💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › petr-kropotkin-are-prisons-necessary.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:21:15. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Are Prisons Necessary?
Author: Pëtr Kropotkin
Date: 1887
Language: en
Topics: prison
Source: Retrieved on September 8, 2014 from http://www.panarchy.org/kropotkin/prisons.html
Notes: Chapter X of Kropotkin’s In Russian and French Prisons

Pëtr Kropotkin

Are Prisons Necessary?

If we take into consideration all the influences indicated in the above

rapid sketch, we are bound to recognize that all of them, separately and

combined together, act in the direction of rendering men who have been

detained for several years in prisons less and less adapted for life in

society; and that none of them, not a single one, acts in the direction

of raising the in intellectual and moral faculties, of lifting man to a

higher conception of life and its duties, of rendering him a better, a

more human creature than he was.

Prisons do not moralize their inmates; they do not deter them from

crime. And the question arises: What shall we do with those who break,

not only the written law — that sad growth of a sad past — but also

those very principles of morality which every man feels his own heart?

That is the question which now preoccupies the best minds of our

century.

There was a time when a time when Medicine consisted in administering

some empirically-discovered drugs. The patients who fell into the hands

of the doctor might be killed by his drugs, or they might rise up

notwithstanding them, the doctor had the excuse of doing what all his

fellows did; he could not outgrow his contemporaries.

But our century which has boldly taken up so many questions, but faintly

forecast by its predecessors, has taken up this question too, and

approached it from the other end. Instead of merely curing diseases,

medicine tries now to prevent them; and we all know the immense progress

achieved, thanks to the modern view of disease. Hygiene is the best of

medicines.

The same has to be done with the great social phenomenon which has been

called Crime until now, but will be called Social Disease by our

children.

Prevention of the disease is the best of cures: such is the watchword of

a whole younger school of writers which grew up of late, especially in

Italy, represented by Poletti, Ferri, Colajanni, and, to some limited

extent, by Lombroso [1]; of the great school of psychologists

represented by Griesinger, Krafft-Ebing, Despine on the Continent, and

Maudsley in this country; of the sociologists like Quételet and his

unhappily too scanty followers; and finally, in the modern school of

Psychology with regard to the individual, and of the social reformers

with regard to society. In their works we have already the elements of a

new position to be taken with regard to those unhappy people whom we

have hanged, or decapitated, or sent to jail until now.

Three great causes are at work to produce what is called crime: the

social, the anthropological, and, to use Ferri’s expression, the

cosmical.

The influence of these last is but insufficiently known, and yet it

cannot be denied. We know from the Postmaster-General’s Reports that the

number of letters containing money which are thrown into the

pillar-boxes without any address is very much the same from year to

year. If so capricious an element in our life as oblivion of a certain

given kind is subject to laws to as strict as those which govern the

motion of the heavenly bodies, it is still more true with regard to

breaches of law. We can predict with a great approximation the number of

murders which will be committed next year in each country of Europe. And

if we should take into account the disturbing influences which will

increase, or diminish, next year, the number of murders committed, we

might predict the figures with a still greater accuracy.

There was, some time ago, in Nature, an essay on the number of assaults

and suicides committed in India with relation to temperature and the

moisture of the air. Everybody knows that an excessively hot and moist

temperature renders men more nervous than they are when the temperature

is moderate and a dry wind blows over our fields. In India, where the

temperature grows sometimes exceedingly hot, and the air at the same

time grows exceedingly moist, the enervating influence of the atmosphere

is obviously felt still more strongly than in our latitudes. Mr. S. A.

Hill, therefore, calculates from figures extending over several years, a

formula which enables you, when you know the average temperature and

humidity of each month, to say, with an astonishing approximation to

exactitude, the number of suicides and wounds due to violence which have

been registered during the month. Like calculations may seem very

strange to minds unaccustomed to treat psychological phenomena as

dependent upon physical causes, but the facts point to this dependence

so clearly as to leave no room for doubt. And persons who have

experienced the effects of tropical heat accompanied by tropical

moisture on their own nervous system, will not wonder that precisely

during such days Hindus are inclined to seize a knife to settle a

dispute, or the men disgusted with life are more inclined to put an end

to it by suicide.

The influence of cosmical causes on our actions has not yet been fully

analyzed; but several facts are well established. It is known, for

instance, that attempts against persons (violence, murders, and so on)

are on the increase during the summer, and that during the winter the

number of attempts against property reaches its maximum. We cannot go

through the curves drawn by Professor E. Ferri, and see on the same

sheet the curves of temperature and those showing the number of attempts

against persons, without being deeply impressed with their likeness: one

easily mistakes them for one another. Unhappily this kind of research

has not been prosecuted with the eagerness it deserves, so that few of

the cosmical causes have been analyzed as to their influence on human

actions.

It must be acknowledged also that the inquiry offers many difficulties,

because most cosmical causes exercise their influence only in an

indirect way; thus, for instance, when we see that the number of

breaches of law fluctuates with the crops of cereals, or with the

wine-crops, the influence of cosmical agents appears only through the

medium of a series of influences of a social character. Still, nobody

will deny that when weather is fine, the crops good, and the villagers

cheerful, they are far less inclined to settle their small disputes by

violence than during stormy or gloomy weather, when a spoiled crop

spreads moreover general discontent. I suppose that women who have

constant opportunities of closely watching the good and bad temper of

their husbands could tell us plenty about the influence of weather on

peace in their homes.

The so-called ‘anthropological causes’ to which much attention has been

given of late, are certainly much more important than the preceding. The

influence of inherited faculties and of the bodily organization on the

inclination towards crime has been illustrated of late by so many highly

interesting investigations, that we surely can form a nearly complete

idea about this category of causes which bring men and women within our

penal jurisdiction. Of course, we cannot endorse in full the conclusions

of one of the most prominent representatives of this school, Dr.

Lombroso, especially those he arrives at in one of his writings

[Sull’Incremento del Delitto, 1879]. When he shows us that so many

inmates of our prisons have some defect in the organization of their

brains, we must accept this statement as a mere fact. We may even admit

with him that the majority of convicts and prisoners have longer arms

than people at liberty. Again, when he shows us that the most brutal

murders have been committed by men who had some serious defect in their

bodily structure, we have only to incline before this statement and

recognize its accuracy. It is a statement — not more.

But we cannot follow Mr. Lombroso when he infers too much from this and

like facts, and considers society entitled to take any measures against

people who have like defects of organization. We cannot consider society

as entitled to exterminate all people having defective structure of

brain and still less to imprison those who have long arms. We may admit

that most of the perpetrators of the cruel deeds which from time to time

stir public indignation have not fallen very far short of being sad

idiots. The head of Frey, for instance, an engraving of which has made

of late the tour of the Press, is an instance in point. But all idiots

do not become assassins, and still less all feeble-minded men and women;

so that the most impetuous criminalist of the anthropological school

would recoil before a wholesale assassination of all idiots if he only

remembered how many of them are free — some of them under care, and very

many of them having other people under their care — the difference

between these last and those who are handed over to the hangman being

only a difference of the circumstances under which they were born and

have grown up. In how many otherwise respectable homes, and palaces,

too, not to speak of lunatic asylums, shall we not find the very same

features which Dr. Lombroso considers characteristic of “criminal

madness” Brain diseases may favour the growth of criminal propensities;

but they may not, when under proper care. The good sense, and still more

the good heart of Charles Dickens have perfectly well understood this

plain truth.

Certainly we cannot follow Dr. Lombroso in all his conclusions, still

less those of his followers; but we must be grateful to the Italian

writer for having devoted his attention to and popularized his

researches into, the medical aspects of the question. Because, for an

unprejudiced mind, the only conclusions that can be drawn from his

varied and most interesting researches is, that most of those whom we

treat as criminals are people affected by bodily diseases, and that

their illness ought to be submitted to some treatment, instead of being

aggravated by imprisonment.

Mr. Maudsley’s researches into insanity with relation to crime are well

known in this country. But none of those who have seriously read his

works can leave them without being struck by the circumstance that most

of those inmates of our jails who have been imprisoned for attempts

against persons are people affected with some disease of the mind; that

the “ideal madman whom the law creates,” and the only one whom the law

is ready to recognize as irresponsible for his acts, is as rare as the

ideal “criminal” whom the law insists upon punishing. Surely there is,

as Mr. Maudsley says, a wide “borderland between crime and insanity,

near one boundary of which we meet with something of madness but more of

sin (of conscious desire of doing some harm, we prefer to say), and near

the other boundary of which something of sin but more of madness.” But,

“a just estimate of the moral responsibility of the unhappy people

inhabiting this borderland” will never be made as long as the idea of

“sin,” or of “bad will,” is not got rid of.

Unhappily, hitherto our penal institutions have been nothing but a

compromise between the old ideas of revenge, of punishment of the “bad

will” and “sin,” and the modern ideas of “deterring from crime,” both

softened to a very slight extent by some notions of philanthropy. But

the time, we hope, is not far distant when the noble ideas which have

inspired Griesinger, Krafft-Ebing, Despine, and some of the modern

Italian criminalists, like Colajanni and Ferri, will become the property

of the general public, and make us ashamed of having continued so long

to hand over those whom we call criminals to hangmen and jailers. If the

conscientious and extensive labours of the writers just named were more

widely known, we should all easily understand that most of those who are

kept now in jails, or put to death, are merely people in need of the

most careful fraternal treatment. I do not mean, of course, that we

ought to substitute lunatic asylums for prisons. Far be it from me to

entertain this abhorrent idea. Lunatic asylums are nothing else but

prisons; and those whom we keep in prisons are not lunatics, nor even

people approaching the sad boundary of the borderland where man loses

control over his actions. Far be from me the idea which is sometimes

brought forward as to maintaining prisons by placing them under

pedagogists and medical men. What most of those who are now sent to jail

are in need of is merely a fraternal help from those who surround them,

to aid them in developing more and more the higher instincts of human

nature which have been checked in their growth either by some bodily

disease — anemia of the brain, disease of the hearth, the liver, or the

stomach — or, still more, by the abominable conditions under which

thousands and thousands of children grow up, and millions of adults are

living, in what we call our centres of civilization. But these higher

faculties cannot be exercised when man is deprived of liberty, of the

free guidance of his actions, of the multifarious influences of the

human world. Let us carefully analyse each branch of the moral unwritten

law, and we shall always find — as good old Griesinger said — that it is

not due to something which has suddenly sprung up in the man who

accomplished it: it is the result of effects which, for years past, have

deeply stirred within him. Take, for instance, a man who has committed

an act of violence. The blind judge of our days comes forward and sends

him to prison. But the human being who is not overpowered by the kind of

mania which is inculcated by the study of Roman jurisprudence — who

analyzes instead of merely sentencing — would say, with Griesinger, that

although in this case the man has not suppressed his affections, but has

left them to betray themselves by an act of violence, this act has been

prepared long since. Before this time, probably throughout his life, the

same person has often manifested some anomaly of mind by noisy

expression of his feelings, by crying loudly after some trifling

disagreeable circumstance, by easily venting his bad temper in those who

stood by him; and, unhappily, he has not from his childhood found

anybody who was able to give a better direction to his nervous

impressibility. The cause of the violence which has brought him into the

prisoners’ dock must be sought long years before. And if we push our

analysis still deeper, we discover that this state of mind is itself a

consequence of some physical disease either inherited or developed by an

abnormal life; some disease of the hearth, the brain, or the digestive

system. For many years these causes have been at work before resulting

in some deed which falls within the reach of the law.

More than that. If we analyse ourselves, if everybody would frankly

acknowledge the thoughts which have sometimes passed through his mind,

we should see that all of us have had — be it as an imperceptible wave

traversing the brain, like a flash of light — some feelings and thoughts

such as constitute the motive of all acts considered as criminals. We

have repudiated them at once; but if they had had the opportunity of

recurring again and again; if they were nurtured by circumstances, or by

a want of exercise of the best passions — love, compassion, and all

those which result from living in the joys and sufferings of those who

surround us; then these passing influences, so brief that we hardly

noticed them, would have degenerated into some morbid element in our

character.

That is what we ought to teach our children from the earliest childhood,

while now we imbue them from their tenderest years with ideas of justice

identified with revenge, of judges and tribunals. And if we did this,

instead of doing as we do now, we should no longer have the shame of

avowing that we hire assassins to execute our sentences and pay warders

for performing a function for which no educated man would like to

prepare his own children. Functions which we consider so degrading

cannot be an element of moralization.

Fraternal treatment to check the development of the anti-social feelings

which grow up in some of us — not imprisonment — is the only means that

we are authorized in applying, and can apply, with some effect to those

in whom these feelings have developed in consequence of bodily disease

or social influences. And that is not a Utopia; while to fancy that

punishment is able to check the growth of anti-social feelings is a

Utopia — a wicked Utopia; the Utopia of “leave me in peace, and let the

world go as it likes.”

Many of the anti-social feelings, we are told by Dr. J. Bruce Thompson

and many others, are inherited; and facts amply support this conclusion.

But what is inherited? Is it a certain bump of criminality, or something

else? What is inherited is insufficient self-control, or a want of firm

will, or a desire for risk and excitement or disproportionate vanity.

Vanity, for instance, coupled with a desire for risk and excitement, is

one of the most striking features amidst the population of our prisons.

But vanity finds many fields for its exercise. It may produce a maniac

like Napoleon the First, or a Frey; but it produces also, under some

circumstances — especially when instigated and guided by a sound

intellect — men who pierce tunnels and isthmuses, or devote all their

energies towards pushing through some great scheme for what they

consider the benefit of humanity; and then it may be checked, and even

reduced almost to nothingness, by the parallel growth of intelligence.

If it is a want of firmness of will which has been inherited, we know

also that this feature of character may lead to the most varied

consequences according to the circumstances of life. How many of our

“good fellows&” suffer precisely from this defect? It is a sufficient

reason for sending them to prison?

Humanity has seldom ventured to treat its prisoners like human beings;

but each time it has done so it has been rewarded for its boldness. I

was sometimes struck at Clairvaux [2] with the kindness bestowed on sick

people by several assistant in the hospital; I was touched by several

manifestations of a refined feeling of delicacy. Dr. Campbell, who has

had much more opportunity of learning this trait of human nature during

his thirty years’ experience as prison-surgeon, goes much farther. By

mild treatment, he says, “with as much consideration as if they had been

delicate ladies [I quote his own words] the greatest order was generally

maintained in the hospital.” He was struck with that “estimable trait in

the character of prisoners — observable even among the roughest

criminals; I mean the great attention they bestow on the sick.” “The

most hardened criminals,” he adds, “are not exempt from this feeling.”

And he says elsewhere: “Although many of these men, from their former

reckless life and habits of depredation might be supposed to be hardened

and indifferent, they have a keen sense of what is right or wrong.” All

honest men who have had to do with prisoners, can but confirm the

experience of Dr. Campbell.

What is the secrete of this feature, which surely cannot fail to strike

people accustomed to consider the convict as very little short of a wild

beast? The assistants in hospital have an opportunity of exercising

their good feelings. They have opportunities of feeling compassion for

somebody, and of acting accordingly. Moreover, they enjoy within the

hospital much more freedom than the other convicts; and those of whom

Dr. Campbell speaks were under the direct moral influence of a doctor

like himself — not of a soldier.

In short, anthropological causes — that is, defects of organization —

play a most important part in bringing men to jail; but these causes are

not causes of “criminality,” properly speaking. The same causes are at

work amidst millions of our modern psychopathic generation; but they

lead to anti-social deeds only under certain unfavourable circumstances.

Prison do not cure these pathological deformities, they only reinforce

them; and when a psychopath leaves a prison, after having been subjected

for several years to its deteriorating influence, he is without

comparison less fit for life in society than he was before. If he is

prevented from committing fresh anti-social deeds, that can only been

attained by undoing the work of the prison, by obliterating the features

with which it inculcates those who have passed through its ordeal — a

task which certainly is performed by some friends of humanity, but a

task utterly hopeless in so many cases.

There is something to say also with regard to those whom criminalists

describe as qualified assassins, and who in so many countries imbued

with the old Biblical principle of a tooth for a tooth, are sent to the

gallows. It may seem strange in this country, but the fact is that

throughout Siberia — where there is ample opportunity to judge different

categories of exiles — the “murderers” are considered as the best class

of the convict population; and I was very happy to see that Mr. Davitt,

who has so acutely analyzed crime and its causes, has also been able to

make a like observation. It is not known as generally as it ought to be

that the Russian law has not recognized capital punishment for more than

a century. However freely political offenders have been sent to the

gallows under Alexander II and III, so that 31 men have been put to

death during the preceding reign and about 25 since 1881, capital

punishment does not exist in Russia for common-law offences. It was

abolished in 1753, and since that time murderers are merely condemned to

hard-labour from eight to twenty years (parricides for life), after the

expiration of which term they are settled free for life in Siberia.

Therefore, Eastern Siberia is full of liberated assassins; and,

nevertheless, there is hardly another country where you could travel and

stay with greater security. During my very extensive journeys in Siberia

I never carried with me a defensive weapon of any kind, and the same was

the case with my friends, each of whom every year travelled something

like ten thousand miles across this immense territory. As mentioned in a

preceding chapter the number of murders which are committed in East

Siberia by liberated assassins, or by the numberless runaways, is

exceedingly small; while the unceasing robberies and murders of which

Siberia complains now, take place precisely in Tomsk and throughout

Western Siberia, whereto no murderers, and only minor offenders are

exiled. In the earlier parts of this century it was not uncommon to find

at an official’s house that the coachman was a liberated murderer, or

that the nurse who bestowed such motherly care upon the children bore

imperfectly obliterated marks of the branding-iron. As to those who

would suggest that probably the Russians are a milder sort of men than

those of Western Europe, they have only to remember the scenes which

have accompanied the outbreaks of peasants; and they might be asked

also, how far the absence of executions and of all that abominable talk

which is fed by descriptions of executions — the talk in which English

prisoners delight most — has contributed to foster a cold contempt for

human life.

The shameful practice of legal assassination which is still carried on

in Western Europe, the shameful practice of hiring for a guinea an

assassin to accomplish a sentence which the judge would not have the

courage to carry out himself — this shameful practice and all that

hardly-imaginable amount of corruption it continues to pour into

society, has not even the excuse of preventing murder. Nowhere has the

abolition of capital punishment increased the number of murders. If the

practice of putting men to death is still in use, it is merely a result

of craven fear, coupled with reminiscences of a lower degree of

civilization when the tooth-for-tooth principle was preached by

religion.

But if the cosmical causes — either directly or indirectly — exercise so

powerful an influence on the yearly amount of anti-social acts; if

psychological causes, deeply rooted in the intimate structure of the

body, are also a powerful factor in bringing men to commit breaches of

the law, what will remain of the theories of the writers on the criminal

law after we have also taken into account the social causes of what we

call crime?

There was a custom of old by which each commune (clan, Mark, Gemeinde)

was considered responsible as a whole for any anti-social act committed

by any of its members. This old costume has disappeared like so many

good remnants of the communal organization of old. But we are returning

to it; and again, after having passed through a period of the most

unbridled individualism, the feeling is growing amongst us that society

is responsible for the anti-social deeds committed in its midst. If we

have our share of glory in the achievement of the geniuses of our

century, we have our part of shame in the deeds of our assassins.

From year to year thousands of children grow-up in the filth — material

and moral — of our great cities, completely abandoned amidst a

population demoralized by a life from hand to mouth, the incertitude of

to-morrow, and a misery of which no former epoch has had even an

apprehension. Left to themselves and to the worst influences of the

street, receiving but little cure from their parents ground down by a

terrible struggle for existence, they hardly know what a happy home is;

but they learn from earliest childhood what the vices of our great

cities are. They enter life without even knowing a handicraft which

might help them to earn their living. The son of a savage learns hunting

from his father; his sister learns how to manage their simple household.

The children whose father and mother leave the den they inhabit, early

in the morning, in search of any job which may help them to get through

the next week, enter life not even with that knowledge. They know no

handicraft; their home has been the muddy street; and the teachings they

received in the street were of the kind known by those who have visited

the whereabouts of the gin-palaces of the poor, and of the places of

amusement of the richer classes.

It is all very well to thunder denunciations about the drunken habits of

this class of the population, but if those who denounce them had grown

up in the same conditions as the children of the labourer who every

morning conquers by means of his own fists the right of being admitted

at the gate of a London dockyard, — how many of them would not have

become the continual guests of the gin-palaces? — the only palaces with

which the rich have endowed the real producers of all riches.

When we see this population growing up in all our big manufacturing

centres we cannot wonder that our big cities chiefly supply prisons with

inmates. I never cease to wonder, on the contrary, that relatively so

small a proportion of these children become thieves or highway robbers.

I never cease to wonder at the deep-rootedness of social feelings in the

humanity of the nineteenth century, at the goodness of heart which still

prevails in the dirty streets, which are the causes that relatively few

of those who grow up in absolute neglect declare open war against our

social institutions. These good feelings, this aversion to violence,

this resignation which makes them accept their fate without hatred

growing in their hearts, are the only real barrier which prevents them

from openly breaking all social bonds, — not the deterring influence of

prisons. Stone would not remain upon stone in our modern palaces, were

it not for these feelings.

And, at the other end of the social scale, money that is representative

signs of human work, is squandered in unheard-of luxury, very often with

no other purpose than to satisfy a stupid vanity. While old and young

have no bread, and are really starving at the very doors of our

luxurious shops, — these know no limits to their lavish expenditures.

When everything round about us — the shops and the people we see in the

streets, the literature we read, the money worship we meet with every

day — tends to develop an insatiable thirst for unlimited wealth, a love

for sparkish luxury, a tendency towards spending money foolishly for

every avowable and unavowable purpose; when there are whole quarters in

our cities each house of which reminds us that man has too often

remained a beast, whatever the decorum under which he conceals his

bestiality; when the watchword of our civilized world is: “Enrich

yourselves! Crush down everything you meet in your way, by all means

short of those which might bring you before a court!” When a part from a

few exceptions, all — from the landlord down to the artisan — are taught

every day in a thousand ways that the beau-ideal of life is to manage

affairs so as to make others work for you; when manual work is so

despised that those who perish from want of bodily exercise prefer to

resort to gymnastics, imitating the movements of sawing and digging,

instead of sawing wood and hoeing the soil; when hard and blackened

hands are considered a sign of inferiority, and a silk dress and the

knowledge of how to keep servants under strict discipline is a token of

superiority; when literature expends its art in maintaining the worship

of richness and treats the “impractical idealist” with contempt — what

need is there to talk about inherited criminality when so many factors

of our life work in one direction — that of manufacturing beings

unsuited for a honest existence, permeated with anti-social feelings!

Let us organize our society so as to assure to everybody the possibility

of regular work for the benefit of the commonwealth — and that means of

course a through transformation of the present relations between work

and capital; let us assure to every child a sound education and

instruction, both in manual labour and science, so as to permit him to

acquire, during the first twenty years of his life, the knowledge and

habits of earnest work — and we shall be in no more need of dungeons and

jails, of judges and hangmen. Man is a result of those conditions in

which he has grown up. Let him grow in habits of useful work: let him be

brought by his earlier life to consider humanity as one great family, no

member of which can be injured without the injury be felt by a wide

circle of his fellows, and ultimately by the whole of society; let him

acquire a taste for the highest enjoyment of science and art — much more

lofty and durable than those given by the satisfaction of lower

passions, — and we may be sure that we shall not have many breaches of

those laws of morality which are un unconscious affirmation of the best

conditions for life in society.

Two-third of all breaches of law being so-called “crimes against

property,” these cases will disappear, or be limited to a quite trifling

amount, when property, which is now the privilege of the few, shall

return to its real source — the community. As to “crimes against

persons,” already their numbers are rapidly decreasing, owing to the

growth of moral and social habits which necessarily develop in each

society and can only grow when common interests contribute more and more

to tighten the bonds which induce men to live a common life.

Of course, whatever be the economical bases of society, there will

always be in its midst a certain number of beings with passions more

strongly developed and less easily controlled than the rest; and there

always will be men whose passions may occasionally lead them to commit

acts of an anti-social character. But these passions can receive another

direction, and most of them can be rendered almost or quite harmless by

the combined efforts of those who surround us. We live now in too much

isolation. Everybody cares only for himself, or his nearest relatives.

Egotistic — that is, unintelligent — individualism in material life has

necessarily brought about an individualism as egotistic and as harmful

in the mutual relations of human beings. But we have known in history,

and we see still, communities where men are more closely connected

together than in our Western European cities. China is an instance in

point. The great “compound family” is there still the basis of the

social organization: the members of the compound family know one another

perfectly; they support one another, they help one another, not merely

in material life, but also in moral troubles; and the number of “crimes”

both against property and persons, stands at an astonishingly low level

(in the central provinces, of course, not on the sea-shore). The

Slavonian and Swiss agrarian communes are another instance. Men know one

another in these smaller aggregations; they mutually support one

another; while in our cities all bond between the inhabitants have

disappeared. The old family, based on a common origin, is

disintegrating. But men cannot live in this isolation, and the elements

of new social groups — those ties arising between the inhabitants of the

same spot having many interests in common, and those of people united by

the prosecution of common aims — is growing. Their growth can only be

accelerated by such changes as would bring about a closer mutual

dependency and a greater equality between the members of our

communities.

And yet, notwithstanding all this, there surely will remain a limited

number of persons whose anti-social passions — the result of bodily

diseases — may still be a danger for the community. Shall humanity send

these to the gallows, or lock them up in prisons? Surely it will not

resort to this wicked solution of the difficulty.

There was a time when lunatics, considered as possessed by the devil,

were treated in the most abominable manner. Chained in stalls like

animals, they were dreaded even by their keepers. To break their chains,

to set them free, would have been considered then as a folly. But a man

came — Pinel [3] — who dared to take off their chains, and to offer them

brotherly words, brotherly treatment. And those who were looked upon as

ready to devour the human being who dared to approach them, gathered

round their liberator, and proved that he was right in his belief in the

best features of human nature, even in those whose intelligence was

darkened by disease. From that time the cause of humanity was won. The

lunatic was no longer treated like a wild beast. Men recognized in him a

brother.

The chains disappeared, but asylums — another name for prisons —

remained, and within their walls a system as bad as that of the chains

grew up by-and-by. But then the peasants of a Belgian village, moved by

their simple good sense and kindness of heart, showed the way towards a

new departure which learned student of mental disease did not perceive.

They set the lunatics quite free. They took them into their families,

offered them a bed in their poor houses, a chair at their plain tables,

a place in their ranks to cultivate the soil, a place in their

dancing-parties. And the fame spread wide of “miraculous cures” effected

by the saint to whose name the church of Gheel was consecrated. The

remedy applied by the peasants was so plain, so old — it was liberty —

that the learned people preferred to trace the result to Divine

influences instead of taking things as they were. But there was no lack

of honest and good-hearted men who understood the force of the treatment

invented by the Gheel peasants, advocated it, and gave all their

energies to overcome the inertia of mind, the cowardice and the

indifference of their surroundings.

Liberty and fraternal care have proved the best cure on our side of the

above-mentioned wide borderland “between insanity and crime.” They will

prove also the best cure on the other boundary of the same borderland.

Progress is in that direction. All that tends that way will bring us

nearer to the solution of the great question which has not ceased to

preoccupy human societies since the remotest antiquity, and which cannot

be solved by prisons.

[1] Cesare Lombroso (1835 — 1909) Professor of psychiatry and

criminologist. He purported the existence of a link between criminality

and certain physical characteristics. This hypothesis is nowadays

discredited. His work encouraged also a more humane treatment of the

convicts.

[2] The former Abbey of St. Bernard at Clairvaux in France had been

transformed by the state rulers into a prison where Kropotkin was

detained from 1883 to 1886 on charges of being a member of the

International Workingmen’s Association which had been outlawed by the

state rulers after the Paris Commune of 1871.

[3] Philippe Pinel (1745 — 1826) Physician and advocate of a psychiatry

pioneering the humane treatment of the mentally ill.