💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › petr-kropotkin-scientific-basis-of-anarchy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:24:24. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Scientific Basis of Anarchy Author: PĂ«tr Kropotkin Date: 1887-02 Language: en Source: The Nineteenth Century, Feb. 1887, online source https://www.revoltlib.com/anarchism/the-scientific-basis-of-anarchy/.
ANARCHY, the No-Government system of Socialism, has a double origin. It
is an outgrowth of the two great movements of thought in the economical
and the political fields which characterize our century, and especially
its second part. In common with all Socialists, the anarchists hold that
the private ownership of land, capital, and machinery has had its time;
that it is condemned to disappear; and that all requisites for
production must, and will, become the common property of society, and be
managed in common by the producers of wealth. And, in common with the
most advanced representatives of political Radicalism, they maintain
that the ideal of the political organization of society is a condition
of things where the functions of government are reduced to a minimum,
and the individual recovers his full liberty of initiative and action
for satisfying, by means of free groups and federations—freely
constituted—all the infinitely varied needs of the human being. As
regards Socialism, most of the anarchists arrive at its ultimate
conclusion, that is, at a complete negation of the wage-system and at
communism. And with reference to political organization, by giving a
further development to the above mentioned part of the Radical program,
they arrive at the conclusion that the ultimate aim of society is the
reduction of the functions of government to nil—that is, to a society
without government, to Anarchy. The anarchists maintain, moreover, that
such being the ideal of social and political organization, they must not
remit it to future centuries, but that only those changes in our social
organization which are in accordance with the above double ideal, and
constitute an approach to it, will have a chance of life and be
beneficial for the commonwealth.
As to the method followed by the anarchist thinker, it differs to a
great extent from that followed by the Utopists. The anarchist thinker
does not resort to metaphysical conceptions (like the 'natural rights,'
the 'duties of the State,' and so on) for establishing what are, in his
opinion, the best conditions for realizing the greatest happiness of
humanity. He follows, on the contrary, the course traced by the modern
philosophy of evolution—without entering, however, the slippery route of
mere analogies so often resorted to by Herbert Spencer. He studies human
society as it is now and was in the past; and, without either endowing
men altogether, or separate individuals, with superior qualities which
they do not possess, he merely considers society as an aggregation of
organisms trying to find out the best ways of combining the wants of the
individual with those of co-operation for the welfare of the species. He
studies society and tries to discover its tendencies, past and present,
its growing needs, intellectual and economical; and in his ideal he
merely points out in which direction evolution goes. He distinguishes
between the real wants and tendencies of human aggregations and the
accidents (want of knowledge, migrations, wars, conquests) which
prevented these tendencies from being satisfied, or temporarily
paralyzed them. And he concludes that the two most prominent, although
often unconscious, tendencies thought our history were: a tendency
towards integrating our labor for the production of all riches in
common, so as finally to render it impossible to discriminate the part
of the common production due to the separate individual; and a tendency
towards the fullest freedom of the individual for the prosecution of all
aims, beneficial both for himself and for society at large. The ideal of
the anarchist is thus a mere summing-up of what he considers to be the
next phase of evolution. It is no longer a matter of faith; it is a
matter for scientific discussion.
In fact, one of the leading features of our century is the growth of
Socialism and the rapid growth of Socialism and the rapid spreading of
Socialist views among the working classes. How could it be otherwise? We
have witnessed during the last seventy years an unparalleled sudden
increase of our powers of production, resulting in an accumulation of
wealth which has outstripped the most sanguine expectations. But owing
to our wage system, this increase of wealth—due to the combined efforts
of men of science, of managers, and workmen as well—has resulted only in
an unprecedented accumulation of wealth in the hands of the owners of
capital; while an increase of misery for the great numbers, and an
insecurity of life for all, have been the lot of the workmen. The
unskilled laborers, in continuous search for labor, are falling into an
unheard-of destitution; and even the best paid artisans and the skilled
workmen, who undoubtedly are living now a more comfortable life than
before, labor under the permanent menace of being thrown, in their turn,
into the same conditions as the unskilled paupers, in consequence of
some of the continuous and unavoidable fluctuations of industry and
caprices of capital. The chasm between the modern millionaire who
squanders the produce of human labor in a gorgeous and vain luxury, and
the pauper reduced to a miserable and insecure existence, is thus
growing more and more, so as to break the very unity of society—the
harmony of its life—and the endanger the progress of its further
development. At the same time, the working classes are the less inclined
to patiently to endure this division of society into two classes, as
they themselves become more and more conscious of the wealth-producing
power of modern industry, of the part played by labor in the production
of wealth, and of their own capacities of organization. In proportion as
all classes of the community take a more lively part in public affairs,
and knowledge spreads among the masses, their longing for equality
becomes stronger, and their demands of social reorganization become
louder and louder: they can be ignored no more. The worker claims his
share in the riches he produces; he claims his share in the management
of production; and he claims not only some additional well-being, but
also his full rights in the higher enjoyments of science and art. These
claims, which formerly were uttered only by the social reformer, begin
now to be made by a daily growing minority of those who work in the
factory or till the acre; and they so conform with our feelings of
justice, that they find support in a daily growing minority amid the
privileged classes themselves. Socialism becomes thus the idea of the
nineteenth century; and neither coercion nor pseudo-reforms can stop its
further growth.
Much hope of improvement was laid, of course, in the extension of
political rights to the working classes. But these concessions,
unsupported as they were by corresponding changes in the economical
relations, proved delusory. They did not materially improve the
conditions of the great bulk of the workmen. Therefore, the watchword of
Socialism is: 'Economical freedom, as the only secure basis for
political freedom.' And as long as the present wage system, with all its
bad consequences, remains unaltered, the Socialist watchword will
continue to inspire the workmen. Socialism will continue to grow until
it has realized its program.
Side by side with this great movement of thought in economical matters,
a like movement was going on with regard to political rights, political
organization, and the functions of government. Government was submitted
to the same criticism as Capital. While most of the Radicals saw in
universal suffrage and republican institutions the last word of
political wisdom, a further step was made by the few. The very functions
of government and the State, as also their relations to the individual,
were submitted to a sharper and deeper criticism. Representative
government having been experimented on a wider field than before, its
defects became more and more prominent. It became obvious that these
defects are not merely accidental, but inherent to the system itself.
Parliament and its executive proved to be unable to attend to all the
numberless affairs of the community and to conciliate the varied and
often opposite interests of the separate parts of a State. Election
proved unable to find out the men who might represent a nation, and
manage, otherwise than in a party spirit, the affairs they are compelled
to legislate upon. These defects became so striking that the very
principles of the representative system were criticized and their
justness doubted. Again, the dangers of a centralized government became
still more conspicuous when the Socialists came to the front and asked
for a further increase of the powers of government by entrusting it with
the management of the immense field covered now by the economical
relations between individuals. The question was asked, whether a
government, entrusted with the management of industry and trade, would
not become a permanent danger for liberty and peace, and whether it even
would be able to be a good manager?
The Socialists of the earlier part of this century did not fully realize
the immense difficulties of the problem. Convinced as they were of the
necessity of economical reforms, most of them took no notice of the need
of freedom for the individual; and we have had social reformers ready to
submit society to any kind of theocracy, dictatorship, or even Cæsarism,
in order to obtain reforms in a Socialist sense. Therefore we saw, in
this country and also on the Continent, the division of men of advanced
opinions into political Radicals and Socialists—the former looking with
distrust on the latter, as they saw in them a danger for the political
liberties which have been won by the civilized nations after a long
series of struggles. And even now, when the Socialists all over Europe
are becoming political parties, and profess the democratic faith, there
remains among most impartial men a well-founded fear of the Volksstaat
or 'popular State' being as great a danger for liberty as any form of
autocracy, if its government be entrusted with the management of all the
social organization, including the production and distribution of
wealth.
The evolution of the last forty years prepared, however, the way for
showing the necessity and possibility of a higher form of social
organization which might guarantee economical freedom without reducing
the individual to the role of a slave to the State. The origins of
government were carefully studied, and all metaphysical conceptions as
to its divine or 'social contract' derivation having been laid aside, it
appeared that it is among us of a relatively modern origin, and that its
powers grew precisely in proportion as the division of society into the
privileged and unprivileged classes was growing in the course of ages.
Representative government was also reduced to its real value—that of an
instrument which has rendered services in the struggle against
autocracy, but not an ideal of free political organization. As to the
system of philosophy which saw in the State (the Kultur-Staat) a leader
to progress, it was more and more shaken as it became evident that
progress is the more effective when it is not checked by State
interference. It thus became obvious that a further advance in social
life does not lie in the direction of a further concentration of power
and regulative functions in the hands of a governing body, but in the
direction of decentralization, both territorial and functional—in a
subdivision of public functions with respect both to their sphere of
action and to the character of the functions; it is in the abandonment
to the initiative of freely constituted groups of all those functions
which are now considered as the functions of government.
This current of thought found its expression not merely in literature,
but also, to a limited extent, in life. The uprising of the Paris
Commune, followed by that of the Commune of Cartagena—a movement of
which the historical bearing seems to have been quite overlooked in this
country—opened a new page of history. If we analyze not only this
movement in itself, but also the impression it left in the minds and the
tendencies which were manifested during the communal revolution, we must
recognize in it an indication showing that in the future human
agglomerations which are more advanced in their social development will
try to start an independent life; and that they will endeavor to convert
the more backward parts of a nation by example, instead of imposing
their opinions by law and force, or submitting themselves to the
majority-rule, which always is a mediocrity-rule. At the same time the
failure of representative government within the Commune itself proved
that self-government and self-administration must be carried on further
than in a mere territorial sense; to be effective they must be carried
on also with regard to the various functions of life within the free
community; a merely territorial limitation of the sphere of action of
government will not do—representative government being as deficient in a
city as it is in a nation. Life gave us thus a further point in favor of
the no-government theory, and a new impulse to anarchist thought.
Anarchists recognize the justice of both the just-mentioned tendencies
towards economical and political freedom, and see in them two different
manifestations of the very same need of equality which constitutes the
very essence of all struggles mentioned by history. Therefore, in common
with all Socialists, the anarchist says to the political reformer: 'No
substantial reform in the sense of political equality, and no limitation
of the powers of government, can be made as long as society is divided
into two hostile camps, and the laborer remains, economically speaking,
a serf to his employer.' But to the Popular State Socialist we say also:
'You must limit the powers of government and renounce Parliamentary
rule. To each new economical phases of life corresponds a new political
phases. Absolute monarchy—that is, Court-rule—corresponded to the system
of serfdom. Representative government corresponds to Capital-rule. Both,
however, are class-rule. But in a society where the distinction between
capitalist and laborer has disappeared, there is no need of such a
government; it would be an anachronism, a nuisance. Free workers would
require a free organization, and this cannot have another basis than
free agreement and free co-operation, without sacrificing the autonomy
of the individual to the all-pervading interference of the State. The
no-capitalist system implies the no-government system.'
Meaning thus the emancipation of man from the oppressive powers of
capitalist and government as well, the system of anarchy becomes a
synthesis of the two powerful currents of thought which characterize our
century.
In arriving at these conclusions anarchy proves to be in accordance with
the conclusions arrived at by the philosophy of evolution. By bringing
to light the plasticity of organization, the philosophy of evolution has
shown the admirable adaptively of organisms to their conditions of life,
and the ensuing development of such faculties as render more complete
both the adaptations of the aggregates to their surroundings and those
of each of the constituent parts of the aggregate to the needs of free
co-operation. It familiarized us with the circumstance that throughout
organic nature the capacities for life in common are growing in
proportion as the integration of organisms into compound aggregates
becomes more and more complete; and it enforced thus the opinion already
expressed by social moralists as to the perfectibility of human nature.
It has shown us that, in the long run of the struggle for existence,
'the fittest' will prove to be those who combine intellectual knowledge
with the knowledge necessary for the production of wealth, and not those
who are now the richest because they, or their ancestors, have been
momentarily the strongest. By showing that the 'struggle for existence'
must be conceived, not merely in its restricted sense of a struggle
between individuals for the means of subsistence, but in its wider sense
of adaptation of all individuals of the species to the best conditions
for the survival of the species, as well as for the greatest possible
sum of life and happiness for each and all, it permitted us to deduce
the laws of moral science from the social needs and habits of mankind.
It showed us the infinitesimal part played by the natural growth of
altruistic feelings, which develop as soon as the conditions of life
favor their growth. It thus enforced the opinion of social reformers as
to the necessity of modifying the conditions of life for improving man,
instead of trying to improve human nature by moral teachings while life
works in an opposite direction. Finally, by studying human society from
the biological point of view, it came to the conclusions arrived at by
anarchists from the study of history and present tendencies, as to
further progress being in the line of socialization of wealth and
integrated labor, combined with the fullest possible freedom of the
individual.
It is not a mere coincidence that Herbert Spencer, whom we may consider
as a pretty fair expounder of the philosophy of evolution, has been
brought to conclude, with regard to political organization, that 'that
form of society towards which we are progressing' is 'one in which
government will be reduced to the smallest amount possible, and freedom
increased to the greatest amount possible.'1 When he opposes in these
words the conclusions of his synthetic philosophy to those of Auguste
Comte, he arrives at very nearly the same conclusion as Proudhon2 and
Bakunin.3 More than that, the very methods of argumentation and the
illustrations resorted to by Herbert Spencer (daily supply of food,
post-office, and so on) are the same which we find in the writings of
the anarchists. The channels of thought were the same, although both
were unaware of each other's endeavors.
Again, when Mr. Spencer so powerfully, and even not without a touch of
passion, argues (in his Appendix to the third edition of the Data of
Ethics) that human societies are marching towards a state when a further
identification of altruism with egoism will be make 'in the sense that
personal gratification will come from the gratification of others;' when
he says that 'we are shown, undeniably, that it is a perfectly possible
thing for organisms to become so adjusted to the requirements of their
lives, that energy expended for the general welfare may not only be
adequate to check energy expended for the individual welfare, but may
come to subordinate it so far as to leave individual welfare no greater
part than is necessary for maintenance of individual life'—provided the
conditions for such relations between the individual and the community
be maintained4 —he derives from the study of nature and the very same
conclusions which the forerunners of anarchy, Fourier and Robert Owen,
derived from a study of human character.
When we see further Mr. Bain so forcibly elaborating the theory of moral
habits, and the French philosopher, M. Guyau, publishing his remarkable
work on Morality without Obligation or Sanction; when J.S. Mill so
sharply criticizes representative government, and when he discusses the
problem of liberty, although failing to establish its necessary
conditions; when Sir John Lubbock prosecutes his admirable studies on
animal societies, and Mr. Morgan applies scientific methods of
investigation to the philosophy of history—when, in short, every year,
by bringing some new arguments to the theory of anarchy—we must
recognize that this last, although differing as to its starting-points,
follows the same sound methods of scientific investigation. Our
confidence in its conclusions is still more increased. The difference
between anarchists and the just-named philosophers may be immense as to
the presumed speed of evolution, and as to the conduct which one ought
to assume as soon as he has had an insight into the aims towards which
society is marching. No attempt, however, has been made scientifically
to determine the ratio of evolution, nor have the chief elements of the
problem )the state of mind of the masses) been taken into account by the
evolutionist philosophers. As to bringing one's action into accordance
with his philosophical conceptions, we know that, unhappily, intellect
and will are too often separated by chasm not to be filled by mere
philosophical speculations, however deep and elaborate.
There is, however, between the just-named philosophers and the
anarchists a wide difference on one point of primordial importance. This
difference is the stranger as it arises on a point which might be
discussed figures in hand, and which constitutes the very basis of all
further deductions, as it belongs to what biological sociology would
describe as the physiology of nutrition.
There is, in fact, a widely spread fallacy, maintained by Mr. Spencer
and many others, as to the causes of the misery which we can see round
about us. It was affirmed forty years ago, and it is affirmed now by Mr.
Spencer and his followers, that misery in civilized society is due to
our insufficient production, or rather to the circumstance that
'population presses upon the means of subsistence.' T would be of no use
to inquire into the origin of such a misrepresentation of facts, which
might be easily verified. It may have its origin in inherited
misconceptions which have nothing to do with the philosophy of
evolution. But to be maintained and advocated by philosophers, there
must be, in the conceptions of these philosophers, some confusion as to
the different aspects of the struggle for existence. Sufficient
importance is not given to the difference between the struggle which
goes on among organisms which do not co-operate for providing the means
of subsistence, and those which do so. In this last case again there
must be some confusion between those aggregates whose members find their
means of subsistence in the ready produce of the vegetable and animal
kingdom, and those whose members artificially grow their means of
subsistence and are enabled to increase (to a yet unknown amount) the
productivity of each spot of the surface of the globe. Hunters who hunt,
each of them for his own sake, and the hunters who unite into societies
for hunting, stand quite differently with regard to the means of
subsistence. But the difference is still greater between the hunters who
take their means of subsistence as they are in nature, and civilized men
who grow their food and produce all requisites for a comfortable life by
machinery. In this last case—the stock of potential energy in nature
being little short of infinite in comparison with the present population
of scientific knowledge; so that for human beings who are in possession
of scientific knowledge, and co-operate for the artificial production of
the means of subsistence and comfort, the law is quite the reverse to
that of Malthus. The accumulation of means of subsistence and comfort is
going on at a much speedier rate than the increase of population. The
only conclusion which we can deduce from the laws of evolution and of
multiplication of effects is that the available amount of means of
subsistence increases at a rate which increases itself in proportion as
population becomes denser—unless it be artificially (and temporarily)
checked by some defects of social organization. As to our powers of
production (our potential production), they increase at a still speedier
rate; in proportion as scientific knowledge grows, the means for
spreading it are rendered easier, and inventive genius is stimulated by
all previous inventions.
If the fallacy as to the pressure of population on the means of
subsistence could be maintained a hundred years ago, it can be
maintained no more, since we have witnessed the effects of science on
industry, and the enormous increase of our productive powers during the
last hundred years. We know, in fact, that while the growth of
population of England has been from 16 ½ millions in 1844 to 26 ¾
millions in 1883, showing thus an increase of 62 per cent., the growth
of national wealth (as testified by schedule A of the Income Tax Act)
has increased at a twice speedier rate; it has grown from 221 for 507 ½
millions—that is, by 130 per cent.5 And we know that the same increase
of wealth has taken place in France, where population remains almost
stationary, and that it has gone on at a still speedier rate in the
United States, where population is increasing every year by immigration.
But the figures just mentioned, while showing the real increase of
production, give only a faint idea of what our production might be under
a more reasonable economical organization. We know well that the owners
of capital, while trying to produce more wares with fewer 'hands,' are
also continually endeavoring to limit the production, in order to sell
at higher prices. When the benefits of a concern are going down, the
owner of the capital limits the production, or totally suspends it, and
prefers to engage his capital in foreign loans or shares of Patagonian
gold-mines. Just now there are plenty of pitmen in England who ask for
nothing better than to be permitted to extract coal and supply with
cheap fuel the households where children are shivering before empty
chimneys. There are thousands of weavers who ask for nothing better than
to weave stuffs in order to replace the Whitechapel rugs with linen. And
so in all branches of industry. How can we talk about a want of means of
subsistence when 246 blasting furnaces and thousands of factories lie
idle in Great Britain alone; and when there are, just now, thousands and
thousands of unemployed in London alone; thousands of men who would
consider themselves happy if they were permitted to transform (under the
guidance of experienced men) the heavy clay of Middlesex into a rich
soil, and to cover with rich cornfields and orchards the acres of
meadow-land which now yield only a few pounds' worth of hay? But they
are prevented from doing so by the owners of the land, of the weaving
factory, and of the coal-mine, because capital finds it more
advantageous to supply the Khedive with harems and the Russian
Government with 'strategic railways' and Krupp guns. Of course the
maintenance of harems pays: it gives ten or fifteen per cent., on the
capital, while the extraction of coal does not pay—that is, it brings
three or five per cent.,—and that is a sufficient reason for limiting
the production and permitting would-be economists to indulge in
reproaches to the working classes as to their too rapid multiplication!
Here we have instances of a direct and conscious limitation of
production, due to the circumstance that the requisites for production
belong to the few, and that these few have the right of disposing of
them at their will, without caring about the interests of the community.
But there is also the indirect and unconscious limitation of
production—that which results from squandering the produce of human
labor in luxury; instead of applying it to a further increase of
production.
This last even cannot be estimated in figures but a walk through the
rich shops of any city and a glance at the manner in which money is
squandered now, can give an approximate idea of this indirect
limitation. When a rich man spends a thousand pounds for his stables, he
squanders five to six thousand days of human labor, which might be used,
under a better social organization, for supplying with comfortable homes
those who are compelled to live now in dens. And when a lady spends a
hundred pounds for her dress, we cannot but say that she squanders, at
least, two years human labor, which, again under a better organization,
might have supplied a hundred women with decent dresses, and much more
with applied to a further improvement of the instruments of production.
Preachers thunder against luxury, because it is shameful to squander
money for feeding and sheltering hounds and horses, when thousands live
in the East End on sixpence a day, and other thousands have not even
their miserable sixpence every day. But the economist sees more than
that in our modern luxury: when millions of days of labor are spent
every year for the satisfaction of the stupid vanity of the rich, he
says that so many millions of workers have been diverted from the
manufacture of those useful instruments which would permit us to decuple
and centuple our present production of means of subsistence and of
requisites for comfort.
In short, if we take into account both the real and the potential
increase of our wealth, and consider both the direct and indirect
limitation of production, which are unavoidable under our present
economical system, we must recognize that the supposed 'pressure of
population on the means of subsistence' is a mere fallacy, repeated,
like many other fallacies, without even taking the trouble of submitting
it to a moment's criticism. The causes of the present social disease
must be sought elsewhere.
Let us take a civilized country. The forests have been cleared, the
swamps drained. Thousands of roads and railways intersect it in all
directions; the rivers have been rendered navigable, and the seaports
are of easy access. Canals connect the seas. The rocks have been pierced
by deep shafts; thousands of manufactures cover the land. Science has
taught men how to use the energy of nature for the satisfaction of his
needs. Cities have slowly grown in the long run of ages, and treasures
of science and art are accumulated in these centers of civilization.
But—who has made all these marvels?
The combined efforts of scores of generations have contributed towards
the achievement of these results.
Our cities, connected by roads and brought into easy communication with
all peopled parts of the globe, are the growth of centuries; and each
house in these cities, each factory, each shop, derives its value, its
very raison d'etre, from the fact that it is situated on a spot of the
globe where thousands or millions have gathered together. Every smallest
part of the immense whole which we call the wealth of civilized nations
derives its value precisely from being a part of this whole. What would
be the value of an immense London shop or storehouse were it not
situated precisely in London, which has become the gathering spot for
five millions of human beings? And what would be the value of our
coal-pits, our manufactures, our shipbuilding yards, were it not for the
immense traffic which goes on across the seas, for the railways which
transport mountains of merchandise, for the cities which number their
inhabitants by millions? Who is, then, the individual who has the right
to step forward and, laying his hands on the smallest part of this
immense whole, to say, 'I have produced this; it belongs to me'? And how
can we discriminate, in this immense interwoven whole, the part which
the isolated individual may appropriate to himself with the slightest
approach to justice? Houses and streets, canals and railways, machines
and works of arts, all these have been created by the combined efforts
of generations past and present, of men living on these islands and men
living thousands of miles away.
But it has happened in the long run of ages that everything which
permits men further to increase their production, or even to continue
it, has been appropriated by the few. The land, which derives its value
precisely from its being necessary for an ever-increasing population,
belongs to the few, who may prevent the community from cultivating it.
The coal-pits, which represent the labor of generations, and which also
derive their value from the wants of the manufacturers and railroads,
from the immense trade carried on and the density of population (what is
the value of coal-layers in Transbaikalia?), belong again to the few,
who have even the right of stopping the extraction of coal if they
choose to give another use to their capital. The lace-weaving machine,
which represents, in its present state of perfection, the work of three
generations of Lancashire weavers, belongs again to the few; and if the
grandsons of the very same weaver who invented the first lace-weaving
machine claim their rights of bringing one of these machines into
motion, they will be told 'Hands off! This machine does not belong to
you!' The railroads, which mostly would be useless heaps of iron if
Great Britain had not its present dense population, its industry, trace,
and traffic, belong again to the few—to a few shareholders, who may even
not know where the railway is situated which brings them a yearly income
larger than that of a medieval king; and if the children of those people
who died by thousands in digging the tunnels would gather and go—a
ragged and starving crowd—to ask bread or work from the shareholders,
they would be met with bayonets and bullets.
Who is the sophist who will dare to say that such an organization is
just? But what is unjust cannot be beneficial for mankind; and it is
not. In consequence of this monstrous organization, the son of a
workman, when he is able to work, finds no acre to till, no machine to
set in motion, unless he agrees to sell his labor for a sum inferior to
its real value. His father and grandfather have contributed in draining
the field, or erecting the factory, to the full extent of their
capacities—and nobody can do more than that—but he comes into the world
more destitute than a savage. If he resorts to agriculture, he will be
permitted to cultivate a plot of land, but on the condition that he
gives up one quarter of his crop to the landlord. If he resorts to
industry, he will be permitted to work, but on the condition that out of
the thirty shillings he has produced, ten shillings or more will be
pocketed by the owner of the machine. We cry against the feudal baron
who did not permit anyone to settle on his land otherwise than on
payment of one quarter of the crops to the lord of the manor; but we
continue to do as they did—we extend their system. The forms have
changed, but the essence has remained the same. And the workman is
compelled to accept the feudal conditions which we call 'free contrast,'
because nowhere will he find better conditions. Everything has been
appropriated by somebody; he must accept the bargain, or starve.
Owing to this circumstance our production takes a wrong turn. It takes
no care of the needs of the community; its only aim is to increase the
benefits of the capitalist. Therefore—the continuous fluctuations of
industry, the crises periodically coming nearly every ten years, and
throwing out of employment several hundred thousand men who are brought
to complete misery, whose children grow up in the gutter, ready to
become inmates of the prison and workhouse. The workmen being unable to
purchase with their wages the riches they are producing, industry must
search for markets elsewhere, amid the middle classes of other nations.
It must find markets, in the East, in Africa, anywhere; it must
increase, by trade, the number of its serfs in Egypt, in India, in the
Congo. But everywhere it finds competitors in other nations which
rapidly enter into the same line of industrial development. And wars,
continuous wars, must be fought for the supremacy on the
world-market—wars for the possession of the East, wars for getting
possession of the seas, wars for having the right of imposing heavy
duties on foreign merchandise. The thunder of guns never ceases in
Europe; whole generations are slaughtered; and we spend in armaments the
third of the revenue of our States—a revenue raised, the poor know with
what difficulties.
Education is the privilege of the few. Not because we can find no
teachers, not because the workman's son and daughter are less able to
receive instruction, but because one can receive no reasonable
instruction when at the age of fifteen he descends into the mine, or
goes selling newspapers in the streets. Society becomes divided into two
hostile camps; and no freedom is possible under such conditions. While
the Radical asks for a further extension of liberty, the statesman
answers him that a further increase of liberty would bring about an
uprising of the paupers; and those political liberties which have cost
so dear are replaced by coercion, by exceptional laws, by military rule.
And finally, the injustice of our repartition of wealth exercises the
most deplorable effect on our morality. Our principles of morality say:
'Love your neighbor as yourself'; but let a child follow this principle
and take off his coat to give it to the shivering pauper, and his mother
will tell him that he must understand the moral principles in their
right sense. If he lives according to them, he will go barefoot, without
alleviating the misery round about him! Morality is good on the lips,
not in deeds. Our preachers say, 'Who works, prays,' and everybody
endeavors to make others work for himself. They say, 'Never lie!' and
politics is a big lie. And we accustom ourselves and our children to
live under this double-faced morality, which is hypocrisy, and to
conciliate our double-facedness by sophistry. Hypocrisy and sophistry
become the very basis of our life. But society cannot live under such a
morality. It cannot last so: it must, it will, be changed.
The question is thus no more a mere question of bread. It covers the
whole field of human activity. But it has at its bottom a question of
social economy, and we conclude: The means of production and of
satisfaction of all needs of society, having been created by the common
efforts of all, must be at the disposal of all. The private
appropriation of requisites for production is neither just nor
beneficial. All must be placed on the same footing as producers and
consumers of wealth. That would be the only way for society to step out
of the bad conditions which have been created by centuries of wars and
oppression. That would be the only guarantee for further progress in a
direction of equality and freedom, which always were the real, although
unspoken goal of humanity.