conception, and analysis of our reality and struggles. We don’t just

reproduce ideas that we find, but we also invent new concepts, create

new ways of thinking about changing reality, and propose ways of

thinking to help us change the world. We make and reform methodologies,

analyses, and concepts. That is, we build theory. The framework we use

to build theories is called metatheory, or the tools used to construct

theory out of. It is the basic unit or vocabulary of political work—the

bricks and mortar of a building, the basic conceptions that allow us to

have thoughts. It gives us a language to describe our political language

or thoughts with.

At this moment in history however, philosophy is an embattled territory.

Science’s expanding grasp of the universe has brought within reach many

things that once only philosophers considered within the grasp of raw

empirical inquiry. Today it’s miraculous to look at the endurance of

Aristotle’s physics within Western thought. A millennia passed before

new ways of explaining physics beyond the framework laid out in

Aristotle’s theories. Today imagining any scientific theory, let alone

one created by a philosopher, lasting a generation would be unusual let

alone centuries. Out of philosophy the sciences and disciplines were

constructed and the expansion of knowledge brought about by scientific

inquiry has led to rapid change in theorizing. Subsequently, philosophy

has shrunk and changed, and where its borders lie seem harder to pick

out than ever before—borders that are rapidly shifting and contested.

Strong anti-intellectual currents, at least in US society, make

philosophy seem to many the purest form of erudite elitism and

abstraction for abstraction’s sake. Purged of its empirical elements,

philosophy appears to be the business of settling problems whose

solutions have no outcome anyway—pure speculation and mental

masturbation. None of this is aided by actually existing philosophy,

which unfortunately is often characterized by feuding men at elite

institutions who view their role more as gladiators for hire in an arena

than as engaged citizens. These sentiments are particularly true for

liberatory political thought, which draws from sometimes justified

suspicions of professional intellectuals as well as from a desire to

move to action without the mediation of the baggage of previous

historical debates, obsessions with canonical texts, and intellectual

hierarchies stacked against the exploited and oppressed.

At the same time battles are being waged over different traditions

philosophers, canons, and what role previous philosophies will play in

understanding the victories and tragedies of political struggle. The

intellectual crises of traditional left movements with the fall of the

USSR (combined with a twin threat of an insurgent and rising global

anarchism eclipsing the Marxism and socialism of previous generations)

have created a vacuum of philosophical space. Lineage, tradition,

foundations, and starting points are being rewritten and re-evaluated.

The work of French and Italian revolutionaries brought them to Spinoza

as they sought to work out perceived shortcomings they encountered in

applying Marxism and Marx’s Hegelianism to their experiences in Paris in

1968 and Italy’s struggles throughout the 60s and 70s. Many Maoists and

Marxist-Leninists of today look to the work of Alain Badiou to provide a

philosophical foundation for understanding the limitations of the

official authoritarian Marxist-Leninist state experiences of the 20^(th)

century and paths forward while still retaining the legacy of such

movements. Anarchist and libertarian thinkers likewise have sought

philosophical tools for elaborating their conceptions apart from the

dialectics, Hegelianism, and most of all the domination of Marxism and

liberalism within liberatory thought in recent decades.

From the perspective of liberation, philosophy is live territory perhaps

now more so than in recent memory. Foucault, Badiou, Althusser, Negri,

and Butler are examples of recent thinkers who have had influence on a

wide array of relevant political issues. The importance for example of

Negri and Hardt’s Empire exemplified that.[30] Its influence was grossly

disproportionate to its actual content, and in retrospect can be viewed

as capturing the uncertainty of the time at which people began rising up

against neoliberalism while leftist dogmas one by one crumbled. With the

World Trade Organization protests coming on its heels, Empire was in the

right place at the right time. Often bizarre and strained attempts to

apply such thinkers to concrete work speaks to the poverty of and hunger

for these ideas. There is a push and pull between anti-intellectualism

on the one hand, and then a poverty of theory that speaks to the moments

and positions people who are struggling find themselves in without

roadmaps or mentors. The gap between theory and practice is more literal

than figurative.

While it is true that very few, even among hardcore political activists,

look to such philosophical work, the impact of it should not be

underestimated. Theory and philosophy matter in part because some people

think they do. Only a tiny fraction of people engaged in Marxist

struggles actually read Marx himself, but the influence of Marx and his

works was massive. This is because key actors always come back to

philosophy to help make sense of experiences. While the influence of

theory is diffused through innumerable factors, the fact remains that

philosophy is a place where important elements return to frequently and

especially so in moments of change.

Philosophy does not derive its importance from the simple fact that

influential (however we understand that) people use it and take it

seriously. If that were the end of the story, we might simply take note

of it and submit that faith in philosophy to greater scrutiny. Just

because some people believe in philosophy does not ensure that it’s

useful, worthwhile, or fruitful. There is something deeper going on in

the ebb and flow of philosophy within society. Philosophy is not only a

tool, but is also an inherent part of human life and thought.

Philosophy has no opt-out option therefore. Our mental lives are built

upon philosophy and all people engage in philosophical thinking, though

not necessarily as a conscious effort. It is through finding answers to

other questions that philosophy rises to the surface, and when our

ability to find answers in our daily lives breaks down, the underlying

philosophical elements become more obvious. This is to say that there

are inherent philosophical elements to all human thought.

What is philosophy then? Attempting to define philosophy is a minefield,

and if done seriously, would require an entire book. Bertrand Russell

underlines the trouble defining philosophy:

We may note one peculiar feature of philosophy. If someone asks the

question what is mathematics, we can give him a dictionary definition,

let us say the science of number, for the sake of argument. As far as it

goes this is an uncontroversial statement... Definitions may be given in

this way of any field where a body of definite knowledge exists. But

philosophy cannot be so defined. Any definition is controversial and

already embodies a philosophic attitude. The only way to find out what

philosophy is, is to do philosophy.[31]

A core component of doing philosophy is looking at the underlying

assumptions, structures, and values of various problems or fields of

thought. There are philosophical questions for physics, sociology, art,

literature, religion, the mind, space, time, and so on. Philosophy is

not about topics, texts, or subjects, but rather it is a type of

approach and types of questions. Traditionally the approach of

philosophy is primarily aimed at exploring elements of our knowledge,

evaluations, ultimate nature or being, and methodologies underlying

fundamental problems. Immanuel Kant delineates the terrain well showing

the wonder that philosophy can inspire in us as agents approaching a

world empowered and required to inquire and intervene:

Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and

awe, the more often and steadily we reflect upon them: the starry

heavens above me and the moral law within me. I do not seek or

conjecture either of them as if they were veiled obscurities or

extravagances beyond the horizon of my vision; I see them before me and

connect them immediately with the consciousness of my existence. The

first starts at the place that I occupy in the external world of the

senses, and extends the connection in which I stand into the limitless

magnitude of worlds upon worlds, systems upon systems, as well as into

the boundless times of their periodic motion, their beginning and

continuation. The second begins with my invisible self, my personality,

and displays to me a world that has true infinity, but which can only be

detected through the understanding, and with which ... I know myself to

be in not, as in the first case, merely contingent, but universal and

necessary connection. The first perspective of a countless multitude of

worlds as it were annihilates my importance as an animal creature, which

must give the matter out of which it has grown back to the planet (a

mere speck in the cosmos) after it has been (one knows not how)

furnished with life-force for a short time.[32]

If we step back, we can discern two broad kinds of philosophical issues:

descriptive and normative. Normative issues are issues of evaluations

(or norms), most commonly morals and ethics, but not exclusively. Issues

such as beauty, good taste, and even the rationality of judgments are

forms of value judgments. It’s important to note that there is no

science that could explain such problems. Science might tell us what

value judgments we actually make based on the universe and our biology,

but there is no science that can tell us we ought to make those

judgments or not. The universe is ambivalent to those facts; we are the

only ones who care. Normative questions concern what ought to be, rather

than what is. Normative questions reside almost exclusively in the

domain of philosophical thought.

Normative judgments, evaluations, questions, reasoning, and action

guided by such are widespread and evident in our lives. This is because

it is fundamentally human to have to contemplate our actions, their

effect, and those of others who can decide what to do or not to do.

Likewise, these judgments are contested. One generation may not even

contemplate abortion as relevant to moral thinking, yet the next might

be willing to kill over it. The prominent debates over how people make

economic choices is an example of a philosophical normative issue; what

decisions one ought to make, what purchases are rational, and so on all

embody a philosophical worldview and latent value assumptions that are

contested on all sides today. Though few discuss these issues as

philosophy it is a debate that touches nearly all of us through the

media, advertising, and education. This is the first way in which

philosophy is inevitable. Because we are creatures that must evaluate

actions, we are inherently tied to philosophy.

Descriptive philosophy deals with questions that try to capture elements

of our world. There is more overlap here with science than with

normative matters. For instance, someday neuroscience may demonstrate

how the mind and body are one and the same. People can argue that

different ways (and in fact the belief that science can is itself a

philosophical position). The science of the mind is about explaining the

data of its functioning. A robust neuroscience would be able to explain

the chemistry and biology of our bodies, and through some elaborate

explanation, the mental states, behaviors, and so on that humans have.

Science is (roughly) about explaining data based on theories that can be

reproduced through experimentation and predictions. The theory tells you

how things function, and how they ought to behave given the model. There

is a missing component though—neuroscience cannot tell us what a mind

itself is. Science is neutral to how we understand what the mind is,

except through its functioning. This is because science is about

prediction over time, but not all elements of what something is will

affect what it does. If the mind is purely matter or if it is ideas in

God’s mind, it will behave the same from the perspective of science.

Questions about the nature of things like the mind are one element of

descriptive philosophy.

Consider how we attain knowledge of the nature of the mind. Whatever the

mind is, whatever the account of its behavior and laws, questions abound

as to how we would come to know any of this. Science provides accounts

of the world as we happen to know it, but that doesn’t answer any

evaluation of whether or not that process gives us knowledge, the

underlying reality of our knowledge, or indeed what we are or reality

is. These are philosophical issues. In general, descriptive philosophy

deals with how we come to know things and the essence or being of

things. Though it is less obvious than with normative questions,

descriptive philosophy is an inherent component of our thought as well.

Religion is an evident domain where human philosophizing becomes

apparent.

Religions change, which causes philosophical explanations to shift. Some

religions placed humanity within a false reality, in the belly of hell

awaiting our awakening to a hidden reality. Other religious thought

placed deities as the ultimate source of all knowledge, and instructed

people to seek out truth through prayer and introspection alone.

Religions disagreed over our connection with other humans, either wholly

separating us as purely individual or autonomous beings, or placing us

as actually a single being divided by illusions of separate existence

from a unified totality. Religious thought exemplifies human attempts to

find answers to questions that underlie our other inquiries. There is no

experiment we could perform that would tell us whether or not we are in

the belly of a devil. People’s aspiration to understand the knowledge

and reality of the world lead them to popular forms of philosophy.

Another example of inherent philosophizing is politics itself. While

much of politics falls in the normative domain, people come to form

political beliefs based on a latticework of more basic philosophical

positions. The debate about abortion makes this explicit. Though

religion dominates the discussion, it’s worth noting that some atheists

also reject abortion, and many religious people do not see abortion as

murder. The basic disagreement centers on a philosophical position of

what constitutes life, which is wholly distinct from scientific notions.

One way to look at the debate is that there is no fact of the matter of

when life starts in the sense that people care about; there are only

debates about the basic conceptions of life, its value, and the meaning

of our actions. Under the political issue lies questions about

causality, our agency, the nature of life, and morality. These persist

because they are questions that concern us, but which no amount of

empirical data or experiments could help us solve. Because of our

values, abortion pushes philosophical questions about life and our

actions onto us. It throws us into philosophy unknowingly. The structure

of our minds and world makes us face questions like these that are can’t

be approached without philosophy.

With this in mind, we can say that all people engage in philosophy,

though not necessarily overtly. Everyone has philosophical ideas,

assumptions, and theories to explain the world. Sometimes this is

manifested in religious beliefs, folk wisdom, and unconscious reasoning.

At other times people put forward overt theories, though generally not

as philosophy per se. In the abortion example we can see how different

positions, which nearly everyone on some level has, take distinct

positions on both descriptive and normative philosophy of mind, ethics,

metaphysics, and life. This is distinct from making those processes

conscious, codifying them, having a language specific to describe them,

and so on. People may have tacit beliefs about what the ultimate reality

of life is without either naming or being aware of them, and yet engage

in self-reflection and change their underlying theories based on

reasoning. We can compare thinking of life as the beginning of a chain

of events starting at sex, the growth of a sentient humanlike being, or

the moment when a new form of life is shifted from the cells of the egg

upon conception. Each carries a philosophical view with associated

beliefs and explanations.

Antonio Gramsci, an Italian revolutionary, made a famous distinction

between good sense and common sense. For Gramsci, all people had both

good sense and common sense. Common sense is socially inherited for the

most part. Each individual has their own thoughts and beliefs, many of

which are founded upon habit and tradition embodied in a place and their

period. This is the fragmented contradictory set of philosophical

thinking we all have. Good sense on the other hand is where people’s

thought becomes more conscious, ordered, and coherent. Gramsci

especially praised the attempts of everyday people to try and shape

their thinking to their experiences. Theory moving in tandem with and

influencing practice was called praxis. People have experiences, they

theorize them, and those theories generate new practices, which in turn

modify the theory, and so on.

While everyone philosophizes consciously and unconsciously — good sense

must be cultivated. Gramsci lays out then the inherent nature of

philosophy to living, and argues that we should perfect it. Yet we’re

not perfecting philosophy as an abstract, but rather to fit our concrete

context: our struggles, position, and aspirations both informing and

being informed by our experiences. The distinction between good sense

and common sense points to the reasonable notion that all people no

matter their education, intelligence, or position engage in

philosophical thinking though with different levels of conscious

processes, specificity, and effort.[33]

People do not normally consider this theorizing or engaging in high

intellectual activity, but it is. Obviously there’s a distinction

between the work of individuals who spend decades working out an

analyses of their own and the positions individuals come to as a

reaction to things occurring to them and around them. Yet the gulf is

not as wide as might be thought. Between viewing our political mental

life as purely passive or cultivated, there lies a dynamic interplay.

People are not merely responsive, but also must filter their responses.

Responses come through the lens of their beliefs, desires, and

intentions. As people live and grow, they inevitably encounter elements

of life that contradict what they think and what they have been taught.

How they choose to respond to these contradictions is one path that

leads to philosophical thinking, and politics is no different. We need

only look at all the various shifts in discourse, surveys, and activity

following the financial crisis of 2008 to see evidence for widespread

philosophical thought throughout society.

A significant barrier to recognizing this ultimately comes from an

excessively individualistic world view in which people form their ideas

roughly in a vacuum, as though peering through the windows that are our

eyes at the world outside, and only then return to social life to

implement their ideas. In reality the situation is much more complex

since divisions between individual and social life are incredibly

blurred. People’s responses and questions do not occur in isolation. The

speech, actions, and reactions of the countless others with whom we are

in intimate contact (in modern cities and suburbs) influence our

conscious thinking and unconscious activity. We do not ask questions out

of nowhere, but rather we bring our own contributions to the experiences

and options offered to us. Our own ideas and behavior inherently refer

to the thoughts and actions of others in an endless spiral, each

affecting one another. We all rely on, reformulate, adjust, and create

theory in the course of our lives in order to understand our world, our

position within it, and the best course of action for us. Philosophy is

not alien or external to us. These are underlying issues inherent to

being the thinking creature that we are, and they are both inescapable

and completely widespread throughout our societies. Philosophers may

have the distinction of being called such, but it is only because they

have a discipline, tradition, and institutions that support their titles

and work. We are all philosophers.

This isn’t to diminish the unique contributions individuals make, nor

the idea that people can innovate and create genuinely new ideas. It is

simply to acknowledge that we can’t make sense of any aspect of human

mental and social life without referencing the lives, thoughts, and

relationships with others. From this perspective, the universality of

philosophical thinking is a consequence of the philosophical thought of

all of us united in complex networks throughout societies. Intellectuals

with texts, theories, and work are one manifestation of that broader

social process at hand. Yet more fundamentally it is the inherent

process within us all that makes theories possible.

Moves to Deflate

Yet one might ask if philosophy actually adds anything to our thoughts.

Is it simply a trick? A mental trap? The ordinary language philosophers

argued as such, claiming that philosophical problems develop out of

snares in ordinary use of language that philosophers take out of their

use-context to generate their quandaries. In some instances, they sought

to reduce philosophical problems to linguistic, semantic, or conceptual

problems. Wittgenstein, for example argued:

[Philosophical problems] are solved
by looking into the workings of our

language, and that in such a way as to make us recognize those workings:

in despite of an urge to misunderstand them. The problems are solved,

not by giving new information, but by arranging what we have always

known. Philosophy is a battle against the bewitchment of our

intelligence by means of language.[34]

This approach can reduce philosophical questions to puzzles that fall

out of the questions or problem itself. Philosophy then does not

actually change our course, but instead only helps us explain away the

problems that come out of our language. For example, take the issue of

truth. Deflationism about truth similarly attempts to deflate or

eliminate the philosophical tension about the nature of truth through an

account that is about language and our use of the concept.[35]

Deflationists argued that to say that “grass is green” is true, we are

simply saying “grass is green.” Truth adds no new content to the

sentence, but can be a useful way to use language as a shorthand for

repetition. In doing so, they reduced the problem of truth to a

syntactic one, and showed that the ability to assert sentences using

truth as a tool played a role.[36]

This move was quite pervasive in the field in an earlier era and

parallels popular ideas about the irrelevancy of theoretical issues. At

its most extreme this approach rejected the relevance of philosophy

altogether. Extrapolating, we see that if such questions are merely

semantic tricks which add no new content to our understanding of

questions, then what bearing could they have on anything of substance?

Even if we inherently end up philosophizing, this doesn’t show that it

has any use beyond the curiosity of the theory-phile.

First, it’s worth considering that philosophy for its own sake has an

inherent good. It may be good for people engaging in inquiry to test

their minds, more deeply analyze assumptions unexamined, and develop

abilities within the philosophical realm that help with analysis and

reasoning that are more applied. Philosophical practice could be a type

of mental exercise to build abilities one wouldn’t otherwise get. The

process alone can improve us and benefit us.

Yet, broad skepticism concerning the importance of all philosophical

inquiries is hard to sustain. For one, large sections of contested

social life are imbued with purely theoretical questions. Ethics is an

obvious example. It is not that there are timeless and unmoving ethical

contents that philosophy merely tries to reconcile with our intuitive

beliefs and practices. Instead, ethical sentiments have both apparent

universals and historical and sociological variation. The values of the

ancients are not necessarily the values of today. Whether we ought to

have values different than our own is a philosophical problem.

Historically humanity has been repeatedly wrong concerning ethical

judgments, particularly concerning the lower orders of society, the

dominated, and the exploited. Euthanasia, racism, sexism, and countless

forms of dehumanization point to the contextual and changing nature of

values. There is no way of approaching these questions, which are

clearly vital, without philosophy in one form or another.

Beyond ethical issues there are always fundamental assumptions beneath

all forms of thought that are likewise contested. Psychology, politics,

sociology, the sciences, and literature all have their philosophical

bedrock they are built upon. In the literary arts, for example, growing

interest in language, globalization, and broad cross-linguistic trends

led to an examination of the notion of translation. Translating works of

literature is common, and when reflected upon choices around translation

show elements of artistic creation. For translators of literature,

concepts like meaning, intention, form, and aesthetic judgments form the

core of their activity. Each discipline and human endeavor has its

philosophical issues like translation in literature.

Physics would appear to be the most solid of all subjects. Yet, physics

is beset by methodological issues raised by theories that explain the

behavior of subatomic particles. Quantum mechanics and string theory are

two examples of theories that provide answers that contradict basic

beliefs we have about what it means to be an observer, how we come to

have knowledge about observed phenomena, space, time, and motion.[37]

Hard problems in the physical sciences that contradict what we believe

about the world can lead to philosophical investigations, which likewise

can generate new research. It is no accident that many of the great

scientists themselves were invested in philosophical debates of their

time, such as Einstein with the logical positivists and Newton with the

rationalists and Neo-Platonists.

The problem of consciousness in recent time is one example of an issue

raised by philosophers, drawing from neuroscience, which has been taken

up further by neuroscientists for new kinds of research. Philosophical

interest in the raw experiential sense of “what is it like” has led to

investigations and model from cognitive scientists and

neuroscientists.[38] Philosophers of mind draw from new research to help

find those boundaries as well: where does our concept of consciousness

meet with what we know about the brain? Philosophy can help us with

roadblocks in other domains, and it also provides the underlying basis

for doing work in other fields, which can help or hinder our

understanding of that work (such as conceptualizations of things like

time, causation, perception, and so on in physics). Discipline-specific

philosophical problems reflect the ethical, metaphysical, and

epistemological quandaries of their domain. At the same time, they raise

the underlying general philosophical problems they draw from and

contribute to. Philosophy is perhaps less of a separate sphere or brand

than a type of activity exhibited in broad swaths of human life with

associated content and questions.

In politics, consider the role of philosophy in major world events.

Marxism in the political world became one of the most influential

currents in history. Marxism likewise arose partly from debates within

the Hegelian societies, which in turn were debates generated by

disagreements over history, knowledge, and the ultimate nature of

subjectivity and reality. This isn’t to abstract away the role of

history and struggle in forming political currents, but just to raise

the relevancy of a philosophical element amongst others. All major

political thought has found its grounding in philosophical problems

concerning a few key questions: ethics, agency, knowledge, and society.

Political problems are ones that address us both as members of societies

and as agents within the world. It is unavoidable that there be deep

questions about the direction, foundation, and justification for our

judgments, a path to a good society, and how we come to have our beliefs

about political questions. This is even truer for any critical politics.

Rejecting doing philosophy within liberatory thought means embracing

exclusively what we happen to believe or practice without reflection. If

the present order is rejected, then the ability to deflate philosophical

problems about politics becomes problematic as intuitive political

philosophy is often based upon a corrupt material and moral order.

Looking to science, politics, and even literature, philosophy raises

elements both of thought and practice that can contribute to changing

activity and generating new ideas. As experiences generate new ideas, we

respond to the ideas and create new forms of practice. This relationship

is complex and not obvious, but it points to a deeper analysis of the

role of philosophy beyond mere semantics. If we accept that there are

philosophical questions of substantive content and that these are

unavoidable at least on some level, then additional questions are

raised.

Good Sense and the Professionals

Our world thus reflects our inherent philosophical beliefs, and when our

beliefs change they can reshape the world (though not necessarily

directly or simply). Philosophy, as we discussed, helps us when our

thoughts hit limits. Particularly in times of turmoil, philosophy is

turned to for help. But what are the consequences of having it be the

domain only of philosophers? That is, if only professional philosophers

do philosophy, how will that affect our own thinking?

If we refuse to engage in it, we cede that territory to others and often

others who may or may not have our best interests in mind. Philosophy as

a professional field relies upon a series of elite institutions to fund,

train, and employ their staff. The politics and dynamics of academic

employment is sordid enough to raise questions about the ability of

professional academics to generate tools for people trying to better

their lives and societies. Their institutions are largely run by elite

intellectuals who uphold philosophy as the property of fulltime

academics, which serves a hierarchical social organization that

continually places the thinking of what is best for society into the

hands of the few. Immense social pressure exerted through competition,

funding, and the moderating effect of employment judged through ability

to publish has deeply conservative effects on every discipline in

academia. On the one hand there is a steady stream of trivial technical

work aimed at securing and maintaining one’s employment, and, on the

other hand, strong defense of the existing power structures in one

modified form or another. This is merely to say that professional

institutions reflect the power dynamics within society as a whole.

Privilege and power get disproportionate voices and have extensive means

to reproduce ideology throughout society, academia included.

By failing to take up the theories that are continually pushed upon us,

and questioning our own, we allow leaders (either of movements or of

dominant society) to often decide key questions for us that not only can

impact the underlying theories, but often day-to-day strategies and

tactics of struggles for liberation. For instance, contemplate writings

and coverage of things like the foreclosure crisis in the United States.

Through the media, academic publications, think-tanks, and government

reports various positions on resistance, the problem, and potential

solutions are developed. People interact with these through points of

intersection in their daily life: their union, church, school,

workplace, television, associations, and political affiliations. These

positions are developed largely by people who have direct investment in

the maintenance of the system through the funding of their employment,

and the simple fact that it is working for them. Consequently,

institutions of the powerful tend to set the debates. In the case of

foreclosures key actors like SEIU, the Democratic Party, and a network

of non-profits tied to foundation grants or unions led to focusing on

the defense of private property of individuals rather than questioning

capitalist housing itself that turns people’s homes and neighborhoods

into commodities which has generated countless similar crises.

While this does not mean that it’s not possible for such people to be

critical, on a broader social level it is true that perspectives that

protect the dominant view are consistently overrepresented and defended

by professional thinkers. This translates into people seeking to remedy

the problem looking towards official channels set by the dominant power

holders.

Dissidents do exist of course. Yet still too often we are lacking a

vehicle for independent thought. Meanwhile, hostile perspectives that

seek to maintain the status quo are able to use a monopoly of

professional intellectuals to move concrete philosophies in everyday

life that serve their interests, often against the interests of the

great majority. This is not to pass judgment on those individuals or to

reduce their positions to their social class, but rather to raise the

issue that allowing for a whole realm of human mental life to be

dominated by professionals or even to write it off is to passively

accept the reproduction of the ruling ideology on fundamental questions

for people trying to enact change. If we want to see critical

perspectives, especially those of the dominated, we have to

independently intervene and create philosophy with wider participation.

Recognizing the role of philosophy in our lives begs for another

approach. The division of labor between thinkers and workers, the

academies and society at large should be questioned. There should be an

effort to expand working intellectual life, and to deepen both the

capacity of people to engage with philosophy in their daily lives.

Obviously not everyone will become a philosopher and write theories, but

everyone can learn to think philosophically, question dominant

philosophical thinking, and develop their own positions. Everyone,

though particularly liberatory movements, should engage in questioning

and developing theory in the course of their actions. There’s no reason

to assume this is only a matter of individual education and willpower,

either. Our education system pushes us to think individualistically in a

way that doesn’t reflect how people learn. Scientists most evidently do

not do research in this manner. Collaboration and collective projects

are at the heart of their practice, beyond some base level of mastery

that all scientists much engage on their own. If we recognize the

potential for people to learn collaboratively with common aims and

interests, the possibility of a popular intellectual life informed by

people’s aspirations could be a tangible reality.

This is not a call for everyone to sit, as Descartes did, in front of a

fireplace contemplating the mysteries of the universe. That is fine and

often fulfilling to many, yet it is different from what we have been

discussing. Within us, philosophy grows and develops, tracing the arcs

of our lives and our beliefs. Theory and philosophy are not islands to

which we swim only when things have gotten rough on the mainland. Our

theory is not simply internal to us, but it additionally undergirds the

rest of our activities and thinking. Theory evolves with our

experiences. Humans are biological creatures with an endowment that

shapes our thought through our genetic legacy, yet it is an open

process. As we grow, change, struggle, and thrive, our ideas about the

world change with our experiences. Living in cities and experiencing the

technological revolution of mass communication, for example, certainly

altered the way humans thought about their lives, families, work, and so

on. In actual fact, theory and practice do grow together.

The best, of course, is when our theory and our practice move together

organically, learning from practice and creating new theory, and the

theory generating new practice. This is sometimes called praxis. Praxis

is an ideal we aspire to. That is, that we should make our philosophies

explicit, question them, weigh them against our experiences, and

reformulate them so we have more tools to keep doing what we think is

the best thing to do. This intentional, conscious process can help us

think more clearly and learn from our mistakes. Action is more than our

conscious intentions, and yet at the same time this doesn’t invalidate

the usefulness of trying to achieve a praxis.

Philosophy as something inherent to our mental lives, something within

reach of all, can be liberating both in understanding these points and

in applying them. The universality of philosophy within society doesn’t

mean that we should diminish nor exalt explicitly- theoretical texts

like this one. Instead, it is to recognize that philosophy is the domain

of all people irrespective of their intelligence, gender, class, race,

or position. In societies based on domination the alienation from

philosophy is apparent. It is also a grave mistake to look at such

activity as alien to the oppressed and the sole property of elites.

There is no option to avoid doing philosophy; there is only a choice to

do it well or not.

This isn’t to say there aren’t barriers. Today’s society is built on

divisions that try to enforce the ownership of theoretical thought by

professional intellectuals. Anti-intellectualism is ultimately

self-defeating. In the course of this struggle we have to be creative

and find new ways to do philosophy—a philosophy of collective creation

and a liberatory philosophy. Simply wishing philosophy to be popular is

not enough. We can’t merely overcome these issues by manipulating the

terminology or method to be more accessible, while people continue to

experience the limiting and alienating effects of capitalist work and

all its stupefaction of everyday life. Just as artistic creation has

been stolen from the public and relegated to a spectacle by

professionals reproducing artistic commodities for the market, so

philosophy often has been chained to an exploitive system of thought. We

need to seize philosophy again, see what we have available to us, and

discern how we can recreate it for our own purposes.

Metapolitics

Issues inherent to ethics, social justice, biology, science, and

societies are confronted through the course of the arguments working

from emergence to agency. Though we’ve been speaking about philosophy in

general, much of this work takes on critical political philosophy

specifically. In this sense it comes from the perspective of a critique

of today’s society alongside aspirations for a fundamentally different

social order. The main focus of such is with political questions, and

specifically with the underlying method and framework for doing

politics.

Political questions can be divided into two different levels of

analysis. One the one hand are raw political questions like: Is abortion

wrong? Is it just for starvation to exist? What is the best form of

governance for society? These questions deal with content and specific

issues within a broader framework for political debate. This is simply

politics or perhaps social questions. Answers at this level address

assertions, such as “Abortion is morally permissible because it is not

murder, and therefore should be socially permitted by law.”

Beneath these is a different type of questioning, questions about the

underlying methodology and theoretical foundations for asking any

political questions at all. This is the metapolitical. Metapolitics

deals with the fundamentals that make settling political questions

possible. For example, we might ask what the notion of a polity is

altogether. What methods yield political truths? What distinguishes the

political from other categories like the social or biological?

Metapolitical inquiries provide answers not to political questions, but

rather to the underlying concepts and structures upon which political

questions are built. All political actors have latent philosophical

foundations that they use to understand and guide their struggles.

Ethical, social, and philosophical beliefs form the core from which

people create their ideas for a political path to the world they seek,

and an understanding of the current one. Metapolitical theories then

give us the tools with which we build our theories.

This does not mean that when people come to political conclusions and

take part in political acts that take sides they are explicitly thinking

first of their metapolitical assumptions and then second working out a

response. Metapolitics is a level of analysis, a place where questions

of a certain sort can be asked. Anyone who engages in political life

(which means social life in general and not merely conscious political

activity), engages in metapolitical thought. The reasons are the same as

for the universality of doing philosophy. Since we are creatures with

minds and live in societies like we do, metapolitics is an implicit and

unconscious element of human social life. We can attribute metapolitical

assumptions to people either by their thoughts and expressions or by

their actions. Human nature, for instance, often plays a strong role in

political theory. Most people likely have thoughts about human nature,

make judgments based on it, and indeed shape their lives in relation to

perceived nature in people. Yet what about the concept of human nature

itself? What is it? Answers to these questions are metapolitical; but

simply by having belief about human nature, people have tacit

commitments to ideas about nature itself.

Besides latent thoughts, there is as well conscious metapolitical

thought. This is also universal, though not in an obvious form. Because

of the dominance of professional intellectuals and the sequestering of

their thought to institutions, such as academia, think-tanks, NGOs, and

so on, metapolitical activity of nonprofessionals is not widely

recognized. Yet people do come to change their beliefs about fundamental

ways in which society operates and how to effect change. People come to

believe or stop believing in the ability of individuals to fundamentally

control the course of history. People come to see institutional

structures of power or capital as determining agents controlling all

society independent of the individuals involved. People become cynical

of the potential for escaping the invariable dominance of human nature

corrupting all social life. Within these attitudinal responses to

political events, people take on political positions proper, but also

are changing their underlying assumptions about how societies operate,

and forming new opinions based on this.

Simply making our internal process conscious doesn’t guarantee it will

help us either though. Most of human mental life is unconscious anyway,

and being conscious of underlying assumptions does not necessarily allow

us to escape pervasive errors or introduce new ones. Engaging in

explicit metapolitics as this work is intended to do is simply to add to

our capabilities and experience as people trying to work critically

within a process for liberation. The explicitness is not a holy grail,

nor is it a standalone solution. It is one part of our political

activity, amongst many. The relative importance of this is an open

question. Realistically, it is likely to help us through addressing real

underlying issues, but it also does not have any great privileged status

that invalidates other elements of political life. The contestation of

theory, practice, intuition, creativity, emotion, reason, and so on

reflect the divisions within society that try to advertise and

monopolize their dominance alongside the struggle of individuals and

institutions within this system. More collaboration, humility, and

respect for the plurality of contributions is sorely needed. The crisis

in political thinking is unfolding rapidly in an evolving world, making

rethinking foundations for political inquiry more relevant today than

ever.

Method and Content

Anarchism is not, as some may suppose, a theory of the future to be

realized through divine inspiration. It is a living force in the affairs

of our life, constantly creating new conditions. The methods of

Anarchism therefore do not comprise an iron-clad program to be carried

out under all circumstances. Methods must grow out of the economic needs

of each place and clime, and of the intellectual and temperamental

requirements of the individual. –Emma Goldman.[39]

One approach to doing politics centers on the nature of political

methods. Some radicals have proposed viewing political methodology as

the fundamental basis for politics. Within the Marxist tradition one

school of thought used methods as what defines Marxism. For example,

Karl Korsch[40] argued that:

‘Scientific socialism’ properly so-called is quite essentially the

product of the application of that mode of thought which Marx and Engels

designated as their ‘dialectical method’
 Only those who completely

overlook that Marx’s ‘proletarian dialectic’ differs essentially from

every other (metaphysical and dialectical) mode of thought, and

represents that specific mode of thought in which alone the new content

of the proletarian class views formed in the proletarian class struggle

can find a theoretical-scientific expression corresponding to its true

being; only those could get the idea that this dialectical mode of

thought, as it represents ‘only the form’ of scientific socialism,

consequently would also be ‘something peripheral and indifferent to the

matter,’ so much so that the same material content of thought could be

as well or even better expressed in another form.[41]

Since this position is about how we carry out politics altogether, it is

a metapolitical position, though one that attempts to sidestep doing

theoretical work in a way. The popularity amongst political thinkers in

discussing method and political-struggle-as-method warrants

investigations of the problem. What is method? What is content? What

relationship is there between theory and method?

Alongside issues with philosophy sits the problem of methods. Methods

are

not simply a section of theoretical issues. In their rawest form,

methods are systematic ways (and associated conceptual tools, analysis

of such, and so on) of trying to achieve something. Methods involve

steps, sequences, and instruments for carrying out practices in some

form or another. This is often obscured in metapolitical discussions of

method, which more frequently focus on hazy notions of frames,

world-views, and perspectives as methods. Hard cases make bad law, so

let’s take up more concrete notions of method.

The scientific method is one of the most tangible examples we have. In a

nutshell, the scientific method consists of research, posing a

hypothesis or something we propose in order to test it, conducting

experiments, and drawing conclusions. The parts are related, but also

related in the sense of moving through the steps in a direction. Methods

have elements of theory or concepts and elements of construction or

process. From another perspective, the scientific method is about

systematically weighing certain kinds of beliefs (scientific ones)

against their ability to predict real world events.[42] There are past

evidence, hypotheses, future experiments, and/or predictions we test

them against. Each component is related and serves to gain our object

(knowing what’s right or not). Likewise, there’s a process we go

through.

The scientific method was practiced throughout history before being

codified as the method of science. There were experiments, hypotheses,

and people went through similar steps to draw conclusions about the

world. This isn’t to say people always intuitively engaged in the

method, but people certainly formed hypotheses, conducted experiments,

and used the data as the judge of their beliefs.[43] A method then is

not only something we consciously follow or even understand, there’s

also an unconscious practical element to it that our theory of methods

tries to codify and capture.

At the same time the production of the theory of the scientific method

gave scientists further tools for doing their work. Armed with a way to

understand that work, future scientists inherited an understanding of

how to account for existing data (research) as well as future data

(experiments) in a way that can be reproduced, thus verifying

hypotheses. The theory posed a challenge; run your belief through this

course of tests, and the likelihood of it being true is high. That

common ground allowed for collaboration, evaluation, and assessing

scientific work. With set rules of the game open to all, it forms a

shared way of hashing out our beliefs not just as individuals but also

collectively. It created the backbone then not just of specific

theories, but for how science as a collective activity of humanity would

develop.

The first thing we should take from this is that theory (or philosophy)

and methods are not identical. Theories are not necessarily organized

into methods, and methods are more than just specific theories. The

scientific method was practiced in various forms before it was

theorized, systematized, or institutionalized. Likewise, methods

themselves have theoretical components. There are the steps, sequences,

relationships among the elements

(hypothesisevidence-experiments-conclusions), and importantly practices.

There’s theoretical work and there’s methodological work; related but

distinct. The scientific method commits people to theories about

evidence, experimentation, predictions, inference, time, observation,

and so on. There may be many positions compatible with a method, but it

is not theory-neutral.

Sometimes people try to argue that theory is a waste of time and that

instead we should focus on strategy and methods only (or worse, just do

what’s most immediate). It should be clear why this is a false

dichotomy. Theory is inherently a part of methods. Without reflecting on

our underlying assumptions (and theories), people tend to reproduce

uncritically the dominant schools of thought of their time. While

somewhat inevitable, accepting assumed theory robs us of tools to

critically assess our work via our methods.

The example of the scientific method clarifies what use theory can have.

By creating a method, with associated theorizing, the scientific method

was able to blossom and expand the scope of inquiry. Though any method

we might want to consider may be in existence already producing fruitful

activities, the story doesn’t end there. By creating overt methods

(through engaging in theoretical or philosophical accounts of both

existing processes and ones that we want to exist), we gain extra tools

to do what we want to do. Making things explicit lets us evaluate our

underlying assumptions, identify problems, and experiment. It gives us

more space to try new things and figure out what’s ultimately driving us

forward or holding us back.

This is all true independently of the fact that explicit theorizing

isn’t the be-all and end-all of doing good work. Method is judged not by

our conceptualization of it, but by the sum functioning of getting us

what we want. Theory has a role there, but only as a component of the

total effort. We don’t get to opt out of theory, but likewise we can’t

only do theory and believe that we have a method.

Methods for Liberation

What about methods for liberation specifically? Understanding the

differences and relationships between philosophy and methods, and their

respective uses, leads us to further questions. Radical thinkers have

often sought to cast their traditions as ultimately reflecting a

methodology of struggle rather than an ideology. Emma Goldman is one

example of this within anarchism. Goldman was an Eastern European

immigrant radicalized by her experience of life in the United States.

She came to be one of the foremost radical voices of her day for not

only anarchism, but also the liberation of women and the struggles of

workers. George Lukacs is another within Marxism. A participant in the

Hungarian insurrection, he was a one-time dissident Marxist who later

joined the officialdom, repudiated his own ideas, and ultimately became

a faithful defender of the orthodoxy of the Soviet Union. The young

Lukacs argued that Marxism was not a set of theses to implement as a

canon, but instead a method for coming to conclusions.

Orthodox Marxism
 does not imply the uncritical acceptance of the

results of Marx’s investigations. It is not the ‘belief ’ in this or

that thesis, nor the exegesis of a ‘sacred’ book. On the contrary,

orthodoxy refers exclusively to method. It is the scientific conviction

that dialectical materialism is the road to truth and that its methods

can be developed, expanded and deepened only along the lines laid down

by its founders.[44]

Since Lukacs and Goldman, many thinkers sought to elaborate and

sometimes place method at the center of radical work. Yet what does this

mean? What does such a method look like? Lukacs says such a method is

the scientific conviction—which we can only interpret to mean a belief

that is evaluated against evidence rather than faith.

Goldman’s quote at the outset of this chapter goes perhaps more deeply

in placing the implementation of the method into the context of the

people carrying it out. It varies based on the environment it is

realized in. These were ideas also raised by Errico Malatesta, the

Italian revolutionary electrician and theorist of anarchism whose

participation in the movement led him to organizing and participating in

revolts across Europe, the Americas, and Africa.[45] Malatesta took such

a position in discussing how an anarchist society would develop

economically through a series of experiments varying with local context.

Kropotkin himself argued similarly in describing the function of

anarchist society.[46]

If we understand methods to be a set of practices in sequence with

associated theoretical assumptions, there is good reason to be a skeptic

about the use of methods that are in currency amongst some radical

thinkers. For instance, consider the differences between Lukacs’ method

and those of the anarchists discussed above. Lukacs centers his ideas on

method on notions of dialectical materialism, and the teachings of its

founders. What would those steps be and how could they be understood to

follow a systematic pattern? Understanding in any usable way how

dialectics are a method to draw conclusions is notoriously obscure.

Whatever use of dialectics there is, there’s a looseness about method

being employed here.[47] Compare this to Goldman’s notions or Malatesta

conception of creating a just economy based on experimentation in a

postrevolutionary moment. The anarchist conception of method embodied

here is about implementing libertarian practice with libertarian means.

Sometimes this is partially characterized by having one’s means match

one’s ends. This is much more methodical than what Lukacs is proposing.

There are theoretical commitments (ethics, notions of practice), a

series of strategic and tactical proposals, and a method for how to

relate them across time.

There is good reason to be skeptical in general about what Lukacs calls

a method at all. If it is taken at its crudest, one would have to try to

extract sequences from dialectics. One approach would be trying to

reduce phenomena to their contradictions and look to a synthesis in some

complicated manner. Lukacs and most Marxists would likely reject this as

a crass deformation of their ideas, though it is often what the

Stalinist orthodoxy (and notably the overwhelming majority of Marxists

throughout history) tried to pass off as their dialectical science for

decades. On the other hand, a broader approach of defining the

dialectical method as looking to multi-level changing processes across

time is not a method. It’s much more of a framing for problems, or a set

of vocabulary and ways of thinking that we can use. Used in this way,

Lukacs gives us more of a theoretical perspective than a method. There’s

a laxity here about what counts as a method. A method is not simply a

way of looking at things and broad lessons to learn from. Indeed, when

most write about “a Marxist method,” they in fact do not mean a method

at all, but instead a collection of ways of framing things,

question-posing, and assumptions that have no clear methodology. In

practice this is evident. The rarity of people able to understand and

apply a dialectical or Marxist method makes its obscurity and difficulty

applying it clear.

Historically there was a strong strand of thought, determinism, that

made methods appear perhaps more important than they are. Many Marxists

and a few anarchists (such as perhaps Kropotkin) followed the belief of

the inevitability of their future society. The victory against

capitalism was seen as being secured by natural economic laws governing

society. Believing that such laws guaranteed ultimate victory led to

privileging methods both for interpreting history and in trying to act.

If historical fate secures victory, then theory as well as action are

somewhat less important than our method for understanding and proceeding

with the inherent laws that are already unfolding. Analysis (and

methodology of analysis) would have a higher place than actually trying

to solve problems and intervene since we already know the outcome.

Determinism pushes people towards passivity, since the inevitability of

victory problematizes which, if any, actions are necessary. At its worst

it provided justification for religiosity towards the actions of its

adherents, often at the same time they perpetrated great crimes of

history.[48] Today determinism has fallen out of style, perhaps in part

because of the historical failures of the Marxist-Leninist states and

the seemingly never-ending human tragedies of the 20^(th) century and

beyond (fascism, ethnic cleansing, religious and nationalism terrors,

life in the capitalist peripheries, and so on). Whatever history’s

course, it doesn’t seem to be headed step-by-step towards paradise.

Based on the previous discussion, we should be skeptical of a strong way

of interpreting those ideas in general. Anarchism for example is more

than simply a method for achieving anarchist goals. If different radical

philosophies are only methods, then they run up against the problem that

they contain within their methods underlying theories, and theories that

go beyond the steps and process of their method. The vision, goals, and

assumptions of all radical projects commit us to doing theory in one

form or another. Methodology is also important, but doesn’t allow us to

evade theory as methodology itself has its own theoretical work.

Stepping back a bit allows us to extract truths from these ideas. A more

charitable way of reading it, perhaps, is less as a way of rejecting

theory altogether (in favor of pure method), and instead that radicals

do not hold their theoretical forefathers as pure truth-bearers.

Everything is on the table. People set out from the path of their

inspiration, but the ultimate judge of the beliefs is our practices.

These impulses are broadly correct and useful. While we may not be able

to circumvent politics or theory by focusing on a pure methodology,

methods are clearly important. Against dogmas and stagnant ideologies,

looking to methods and practices gives us ways to discuss and test our

ideas in the political world. In this way, methodology-centric politics

does stress important elements of political work.

A Liberatory Method

What about a liberatory method? What would a method of liberatory

thought entail? What makes a method liberatory in the first place? A

liberatory method should contain a few key elements: the techniques and

methods, the aim and scope, and evaluations. Here libertarians have

elaborated considerable work. Tactical elements, the objects of

libertarian struggle, and truth have been explored by the tradition. Yet

explicit discussions of the method are unfortunately rare and unsettled.

First, there is the scope of the libertarian’s objectives. There is no

single theory of such, and indeed it is contested. One central theme is

that of libertarian struggle as being defined not by particular

institutions, but through the relationships of those struggling to the

power relations they are combatting or new powers being constructed.

Libertarians do not seek to rid us of injustice simply by attacking the

existing State as an institution, but rather by transforming the

relationships between those in power and those suffering the

consequences of illegitimate power. The construction of liberatory

answers is therefore based on contextual historical and regional

circumstances. Social relations of power vary, and thus particular

solutions reflect the historical, objective, and subjective features of

the problems posed. The libertarian struggle is defined by its material

circumstances, its participants, and their place in history. There is

neither a timeless central framing (good vs. evil), nor is it only

defined through central institutions like particular states or

capitalists. Noam Chomsky puts forward a definition of anarchism quite

close to this view in his introduction originally to Daniel Guerin’s

book, Anarchism:

At every stage of history our concern must be to dismantle those forms

of authority and oppression that survive from an era when they might

have been justified in terms of the need for security or survival or

economic development, but that now contribute to---rather than

alleviate---material and cultural deficit. If so, there will be no

doctrine of social change fixed for the present and future, nor even,

necessarily, a specific and unchanging concept of the goals towards

which social change should tend.[49]

Emma Goldman likewise emphasized the relativity of the application of an

anarchist method in the quote at the outset of the chapter. This isn’t

to say simply that there is a plurality of different ways anarchism

could manifest, but rather that methodology gets its life directly

through its struggles. If we think in terms of what Chomsky writes, the

method is worked out based on the oppressions and illegitimate

authorities that people seek to dismantle. The doctrine is understood

through application of the method to the reality of the rebels seeking

liberation, and not merely through attempting to codify it or imposing a

set of beliefs to a subservient reality.

Secondly, there are the actual tactics and techniques inherent to the

method that define it. Typically, anarchists focus on tactics, and

usually direct action, directly democratic assemblies, and horizontal

delegation. Using these ways of solving problems is supposed to bring us

towards the anarchist ideals. It is not simply the targets (the State,

capital, oppression, and so on), nor a decentralized and historically

rooted application. Inherent to the method itself are certain practices

that make it anarchist. There is a relationship between the ends (goals)

and the means, and the means are secured by choice of tactics. Direct

action and direct democracy are themselves thought to deconstruct

statist relationships within those struggling. Horizontal structures

begin to rebuild power relationships on an anarchist basis.

This framing of the issue is not completely right though. At the core it

seeks to express the idea that a libertarian method uses libertarian

means to libertarian ends. This connects the third piece. There is a

core set of values that helps us choose our tactics, evaluate struggles,

and analyze our situation. Yet in the second component of the method,

people often put forward structures or forms of tactics. Direct

democracy is a structure in which decisions are made, but not

necessarily the relationships or decisions of those people. Direct

action is a type of action carried out by people, but it is not

necessarily direct action to libertarian ends by people with libertarian

intentions. Direct action can also be used to different

ends—authoritarian and repressive ones like radical fascist actions.

Using libertarian means will not necessarily bring us libertarian

outcomes.

Consider when hierarchy emerges from horizontal structures. There are

many mundane examples. Formal democratic procedures don’t bar people

from dominating through other means, such as charisma, social

connections, education, or knowledge. Fascist groups use direct action

to attack immigrants, queers, and leftists. People can use informal

hierarchies and re-create bureaucracies in directly democratic councils

to dominate. Horizontal delegation can be manipulated through networks

of power, which can be utilized to carry out agendas against minorities

or even majorities. For instance, a militant racist and anti-communist

in the US military developed a concept of leaderless resistance against

a potential soviet invasion. Louis Beam, a Ku Klux Klan leader, took

this up and argued for decentralized cells organized without higher

bodies:

An alternative to the pyramid type of organization is the cell system.

In the past, many political groups (both right and left) have used the

cell system to further their objectives. Two examples will suffice.

During the American Revolution “committees of correspondence“ were

formed throughout the Thirteen colonies. Their purpose was to subvert

the government and thereby aid the cause of independence. The “Sons of

Liberty“, who made a name for themselves dumping government taxed tea

into the harbor at Boston, were the action arm of the committees of

correspondence. Each committee was a secret cell that operated totally

independently of the other cells. Information on the government was

passed from committee to committee, from colony to colony, and then

acted upon on a local basis. Yet even in these bygone days of poor

communication, of weeks to months for a letter to be delivered, the

committees without any central direction whatsoever, were remarkable

similar in tactics employed to resist government tyranny. It was, as the

first American patriots knew, totally unnecessary for anyone to give an

order for anything. Information was made available to each committee,

and each committee acted as it saw fit. A recent example of the cell

system taken from the left wing of politics are the Communists. The

Communist, in order to get around the obvious problems involved in

pyramidal organization, developed to an art the cell system. They had

numerous independent cells which operated completely isolated from one

another and particularly with no knowledge of each other, but were

orchestrated together by a central headquarters. For instance, during

World War II, in Washington, it is known that there were at least six

secret Communist cells operating at high levels in the United States

government (plus all the open Communists who were protected and promoted

by President Roosevelt), however, only one of the cells was rooted out

and destroyed. How many more actually were operating no one can say for

sure.[50]

This did not make Beam’s ideas liberatory obviously, no more than others

using decentralized organizations to authoritarian ends. While a

libertarian methodology is necessary to achieving equality and liberty,

it isn’t sufficient. Structures and forms alone don’t come with

automatic guarantees. You may utilize a libertarian method and still

produce new (or old) forms of destructive hierarchy.

Using libertarian structures certainly will help us. Direct democracy

likely minimizes potentials for authoritarian abuse. All things being

equal direct democracy is better than directives from dictators or the

aristocracy of representative structures. Direct action does have an

inherent liberatory potential as well. Acting directly means cutting out

the mediation from our lives: representatives, bureaucrats, recuperative

institutions, and so on. Yet this is different from identifying our

goals with the structures that can help us achieve those goals. What

makes something liberatory is its recognition of the capacity of people

to self-govern, implement egalitarian social relations, or whatever. The

content of our goals is served by structures, but structures and means

provide no guarantees that we will achieve them. There is another

component missing here.

This is another way to say that there is also a need for content in the

radical project of transforming society. On the skeleton of our method

and tactics, we build it up through putting the flesh of content on the

bones. Anarchism can be liberatory not only because it uses direct

democracy to achieve its ends, but also because of its ends:

organization of society’s products for all, self-organization,

cooperative labor, and a holistic development of individuals for their

own chosen ends (to give potential examples). Tactics are applied to

ends; ends aren’t automatically generated by tactics. This cuts both

ways for instance between different trends in the libertarian world:

social anarchism and insurrectionary anarchism. Militancy itself isn’t

inherently liberating, even decentralized or popular militancy.

Likewise, popular democracy can just as easily produce authoritarian

consequences as liberatory ones. There is no reason to assume that

struggles against authority towards a better social order could be

divorced from the ethical content of such aims. It is easy to forget

that libertarian means can be directed at contradictory ends, like when

people use process and spaces for their own emotional needs against the

collectivity. Without such, we rely upon either a belief in the

inevitability of our victory, or that the means themselves inherently

produce just and good outcomes. Both beliefs are false since what

produces injustice and hierarchy is not simply how they are achieved,

but also why. Part of structures and social relationships are the ideas

and goals of the people within them.

There are lessons we can extract from the exploration of methodological

thought in whatever form. First, the emphasis on the historical nature

of liberatory thought is critical. Often philosophies are thought of as

things that are contemplated, laid out, and brought back to the world to

be debated and in some manner implemented. Perhaps in other less

concrete fields this can seem more plausible, but in the social world it

is patently impossible. The issue involves both time and space.

Concepts, institutions, and actors do not remain the same across time.

People who expend their time, for example, in order to live are not the

same in every age. A slave, peasant, worker, and a subsistence farmer

all expend time for their ability to live, but the social relationships

that define their work change across the ages. This change is both

defined by the society they grow up in, and the time period they exist

in. An emphasis on understanding our ideas through method helps keep us

grounded in analyzing these factors. If we seek liberation, what does

that mean in this environment for these people with this situation and

this history?

Secondly, these accounts highlight the way in which a theory of

practices can guide us towards our aims. It is not merely getting to the

gates of power that matters, but the process and tools by which we got

there. A putsch is different from a popular uprising. The sequences of

events that produces putsches and popular uprisings have historically

meant a great deal in terms of the ability of rulers or would-be rulers

to stem the tide of popular power. And as another example: wining the

freedom of political prisoners through taking action versus it being

granted by the courts acting on a purely legal basis is different.

Process is an inherent part of liberatory politics—not merely outcomes.

Lastly, the content of our struggles combined with our methodology are

what makes struggles liberatory or not. Liberatory methods are grounded

in the conjuncture of those struggling, are based on liberatory

processes, but they also are directed at liberatory content. This

content must also be fought for, and is not contained within the fight

itself (even if it’s suggested). By honing in on content one can see

that within liberatory methods there is still a struggle for liberation.

That is, the struggle is not merely between liberatory methods and other

methods, but within libertarian struggles there are other tendencies

that lead us away from our goals. Those battles are fought largely

around content.

When past thinkers honed in on method they unearthed strong

relationships among history, aims, and tactics. This is a relevant

insight today. It is clear however that something deeper is necessary as

well. Part of the task of building a liberatory thought and practice is

elaborating a method that incorporates within it a positive content of

liberation, and harvests the material reality of its application at the

same time. Such a method connects the relationship between social forces

and our orientation as agents figuring out what to do in a constantly

changing world. The tools extracted in the course of this inquiry will

give us insights into some of the contradictions seen already: how

hierarchy can emerge from anti-hierarchy, how dispositions and

intentions relate to beliefs and desires, and where motivation fits in.

Part 2: Emergence

What is Emergence?

Emergence is a concept originally developed in the 19^(th) century by

philosophers looking at the problems of life and change. Today,

alterations in our understanding of the living and physical world are

spreading its use throughout the sciences. The social world, being a

formation of living things, also exhibits emergence, and theories of

emergence can help us understand otherwise mysterious social phenomena.

Emergence gives us a toolbox to understand and explain complex

phenomenon through familiar things from daily life like cities, bodies,

and natural phenomena. Because emergence is a feature that is familiar

and surrounds us, it can become a means of comprehending and better

communicating liberatory critiques and proposals.

Early theorists of emergence began writing about the subject in the

19^(th) century. They came from the UK primarily, though some US

thinkers also wrote on the subject.[51] John Stuart Mill was perhaps one

of the first, and with impressive brevity and clarity set out the

problem in his A System of Logic in the chapter “On the Composition of

Causes.” Mill came to emergence looking at what happens when different

forces combine. In many cases, causes simply add. In other situations,

the addition of different causes produces totally novel qualities that

are not derived from the mere addition of their parts, such as in

chemical reactions in which new substances are formed or when substances

are heated to the point at which they change states of matter. After

exploring various examples in which the combination of chemicals or

forces produces novel materials, reactions, or properties, he concludes:

As a general rule, causes in combination produce exactly the same

effects as when acting singly: but that this rule, though general, is

not universal: that in some instances, at some particular points in the

transition from separate to united action, the laws change, and an

entirely new set of effects are either added to, or take the place of,

those which arise from the separate agency of the same causes: the laws

of these new effects being again susceptible of composition, to an

indefinite extent, like the laws which they superseded.[52]

Another early theorist of emergence was G.H. Lewes, a nineteenth-century

philosopher, who tried to understand the mind and how ultimately

thoughts can arise from the physical matter of the brain. He defines

emergence in terms of the difference between the parts and the whole,

and stresses the difficulty reducing one to the other:

Every resultant is either a sum or a difference of the co-operant

forces; their sum, when their directions are the same—their difference,

when their directions are contrary. Further, every resultant is clearly

traceable in its components, because these are homogeneous and

commensurable. It is otherwise with emergents, when, instead of adding

measurable motion to measurable motion, or things of one kind to other

individuals of their kind, there is a co-operation of things of unlike

kinds. The emergent is unlike its components insofar as these are

incommensurable, and it cannot be reduced to their sum or their

difference.[53]

Note the presence of two framings of emergence here that had already

arisen in the discussion. There are the ways in which our minds are

capable of comprehending the transformation of emergent properties from

their parts, and there is the transformation itself. One way to

understand the newness or novelty of emergent things (or the more than

in the end being more than the sum of its parts) is to look at the thing

itself and another is to look at how we come to know it.

There’s a gap between the complex systems as a whole that produce

emergence and our experience of our world as organized, predictable, and

discernible. In this gap, we see different levels produce different

rules and activities. My thoughts are not chemicals, yet chemicals

produce my thoughts. A single thought, such as thinking of a goldfish

floating in a bowl, is created by the events and substance of the brain,

the nerves, and the whole organism of the human being thinking the

thought. Yet reducing that thought simply to relationships between

sodium, potassium, and chloride in neurons, for example, (if that were

possible) does not describe the thought itself. The thought has

different properties than its constitutive components. There’s a

transformation that occurs that produces thinking out of material and

chemical components. The atomic level is distinct from that of thoughts.

But where is the gap? Is it in the thinking? In the substance? What are

the new things that emerge out of their parts, yet do not resemble or

work like the parents that gave birth to them?

Within emergentist thought there has been a variety of positions. Some

philosophers have introduced a distinction that classifies different

theories as strong or weak emergence. Strong emergence involves

commitments to fundamentally new things emerging out of unlike things,

something from nothing in a sense. For something to be strongly

emergent, it isn’t just that we have trouble understanding how the

emergent thing/property/behavior arose out of its producing elements,

but also that it’s impossible to reduce it to its parts. Perhaps

counterintuitively they still have the power to causally affect lower

levels despite being fundamentally distinct. On the other hand, weak

emergence is described in terms of the models we use to understand

emergent phenomena, and the nature of our ability to follow such

processes.[54] Weak emergence is a question of knowledge or

epistemology, and strong emergence is a question of the nature of

emergent things themselves or metaphysics. Different philosophers of

emergence carve out different terrain based on how they define strong

versus weak emergence and whether they believe in one or both. Some are

committed only to weak or strong; others argue not only for weak

emergence, but also for strong emergence while connecting it to physical

causes that seek to eliminate the alleged mystery.[55]

A different position argues that these two phenomena are not

incompatible. It is possible for fundamentally new things to emerge from

unlike components in a way that is still wholly determined by a chain of

causes. The issue hinges on reducibility. Does the mind reduce to

chemical interactions or not? Ultimately can we follow the path directly

from chemical interactions to thoughts? Weak emergentists argue that,

yes, we could; we just don’t have the cognitive ability to trace it

(except perhaps by modeling artificial life that could show us such

paths).[56] Strong emergentists say emphatically no; the mind is

produced by chemicals, but there is a leap when the mind is created that

is objectively new and irreducible.[57] A third position argues that

there are different activities when looking at causes and effects and

when comparing the qualities and order of things at different levels.

Corning, for instance, tries to connect emergence to broader synergistic

effects of combinations of things throughout the world.[58] The synergy

of combinations presents new useful elements not present in the

constituting components, and this is true whether or not there are any

creatures to use or understand them. The novelty is objective (that is,

it exists outside our minds or capability of knowing things). Such

properties are measurable and observable, and yet they are still made up

of and created by more fundamental causes. The third view in one way or

another makes reference to different conceptual modes between causal

explanations (following chains of causes and events) and understanding

novelty at different levels characterized by emergence. It involves both

limits on knowledge based on our minds and fundamentally new physical

properties that emerge.

Wherever one stands in the debate, its sufficient to note the

limitations of our minds to follow such changes and the novelty of the

properties created for the purposes of the arguments here. Because of

the way that emergence happens, there is a division between reality and

our experience of it.

In one sense this is obvious. We can’t see the microscopic world with

our eyes. Artificial tools are necessary to experience or even model the

heavens above and the worlds below. While my thoughts evolve from

interactions of chemicals, it isn’t necessarily the case that we could

ever trace an individual thought to particular chemical reactions. It is

likely the case that causal chains are sufficiently complex that we

can’t follow how it evolves in particular instances.

There’s no good way to look at the popular revolt in Hungary in 1956,

for example, and explain exactly how particular individuals physically

and chemically came to the decision to take up arms against the USSR.

But they did so for reasons that are built out of that same physical

stuff on some level. Everything emergent is made of matter. However,

when you put it all together, it’s sufficiently complicated that for any

one instance we can’t say exactly how it occurred (except by larger

trends, general rules, models, and so on).

When I raise a glass to my lips, no scientific account yet can trace all

the physical and chemical reactions to produce an account of my hand

rising. More importantly, even with such a list, we wouldn’t learn very

much about that act, someone raising an arm. There is therefore a

division between our knowledge and the reality of living systems and

events therein. This creates a limitation in our knowledge and ability

to foresee how particular events may unfold both for upcoming events and

our influence on them. We may never know in any exact sense what causes

a particular protest, nor how our actions will affect the development or

death of social changes.

Likewise, the experience of the taste of salt, the shape of its

formations in the earth, the shine of its flats against the sun, and

other such emergent properties of sodium chloride are all distinct in

some sense from the chemical and physical forces that make it so. There

are the forces themselves and then the qualities of those forces in the

world. Physical things correspond to these forces and qualities, and

living things as well. Reactions occur to the uses things are put to, to

their phenomenal experience, and to their role within the actions of

living organisms. There is a practical level of explanation here that is

distinct from lower ones, and is not identical to how we explain it. The

functioning at one level is different from that at another. Salt in my

body is on another plane in some way from the electrons and neutrons

that make it up.[59]

Emergence isn’t magic; something does not come from nothing. Nor is it

random or disorganized. Emergence is systematic. Certain properties of

systems produce emergent things in discreet processes. The science of

emergence is to understand and model the functioning of such systems,

and explain the processes and rules governing emergence. Any deeper

understanding of the way that things emerge takes us into the territory

of complexity—systems that exhibit very unique properties in the natural

world.

The Mystery of Political Events: The Problem of Emergence

Action is at the center of social thought, particularly when viewed

through an ethical or political lens. We approach the world as beings

that feel, perceive, weigh, decide, and chose courses of action.

Likewise, things beyond our choosing act upon us. Society is built from

a multiplicity of interwoven forces, events, causes, and responses.

Faced with this, we choose how to act while limited by our objective

situation. In a messy world with limited possibilities, questions about

how to proceed ethically and bring about the best outcomes perpetually

arise.

Within the political realm, a number of cases are troubling. For

instance, many movements for human liberation contribute to catastrophic

disasters and, worse, end up setting back freedom and wellbeing for

decades. As discussed in the preceding chapter, struggles against

hierarchy can produce new hierarchies; libertarian methods can produce

authoritarian structures. Many of the 20^(th) century’s revolutions (at

certain points in their trajectories) seem to have had this character.

Whole sections of the socialist movement helped mobilize Europe for the

First World War and popular revolts contributed to creating the

repressive world of the official Marxist-Leninist countries (Russia,

China, Vietnam, Cuba, and so on) that strangled their peoples for nearly

a century (and a few still continue to do so today). Oppressive

hierarchies and injustices repeatedly emerge from otherwise liberatory

and non-hierarchical efforts.

Indeed, many dramatic political events appear to have come out of

nowhere, even when we know they do not. Riots, revolutions, crises, and

coups are clearly the product of countless actions of individuals. But

when they occur, they often don’t seem that way. The singularity of

historical events, their apparent uniqueness, can make the actions of

individuals and groups appear strange and almost magical. This is more

acute with dramatic events, but equally present in our daily lives and

social existence. From the perspectives of people committed to changing

society, such quandaries are even more troubling. Actions have force;

they change things. Yet it is nearly impossible to trace the force of

those acts in practice. History rolls along either in spite of our

actions or disproportionately explodes because of them.

It is here that the structure of the most fundamental political disputes

gets laid. There is a gulf between behavior on a gross social level

(with associated forces, structures, powers, and entities) and the

actions of agents within those systems. Our experiences and ideas about

how our actions affect the world seem to depart from how political

events often unfold and respond to our actions. Strangely, political

thought has often been only glancing, or worse silent, on these issues.

There’s a gap that needs to be fleshed out. The world of agents is

connected physically and conceptually to the world of social forces. Yet

how? Where do the reasoning, problems, and interventions of people come

into contact and separate from, or where are they even born within those

large scale social forces that are so evident in our lives? Such a gap

lies beneath political theory in its philosophical and metatheoretical

groundings—the structures upon which all of our social thinking rests.

This problem, connecting the worlds of agency and emergent social

forces, is a political question because it speaks to the attempts of

individuals and groups to find ways to alter the course of history

through their actions. Looking at it another way, it is simply to

explore how our actions can positively affect efforts towards a

liberatory society given the immense and unpredictable powers that seem

beyond our grasp and defy prediction.

How does a riot happen? Or how did the financial crisis which began at

the end of the first decade of the millennium come to be? What reality

is there behind the mythology of the Great Men of history? Did a small

handful of armed guerrillas in the mountains really overtake Cuba? Did

Hitler conquer Germany? How was Russia brought under the tyranny of the

Stalinist bureaucracy? Hierarchy emerging from non-hierarchy, apparently

spontaneous events, disproportionate influences of actions on the course

of history, the impossibly complex ping-ponging of individuals’ actions

in creating riots and revolts, and power which takes on a life of its

own, these phenomena need explanations and interventions. If we were

able to connect societal functioning to the world of actors

systematically, a foundation could be constructed to approach these

problems. In our new century such issues have become too present to not

take up in light of the events of Egypt, Tunisia, Latin America, and

Occupy, the disruptions in China and India, or even worker unrest in the

United States. Each month the political landscape shifts, revealing

slowly a changing world and unfamiliar environment for those who seek

the transformation of society.

This series of problems is connected by key characteristics and

relationships. The events are more than the sum of their parts. New

things appear that do not share the traits of the actions, parts, and

structures that produced them. It is this coming out from that will take

up the course of this work and lead us through biology, power, agency,

and cognition. This is the problem of emergence.

Living Systems

Emergence is a product of systems that exhibit forms of complexity. In

fact, one definition of complex systems is that they are systems in

which agents or elements interact in a way that produces emergence.

Complexity itself, and the systems that exhibit it, would require a

whole book for full exploration. Instead, we will look at what some of

the notable features of complex systems are, and specifically those that

contribute to our understanding of agency and events in the political

world of societies. Such systems exist in a range of domains: raw

physical forces, astronomy, biology, and psychological, chemical, and

social systems. We find emergent behavior in the interaction of forces

within subatomic particles, large scale interactions of planetary

systems and galaxies; we also find emergent forces within weather like

hurricanes, geologic phenomena like earthquakes, and so on. Non-living

non-rational systems can produce emergent forces as real as the fury of

a tornado, and out of chaos produce reliable orderly large-scale

emergent events.

If we look ahead to the exploration of social emergence, the treatment

of these non-living systems will be limited. Though they are no less

examples of emergence and there is a great deal to learn from there, the

primary task will be understanding the living systems that produce

emergence. This is because living systems are most closely linked to

social systems to the point that one could reasonably ask whether a

distinction between living and social systems is even worthwhile. More

importantly as politics agents, we have a setting off point within the

living world. Our perspective and framework derive from such systems,

and it is the characteristics of those systems that give us the tools to

gain deeper insights into the politics of emergence.

A Living World

We inhabit a living biological world. Our bodies, environment, social

world, and cities all exist and evolve either as or because of living

organisms. There’s something special about the way living things work.

Living organisms and systems change and develop new capabilities over

time (evolution and adaptation). Through the march of time, life takes

on new properties to survive and adapt to its environment. Our planet

has some amazing examples of this like bacteria that developed to live

within volcanoes or that survive within nuclear waste, or even the

coconut palm, which developed the ability to travel across the seas with

its seeds to find new shores to grow upon. Living things and systems are

able to respond to and create new situations based on their environment

and neighboring life. Trees shed leaves to survive the winter; people

gain immunity to diseases through exposure; and streams of traffic keep

moving around accidents that block their course.

Most importantly, living things are emergent. New properties emerge out

of the organization of their parts (organs, cells, and units). In a

basic sense, a living adapting organism is the most obvious example of

emergence. Out of countless chemical/physical events and reactions, a

more highly organized entity emerges—life. Life constructs larger

structures though; organisms join together; they struggle, co-evolve,

form ecosystems, make war, and cooperate. Life selforganizes forests,

cities, and our whole planet. Living organisms are systems, but they

also build larger scale systems through their actions. The world itself

as we experience it is an emergent product of the interaction of

countless living organisms bound together in vast networks of systems.

The connection between biology and emergence traces back to at least to

Darwin, who proposed a process of natural selection in which traits were

(somehow) promoted or inhibited across time, which led to adaptations to

increase survival or the flourishing of a species. It’s easy to

misunderstand how this works in practice. Darwin did not mean to imply

that this principle applied to individuals per se. Given the complexity

of biological systems, many living things may happen to survive while

others more adapted to survival can die. Darwin wrote:

It may be well here to remark that with all beings there must be much

fortuitous destruction, which can have little or no influence on the

course of natural selection. For instance, a vast number of eggs or

seeds are annually devoured, and these could be modified through natural

selection only if they varied in some manner which protected them from

their enemies. Yet many of these eggs or seeds would perhaps, if not

destroyed, have yielded individuals better adapted to their conditions

of life than any of those which happened to survive. So again a vast

number of mature animals and plants, whether or not they be the best

adapted to their conditions, must be annually destroyed by accidental

causes, which would not be in the least degree mitigated by certain

changes of structure or constitution which would in other ways be

beneficial to the species.[60]

It is only when we look at broader statistical trends that the evolution

of the species can be said to take place.[61] Within the lives of

particular individuals, a number of other factors (being in the right

time or the right place for instance) may end up determining their

personal circumstances of survival, health, and proliferation. At a

higher level of biologic organization and over time, patterns of

emergent biological orders evolve.

From the Biological World to Emergence

To understand a living systems approach to anything social (let alone

struggles and movements), we must first understand the nature and

functioning of such systems. First, those things are living or have

life, and second they exist in systems. A definition of life itself is a

well-worn philosophical battleground. Whatever it is that makes

something alive versus inanimate, living things are more than a list of

their chemical facts. They are higher-level organizations of chemical

components that exhibit all the things we know living things to do.[62]

Defining a system is equally treacherous and would represent another

detour from our road. Roughly, living systems are organized; they have

things (living and non-living) in interconnected relationships; and they

have properties and behavior specific to their arrangement. Apart from

the philosophical and scientific jargon, living systems are organized

groupings of a particular kind. In the following discussion, we’ll get a

sense of the types of things that living systems do, and in the process

better understand life and systems.

One of the hallmarks of our experience as humans is that our world is

ordered, organized into levels. This is to say that biological and

social reality isn’t flat like a plate where everything is laid out next

to each other. Instead there are worlds of atoms, worlds of chemicals,

worlds of cells, creatures, eco-systems, and galaxies. There is the

level of the creatures and plants in an area, and then the level of the

forest itself. There is our settlement, and then the mountain range we

live in. The body has organs. Within organs are cells, organelles,

enzymes, chemicals, and so on. Society has individuals, groups,

formations, structures, etc. As time rolls on, the levels change and

affect one another; new levels emerge and others crumble. The world of

living systems is the world of organisms, bodies, minds, ecosystems,

bioregions, and societies.

What happens at different levels is organized. For example, DNA is the

hallmark of life as we know it. Biologists now have sophisticated

knowledge of how DNA is transcribed and replicated, and how it produces

proteins within the cells that make most of the behavior of living

organisms possible. When we talk about cells, we can talk about the

order of DNA, proteins, membranes, and so on. There are rules of how DNA

functions in cells, how cells work, the role of the specific enzymes or

proteins, and so on. These rules and behaviors are consistent,

regulated, and predictable. But these are not identical universal rules

that apply willy-nilly everywhere at all levels and at any time. Though

my arm runs on the power of DNA, we have different concepts and order

for my arm than for one cell in my arm. We could look at DNA forever,

but it would not tell you about why dancers move the way they do. Dance

is made possible by the activity of DNA, yet DNA’s organization and that

of dancing are different. The rules in each domain are distinct.

A Single Spark Can Light a Prairie Fire

Higher levels are generated by lower levels, and yet the path is not

evident. This is because the individual pieces are hard to separate, and

because of the complexity of interactions among the pieces. How do all

the cells in the arm of a dancer add up to a graceful or clumsy

maneuver? Feedback is an integral concept to understanding living

systems. Things don’t happen in isolation in bodies, ecosystems,

societies, or worlds. They occur in the context of infinite other acting

entities that are all responding to the changes around them.

For example, for every chemical reaction in each individual cell, nearly

every other cell responds in one way or another through hormones,

intercellular signaling, consumption and generation of energy, and so

on. Take oxygen. Cells use oxygen in their basic functioning. Cells use

up oxygen in making energy, and produce carbon dioxide as a byproduct.

Oxygen is breathed in; carbon dioxide is breathed out. Oxygen and carbon

dioxide can build up in the bloodstream of animals in various

proportions. As each cell is consuming and producing oxygen and carbon

dioxide, there is a balance in the blood. Too much carbon dioxide in the

blood causes a chain of reactions telling the cells to slow down, use

less oxygen, and produce less carbon dioxide. With each change in

direction, every other cell in the body is affected in one way or

another, though obviously some more than others. The actions of each

cell resonates with all others in essence. It is like a web in which

pulling one strand pulls on every other strand.

For even the simplest event like lifting a can with my hand, the sheer

number of chemical reactions and atomic movements, as well as all the

physical forces involved, are overwhelming. Imagine that I could name

every chemical and every event in all the cells of my arm (which would

be in effect infeasible because of the sheer number of cells, reactions,

complexity, and so on). It would be impossible in practice to trace

exactly how my arm moved. A full explanation of a single movement would

involve all the reactions and occurrences in cells and components that

play a role. Yet, if all cells are being inherently affected by each

other, responding to each other, and sending signals to one another,

then in every event, such as a motion, countless cells and causes would

be involved. Looking to the oxygen example, we see that in living

systems causes are tied together. Individual units are inherently bound

up to the goings on of all the other units linked to them in systems.

All their actions are in feedback with one another. The contribution of

individuals must be described in relation to others because all causes

are inherently linked. They refer to one another to the point that their

actions are mutually referential.

Think about a crowd in a frenzy, perhaps if there’s a fire in a

building. If we want to trace the paths of all individuals trying to

escape, we can simply look at how they move (their intentions, paths,

abilities, and so on). As each person moves (causes motion), every other

person in the crowd reacts to a degree and moves as well, though to

greater or lesser degrees based on their distances to one and another,

the chairs and exits in their way, and so on). That movement influences

everyone else around: if someone turns in front of me my path is blocked

and I move right, thereby altering the course of those behind and to the

right of me, and so on. This is feedback—the echoing, amplification, and

mutual resonance of causes in a complex system. One special hallmark of

living systems then is that the behavior of any individual or component

cannot easily be understood to act without looking to a greater system

of causes. Though this seems intuitive in a sense, it goes against our

experience of the world. As individuals in crowds, we often do not

perceive our own path as inherently intertwined with that of the crowd

as a system. We perceive it as arising from our will, and perhaps feel

frustrated by people who stand in our way.

The Identity of Individuals

Looking at the complex web of causes behind my arm moving raises

additional problems. What causes are my own causes that make my arm

move? Is it merely my will or my muscles, or does it include the gases

and forces that my arm moves through, or the compounds that fuel its

movement? We cannot only look at people to understand their actions, but

rather we also need to see the complete environment in which actions

take place. In the world of individuals and causes, separating the agent

out is, in practice, difficult. This is because biological entities are

historical, and have both an individual developmental story and a

collective one connected to countless other life forms.[63]

That history is not monodirectional. The story of each living thing is

constantly itself contributing to the vast changes swirling around us at

all time, and being redefined by all the others it is in constant

connection with, and which indeed make up its being despite being in

some sense separate. There are all the living organisms inside me, on my

skin, and in the air, the energy around me, the forces of physics, the

energy my body creates and absorbs, and so on. Bacteria live on my skin,

in my gut, and throughout my body. Without them I could not survive,

even while we normally would not include them as a part of ourselves.

When the food I eat is digested and sustains me—we tend to think that we

do it. What about the myriad of organisms involved? Is the bacteria part

of me? Is it separate? In what sense is the digestion mine? Two things

are true: there is something that is me that is digesting, and there is

a whole world of causes and effects apart from me occurring. In living

systems those relationships are nearly impossible to pull apart.

Take the example of mitochondria, the energy factory of cells.

Mitochondria exist within cells and help them do what they need to do.

Mitochondria have distinct DNA from the rest of your cells (i.e. nuclear

DNA, what most people mean by saying DNA). The striking resemblance of

mitochondria (in terms of their DNA and organization) to bacteria led

scientists to hypothesize that they are an adaptation of internalized

bacteria (to simplify things) that was beneficial along the way. At some

stage in evolution, bacteria likely made it inside the cell and

co-evolved to play a functional role within the cell. We now consider

mitochondria to be a part of us, a component of our cells.

The divisions between our environment, things alongside us, things in

cohabitation with us, and parts of us are much blurrier than we believe.

Rather than discovering clear lines of what is internal versus external,

part of us versus environmental, in reality we are finding changing and

adapting interactions between individual components and environment. The

degree of interaction is so vast and complex that distinguishing among

the contributions of individual components and their effects, as well as

borders between elements that are neither fixed nor easily identifiable,

becomes for practical purposes impossible. That is, not only does

complexity make it difficult to trace the path of causation between

lower and higher levels in living systems (like our bodies), but also

the divisions between the components themselves are often unclear.

Disproportionate Effect

This state of feedback is not only characterized by mutual influences,

but also by dramatic causes. Normally, when we combine things, you can

say that we add them. Simplifying for the purpose of argument, if I use

5 lbs. of strength, I could push a 1-lb. object a given distance. If I

use 10 lbs. of strength, I could push the same object double the

distance. The relationship between the increase of force I use produces

a proportional increase in effect; the distance is increased by the same

measure. In emergence, it doesn’t work like that.[64]

A popular metaphor for this is a butterfly flapping its wings in South

America, causing a tsunami in Japan. The butterfly’s wings do this

because they help initiate a series of events that have much greater

power than itself. The example of the butterfly is actually a distortion

because it abstracts the way in which the butterfly is merely a single

link in a chain. The butterfly flaps its wings and flies upon the winds

caused by temperatures, lakes, oceans, and currents. Other wings,

machinery, factories, mountains, and so on shape the air that moves the

butterfly. In turn the butterfly has an effect upon the air it flies

upon. The air is systematically connected to waters, such as seas, which

respond to temperature, force, and shifts in the airs above. Butterflies

flying cannot be extracted from all the forces of nature, living things,

and interactions of the systems they exist in. In this way then in

theory the flapping of the butterfly’s wings could initiate a series of

events that cause a tsunami.

Taking another example, think of someone applying force on a bicycle.

Weather is a complex system that can produce unpredictable events like

large gusts. In the broader system including the environment and all the

forces moving a cyclist, a random rapid gust can make the cyclist’s

application of force to the pedals have a disproportionate effect by

changing the action’s relationship to motion through air. This is an

extreme example, but it illustrates the ways in which in such systems

causes can be amplified dramatically, and even take on new

characteristics in light of the strength of response.

Like the disproportionate power of the butterfly’s wings flapping,

complex (living) systems exhibit what can be called nonlinear causation.

It’s nonlinear because what happens isn’t a straight line of actions

with equal and proportional response like dominos falling in a row, but

instead even small causes like butterfly wings can have disproportionate

power. Social disruptions are the perfect example of this, as simple

events can set off a rapid and dramatic chain of events. For example, in

2011 when Mohamed Bouazizi, a street vendor in Tunisia, set himself on

fire, it contributed to subsequent protests in ways that went well

beyond the act itself. The symbol of the vendor’s suffering, his

suicide, mobilized other forces in a disproportionate way, spreading the

fires of resistance well beyond the single act of defiance. In a system

in which parts are systemically interrelated, causes don’t occur in

isolation, but instead ricochet and amplify each other. This isn’t to

say that the suicide caused the protests throughout Tunisia. Instead,

its effect was disproportionate because of its occurrence within a

complex system that overall produced an emergent event, the ruptures of

2011. The focus of media on the event itself in some ways shows how

complex systems work since it is the salience of the act of protest that

is so important to us and not the conditions that allowed the act to

have whatever resonance it may have had.

Both feedback and nonlinear causation make single acts difficult to

trace. In a hurricane it would be hard to tell what caused any

individual object flying through the air to take flight. If I had not

pushed the weight, would it have spontaneously taken to flight anyway?

What interactions with other flying objects, currents, reflection of

winds off buildings, and so on are relevant? This disconnect occurs

between the different levels of organization. We can’t follow the chain

from chemicals to motion, or from individuals to a riot. It requires a

different level of explanation, which our minds at least cannot trace

from lists of chemical facts. There is a shift from one level of

explanation to the other that escapes our way of thinking. The

complexity and interconnectedness of causes makes analyzing them

difficult in such systems.

Levels and Properties

These systems then have forms of interconnectedness in which the pieces

are mutually defined, produce effects in a broad system of interrelated

causes, and do so in ways that make them challenging to parse for our

minds. Within this complex web of relationships there are organized

levels like we discussed. There are chemicals, cellular components,

cells, organs, and bodies. Importantly, the levels don’t merely differ

by scale. Cells don’t look like bodies and bodies don’t look like cells

(except when you go back down to the level of cells). At different

levels, new elements emerge. Emergence is made possible by the different

levels of organization by complex systems. Take a very simple example,

salt. When sodium and chlorine combine, they create a familiar compound:

salt. Salt has properties that neither sodium nor chlorine has—the

tastes of salt, its formation of crystals, and so on. Sodium is a

silvery-white very reactive explosive metal. Chlorine is a pale yellow

gas. Salt is a stable, innocuous compound unlike its dangerous parents,

sodium and chloride.

The new properties of salt are caused by the atomic properties of its

components (sodium and chlorine). Yet the properties of the new thing

are not described by just putting them together. The effect, salt, is

more than the sum of its parts. Whatever way we look at it, the metallic

and gaseous properties of sodium and chlorine don’t add up to salty

properties. However the combination occurs, it ends up producing

something fundamentally different. Thus with emergence there are new

things that emerge from lower levels, and the properties that emerge are

more than simply the sum of the properties of their lower level

components.[65]

Emergence, then, is a theory of organization and existence across time.

Chemicals interacting over time create compounds. Cells replicating and

dividing grow until a baby is created (with a lot of work along the

way). Out of the chaos of heat and pressure over a time period, a highly

ordered diamond forms from carbon. Living systems are merely a more

particular case of these, as are social systems within living systems.

Representative government evolves alongside emergent forces of wealth

and power that interact to try and wrest more and more control over the

forces of the State from other powers and the citizenry. In complex

adaptive systems, there are ordered or organized interrelationships

among components in the whole that act together to produce new events,

structures, or properties.

Stability and Disruption

This world is not simply chaos, however. Systemic order also exists. New

things do not emerge without organization. New things emerging and

causing transformations in massively complex chains may seem mysterious.

This is actually counterintuitive since it doesn’t feel that way. We

walk on the ground and eat food regularly because of the stability of

our world, not because of its chaos. We can rely upon the sun rising,

rivers flowing to the seas, and people behaving largely in a regular

fashion. Every day the efforts of billions of people deliver food,

medicine, energy, and goods to people all over the world with remarkable

regularity. The order itself is emergent, the product of countless

interactions of pieces in a systemic whole.

Living systems in general (though not only living systems) are

selforganizing. Self-organization means that they are able to respond as

a system with ordered internal behavior. Consider body temperature in

mammals. The environmental temperature fluctuates, but the

self-organizing system of the mammalian body maintains a stable body

temperature throughout. The body emergently produces consistency through

the interaction of all the heat-bearing and heat-shedding activities of

the cells, ingestion of compounds, sweating, cool/heat-seeking behavior,

and so on. Living systems then can respond in an ordered fashion to

neighboring causes (such as when our bodies respond to infections), and

over time tend to evolve. On a short timescale, they adapt. As we

reproduce, as all living systems do, the offspring respond to their

environment and traits are promoted or inhibited in an ongoing cycle of

reproduction over time. On a longer timescale, they evolve. Species

develop abilities that allow them to thrive in their environment and

pass on mutations to their offspring.

Within the organization of these systems, there are varying degrees of

stability. Just as laws operate at different levels (like DNA behaving

predictably), stability too emerges in systems. Ecosystems are a vivid

example of this. Out of the chaos of the innumerable parts of the

forest, a relatively stable order emerges in which all the creatures and

plants are connected and evolve alongside one another. A forest often

can be a forest for thousands of years without gross disruptions,

absorbing damage from even landslides, volcanoes, or hurricanes.

Still, it would be a mistake to see equilibrium as timeless because our

world is alive; equilibriums occur, grow, change, and also break down;

mass extinctions occur; forests die; seas grow and retreat; asteroids

destroy regions; new forms of life evolve that colonize novel areas. In

society, regimes fall; empires last a thousand years before collapsing;

slavery is destroyed and resurrected; revolutions lay waste to

everything people thought about governments and economies. Living

systems grow, stabilize, die, and give birth to new offspring,

ecosystems, and orders.

A body when ill begins to lose its order. If bacteria can spread

throughout the body, the body loses its ability to self-regulate,

disease may set in, and the results are potentially fatal. Chemicals run

wild opening veins, temperatures increase, organs become damaged through

loss of blood, and toxins from bacteria corrode living tissue. These

systems then have equilibrium, which can vary. When stability or

equilibrium decreases, disorder increases and space emerges for new

orders to reproduce and spread.

Social Emergence

The social world is a world of emergence. Two people exchanging crops

from their back yards exhibit a social relationship of exchange. Similar

exchanges on a global scale create emergent forces of markets whose

effects are grossly distinct from simple one-to-one exchanges of

surpluses amongst neighbors. Individuals owning property create forces

within society of vested interests that create laws, attack other

forces, anticipate challengers, and act nearly as organisms within a

field of other emergent organisms. The interactions of individuals

create such forces, but the forces themselves exhibit behavior distinct

from individuals.

Emergence then is a potential tool for understanding how societies and

social organizations develop, unfold, and change. In a cell, all the

enzymes, DNA, RNA, organelles, and so on systematically interact to make

things happen. You can’t understand anything that happens in a cell

except in reference to the totality of causes, or at least a rather

complicated chain of chemicals and structures. Society is the same.

Let’s take a series of examples.

Earlier we discussed the path of people fleeing a fire. Traffic is a

ready phenomenon that shows emergence in societies. From pedestrian

traffic to the great flows of the world’s cities, the movement of people

within complex adaptive transit systems exhibit the behavior of living

systems. Traffic jams can be disproportionately caused by small actions

by one or two individuals, such as in a crash. Slow traffic causes large

shifts in the system, rerouting many people, changing the behavior of

drivers, and unfurling countless events in the lives of those traveling

and awaiting those traveling across cities.

Another obvious case is the growth and change of cities themselves. Far

from growing linearly bit-by-bit, cities evolve in an emergent fashion.

Urban decay of neighborhoods or the boom of fashionable areas emerge out

of innumerable changes happening in the homes, businesses, and streets

of their areas. Those changes themselves are intimately connected to

larger shifts in society, which are affected by the evolution of the

neighborhoods and their residents. Neighborhoods can expand and decay

explosively, though gradual change is more common.

People act and develop in ways that aren’t simply the sum of

perspectives or actions of the individuals involved. A common example of

this is mob mentality, when crowds behave differently from how people

normally would on their own in some sense. When combined into social

groups, individuals become generators of emergent powers and behaviors

that do not directly reflect their routine mental states or even

actions. A mob is simply a different kind of entity than the people who

are swept up into it, though obviously the people create the mob. The

law reflects these different perspectives as well. There are different

crimes and sentences for rioting, the acts of property destruction or

violence associated with it, and inciting to riot. This is part of an

attempt to segregate components of the emergent force that comes into

motion, its causes, and manners of participation.

All of human life in societies exhibit emergence. The most mundane facts

and changes can be viewed in a new light once we grasp the influence of

living systems and their emergence within our lives. Though this is

clear with the mundane, it’s more profound when we look at the political

world. Social organizations of power, and events contesting that power,

also lie within the realm of emergence.

Though often people fixate on the power of the media, we see examples of

emergent phenomena with governments, elections, and “popular support.”

Consider the evolution of the victor in elections. The end results of

votes can differ from opinion polling, visible activity in the streets,

and even established methods of advertising, funding, and hype. This

isn’t only because governments and capitalists attempt to socially

engineer legitimacy and support, but also because of the ping-ponging of

people’s views, actions, and social groups. Whether or not people think

a candidate is winning or not influences their likelihood to show their

support and mobilize. The sense of a candidate’s likely victory is

complexly produced, not from a single organ like the media, but rather

from a multiplicity of factors throughout society. This is infamously

fickle, including factors such as weather on voting day, positioning

within the ballot, physical appearances, and so on.

Popular opinion has an emergent character that can resist even massive

attempts to socially engineer the public’s thinking. Politicians have

repeatedly attacked social security and utilized corporate media to try

to assault the vast popularity for the program. Despite such attempts,

popular opinion continues to strongly support maintaining and even

expanding social security, and that support alone is sufficient to stave

off further attacks. This is true even without any major public force

protecting or advocating for social security (perhaps until recently).

Institutional liberal organizations in the past were content to accept

market reforms alongside a trimmed-down social safety net, something

that remains unpopular, leaving public opinion without an advocate.[66]

It is the emergent force of popular will here that poses a threat to

established power, and that will is created not only through the organs

of ruling powers (media, schools, think-tanks, organizations, and so

on), but also through the complex interaction of individuals throughout

society. In this case, power was unable to impose its will on a system

that continues to reproduce emergent counter-powers against austerity of

that kind.

Today social scientists have begun exploring the impact of emergence in

their fields.[67] Complex systems and emergence present narratives of

social structure and behavior that link individual psychology and

biology, while contributing explanations of how social structure

functions in line with more basic natural phenomena. Viewing society and

social structures through the prism of living systems and emergence also

raises questions for those who seek social liberation. These concepts

reflect the divisions in both our experience of the world (as thinking

agents trying to respond from our own perspective to others and forces

greater than ourselves) and the emergent orders that govern everything

that are beyond any of us. If things like states, movements,

institutions, rights, freedoms, work, and slavery are emergent, then

what questions does it raise about how things came to be the way they

are? What other ways of being are possible?

Most importantly, how could we change what shouldn’t be?

Revolutionaries and Emergence: Prelude to a Politics

Emergence is not only a tool of knowledge, but also one of action. The

specific properties of living systems have implications suggestive of

directions for struggle and show the limits of others. An understanding

of social systems and emergence can unify seemingly disparate social

categories. It gives us a foundation for critical thought and practice

when applied to the social world.

Yet despite years of work by scientists and philosophers, the

application of this work to a critical politics is rare. Bringing an

emergence perspective to social struggles is work that must be carried

out in the coming years. The connection of large-scale political

questions like the nature of the State, capitalism, and hierarchical

oppression are clear examples of places where emergence can inform our

understanding and potentially transform our practices. What is the

essence of the State? How does it reproduce itself? How can the State be

overcome?

We have a general framework for understanding emergence and a direction

to approaching social problems. The task of working through the specific

problems is up to those of us active in taking up emergence. Addressing

things like the State, capitalism, patriarchy, and so on is beyond the

scope of this text and in some ways would distract from laying out

emergence as a means to take a variety of positions on those

issues—emergence as a metapolitical tool.

Interestingly, anarchist thought had from its outset deep emergentist

currents within. This isn’t to say that other theories were not present;

some adopted dialectical or other alternatives of their day, but

anarchism was unique amongst modern social movements for developing

independent ideas about emergence in an environment in which such ideas

were both uncommon and largely unexplored. Explicit discussion of

emergence in the anarchist literature is uncommon, but the general

approach is clear enough if you look throughout the tradition—something

that should be celebrated and highlighted.

Two of the heavyweights of libertarian thought came to anarchism in part

due to their scientific research. Peter Kropotkin became an anarchist

partly due to his work as an evolutionary biologist. He is widely

recognized for his foundational work on the role of cooperation and

mutual aid in evolution.[68] Kropotkin’s ideas about emergence are

clearest in his biological writings and within his political work in

which he speaks of nature and evolution. There is a clear connection

between those ideas and his political proposals, but it is one that has

not been made explicit frequently. Graham Purchase did so and

demonstrates Kropotkin’s anticipation of emergence and complexity theory

in his PhD thesis about Kropotkin’s thought.[69]

Elisée Reclus, a contemporary of Kropotkin, veteran of the Paris

Commune, and militant anarchist, is famed as one of the founders of

modern geography. Reclus describes in his writings on the natural world

how order emerges from complex interaction between innumerable elements,

and ties this to how order can emerge from the base up in anarchist

society and the struggle against the State and capitalism. In his

chapter, “The Distribution of Human Population,” from Man and the Earth,

he presents a view of human societies as coevolving with their

environment and producing emergent organisms out of their activity and

adaptation. His concept of geography, surely one of the earliest such

approaches in modern European traditions, is on display when he argues

that “(e)very new city immediately constitutes, by its configuration of

dwellings, a collective organism. Each cell seeks to develop in perfect

health, as is necessary for the health of the whole. History

demonstrates that sickness is no respecter of persons; the palace is in

danger when the plague rages through the slums.”’[70] His geography is

embedded with a picture of human (and ecological) life viewed through

the prism of living systems (microcosms) that interact to form emergent

structures with their own separate properties.

The earliest groupings are microcosmic, and then they become more and

more extended and complex over time, to the degree that an ideal arises

and becomes more difficult to achieve. Each of these small societies

constitutes by nature an independent and self-sufficient organism.

However, none of them are completely closed, except for those that are

isolated on islands, peninsulas, or in mountain cirques whose access has

been cut off. As groups of men encounter one and another, direct and

indirect relations arise. In this way, following internal changes and

external events, each swarm ends its particular, individual evolution

and joins willingly or forcibly with another body politic so that both

are integrated into a superior organization with a new course of life

and of progress before it.[71]

It was not only the scientists amongst the anarchists who came to

emergence. Pierre Proudhon, the French socialist and member of the First

International Workingmen’s Association, was an important early thinker

of the anarchist movement. He influenced key figures, such as Bakunin,

Kropotkin, and Reclus, though he held important differences with the

collectivist and communist forms of anarchism that developed thereafter

by preferring cooperatives and a people’s bank in what he called

mutualism. Laying out his theory of power, Proudhon argued that there

are specifically collective forms of power that are not reducible to

individuals who constitute them.

It is not only individuals that are endowed with force; collectivities

also have theirs. To speak here only of human collectivities, let us

suppose that the individuals, in such numbers as one might wish, in

whatever manner and to whatever end, group their forces: the resultant

of these agglomerated forces, which must not be confused with their sum,

constitutes the force or power of the group
 Collective force being a

fact as positive as individual force, the first perfectly distinct from

the second, collective beings are as much realities as individual

ones.[72]

This argument may seem out of place or extraneous except that Proudhon

then immediately uses the concept of emergent powers to construct his

critique of the State, a topic we will return to. Likewise, he

understood that the issue of our knowledge of emergence was a key factor

in disguising the functioning of social systems. “Social power,

inaccessible to the senses in spite of its reality, seemed to the first

men an emanation of the divine Being, for this reason the worthy object

of their religion
 Even today, the economists have barely identified the

collective force.”[73] Nor did he believe that emergence was produced in

a unidirectional manner of individuals creating higher-level

organization, as can be seen when he argued that “(t)hrough the grouping

of individual forces, and through the relation of the groups, the whole

nation forms one body: it is a real being, of a higher order, whose

movement implicates the existence and fortune of everyone. The

individual is immersed in society; he emerges from this great power,

from which he would separate only to fall into nothingness.”[74] Here

the individual is seen both as a product of society and an element

producing the society shaping her at the same time. Proudhon clearly

elaborates the novel aspects of emergent social forms, and connects them

to the individual with all the political implications of the view at the

center of his thinking around the State and even his economic ideas.

It’s safe to say that this aspect of his contribution is not well

recognized, and though his ideas on emergence are not fully developed,

he is one of the few thinkers both to utilize that framework and to

connect it to his critique of capitalism and the potential of liberatory

society.

Anarchist thinking around emergence was not limited to describing

nature, but rather it was also integral to an understanding of power and

the capacity of groups for their own liberation. Rudolph Rocker, the

German union organizer and theorist of anarcho-syndicalism, elaborates

an emergence approach to how radicals attempt to sort out history and

courses of action. Criticizing the Marxian view of history as determined

purely by economic forces, he wrote:

There is scarcely an historical event to whose shaping economic causes

have not contributed, but economic forces are not the only motive powers

which have set everything else in motion. All social phenomena are the

result of a series of various causes, in most cases so inwardly related

that it is quite impossible clearly to separate one from the other. We

are always dealing with the interplay of various causes which, as a

rule, can be clearly recognized but cannot be calculated according to

scientific methods.[75]

More recently, Graham Purchase developed a unique ecological critique

based on complexity and chaos theory. He posits a natural order that is

stifled when the emergent order of society is constrained through

centralized of dominating minorities. Starting in the 1980s, he

connected the potential for climate crisis to capitalism and the State

via emergent disequilibriums that might problematize human

societies.[76] One could object to the narrative of naturalness as being

arbitrarily defined. Where would the line be drawn exactly in terms of

nature on different forms of social organization? Still, exchanging

naturalness for values is an obvious way to see the utility of

Purchase’s writings. There are better and worse ways to organize

societies based on the goals the author argues for, such as ecological

health, solidarity, and human flourishing; and those can be connected to

an understanding of the natural phenomena of emergence that could either

encourage or inhibit achieving those goals.

Though it would be a longer argument this is at least part of what is

going on with Murray Bookchin’s social ecology.[77] Part of the break

from Marxism by Bookchin was a shift towards the more methodologically

open process Rocker speaks of and coming to view struggles and the new

society in terms of emergent relationships between people and their

environment. Like Purchase, Bookchin uses ideas about living systems and

complexity in both his critiques and proposals, without necessarily

elaborating a theory of emergence.

There are three aspects to the role of (perhaps proto-) emergence

theories within anarchism: an understanding of the natural world as

exhibiting emergence out of complex systems, using that functioning to

demonstrate weaknesses in the dominant power system, and proposals for

social change and future society drawn from emergence. In Reclus and

Kropotkin, these are implicit threads that run throughout their thought.

Proudhon directly addresses the phenomenon and uses it to critique the

State and capitalism. Purchase raises the potentials of emergence for

anarchist thought, including ecology and our relationship with the

natural world, though without elaborating a theory of emergence or

agency. These developments are particularly remarkable given that the

general thrust of European thinking from the 1600s until the present can

be classified essentially as reductionism.[78] Such science was

reductive in so far as scientists and thinkers broke up their subjects

of study into analyzable parts and sought to reconstruct them piece by

piece. This method led to the emergence of science as we know it, and

only hundreds of years later did the limitations of such approaches

become clear.

More recently some radical thinkers have taken up emergence directly and

drawn out lessons. Immanuel Wallerstein, Dante Arrighi, and other World

Systems theorists should be mentioned. Wallerstein in particular was

influenced by complexity theory and his analysis of capitalism and

predictions for how the system evolves clearly use his interpretation of

that framework in a way that is productive and is useful for

revolutionaries.[79] While critical of liberal reform and the social

democratic tradition Wallerstein has been often agnostic on other

possibilities or at times bordering on similar positions he critiques.

His positive proposals then have limited applicability for those who

seek a different route to a society beyond the State and capital. Still,

for such theorists it is clear that they’ve moved beyond the methods,

vocabulary, and theories of the left they grew out of and are producing

interesting novel analyses that are relevant and challenging.

A few scattered articles have explored more overtly revolutionary

implications of emergence and complexity in preliminary ways. Nicole

Pepperell’s dissertation attempts to cash out a Marxist approach to

capitalism via emergence. Pepperell seeks to make dialectics compatible

with emergence, and to recast concepts of Marxist political economy into

the language of emergence. If we set aside whether polar dialectics are

compatible with the multidimensional world of emergence, we will see

that this is an important attempt to wrestle with our changed

understanding and struggles with large scale forces like capitalism from

a critical perspective.[80] Richard Lewontin and Richard Levins explore

emergence in depth as biologists. However, their aim is not to elaborate

a framework from an emergence perspective, but rather to explore biology

through the lens of Marxian dialectics.[81] They do however draw

interesting conclusions for social change out of these issues.

Interest, unfortunately, in emergence has been largely academic, and

it’s found much more popularity as a tool for metaphors about existing

theories than in something worth taking seriously on its own.

Specifically, there has been a failure to thoroughly consider the

implications for practice of viewing social struggle and societies via

emergence. Previously I’ve tried to introduce emergence in the course of

analyses of post-capitalist economics, workplace organizing, and

political organization within history.[82] Beyond limited attempts like

these, the field remains wide open.

Emergent Potentials and Limits: Applied Knowledge and Nature

Emergence and living systems teach us two kinds of lessons that help us

struggle: lessons about what we know and how we know it, and lessons

about the nature and qualities of the social world. The most intuitive

and obvious outcome of these ideas are as limits of what we can know,

understand, and do. As aweinspiring as emergence is, it makes clear the

limits of our minds and capacities. Our abilities to predict, control,

and interpret living systems are limited by both our own capacity to

follow them and by the sheer force of dominant powers within. On the

streets of New York City, the patterns and undulations of the crowd are

impossible to see. We only get a sense of it in glimpses. From the

trees, the shape and evolution of the forest is obscured. Or take the

example of Mohamed Bouazizi, the Tunisian street vendor whose suicide

served as inspiration for many in 2011. As individuals, our ability to

register events like this and make predictions is quite limited. Other

such suicides have occurred throughout history without the same effect.

Similar causes, based on their context, have dissimilar results. From

the level of agents where we stand, we are unable to pull ourselves out

of our own situation to the higher-level of organization, society, and

track the events of our lives towards larger emergent ones. This is a

hard limit based on the structure of society and the limitations of our

minds.

While it may seem intuitive, in fact it goes against a large portion of

liberatory thinking and tradition. Adoption of different approaches as

political agents will not elevate us above the system we reside in nor

the emergent forces that are beyond our immediate control. Had we been

participants in the crowd in Tunisia, we would have had no way of

knowing that such an event would have the effect it did. Neither could

we anticipate the effect of the struggles that occurred surrounding

Bouazizi’s suicide. Our position within the tumult of actions places us

in a poor vantage point to the stage upon which social forces act out in

history. We do gain insight about emergent events, but only when we

switch frames to that higher-level of analysis, and neither translate

directly into each other. Each level has its own domain, logic,

practice, and analysis.

Likewise, within levels, complexity exceeds our capacity to follow the

movement of social forces. It is logical that we would be unable, say,

to trace the actions and causality of each person in a crowd that comes

to take part in a riot.

The riot is made up of all the myriad thoughts, beliefs, desires,

physicality between individuals, motions, and experiences of all the

participants. Each motion, action, and response in combination yields

uncountable interactions each defining each other in a dizzying array of

reactions. Though it’s readily understandable why it’s difficult to

think that way, we regularly attempt to do this anyway. Much of

political thinking is directed towards applying the logic of individuals

to these group situations, something emergence should make us suspicious

of.

During the Arab Spring many activists and some in the media sought to

attribute the protests to the role of social media. In Tunisia the

suicide of Bouazizi was cited as the cause of the disruptions. Obama’s

messages of hope and change in 2008 are argued to have caused youth,

blacks, and Latinos to vote in record numbers. Surely all these things

played roles in the events analyzed. Likely these analyses seek to

capture what is different about these situations from others when

similar events did not take place. Yet they share an attempt to isolate

the interaction of individuals with their respective factors (actions of

Bouazizi, content of Obama’s message, social media in the Arab Spring)

with the overall event.

In fact, the causality is much more complex than that. Similar to

explaining a riot, what makes people vote is complicated. It may be

useful to isolate single elements to look at them, but that’s not how

those decisions are made. Even when we’re not in physical proximity to

each other, such as in riots, crowds, traffic, and so on, our political

decisions are made through constant dialogue among ourselves on a

worldwide scale (though obviously how worldwide and to what extent

depends on the individual event, too). The decision to escalate

protests, enter into the electoral world, or modify my relationship to

those movements comes not in isolation, but instead within a total

framework of the world political environment, the forces around me, and

the decisions of people I know, my own history, etc.

Both levels of organization and complexity can thus change the way we

look at political events, but emergence itself also makes its own

contribution. Consider the newness of emergence. With emergence, things

that are not contained (however we understand this) in their parts come

into existence. Neither study of its parts nor the thing itself will

tell us the complete story of the emergent thing. As we said before, no

list of chemical reactions could tell us about the life of a cell.

Likewise, with political entities we are similarly limited. Take the

State. If we look at the institutions, personalities, and functions of

the State in society, we will fail to understand the way in which the

State is created through the relationships of individuals throughout

society. Yet looking only at those interactions will not make visible to

us the overarching force of the State in society. The State is more than

the sum of the interactions of individuals that create its reality. It

is an emergent force beyond the level of individuals, though constituted

by them. The State has properties that the individuals do not, even

though the individuals create it. This isn’t to say analysis is

impossible or unimportant; quite the opposite is true. As political

agents, the complexity of living systems limits our predictive and

anticipatory power. Yet there are other tools available that let us

address complexity, levels, and emergence.

Today’s complexity science in practice bears this out. Unbound by prior

radical thinkers’ methodologies, today’s scientists use artificial

modeling of complex systems to make projections. Researchers of the

dominant ruling forces (economists, political scientists, sociologists,

biologists, military planners, law enforcement, and so on) look to

large-scale modeling to help guide their attempts to drive society. In

2013 complexity researchers used emergence theory to predict worldwide

disruptions surrounding food, which made international news and exposed

a wider trend of military and government researchers attempting to

outpace explosive protest movements and maintain social control.[83] The

prevalence of such models is becoming deeper, touching everything from

election campaigning, the National Weather Service, military models of

artificial life in warfare, and law enforcement’s attempts to use

passive technology to track potential radicals.

This is the burgeoning field of artificial life, or more mundanely

simply modeling. Models exist, but as of yet they are very broad. Still,

reflect on the fact that it is through modeling the system as a whole

that the path of hurricanes and famines, spread of disease, and so on

may be tracked rather than just contemplated by thinkers creating lists

of historical events and trends. Likewise, this departs from the

traditional sociology of individual researchers trying to pinpoint

trends using their reflection in combination with citing studies, and

extrapolating an order in a linear manner. Artificial life and modeling

integrates the lessons of emergence through its centering on levels and

the special behavior of living systems.

This isn’t to say that individual analyses of sociologists,

philosophers, or political thinkers are irrelevant. Rather it’s to

delineate how different types of analyses put us into different

relations with different points of the system. Models abstract features

to make them manageable. They represent reality so we can play with it

and get results that approximate reality, more or less. They reflect

reality then, but they are not reality. Likewise, the role of the

political thinker isolates other features of society, crafting a

narrative and arguing for threads. Both reflect reality and have their

own role. Looking at the difference between those two modes of analysis

illuminates emergence. The multiplicity of perspectives characteristic

of emergence produces those different paths to discovery. Living systems

create different channels we can explore, and each channel contains

truths and projects singular to its own domain. Emergence shows us the

limitations of the nature of our inquiries at least in attempting to

grasp all social phenomena from the comforts of the armchairs of

political strategists. Modeling can show us the emergent behavior of

different elements of systems at certain levels, but it is limited by

its variables, perception, and level of analysis. The same is true with

individual analyses, statistical regressions, or experiments in action.

The uptake of all this is not only limits, but also suggested directions

for action. First, emergence allows us to understand specific failures

and avoid them, showing more promising paths. For example, levels of

organization and causality demonstrate why attempts to control

individuals and society on a broad level fail. At work, micromanaging is

a good example of how trying to impose upper-level plans directly on

groups actually breaks down efficient production (except when the

workers disregard managerial discipline). Bosses micromanaging disrupts

the emergent workflow through their attempts to insert concerns from the

managerial level directly on the plane of the employees carrying out the

work.

A traditional method of striking called work-to-rule uses exactly this

tension. Working-to-rule involves following all the formal rules and

standards management creates, but which are essentially never followed

precisely because to do so would be too inefficient. Before mail sorting

and processing was mechanized, in theory workers were required to weigh

all letters to ensure proper postage was paid. Workers in the Austrian

postal service typically did not weigh letters that were clearly

underweight, thereby obeying the rules in spirit but modifying them to

ensure workflow. During conflict with management, they began weighing

each piece of mail, which tied up deliveries significantly. Workers

thereby effectively rebelled against management through strict

obedience.[84] This manipulates management’s weakness in organizing the

workplace from above.

It is successful because when workers actually follow all of

management’s rules, work stops. This is due to the fact that the rules

created by managerial hierarchies do not reflect the reality of daily

work life. The bureaucracy of management is an emergent product of the

company separate from the workforce. The rules they create are often

contradictory, inefficient, and could not function if they were applied

fully. Workers know this and selectively ignore them without ever

spelling out in paper or deciding explicitly which rules they follow.

Work-to-rule shatters this emergent order by implementing the artificial

regime of management, grinding work to a halt by following the rules

that cannot be applied at that level.

There is a subtle genius here. One on hand, it means that the rules and

order of which management conceives aren’t really followed, or at least

that workers selectively and intuitively follow rules in a way that

allows work to continue. This is done intuitively— workers do not

generally sit down together and decide which rules will be followed

when. Workers instead produce the rules collectively through their

interactions and follow some level of discipline. The example of

work-to-rule strikes shows the ability of people to emergently create

organization in the face of attempts to impose order constructed at a

different level and points to their ability to destroy and replace it at

will.

There are darker examples, such as the USSR’s attempts to build the

Belomor canal. The canal was taken by the Soviet authorities as a

triumph of central planning in the Soviet economy using gulag labor. The

canal was conceived as part of building industrial infrastructure

necessary for transforming the Soviet economy into a functioning

industrial economy. The building of the canal cost countless lives and

created massive suffering for the gulag laborers who built it.[85]

Separated from the reality of construction on the ground, and insulated

from the creativity and collective knowledge of the laborers forced to

work under tight centralized discipline, the bureaucracies could not

produce a well-functioning project. Though often ignored, the individual

and collective creativity of workers serve a crucial role in making

plans and engineering function properly in implementation. Workers solve

problems with collective intelligence that could neither be planned for

nor anticipated by bureaucracies. The massive financial and human costs,

prison labor, and so on of the canal are severe enough to show the

dangers of central planning. Yet even more ironic is that the canal

itself ultimately served no function except to transport foreign

dignitaries and party officials on tourist ferries as a propaganda

effort. The canal was never made wide enough to transport the industrial

vessels it was meant for, and thus both wasted humanity in its creation

and made the effort in vain.[86]

The focus on central planning and party discipline of these governments

explains their fascination with crowds. Mass games, large orchestrated

exhibits of synchronized movements and images generally telling official

party history, and military marching formations can be viewed through

this light. It was a totalitarian fantasy to reduce the chaos of the

crowd to the discipline and organization of the committee, politburo,

and sect. People are transformed into colors, objects, and components

moving much as a machine does, and without any relationship to their

aesthetic creation except their implementation of the planned spectacle.

Mass games are a metaphor for the totalitarian imagination in which the

party can drive all of society through central planning, and where

society is mobilized into an amorphous mass unified around the thought

of the planner.[87]

Both traditional micro-management and centralized planning of

Marxist-Leninist governments (USSR, China, Cuba, and so on) were

likewise bound to suffer systematic problems for similar reasons. Acting

at a higher level of organization, such strategies attempt to directly

cause activity in systems with different logic at lower levels, where

simple causation is materially impossible in the way conceived. There

simply is no way to force the complexity of workforces into the logic of

individuals in a boardroom. Nothing gets done without the collective

intelligence and emergence of order from workers interacting in an

adaptive system. It is literally impossible to engineer liberated

societies in the manner of social engineering and totalitarian thinking

that emerged in the 19^(th) and 20^(th) centuries.

The point is deeper than just a rejection of the worst forms of social

engineering and the crassest management. When we look at the emergent

world, we see that in fact other alternatives can be more fruitful.

Interestingly, managers and industrial relations theorists have begun

looking at emergence for management strategies through creating

environments of autonomous workflow organization aimed at profit. In

other words, they see that what functions the best is when organization

arises organically out of social relationships of workers cooperating on

the job. People are creative, and collaboratively they make work run

better with minimal mediation by managerial structures. Workers can

independently solve problems that hold back profit, but often are

impeded by managerial bureaucracy from improving business. This is

something that is evident to anyone who’s ever worked in a subservient

position. Social order emerges from the complex interactions of

individuals united in an effort through largely decentralized

person-to-person networks.

But there’s work and then there’s work. There is a complex interplay

between emotional bonds, aspirations, incentives, and a system of

control that maintains an individual’s participation in the workforce.

Workers engage in work not because they are necessarily personally

committed to their job, but also because of a compulsory system of

discipline. We work because we need to pay the bills, and if we don’t

work how they want us to, there’s an array of disciplinary measures in

place to force us back into line and to work harder. On the one hand,

you need the voluntary labor and initiative of individuals creating

solutions to problems in an unmediated collective environment. On the

other hand, you need to ensure that people work and do so for the profit

of the company. That mediation creates inefficiency and antagonism.

The rub here though is that there’s an inherent tension in the attempt

(selforganized capitalist workplaces) to empower workers to perfect

their work because disciplinary infrastructure is always necessary. If

there weren’t coercive and repressive means within the workplaces,

people might otherwise organize it to their benefit (let alone avoid

work all together), and management recognizes this problem. If workers

were radically free, they might redirect their activity not towards

profit of the owners, but rather toward their own collective benefit,

toward the benefit of others, or toward some other aim. Just as the

order they produce is emergent, people working together can create

emergent forces towards their ends. This is something management exists

to restrain, repress, and channel into the desires and whims of those

who maintain wealth and power.

This example teaches us a number of things. Inherent in emergence is a

critique of hierarchical power relations. In understanding how social

organization is an emergent property of social relationships, and how

centralized power is inherently flawed in attempting to bridge those

gaps, we see also a critique of institutionalized hierarchies and a

libertarian method for political work. Those hierarchies are a net drain

on society and introduce a form of disease into how the social organism

functions. Complex systems help us critique why centralized management

of labor and society are regressive forces that parasitically feed off

the emergent orders of human collective creations.

Likewise, the order that exists is already emergently produced by people

adapting and responding to their circumstances. In our daily lives, we

have the inherent ability to construct alternative orders, not as

architects or planners, but rather through our interactions within the

social ecology. While there are no guarantees about what kinds of

organization can be produced, investigating emergence opens up

possibilities. We see both inherent antagonism created by emergent

parasitic classes and the possibilities of more libertarian orders

without dystopian social engineering schemes. Emergence provides a

framework to think through that project, leaving that plane open and

arming us with both critique and examples for moving forward in a

critical liberatory struggle.

Second, emergence allows us to understand and act upon the potential of

political events. It presents an alternative means of understanding

political events that moves away from mechanistic and determinist

accounts. Emergence uses the multiplicity of levels within events and

the complexity in how they unfolding over time. Doing so presents a

number of available approaches to both creating and understanding

action. For instance, ruptures are political events that roughly break

from the dominant order of their time, often ushering in new eras.

Though caused by the actions of individuals, events such as ruptures

burst politics as usual to present new potentials as the equilibrium of

dominant power is disrupted. These shifts are disorienting for political

agents, because they are disproportionately caused by and occur with

complexity that outpaces our capacity to understand them. We cause them,

but they seem to us to come out of nowhere (until much later we are able

to carry out a higher level of analysis). Ruptures are clear examples of

nonlinear causation and emergence forces coming out of seemingly

nowhere. Without understanding social emergence, the speed and depth of

changes in such insurrectionary eras can seem mystical. Indeed, much

political thinking is divided between belief in spontaneous rebellion

and in only relying on the actions of small groups substituting

themselves for larger bodies. Emergence gives us tools to see how

ruptures are possible and how they come from real activity of groups and

individuals before the rupture, as well as to situate them within the

functioning and evolution of systems of power.

If this is right, it is evident how we can both help facilitate ruptures

(though we will be unable to reliably predict them with any great

accuracy) and deepen them. Ruptures are another way of saying a

breakdown in the equilibrium of social forces and institutions. Think

about a body struck with a horrible disease like cancer. Whole organ

systems, hormonal triggers, blood vessels, and so on are hijacked by the

cancer to sustain its own life against the body it emerged from (since

cancer cells are your own cells mutated against you). The normal

functioning of the body begins to change and rapid shifts in the rules

of normal chemical reactions, body functions, and so on occur. In

society likewise, when the forces of equilibrium are functioning well,

some doors are realistically closed. Our ability to help produce

emergent liberatory forces on any significant basis is improbable

(though it’s hard to know this from where we stand at any given moment).

While the system has a functioning cooling system and can absorb the

heat we produce, it keeps moving. But sometimes systemic problems can

break down those recuperative mechanisms and produce so much activity

that the whole thing begins to deteriorate.

As that order breaks down, however, new possibilities for new emergences

can rapidly explode as the previous system’s means of ensuring stability

break down. Political events have systemic contexts. Ruptures are merely

a name for particularly extreme version of events that are more routine.

How causality unfolds depends on the broader stability and equilibrium

of the system, the emergent forces within, and the composition of the

higher-level emergent powers maintaining order. Emergence allows us to

feel out where we stand in the changes of the system, where to

intervene, and how to grow with the changing forces that social struggle

creates. As a framework, it gives us the ability to propose specific

answers to those questions, though not any particular proposal. This

isn’t to say have faith in spontaneity, but rather it is the opposite;

it gives us tools and an understanding of the historical reality of the

dynamic between organized activity and the emergence of new protagonists

in struggle. As we stand, agents trying to choose different courses of

action, emergence brings to light how we are situated in a web of causes

throughout society that can reverberate with other forces in society and

either be absorbed, amplified, or transformed in the unfolding of

political events.

Likewise, the activities of organized bodies, even quite small ones, can

in the right context have disproportionate effects. We don’t need to

look only at butterfly wings and tsunamis here. Anyone seriously

involved in social struggle has tasted the dramatic shifts that can help

when a small group in a certain moment takes action. This can be both

positively when it moves a movement forward, such as in the Flint

sit-down strike when the organizers made the decision to strike by

occupying the factory and thereby started a revolution in workplace

organizing, or negatively when small groups clumsily attack the police

at the wrong moment and a protest collapses. Groups acting in a

favorable context can have deep transformative consequences. In the

right situation, organized revolutionaries can have a disproportionate

effect either against popular power or with it. Lewontin and Levins

propose a model of action based on these considerations.

In chaotic systems, anything cannot happen; only a range of alternatives

within a set of constraints can happen. It would take more than the flap

of a butterfly’s wing to induce monsoon rains in Finland or a drought in

the Amazon or equal representation of women on the Harvard faculty.

Great quantities of energy and matter are involved in particular

configurations for the major events to occur. Only when a system is

poised on the brink can a tiny event set it off. Therefore, the task of

promoting change is one of promoting the conditions under which small,

local events can precipitate the desired restructuring.[88]

Here the authors focus primarily on these kinds of ruptures and suggest

focusing on facilitating them, but we could expand that view. From the

perspective of human liberation, it may be superior to find ways to

promote consistent counter-powers across a wide area that may not lead

immediately to such ruptures, but may improve the lives of numbers of

people, and encourage the shifts in conviction and thought that empower

new revolutionaries and aid insurrectionary work in other contexts.

These differences show the potential of the theory for cashing out

strategic differences, rather than being limited only to a single frame.

This isn’t to overemphasize the actions of small groups, nor to say

groupings should act in the name of movements, but rather to place

revolutionaries within a non-privileged sphere of revolutionary action

without the assumption of leadership that substitutes itself for the

multitude. There are potentials and limitations to this kind of

causation, and understanding the problems of groups attempting to act in

the name of systems as a whole, emergence places the role of organized

revolutionaries back within the movement, rather than as its executor.

Ruptures are when these elements become most obvious and necessary.

Yet even within normal political activities where equilibrium is

sustained, these tools can be applied to understand counter-systemic

action by political agents in more localized forms and in strategic

thinking. Brazil, for example, exploded in protest that nearly brought

the government to its knees in 2013 over increases in the cost of

transit with grievances over the existing services. The Movimento Passe

Livre, or Free Fare Movement, arose some ten years earlier out of

localized struggles in different cities where organizers were

persistently agitating around transit issues with limited success until

the fury of the population boiled over.[89] It is easy to forget that a

vast sea of grievances that exists within society is typically brought

to a more cohesive form by the investment and experience of committed

militants who have the vision and practice to shift proposals into

concrete actions.

Navigating the evolution of the system, its ability to reproduce, and

the breakdown of its order is part of the tasks for forces organizing

for liberation. Understanding our limitations, the tentativeness of our

predictions, and the real potential (both for recuperation and for

disproportionate influences) places both objective factors and group

intervention at the core of action. This seems common sense, though for

much of the history of political thinking there was an unbridgeable

chasm between the individual and society created by ideology that failed

to connect agency to society. Living systems demonstrate the balance and

relation between different modes of social activity and struggle, not

merging them simply by squishing them together, but rather giving each

its place in a coherent whole reflecting the structure and adaption of

society itself.

Lastly, it’s worth stating that emergence is a materialist theory of the

political world.[90] Materialism in its widest sense tries to explain

reality through only appealing to matter. That is to say, there is no

external realm of ideas or spirit outside the material world in which we

live and breathe. It thus provides a potential method for showing how

basic physical forces produce the whole universe, of which the

psychological, social, and political spheres are only different

presentations of that same basic underlying material reality. Having a

direct connection to physical existence and science is a strength of

these ideas, for the basic reason that it makes the political cohere to

more basic forces in nature.

This isn’t to say that society doesn’t have its own specific content,

but it makes it less magical and mysterious and brings it within the

domain of potential actions. Indeed, it’s been the obscurity of

society’s functioning that often has been used as a tool against people,

a tool to reinforce dominant power through ritual, faith, and even

obscurantist or technocratic science. Political leadership of the State,

despite the rhetoric of participation and democracy, wraps itself in

rituals of expertise and superhuman abilities to reinforce its exclusive

claim to governing, when in reality it is the unconscious actions of

millions that sustain the social order that the State struggles to

maintain its influence over. The theater of power is filled with

parliaments, architectural feats of awe, oval offices, pulpits, and

presidential limousines and airplanes. These are not only the excesses

of an insulated elite drunk on their own power, but also a conscious

cultivation to hide the fact that their decisions can be forced and

eroded not with expensive fountain pens, but with the calls and

footsteps on the streets below their balconies.[91] The more we can

grasp at this world and bring it within the reach of all, the more power

we have to challenge the wrongs enforced on people every day.

Through the discussion of emergence, a view of political events has been

elaborated that frames and centers the role of agents and provides a

framework for the relationships between peoples’ actions and larger

social forces. Likewise, this understanding contributes to unifying the

living and physical world based on shared laws and matter by explaining

why it is difficult for us to conceive of the transformation of the

physical into the living and social. It does so arguing that different

levels of organization produce different behaviors and properties.

Inherent properties of living systems have political significance in

demonstrating how order is emergently produced; institutionalized

hierarchies introduce inherent problems into social systems and mark the

potential for a liberatory selforganized social order.

The real work of this theory is yet to be done. Its implications for our

understanding of capitalism, the State, and oppressions are in its

infancy and will be the task of those of us working to develop this line

of thought. Revolution, self-management, non-statist society, and

organization are questions ripe for critical answers from an emergentist

perspective. It is there in the large questions of liberatory politics

that emergence shows its real use. The work of addressing all of them

would require a text on its own. There are a few core concepts though

that increase our ability to tackle these large questions, and which

require their own sections of this book. Part of the appeal of this

perspective is its ability to explain the functioning of power as an

emergent force in society, and to situate political thinking and action

in a radical light. In the next section, power will be explored.

Part 3: Power

Power in the Libertarian Tradition

In social and political life two spheres weave around each other and the

events that make up our reality. On the one hand there is the experience

of living as individuals with all of our senses, feelings, perceptions,

and thoughts. We are creatures with subjective experiences of the world.

On the other hand, there is the construction of the social world by

large-scale emergent forces that shape us even from before we’re born.

The cities we live in, political institutions, cultural patterns, and

group behaviors all are living forces around us that are greater than

the sums of the individuals within them, and in fact make up part of how

we become who we are. We inhabit a socially-constructed order of powers

that divide, arrange, organize, and rearrange society’s many divisions.

We ourselves are shaped by our relationships to these forces in all

their manifestations, whether classes, genders, races, or more mundane

structuring like beauty, charisma, and urban/suburban/rural life. Yet we

come at that world as beings with senses, and we enter into political

activity through our experiences, desires, and intentional and

motivational subjectivity.

As we saw in the last chapter, linking these two aspects of our world is

the concept of emergence. Emergence, a concept borrowed from the

biological sciences, describes the process of events happening based on

higher-level behaviors being produced by lower levels through complex

and adaptive means. Just like countless cells having chemical reactions

eventually producing our thoughts, systems of domination emerge from

countless individuals’ experiences and actions. The rules at different

levels of analysis are themselves distinct. For example, our neurons use

sodium, calcium, and potassium to create signals and patterns in our

brains. Those electrolytes however don’t feel longing for a lover, but

the lovers’ loving is made up of and caused in part because of the

action of the electrolytes working to make our neurons do what they do.

In a way the world of our experiences and the world of emergent social

forces are separated by a great chasm. Individuals function at a level

of organization with different rules from, say, capitalism. Our actions

produce capitalism, but do so generally without our knowledge and only

through the relationships of the system (between individuals,

individuals and groups, and between groups and groups). Emergence

bridges the world of our mental lives and the world of systems like

capitalism.

There is a parallel distinction in the political sphere between emergent

social forces and the perspectives of political actors. Power, like

emergence, is a concept that functions with our subjectivity and in

social relationships or intersubjectively. This aspect of power is

underappreciated, and carries with it the potential to understand how

our agency interacts with the context we act within.

Anarchism and Power

One of the central insights and value of the anarchist tradition is that

power lies at its core. Anarchism builds a critique of existing society

and the potential to transform it from an analysis of power in human

life. Power itself, however, has been greatly overlooked primarily by

the historic left, who have followed selective readings of Marx.[92]

They sought to explain power only as a distant effect of economic

forces; mere superstructure produced by the economic base.[93] Against

this, anarchism consistently critiqued the view of power as a derivative

of economic forces. Luigi Fabbri, for instance, wrote “We believe as

well that political power is not only an effect of economic force,

rather that one and another are alternatively cause and effect.”[94]

There were, in fact, a number of different positions within the

anarchist movement, which are present up till today, concerning power.

Some libertarian thinkers emphasized power as an exclusively negative

concept. Power is thus a means of coercing autonomous beings to follow

one’s will. In keeping with these goals, this is not typically a

philosophy of power, but rather a revolutionary political orientation to

the political powers of the day. Elisée Reclus, for example, argued that

anarchism is defined by the resistance to the corrupting influence of

power, and aims at dismantling permanent structural power.

The conquest of power can only serve to prolong the duration of the

enslavement that accompanies it
 It is in fact our struggle against all

official power that distinguishes us most essentially. Each

individuality seems to us to be the center of the universe and each has

the same right to its integral development, without interference from

any power that supervises, reprimands, or castigates it.[95]

Malatesta, similarly, does not give a general theory of power, but

attempts to delineate its role and functioning both amongst the ruling

class and those resisting. His treatment of power, at least in the

limited writings of his we have access to in English, focuses on the

State.

For us, government is made up of all the governors; and the governors—

kings, presidents, ministers, deputies, etc.—are those who have the

power to make laws regulating inter-human relations and to see that they

are carried out; to levy taxes and to collect them; to impose military

conscription; to judge and punish those who contravene the laws; to

subject private contracts to rules, scrutiny and sanctions; to

monopolize some branches of production and some public services or, if

they so wish, all production and all public services; to promote or to

hinder the exchange of goods; to wage war or make peace with the

governors of other countries; to grant or withdraw privileges...and so

on. In short, the governors are those who have the power, to a greater

or lesser degree, to make use of the social power, that is of the

physical, intellectual and economic power of the whole community, in

order to oblige everybody to carry out their wishes. And this power, in

our opinion, constitutes the principle of government, of authority.[96]

Mikhail Bakunin, Russian participant of the First International

Workingmen’s Association and generally considered one of the most

important founders of modern anarchism, wrote extensively about power in

the context of its transformative effect over individuals. This was

against the authoritarian socialists of his day, who believed the

existing capitalist State or future potential workers’ State could be

harnessed to create a free socialist society.[97] Though his view of

power is largely a negative one, he made a distinction between power and

authority. “In the matter of boots, I defer to the authority of the

bootmaker.”[98] Power then for Bakunin consisted of institutionalized

and coercive powers, while authority could be oppressive or based on

some earned capacity that others could voluntarily respect. If authority

is taken as a form of non-State power, his view could be construed as

recognizing different forms of power, some constructive and others

parasitic.

Similar to what Bakunin had done, Rudolph Rocker divided destructive

power from constructive authority in his book, Nationalism and Culture.

Just as power is negative and authority potentially positive, so Rocker

argued against a dangerous nationalism and for a potentially sociable

culture. Influenced by the German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche,

Rocker argues for the centrality of power in understanding politics when

he claims that “(t)he will to power that always emanates from

individuals or small minorities in society is in fact an important

driving force in history. The extent of its influence has up to now been

studied far too little, although it has frequently been the determining

factor in the shaping of the whole of economic and social life.”[99]

Though not strictly an anarchist, British philosopher and activist

Bertrand Russell was at one time a libertarian socialist and retained

ties to anarchist causes late into his life. His book, Power, reflects

that libertarian perspective of centering social life and analysis of

power alongside a critique of the dangers of State power. Criticizing

orthodox economists and Marxist views that placed economic interest as

the fundamental drive of social life, he wrote:

This error in orthodox and Marxist economics is not merely theoretical,

but is of the greatest practical importance, and has caused some of the

principle events of recent times to be misunderstood. It is only by

realizing the love of power is the cause of the activities that are

important in social affairs that history whether ancient or modern, can

be rightly interpreted
 The fundamental concept in social science is

Power, in the same sense in which Energy is the fundamental concept in

physics.[100]

Russell goes on to provide an analysis of power as the ability to

produce intended effects. His account ties power to the intentionality

of the agent, something that will be explored more in depth in the

fourth part of this book.

Emma Goldman similarly took a Nietzschean view of the will to power as

the main force of life. She was not alone. Benjamin Tucker, American

individualist anarchist, was one of the first to translate Nietzsche

into English for an American audience. Nietzsche’s influence on

anarchism was greater than one would imagine given Nietzsche’s elitism

and explicit hostility to socialist and anarchist ideas. In general, it

was his critiques of the State, nationalism, and the destructive aspects

of power in modern society that appealed to thinkers like Goldman and

Rocker, though surely many anarchists felt great disdain for the

philosopher. His promotion of the positive aspects of power immanent to

all humanity, however, are less easy to identify in the anarchists who

explicitly engaged him.

There are other threads within anarchism however that have recognized

power as a broader concept. Indeed, within Russell, Rocker, and Goldman

power is seen as one of the central components of all social life, and

not merely as a negative property of abusive authority. Luce Fabbri,

anarchist theorist from Uruguay and daughter of the famous Italian

anarchist Luigi Fabbri, argued for such in the early 1950s.

Socialism does not deny that expansive manifestation of the life

instinct that is often called the will to power; it satisfies it rather

in that which is higher, and that is to say more human if not for fear

that we would embarrass ourselves with too many examples of animal

solidarity that Kropotkin gives us in his “Mutual Aid” and that we find

day to day in nature. A healthy will to power leads to the desire for

freedom and self-control, in the desire to form hostile nature and inert

matter to the needs of man, the appetite for work, creation of

knowledge; and especially in the association that multiplies and

extends, until the limits of the known universe, the possibilities and

energy of individual action, in the solidarity that is the basis of the

collective subconscious of the species, it becomes in the field of

consciousness, fraternity, love, spirit of sacrifice. In the individual,

a healthy life instinct leads both to give and to do as to take and to

enjoy; and in this to give and in this to do seeks ultimately, a

superiority.[101]

Here power is a feature of daily life and not merely a property of the

State and hierarchies. Power indeed can be actively productive. Luce

Fabbri does not make use of the distinction between power and authority,

but instead focuses on good and bad forms of power. In his introduction

to anarchism, Angel Cappelletti similarly dismisses the idea that

anarchism is against power per se.

‘Anarchism’ does not want to call for the negation of all power and all

authority: it wants only to call for the negation of permanent power and

institutionalized power or, in other words, negation of the State
 The

socalled primitive societies are not unfamiliar with power (and even as

Pierre Clastres[102] wishes, political power) but are characterized

essentially against civilized people to ignore the state, that is,

permanent and established political power. Anarchists aspire to a

society without divisions between rulers and ruled, a society without

fixed and predetermined authority, a society where power is not

transcendent to the knowledge, moral, and intellectual capacity of each

individual.[103]

Proudhon interestingly attempted to give an account of power, even

emergent power, in terms of individual and collective force. He begins

by questioning what makes up the reality of social power and answers,

“collective force,” which he defines as “the faculty or property
of

being able to attract and be attracted, to repulse and be repulsed, to

move, to act, to think, to PRODUCE, at the very least to resist, by its

inertia, influences from the outside.”[104] Power is something then that

expresses itself differently in the entities that contain it. It is a

property both of the rulers and the ruled; there is liberating force and

repressive force but also mundane force. Proudhon uses this basic

concept of power to demonstrate how collective force takes on its own

powers beyond the “sum” of its individuals.

Anticipating theorists of power today, Proudhon places the power of the

State not in its purely violent force, but in its capacity to reproduce

obedience. “It is
not actually the exploiter, it is not the tyrant, whom

the workers and citizens follow
 It is the social power that they

respect, a power ill-defined in their thinking, but outside of which

they sense that they cannot subsist.” Rulers thus appeal to a broader

force to sustain themselves, and the failure to do so leads to revolt

Proudhon argues. The nation itself is not its rulers or institutions,

but “
the grouping of individual forces, and through the relation of the

groups, the whole nation forms one body: it is a real being of a higher

order, whose movement implicates the existence and fortune of

everyone.”[105] This approach of connecting emergent social force to

maintaining hierarchical power that is dependent on those emergent

networks has not been given its due. Proudhon lays out a barebones

emergentist understanding of the State and power in these passages and

connects them to a liberatory politics, something unique in his time and

rare still today.

Though there are differences between these positions, the commonality is

the belief in the centrality of an understanding of power within

society, in pursuit of liberation, and against specific forms of power

that sustain exploitation and oppression. Building upon this current

with its analysis and critique of power, complex systems and emergence

offer another view of how power operates within social groups. Power’s

unique character that crosses between agency and the world of emergence

can give us new ways to understand and transform our reality, not merely

as a critique of institutional power, but as a living concept of social

systems and individuals.

Emergence and Power: Defining Power

Pinning down power is tricky in part because we use it so often. Our

daily lives are shaped by the contours of power in all our

relationships, intimate and political. It is such an integral part of

human experience, it’s not surprising to find power peppered throughout

our language, culture, and thinking about ourselves and the world.

Understanding power means having to grapple with different aspects of

the concept. There are so many senses, applications, and uses of power

that any analysis of it as a concept will struggle to navigate all of

its varied uses. We tend to define power in terms of other concepts that

invoke it like potential, potency, ability, and so on. At its most

basic, having power means someone can or could do something.

Consider the sentence, “Jane has the power to inspire.” If we dissect

power, a few elements stand out. There’s the relationship between Jane

and whatever she has the power to do or over; there’s the power itself;

and then there’s Jane as a powerful person. These three pieces are the

relationship of power, what power itself is, and the subject of power.

Exploring those different aspects of power will help unpack the problem.

Traditionally most political analyses of power have been about its

exercise by political institutions: the power of police or military as

armed forces, the power to reconstruct society through State

intervention, contestation of the State machinery, and so on. In

English, we commonly refer to this as power over something or another.

The police have power over this neighborhood. A patriarchal husband

holds power over his wife. Parents have power over their children.

Foucault famously made a lot out of its comparison with another sense of

power, the power to do something.[106] One can have the power to

persuade others to listen, the power to seduce a lover, the power to

inspire action. Power over is about the potential to get others to do

what you wish, whereas power to is about abilities to act. Both are

forms of capacities, one as influence and the other as capabilities.

Discussions of power typically rely on concepts like abilities,

potential, potency, or possibility to explain it. Yet such concepts

reference power in a basic sense. Defining power in terms of capacity,

influence, or ability covertly makes reference to the power to do

something in other terms. If Jane is able to jump, she has the power to

job; she can or could jump; she is jump-able.

These definitions are circular because power is such a deep component of

our mental and social lives that much of our thinking is constructed out

of it. Our thinking about actions are built upon our own abilities and

limitations, patterns of behavior structures surrounding powers, the

abilities of others, and the imposition of the powers of the natural

world on our wills. So we drive differently in rain or snow, walk with

caution in dangerous neighborhoods, greet friends and loved ones

distinctly from others, and exercise rage within the boundaries of

acceptable targets and circumstances.

Lewes in his early emergentist text takes up power during his

discussions of cause and effect. For similar reasons to above he

concludes that power is merely a concept we use to talk about causality

with agents. He is a power skeptic therein arguing that there is no

thing beyond the cause and effect itself.[107] In a sense this is true,

but he is missing a few things. Most importantly such an account would

not explain the social notions of power or more abstract potentials.

Having a concept like power gives us additional mental tools to

understand and describe such states. Perhaps power is merely a robust

form of causality, but if so it is a special one, and one we can’t

manage to think without.

Power shapes both our own thinking about how to act and the society we

live and grow in. It stands intimately close to our basic mental

processes surrounding action and relationships with others because power

is part of our fundamental conceptual vocabulary and is something that

resists further breaking down into conceptual parts. Power’s closeness

to our mental life and its operation throughout society gives it

strength as a potential tool for understanding societies and politics.

What about who and what can have power? People can have power, but we

also apply the term to other things as well. For instance, power can be

discussed as a concept of social events, institutions, and behaviors. In

this sense it is described as property of powerful institutions, groups,

and people. Governments hold power over people, the working class has

the power to shut down production, and a riot has a powerful resonance

in the history of a city.

Another framing for power is as a subjectivity and element of

experiential life. This is the way in which one experiences power nearly

as a sensation. There is a particular feeling when our words inspire

others, when another dominates us and we are powerless to fight back,

when we are aware of our ability to wrong or violate others, but choose

not to, etc. We experience the power of our words, the power of touch,

the powerlessness we feel with lovers, and the feeling of power building

up in us that we fail to exercise when calming down from a rage. There

are then experiences of power as agents, and structures or forces of

power in societies. Both can be the agents of power, and in fact

individual agents themselves interlinked in a society produce the larger

emergent forces of power.

What kinds of things can be in relationships of power? The most common

discussions focus on power relationships between people or groups. Yet

only looking at the relationships between people gives an incomplete

picture. We talk about the power of a politician over a country, the

power of the US military to impose its will, or the power of Wall Street

in Washington DC. Power is not simply a social relationship, however,

because power can also exist not just in relationship to other people,

but also in relation to ourselves and to the natural world, such as the

power to change one’s environment and oneself. We exert power on

inanimate objects like lakes, trees, animals, and mountains. Our ability

to impose changes on our own personality, habits, or thinking (or the

inability to do so) is also a kind of potency.

Additionally, power can be abstract and exist between forces rather than

people or groups of people. Emergent forces themselves (which are not

people) stand in relationships of power to each other. Think about

things like the stock market of futures in commodities like cattle and

agencies’ predictions of weather. Bad weather predictions have the power

to change the price of futures markets because of the anticipation of

shortages from things like drought, or good corn years making feed

cheaper, and so on. The institutions generating the predictions have

power that influences the market. Both the institutions and the behavior

of the market are connected to real things like cows, people, weather,

feed, and so on, but the relationship of power occurs at a higher level

of organization between the forces of the market and the predictions

(both of which can be absolutely wrong about what is actually

happening). Agents of power can thus be people or emergent forces.

It’s important to consider that power is not simply exercised by

powerful bodies, but also linked as relationships across society.

Exercising power makes good on the potentials actors have. Society is

built upon powers, exercised and latent, standing between individuals

and groups. The power of the police, for example, structures the

behavior of individuals through existing balances of forces. Power

influences society without being exercised at each moment, however.

Stable relationships develop based on balances of power, experiences of

individuals in relationship to powers, and the collective patterning of

relationships.

We don’t obey the State, for example, simply because there are armed

people who will harm us if we don’t. Instead respect of State authority

is transmitted and reproduced constantly in smaller ways (i.e.,

deferring to State authorities in trying to solve neighborhood problems,

framing discussions with friends in terms of the boundaries laid out in

official channels, affirming each other’s need to go through established

hierarchies, and so on). Similarly, when the respect for authority

breaks down or is resisted, it often happens because of subtle acts of

defiance and power being reproduced within social groups.

Consider workplaces. They are structured to enforce the existing power

relations between bosses and workers, but also between workers. Offices

are arranged to reinforce the perception of the boss as powerful and in

control (management’s offices, parking schemes, break rooms, freedom and

direction of foot traffic, and so on), to divide workers from each

other, to minimize unproductive social interaction, and so on. This

happens through layout design of the rooms, surveillance equipment

installation, active patrols by managers, and building in tasks that

need perpetual monitoring to keep workers busy. Workers can reinforce

the power of management through enforcing management’s rules on each

other, giving gifts to the boss, hiding conversations between coworkers,

and seeking out management to solve interpersonal problems rather than

settling them amongst themselves. The power of the boss is constructed

through the structures and framework that management organizes, yet the

actual power they hold over workers comes in large part from reproducing

the respect and order management seeks amongst the workers.

Conversely, the power of the boss is threatened by the failure of

workers to reproduce it. When they disobey and start following their own

rules, the authority of the boss can evaporate. This is precisely what

happens in strikes and job actions that target the workflow inside, such

as sit-down, working to rule or slow-down strikes, and even workplace

occupations and seizures. Such breaks from the power of bosses are

things we see emerge again and again in periods of militancy when

workers have begun reorganizing their workplaces with their own desires

and perspectives in mind.

In our interactions with countless individuals, we transmit and maintain

relationships of power through our actions and thinking. Social

interactions are opportunities to express the language of power through

our actions. Those relationships, constantly reproduced and modified in

daily life, provide the terrain for the construction of power relations

across society. Emergent powers come out of those interactions, and draw

their life force from the decisions individuals make in groups

responding to the structures, patterns, and mechanisms of emergent

powers within society. Different power relations are transmitted when we

break from established power, and social unrest spreads, creating new

relationships and capacities. Protests, strikes, riots, revolutions, and

other forms of political events are alterations in the networks of

power, and they transmit activity and information through the social

networks constitutive of society. When we struggle, we are creating new

abilities—powers to do things that were not or could not done

previously. The bedrock of power then is our actions and interactions

either to confirm, reject, or change the flow of power relationships in

society. Emergent social forces like the State or the capitalist class

exercise power on individuals and social classes. The State uses its

power over the population in crackdowns, propaganda efforts, and social

engineering. Capitalists use their power to mobilize vast resources to

create new markets. Just as individuals have and transmit power, so do

groups and emergent social forces.

Looking at the role of power takes us to its relational aspect. Remember

that power can be both experiential and social; it can exist between

individuals and the world, individuals and themselves, between

individuals, and between groups. A power relationship then is the type

of relationship between an agent or force, the object of their power,

and the capacity to do something or another. The power to make others

laugh is characterized by ability to humor, to bore, and so on. Powers

carve out sets of capacities that are related in such a way. They then

are constituted by particular sets of relations between abilities and

inabilities of individuals and/or groups.

Power relations take the form of a potential of an actor A to do action

X, when that possibility may invoke some B that is another person,

group, or institution, or A themselves or itself. Power is thus a

concept based on possibilities that modify relationships between people,

objects, and their strength to do or not do various things. Each power

has a different relation. The power to seduce is about the relationship

of someone’s presence to the motivational states of others. The power to

run quickly is about the states of the body, someone’s capacity, and

facts about the world. The form of those relationships represent power

in general in its role. A better understanding of the concept is had by

seeing it as a way of correlating relational states of agents and

potential agents to different actions. Politics has largely been

concerned with specific types of power rather than power itself. We can

think of political power as a set of particular capacities (political

ones) between people and social forces. Other forms of power are

constructed around different sets of abilities.

Emergent Power

These relations are divvied out in a tiered manner. Power is organized

according to the relations and states between actors. As said before,

power relations can be between individuals and the world, individuals

and others, and emergent forces with any combination of individuals/the

world/other emergent forces. For the agents of those relationships,

power has different effects as well. These relations manifest at three

levels: states of mind, social relations, and as emergent behaviors of

groups.

It’s important to note the internal subjective or phenomenological

component of power, because it can be easily ignored in the more obvious

examples of power between people. There is an experience of power that

we go through as beings. Even more still, there are power relationships

we can have to ourselves reflexively. For example, the experience of

being powerless to overcome one’s challenges as a rock climber is a form

of power, and one with a reflexive subjective character that is inherent

to that power itself. Without being an agent that is capable of

experiencing, willing, and struggling, we couldn’t make sense of that

type of power or powerlessness.

Taking a similar example, the experience of being crushed by a rock, but

unable to free oneself is again a power relationship. It is a power

relationship with an inanimate object, something incapable of having

agency, and yet it is still a power relationship. Out of the basic

relationship of power, a number of things emerge. Individuals’ power

relations produce subjective states. There is a particular kind of

terror to being rendered powerless by natural disasters or from attacks

by wild animals. There are distinct sensations of pleasure from our

power to please others. Our subjective states of power derive in part

from our relationship to those powers.

This is not merely metaphorical. Power is a fundamental experience of

human life only because we have agency and will to do things. Yet our

existence in a social and physical world outside our creation both

constitutes and inhibits our will within all the dizzying complexity of

our environment. Power doesn’t only enter our life once we enter into

all the loves and struggles of being a social creature. It resides

deeper in the basic make up of our minds since we are perceptual and

cognitive beings.

As agents, we exist in a world of other agents with their own powers and

relationships throughout societies. Individuals systematically interact

with groups and other individuals, and in doing so sustain the social

aspect of power. Power as a relational force of possibilities

fundamentally shapes our activity as social creatures, causing us to

pursue or avoid each other, and providing basic underlying drive and

logic to our interactions. These interactions create social force. The

social relationships between workers produce the power that can maintain

or stop production. Power relations between lovers can sustain or

prevent abuse. People exercise, withhold, and transmit power among each

other.

With groups, power relations produce emergent forces, events, and even

structures. Within the State, ruling forces battle for dominance.

Countries engage in power struggles over territory, resources, and

position within global hierarchies. Emergent blocks among capitalists

struggle for market dominance. Power has an animate life within society

that emerges at the level of social forces. Beyond the individuals

within, we can see the conquest of power by institutions and emergent

powers, such as social organisms (or perhaps ecologies) like the State,

classes, and social formations.

At each stage (individual, intersubjective, and emergent social) power

relations influence each other in a broad social system. Individual

experiences of power influence actions. Transmitted between individuals,

they sustain large scale power structures like domination. Regimes’

power is challenged or sustained by the actions of individuals working

in groups. Power is part of the living system of society, and flows

through the different levels, creating new forms and structures. Working

between subjective and intersubjective worlds, power is constructed,

reproduced, modified, and transmitted between humans throughout society.

Power is either a capacity or an incapacity that people and groups have.

Likewise, power is not simply exercised, it may be retained and implied

without ever having to be realized. Therefore, power is inherently

contextual between the social relationships of its actors and the total

environment of an individual with powers. In other words, to understand

power we have to understand both the actors that have the powers, the

powers themselves, and the total situation that created both the actors

and their situation. To understand the ability to go to war, we must

understand the nation, the soldier, the means of producing war

materials, living, the species, etc.

Power then occupies a unique position in human life. It is both a

constitutive element of our experience of the world, and at the same

time a social relationship with emergent powers and properties beyond

our individual experience of such. Power is part of who we are, and an

expression of our intentionality in the world as actors. At the same

time, it makes up our social reality and its force bears down upon us.

It comes from within, and while acting from without changes our very

being. By occupying this space, a common substance of different

arrangements in the subjective and intersubjective realms, power gives

us a gift. It can both account for the breadth of much of political life

and our experience of such. It is a unifying conceptual force in the

hands of political actors.

An Example: The State

It’s beyond the scope of this text to provide an adequate analysis of

the State. Still looking specifically at power, we can lay out some of

the ways that emergence and power can be used for political action. In

the realm of the State, for example, power gives us the ability to

understand why it is naĂŻve to believe that building a State with the

exploited rather than a dominant class would insulate any movement from

the corrupting influence of capitalism. If we analyze movements and the

State not simply in terms of their class character, but also in terms of

an underlying foundation of power relationships, the falsity of that

view becomes evident.

This gets at the center of anarchism, which is to center constructive

proposals for society in juxtaposition to a critique not of particular

elements of power, but in more fundamental power relationships that

penetrate society. Bakunin warned against such a simplistic perspective

of the corrupting influence of State power in his debate with statist

socialists.

There can be no equality between the sovereign and the subject. On one

side there is the feeling of superiority necessarily induced by a high

position; on the other, that of inferiority resulting from the

sovereign’s superior position as the wielder of executive and

legislative power. Political power means domination. And where there is

domination there must be a substantial part of the population who remain

subjected to the domination of their rulers: and subjects will naturally

hate their rulers. who will then naturally be forced to subdue the

people by even more oppressive measures, further curtailing their

freedom. Such is the nature of political power ever since its origin in

human society. This also explains why and how men who were the reddest

democrats, the most vociferous radicals, once in power become the most

moderate conservatives. Such turnabouts are usually and mistakenly

regarded as a kind of treason. Their principal cause is the inevitable

change of position and perspective. We should never forget that the

institutional positions and their attendant privileges are far more

powerful motivating forces than mere individual hatred or ill will. If a

government composed exclusively of workers were elected tomorrow by

universal suffrage, these same workers, who are today the most dedicated

democrats and socialists, would tomorrow become the most determined

aristocrats, open or secret worshippers of the principle of authority,

exploiters and oppressors.[108]

Today we can see that he had great clarity about the ability of the

internal institutional dynamics of the State in sustaining the

participation and investment of its members reaching beyond their

ideologies. This mechanism of power can be separated from the repressive

mechanism Bakunin describes. In the modern nation state, recuperative

functions have perhaps transformed that dynamic that may have seemed

more plausible in the 19^(th) century than today. The awareness of the

emergence of power through the collective entity of the State

transforming individuals into guardians of privilege here sets the

libertarian critique of the State apart from the more selective

critiques in terms of the composition of the State, its laws, or the

embrace of hypothetical class/racial/national reconstructed states.

Reproducing hierarchical power relations within an authoritarian state

carries the potential for capitalist relationships to re-emerge. Even if

one makes the argument that destroying the economic basis for capitalism

is a form of intervention against capitalist power relations, it is

insufficient because power relationships do not only flow from single

sources, such as the State. Hierarchical power can be constructed from

countless points in a decentralized manner and emerge just as our

actions emerge not from a single core, but instead they are the products

of innumerable chemical reactions in cells. If the statist power

relations are not destroyed and an institutionalized form of hierarchy

remains within the control of a privileged class of State bureaucracy,

from the perspective of power, there’s no reason to believe that class

tyranny won’t re-emerge. That is, unless we specifically undermine such

relationships and reproduce new ones on a different basis, it’s unlikely

if not impossible that statist and capitalist power would be overcome.

The State itself is an emergent product of power relationships built in

hierarchical society. Yet if we take the analysis of power seriously,

then the structure of the State itself is not enough to grapple with it.

Just as we cannot expect the class character of its participants to

automatically abolish its role, the abolition of statist relationships

is bigger than its structure. If power is emergent and emergent from the

reproduction of its relations in a diffuse manner, then simply attacking

its structure doesn’t guarantee a liberatory outcome. Replacing the

State with a system of direct democracy, for example, doesn’t ensure

that the State will not re-emerge. It is necessary that people and

society produce new social relationships, and in essence are transformed

in order to make the State’s reemergence unlikely.

The problem then with the State is not simply who is in charge of it,

but rather the basis for statist relationships throughout society. Here

the analysis of power shows its use not only as a tool for

understanding, but also as a tool for action. We need to destroy not

only the institutionalized hierarchies of the State, but also their

basis for ruling throughout social relationships.

This does not mean however that we will understand the State only by

looking at power. Power is a foundation for understanding and acting on

social struggle. On top of that foundation, the whole social world is

built. To understand the State, we need to look the particulars in the

context within the development of the situation.[109] This is to say

that power is a fundamental concept, but one concept among many, and we

should not make the confusion of seeing the importance of comprehending

power with overlooking the need to have specific contextual analyses of

our situation and moment. For example, to give a full account of the

State one must grasp not only the State as social relationships, but

also its history, institutions, its class basis and role, relations

between force and consent, divisions, and so on. The examples offered

here are illustrative and should be taken as demonstrating directions

that theorists could develop using such a concept, rather than being

sufficient in themselves.

Still with the example of statist social relationships, it should be

noticed that the understanding of power offered outlines a concrete

historical approach itself. Power is a bridge between the subjective and

intersubjective worlds, and is so only in reference to concrete social

and physical contexts that make power possible. This understanding is

part then of a method of rooting political work both in the ethical

challenges of liberatory struggle and in a concrete reality of social

struggle across different specific historical points.

Power in Action

The concept of power is nearly physical; it is so close to life. One can

practically feel it whenever we find ourselves in families, schools,

amongst feuding friends, and in the clutches of the disciplinary State.

Though there isn’t space to lay out a specifically anarchist conception

of power here; emergence and social systems provide some interesting

directions in that effort for integrating power into the core of our

thinking and work. Power traditionally had been thought of as something

exercised against people (by political science and sociology), or either

ignored or denied beneath economic foundations (by portions of the

Marxist tradition.) Yet as Foucault[110] and indeed many anarchist

thinkers argued,[111] power is something that is as much an ability as

something repressive. We have the power to do things and powers over

others. Most importantly, Foucault argued that power isn’t simply

mirrored from the powerful through individuals nor merely exercised

against people, but indeed transmitted as a social relationship across

individuals and groups throughout society. Power within society is an

emergent product of social relationships alongside the institutions and

forms of the State, instead of simply a property of the State itself

(and its police, military, and so on).

Emergence can help us integrate these ideas into a broader framework.

The State can be seen as an emergent product, in part, of power

relations throughout society that maintain institutions and hierarchies

of power, rather than simply being exercised by them. The vast

interactions acted out daily by all of us help reproduce the dominance

of the State in reaction to the State’s institutions and actors. The

reach of the State goes beyond its forces of violence, social services,

and propaganda in so far as it is able to be created perpetually out of

the emergent order of our actions.

This also shows a distinct weakness of State powers. If we participate

in the maintenance and construction of power at its most basic level,

it’s both the case that there is a field of struggle (power) and that we

are able to produce different forms of power should the possibility of

systemic change arise through emergent power relationships. Where we

create and sustain State power comes the potential to disrupt. Since the

more obvious displays of State power (police, prisons, and the military)

depend on the reproduction of statist relations, new investigations into

the conditions that help sustain or interrupt power relations could

expose different moments and areas susceptible to liberatory

alternatives and resistance.

Emergence places the power to create and destroy oppressive powers in

our hands, and the ability to construct alternative human organization

for society through emergent social organization. We have then not

merely a theory that explains existing power, but a direction on the

path towards libertarian society. Coming to think with power and

emergence brings additional tools for confronting decisions for how we

move against dominant power, and constructions of proposals for action

in our context.

On a critical note these reflections feed a skepticism towards

revolutionary aspirations for new states. The composition of the ruling

powers will not substantially change the operation of the State itself,

which as an emergent entity is the product of the complexity of forces

producing it, of which its powerful individuals may try to imprint their

will, but ultimately themselves are merely responding to a complex and

adaptive system beyond their total control. Domination is maintained by

ruling elites only through that system in which their will and influence

of course plays a role, but a much more limited one than many believe.

Likewise, this explains how so-called revolutionary states often end up

reproducing exploitation despite changing the people and goals. It is

not enough to merely destroy the State apparatus or its institutions

unless the void of the State can be filled with new forms of emergent

orders that disorganize and replace statist ones. Otherwise the State

will grow from the forces whose activity becomes organized and

coordinated around the functions and relationships of statist power.

Instead, we must destroy both the central organs of repression as well

as the transmission and emergent relationships that stabilize the State

and replace it through new relationships that produce and sustain a

libertarian order. Emergence thus shifts our targets of struggle and

understanding of where the strength of the State lies.

To the connection between emergence and power, we should add a third

concept: cognition. Cognition is where thought and action interact

within the minds of agents. At this point the discussion has largely

been about largescale forces produced by numbers of actors without

delving into the functioning of action. Given the stress on the

maintenance or disruption of order by a multitude of agents, it is

important for our argument to know how individuals come to act in

revolutionary ways, as well as arrive at mental commitment to radical

action. Exploring the connections between cognition, emergence, and

power can offer us a different approach to how liberatory forms of

cognition can emerge. The next sections of this book will explore the

relationships between cognition, action, and power.

Part 4: Agency and Cognition

Political Cognition

In the preceding chapters action, motivation, and mental life were

touched upon. A number of themes are repeated throughout when we look at

human action: ideas, awareness, the conscious vs. the unconscious,

intention, judgements, values, and norms. In specifically political

thought, ideas have always posed a central question: what role do ideas

and ideology play in political action? That is, to what degree do

political ideas motivate? Are they necessary in order to accomplish

political ends? And what function do they play within the causal chains

that produce political action?

There are two pieces to the problem. First, what is the relationship

between simple thought and action? Second, what is the nature of

specifically political ideas? These issues have often been called the

problem of political consciousness. Consciousness here is thought of as

having overt awareness and intention of the political framework that the

person wants to put into place. Within this framing a division was

formed between those who believed that such consciousness was a

prerequisite for action and those who saw such consciousness as

secondary to actions. Realistically, most people fell somewhere in the

middle seeing it either as a product of action, something that gradually

develops, or a back and forth between the two.

This division is most pronounced in the Marxist tradition due to their

focus on the relationship of ideas to capitalism. Leninists

traditionally saw revolutionary consciousness coming from a socialist

minority, if not from the upper classes, who had the free time for the

study of Marxism and would bring these ideas to the proletariat burdened

by the daily routine of capitalism.[112] Conversely, a broad swath of

leftist opposition to official Leninism identified with alternatives to

this model. Martin Glaberman and CLR James, dissident exTrotskyists in

the United States, proposed the transformative potential of action that

precedes shifts in consciousness in the working class. Council

communists emphasized the spontaneous activity of the class that could

lead to radicalization in practice, even asserting that workers were

only potentially radical within the factory walls. EP Thompson argued in

the Making of the English Working-Class that class consciousness is a

process developed across time in experiences rather than a thing or an

ideology one adopts.[113]

This problem in many ways is influenced by issues within the most

popular

forms of Marxism, where the dynamics of capitalism themselves creates

the working class who are given their revolutionary potential by their

position within relations of production. With workers failing to

consistently develop socialist ideas, Marxist thinkers then wrestled

with a series of models for why this happens. Anarchism came at things

from a different angle as its ideas about class and revolutionary

potential were more open. Libertarians saw radicalization as a rather

specific process of the local context of the revolutionary subject and

involving both the conscious cultivation of libertarian ideas and the

transformative potential of struggle within and against capitalism.[114]

The initial framing itself starts off on the wrong foot, however.

Consider a person who believes in the need to abolish the death penalty,

subscribes to a legislative agenda to achieve that end, has all the

resources necessary to start taking those actions, but never in life

takes up the cause. In the sense of thought, the person has political

consciousness concerning the death penalty. There is the awareness,

thinking, ethical elements, and intent. Yet still, the person never

moves to act upon those. This case is not merely speculative, because a

lots of people do live like this. A number of factors can disassociate

someone’s will to implement their plans: weakness of will, distractions,

alienation, depression, lack of interest, other priorities, feelings of

helplessness, and so on.

In this case, we would not really think that the person has political

consciousness in the strong sense, because they never act on it. The

action validates the mental content of their beliefs, and specifically

their intent and ethical commitments. To will something and think that

it’s the good or right thing to do carries with it some commitment to

action. In extreme cases, if someone never acts at all, it casts some

doubt at least on the depth of belief. It certainly is possible to hold

things one fails to act upon, but political consciousness is a stronger

kind of thing. It is one we expect to have some causal force beyond a

mere speculative commitment. There appears to be an action component of

consciousness.

For these reasons, consciousness is a bad framing of the issue.[115]

Consciousness reduces the role of political ideas to their role as part

of experience as a subject, reasoning, and decisions. Recall that this

is a similar and consistent mistake that came up earlier in our inquiry.

As agents, we come at the world through our experience as reasoning

subjects making choices. Beyond that conscious experience as agents,

there is also an interaction with the world that makes up political

subjectivity.

A better way to approach the problem is thinking of it as a form of

cognition. Cognition is a concept of mental processes. Cognition

involves mentation, but not necessarily always conscious mentation or

awareness. Cognition is likewise connected to behavior. While

consciousness is fundamentally about experiences of phenomena, cognition

straddles the line between thought and thought embodied in the behavior

and activities of agents. Roughly speaking, cognition is a broad enough

concept to let us get at the problem looking at the experiences,

awareness, and activity of agents. Political cognition is a series of

processes both conscious and unconscious (or exhibited) through

patterned activity and mental content. It is the synthesis of internal

life that is acted out.

With the death penalty example, consider now an activist who does

participate in associated activity, such as letters to senators,

rallies, reading publications, and so on. We have a few components.

There are the person’s convictions about what constitutes undue killing,

the role of society and prisons, beliefs about justice, and alternatives

to dealing with criminals. These constitute the normative and ethical

states associated with the ideas. Additionally, there are ideas about

how changes might occur, actions that are warranted, and the beliefs

that make up the implementation of their vision. Lastly, there are the

activities themselves that both reflect the thinking and are themselves

a component of what it means to hold such beliefs and convictions.

Political cognition then is a systematic relationship between thought,

activity, and values in an agent. Here the previous discussion helps us

understand how it develops. In a certain respect it is no different from

how people come to form ideas in general. Taken another way, political

cognition is a very particular sort of facet of mental life. It isn’t

simply ethical positions, because within it, it contains both an

analysis of the existing social world and certain practical commitments

to changing it. Likewise, it’s not merely a series of practices because

of the necessary ethical commitments and beliefs inherent. There appears

to be two factors bearing down on the situation.

First, there is mental life and the thinking of the individual.

Reflection on the death penalty certainly has a role to play in bringing

the agent to act, form beliefs, and maintain various desires and

intensions. Reflection can change behavior, alter beliefs, and bring

about new forms of thought and relationships to others. This is evident

in simple ways. If I find myself biting my nails unconsciously, becoming

aware of that fact can allow me to stop my behavior. It’s also true of

larger scale beliefs. Consider people watching television in the

1950s who witnessed the brutal repression of civil rights activists by

State and mob violence. The overt awareness of brutality and repression

made conscious by the perception of the images of violence led to

changes regarding segregation and racism in some.[116] Conscious beliefs

like “the world is round,” “capitalism is wrong,” or “this world is an

illusion,” can have a deep influence on the course of history. Occupy’s

“1% versus the 99%” certainly had, in whatever complicated scheme we

want to cook up, a causal effect on the events of history. Thoughts can

make things happen. The act of reflection certainly can then have the

power to transform tacit beliefs, values, and ideology alongside

behavior.

Second, there is the force of history acting upon individuals. Our

thinking often is changed not by our conscious reflection, but rather by

the imposition of external forces on our minds. Advertising is a

particularly obvious example of this. Many of the cultural associations

with smoking (relaxation, rebellion, being hip, and so on) are directly

related to the interventions of the industry through advertisement.

Typically, people did not think they would start smoking to be cool.

Unconscious elements can shift people’s motivational states without

their awareness. Or consider the role that the illness of a loved one

plays in changing people’s beliefs about right and wrong. The TV show

Breaking Bad immortalized this example through the protagonist, who

turns to the underworld of the drug economy to fund his chemotherapy

when he finds no other options. Faced with utter deprivation, many

people come to re-evaluate the morality of using whatever means at their

disposal to help their loved ones, though this is typically not through

issues so explicitly reasoned out.

In the world of politics, a riot is yet another example of these

external forces apparently acting upon cognition rather than the other

way around. Whatever the process is of the readiness to riot, it is

largely facts about the situation and crowd that tell us about a riot,

rather than the explicit conscious reasoning of individuals—though this

isn’t to diminish the role of the deliberate aspect of rioting. In most

riots, the actions of the rioters likely go against whatever conscious

political beliefs the individuals hold. Perhaps some rioters are

ideologically prepared to wage urban warfare for their cause, but for

the majority this is likely not the case except in exceptional

historical moments of prolonged social war. For the purposes of

argument, consider only those who act against their political beliefs

based on the force of the moment to draw a lesson. This is where,

historically, the division has been laid. Is cognition a distraction

while the real forces that move political action are objective facts

about societies in conflict? Without overt cognition will change forever

be displaced by deception, recuperation, and inertia? There is a

parallel gap between social emergent forces and agency in the realm of

political cognition, just as with power, action, and motivation.

Thoughts

Whatever theory we desire should capture these facts then: conscious

reflection can cause political changes in the world, and largescale

forces sometimes act against the apparent thinking of political agents.

The first piece of the puzzle is to question the conceptualization of

thoughts. In much discussion of political ideas, thoughts are considered

as timeless entities that can appear and disappear at will. There’s a

logic to this. You can think the same thing I’m thinking (more or less)

and these thoughts can be thought of whenever we like. I can think, “I

like kittens,” a hundred times over any day of the year I like, and you

can think it too.

This is a limited picture of human thinking, however. Thoughts are not

only passing elements that catch our eye like magnificent clouds that

blow through at random. Thoughts are more like a continuous stream, each

feeding into one another, and all bound together in an enormous thread

stretching back into time. Thoughts have history. My love of kittens is

a complete entity, but it is tied to a number of other thoughts,

experiences, and concrete physical things in the world. There are the

pleasures I’ve experienced, thoughts I’ve had about myself, and the

kinds of things I like, e.g. kittens, books, and so on. Thoughts

themselves reflect facts about the world, my own history, and my

conscious relationship to my memories/experiences/self-conceptions.

It’s perceivable when we consider the difference between two people in

the 1950s—a Southern white and a foreigner who think “segregation is

wrong,” that there is a similarity between the two thoughts, yet

relevant to understanding the thoughts in the two people is an

understanding of the history of the person in relation to their thought,

and the relationship of that person to the history of the world they

exist in. The white Southerner came to have that thought in a different

way than the foreigner, and the meaning (both in terms of significance

and literal meaning) of the thought is different.

By understanding thoughts as historical entities, acted upon by physical

and social forces, we begin to dissolve the apparent fork between

thought and action in the political domain. This is because political

cognition is an emergent product of the interaction of individuals with

their political world. That is that the cognitive states of individuals

emerge out of complex systemic interactions between agents, their

biology, and emergent forces in the world on a number of levels

(interpersonal, social, and high level emergent structures). These

thoughts do not stand outside of that causal world, however. Thoughts

themselves create changes within agents that then create shifts in the

world.

The problem with cruder ideas about this is that it is difficult to

conceive how shifts in thinking can have such force. Reflect on the

earlier discussion of people being motivated to follow through with

their ideas. It is clear that there are gaps between thought and action,

internal life and weight of force on our whole beings. Recall the

concepts of disproportionate causation and equilibrium from emergence.

Our naive view of causality is that of billiard balls hitting each other

and creating observable and measurable shifts. Most causation isn’t like

this, and especially not our thoughts. Throwing a ball into a hurricane

produces a different trajectory of the ball than on a windless day.

Thoughts likewise have different causal impact based on the total

context they act upon (if they become instantiated). Anti-militarist

actions during World War I had a different context than during the

Vietnam War. Our thoughts are filtered through a specific social context

of action (and the experiences of the agent previously), and have their

effect based on their place both within us and history.

Our thoughts are then emergent products of history, and likewise history

is partly an emergent product of our thoughts. Seeing this as a system

that grows and adapts with emergent properties gets us out of the

chicken or the egg analogy that plagued much thinking on the matter.

People fought segregation both because of changes in their political

cognition and their political cognition changed because of changes

within society (and later with their actions). The concept of cognition

itself helps us understand this by providing a relation between thought

and action. Rather than seeing them as wholly separate entities acting

on each other, cognition shows us the way in which our agency and

consciousness is systemic and constantly changing in parallel with and

as a part of the world. We are responding to the world and at the same

time creating new worlds, with our thinking and action transforming and

representing these facts at the same time. We hold these relations to

ourselves as well as to others and the world.

Note that power is key within this dynamic. In the last chapter, we saw

that power functions as an internal experience, sets of abilities,

relations between agents, and as an emergent force between groups. That

form, power’s ability to move between levels and spheres, is reflected

in political cognition. Existing channels, networks, and transmissions

of power form roads that our cognition travels down and acts upon. In

many ways, power relationships are the basic building blocks of society,

though fluid ones that are constantly being recreated.

Our mental life flows along these webs of power, changing them,

responding to them, and recreating power both internally and in our

social relations. So people do not support democracy or monarchy because

of timeless abstract considerations. People come to consider such issues

because there are a series of channels that they interact with in

society: people discuss them; there are institutions and organs that

project them; they have experiences with emergent power structures; and

they reflect on the various intersections of these facts in their life.

Power is at the center of political cognition, because it is a force

that shapes and guides the way our thought flows and is the ultimate

underlying field of struggle. There is a key to understanding political

cognition in power.

Liberatory Cognition: The Weight of the Present Against the Future

The problem of political cognition then is ill-framed, placed in a trap

of false dichotomies. Armed with emergence, we see the problem is not

how cognition and ideology have a role in the abstract, but rather what

role? The real problem for libertarians lies in understanding critical

cognition or political cognition applied against the existing order.

Specifically, when looking at a critique not simply of elements of

society, but rather a systemic critique of the fundamental

socio-political order present society is founded on. How is it that such

a society could be dismantled in spite of the fact that an overwhelming

majority of people do not have such political cognition? With people

living and thinking the way they are, how is a transformation possible?

There are many aspects to these issues, but let us take them up from the

perspective of the cognitive element.

It can seem unlikely that the majority of people could become

consciously revolutionary in the present conditions. The world we

inhabit isn’t one that pushes people automatically to radically embrace

a fundamentally new social order. The opposite is true. Elaborate and

exhaustive resources are brought to bear on the entire population to

contest and ensure the direction and habits of people’s thinking and

actions. The State and capital control information networks, education,

and have massive resources for intervening to prevent the spread of

radical ideas even without directly dictating content or needing to

coerce obedience. Foucault’s later lectures tried to map out the shift

towards the modern State and techniques of governance along these

lines.[117] The potency of the State stretches far beyond its immediate

functionaries, police, and soldiers through its adoption of large

sectors of social life that previously were provided by the community or

voluntary activity of organizations. State funding and carefully

cultivating relationships of permission, privilege, and punishment for

political opposition penetrate daily life through the organs of

organized social activity. Our schools are built around their

priorities. Churches are regulated and given special status for owning

property and exemption from taxes in the United States, thereby creating

relationships of dependency and implied consequences for

opposition.[118] The media consistently reproduces the limits of debate

in line with the interests of the powerful without needing any central

censure.[119] When there are breakdowns in the unity of social

institutions behind the State, there is infrastructure that puts limited

reforms on the table. The system can repress (and will), but it can also

integrate and internalize oppositions and demands through responding to

the needs of its opponents.

This may seem innocuous. Logically, any society would seek to reflect

and consciously reproduce its values and structural bases. States are

not different. For the critical libertarian thinker, the problem is

different. In broad brush strokes, the critical thinker identifies

exploitation and oppression as the core of systemic critique. Yet it is

precisely authority and hierarchical relationships that are reproduced,

engineered, and guarded by the forces of power acting on society. This

occurs not only through official institutions of power like prisons,

schools, military, police, and political parties, but also through other

institutionalized sites of ideological reproduction like think-tanks,

the institutionalized left and right, academia, hospitals and mental

health facilities, workplaces, and neighborhood organizations.

Workplaces are engineered for social control not only of the behavior of

workers, but also of their thoughts. Media is constructed around the

ideology, finance, and control of the perspectives of the various

factions of dominating power. More than institutions imposing this upon

us, we see immense networks of social relationships that in subtle ways

transmit and reproduce authority, hierarchy, and oppressive social

relationships throughout society. Families, churches, hospitals,

prisons, schools, and daily life are richly decorated with all the marks

of power and ideology being transmitted through our interactions and

thoughts. How we break from this, not just as individuals, but as a

whole society, is a profound problem and proves even more problematic

for people working towards a more libertarian society. That is, how can

huge numbers of people voluntarily shift not only their thinking, but

also come to act against immense powers?

Yet if a majority of people aren’t committed to liberatory struggle and

society, it doesn’t seem possible (or desirable) that a minority could

impose revolutionary change on an unwilling majority. It is not possible

because society would not be libertarian if it were imposed, and

unlikely simply because dismantling hierarchical power seems to require

a component of intentional collective action. A new society must be

constructed, and the freedom and equality that libertarians seek require

the active creativity and effort that can only come from the dedication

of countless individuals, rather than the watchful labor under gun,

whip, camera, or other means of economic and political coercion. There

is no trick, no institution, nor any daring act that could guarantee

this.

If society must be rebuilt on a freer and more equal basis, it implies a

great deal of thought and voluntary activity. This is the same voluntary

activity that seems so difficult today in light of authoritarian social

relations and ideology. Here we have a tension: the need for

transformation and the emergent social forces working to maintain an

equilibrium in society that prevents the spread of such cognition. This

tension often led people to seek shortcuts through putsches, imposition

of new social orders, or the magical thinking of fate. Malatesta warned

against believing that a mere victory by political activists could bring

about a free society.

We have undertaken the task of struggling against existing social

organization, and of overcoming the obstacles to the advent of a new

society in which freedom and wellbeing would be assured to everybody. To

achieve this objective, we organize ourselves and seek to become as

numerous and as strong as possible. But if it were only our anarchist

groupings that were organized; if the workers were to remain isolated

like so many units unconcerned about each other and only linked by the

common chain; if we ourselves besides being organized as anarchists in a

federation, were not as workers organized with other workers, we could

achieve nothing at all, or at most, we might be able to impose

ourselves...and then it would not be the triumph of anarchism, but our

triumph. We could then go on calling ourselves anarchists, but in

reality we should simply be rulers, and as impotent as all rulers are

where the general good is concerned.[120]

Space for Criticism

One reply to that tension is to look to ruptures or extreme political

events. Sometimes the course of historical events can sweep up whole

societies, and changes in conditions can open up spaces. Societies in

crisis lose equilibrium, disorder increases, and cognitive space is

available to question fundamental elements of society that were normally

assumed to be functional and necessary. Certainly, some of those

environments may facilitate transformations of some sort or another.

Looking for alternatives as systems lose political credibility could

lead to people seeking out liberatory possibilities. This may be a

partial answer to these issues as it identifies spaces where such

transformations might or might not occur.

It’s important to recognize other alternative courses. Similar

environments, breakdowns in the ability of ruling powers to rule, also

open space for deeply repressive and authoritarian potentials, or more

innocuously for forms of reformism that reshape society to address

immediate needs, while leaving the fundamental social ills intact. All

the failures of the social struggles of the 19^(th) and 20^(th)

centuries suggest the dangers and limits of history simply delivering

liberatory cognition. Ruptures may provide some special opportunities,

but also may provide dangers without guarantees. Fascism in Germany

arose in the country perhaps with the largest and most organized

socialist left. Likewise, the Great Depression in the United States

built up a long-term momentum to save capitalism via the New Deal and

the Second World War, which created one of the most sustained periods of

capitalist regrowth in history. To avoid dystopian futures or getting

merely channeled into new circuits for capitalism and power, we need to

look further.

Reflect on what a rupture is. A rupture, in political terms, is some

kind of fundamental break or explosion from the dominant order of how

struggles normally happen. We could say more, but the key aspect here is

that a rupture is a sharp shift. It’s surprising. You go from A to Z in

a sense. Ruptures exhibit emergent behavior in which the situation is

not easily traceable to the individuals in the moment or in previous

moments. If it is discernible, it’s only in retrospect and it is largely

rough and speculative.

A political strategy that relies on waiting for such moments faces an

epistemological problem brought to light by emergence. We don’t have a

good way of knowing what leads up to these events, knowing when they

occur (except in more grand exhibitions), or even understanding the

processes within them. Complexity and action at a series of different

levels of analysis limit our thinking as protagonists. We’re coming at

political struggle as people trying to figure out what to do. Ruptures

do not greet us that way. Ruptures are complex phenomena existing across

different planes—political whirlwinds.

A few things can be taken from both this and the preceding discussion in

this text. We don’t know in what way our present actions will or won’t

contribute to any potential situation that might give us opportunities.

This means that there is no neutral position regarding activity outside

ruptures. Waiting for them, trying to create them, or step-by-step

trying to walk towards liberation all have their own outcomes, though

not easily predictable ones. We can make good assessments and plans as

agents from our limited perspective, while recognizing we will not

necessarily be in positions to understand our place in history along the

way. The best way to view this scenario is that we do our best to find

ways to intervene, reflect, and adjust to our environment with humility.

Awaiting ruptures is one form of action; a form that may actually

prevent some ruptures from occurring that might otherwise have taken

place, and can impair us from responding should they occur. That is,

alongside an understanding of potentials from any historical moment

(ruptures or otherwise), we need an active understanding of our agency.

It’s worth saying that our actions in more difficult mundane situations

carry not only the potential loss of opportunities, but hidden dark

alternatives as well. Failing to take the right course of action

day-to-day may also put us into positions in which when opportunities

arise, we find ourselves organized against them. This is why in many

instances forces of the left, such as many unions, political parties,

and NGOs, find themselves opposed to combative social movements—having

rooted themselves in the power relations of existing capitalism, they

become thrown off balance when the dividing lines shift. That can push

forces for progress into conservative or even reactionary roles in

radical political events. Indeed, the early history of fascist movements

was filled with socialists, Marxists, and some anarchists forming their

first militants in the face of what would become a world revolutionary

wave surrounding the events of 19161921. History is filled with radical

oppositions become ruling tyrants—a historical hangover that haunts us

today in places like Cuba, South Africa, India, and China.

Next, the inherent dangers within the breakdown of social order mean

that our forces are not merely up against a single unified oppositional

order, but rather they are up against an infinite set of potential

opposing, supporting, and overlapping forces that may or may not be

generated from struggles unfolding. This is different from a conception

of history in which the forces of good do battle with the forces of evil

to set the stage for a new humanity. Actions produce new forces and new

questions that we cannot anticipate based on our position both as

sentient beings and within the complex networks of social systems that

we grow and adapt to. There is not then a linear march against the

present order, nor is there any safety in its destruction. Victory is

uncertain (especially in an era of ecological devastation), and any

belief that we can just go forward and maintain ourselves intact through

small struggles is hopelessly naive. The best we can do is set out

towards the libertarian alternative responding as best we can along the

way.

Another way of conceiving the cognitive transformation necessary for

libertarian society is through shifting conditions for the growth of

libertarian thought. While we may not globally be able to dismantle the

reproduction of authoritarian ideology, this does not mean that there

are not factors (nodes, points, and relationships) that we can contest

and change. Ruptures are examples of largescale openings, but

small-scale ones exist as well and likely are more important in creating

the conditions in which libertarian forces could grow, sustain, and

reproduce. Consider the “I am the 99%” meme where individuals uploaded

photos of themselves with a sign describing their troubles and the

phrase “I am the 99%”. People came to take up, develop, and reproduce

the meme as a series of images linking their experiences with features

of the system. Through relationships of art, social media, design, and

sharing, new forms of cognition were being transformed and transmitted

through huge numbers of people relatively rapidly. In a way, this was

part of a rupture. Yet the example is tangible and proximate in a way

that speaks to more run-of-the-mill questions. That reflection of

others’ lives that speaks to the experiential reality of millions itself

caused further thoughts and actions as people were carried into the

streets. In infinite ways throughout society the transformations of

ideology occur and lead to shifts that we do have access to.

Ruptures and these transmissions of power and thought then are on a

continuum, but not a linear continuum. Ruptures are emergent out of

countless contestations, reformulations, actions, and reflections. We

lack the comfort of knowing the effect of our actions, and yet there is

also the potential for our actions to have unknown causes, effect that

is far out from where we had anticipated and has at times radical and

disproportionate influence. We live in the realm of those social

transmissions, and within our daily lives and struggles there are

countless places where we may work as political agents to transform our

situation.

Those struggles can give us space for the flourishing of a critical

cognition in a number of ways. In doing so, we put into practice our

politics, and we test it. Additionally, we can develop a praxis through

successes and challenges. Those moments may have an indirect impact that

can resonate in the lives of those involved well beyond the present.

Society is such that seeds planted today in immediate struggles can

possibly become roots that grow forests of liberation. More strongly,

sometimes our contestations can have direct impact on individuals and

groups, and at times facilitate the development of ruptures.

Critical cognition can be thought of as developing through the

interaction

of conscious and non-conscious processes throughout society. This

cognition develops in parallel to activity against the system. Evolving

alongside political action, it emergently produces countless breaks,

transformations, and potentials both at small-scale and large-scale

levels. Thus, the roles of intervention and historical forces are

inherently fused, with agents playing a special, though limited, role in

realizing them. Neither the patient planner can will such changes into

existence, nor can we sit back awaiting that they be inevitably carried

to us.

Fundamentally organized around power as the central plain that cognition

grows around; the task of the radical is to try to root their actions in

their historical moment as agents, while preparing to adapt to an

uncertain and unpredictable future. In this way, we can see that the

problem of liberatory cognition is that of political agency navigating

the tangles of our lives. This poses an alternative to views of history

as being written by a divine playwright versus radicalism as a form of

personal enlightenment.

Looked at this way, the field of liberatory cognition is wide open. We

have much to gain from exploring spaces for the transformation of

cognition. That is, what environments is it most likely to grow in?

Where are places we can challenge the transmission of ideology? Which

actions open up that space? What role can ideas play in interpreting

events and actions?

These are not timeless or universal questions, but rather they are

things to be settled in the lived political struggles of particular

contexts. With an understanding of emergence and power, libertarian

thinkers can set out to open up these channels and create new thinking

and practices around the possibilities for change that stand before us.

Action

Having explored the problem of what revolutionary cognition is and how

it comes to be obtained, other problems present themselves. Setting

aside whether or not someone is engaging in such cognition, we can ask

what it looks like when it comes to have force. How does cognition

translate into action? There is overt conscious cognition, and yet there

are other cases that are more ambiguous— people who do not consider

themselves militants who break from the inertia of the present order and

take action that sets them against immense forces. There are a number of

cases to consider:

lifetime’sindoctrination of the evils of such thinking.

theState, and charges into machine gun fire to bring down a regime.

management, the State, and the union despite willingly and

overwhelmingly having signed contracts not to strike.

There are certainly more examples we could consider. Yet there is a

parallel here between the cases. At their core they involve a specific

type of motivation in their actions. Liberatory political motivation is

a motivation of a specific sort. It is not the motivation to merely act,

but rather to act against the present order (and potential future

orders) in spite of the weight of history, the mechanisms of order of

the present, and the ill consequences of the present towards a better

potential future. In these instances, the actions of the participants

also weigh against common sense of their day and even the normal reasons

for acting.

Action itself seems quite simple, but explaining what exactly it is and

its function has created puzzles that have sustained philosophers for

millennia. To understand how it is that radical situations can come to

have motivational force for actors, we need to understand both

motivation and action.

The first relevant distinction is between actions and events. Consider

the act of urination. On the one hand, someone getting up and urinating

in a toilet is a clear action. Now consider incontinent people who

urinate on themselves. This is not an action. Why is that? It may be an

action in the sense that someone does it, but it is no more an action

than other things that happen to us. No one would argue that my liver

processing sugars is an action I carry out, since it happens whether or

not I like it. Happenings to us may be external like rocks falling on

us, or internal like losing control of our bladder muscles and having an

experience of incontinence. The difference between incontinence and

urinating is that someone does the latter and not the former.

What distinguishes (in part, or at its simplest) action from events is

that there is someone, an agent, who intends to do something or another.

A lot of ink has been spilt to distill the correct formula that captures

only actions and not events, but a rough-and-ready distinction like that

is fine for our purposes.

The common way of explaining actions appeals to people’s intentions and

things about the world. This is enshrined in the joke “Why did the

chicken cross the road? To get to the other side.” It is a joke because

it’s obvious that if the chicken crossed the road, it in some sense

intended to do so. Actions have intentions and reasons to act.

Consider further distinctions. Though all action is intentional, not all

action is consciously intentional. In other words, if I unconsciously

increase my speed on a bicycle in the rain, the fact that I was not

aware that I did so does not change the fact that I, as an agent,

intentionally did so. By accelerating in the rain, I sought to get to my

destination and out of the rain more quickly, and the acceleration

brought me my aim. Conscious awareness of action then is not necessary

for us to act.

Similarly, it’s possible for us to act against our conscious reasons for

acting, and to do so intentionally. Think about the weak-willed cheater

who wishes to remain faithful to a partner, but sleeps with someone in

spite of consciously willing instead to go home. The act of infidelity

exhibits the agent’s intention to have sex, in spite of consciously

willing otherwise. Conscious intentional action is then only a smaller

subset of action, and many psychologists believe it is perhaps even a

small minority.

There are a number of problems that contradict the intuitive idea of

action. First, consider groups. If we understand action via the

intention and reasons of an individual, then how do we understand

groups? Groups carrying out acts together would have to be understood in

some way as the product of the intentions of individuals in combination.

The problem becomes that there is no distinction between a group, as in

a cohesive band of individuals acting in concert, and a collection of

individuals who happen to share an intention.

Take the example of a group stuck in traffic after an interminable

wreck. Imagine one scenario in which there is a group of drivers who all

decide to honk in unison and express their collective rage. Now think of

another scenario in which the same drivers independently honk, and

happen to honk in unison. What are the differences between these two in

terms of agency? One could say that part of the difference is that

groups intend to act together. You could try to stipulate that

intentions involve the method by which they’re achieved. Still this

fails to capture the difference between a group of drivers who honk

together, and a collection of individuals honking. An organized honking

group is one thing. Individuals who happen to honk together or who join

in honking out of anger are different. That is, the group agency has

different forms, and those forms are not just facts about each

individual’s intentions. There seems to be something more to being a

group than the sum of intentions of individuals. Group agency is

emergent and takes different forms based on different processes.

Taking the point further, reflect on the fact that group agency is

supposed to derive from the intention of individuals since this is what

agency is supposed to be about. Yet, often, groups acting consciously in

concert have contradictory intentions. People in the course of the group

act come to take part in a group action, but contradict the group

intention in the midst, and yet remain a part of the group and the act.

For example, consider a band of kidnappers who set forth to hold some

unlucky person ransom. Different members of the band have their

respective roles, but one kidnapper gets cold feet and questions his

role. He is assigned to shoot the bodyguard to facilitate the grab. The

kidnapper then fails to shoot the bodyguard and laments his role in the

act, vowing to have no part of the bounty or take any part in the

aftermath. The robber still engaged in the kidnapping with the band, and

though he lost his intention to hold the person ransom, ended up being a

part of a kidnapping. Setting aside the judgment of the kidnapper (who

would be culpable nonetheless for the crime), we see that it is still

the case that this band, of which the kidnapper was a part, did in fact

take such an action. This shows that group agency can permit

contradictory intentions. This is true to some extent, though we can

imagine that if enough individuals fail to intend to complete the act,

such actions would fail. Still, this case shows how group agency is not

a matter of simply the collection of individual intentions, since

contradictory intentions are permissible. Group agency is an emergent

force that is greater than the sum of individual intentions, and takes

on its own behavior beyond the intentionality of its constituting

members.

The second problem with the intuitive account understanding of action

arises from our understanding of our mental states. Remember that action

was proposed to be about beliefs, desires, and intentions—mental states

of an agent.

There are clear supporting reasons for this. When grabbing a glass of

water, we do need to understand a desire to drink, beliefs about what it

would take to drink such water, and facts about beings that can will

something to be so and carry it out. Part of what group agency raises

points to another lingering issue though: the way in which things

outside ourselves, external matters, relate to our intentions. Take the

cases of the two groups of honking people. Relevant to understanding the

differences between an individual intending to honk, a collection of

individuals honking, and a group honking in concert are not merely facts

about the internal mental life of the individuals, but also occurrences

and context in the world outside those individuals.

If group agency is in fact more than the simple sum of the intentions of

the individuals contained in the group, then likewise the account of the

actions of such groups is more than the sum of their mental states. At

the very least we can say that in some instances we must appeal to

external context as an explanation of action in order to make sense of

it. Or in other words, the mental states of individuals are incomplete

(though necessary). Part of the content of the individual’s mental

states are things in the world. This was indicated by the account of

cognition in the previous chapter. Thoughts are mutually constitutive

states of mental states, relationships, and features of the objective

context that make up the world of the agent. In group agency, the states

of the individuals define the action of the group in a complex and

dynamic fashion not wholly understandable in terms of facts about the

individual alone. Thoughts themselves are emergent, and the feedback

between agency and action in societies produces new emergent forms of

agency.

To clarify we can introduce a number of distinctions to clarify the

cases. Imagine that the same group of people honking in traffic instead

happen to accidentally honk at the same time. We might call this an

unintentional group event, as it is not an action in the sense that no

one intended to do anything as a group. In the situation in which

individuals honk together intentionally out of frustration, the group

action is done unconsciously (without identification with the group).

This would be a form of unconscious intentional group action. When the

honkers act as a group, perhaps a coordinated honking flash mob of rage,

this could be called conscious intentional group action.

In summary, intuitive ideas about action fall short on a few accounts:

mental states are insufficient to explain actions, and understanding

agency requires looking not only at individuals, but also at more

complex configurations such as groups. Recognizing the shortcomings of

the intuitive account yields some points to reflect on. First, action

concerns agents and their mental states, but is not reducible to those

facts. Second, groups can have agency that is greater than the agency of

the individuals. Third, the relationship between awareness, intention,

and successfully completing an action depends greatly on the situation

(the agent, context, and other agents). Without proposing a theory of

action itself, which would take us far from our task, we can assert that

agency is relative, that there are emergent products of the interaction

of individual agents with the world and other agents, and that nonmental

facts are necessary to understanding the actions of agents.

Motivation

Now let us return to motivation. Given a rough sense of action, what

bearing do these issues have on motivation? Like the intuitive account

of action, the intuitive understanding of motivation runs into some

problems. Similarly, we typically think of motivation as being a product

of reasoning and determined by our mental lives. We can contemplate this

as part of a naive psychology of our lives as subjects, wherein the

conscious mind is the driver and our mental life is the core of our

personhood, actions, and decisions. These ideas are not totally crazy.

Many of the most important things that happen in one’s life do fit this

picture. Yet with motivation there are again some key things missing.

Unconscious motivations are fairly obvious. Advertising certainly uses

techniques aimed at motivating agents to act without their awareness of

having been motivated by outside forces. Indeed, when we are so moved,

we feel as though we motivated ourselves to seek out whatever they are

trying to sell us.

In fact, the problem is deeper. The line between what is a conscious and

unconscious motivation to act is extremely blurry. For instance, sex is

one area where such forces are notorious difficult to pull apart. There

are clear cases of unconscious motivation towards sex, such as people

being manipulated into acts because of instinctual sexual desires they

are unaware of. People use flirting to influence decisions in unrelated

matters like when people dress sexy and flirt to land jobs or seek

non-sexual favors from people they know are susceptible. Likewise, there

are conscious sexual motivations in which agents think to themselves

that they ought to do some act in order to attain sex. At what stage is

sexual motivation about conscious thoughts and intentions versus

unconscious ones? Our conscious ideas about someone else influence our

perception of their sensuality. That appeal becomes an unconscious

force, which in turn can influence our thinking and motivation about

that person. The line in practice is quite fluid.

Or take a more mundane example: do depressed people who binge on ice

cream do so by unconscious or conscious motivation? From the conscious

side, depressed people likely do have the thought, “I want to eat ice

cream,” and are motivated by its pleasing aspects in some broad sense or

another. Yet, surely unconscious elements are at play here as well.

Depressed people seeking gratification have connections to such activity

through socialization related to food and eating, advertising and group

behavior associated with ice cream and sweets, and even chemical

processes perhaps incentivizing behavior on some level. In practice the

gap between the thoughts that motivate eating the ice cream and

unconscious forces that push the agent towards the thoughts are hard to

pull apart. This is because those unconscious forces are the kinds of

things that make us who we are.

Our dispositions and motivations as agents are clearly shaped by our own

internal mental processes. Yet at the same time, it is our relationship

and reaction to the world that intrinsically shapes those thoughts in a

feedback cycle. This is true first because the nature of our thoughts

refer to and are partly defined by external things and relations. It is

also true because unconscious elements in our mind may influence

conscious elements, and vice versa. The causal chains between conscious

mental activity, unconscious mental activity, and the world are complex.

They exhibit, in sum, emergent properties that produce motivations and

actions of the individual in a complex and adaptive manner.

This bucks how we normally think about our actions. We don’t think about

the sum context upon which our decisions and drives are produced. One

could speculate this is largely connected to our awareness of our

experiences as agents having made such decisions. It feels as though we

arrive at decisions and act on our own somehow. Of course, there are

counterexamples, such as when we fail ourselves by doing against our

best intentions what we decided not to. Emergence gives us an out

though, because at the level of organization of an agent, it may be true

that our experience of mental life is valid as such, while likewise

being constituted by external factors that mutually produce those

experiences. Emergence should be taken not just in terms of levels, but

also as showing that particular decisions of individuals, motivations,

or courses of action coevolve in the environment in which they occur and

in the relative context leading up to that event.

Such a discussion clearly parallels concepts of free will. While getting

into that mire would take us far afield, it’s worth recognizing that

however we understand it, similar concepts are involved. There does

appear to be on some level a will that has causal power. People have a

mental life that, for all intents and purposes, does seem capable of

causing actions to occur. Likewise, those actions are understandable in

terms of some complicated account of the total of causes that made any

particular action occur. And with emergence those causes must be

understood as producing novel properties, such as wills that are both

causally bound by the world, and containing an experience of what it is

like to be an agent. This debate can become torturous and ultimately a

distraction. The argument here merely requires acceptance of both will

and the causal chain that determines our actions.

A Metapolitics of Motivation

Let us summarize then. Typically, we think of motivation as largely a

conscious reasoned process determined by our mental lives. Our decisions

based on motivations are thought to be relatively context neutral,

arising from our decisions and dispositions. In the above arguments this

view has been problematized, and an alternative understanding proposed.

In political thinking specifically, we see variants of these views. On

the one hand, it is proposed that people act and are motivated

politically by use of their reason or rationality. On the other hand,

there are suppositions that base instincts and interests drive political

action. Based on the above account, any such distinction should be

questioned thoroughly. The division between conscious and unconscious

motivations is untenable in practice from a political perspective. If

it’s not easily distinguishable how much rational versus arational

processes motivating us contribute to action, any theory that bases a

political program for action on such distinctions will be prone to

getting it wrong.

Next, consider the context relativity of motivation. The death of a

loved one can make some acts, self-destructive behaviors, motivational

that otherwise wouldn’t be. Likewise, politically, it is actually quite

profound that motivations should be relative. This speaks to situations

in which people become swept up into political action when they might

not have otherwise, both in terms of the possibility of such acts and

their limitations.

Taking a concrete example, think of popular attacks on police stations

following the killing of a community member. While conscious reason may

play some role, the interplay between perception, conditioned

experiences with power and police, reactions to the responses of others,

and the scope of political participation all interact to produce a

complex (emergent) situation. Here group agency, emergent behavior,

novel forms of power, and cognition interact to produce situations that

may not have existed earlier and that are not reducible to any of the

individual components. Such examples illustrate the insufficiency of the

intuitive account, and the role of power, emergence, and an emergent

approach to cognition and motivation in helping us to make sense of the

intervention of political forces within concrete circumstances.

Motivation then reflects both the historical context of the actor, the

power relationships that the actor stands in, and the emergent forces

acting upon the agent. At the same time, the agent is bound within a

system with recursive feedback wherein the actions of the agent

themselves can change those power relationships and the context for

action. There can be said to be a complex interrelation between the

motivation of agents, their actions, and the political context.

Traditional political thought, including most of the historic left,

tends to reduce these questions to intention, leadership, and morals, or

negate them altogether. However, the social, individual, and objective

context are relevant for the unconscious and conscious decisions made by

political actors.

Here we can return to the fundamental question of how it is that radical

acts, breaks, and ruptures can come to have motivational force for

political agents. More importantly, how is it that people in general can

come to act in a liberatory manner against the dominant order, whether

in a rupture or otherwise? Like the answers to similar quandaries

throughout the book, the framework laid out shifts the problem from

universals to the specificity of our biological and historical moments.

Motivational states are relational. They reflect processes both

conscious and unconscious within a broader social systemic context. As

cognition is built upon the latticework of power relationships in social

systems, motivation traces the curves of action through the paths of the

mind of the actor, constantly redefining itself and acting within the

social world. Motivation is not then a matter of raw force or raw will,

but rather a matter of history.

Motivation is emergent from the mind of the agent, but comes to be so

only relationally through the reference and power of forces outside the

individual. These features interact, shift, and influence each other in

a constant process. Motivation is not fixed then, but constantly

changing us, changing our actions, and being changed by our experiences.

Utilizing a theory of power and emergence, we can understand such

situations in terms of the social relationships of the agent, their

abilities and the abilities of those they stand in relation with, a

physical-historical context of action, and (emergent) agency produced

via the interaction of agents with the world and each other. Such events

are understood in terms of agents, context, emergent properties, and

power. In one way, we could question altogether why it would be that

motivation would be a problem at all. If we seek motivation to act on

liberatory lines, the problem is not how any such motivation is

possible, but rather how motivation to do this or that act can be.

Emergence and power provide maps that lead us out of determinist and

reductionist thinking and that situate motivational problems within the

concrete forces and moments they occur.

The solution to the role of motivation in liberatory acts is then a

matter of the relation of the act to the actors in the context of the

trajectory of history and struggle. We do not have abstract formulas for

this. Just as with liberatory cognition, the work of the radical in

terms of motivation is to look to the struggles, acts, and actors for

answers. The complexity of living systems bars us from creating

off-the-cuff blueprints for, say, revolutions or even post-capitalist

societies. Still, looked at from this perspective, theories can be

created that help us better understand how people can act against

dominant orders. In what context might immigrant communities in the US

take up struggle directly against immigration authorities? How could

factory seizures become motivational for the mass unemployed in this

country today? Can ghettoized communities repel the effects of prison

society and drug organizations to create a collective neighborhood

order? With a theory of motivation, the steps to take up these questions

within the spaces we find ourselves in are in front of us.

These conclusions came from the investigation of motivation to act that

was broken down into thought and action through cognition. Non-mental

factors and unconscious mental life have a strong role in the production

of motivational states of actors. Motivation then arises out of the

emergent relationship between will, context, and unconscious mental

states within the agent. From a liberatory perspective, motivation to

engage in radical acts does not come from indoctrination, pure reason,

or generalities, but instead is a feature of different contexts and

populations responding to the world they are adapting and responding

within. Here the theory returns to the beginning of the arguments.

Agency and action are activity shaped by the interdependence between an

individual’s role and social forces that are at the same time forming

and formed of our actions.

Post-script

Viewed in reverse, the arguments of this book begin with the proposal of

agency that is constantly defining and defined by a complex and adaptive

social system mutually constituted. Mental life is built not only out of

conscious thought and reasoning, but in reference to things and forces

outside us, our profound unconscious internal processes, and the back

and forth between these elements. We experience this process over time

as historical beings aware of our existence, and recorded in ever

changing memories that are set against our identities and altered in

light of our acts and thoughts. Inherently connected to the thoughts and

actions of others in human societies, relationships of power permeate

our mental lives and make concrete the constantly forming social order.

Power bridges our cognition and the social world in action, becoming

institutionalized in perpetual habits reproduced collectively. Modern

forms of power are built upon this older human foundation, of which the

State and capitalism represent a tiny fragment of our common history.

Emergence provides a view to comprehend and strategize for action within

this global system of living beings from the smallest element to the

totality of social systems.

There are elements of these issues that I didn’t consider until years

after these arguments were already solidified. Some of them have already

arisen or been hinted at in the course of the reasoning that led me down

the path to more extensive consideration. Time is central to the

arguments given in the book because of the role of time in the formation

of cognition. Our experience of acting as creatures in time, and with

time limits imposed by our mortality, underlies the discussion of

cognition, for example. Social rituals and concepts of time are also

emergently produced, reflecting both the dominant powers of their day

and struggle against such. Connected to time is change. Our perception

or ignorance of change shapes how we come to act and how we respond to

the flow of time in societies marked by struggles over power and the

broader human pursuit of better lives.

As with any discussion of liberation, ethics also was latent within

these issues. Liberatory ethics has been underexplored sometimes with

disdain from the Marxist tradition for so-called moralism and desires to

keep a distance from liberal morality. Still the outlines of ethical

issues that could be fruitfully explored are within the text, especially

concerning how motivation connects with values, what role values have in

cognition, and exploring how emergence does or doesn’t impact our values

and their implementation. These are issues I’ve since begun to address

in the years that followed starting my initial manuscript.

While the focus here has been on theory, its worth will only be showed

through it being able to aid work by helping people to navigate the

situations that unfold in coming years. The best that theory can do is

give words to things that were fragmented and on the tips of the tongues

of many, and in doing so deepen tendencies and give them a more coherent

and organized form. The production of theory itself is emergent in the

same way as other forms of human thought and activity, and defined by

the debates, history, and actions of human community and those of us

within it fighting for libertarian society. As we are writers stealing

time away from our jobs and social obligations, the best legacy for a

work such as this is to spur others to solidify their ideas and

experiences within their own perspectives.

Bibliography

Bakunin, Mikhail Aleksandrovich. Bakunin on Anarchy. Edited and

translated by Sam Dolgoff. New York: Vintage Books, 1971. Accessed

February 2, 2016.

www.marxists.org

.

———. The Political Philosophy of Bakunin: Scientific Anarchism. Compiled

and edited by Grigorii Petrovich Maksimov. London: The Free Press, 1964.

Barclay, Harold B. The State. London: Freedom Press, 2003.

Barret, Daniel. Los Sediciosos Despertares de la AnarquĂ­a. Buenos Aires:

Libros de Anarres, 2011. Accessed April 27, 2016.

laturbaediciones.files.wordpress.com

.

Beam, Louis. “Leaderless Resistance.” The Seditionist 12 (1992): 12–13.

Accessed April 27, 2016.

www.researchgate.net

’.

Bedau, Mark A. “Downward Causation and Autonomy in Weak Emergence.”

In Emergence: Contemporary Readings in Philosophy and Science, edited by

Mark A. Bedau and Paul Ed Humphreys, 155–188. Cambridge, Massachusetts:

MIT press, 2008.

———. “Weak Emergence.” NoĂ»s 31, s11 (1997): 375–399. Accessed May 7,

2016.

people.reed.edu

.

Bookchin, Murray. The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution

of Hierarchy.

Palo Alto, CA: Cheshire Books, 1982. Accessed May 7, 2016.

libcom.org

Cappelletti, Angel J. La IdeologĂ­a Anarquista. Buenos Aires, Argentina:

Libros de la Araucaria, 2006.

Carlyle, Thomas. On Heroes, Hero-Worship, and the Heroic in History. New

York: Frederick A. Stokes & Brother, 1888. Accessed April 27, 2016.

www.questia.com

.

Chomsky, Noam. “Notes on Anarchism.” In Daniel Guerin, Anarchism: From

Theory to Practice. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970. Accessed May

8, 2016,

chomsky.info

.

Chomsky, Noam and Herman, Edward. Manufacturing Consent: The Political

Economy of the Mass Media. New York: Pantheon, 1988.

Clastres, Pierre. Society Against the State: Essays in Political

Anthropology. New York: Zone Books, 1987.

Coletivo Maria Tonha. “Fundador do MPL Fala Sobre o Movimento, as

Jornadas de Junho e o Tarifa Zero.” Brasil De Fato, July 25, 2013.

Accessed January 14, 2016.

www.brasildefato.com.br

.

Corning, Peter A. “The Re-emergence of “Emergence”: A Venerable Concept

in Search of a Theory.” Complexity 7, no. 6 (2002): 18–30. Accessed

April 27, 2016.

onlinelibrary.wiley.com

v=1&t=injrzjnu&s=24031294b897aaa50d42864ed8b06ff4ef857bae.

Correa, F. “Crear un Pueblo Fuerte.” In Anarquismo y Poder Popular:

TeorĂ­a y PrĂĄctica Suramericana. BogotĂĄ, Colombia: Ediciones Gato Negro,

2011.

Darwin, Charles. The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection:

Or, the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life and the

Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex New York: Modern

library, 1872.

d’Espagnat, Bernard. On Physics and Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton

University Press, 2006.

Dolgoff, Sam, ed. and trans. Bakunin on Anarchy. New York: Vintage

Books, 1972.

Dugatkin, Lee Alan. “Kropotkin’s Adventure in Science and Politics.”

Scientific American, September 13, 2011. Accessed February 16, 2015.

www.scientificamerican.com

.

Fabbri, Luigi. “El Concepto Anarquista de la Revolución.” In Dictadura y

RevoluciĂłn. Buenos Aires, Argentina: Ediciones Libertad, 1921. Accessed

May 8, 2016.

folletoslibertad.angelfire.com

Fabbri, Luce. El Camino: Hacia un Socialismo sin Estado: En Cada Paso la

Realidad de la Meta. Montevideo, Uruguay: Editorial Nordan-Comunidad,

2000.

Fisher, Mark. Capitalist Realism: Is There No Alternative? Ropley,

Hants, UK: Zero Books, 2009.

Foucault, Michel. Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the

CollĂšge de France 19771978. Vol. 4. Translated by Graham Burchell. New

York: Picador, 2009.

———. Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the Collùge de France,

1975–76. Translated by David Macey. New York: Picador, 2003.

Gelles, David. “At Zappos, Pushing Shoes and a Vision.” New York Times,

July 17, 2015. Accessed December 28, 1015.

www.nytimes.com

.

Glaberman, Martin. Wartime Strikes. Detroit, MI: Bewick Editions, 1980.

Accessed December 28, 2015.

libcom.org

.

Goldman, Emma. Anarchism and Other Essays. New York: Mother Earth

Publishing Association: 1911. Accessed April 27, 2016.

archive.org

.

Gordon, Daniel. A State of Mind. DVD. Directed by Daniel Gordon. 2004.

New York: Kino International, 2005.

Graeber, David. Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology. Chicago: Prickly

Paradigm Press, 2004. Accessed April 27, 2016.

abahlali.org

.

Gramsci, Antonio. Prison Notebooks: Three Volume Set. New York, Columbia

University Press, 2011.

Grosz, Elizabeth. The Nick of Time: Politics, Evolution, and the

Untimely. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2004.

GuillamĂłn, AgustĂ­n. Ready for Revolution: The CNT Defense Committees in

Barcelona, 1933–1938. Translated by Paul Sharkey. Oakland, CA: AK Press,

2014.

Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press, 2001.

Herman, Edward S. and Noam Chomsky. Manufacturing Consent. New York,

Pantheon, 1988.

Hirsch, Steven and Lucien Van der Walt, eds. Anarchism and Syndicalism

in the Colonial and Postcolonial World, 1870–1940: The Praxis of

National Liberation, Internationalism, and Social Revolution. Leiden,

the Netherlands: Brill, 2010.

James, W. “Great Men, Great Thoughts, and the Environment (Lecture

Delivered before the Harvard Natural History Society).” Atlantic

Monthly, October, 1880. Accessed January 1, 2015.

www.uky.edu

.

Johnson, Steven. Emergence: The Connected Lives of Ants, Brains, Cities,

and Software. New York: Scribner, 2002.

Holland, John H. Emergence: From Chaos to Order. Cambridge, MA: Perseus

Books, 1998.

Industrial Workers of the World. “Work-to-Rule: A Guide.” Edited by the

Libcom Collective. 2006. Accessed April 27, 2016.

libcom.org

.

Kant, Immanuel. Practical Philosophy. Translated and edited by Mary J.

Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

Kaplan, Robert D. “The South China Sea is the Future of Conflict.”

Foreign Policy, August 15, 2011. Accessed December 28, 2015.

foreignpolicy.com

.

King, Michael and Christopher J. Thornhill. Niklas Luhmann’s Theory of

Politics and Law. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire, UK: Palgrave

Macmillan, 2003. Accessed April 27, 2016.

dl4a.org

Klein, Naomi. “How Science Is Telling Us All to Revolt.” New Statesman,

October 29, 2013. Accessed December 28, 2015.

www.newstatesman.com

.

Korsch, Karl. “The Marxist Dialectic.” Translated by Karl-Heinz Otto.

The Marxist Internet Archive, 1923. Accessed January 4, 2015.

www.marxists.org

.

———. “A Non-Dogmatic Approach to Marxism.” Politics, May, 1946. Accessed

April 27, 2016.

libcom.org

.

———. “Ten Theses on Marxism Today.” TELOS 26 (Winter 1975–1976).

Accessed April 27, 2016.

www.marxists.org

.

Kropotkin, Peter. Encyclopedia Britannica, 11^(th) ed., s.v.

“Anarchism.” New York, Encyclopaedia Britannica, 1910. Accessed January

14, 2016.

dwardmac.pitzer.edu

———. The State: Its Historic Role. London: “Freedom” Office, 1898.

Accessed May 8, 2016.

theanarchistlibrary.org

.

Lagi, Marco, Yavni Bar-Yam, and Yaneer Bar-Yam. “UPDATE July 2012—the

Food Crises: The US Drought.” July 23, 2012. Accessed April 27, 2016.

necsi.edu

.

Lagi, Marco, Karla Z. Bertrand, and Yaneer Bar-Yam. “The Food Crises and

Political Instability in North Africa and the Middle East.” September

28, 2011. Accessed April 27, 2016.

necsi.edu

.

Laursen, Eric. The People’s Pension: The Struggle to Defend Social

Security since Reagan. Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2012.

Leval, GastĂłn, Juan GĂłmez Casas, and Florentino Iglesias. El Estado en

la Historia. Cali, Colombia: Zero, 1978.

Lewes, George Henry. Problems of Life and Mind. London: Trubner & Co.,

1874. Accessed April 27, 2016.

archive.org

.

Lewontin, Richard. The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism, and Environment.

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001.

Lewontin, Richard and Richard Levins. Biology under the Influence:

Dialectical Essays on the Coevolution of Nature and Society. New York,

Monthly Review Press, 2007.

Lih, Lars T. Lenin Rediscovered: What is to be done? in Context.

Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2008. Accessed April 27, 2016.

ouleft.org

.

LukĂĄcs, Georg. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist

Dialectics. Translated by R. Livingstone. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,

1971. Accessed April 29, 2016.

www.Marxists.org

.

Mahmood, Saba. Religious Difference in a Secular Age: A Minority Report.

Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2015.

Malatesta, Errico. Anarchism and Organization. Marxist Internet Archive,

1897. Accessed Aril 26, 2016.

www.marxists.org

.

———. Anarchy: A Pamphlet. 1891. Accessed February 2, 2016.

dwardmac.pitzer.edu

. ———. Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas. Edited by Vernon Richards.

London: Freedom Press, 1984.

Marx, Karl. Preface and Introduction to a Contribution to the Critique

of Political Economy. Pekin: Foreign Languages Press, 1976.

Mason, Paul. Why It’s Kicking Off Everywhere: The New Global

Revolutions. New York: Verso Books, 2012.

McLaughlin, Brian. “The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism.” In

Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism, edited

by Ansgar Beckermann,

Hans Flohr, and Jaegwon Kim, 49–93. New York; Walter de Gruyter, 1992.

Mill, John Stuart. A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. New

York: Harpers and Brothers Publishers, 1882. Accessed April 27, 2016.

archive.org

.

Nappalos, Scott Nicholas. Towards Theory of Political Organization for

Our Time. 2011. Accessed April 27, 2016.

libcom.org

.

———. The Anarchosyndicalist Contribution to the Theory of Revolutionary

Consciousness. 2009. Accessed February 15, 2016.

snappalos.wordpress.com

.

———. “Ditching Class.” In The Accumulation of Freedom: Writings on

Anarchist Economics, edited by Anthony J. Nocella, Deric Shannon, and

John Asimakopoulos, 291–331. Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2012.

Nocella, Anthony J., Deric Shannon, and John Asimakopoulos. The

Accumulation of Freedom: Writings on Anarchist Economics. Oakland, CA:

AK Press, 2012.

Pepperell, Nicole. “Disassembling Capital.” PhD diss., RMIT University,

2010. Accessed April 27, 2016.

rtheory.files.wordpress.com

.

Proudhon, JP. Property is Theft!: A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology.

Edited by Iain McKay. Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2011.

Purchase, Graham. Anarchism and Ecology. Montreal: Black Rose Books

Limited, 1997.

———. “Peter Kropotkin: Ecologist, Philosopher and Revolutionary.” PhD

diss., University of New South Wales, 2003. Accessed February 15, 2016.

libcom.org

Reclus, Elisée. Anarchy, Geography, Modernity: Selected Writings of

Elisée Reclus. Edited and translated by John Clark and Camille Martin.

Oakland, CA: PM Press, 2013.

Rocker, Rudolf. Nationalism and Culture. Translated by Ray E. Chase. New

York: Covici-Freide, 1937.

Ruder, Cynthia Ann. Making History for Stalin: The Story of the Belomor

Canal.

Gainesville, FL: University Press of Florida, 1998.

Russell, Bertrand. Power: A New Social Analysis. London: Routledge,

2004.

———. Wisdom of the West a Historical Survey of Western Philosophy in its

Social and Political Setting. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1959.

Sawyer, Robert Keith. Social Emergence: Societies as Complex Systems.

Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005.

Shaer, Matthew. “The Boss Stops Here.” New York Magazine, June 16, 2013.

Accessed December 28, 2015.

nymag.com

.

Shirky, Clay. Here Comes Everybody: How Change Happens When People Come

Together. New York: Penguin, 2008.

Spencer, Herbert. The Study of Sociology. New York: D. Appleton and

Company, 1896. Accessed January 1, 2015.

www.questia.com

.

Stoljar, Daniel and Nic Damnjanovic. Stanford Encyclopedia of

Philosophy, Fall 2014 ed., s.v. “The Deflationary Theory of Truth.”

Accessed April 27, 2016.

plato.stanford.edu

.

Tarski, Alfred. “The Semantic Conception of Truth: And the Foundations

of Semantics.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4, no. 3 (1944):

341–376.

Thompson, Edward Palmer. The Making of the English Working Class. New

York: Pantheon Books, 1963.

U.S. Department of Defense. “National Security Implications of

Climate-Related Risks and a Changing Climate.” July 23, 2015. Accessed

April 27, 2016.

archive.defense.gov

.

Wallerstein, Immanuel. “Crisis of the Capitalist System: Where Do We Go

from Here?” The Harold Wolpe Lecture, University of KwaZulu-Natal,

November 5, 2009 . Republished in Monthly Review Zine, November 11,

2009. Accessed January 24, 2016.

mrzine.monthlyreview.org

.

Weber, Bruce H. “What is Life? Defining Life in the Context of Emergent

Complexity.” Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres 40, no. 2

(2010): 221–229.

Winn, Peter. Weavers of Revolution: The Yarur Workers and Chile’s Road

to Socialism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations. Chichester, West

Sussex, UK: Blackwell Publishing, 2010.

[1] Elisée Recluse, Anarchy, Geography, and Modernity, trans. and ed.

John Clark and Camille Martin (Oakland: PM Press, 2013), 233. Taken from

the last chapter, “Progress,” of his magnum opus, Man and the Earth

(1905).

[2] Álvaro Girón Sierra, En la mesa con Darwin: evolución y revolución

en el movimiento libertario en España (1869–1914) (Madrid: Consejo

Superior de Investigaciones CientĂ­ficas, 2005), 66.

[3] Peter Kropotkin, “Modern Science and Anarchism” in Roger N. Baldwin

ed., Anarchism: A Collection of Revolutionary Writings (Mineola, New

York: Dover Publications, 2002), 15556.

[4] William Archer, The Life, Trial and Death of Francisco Ferrer (New

York: Moffat, Yard and Co., 1911), 22.

[5] José Álvarez Junco, La ideología política del anarquismo español

(1868–1910) (Madrid: Siglo veintiuno editories, 1976), 316.

[6] Ibid., 50.

[7] Ibid., 161; Ferran Aisa, La cultura anarquista a Catalunya

(Barcelona: Edicions de 1984, 2006), 78; GirĂłn Sierra, En la mesa con

Darwin, 63.

[8] For an in depth account from a worker-theorist who participated, see

Martin Glaberman, Wartime Strikes: The Struggle against the No Strike

Pledge in the UAW during World War II (Detroit: Bewick Editions, 1980),

accessed December 28, 2015

libcom.org

.

[9] Focusing on cotton workers in Santiago, Peter Winn presents that

narrative arc of the Chilean experience during that period in Weavers of

Revolution: The Yarur Workers and Chile’s Road to Socialism (New York:

Oxford University Press, 1987).

[10] AugustĂ­n GuillamĂłn, Ready for Revolution: The CNT Defense

Committees in Barcelona, 19331938 (Oakland: AK Press, 2014), passim.

[11] The last chapter gives a short overview, but some background may be

found throughout Steven Hirsch and Lucien Van der Walt eds., Anarchism

and Syndicalism in the Colonial and Postcolonial World, 1870–1940: The

Praxis of National Liberation, Internationalism, and Social Revolution

(Leiden, Netherlands: Brill publishers, 2010).

[12] Daniel Barret, Los Sediciosos Despertares de la AnarquĂ­a (Buenos

Aires, Argentina: Libros de Anarres, 2011), passim.

[13] For overviews, see: John Holland, Emergence: From Chaos to Order

(Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Helix, 1998); Peter Corning, “The

Re-emergence of “Emergence”: A Venerable Concept in Search of a Theory”

Complexity 7, No. 6 (2002): 18–30; Richard Lewontin, The Triple Helix:

Gene, Organism, and Environment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

Press, 2001); and Steven Johnson, Emergence: The Connected Lives of

Ants, Brains, Cities, and Software (New York: Scribner, 2002).

[14] A succinct account of emergence within the social sciences is found

in Richard Sawyer, Social Emergence: Societies as Complex Systems

(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005).

[15] Marco Lagi, Karla Z. Bertrand, and Yaneer Bar-Yam, The Food Crises

and Political Instability in North Africa and the Middle East (2011),

accessed April 27, 2016,

necsi.edu

.

[16] U.S. Department of Defense, National Security Implications of

Climate-Related Risks and a Changing Climate (July 23, 2015), accessed

April 27, 2016,

archive.defense.gov

.

[17] Robert D Kaplan, “The South China Sea is the Future of Conflict,”

Foreign Policy (August 15, 2011), accessed December 28, 2015,

foreignpolicy.com

.

[18] Reported in Naomi Klein, “How Science Is Telling Us All to Revolt,”

New Statesman, October 29, 2013, accessed December 28, 2015,

www.newstatesman.com

. Original paper by Brad Werner, “Is earth F**ked? Dynamically Futility

of Global Environmental Management and Possibilities for Sustainability

via Direct Action Activism,” American Geophysical Union, Fall Meeting

2012,

adsabs.harvard.edu

.

[19] David Gelles, “At Zappos, Pushing Shoes and a Vision,” New York

Times, July 17, 2015, accessed December 28, 2015,

www.nytimes.com

. Matthew Shaer, “The Boss Stops Here,” New York Magazine, June 16,

2013, accessed December 28, 2015,

nymag.com

.

[20] Thomas Carlyle, On Heroes, Hero-Worship, and the Heroic in History

(New York: Frederick A. Stokes & Brother, 1888), accessed April 27,

2016,

www.questia.com

.

[21] Herbert Spencer, The Study of Sociology (New York: D. Appleton and

Company, 1896), passim, accessed January 1, 2015,

www.questia.com

.

[22] William James, “Great Men, Great Thoughts, and the Environment

(Lecture Delivered before the Harvard Natural History Society),”

Atlantic Monthly, October, 1880, passim, accessed January 1, 2015,

www.uky.edu

.

[23] Particularly look to Chapters one, two, and six of Michael King and

Christopher J. Thornhill. Niklas Luhmann’s Theory of Politics and Law

(Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003),

accessed April 27, 2016,

dl4a.org

[24] Richard Lewontin and Richard Levins, Biology under the Influence:

Dialectical Essays on the Coevolution of Nature and Society (New York:

Monthly Review Press, 2007), passim.

[25] See Clay Shirky’s Here Comes Everybody: How Change Happens When

People Come Together (New York: Penguin, 2008); and Paul Mason’s Why

It’s Kicking Off Everywhere: The New Global Revolutions (New York: Verso

Books, 2012) for examples of these uses of emergence.

[26] Graham Purchase, Anarchism and Ecology (Montreal, Canada: Black

Rose Books Limited, 1997), 33–74.

[27] Ibid., 111–135.

[28] Noam Chomsky and Edward Herman, Manufacturing Consent: The

Political Economy of the Mass Media (New York: Pantheon, 1988).

[29] This is not helped by the lack of original sources or historical

exploration due to institutional hostility to the tradition.

[30] Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press, 2001).

[31] Bertrand, Russell “Wisdom of the West a Historical Survey of

Western Philosophy in Its Social and Political Setting” (Garden City,

NY: Doubleday, 1959), 7.

[32] Immanuel Kant, Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor

(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999).

[33] Antonio Gramsci, Prison Notebooks: Three Volume Set (New York,

Columbia University Press, 2011), passim.

[34] Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations. (Chichester,

West Sussex, UK: Blackwell Publishing, 2010), section 109.

[35] Those interested for an overview may see Daniel Stoljar and Nic

Damnjanovic, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2014 ed., s.v.

“The Deflationary Theory of Truth,” accessed April 27, 2016,

plato.stanford.edu

.

[36] The classic elaboration of this is Alfred Tarski, “The Semantic

Conception of Truth: And the Foundations of Semantics,” Philosophy and

Phenomenological Research 4, no. 3 (1944): 341–376.

[37] For an accessible overview of some of these issues, see Bernard

d’Espagnat, On Physics and Philosophy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton

University Press, 2006).

[38] I’m isolating philosophy’s contribution here, whereas in reality it

is a consistent back and forth between all the elements and disciplines

of cognitive science driving forward these questions.

[39] Emma Goldman, Anarchism and Other Essays (New York: Mother Earth

Publishing Association: 1911), 62, accessed April 27, 2016,

archive.org

.

[40] Though it is an interesting twist in the story that Karl Korsch

himself came to critique the idea that a coherent Marxist method exists

and Marxism’s role in the failures of the Russian revolution and Germany

post-WWI in his worthwhile texts “A Non-Dogmatic Approach to Marxism”

Politics, May, 1946, accessed April 27, 2016,

libcom.org

and “Ten Theses on Marxism Today” TELOS 26 (Winter 1975–1976), accessed

April 27, 2016,

www.marxists.org

.

[41] Karl Korsch, The Marxist Dialectic, trans. Karl-Heinz Otto (1923),

accessed January 4, 2015,

www.marxists.org

.

[42] Whether or not science is fundamentally about predictions or

whether it is adequate to give better accounts of the past/present and

potential predictions does not affect my argument either way, so I

proceed with this most simplistic notion of science for argument’s sake.

[43] There were certainly other methods such as magical or religious

methods which sought knowledge through appealing to spiritual beings in

rituals, prayers, etc.

[44] Georg LukĂĄcs, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist

Dialectics, trans. R. Livingstone (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1971),

accessed April 29, 2016,

www.Marxists.org

.

[45] Ericco Malatesta, Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas, ed. Vernon

Richards (London: Freedom Press, 1984), 104.

[46] Peter Kropotkin, Encyclopedia Britannica, 11^(th) ed., s.v.

“Anarchism” (New York, 1910), passim, accessed January 14, 2016,

dwardmac.pitzer.edu

. See also the discussion of an anarchist method to post-capitalist

society in Wayne Price’s essay “The Anarchist Method: An Experimental

Approach to Post-Capitalist Economics” in eds. Deric Shannon, Anthony J

Nocella II, and John Asimakopoulas, The Accumulation of Freedom:

Writings on Anarchist Economics (Oakland: AK Press, 2012).

[47] The best of dialectics uses it as a way of looking at problems.

There are some similarities with a more fluid and libertarian approach

to dialectics with emergence. This is not the place to address the good

and bad of dialectics, but emergence could be seen as a possible tool

for people who do think dialectics is useful and want a more rigorous

and usable form of that kind of thinking. All of this line of thinking

reinforces the misuse of the concept of method in some circles.

[48] Determinism was perhaps the manifest destiny of the official

Marxist-Leninist ideologues and states.

[49] Noam Chomsky, “Notes on Anarchism,” in Daniel Guerin, Anarchism:

From Theory to Practice (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970), accessed

May 8, 2016,

chomsky.info

.

[50] The length of this quote is instructive and worth repeating because

it is a strong example against this kind of thinking. Louis Beam,

“Leaderless Resistance,” The Seditionist 12 (1992): 12–13, accessed

April 27, 2016,

www.researchgate.net

’.

[51] For the history of this current of thought see Brain McLaughlin,

“The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism” in Emergence or Reduction?:

Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism, eds. Ansgar Beckermann, Hans

Flohr, and Jaegwon Kim (New York; Walter de Gruyter, 1992), 49–93.

[52] John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive

(New York: Harpers and Brothers Publishers, 1882), 246, accessed April

27, 2016,

archive.org

.

[53] George Henry Lewes, Problems of Life and Mind (London: Trubner &

Co., 1874), 369, accessed April 27, 2016,

archive.org

.

[54] Mark A. Bedau, “Weak Emergence” NoĂ»s 31, s11 (1997): 375–399,

accessed May 7, 2016,

people.reed.edu

.

[55] Mark A. Bedau, “Downward Causation and Autonomy in Weak Emergence”

in Emergence: Contemporary Readings in Philosophy and Science, eds. Mark

A. Bedau and Paul Ed Humphreys (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT press,

2008), 155–188.

[56] This position is supported by rapidly increasing examples of

artificial life models being able to predict otherwise indescribable

phenomena like the path of weather, diseases, birthrates, traffic, etc.

Research increasingly shows the validity of such models for making

predictions and learning about the systems themselves. We can engineer

models that can do calculations and follow paths that our minds cannot.

[57] Though not relevant to the purposes of this text, assessing the

relevance of social and political emergence, there are varieties here we

are skipping. Some forms of emergentism reject both reducibility and

physicalism (the idea that the world is exclusively physical). There are

non-reducible variants of physicalism, reducible physicalism (in matter

not thought), and irreducible non-physicalism (amongst other positions).

At stake here is both what the universe is made of, how high-level

things relate to lower-level things, our explanations of the world and

sciences, and how we understand it. An adequate exploration of these

themes would take us well outside our domain. An excellent resource for

these debates is found in the collection of philosophical and scientific

articles within Bedau and Humphreys, Emergence: Contemporary Readings in

Philosophy and Science (2008).

[58] Corning “The Re-Emergence of “Emergence”: A Venerable Concept in

Search of a Theory,” 18–30.

[59] This is distinct from the discussion of whether properties of salt

can be reduced to a robust chemical explanation of such, which indeed is

more plausible with salt than other examples of reported emergence. It

would not, however, likely explain our experience of salt or the

emergent responses of living systems to salt even if you can reduce

salt’s properties to a combination of sodium and chlorine’s collective

natures.

[60] Charles Darwin, The Origin of the Species, (1872), quoted in

Elizabeth Grosz, The Nick of Time: Politics, Evolution, and the Untimely

(Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2004), 49

[61] Grosz, The Nick of Time: Politics, Evolution, and the Untimely,

46–61.

[62] We could make any number of lists here (adaptation, evolution,

self-organization, reproduction, etc.). This is mostly incidental to the

following arguments, but worth studying for those with interest. From

the emergentist perspective, see Bruce H. Weber, “What is Life? Defining

Life in the Context of Emergent Complexity” Origins of Life and

Evolution of Biospheres 40, no. 2 (2010): 221–229.

[63] Lewontin and Levins, Biology under the Influence: Dialectical

Essays on the Coevolution of Nature and Society, 223.

[64] A more robust account of the physics of moving an object would also

complicate the example I gave of course.

[65] With the case of salt, we could probably produce a sufficiently

robust chemical explanation of its chemical properties based on the

atomic and molecular facts. Still the example is illustrative, so it is

worth keeping.

[66] The failure of those attempts is covered in Erik Laursen, The

People’s Pension: The Struggle to Defend Social Security since Reagan

(Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2012).

[67] See Sawyer, Social Emergence: Societies as Complex Systems.

[68] For an overview from the sciences, see Lee Alan Dugatkin,

“Kropotkin’s Adventure in Science and Politics” Scientific American,

September 13, 2011, accessed February 16, 2015,

www.scientificamerican.com

.

[69] Graham Purchase, “Peter Kropotkin: Ecologist, Philosopher and

Revolutionary” (PhD diss., University of New South Wales, 2003), passim,

accessed February 15, 2016,

libcom.org

[70] Reclus, Anarchy, Geography, Modernity: Selected Writings of Elisée

Reclus, 178.

[71] Ibid., 217.

[72] Pierre Joseph Proudhon, Property is Theft!: A Pierre-Joseph

Proudhon Anthology, ed. Iain McKay (Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2011), 655.

[73] Ibid., 661.

[74] Ibid., 663.

[75] Rocker, Nationalism and Culture, 28.

[76] His collection of writings here gives a good overview: Purchase,

Anarchism and Ecology.

[77] See for example Murray Bookchin, The Ecology of Freedom: The

Emergence and Dissolution of Hierarchy (Palo Alto, CA: Cheshire Books,

1982), accessed May 7, 2016,

libcom.org

.

[78] Lewontin and Levins, Biology under the Influence: Dialectical

Essays on the Coevolution of Nature and Society, 183. The authors here

however mean a more specific type of reductionism that would negate

emergence conclusions. This is not necessary for the argument that

follows.

[79] For example, look at Immanuel Wallerstein, “Crisis of the

Capitalist System: Where Do We Go from Here?” The Harold Wolpe Lecture,

University of KwaZulu-Natal, November 5, 2009, republished in Monthly

Review Zine, November 11, 2009, accessed January 24, 2016,

mrzine.monthlyreview.org

.

[80] These ideas are most explicit in Nicole Pepperell, “Disassembling

Capital” (PhD diss., RMIT University, 2010), accessed April 27, 2016,

rtheory.files.wordpress.com

.

[81] See their collection of essays, Lewontin and Levins, Biology under

the Influence: Dialectical Essays on the Coevolution of Nature and

Society.

[82] A few examples of such are Scott Nicholas Nappalos, “Ditching

Class,” in The Accumulation of Freedom: Writings on Anarchist Economics,

eds. Anthony J. Nocella, Deric Shannon, and John Asimakopoulos,

(Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2012), 291–331. Also see the three-part essay

Towards Theory of Political Organization for Our Time (2011), accessed

April 27, 2016,

libcom.org

.

[83] Marco Lagi, Yavni Bar-Yam, and Yaneer Bar-Yam, “UPDATE July

2012—the Food Crises: The US Drought” (July 23, 2012), accessed April

27, 2016,

necsi.edu

.

[84] Industrial Workers of the World. “Work-to-Rule: A Guide” ed. Libcom

Collective (2006), passim, accessed April 27, 2016,

libcom.org

.

[85] An extended history of such is contained in Cynthia Ann Ruder,

Making History for Stalin: The Story of the Belomor Canal (Gainesville,

FL: University Press of Florida, 1998).

[86] Fisher’s describes the history and situates it well as a more

general phenomenon in Mark Fisher, Capitalist Realism: Is There No

Alternative? (Ropley, Hants, UK: Zero Books), 2009.

[87] The documentary, A State of Mind, provides an interesting look into

this phenomenon in contemporary North Korea. Daniel Gordon, A State of

Mind, DVD (New York: Kino International, 2005).

[88] Lewontin and Levins, Biology under the Influence: Dialectical

Essays on the Coevolution of Nature and Society, 183.

[89] Coletivo Maria Tonha. “Fundador do MPL Fala Sobre o Movimento, as

Jornadas de Junho e o Tarifa Zero,” Brasil De Fato, July 25, 2013,

accessed January 14, 2016,

www.brasildefato.com.br

.

[90] Marxism coined its own version of materialism as meaning a very

specific thing linked to the ideas of Marx. However, here I am using it

in the more general sense that philosophers have used it outside of

Marxist circles.

[91] Michel Foucault ties the rise of the state to the theater of

governing that distinguishes it from prior means of governance. See

Michel Foucault, Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the

Collùge de France 1977–1978, vol. 4, trans. Graham Burchell (New York:

Picador, 2009), 265–278.

[92] Rocker, Nationalism and Culture, 21–41.

[93] Famously in Karl Marx, Preface and Introduction to a Contribution

to the Critique of Political Economy (Pekin: Foreign Languages Press,

1976).

[94] Luigi Fabbri, “El Concepto Anarquista de la Revolución,” in

Dictadura y RevoluciĂłn (Buenos Aires, Argentina: Ediciones Libertad,

1921), accessed May 8, 2016,

folletoslibertad.angelfire.com

.

[95] Reclus, Anarchy, Geography, Modernity: Selected Writings of Elisée

Reclus, 122–123.

[96] Ericco, Malatesta, Anarchy: A Pamphlet (1891), accessed February 2,

2016,

dwardmac.pitzer.edu

.

[97] Mikhail Aleksandrovich Bakunin, “On Representative Government and

Universal Suffrage,” in Bakunin on Anarchy, ed. and trans. Sam Dolgoff

(New York: Vintage Books, 1971), accessed February 2, 2016,

www.marxists.org

.

[98] Mikhail Aleksandrovich Bakunin, The Political Philosophy of

Bakunin: Scientific Anarchism, comp. and ed. Grigorii Petrovich Maksimov

(London: The Free Press, 1964), 253.

[99] Rocker, Nationalism and Culture, 28.

[100] Bertrand Russell, Power: A New Social Analysis (London: Routledge,

2004), 4.

[101] Luce Fabbri, El Camino: Hacia un Socialismo sin Estado: En Cada

Paso la Realidad de la Meta (Montevideo, Uruguay: Editorial

Nordan-Comunidad, 2000). 53.

[102] Clastres was a French anarchist anthropologist who broke from

Marxism to argue that the State is the creator of class and that some

primitive societies are organized against the emergence of the state.

[103] Angel J Cappelletti, La IdeologĂ­a Anarquista (Buenos Aires,

Argentina: Libros de la Araucaria, 2006), 18. Translated by the author.

[104] Proudhon, Property is Theft!: A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Reader,

654–662.

[105] Ibid., 663.

[106] Michel Foucault, Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the CollĂšge

de France, 1975–76, trans. David Macey (New York: Picador, 2003),

passim.

[107] Lewes, Problems of Life and Mind, 340–346.

[108] Bakunin, Bakunin on Anarchy.

[109] A series of anarchists have attempted to answer these questions

historically and anthropologically including Harold B. Barclay, The

State (London: Freedom Press, 2003); Pierre Clastres, Society Against

the State: Essays in Political Anthropology (New York: Zone Books,

1987); David Graeber, Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology (Chicago:

Prickly Paradigm Press, 2004), accessed April 27, 2016,

abahlali.org

; Peter Kropotkin, The State: Its Historic Role (London: “Freedom”

Office, 1896), accessed May 8, 2016,

theanarchistlibrary.org

; and Gaston Leval, Juan GĂłmez Casas, and Florentino Iglesias, El Estado

en la Historia (Cali, Colombia: Zero, 1978).

[110] For example, Foucault, Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the

College de France 1975–1976.

[111] See Felipe Correa, “Crear un Pueblo Fuerte,” in Anarquismo y Poder

Popular: TeorĂ­a y PrĂĄctica Suramericana (BogotĂĄ, Colombia: Ediciones

Gato Negro, 2011).

[112] Some admirers of Lenin dispute this today and are invested in a

textual exegesis project such as that of Lars Lih in his 2006 Lenin

Rediscovered: What is to be done? in Context. Chicago: Haymarket Books,

(2008), accessed April 27, 2016,

ouleft.org

. But in some ways that speaks to the large scale political shifts

created by the collapse of the Soviet Union, and the integration of

libertarian if not anarchist ideas such as rejection of

institutionalized political elites, direct democracy, and a critique of

power within the radical left mainstream today.

[113] Edward Palmer Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class

(New York: Pantheon Books, 1963), passim.

[114] For my account of such, see Scott Nicholas Nappalos, The

Anarchosyndicalist Contribution to the Theory of Revolutionary

Consciousness (2009), accessed February 15, 2016,

snappalos.wordpress.com

.

[115] On the more semantic side, consciousness carries with it spiritual

connotations in popular speech, which may unintentionally encourage

overly intellectual takes on the role of ideas. Framing is only so

important, but it is worth a mention.

[116] This has been often overstated relative to the role of social

struggle however.

[117] For example, Foucault, Security, Territory, Population: Lectures

at the CollĂšge de France 19771978.

[118] An interesting analysis of the secular State’s role in religious

organization is found in Saba Mahmood, Religious Difference in a Secular

Age: A Minority Report, (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,

2015).

[119] Chomsky and Herman, Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy

of the Mass Media, passim.

[120] Ericco Malatesta, Anarchism and Organization (1897), accessed Aril

26, 2016,

www.marxists.org

.