💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › noam-chomsky-force-and-opinion.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:57:10. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Force and Opinion
Author: Noam Chomsky
Date: 1991
Language: en
Topics: force, philosophy
Source: Retrieved on 8th June 2021 from https://chomsky.info/199107__/
Notes: From Z Magazine, July-August, 1991

Noam Chomsky

Force and Opinion

In his study of the Scottish intellectual tradition, George Davie

identifies its central theme as a recognition of the fundamental role of

“natural beliefs or principles of common sense, such as the belief in an

independent external world, the belief in causality, the belief in ideal

standards, and the belief in the self of conscience as separate from the

rest of one.” These principles are sometimes considered to have a

regulative character; though never fully justified, they provide the

foundations for thought and conception. Some held that they contain “an

irreducible element of mystery,” Davie points out, while others hoped to

provide a rational foundation for them. On that issue, the jury is still

out.

We can trace such ideas to 17^(th) century thinkers who reacted to the

skeptical crisis of the times by recognizing that there are no

absolutely certain grounds for knowledge, but that we do, nevertheless,

have ways to gain a reliable understanding of the world and to improve

that understanding and apply it — essentially the standpoint of the

working scientist today. Similarly, in normal life a reasonable person

relies on the natural beliefs of common sense while recognizing that

they may be parochial or misguided, and hoping to refine or alter them

as understanding progresses.

Davie credits David Hume with providing this particular cast to Scottish

philosophy, and more generally, having taught philosophy the proper

questions to ask. One puzzle that Hume posed is particularly pertinent

today. In considering the First Principles of Government, Hume found

“nothing more surprising” than “to see the easiness with which the many

are governed by the few; and to observe the implicit submission with

which men resign their own sentiments and passions to those of their

rulers. When we enquire by what means this wonder is brought about, we

shall find, that as Force is always on the side of the governed, the

governors have nothing to support them but opinion. ‘Tis therefore, on

opinion only that government is founded; and this maxim extends to the

most despotic and most military governments, as well as to the most free

and most popular.”

Hume was an astute observer, and his paradox of government is much to

the point. His insight explains why elites are so dedicated to

indoctrination and thought control, a major and largely neglected theme

of modern history. “The public must be put in its place,” Walter

Lippmann wrote, so that we may “live free of the trampling and the roar

of a bewildered herd,” whose “function” is to be “interested spectators

of action,” not participants. And if the state lacks the force to coerce

and the voice of the people can be heard, it is necessary to ensure that

that voice says the right thing, as respected intellectuals have been

advising for many years.

Hume’s observation raises a number of questions. One dubious feature is

the idea that force is on the side of the governed. Reality is more

grim. A good part of human history supports the contrary thesis put

forth a century earlier by advocates of the rule of Parliament against

the King, but more significantly against the people: that “the power of

the Sword is, and ever hath been, the Foundation of all Titles to

Government.” Force also has more subtle modes, including an array of

costs well short of overt violence that attach to refusal to submit.

Nevertheless, Hume’s paradox is real. Even despotic rule is commonly

founded on a measure of consent, and the abdication of rights is the

hallmark of more free societies — a fact that calls for analysis.

The Harsher Side

The harsher side of the truth is highlighted by the fate of the popular

movements of the past decade. In the Soviet satellites, the governors

had ruled by force, not opinion. When force was withdrawn, the fragile

tyrannies quickly collapsed, for the most part with little bloodshed.

These remarkable successes have elicited some euphoria about the power

of “love, tolerance, nonviolence, the human spirit, and forgiveness,”

Vaclav Havel’s explanation for the failure of the police and military to

crush the Czech uprising. The thought is comforting, but illusory, as

even the most cursory look at history reveals. The crucial factor is not

some novel form of love and nonviolence; no new ground was broken here.

Rather, it was the withdrawal of Soviet force, and the collapse of the

structures of coercion based upon it. Those who believe otherwise may

turn for guidance to the ghost of Archbishop Romero and countless others

who have tried to confront unyielding terror with the human spirit.

The recent events of Eastern and Central Europe are a sharp departure

from the historical norm. Throughout modern history, popular forces

motivated by radical democratic ideals have sought to combat autocratic

rule. Sometimes they have been able to expand the realms of freedom and

justice before being brought to heel. Often they are simply crushed. But

it is hard to think of another case when established power simply

withdrew in the face of a popular challenge. No less remarkable is the

behavior of the reigning superpower, which not only did not bar these

developments by force as in the past, but even encouraged them,

alongside of significant internal changes.

The historical norm is illustrated by the dramatically contrasting case

of Central America, where any popular effort to overthrow the brutal

tyrannies of the oligarchy and the military is met with murderous force,

supported or directly organized by the ruler of the hemisphere. Ten

years ago, there were signs of hope for an end to the dark ages of

terror and misery, with the rise of self-help groups, unions, peasant

associations, Christian base communities, and other popular

organizations that might have led the way to democracy and social

reform. This prospect elicited a stern response by the United States and

its clients, generally supported by its European allies, with a campaign

of slaughter, torture, and general barbarism that left societies

“affected by terror and panic,” “collective intimidation and generalized

fear” and “internalized acceptance of the terror,” in the words of a

Church-based Salvadoran human rights organization. Early efforts in

Nicaragua to direct resources to the poor majority impelled Washington

to economic and ideological warfare, and outright terror, to punish

these transgressions by destroying the economy and social life.

Enlightened Western opinion regards such consequences as a success

insofar as the challenge to power and privilege is rebuffed and the

targets are properly chosen: killing prominent priests in public view is

not clever, but rural activists and union leaders are fair game — and of

course peasants, Indians, students, and other low-life generally.

Shortly after the murder of the Jesuit priests in El Salvador in

November 1989, the wires carried a story by AP correspondent Douglas

Grant Mine entitled “Second Salvador Massacre, but of Common Folk,”

reporting how soldiers entered a working class neighborhood, captured

six men, lined them up against a wall and murdered them, adding a

14-year-old boy for good measure. They “were not priests or human rights

campaigners,” Mine wrote, “so their deaths have gone largely unnoticed”

— as did his story, which was buried.

“The same week the Jesuits were killed,” Central America correspondent

Alan Nairn writes, “at least 28 other civilians were murdered in similar

fashion. Among them were the head of the water works union, the leader

of the organization of university women, nine members of an Indian

farming cooperative, ten university students,…. Moreover, serious

investigation of the Salvadoran murders leads directly to Washington’s

doorstep.” All “absolutely appropriate,” hence unworthy of mention or

concern. So the story continues, week after grisly week.

The comparison between the Soviet and U.S. domains is a commonplace

outside of culturally deprived sectors of the West, as illustrated in

earlier Z articles. Guatemalan journalist Julio Godoy, who fled when his

newspaper, La Epoca, was blown up by state terrorists (an operation that

aroused no interest in the United States; it was not reported, though

well-known), writes that Eastern Europeans are, “in a way, luckier than

Central Americans”: “while the Moscow-imposed government in Prague would

degrade and humiliate reformers, the Washington-made government in

Guatemala would kill them. It still does, in a virtual genocide that has

taken more than 150,000 victims… [in what Amnesty International calls] a

‘government program of political murder’.” That, he suggested, is “the

main explanation for the fearless character of the students’ recent

uprising in Prague: the Czechoslovak Army doesn’t shoot to kill…. In

Guatemala, not to mention El Salvador, random terror is used to keep

unions and peasant associations from seeking their own way” — and to

ensure that the press conforms, or disappears, so that Western liberals

need not fret over censorship in the “fledgling democracies” they

applaud.

Godoy quotes a European diplomat who says, “as long as the Americans

don’t change their attitude towards the region, there’s no space here

for the truth or for hope.” Surely no space for nonviolence and love.

One will search far to find such truisms in U.S. commentary, or the West

in general, which much prefers largely meaningless (though

self-flattering) comparisons between Eastern and Western Europe. Nor is

the hideous catastrophe of capitalism in the past years a major theme of

contemporary discourse, a catastrophe that is dramatic in Latin America

and other domains of the industrial West, in the “internal Third World”

of the United States, and the “exported slums” of Europe. Nor are we

likely to find much attention to the fact, hard to ignore, that the

economic success stories typically involve coordination of the state and

financial-industrial conglomerates, another sign of the collapse of

capitalism in the past 60 years. It is only the Third World that is to

be subjected to the destructive forces of free market capitalism, so

that it can be more efficiently robbed and exploited by the powerful.

Central America represents the historical norm, not Eastern Europe.

Hume’s observation requires this correction. Recognizing that, it

remains true, and important, that government is typically founded on

modes of submission short of force, even where force is available as a

last resort.

The Bewildered Herd And Its Shepherds

In the contemporary period, Hume’s insight has been revived and

elaborated, but with a crucial innovation: control of thought is more

important for governments that are free and popular than for despotic

and military states. The logic is straightforward. A despotic state can

control its domestic enemy by force, but as the state loses this weapon,

other devices are required to prevent the ignorant masses from

interfering with public affairs, which are none of their business. These

prominent features of modern political and intellectual culture merit a

closer look.

The problem of “putting the public in its place” came to the fore with

what one historian calls “the first great outburst of democratic thought

in history,” the English revolution of the 17^(th) century. This

awakening of the general populace raised the problem of how to contain

the threat.

The libertarian ideas of the radical democrats were considered

outrageous by respectable people. They favored universal education,

guaranteed health care, and democratization of the law, which one

described as a fox, with poor men the geese: “he pulls off their

feathers and feeds upon them.” They developed a kind of “liberation

theology” which, as one critic ominously observed, preached “seditious

doctrine to the people” and aimed “to raise the rascal multitude…against

all men of best quality in the kingdom, to draw them into associations

and combinations with one another…against all lords, gentry, ministers,

lawyers, rich and peaceable men” (historian Clement Walker).

Particularly frightening were the itinerant workers and preachers

calling for freedom and democracy, the agitators stirring up the rascal

multitude, and the printers putting out pamphlets questioning authority

and its mysteries. “There can be no form of government without its

proper mysteries,” Walker warned, mysteries that must be “concealed”

from the common folk: “Ignorance, and admiration arising from ignorance,

are the parents of civil devotion and obedience,” a thought echoed by

Dostoevsky’s Grand Inquisitor. The radical democrats had “cast all the

mysteries and secrets of government…before the vulgar (like pearls

before swine),” he continued, and have “made the people thereby so

curious and so arrogant that they will never find humility enough to

submit to a civil rule.” It is dangerous, another commentator ominously

observed, to “have a people know their own strength.” The rabble did not

want to be ruled by King or Parliament, but “by countrymen like

ourselves, that know our wants.” Their pamphlets explained further that

“It will never be a good world while knights and gentlemen make us laws,

that are chosen for fear and do but oppress us, and do not know the

people’s sores.”

These ideas naturally appalled the men of best quality. They were

willing to grant the people rights, but within reason, and on the

principle that “when we mention the people, we do not mean the confused

promiscuous body of the people.” After the democrats had been defeated,

John Locke commented that “day-labourers and tradesmen, the spinsters

and dairymaids” must be told what to believe: “The greatest part cannot

know and therefore they must believe.”

Like John Milton and other civil libertarians of the period, Locke held

a sharply limited conception of freedom of expression. His Fundamental

Constitution of Carolina barred those who “speak anything in their

religious assembly irreverently or seditiously of the government or

governors, or of state matters.” The constitution guaranteed freedom for

“speculative opinions in religion,” but not for political opinions.

“Locke would not even have permitted people to discuss public affairs,”

Leonard Levy observes. The constitution provided further that “all

manner of comments and expositions on any part of these constitutions,

or on any part of the common or statute laws of Carolines, are

absolutely prohibited.” In drafting reasons for Parliament to terminate

censorship in 1694, Locke offered no defense of freedom of expression or

thought, but only considerations of expediency and harm to commercial

interests. With the threat of democracy overcome and the libertarian

rabble dispersed, censorship was permitted to lapse in England, because

the “opinion-formers…censored themselves. Nothing got into print which

frightened the men of property,” Christopher Hill comments. In a

well-functioning state capitalist democracy like the United States, what

might frighten the men of property is generally kept far from the public

eye — sometimes, with quite astonishing success.

Such ideas have ample resonance until today, including Locke’s stern

doctrine that the common people should be denied the right even to

discuss public affairs. This doctrine remains a basic principle of

modern democratic states, now implemented by a variety of means to

protect the operations of the state from public scrutiny: classification

of documents on the largely fraudulent pretext of national security,

clandestine operations, and other measures to bar the rascal multitude

from the political arena. Such devices typically gain new force under

the regime of statist reactionaries of the Reagan-Thatcher variety. The

same ideas frame the essential professional task and responsibility of

the intellectual community: to shape the perceived historical record and

the picture of the contemporary world in the interests of the powerful,

thus ensuring that the public keeps to its place and function, properly

bewildered.

In the 1650s, supporters of Parliament and the army against the people

easily proved that the rabble could not be trusted. This was shown by

their lingering monarchist sentiments and their reluctance to place

their affairs in the hands of the gentry and the army, who were “truly

the people,” though the people in their foolishness did not agree. The

mass of the people are a “giddy multitude,” “beasts in men’s shapes.” It

is proper to suppress them, just as it is proper “to save the life of a

lunatique or distracted person even against his will.” If the people are

so “depraved and corrupt” as to “confer places of power and trust upon

wicked and undeserving men, they forfeit their power in this behalf unto

those that are good, though but a few.”

The good and few may be the gentry or industrialists, or the vanguard

Party and the Central Committee, or the intellectuals who qualify as

“experts” because they articulate the consensus of the powerful (to

paraphrase one of Henry Kissinger’s insights). They manage the business

empires, ideological institutions, and political structures, or serve

them at various levels. Their task is to shepherd the bewildered herd

and keep the giddy multitude in a state of implicit submission, and thus

to bar the dread prospect of freedom and self-determination.

Similar ideas have been forged as the Spanish explorers set about what

Tzvetan Todorov calls “the greatest genocide in human history” after

they “discovered America” 500 years ago. They justified their acts of

terror and oppression on the grounds that the natives are not “capable

of governing themselves any more than madmen or even wild beasts and

animals, seeing that their food is not any more agreeable and scarcely

better than that of wild beasts” and their stupidity “is much greater

than that of children and madmen in other countries” (professor and

theologian Francisco de Vitoria, “one of the pinnacles of Spanish

humanism in the sixteenth century”). Therefore, intervention is

legitimate “in order to exercise the rights of guardianship,” Todorov

comments, summarizing de Vitoria’s basic thought.

When English savages took over the task a few years later, they

naturally adopted the same pose while taming the wolves in the guise of

men, as George Washington described the objects that stood in the way of

the advance of civilization and had to be eliminated for their own good.

The English colonists had already handled the Celtic “wild men” the same

way, for example, when Lord Cumberland, known as “the butcher,” laid

waste to the Scottish highlands before moving on to pursue his craft in

North America.

One hundred and fifty years later, their descendants had purged North

America of this native blight, reducing the lunatics from 10 million to

200,000 according to some recent estimates, and they turned their eyes

elsewhere, to civilize the wild beasts in the Philippines. The Indian

fighters to whom President McKinley assigned the task of

“Christianizing” and “uplifting” these unfortunate creatures rid the

liberated islands of hundreds of thousands of them, accelerating their

ascent to heaven. They too were rescuing “misguided creatures” from

their depravity by “slaughtering the natives in English fashion,” as the

New York described their painful responsibility, adding that we must

take “what muddy glory lies in the wholesale killing til they have

learned to respect our arms,” then moving on to “the more difficult task

of getting them to respect our intentions.”

This is pretty much the course of history, as the plague of European

civilization devastated much of the world.

On the home front, the continuing problem was formulated plainly by the

17^(th) century political thinker Marchamont Nedham. The proposals of

the radical democrats, he wrote, would result in “ignorant Persons,

neither of Learning nor Fortune, being put in Authority.” Given their

freedom, the “self-opinionated multitude” would elect “the lowest of the

People” who would occupy themselves with “Milking and Gelding the Purses

of the Rich,” taking “the ready Road to all licentiousness, mischief,

mere Anarchy and Confusion.” These sentiments are the common coin of

modern political and intellectual discourse; increasingly so as popular

struggles did succeed, over the centuries, in realizing the proposals of

the radical democrats, so that ever more sophisticated means had to be

devised to reduce their substantive content.

Such problems regularly arise in periods of turmoil and social conflict.

After the American revolution, rebellious and independent farmers had to

be taught by force that the ideals expressed in the pamphlets of 1776

were not to be taken seriously. The common people were not to be

represented by countrymen like themselves, that know the people’s sores,

but by gentry, merchants, lawyers, and others who hold or serve private

power. Jefferson and Madison believed that power should be in the hands

of the “natural aristocracy,” Edmund Morgan comments, “men like

themselves” who would defend property rights against Hamilton’s “paper

aristocracy” and from the poor; they “regarded slaves, paupers, and

destitute laborers as an ever-present danger to liberty as well as

property.” The reigning doctrine, expressed by the Founding Fathers, is

that “the people who own the country ought to govern it” (John Jay). The

rise of corporations in the 19^(th) century, and the legal structures

devised to grant them dominance over private and public life,

established the victory of the Federalist opponents of popular democracy

in a new and powerful form.

Not infrequently, revolutionary struggles pit aspirants to power against

one another though united in opposition to radical democratic tendencies

among the common people. Lenin and Trotsky, shortly after seizing state

power in 1917, moved to dismantle organs of popular control, including

factory councils and Soviets, thus proceeding to deter and overcome

socialist tendencies. An orthodox Marxist, Lenin did not regard

socialism as a viable option in this backward and underdeveloped

country; until his last days, it remained for him an “elementary truth

of Marxism, that the victory of socialism requires the joint efforts of

workers in a number of advanced countries,” Germany in particular. In

what has always seemed to me his greatest work, George Orwell described

a similar process in Spain, where the Fascists, Communists, and liberal

democracies were united in opposition to the libertarian revolution that

swept over much of the country, turning to the conflict over the spoils

only when popular forces were safely suppressed. There are many

examples, often influenced by great power violence.

This is particularly true in the Third World. A persistent concern of

Western elites is that popular organizations might lay the basis for

meaningful democracy and social reform, threatening the prerogatives of

the privileged. Those who seek “to raise the rascal multitude” and “draw

them into associations and combinations with one another” against “the

men of best quality” must, therefore, be repressed or eliminated. It

comes as no surprise that Archbishop Romero should be assassinated

shortly after urging President Carter to withhold military aid from the

governing junta, which, he warned, will use it to “sharpen injustice and

repression against the people’s organizations” struggling “for respect

for their most basic human rights.”

The threat of popular organization to privilege is real enough in

itself. Worse still, “the rot may spread,” in the terminology of

political elites; there may be a demonstration effect of independent

development in a form that attends to the people’s sores. Internal

documents and even the public record reveal that a driving concern of

U.S. planners has been the fear that the “virus” might spread,

“infecting” regions beyond.

This concern breaks no new ground. European statesmen had feared that

the American revolution might “lend new strength to the apostles of

sedition” (Metternich), and might spread “the contagion and the invasion

of vicious principles” such as “the pernicious doctrines of

republicanism and popular selfrule,” one of the Czar’s diplomats warned.

A century later, the cast of characters was reversed. Woodrow Wilson’s

Secretary of State Robert Lansing feared that if the Bolshevik disease

were to spread, it would leave the “ignorant and incapable mass of

humanity dominant in the earth”; the Bolsheviks, he continued, were

appealing “to the proletariat of all countries, to the ignorant and

mentally deficient, who by their numbers are urged to become masters, …a

very real danger in view of the process of social unrest throughout the

world.” Again it is democracy that is the awesome threat. When soldiers

and workers councils made a brief appearance in Germany, Wilson feared

that they would inspire dangerous thoughts among “the American negro

[soldiers] returning from abroad.” Already, he had heard, negro

laundresses were demanding more than the going wage, saying that “money

is as much mine as it is yours.” Businessmen might have to adjust to

having workers on their boards of directors, he feared, among other

disasters, if the Bolshevik virus were not exterminated.

With these dire consequences in mind, the Western invasion of the Soviet

Union was justified on defensive grounds, against “the Revolution’s

challenge…to the very survival of the capitalist order” (John Lewis

Gaddis). And it was only natural that the defense of the United States

should extend from invasion of the Soviet Union to Wilson’s Red Scare at

home. As Lansing explained, force must be used to prevent “the leaders

of Bolshevism and anarchy” from proceeding to “organize or preach

against government in the United States”; the government must not permit

“these fanatics to enjoy the liberty which they now seek to destroy.”

The repression launched by the Wilson administration successfully

undermined democratic politics, unions, freedom of the press, and

independent thought, in the interests of corporate power and the state

authorities who represented its interests, all with the general approval

of the media and elites generally, all in self-defense against the

“ignorant and mentally deficient” majority. Much the same story was

re-enacted after World War II, again under the pretext of a Soviet

threat, in reality, to restore submission to the rulers.

When political life and independent thought revived in the 1960s, the

problem arose again, and the reaction was the same. The Trilateral

Commission, bringing together liberal elites from Europe, Japan, and the

United States, warned of an impending “crisis of democracy” as segments

of the public sought to enter the political arena. This “excess of

democracy” was posing a threat to the unhampered rule of privileged

elites — what is called “democracy” in political theology. The problem

was the usual one: the rabble were trying to manage their own affairs,

gaining control over their communities and pressing their political

demands. There were organizing efforts among young people, ethnic

minorities, women, social activists, and others, encouraged by the

struggles of benighted masses elsewhere for freedom and independence.

More “moderation in democracy” would be required, the Commission

concluded, perhaps a return to the days when “Truman had been able to

govern the country with the cooperation of a relatively small number of

Wall Street lawyers and bankers,” as the American rapporteur commented.

The fears expressed by the men of best quality in the 17^(th) century

have become a major theme of intellectual discourse, corporate practice,

and the academic social sciences. They were expressed by the influential

moralist and foreign affairs adviser Reinhold Niebuhr, who was revered

by George Kennan, the Kennedy intellectuals, and many others. He wrote

that “rationality belongs to the cool observers” while the common person

follows not reason but faith. The cool observers, he explained, must

recognize “the stupidity of the average man,” and must provide the

“necessary illusion” and the “emotionally potent oversimplifications”

that will keep the naive simpletons on course. As in 1650, it remains

necessary to protect the “lunatic or distracted person,” the ignorant

rabble, from their own “depraved and corrupt” judgments, just as one

does not allow a child to cross the street without supervision.

In accordance with the prevailing conceptions, there is no infringement

of democracy if a few corporations control the information system: in

fact, that is the essence of democracy. The leading figure of the public

relations industry, Edward Bernays, explained that “the very essence of

the democratic process” is “the freedom to persuade and suggest,” what

he calls “the engineering of consent.” If the freedom to persuade

happens to be concentrated in a few hands, we must recognize that such

is the nature of a free society.

Bernays expressed the basic point in a public relations manual of 1928:

“The conscious and intelligent manipulation of the organized habits and

opinions of the masses is an important element in democratic society… It

is the intelligent minorities which need to make use of propaganda

continuously and systematically.” Given its enormous and decisive power,

the highly class conscious business community of the United States has

been able to put these lessons to effective use. Bernays’ advocacy of

propaganda is cited by Thomas McCann, head of public relations for the

United Fruit Company, for which Bernays provided signal service in

preparing the ground for the overthrow of Guatemalan democracy in 1954,

a major triumph of business propaganda with the willing compliance of

the media.

The intelligent minorities have long understood this to be their

function. Walter Lippmann described a “revolution” in “the practice of

democracy” as “the manufacture of consent” has become “a self-conscious

art and a regular organ of popular government.” This is a natural

development when public opinion cannot be trusted: “In the absence of

institutions and education by which the environment is so successfully

reported that the realities of public life stand out very sharply

against self-centered opinion, the common interests very largely elude

public opinion entirely, and can be managed only by a specialized class

whose personal interests reach beyond the locality,” and are thus able

to perceive “the realities.” These are the men of best quality, who

alone are capable of social and economic management.

It follows that two political roles must be clearly distinguished,

Lippmann goes on to explain. First, there is the role assigned to the

specialized class, the “insiders,” the “responsible men,” who have

access to information and understanding. Ideally, they should have a

special education for public office, and should master the criteria for

solving the problems of society: “In the degree to which these criteria

can be made exact and objective, political decision,” which is their

domain, “is actually brought into relation with the interests of men.”

The “public men” are, furthermore, to “lead opinion” and take the

responsibility for “the formation of a sound public opinion.” “They

initiate, they administer, they settle,” and should be protected from

“ignorant and meddlesome outsiders,” the general public, who are

incapable of dealing “with the substance of the problem.” The criteria

we apply to government are success in satisfying material and cultural

wants, not whether “it vibrates to the self-centered opinions that

happen to be floating in men’s minds.” Having mastered the criteria for

political decision, the specialized class, protected from public

meddling, will serve the public interest — what is called “the national

interest” in the webs of mystification spun by the academic social

sciences and political commentary.

The second role is “the task of the public,” which is much more limited.

It is not for the public, Lippmann observes, to “pass judgment on the

intrinsic merits” of an issue or to offer analysis or solutions, but

merely, on occasion, to place “its force at the disposal” of one or

another group of “responsible men.” The public “does not reason,

investigate, invent, persuade, bargain, or settle.” Rather, “the public

acts only by aligning itself as the partisan of someone in a position to

act executively,” once he has given the matter at hand sober and

disinterested thought. It is for this reason that “the public must be

put in its place.” The bewildered herd, trampling and roaring, “has its

function”: to be “the interested spectators of action,” not

participants. Participation is the duty of “the responsible man.”

These ideas, described by Lippmann’s editors as a progressive “political

philosophy for liberal democracy,” have an unmistakeable resemblance to

the Leninist concept of a vanguard party that leads the masses to a

better life that they cannot conceive or construct on their own. In

fact, the transition from one position to the other, from Leninist

enthusiasm to “celebration of America,” has proven quite an easy one

over the years. This is not surprising, since the doctrines are similar

at their root. The critical difference lies in an assessment of the

prospects for power: through exploitation of mass popular struggle, or

service to the current masters.

There is, clearly enough, an unspoken assumption behind the proposals of

Lippmann and others: the specialized class are offered the opportunity

to manage public affairs by virtue of their subordination to those with

real power — in our societies, dominant business interests — a crucial

fact that is ignored in the self-praise of the elect.

Lippmann’s thinking on these matters dates from shortly after World War

I, when the liberal intellectual community was much impressed with its

success in serving as “the faithful and helpful interpreters of what

seems to be one of the greatest enterprises ever undertaken by an

American president” (New Republic). The enterprise was Woodrow Wilson’s

interpretation of his electoral mandate for “peace without victory” as

the occasion for pursuing victory without peace, with the assistance of

the liberal intellectuals, who later praised themselves for having

“impose[d] their will upon a reluctant or indifferent majority,” with

the aid of propaganda fabrications about Hun atrocities and other such

devices. They were serving, often unwittingly, as instruments of the

British Ministry of Information, which secretly defined its task as “to

direct the thought of most of the world.”

Fifteen years later, the influential political scientist Harold Lasswell

explained in the Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences that when elites

lack the requisite force to compel obedience, social managers must turn

to “a whole new technique of control, largely through propaganda.” He

added the conventional justification: we must recognize the “ignorance

and stupidity [of] …the masses” and not succumb to “democratic

dogmatisms about men being the best judges of their own interests.” They

are not, and we must control them, for their own good. The same

principle guides the business community. Others have developed similar

ideas, and put them into practice in the ideological institutions: the

schools, the universities, the popular media, the elite journals, and so

on. A challenge to these ideas arouses trepidation, sometimes fury, as

when students of the 1960s, instead of simply bowing to authority, began

to ask too many questions and to explore beyond the bounds established

for them. The pretense of manning the ramparts against the onslaught of

the barbarians, now a popular pose, is scarcely more than comical fraud.

The doctrines of Lippmann, Lasswell, and others are entirely natural in

any society in which power is narrowly concentrated but formal

mechanisms exist by which ordinary people may, in theory, play some role

in shaping their own affairs — a threat that plainly must be barred.

The techniques of manufacture of consent are most finely honed in the

United States, a more advanced business-run society than its allies and

one that is in important ways more free than elsewhere, so that the

ignorant and stupid masses are more dangerous. But the same concerns

arise in Europe, as in the past, heightened by the fact that the

European varieties of state capitalism have not yet progressed as far as

the United States in eliminating labor unions and other impediments to

rule by men (and occasionally women) of best quality, thus restricting

politics to factions of the business party. The basic problem,

recognized throughout, is that as the state loses the capacity to

control the population by force, privileged sectors must find other

methods to ensure that the rascal multitude is removed from the public

arena. And the insignificant nations must be subjected to the same

practices as the insignificant people. Liberal doves hold that others

should be free and independent, but not free to choose in ways that we

regard as unwise or contrary to our interests, a close counterpart to

the prevailing conception of democracy at home as a form of population

control.

A properly functioning system of indoctrination has a variety of tasks,

some rather delicate. One of its targets is the stupid and ignorant

masses. They must be kept that way, diverted with emotionally potent

oversimplifications, marginalized, and isolated. Ideally, each person

should be alone in front of the TV screen watching sports, soap operas,

or comedies, deprived of organizational structures that permit

individuals lacking resources to discover what they think and believe in

interaction with others, to formulate their own concerns and programs,

and to act to realize them. They can then be permitted, even encouraged,

to ratify the decisions of their betters in periodic elections. The

rascal multitude are the proper targets of the mass media and a public

education system geared to obedience and training in needed skills,

including the skill of repeating patriotic slogans on timely occasions.

For submissiveness to become a reliable trait, it must be entrenched in

every realm. The public are to be observers, not participants, consumers

of ideology as well as products. Eduardo Galeano writes that “the

majority must resign itself to the consumption of fantasy. Illusions of

wealth are sold to the poor, illusions of freedom to the oppressed,

dreams of victory to the defeated and of power to the weak.” Nothing

less will do.

The problem of indoctrination is a bit different for those expected to

take part in serious decision-making and control: the business, state,

and cultural managers, and articulate sectors generally. They must

internalize the values of the system and share the necessary illusions

that permit it to function in the interests of concentrated power and

privilege or at least be cynical enough to pretend that they do, an art

that not many can master. But they must also have a certain grasp of the

realities of the world, or they will be unable to perform their tasks

effectively. The elite media and educational systems must steer a course

through these dilemmas, not an easy task, one plagued by internal

contradictions. It is intriguing to see how it is faced, but that is

beyond the scope of these remarks.

For the home front, a variety of techniques of manufacture of consent

are required, geared to the intended audience and its ranking on the

scale of significance. For those at the lowest rank, and for the

insignificant peoples abroad, another device is available, what a

leading turn-of-the-century American sociologist, Franklin Henry

Giddings, called “consent without consent”: “if in later years, [the

colonized] see and admit that the disputed relation was for the highest

interest, it may be reasonably held that authority has been imposed with

the consent of the governed,” as when a parent disciplines an

uncomprehending child. Giddings was referring to the “misguided

creatures” that we were reluctantly slaughtering in the Philippines, for

their own good. But the lesson holds more generally.

As noted, the Bolshevik overtones are apparent throughout. The systems

have crucial differences, but also striking similarities. Lippmann’s

“specialized class” and Bernays’ “intelligent minority,” which are to

manage the public and their affairs according to liberal democratic

theory, correspond to the Leninist vanguard of revolutionary

intellectuals. The “manufacture of consent” advocated by Lippmann,

Bernays, Niebuhr, Lasswell and others is the Agitprop of their Leninist

counterparts. Following a script outlined by Bakunin over a century ago,

the secular priesthood in both of the major systems of hierarchy and

coercion regard the masses as stupid and incompetent, a bewildered herd

who must be driven to a better world — one that we, the intelligent

minority, will construct for them, either taking state power ourselves

in the Leninist model, or serving the owners and managers of the state

capitalist systems if it is impossible to exploit popular revolution to

capture the commanding heights.

Much as Bakunin had predicted long before, the Leninist “Red

bureaucracy” moved at once to dismantle organs of popular control,

particularly, any institutional structures that might provide working

people with some influence over their affairs as producers or citizens.

Not surprisingly, the immediate destruction of the incipient socialist

tendencies that arose during the ferment of popular struggle in 1917 has

been depicted by the world’s two great propaganda systems as a victory

for socialism. For the Bolsheviks, the goal of the farce was to extract

what advantage they could from the moral prestige of socialism; for the

West, the purpose was to defame socialism and entrench the system of

ownership and management control over all aspects of economic,

political, and social life. The collapse of the Leninist system cannot

properly be called a victory for socialism, any more than the collapse

of Hitler and Mussolini could be described in these terms; but as in

those earlier cases, it does eliminate a barrier to the realization of

the libertarian socialist ideals of the popular movements that were

crushed in Russia in 1917, Germany shortly after, Spain in 1936, and

elsewhere, often with the Leninist vanguard leading the way in taming

the rascal multitude with their libertarian socialist and radical

democratic aspirations.

Short of Force

Hume posed his paradox for both despotic and more free societies. The

latter case is by far the more important. As the social world becomes

more free and diverse, the task of inducing submission becomes more

complex and the problem of unraveling the mechanisms of indoctrination,

more challenging. But intellectual interest aside, the case of free

societies has greater significance for us, because here we are talking

about ourselves and can act upon what we learn. It is for just this

reason that the dominant culture will always seek to externalize human

concerns, directing them to the inadequacies and abuses of others. When

U.S. plans go awry in some corner of the Third World, we devote our

attention to the defects and special problems of these cultures and

their social disorders — not our own. Fame, fortune, and respect await

those who reveal the crimes of official enemies: those who undertake the

vastly more important task of raising a mirror to their own societies

can expect quite different treatment. George Orwell is famous for Animal

Farm and 1984, which focus on the official enemy. Had he addressed the

more interesting and significant question of thought control in

relatively free and democratic societies, it would not have been

appreciated, and instead of wide acclaim, he would have faced silent

dismissal or obloquy. Let us nevertheless turn to the more important and

unacceptable questions.

Keeping to governments that are more free and popular, why do the

governed submit when force is on their side? First, we have to look at a

prior question: to what extent is force on the side of the governed?

Here some care is necessary. Societies are considered free and

democratic insofar as the power of the state to coerce is limited. The

United States is unusual in this respect: Perhaps more than anywhere

else in the world, the citizen is free from state coercion, at least,

the citizen who is relatively privileged and of the right color, a

substantial part of the population.

But it is a mere truism that the state represents only one segment of

the nexus of power. Control over investment, production, commerce,

finance, conditions of work, and other crucial aspects of social policy

lies in private hands. Unwillingness to adapt to this structure of

authority and domination carries costs, ranging from state force to the

costs of privation and struggle; even an individual of independent mind

can hardly fail to compare these to the benefits, however meager, that

accrue to submission. Meaningful choices are thus narrowly limited.

Similar factors limit the range of ideas and opinion in obvious ways.

Articulate expression is shaped by the same private powers that control

the economy. It is largely dominated by major corporations that sell

audiences to advertisers and naturally reflect the interests of the

owners and their market. The ability to articulate and communicate one’s

views, concerns, and interests — or even to discover them — is thus

narrowly constrained as well.

Denial of these truisms about effective power is at the heart of the

structure of necessary illusion. Thus, a media critic, reviewing a book

on the press in the New York Times, refers without argument to the

“traditional Jeffersonian role” of the press “as counterbalance to

government power.” The phrase encapsulates three crucial assumptions,

one historical, one descriptive, one ideological. The historical claim

is that Jefferson was a committed advocate of freedom of the press,

which is false. The second is that the press in fact functions as a

counterbalance to government rather than as a faithful servant,

presented here as doctrine, thus evading any need to face the massive

array of detailed documentation that refutes this dogma. The ideological

principle is that Jeffersonian libertarianism (considered abstractly,

apart from its realization in practice) would demand that the press be a

counterbalance to government power. That is incorrect. The libertarian

conception is that the press should be independent, hence a

counterbalance to centralized power of any form. In Jefferson’s day, the

powers that loomed large were the state, the church, and feudal

structures. Shortly after, new forms of centralized power emerged in the

world of corporate capitalism. A Jeffersonian would hold, then, that the

press should be a counterbalance to state or corporate power, and

critically to the state-corporate nexus. But to raise this point carries

us into forbidden ground.

Apart from the general constraints on choice and articulate opinion

inherent in the concentration of private power, it also set narrow

limits on the actions of government. The United States has again been

unusual in this respect among the industrial democracies, though

convergence toward the U.S. pattern is evident elsewhere. The United

States is near the limit in its safeguards for freedom from state

coercion, and, also in the poverty of its political life. There is

essentially one political party, the business party, with two factions.

Shifting coalitions of investors account for a large part of political

history. Unions, or other popular organizations that might offer a way

for the general public to play some role in influencing programs and

policy choices, scarcely function apart from the narrowest realm. The

ideological system is bounded by the consensus of the privileged.

Elections are largely a ritual form. In congressional elections,

virtually all incumbents are returned to office, a reflection of the

vacuity of the political system and the choices it offers. There is

scarcely a pretense that substantive issues are at stake in the

presidential campaigns. Articulated programs are hardly more than a

device to garner votes, and candidates adjust their messages to their

audiences as public relations tacticians advise. Political commentators

ponder such questions as whether Reagan will remember his lines, or

whether Mondale looks too gloomy, or whether Dukakis can duck the slime

flung at him by George Bush’s speech writers. In the 1984 elections, the

two political factions virtually exchanged traditional policies, the

Republicans presenting themselves as the party of Keynesian growth and

state intervention in the economy, the Democrats as the advocates of

fiscal conservatism; few even noticed. Half the population does not

bother to push the buttons, and those who take the trouble often

consciously vote against their own interest.

The public is granted an opportunity to ratify decisions made elsewhere,

in accord with the prescriptions of Lippmann and other democratic

theorists. It may select among personalities put forth in a game of

symbolic politics that only the most naive take very seriously. When

they do, they are mocked by sophisticates. Criticism of President Bush’s

call for “revenue enhancement” after having won the election by the firm

and eloquent promise not to raise taxes is a “political cheap shot,”

Harvard political scientist and media specialist Marty Linsky comments

under the heading “Campaign pledges — made to be broken.” When Bush won

the election by leading the public in the “read my lips — no new taxes”

chant, he was merely expressing his “world view,” making “a statement of

his hopes.” Those who thought he was promising no new taxes do not

understand that “elections and governing are different ball games,

played with different objectives and rules.” “The purpose of elections

is to win,” Linsky correctly observes, expressing the cynicism of the

sophisticated; and “the purpose of governing is to do the best for the

country,” he adds, parroting the necessary illusions that respectability

demands.

Even when issues arise in the political system, the concentration of

effective power limits the threat. The question is largely academic in

the United States because of the subordination of the political and

ideological system to business interests, but in democracies to the

south, where conflicting ideas and approaches reach the political arena,

the situation is different. As is again familiar, government policies

that private power finds unwelcome will lead to capital flight,

disinvestment, and social decline until business confidence is restored

with the abandonment of the threat to privilege; these facts of life

exert a decisive influence on the political system (with military force

in reserve if matters get out of hand, supported or applied by the North

American enforcer). To put the basic point crassly, unless the rich and

powerful are satisfied, everyone will suffer, because they control the

basic social levers, determining what will be produced and consumed, and

what crumbs will filter down to their subjects. For the homeless in the

streets, then, the primary objective is to ensure that the rich live

happily in their mansions. This crucial factor, along with simple

control over resources, severely limits the force on the side of the

governed and diminishes Hume’s paradox in a well-functioning capitalist

democracy in which the general public is scattered and isolated.

Understanding of these basic conditions — tacit or explicit — has long

served as a guide for policy. Once popular organizations are dispersed

or crushed and decision-making power is firmly in the hands of owners

and managers, democratic forms are quite acceptable, even preferable as

a device of legitimation of elite rule in a business-run “democracy.”

The pattern was followed by U.S. planners in reconstructing the

industrial societies after World War II, and is standard in the Third

World, though assuring stability of the desired kind is far more

difficult there, except by state terror. Once a functioning social order

is firmly established, an individual who must find a (relatively

isolated) place within it in order to survive will tend to think its

thoughts, adopt its assumptions about the inevitability of certain forms

of authority, and in general, adapt to its ends. The costs of an

alternative path or a challenge to power are high, the resources are

lacking, and the prospects limited. These factors operate in slave and

feudal societies — where their efficacy has duly impressed

counterinsurgency theorists. In free societies, they manifest themselves

in other ways. If their power to shape behavior begins to erode, other

means must be sought to tame the rascal multitude.

When force is on the side of the masters, they may rely on relatively

crude means of manufacture of consent and need not overly concern

themselves with the minds of the herd. Nevertheless, even a violent

terror state faces Hume’s problem. The modalities of state terrorism

that the United States has devised for its clients have commonly

included at least a gesture towards “winning hearts and minds,” though

experts warn against undue sentimentality on this score, arguing that

“all the dilemmas are practical and as neutral in an ethical sense as

the laws of physics.” Nazi Germany shared these concerns, as Albert

Speer discusses in his autobiography, and the same is true of Stalinist

Russia. Discussing this case, Alexander Gerschenkron observes that

“Whatever the strength of the army and the ubiquitousness of the secret

police which such a government may have at its disposal, it would be

naive to believe that those instruments of physical oppression can

suffice. Such a government can maintain itself in power only if it

succeeds in making people believe that it performs an important social

function which could not be discharged in its absence. Industrialization

provided such a function for the Soviet government…, [which] did what no

government relying on the consent of the governed could have done… But,

paradoxical as it may sound, these policies at the same time have

secured some broad acquiescence on the part of the people. If all the

forces of the population can be kept engaged in the processes of

industrialization and if this industrialization can be justified by the

promise of happiness and abundance for future generations and — much

more importantly — by the menace of military aggression from beyond the

borders, the dictatorial government will find its power broadly

unchallenged.”

The thesis gains support from the rapid collapse of the Soviet system

when its incapacity to move to a more advanced stage of industrial and

technological development became evident.

The Pragmatic Criterion

It is important to be aware of the profound commitment of Western

opinion to the repression of freedom and democracy, by violence if

necessary. To understand our own cultural world, we must recognize that

advocacy of terror is clear, explicit, and principled, across the

political spectrum. It is superfluous to invoke the thoughts of Jeane

Kirkpatrick, George Will, and the like. But little changes as we move to

“the establishment left,” to borrow the term used by Foreign Policy

editor Charles William Maynes in an ode to the American crusade “to

spread the cause of democracy.”

Consider political commentator Michael Kinsley, who represents “the

left” in mainstream commentary and television debate. When the State

Department publicly confirmed U.S. support for terrorist attacks on

agricultural cooperatives in Nicaragua, Kinsley wrote that we should not

be too quick to condemn this official policy. Such international

terrorist operations doubtless cause “vast civilian suffering,” he

conceded. But if they succeed “to undermine morale and confidence in the

government,” then they may be “perfectly legitimate.” The policy is

“sensible” if “cost-benefit analysis” shows that “the amount of blood

and misery that will be poured in” yields “democracy,” in the

conventional sense already discussed.

As a spokesperson for the establishment left, Kinsley insists that

terror must meet the pragmatic criterion; violence should not be

employed for its own sake, merely because we find it amusing. This more

humane conception would readily be accepted by Saddam Hussein, Abu

Nidal, and the Hizbollah kidnappers, who, presumably, also consider

terror pointless unless it is of value for their ends. These facts help

us situate enlightened Western opinion on the international spectrum.

Such reasoned discussion of the justification for terror is not at all

unusual, which is why it elicits no reaction in respectable circles just

as there is no word of comment among its left-liberal contributors and

readers when the New Republic, long considered the beacon of American

liberalism, advocates military aid to “Latin-style fascists…regardless

of how many are murdered” because “there are higher American priorities

than Salvadoran human rights.”

Appreciation of the “salutary efficacy” of terror, to borrow John Quincy

Adams’s phrase, has been a standard feature of enlightened Western

thought. It provides the basic framework for the propaganda campaign

concerning international terrorism in the 1980s. Naturally, terrorism

directed against us and our friends is bitterly denounced as a reversion

to barbarism. But far more extreme terrorism that we and our agents

conduct is considered constructive, or at worst insignificant, if it

meets the pragmatic criterion. Even the vast campaign of international

terrorism launched against Cuba by the Kennedy administration, far

exceeding anything attributed to official enemies, does not exist in

respected academic discourse or the mainstream media. In his standard

and much respected scholarly study of international terrorism, Walter

Laqueur depicts Cuba as a sponsor of the crime with innuendos but

scarcely a pretense of evidence, while the campaign of international

terrorism against Cuba merits literally not a word; in fact, Cuba is

classed among those societies “free from terror.”

The guiding principle is clear and straightforward: their terror is

terror, and the flimsiest evidence suffices to denounce it and to exact

retribution upon civilian bystanders who happen to be in the way; our

terror, even if far more extreme, is merely statecraft, and therefore

does not enter into the discussion of the plague of the modern age. The

practice is understandable on the principles already discussed.

Huge massacres are treated by much the same criteria: theirs are crimes,

ours statecraft or understandable error. In a study of U.S. power and

ideology a decade ago, Edward Herman and I reviewed numerous examples of

two kinds of atrocities, “benign and constructive bloodbaths” that are

acceptable or even advantageous to dominant interests, and “nefarious

blood-baths” perpetrated by official enemies. The reaction follows the

same pattern as the treatment of terrorism. The former are ignored,

denied, or sometimes even welcomed; the latter elicit great outrage and

often large-scale deceit and fabrication, if the available evidence is

felt to be inadequate for doctrinal requirements.

Such devices as mass starvation have always been considered entirely

legitimate, if they meet the pragmatic criterion. As director of the

humanitarian program providing food to starving Europeans after World

War II, Herbert Hoover advised President Wilson that he was “maintaining

a thin line of food” to guarantee the rule of anti-Bolshevik elements.

In response to rumors of “a serious outbreak on May Day” in Austria,

Hoover issued a public warning that any such action would jeopardize the

city’s sparse food supply. Food was withheld from Hungary under the

Communist Bela Kun government, with a promise that it would be supplied

if he were removed in favor of a government acceptable to the U.S. The

economic blockade, along with Rumanian military pressure, forced Kun to

relinquish power and flee to Moscow. Backed by French and British

forces, the Rumanian military joined with Hungarian

counter-revolutionaries to administer a dose of White terror and install

a right-wing dictatorship under Admiral Horthy, who collaborated with

Hitler in the next stage of slaying the Bolshevik beast. The threat of

starvation was also used to buy the critical Italian elections of 1948

and to help impose the rule of U.S. clients in Nicaragua in l990, among

other noteworthy examples.

A review of the debate over Central America during the past decade

reveals the decisive role of the pragmatic criterion. Guatemala was

never an issue, because mass slaughter and repression appeared to be

effective. Early on, the Church was something of a problem, but, as

Kenneth Freed comments in the Los Angeles Times, when “14 priests and

hundreds of church workers were killed in a military campaign to destroy

church support for social gains such as higher wages and an end to the

exploitation of Indians,” the church was intimidated and “virtually fell

silent.” “The physical intimidation ceased,” the pragmatic criterion

having been satisfied. Terror increased again as the U.S. nurtured what

it likes to call “democracy.” “The victims,” a European diplomat

observes, “are almost always people whose views or activities are aimed

at helping others to free themselves of restraints placed by those who

hold political or economic power,” such as “a doctor who tries to

improve the health of babies” and is therefore “seen as attacking the

established order.” The security forces of the “fledgling democracy,”

and the death squads associated with them, appeared to have the

situation reasonably well in hand, so there was no reason for undue

concern in the United States, and there has been virtually none.

Throughout this grim decade of savagery and oppression, liberal

humanists have presented themselves as critical of the terror states

maintained by U.S. violence in Central America. But that is only a

facade, as we see from the demand, virtually unanimous in respectable

circles, that Nicaragua must be restored to “the Central American mode”

of the death squad regimes, and that the U.S. and its murderous clients

must impose the “regional standards” of El Salvador and Guatemala on the

errant Sandinistas.

Returning to Hume’s principles of government, it is clear that they must

be refined. True, when force is lacking and the standard penalties do

not suffice, it is necessary to resort to the manufacture of consent.

The populations of the Western democracies — or at least, those in a

position to defend themselves — are off limits. Others are legitimate

objects of repression, and in the Third World, large-scale terror is

appropriate, though the liberal conscience adds the qualification that

it must be efficacious. The statesman, as distinct from the ideological

fanatic, will understand that the means of violence should be employed

in a measured and considered way, just sufficient to achieve the desired

ends.

The Range of Means

The pragmatic criterion dictates that violence is in order only when the

rascal multitude cannot be controlled in other ways. Often, there are

other ways. Another RAND corporation counterinsurgency specialist was

impressed by “the relative docility of poorer peasants and the firm

authority of landlords in the more ‘feudal’ areas… [where] the landlord

can exercise considerable influence over his tenant’s behavior and

readily discourage conduct inconsistent with his own interests.” It is

only when the docility is shaken, perhaps by meddlesome priests, that

firmer measures are required.

One option short of outright violence is legal repression. In Costa

Rica, the United States was willing to tolerate social democracy. The

primary reason for the benign neglect was that labor was suppressed and

the rights of investors offered every protection. The founder of Costa

Rican democracy, Jose Figueres, was an avid partisan of U.S.

corporations and the CIA, and was regarded by the State Department as

“the best advertising agency that the United Fruit Company could find in

Latin America.” But the leading figure of Central American democracy

fell out of favor in the 1980s, and had to be censored completely out of

the Free Press, because of his critical attitude towards the U.S. war

against Nicaragua and Washington’s moves to restore Costa Rica as well

to the preferred “Central American mode.” Even the effusive editorial

and lengthy obituary in the New York Times lauding this “fighter for

democracy” when he died in June 1990 were careful to avoid these

inconvenient deviations.

In earlier years, when he was better behaved, Figueres recognized that

the Costa Rican Communist Party, particularly strong among plantation

workers, was posing an unacceptable challenge. He therefore arrested its

leaders, declared the party illegal, and repressed its members. The

policy was maintained through the 1960s, while efforts to establish any

working class party were banned by the state authorities. Figueres

explained these actions with candor: it was “a sign of weakness. I admit

it, when one is relatively weak before the force of the enemy, it is

necessary to have the valor to recognise it.” These moves were accepted

in the West as consistent with the liberal concept of democracy, and

indeed, were virtually a precondition for U.S. toleration of “the Costa

Rican exception.”

Sometimes, however, legal repression is not enough; the popular enemy is

too powerful. The alarm bells are sure to ring if they threaten the

control of the political system by the business-landowner elite and

military elements properly respectful of U.S. interests. Signs of such

deviation call for stronger measures, as in Central America through the

past decade. The broader framework was sketched by Father Ignacio

Martin-Baro, one of the Jesuit priests assassinated in November 1989 and

a noted Salvadoran social psychologist, in a talk he delivered in

California on “The Psychological Consequences of Political Terrorism,” a

few months before he was murdered. He stressed several relevant points.

First, the most significant form of terrorism, by a large measure, is

state terrorism, that is, “terrorizing the whole population through

systematic actions carried out by the forces of the state.” Second, such

terrorism is an essential part of a “government-imposed socio-political

project” designed for the needs of the privileged. To implement it, the

whole population must be “terrorized by an internalized fear.” Third,

the sociopolitical project and the state terrorism that helps implement

it are not specific to El Salvador, but are common features of the Third

World domains of the United States. The reasons are deeply rooted in

Western culture, institutions, and policy planning, and fully in accord

with the values of enlightened opinion. But terror is constrained by the

pragmatic criterion. Thus, Martin-Baro observes, the “massive campaign

of political terrorism” in El Salvador declined when “there was less

need for extraordinary events, because people were so terrorized,

paralyzed.”

In a paper on mass media and public opinion in El Salvador which he was

to deliver at an International Congress in December 1989, the month

after he was assassinated, Martin-Baro wrote that the U.S.

counterinsurgency project “emphasized merely the formal dimensions of

democracy,” and that the mass media must be understood as a mechanism of

“psychological warfare.” The small independent journals in El Salvador,

mainstream and pro-business but still too undisciplined for the rulers,

had been taken care of by the security forces a decade earlier in the

usual efficacious manner — kidnapping, assassination, and physical

destruction, events considered here too insignificant even to report. As

for public opinion, Martin-Baro’s unread paper reports a study showing

that among workers, the lower-middle class, and the poor, less than 20

percent feel free to express their opinions in public, a figure that

rose to 40 percent for the rich — another tribute to the salutary

efficacy of terror, and another result that “all Americans can be proud

of,” to borrow George Schultz’s words of self-praise for our

achievements in El Salvador.

When Antonio Gramsci was imprisoned after the Fascist takeover of Italy,

the government summed up its case by saying: “We must stop this brain

from functioning for twenty years.” Our current favorites leave less to

chance: the brains must be stopped from functioning forever, and we

agree that their thoughts about such matters as state terrorism had best

not be heard.

The results of U.S. military training are evident in abundance in the

documentation by human rights groups and the Salvadoran Church. They are

graphically described by Rev. Daniel Santiago, a Catholic priest working

in El Salvador, in the Jesuit journal America. He reports the story of a

peasant woman, who returned home one day to find her mother, sister, and

three children sitting around a table, the decapitated head of each

person placed carefully on the table in front of the body, the hands

arranged on top “as if each body was stroking its own head.” The

assassins, from the Salvadoran National Guard, had found it hard to keep

the head of an 18-month-old baby in place, so they nailed the hands onto

it. A large plastic bowl filled with blood was tastefully displayed in

the center of the table.

Rev. Santiago writes that macabre scenes of the kind he recounts are

designed by the armed forces for the purpose of intimidation. “People

are not just killed by death squads in El Salvador — they are

decapitated and then their heads are placed on pikes and used to dot the

landscape. Men are not just disemboweled by the Salvadoran Treasury

Police; their severed genitalia are stuffed into their mouths.

Salvadoran women are not just raped by the National Guard; their wombs

are cut from their bodies and used to cover their faces. It is not

enough to kill children; they are dragged over barbed wire until the

flesh falls from their bones while parents are forced to watch.” “The

aesthetics of terror in El Salvador is religious.” The intention is to

ensure that the individual is totally subordinated to the interests of

the Fatherland, which is why the death squads are sometimes called the

“Army of National Salvation” by the governing ARENA party, whose members

(including President Cristiani) take a blood oath to the

“leader-for-life,” Roberto d’Aubuisson.

It has been a constant lament of U.S. government officials that the

Latin American countries are insufficiently repressive, too open, too

committed to civil liberties, unwilling to impose sufficient constraints

on travel and dissemination of information, and in general reluctant to

adhere to U.S. social and political standards, thus tolerating

conditions in which dissidence can flourish and can reach a popular

audience.

At home, even tiny groups may be subject to severe repression if their

potential outreach is perceived to be too great. During the campaign

waged by the national political police against The Black Panthers —

including assassination, instigation of ghetto riots, and a variety of

other means — the FBI estimated the “hard core members” of the targeted

organization at only 800, but added ominously that “a recent poll

indicates that approximately 25 per cent of the black population has a

great respect for the [Black Panther Party], including 43 per cent of

blacks under 21 years of age.” The repressive agencies of the state

proceeded with a campaign of violence and disruption to ensure that the

Panthers did not succeed in organizing as a substantial social or

political force — with great success, as the organization was decimated

and the remnants proceeded to self-destruct. FBI operations in the same

years targeting the entire New Left were motivated by similar concerns.

The same internal intelligence document warns that “the movement of

rebellious youth known as the ‘New Left,’ involving and influencing a

substantial number of college students, is having a serious impact on

contemporary society with a potential for serious domestic strife.” The

New Left has “revolutionary aims” and an “identification with

Marxism-Leninism.” It has attempted “to infiltrate and radicalize

labor,” and after failing “to subvert and control the mass media,” has

established “a large network of underground publications which serve the

dual purpose of an internal communication network and an external

propaganda organ.” It thus poses a threat to “the civilian sector of our

society,” which must be contained by the state security apparatus.

We can learn a good deal by attention to the range of choices. Keeping

just to Latin America, consider the efforts to eliminate the Allende

regime in Chile. There were two parallel operations. Track II, the hard

line, aimed at a military coup. This was concealed from Ambassador

Edward Korry, a Kennedy liberal, whose task was to implement Track I,

the soft line; in Korry’s words, to “do all within our power to condemn

Chile and the Chileans to utmost deprivation and poverty, a policy

designed for a long time to come to accelerate the hard features of a

Communist society in Chile.” The soft line was an extension of the

long-term CIA effort to control Chilean democracy. One indication of its

level is that in the 1964 election, the CIA spent twice as much per

Chilean voter to block Allende as the total spent per voter by both

parties in the U.S. elections of the same year. Similarly in the case of

Cuba, the Eisenhower administration planned a direct attack while

Vice-President Nixon, keeping to the soft line in a secret discussion of

June 1960, expressed his concern that according to a CIA briefing,

“Cuba’s economic situation had not deteriorated significantly since the

overthrow of Batista,” then urging specific measures to place “greater

economic pressure on Cuba.”

To take another informative case, in 1949 the CIA identified “two areas

of instability” in Latin America: Bolivia and Guatemala. The Eisenhower

administration pursued the hard line to overthrow capitalist democracy

in Guatemala but chose the soft line with regard to a Bolivian

revolution that had the support of the Communist Party and radical tin

miners, had led to expropriation, and had even moved towards “criminal

agitation of the Indians of the farms and mines” and a pro-peace

conference, a right-wing Archbishop warned. The White House concluded

that the best plan was to support the least radical elements, expecting

that U.S. pressures, including domination of the tin market, would serve

to control unwanted developments. Secretary of State John Foster Dulles

urged that this would be the best way to contain the “Communist

infection in South America.” Following standard policy guidelines, the

U.S. took control over the Bolivian military, equipping it with modern

armaments and sending hundreds of officers to the “school of coups” in

Panama and elsewhere. Bolivia was soon subject to U.S. influence and

control. By 1953, the National Security Council noted improvement in

“the climate for private investment,” including “an agreement permitting

a private American firm to exploit two petroleum areas.”

A military coup took place in 1964. A 1980 coup was carried out with the

assistance of Klaus Barbie, who had been sent to Bolivia when he could

no longer be protected in France, where he had been working under U.S.

control to repress the anti-fascist resistance, as he had done under the

Nazis. According to a recent UNICEF study, one out of three Bolivian

infants dies in the first year of life, so that Bolivia has the slowest

rate of population growth in Latin America along with the highest birth

rate. The FAO estimates that the average Bolivian consumes 78 percent of

daily minimum calorie and protein requirements and that more than half

of Bolivian children suffer from malnutrition. Of the economically

active population, 25 percent are unemployed and another 40 percent work

in the “informal sector” (e.g., smuggling and drugs). The situation in

Guatemala we have already reviewed.

Several points merit attention. First, the consequences of the hard line

in Guatemala and the soft line in Bolivia were similar. Second, both

policy decisions were successful in their major aim: containing the

“Communist virus,” the threat of “ultranationalism.” Third, both

policies are evidently regarded as quite proper, as we can see in the

case of Bolivia by the complete lack of interest in what has happened

since (apart from possible costs to the U.S. through the drug racket);

and with regard to Guatemala, by the successful intervention under

Kennedy to block a democratic election, the direct U.S. participation in

murderous counterinsurgency campaigns under Lyndon Johnson, the

continuing supply of arms to Guatemala through the late 1970s (contrary

to illusory claims) and the reliance on our Israeli mercenary state to

fill any gaps when congressional restrictions finally took effect, the

enthusiastic U.S. support for atrocities that go well beyond even the

astonishing Guatemalan norm in the 1980s, and the applause for the

“fledgling democracy” that the ruling military now tolerates as a means

to extort money from Congress. We may say that these are “messy

episodes” and “blundering” (which in fact succeeded in its major aims),

but nothing more (Stephen Kinzer). Fourth, the soft line and the hard

line were adopted by the same people, at the same time, revealing that

the issues are tactical, involving no departure from shared principle.

All of this provides insight into the nature of policy, and the

political culture in which it is formed.

The Untamed Rabble

Hume’s paradox of government arises only if we suppose that a crucial

element of essential human nature is what Bakunin called “an instinct

for freedom.” It is the failure to act upon this instinct that Hume

found surprising. The same failure inspired Rousseau’s classic lament

that people are born free but are everywhere in chains, seduced by the

illusions of the civil society that is created by the rich to guarantee

their plunder. Some may adopt this assumption as one of the “natural

beliefs” that guide their conduct and their thought. There have been

efforts to ground the instinct for freedom in a substantive theory of

human nature. They are not without interest, but they surely come

nowhere near establishing the case. Like other tenets of common sense,

this belief remains a regulative principle that we adopt, or reject, on

faith. Which choice we make can have large-scale effects for ourselves

and others.

Those who adopt the common sense principle that freedom is our natural

right and essential need will agree with Bertrand Russell that anarchism

is “the ultimate ideal to which society should approximate.” Structures

of hierarchy and domination are fundamentally illegitimate. They can be

defended only on grounds of contingent need, an argument that rarely

stands up to analysis. As Russell went on to observe 70 years ago, “the

old bonds of authority” have little intrinsic merit. Reasons are needed

for people to abandon their rights, “and the reasons offered are

counterfeit reasons, convincing only to those who have a selfish

interest in being convinced.” “The condition of revolt,” he went on,

“exists in women towards men, in oppressed nations towards their

oppressors, and above all in labour towards capital. It is a state full

of danger, as all past history shows, yet also full of hope.”

Russell traced the habit of submission in part to coercive educational

practices. His views are reminiscent of 17^(th) and 18^(th) century

thinkers who held that the mind is not to be filled with knowledge “from

without, like a vessel,” but “to be kindled and awaked.” “The growth of

knowledge [resembles] the growth of Fruit; however external causes may

in some degree cooperate, it is the internal vigour, and virtue of the

tree, that must ripen the juices to their just maturity.” Similar

conceptions underlie Enlightenment thought on political and intellectual

freedom, and on alienated labor, which turns the worker into an

instrument for other ends instead of a human being fulfilling inner

needs — a fundamental principle of classical liberal thought, though

long forgotten, because of its revolutionary implications. These ideas

and values retain their power and their pertinence, though they are very

remote from realization, anywhere. As long as this is so, the

libertarian revolutions of the 18^(th) century remain far from

consummated, a vision for the future.

One might take this natural belief to be confirmed by the fact that

despite all efforts to contain them, the rabble continue to fight for

their fundamental human rights. And over time, some libertarian ideals

have been partially realized or have even become common coin. Many of

the outrageous ideas of the 17^(th) century radical democrats, for

example, seem tame enough today, though other early insights remain

beyond our current moral and intellectual reach.

The struggle for freedom of speech is an interesting case, and a crucial

one, since it lies at the heart of a whole array of freedoms and rights.

A central question of the modern era is when, if ever, the state may act

to interdict the content of communications. As noted earlier, even those

regarded as leading libertarians have adopted restrictive and qualified

views on this matter. One critical element is seditious libel, the idea

that the state can be criminally assaulted by speech, “the hallmark of

closed societies throughout the world,” legal historian Harry Kalven

observes. A society that tolerates laws against seditious libel is not

free, whatever its other virtues. In late 17^(th) century England, men

were castrated, disemboweled, quartered, and beheaded for the crime.

Through the 18^(th) century, there was a general consensus that

established authority could be maintained only by silencing subversive

discussion, and “any threat, whether real or imagined, to the good

reputation of the government” must be barred by force (Leonard Levy).

“Private men are not judges of their superiors… [for] This wou’d

confound all government,” one editor wrote. Truth was no defense: true

charges are even more criminal than false ones, because they tend even

more to bring authority into disrepute.

Treatment of dissident opinion, incidentally, follows a similar model in

our more libertarian era. False and ridiculous charges are no real

problem: it is the unconscionable critics who reveal unwanted truths

from whom society must be protected.

The doctrine of seditious libel was also upheld in the American

colonies. The intolerance of dissent during the revolutionary period is

notorious. The leading American libertarian, Thomas Jefferson, agreed

that punishment was proper for “a traitor in thought, but not in deed,”

and authorized internment of political suspects. He and the other

Founders agreed that “traitorous or disrespectful words” against the

authority of the national state or any of its component states was

criminal. “During the Revolution,” Leonard Levy observes, “Jefferson,

like Washington, the Adamses, and Paine, believed that there could be no

toleration for serious differences of political opinion on the issue of

independence, no acceptable alternative to complete submission to the

patriot cause. Everywhere there was unlimited liberty to praise it, none

to criticize it.” At the outset of the Revolution, the Continental

Congress urged the states to enact legislation to prevent the people

from being “deceived and drawn into erroneous opinion.” It was not until

the Jeffersonians were themselves subjected to repressive measures in

the late 1790s that they developed a body of more libertarian thought

for self-protection — reversing course, however, when they gained power

themselves.

Until World War I, there was only a slender basis for freedom of speech

in the United States, and it was not until 1964 that the law of

seditious libel was struck down by the Supreme Court. In 1969, the Court

finally protected speech apart from “incitement to imminent lawless

action.” Two centuries after the revolution, the Court at last adopted

the position that had been advocated in 1776 by Jeremy Bentham, who

argued that a free government must permit “malcontents” to “communicate

their sentiments, concert their plans, and practice every mode of

opposition short of actual revolt, before the executive power can be

legally justified in disturbing them.” The 1969 Supreme Court decision

formulated a libertarian standard which, I believe, is unique in the

world. In Canada, for example, people are still imprisoned for

promulgating “false news,” recognized as a crime in 1275 to protect the

King.

In Europe, the situation is still more primitive. France is a striking

case, because of the dramatic contrast between the self-congratulatory

rhetoric and repressive practice so common as to pass unnoticed. England

has only limited protection for freedom of speech, and even tolerates

such a disgrace as a law of blasphemy. The reaction to the Salman

Rushdie affair, most dramatically on the part of self-styled

“conservatives,” was particularly noteworthy. Rushdie was charged with

seditious libel and blasphemy in the courts, but the High Court ruled

that the law of blasphemy extended only to Christianity, not Islam, and

that only verbal attack “against Her Majesty or Her Majesty’s Government

or some other institution of the state” counts as seditious libel. Thus

the Court upheld a fundamental doctrine of the Ayatollah Khomeini,

Stalin, Goebbels, and other opponents of freedom, while recognizing that

English law protects only domestic power from criticism. Doubtless many

would agree with Conor Cruise O’Brien, who, when Minister for Posts and

Telegraphs in Ireland, amended the Broadcasting Authority Act to permit

the Authority to refuse to broadcast any matter that, in the judgment of

the minister, “would tend to undermine the authority of the state.”

We should also bear in mind that the right to freedom of speech in the

United States was not established by the First Amendment to the

Constitution, but only through dedicated efforts over a long period by

the labor movement, the civil rights and anti-war movements of the

1960s, and other popular forces. James Madison pointed out that a

“parchment barrier” will never suffice to prevent tyranny. Rights are

not established by words, but won and sustained by struggle.

It is also worth recalling that victories for freedom of speech are

often won in defense of the most depraved and horrendous views. The 1969

Supreme Court decision was in defense of the Ku Klux Klan from

prosecution after a meeting with hooded figures, guns, and a burning

cross, calling for “burning the nigger” and “sending the Jews back to

Israel.” With regard to freedom of expression there are basically two

positions: you defend it vigorously for views you hate, or you reject it

in favor of Stalinist/Fascist standards.

Whether the instinct for freedom is real or not, we do not know. If it

is, history teaches that it can be dulled, but has yet to be killed. The

courage and dedication of people struggling for freedom, their

willingness to confront extreme state terror and violence, is often

remarkable. There has been a slow growth of consciousness over many

years and goals have been achieved that were considered utopian or

scarcely contemplated in earlier eras. An inveterate optimist can point

to this record and express the hope that with a new decade, and soon a

new century, humanity may be able to overcome some of its social

maladies; others might draw a different lesson from recent history. It

is hard to see rational grounds for affirming one or the other

perspective. As in the case of many of the natural beliefs that guide

our lives, we can do no better than to choose according to our intuition

and hopes.

The consequences of such a choice are not obscure. By denying the

instinct for freedom, we will only prove that humans are a lethal

mutation, an evolutionary dead end: by nurturing it, if it is real, we

may find ways to deal with dreadful human tragedies and problems that

are awesome in scale.