💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › negligible-forces-collage.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:02:01. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Collage
Author: negligible forces
Date: Sep 7, 2020
Language: en
Topics: Meta-Anarchism, chaos theory, Gilles Deleuze
Source: Retreived on Feb 18, 2022 from https://negligibles.medium.com/collage-basic-introduction-to-the-meta-anarchist-political-vision-f61a549ad059

negligible forces

Collage

Fragmentation as an alternative to consensus

Consensus is when people reach a mutual agreement on a given issue.

Anarchy loves consensus. Actually, some anarchists seem to believe that

it’s the only acceptable form of decision-making.

Unfortunately, consensus has its limitations. The capacity for consensus

drops rapidly as the size of the group increases; it usually takes a lot

of time to reach one; not everyone are fans of participating in

sophisticated and lengthy discussions on every single issue. Those are

all usual objections to anarchism — and arguments for top-down

governments. That is, states.

States rely on the principle of one-for-all decisions. They claim it as

an inevitable consequence of large-scale organization — because it’s not

like an actual consensus can be reached between millions of people,

right?

But you don’t need a consensus for millions of people.

Sometimes, though arguably so, there is an actual necessity to enact a

decision that has to be shared by a group of people this large. Perhaps,

some kind of an issue of planetary scale — akin to climate change.

However, this happens drastically less often than the state strives to

present. There are far less groups that actually require a commonly

shared decision. The state operates in this manner not because of some

“natural necessity”, and not because it has the best interests of

society in mind, but to impose a type of governance that is more

convenient for the state itself. Unified systems are far more compatible

with centralized governance.

Being used to this approach to decision-making as the “natural” one,

some of us may unconsciously transfer it onto our ideas of a freer

society. That’s kinda what happened to “representative democracy”: all

residents of the country are obliged to express the enormous aggregate

of its collective will through the bottleneck of a single ruler, a

single set of rules, a single voting act. Although some things have

changed, the structure of governance remained similar to that of a

monarchy. No wonder this kind of democracy appears hardly functional to

some people.

If convenience for society (rather than convenience for top-down

governments) is a priority for us, another type of decision-making comes

to the forefront. “Fragmentation”.

What’s that? It’s a type of decision-making which implies that different

people should be able to enact different decisions regarding how they

want to live — and how they want to organize their habitat. It also

implies that their coexistence can be coordinated within prescriptions

of mutually shared protocols.

The principle of fragmentation is highly prominent in the open-source

software industry — known there as “forking”. But can we apply it to

political organization?

Let’s look at examples.

Residents of a neighborhood disagree on whether a road must be built in

the place of a local garden. To resolve this dispute, one could use

conflict resolution techniques, reconcile both sides and achieve

consensus on the basis of a compromise. One could also find new,

nontrivial solutions which would satisfy everyone. If there are no

resources for such luxury — perhaps, act in accordance with the opinion

of the majority. But no matter what type of method we apply here, this

would still remain a one-for-all solution. In this particular case,

technologies of our time leave us with no alternative approaches to this

problem. So, here fragmentation is inapplicable.

Here’s another example. Residents of a town believe that publicly

smoking weed is harmful to everyone in that town. Residents of another

town believe that publicly smoking weed is harmless, and maybe even

beneficial to the smokers. Now, you can fragment the decisions at the

regional level. Weed-haters can prohibit smoking in their town, and

weed-lovers can allow it in theirs. In this situation, fragmentation is

preferable.

All that’s required is a shared protocol to which both towns subscribe,

and which postulates that separate towns can make their own policies on

weed-smoking. Let’s call this an “interpolity protocol”. If necessary,

it can be a formal protocol of explicit mutual agreement — otherwise

it’s an informal protocol of “we just kinda let each other do our own

thing”. It’s the “agree to disagree” principle but applied to actual

political organization.

Now, in some countries, a similar system of decisional fragmentation

already exists, relying on high degree of regional autonomy. But it is

confined by strict borders of states or regions. It is still subject to

central authority. It responds very poorly to the shifts of opinions of

local residents. Whereas fragmentation can take place to a practically

infinite degree — all the way to individuals (or even subpersonalities).

It can allow for much more dynamic and adaptive political organization,

converting on-the-spot decisions into societally recognized ones almost

“in real time”. That is what’s called “free flow of desire” in Deleuzian

jargon.

On the other hand, the idea that a large group has to partake in a

single uniform decision implies suppression of some portion of people

with differing interests, e.g. with differing desire. This is usually

followed by delegitimization of those interests with a variety of

justifications: they’re non-citizen, they’re unpatriotic, they’re

privileged, etc.

Dictatorship of the few, rule by the majority and consensus are all

different methods of coordination within a single architecture of a

cohesive decision-making network. Consensus is, of course, the most

anarchist option within this particular architecture.

But it is possible to invent anarchist methods of decision-making on the

basis of different architecture. For example, networks with high degree

of fragmentation. In those kind of networks, tightly interconnected

areas — one may call them “assemblages” by Deleuzian terminology — are

intermitted by loosely connected “gaps” between different

areas/assemblages.

As a matter of fact, the technology of consensus in a large anarchist

society could function only alongside the technology of fragmentation.

In fully connected areas/assemblages, consensus is most likely to occur.

Those areas/assemblages could be communities of people with similar

values — as well as self-sovereign individuals. The fact that there are

gaps of lesser cohesion between those areas/assemblages allows every

area/assemblage to choose its own paths of existence and development.

Virtual polities and the Collage

What would be the most effective political framework for fragmentation?

I’m not sure there can be a decisive answer to that question right now,

but we can already start trying to outline and implement such a

framework.

Imagine virtual polities, which act as decentralized law providers for

all who wish to use their services. Users of different virtual polities

are subject to different sets of restrictions which they themselves deem

preferable. They often form localized communities, because it is more

convenient to interact with users who have the same providers. But the

providers are not subject to strict borders. Virtual polities are not

territorial in themselves, although they can condense on certain

territories. Somewhere, focal points emerge which gather users only of a

particular virtual polity, while elsewhere users of many different

systems settle alongside each other. Relations between users of

different virtual polities are coordinated by networks of interpolity

protocols of varying scale, formal and informal. Virtual polities can

exist within other virtual polities; they can be of any size and shape;

they can intermingle, intercross, conjoin, dissociate and divaricate.

Let’s call this system a “Collage”. A meta-anarchist Collage, if you

want to be particularly precise. A political system of maximized

self-determination. It is also a system that is entirely emergent and

self-organizing, and with no central authority whatsoever. In other

words, it is a confederated system.

The Collage implies that any kind of communities are possible. Including

those which misalign with your personal values. Including

ethnonationalist enclaves — as well as communes where nationalists are

strictly not welcome. As well as resorts for synthetic drug enthusiasts

exclusively; or a town for people who want to create a completely

functional furry society; or a medieval city with guilds and

knighthoods; or a primitivist hunter-gatherer reserve; or whatever

society you would like to live in.

With that said, we can hypothesize that highly isolated gatherings of

think-alike extremists will probably be a rare occurrence in the

Collage. Although, the possibility for such gatherings will already

resolve a huge amount of social tensions. But for most people it’ll be

probably more preferable and sustainable to live in “conservative”

polities with basic anarchist norms of decentralization and

self-governance; plus moderate fragmentation based on minor

disagreements. By “conservative” I mean only “preserving some set of

values” (in this context, anarchist values), and not the values which

you associate with that word.

The extremist polities, in turn, could serve as “political frontiers” of

consensual courageous experimentation, allowing the Collage as a whole

to try out new unusual sociopolitical frameworks. This will allow for

non-coercive societal evolution — in contrast to societal evolution as

we know it, which happens by violent confrontation between progressive

and conservative groups, as well as mutual coercion and struggle for

power over others. Now, some leftists call it “the dialectical process

of history”, but I prefer to call it “a redundant apparatus of surplus

suffering”.

On the other hand, we can’t really predict what the Collage will look

like. Maybe it will be an infinitely varying smorgasbord of distinct

worlds — rather than an assemblage consisting of a “conservative” core

and “extremist” periphery as described above. Maybe it will be both of

those systems existing as neighboring self-sufficient Collages. Maybe it

will be something entirely unimaginable from today’s perspective. In any

case, historical determinism is structurally fascistic. Remember — we’ll

know it only when we get there.

Alterprise and forks of freedom

Now, don’t mistake this model for simple voluntaryism. It’s not like we

can just get rid of the state and the free market will instantly arrange

us into peaceful consensual autonomies. Actually, the global capitalist

market in its current form, if met with no resistance, would most likely

devour and suppress any attempts at forming a plural meta-anarchist

network of autonomies.

The Collage must evolve independently, gradually and organically: by

many different people trying out many different approaches at the same

time to see what works, and synthesizing those approaches together to

achieve increasingly large-scale solutions. This is how all functional

societal systems emerge — through gradual evolution, not meticulous

planning.

But if so, how can we foster such a system into existence?

First and foremost, everyone should have the right to create their own

political project and invite anyone who wishes to participate. Let’s

call this activity “alterprise” — enterprise of alternatives. So, we

need to acknowledge the right to alterprise. Doing alterprise should be

as easy as doing a commercial start-up in a country that is oriented

towards supporting emerging small businesses.

A lot of nasty things can be said about “unbridled capitalism” — and I

already mentioned some — but it can’t be denied that market dynamics can

be used as a great tool for rapid systemic development. A market, when

organized properly, is essentially a technology of synthetic evolution:

people offer their products on the marketplace; “good” products gain

audience, while “bad” products wither away; the cycle repeats.

Now, what’s defined as a “good” or a “bad” product is entirely

circumstantial. Also, what the product or its providers gain by

attracting audience also varies between different types of markets. In

modern capitalist markets, a product’s success results in financial gain

for its provider and consequent concentration of power in that

provider’s hands. In a marketplace of organizational systems, the

product and its author are rewarded by implementation, as well as

investment of personal resources by willing participants. Think of it as

free, collaborative, open-source political system development.

Similarly, evolution is not just some improvement. It is improvement of

performance of certain tasks. And the tasks which define the

evolutionary selection may be any kind of tasks. In order for political

evolution to not result in optimization of totalitarian and centralized

systems, certain criteria of selection must be configured. Firstly, a

market demand for anarchist systems must emerge — anarchist systems must

prove themselves to be a better political product. Secondly,

Metaanarchy is a panarchy, but not every panarchy is metaanarchy

Some of you may have heard of a similar political idea — called

panarchy. At first glance, it seems identical to the meta-anarchist

vision — a plurality of political systems between which people can

freely choose. However, I believe there is an important distinction to

be made.

A panarchist system does not necessarily rely on anarchist principles of

autonomy and self-governance. It can as well be a plurality of top-down

governments with territorial sovereignty, akin to Moldbug’s Patchwork. A

panarchy is a marketplace of political systems, but, once again, they

can be any kind of political systems— for example, dystopian

dictatorships with no actual alternatives.

Strong anarchist institutions and principles are crucial for

facilitating the free flow of political desire. The Collage must have

widespread reliable instruments of direct bottom-up political agency—

whether based on markets, on direct democracy, on blockchain, or on

something else. Without such instruments, the Collage will devolve back

into statehood.

An advanced meta-anarchist society may afford to have polities with high

risk of coercion — voluntary kingdoms or warrior cultures, for example —

but the systemic core of the Collage must remain anarchical in order for

the Collage to remain extant.

Meta-X. Baseline protocol for the Collage

Interpolity protocols of varying scale are the glue of the

meta-anarchist Collage. To ensure freedom and flexibility, polities must

have the ability to agree on their own protocols. Successful protocols

are then shared and adopted by other polities. However, as with software

development, it might be much more convenient to work out a basic

protocol, on top of which all other protocols will be layered.

What should a baseline protocol for the Collage look like? It probably

shouldn’t have a lot of rules. It shouldn’t interfere with the logic of

individual rule systems, but it should prioritize personal liberty of

individual people over local rules. For example: anyone who wishes to

stop playing by the rules of a given polity must have the ability to

leave it, and they can’t be held back against their will. Or, even

better — anyone, regardless of physical location, can instantly switch

to a different law provider at any moment and, by that, immediately

become positioned within its jurisdiction.

Baseline protocols may themselves be plural and subject to evolution.

Actually, most likely they will. The more successful a given baseline

protocol is, the more parts of the Collage will adopt it.

In that case, the global level of affairs will be managed by more

informal conventions — or even with no explicit conventions at all, but

by emergent swarm-like and stigmergic organization. The informal

approach seems to be the most optimal for large-scale interrelations, as

it arises naturally from the global balance of interests. Today, a major

portion of international relations operates in a similar fashion. This

approach involves far less algorithmization — specific situations and

precedents become significantly more substantial.

At the current moment, this is mostly a vague fantasy. A questionable

utopian proposition. Surely, many problems and peculiarities, not

addressed in this text, will arise in practice. However, certain

meta-anarchist tendencies are already present in our day and age:

autonomous zones, blockchain-driven decision-making, federated social

networks, micronations, private and charter cities, democratic

confederalism of Rojava, free and open-source software — and many more.

The Collage assembly process has already started — but if not properly

facilitated, it will be dissolved and defeated by more totalitarian and

structurally fascistic tendencies: social credit systems, state police

militarization, mass surveillance, usage of AI and big data for top-down

control, automation of coercion, and so on.

To prevent this and ensure the emergence of the Collage, we need to

continuously network meta-anarchist tendencies together; start up our

own alterprises and personal utopias; create forks of existing projects;

make political and ideological innovations; and be ready to encounter

fierce resistance from the systems of status quo.

If we somehow succeed, we may suddenly find ourselves on a planet that

is a flourishing playground of chaotic consensual experimentation and

constant exploration of existential possibilities; a world of

unimaginable variance and beauty; a world of thousands of ontological

frontiers.

I’d say such a world would be worth the struggle.