đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş mitchell-cowen-verter-levinas-perverter.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:38:11. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Levinas: Perverter Author: Mitchell Cowen Verter Date: June 11, 2008 Language: en Topics: Emmanuel Levinas Source: http://www.waste.org/~roadrunner/writing/Levinas/LevinasPerverter_20_1.htm
(for Alphonso Lingis)
Since the inauguration of modern French feminism in Simone DeBeauvoirâs
The Second Sex, Emmanuel Levinas has been criticized for the way his
thought employs gendered, familial tropes. In response, this paper
argues that, although this does constitute a very real and urgent
problematic in Levinasâs thought, it only becomes a problem when his
writing is read in a hermeneutically âstraightâ manner. Beneath the
apparent hetero-normative veneer of Levinasâs prose lurk traces of
queerness. By closely tracing the motifs that Levinas correlates with
gender, this paper will illustrate how, at each instant in the ethical
relationship, the Self is always transforming between masculine- and
feminine-gendered performances for a feminine- or masculine-gendered
Other. Rather than embodying a conservative and essentialist view of
sexuality, Levinas articulates an existential performative perversity.
Levinas, Perverter
âNow I say that Man, and in general every rational being, exists as an
End in Himself.â
-- Immanuel Kant (95)
Throughout his work, most evidently in Totality and Infinity, Levinas
employs motifs of kinship to describe my connection with alterity. When
he describes the world as being âfamiliar to usâ (TI 33), Levinas
implies that experience is constituted as family members. Through each
perspective of the ethical ârelationshipâ (TI 39) opened at each instant
of the ethical genealogy, the Other figures as a different relative: the
father of futural fecundity (TI 274â277), the wife of the economic home
(TI 154â156), the brother of political fraternity (TI 278â280), the
sister soul of incestuous Eros (TI 254), and so on. The prevalence of
these gendered family tropes has led many commentators to criticize
Levinas for having a sexist and heteronormative bias. Over half a
century ago in the foundational work of modern French feminism, The
Second Sex, Simone de Beauvoir accused Levinasâs figuration of woman as
Other to be âan assertion of masculine privilegeâ (xvi n3). More
recently, this protest has been expressed more angrily, with a recent
article claiming that Levinasâs work articulates a âdemonization of
femininity and erasure of maternityâ (Walsh 97).
For anyone who admires the work of Levinas, such anger is alarming.
Rather than reacting against this feminist standpoint, however, it is
precisely our responsibility as Levinas scholars to be awakened by this
alarm and to respond sincerely to this anger. As Andrea Juno and V. Vale
explain, â[Womenâs] anger can spark and re-invigorate; it can bring hope
and energy back into our lives and mobilize politically against the
status quoâ (5). Only by rendering Levinas vulnerable, by exposing him
to feminist critique, can we begin to answer for the problems in his
thought and perhaps even to use these problems to develop new insights
into gender and sexuality.
On the one hand, the feminist objection to Levinasâs language seems to
be exactly correct. Without a doubt, Levinas uses gendered motifs
throughout his philosophy, deploying familial structures inherited from
both the Judaic and the Greek legacies of patriarchy.[1] At all moments
of our reading, this should indeed trouble us. We should always refrain
from masquerading his gendered language by replacing masculine pronouns
with feminine ones, neutral ones, or even the hermaphroditic âhe or
sheâ; perhaps we should cease altogether to use âitâ in our
translations. We must keep in mind that Levinas articulates Humanisme de
lâautre Homme, âHumanism of the Other Man,â and not, as a recent
translation would have it, âHumanism of the Other.â On the other hand,
only to claim that Levinas âprivilegesâ the masculine over the feminine
overlooks the more essential question: what does âprivilegingâ mean and
should we necessarily privilege the privileged over the secondary?
Derrida astutely poses this methodological problem, âWe will attempt to
ask several questions. If they succeed in approaching the heart of this
explication, they will be nothing less than objections but rather the
questions put to us by Levinasâ (WD 84). Perhaps the words that have
caused so much controversy in Levinasâs work are the very terms that he
himself opens up for discussion? Perhaps Levinasâs usage of filial
tropes is not merely one of the âproblemsâ in his view of politics
(Critchley 174) but rather a problematic which must be deepened?
More than any other thinker in the history of Western philosophy,
Levinas stands accused in the very body of his texts, texts that âcall
for the critique exercised by another philosopherâ (OTB 20), texts
radically open to critical readings, texts that constantly require
justification. Exactly because he employs binary gendered concepts, we
can use Levinasâs texts to protest for justice not just in his work but
in philosophy and in Western culture itself. Levinas has inherited
sexist language and patriarchal logic from a long tradition of canonical
Western thought--most of which has been written by white males[2]--that
has typically figured subjectivity as virility and citizenship as
fraternity. Whereas many sensible, egalitarian thinkers try to
masquerade this legacy by using gender-neutral language, Levinas
deliberately foregrounds the problematic of gender. Therefore, perhaps a
careful and critical reading of his texts can begin to think through the
history of thought as masculine and to respond to the anger of our
sisters.
As distressing as it can be when anger is directed against a thinker one
admires, it seems even worse when someone defends his thought with
hostility and even employs it as a weapon of attack. As writers who have
taken responsibility for the thought of Emmanuel Levinas, we have
already committed to responding to the protest that his writings have
engendered. For this reason, it seems inappropriate for Richard A. Cohen
to dismiss the feminist analysis of Tina Chanterâs âAntigoneâs Dilemmaâ
with so much brutality and condescension in his first book Elevations,
characterizing her thoughtful and temperate article as âa hatchet job.
Levinas is once more made to play the tired role of the male fall guy So
why even bother with Levinas, one wonders, that sophisticated
intellectual male chauvinist pig?â (EHG 196) It is hard for me to
understand how a scholar of Levinas--a philosopher of politeness if
nothing else--could be so rude and patronizing to one of our sisters.
However, Cohen dismisses Levinasâs critical questioners--feminist and
otherwise--as âattackersâ (EHG 195) none of whom is given the
individuated respect for separated Otherness, but who are instead
defined collectively as enemies who âdemonstrate loyalty to a party or
school.â (EHG 196)
Elevations opens upon an ominous note. Cohen recounts, âI remember
distinctly to this day the impression Levinas made on me. âThis is
trueâ, I thought, in contrast to all the philosophers and philosophies
which are fascinating or provocativeâ (EHG xi). Although anyone who has
read Levinas can certainly appreciate Cohenâs ânaiveâ (EHG xi) sense of
wonder, Cohen makes the dangerous move of proclaiming Levinasâs thought
to be âtrue,â momentarily overlooking Levinasâs crucial âelevationâ of
the Good over the True. Practically canonizing Levinas as a saint or
prophet, such an orthodox interpretation verges on dogmatism. We can
already hear in Cohenâs contempt for thinkers who are merely
âfascinating or provocativeâ an effort to reduce the ethical height of
Levinasâs phenomenological ethics to a belligerent morality of
ressentiment.
Although Cohen is an astute phenomenologist, he makes the mistake of
placing the normative over the phenomenological without fully
appreciating how Levinasâs phenomenology is already ethics. Cohen states
that âthe central claim in Levinas is that the face of the other is
manifested in and manifests a moral heightâ (EHG 183). Nevertheless, he
reduces Levinasâs thought to a set of moral platitudes: âIt is quite
simple: it is better to be good than anything else. It is better to help
others than to help ourselvesâ (EEP 11). Contrary to Cohenâs
interpretation, however, Levinas does not issue prescriptive commands,
but instead demonstrates how the prescriptive is already embedded in the
existential. Levinasâs project is closely akin to Husserlâs quest to
determine the eidetic essences that structure experience (Ideas 7â8),
and even more similar to Heideggerâs demonstration that our
âeverydaynessâ actually reflects a more fundamental ontology (BT
380â82). That is, Levinas demonstrates how all of our experiences, even
the most âcommonplaceâ (TI 53), are already bent eccentrically by our
moral orientation towards the Other, already penetrated from the rear by
obligation. For example, Levinas does not simply argue that âviolence is
bad,â but rather demonstrates that, thanks to the ethical relationship,
our wills and our bodies are always exposed to violence (TI 229) yet
this violence is always postponed (TI 236).
Cohen equates Levinasâs motif of height with a âmoral forceâ that
justifies hierarchical judgments of âbetterâ and âworseâ (EEP 140).
Without properly articulating what the terms âgoodâ and âevilâ mean in
Levinasâs writing, Cohen expresses this contrast with astonishing
violence, arguing that Levinasâs âbattle cry would beâAgainst evil, for
the good!ââ (EEP 104) Such a polemical cry could not possibly come from
Levinas, but rather from Nietzscheâs man of ressentiment. According to
Nietzsche, ressentiment arises from two inversions: (a) horizontally,
ressentiment, the âsanctification of revenge under the name of justiceâ
(52), looks outwards for an enemy rather than looking inwards for
virtue; (b) vertically, ressentiment expresses the hatred of lowly
people for the high born, and their jealous effort to revalue moral
height. This attitude of ressentiment is most apparent in Cohenâs
description of Levinas as âteaching morality to the intellectual elite
who think themselves too intelligent, too sophisticated, too cultured
for ordinary moralityâ (EEP 1)
To avoid confusing Levinasâs moral height with ressentiment, we must
oppose the hierarchical logic of dogmatic orthodoxy by becoming
subverters, overturning thought from below. [3] Judaism has always been
a religion for subversion, for radical ruptures of thought that express
both supreme disobedience and supreme piety. As Susan Handelman claims,
Judaism contains within it a âheretic hermeneutic [that] can be part of
tradition while simultaneously rebelling against itâ (201). Our first
patriarch, Abraham, became such an iconoclast when he smashed the idols
revered and sold by his own father.[4] Similarly, modern Judaism stands
in the shadow of Sabbatai Sevi, the 17^(th) century apostate Messiah who
consummated the Jewish Law by violating it.[5]
Alongside the violence of critical protest yet against the violence of
rhetorical orthodoxy, we can still embrace the subversive potential of
violent speech by interpreting Levinas blasphemously.[6] In contrast to
Cohenâs hierarchical and orthodox moralism, our subversive and radical
reading will attempt to reveal the immanent roots, the poetic dimension
within Levinasâs hyperbolic, transcendental prose.[7] Such a reading
will show that, although Levinas deliberately uses filial tropes
throughout his work, this would only constitute a âproblemâ if it were
read in a hermeneutically âstraightâ manner. Beneath the apparent
hetero-normative veneer of Levinasâs prose lurk traces of queerness. The
ethical relationship is directed not simply from masculine Self to
feminine Other, but is everywhere perverted.
One of the reasons why readings of Levinas have so consistently upheld a
heteronormative analysis is that many interpretations construe his work
through a set of programmatic proclamations. We often read that
Levinasâs philosophy can summarized as âEthics is First Philosophyâ or
âThe Other is the Most High.â I would argue that, in addition to
considering a statement like âethics is first philosophyâ to be a
thematic declaration, we must meditate upon it as a riddle to be solved.
In order to crack it open, we must think through not only the
metaphysical traditions of protÄ philosophia in Aristotle and prima
philosophia in Descartes, but more importantly, what the word âfirstâ
and what Derrida calls âthe notion of primacyâ (WD 97) mean in a
Levinasian context.
Rather than focusing on the obvious rhetorical gestures Levinas makes, a
radical reading must look carefully at the immanent play of tropes
within his work. Levinasâs writing can only be understood through a
close investigation of the interconnections and transformation between
clusters of metaphors. Derrida slyly indicates this problem when he
explains that âeverything which Levinas designates asâformal logicâ is
contested in its root. This root would not only be the root of our
language, but the root of all western philosophyâ (WD 91).
Derridaâs hint suggests that the easiest place to begin looking at
Levinasâs immanent wordplay would be in his etymological roots. For
example, the Indo-European root âSTAâ has a long tradition in
philosophy. Greek thought articulates it as âhypoSTAsis,â which is
transformed into Latin as âsubSTAntia.â In âThe Origin of the Work of
Art,â Heidegger considers this translation of philosophical terms to be
one of the primordial stages in the forgetting of Being (BW 153). He
redeploys this root using terms common to the German philosophical
tradition such as âVerSTAndâ (understand), âGegenSTAndâ (represent) and
âVorSTEllungâ (notion), and he coins new terms such as âGeSTEllâ
(enframing) (BW 301). Almost parodying Heidegger, Levinas retranslates
this German lexicon back into a Latin tongue, âromancingâ the words back
into a Romance language.[8] Not only does Levinas reclaim the term
âhypostasis,â he transmutes this root into terms such as âdeSTItution,â
âsubSTItution,â and âinSTItution.â
Derrida warns against the temptations of etymological thinking (MP 210),
so I would not make the strong claim that Levinas puts his faith in the
French language the same way Heidegger considers German to be the âHouse
of Beingâ (BW 193). Whatever the ultimate ontological status of
language, it seems clear that Levinas carefully picks each word in his
texts with attention to its etymological and morphological resonances.
In the 1940s, Levinas displays this extraordinary attention to
linguistic detail by noting that what Heideggerâs âbeing-in-the-world,â
âbeing-for-death,â and âbeing-with-Othersâ add to our philosophical
knowledge âis that these prepositions --âinâ,âforâ, andâwithâ are in the
root of the verbâto beâ (asâexâ is in the root of the verbâto existâ)â
(Wahl 50). Thus, we should assume that Levinas is always aware of roots,
prefixes, and suffixes; of the nominal, verbal, prepositional,
adjectival, and adverbial parts of speech; of the active, middle, and
passive voices; of the nominative, vocative, dative, genitive, ablative,
accusative and even locative cases.
In addition to these morphological considerations, we must attend to the
semantic connections between various etymological networks. For example,
words rooted in âSTAâ (e.g. stand), must be correlated with other
etymological networks connoting position and proximity, as well as those
connoting height and depth. The very word âoriginâ comes from oriri, to
rise: for Levinas, man has âovercomeâ the âdestitutionâ of his âanimal
needsâ (TI 116â17) to become homo erectus, already erect and masterful
and virile.
Now that we have proposed an immanent hermeneutical strategy, we are
bold enough to ask the broader interpretive question: what are Levinasâs
books about? What storyline runs through his work? When we pay close
attention to the etymological and the semantic networks immanent to his
sentences, we notice that the same motifs crop up again and again under
new transformations.[9] Derrida gives us an insight into how metaphors
develop through Levinasâs work: âTotality and Infinity proceeds with the
infinite insistence of waves on a beach: return and repetition, always,
of the same wave against the same shore, in which, however, as each
return recapitulates itself, it also infinitely renews and enriches
itselfâ (WD 312, n7). That is, Levinasâs writing, both across the span
of his works and within a single text, can be understood as a process of
reiterative rewriting. Despite the fact that Totality and Infinity is
broken up into a certain number of sections, chapters and subsections;
and that Otherwise than Being was published 12 years after Totality and
Infinity; and that Levinasâs religious work must be distinguished from
his philosophical writings, I would argue that Levinas discusses one and
only one thing again and again: I confront you; or, put dialogically, I
converse with the Other; you say some thing to me and I listen, and then
I say some thing to you and you listen.
What animates Levinasâs corpus is that each new analysis gives us a new
perspective on this singular situation. I would in fact argue that the
notion of âperspectivismâ is as important for understanding Levinasâs
work as it is for Nietzscheâs.[10] Although the dialogical relation of
speech surmounts the theoretical stance of vision, Levinas still retains
the notion of perspective, explaining that âethics itself is an opticsâ
(TI 23). He does not abandon visuality, but instead warps it, perverts
it.[11] âThe differences between the Other and me are due to the I-Other
conjuncture, to the inevitable orientation of beingâstarting from
oneselfâ towardsâthe Other.â The priority of this orientation over the
terms that are placed in it (and which cannot arise without this
orientation) summarizes the theses of the present workâ (TI 215).[12]
Once we understand the way that Levinasâs perspectives bend, we can
begin to reflect upon the metaphorical networks that illuminate his
work. Most frequently, Levinas indicates the double-sidedness of a
phenomenological event by reversing a perspective. For example, to claim
only that the Other is situated in an elevated state as the âMost Highâ
is to miss the full dynamic mobilization of this metaphor. The âheightâ
of the other is the hyperbolic correlate and the perspectival reversal
of the âthe upsurge of the self (le surgisment de soi) One becomes a
subject of being [by] an exaltation, anâabove beingââ (TI 119, TeI 123).
Keeping in mind that the French root âsurâ means âover,â we can then
understand why Levinas insists that we experience history as a
âSURvivorâ (TI 57), why infinity âSURpasses itselfâ (TI 103), and why
fecund temporality is a âreSURrectionâ (TI 56). Through a different
perspectival reversal, this height of separation can also be expressed
as âan abyss within enjoyment itselfâ (TI 141), which becomes
articulated as my âhypostasisâ (TO 54â55) and the Otherâs âdestitutionâ
(TI 78).
Now that we have a preliminary understanding of Levinasâs particular
usage of tropes, we can better investigate why he seems so attached to
what Derrida calls âthe family schemaâ (PF viii). Already a doubling
reversal is expressed through this trope: the âfamiliarâ already
hyperbolically inverts the Otherâs existence as an alien, as ânot
resting on any prior kinshipâ (TI 34). For Levinas, the notion of
âfamilyâ connotes the way an individuated, separated multiplicity of
entities are already related to each other, through social temporalities
and moral obligations that preexist the political order. Contrasting his
analysis with a philosophical tradition stretching from Plato to Hegel,
he asserts âthe family does not only result from a rational arrangement
of animality; it does not simply mark a step towards the anonymous
universality of the State. It identifies itself outside of the State,
even if the State reserves a framework for itâ (TI 306).
Filiality does not emerge simply as a social construction, but rather
constitutes a responsibility for other human beings independently of
unifying structures such as Hegelian Spirit or Heideggerean Being.
Writing from within the phenomenological tradition, Levinas most
pointedly questions the reductive universalization of Husserlâs genus
(TI 194â96), a term derived from the Indo-European GEN, signifying
âbirth.â[13] For Levinas, the generative family demonstrates that,
rather than merely issuing from an origin, existence is a continuous
creation: âthe discontinuity of Cartesian time, which requires a
continuous creation, indicates the very dispersion and plurality of
created beingâ (TI 58).[14]
There is a sense in which Totality and Infinity may be read as if were
the first Book of Moses, Genesis or ×ְ֟ר־×׊×Ö´×ת, [15] the story of the
engendering of generations. It tells a story of life stage development,
from birth through mature home ownership, through old age, through sex
and death, to rebirth. Levinas employs the terminology of birth
repeatedly to describe a variety of interconnected phenomenological
events such as the âlatent birthâ of the subject (OTB 139), the âbirth
of loveâ in Eros (TI 277), and the âbirth of thought, consciousness,
justice, and philosophy of a meaningâ through the third party (OTB 128).
In the life-stage narrative of Totality and Infinity, the event of birth
is explored through the opening section on enjoyment, âthe very
production of a being that is born, that breaks the tranquil eternity of
its seminal or uterine existence to enclose itself in a personâ (TI
147).[16] The motifs Levinas employs in this original section are
connected to other metaphorical networks throughout his work. In
addition to being a member of the biblical triad of destitution along
with the stranger and the widow (TI 77), the âorphanâ describes a
particular aspect of this production of being, âan orphan by birthâ (OTB
105). This orphan event occurs because the child is born separated,
after the erotic death of the mother and the father, âhaving absolved
oneself from relationsâ (TI 195), separated from all relatives,
constantly menaced by neediness. One reversal of this concept--this
conception--of the orphan is the concept of the work, which Levinas
describes as âalways in a certain sense an abortive actionâ (TI 228, my
italics), a doubling of birth and death.
As mentioned above, this continuous GENesis must be understood as a
creative enGENdering, and thus gender informs all phenomenological
matters. As with the family, gender is essential for overcoming a
unifying totality. Levinas asserts, âThe difference between the sexes is
a formal structure, but one that carves up reality in another sense and
conditions the very possibility of reality as multiple, against the
unity of being proclaimed by Parmenidesâ (TO 44). For Levinas, gender is
essential for breaking with âthe neuter (the sole gender formal logic
knows)â (TI 256), and with the neutral, Heideggerean Being that Blanchot
criticizes (TI 298). Unlike German and English which do have neuter
cases, the French language gives all proper nouns a masculine or
feminine gender. For example, âle sujetâ is masculine in French, just as
human subjectivity and political citizenship have traditionally been
figured as masculine by male philosophers.
Now that we have begun to understand what the theme of gender signifies
for Levinas, we can begin to consider the meaning of the Feminine.
Perversely, I am going to attempt to give this Feminine a proper name, a
biblical name. It is not one of the feminine names Levinas gives in
âJudaism and the Feminineâ such as Miriam or Tamar or Leah (DF 31), but
it is perhaps the most frequently used name in the bible. Before I
produce this woman before you, let me begin by suggesting that, in his
early work, Levinas states that âall philosophy is perhaps a meditation
on Shakespeareâ (TO 72). In contrast to the tragic Greek heroes who
confront death as part of their fate and destiny in a Heideggerean
Being-towards-Death, Levinas discusses manâs confrontation with death
through the character of Macbeth. Macbeth not only wishes that the world
would die along with him, âhe wishes that the nothingness of death be a
void as total as that which would have reigned had the world never been
createdâ (TI 231, my italics). Two important things must be said about
this dramatic person who opposes origination. First of all, he is warned
by the witches--the Moirae, the Fates--that his death will come at the
hands of an Other who is ânot of woman born,â his friend MacDuff.
Second, in order to understand who Macbeth himself is, we must
understand that âMacâ is a common Gaelic prefix for âson of.â âMacBethâ
is quite an unusual name because generally these names are patronymic,
such as âJohnsonâ for the son of John or âMacDonaldâ for the son of
Donald, but in this case it would appear that this familiar character is
the son of a woman named âBeth.â
There are multiple reasons why it is useful to express the Feminine as
being named âBeth.â In Hebrew, âBethâ signifies not only a proper name,
but also the second letter of the alphabet, ×Öź. It can function as a
locative prefix indicating âinside,â perhaps even âinteriority.â
Although ×Öź is the second letter of the alphabet, it is the first letter
of creation, the first letter in the first word of the first parshah of
the first book of Torah: ×ְ֟ר־×׊×Ö´×ת, âIn the beginning.â Already in this
very word, the root ר֚×׊×--which can be translated as âheadâ or âfirstâ or
even âáźĎĎÎŽâ-- is preceded by the secondary letter ×Öź. âBethâ in Hebrew
signifies not only the letter ×Öź, but also the word ×ÖźÖˇ×ִת, which translates
as âhouse,â even as âdwelling.â For this reason, âBethâ is the most
frequently used feminine name in the Bible, as a locative signifier in
place names such as âBethelâ and âBeth Israel.â Again, the first word of
Torah, ×ְ֟ר־×׊×Ö´×ת, houses the primary ר֚××Š× within the ×ÖźÖˇ×ִת.
In addition to these various linguistic meanings, ×Öź also has a
mathematical signification: Because Hebrew uses letters to represent
numbers, ×Öź also signifies the number 2. One of the motifs that most
pervasively underlies the Levinasâs work is the question of number. Like
many philosophers before him, Levinas confronts a perennial mathematical
problem: when we think of a certain quantity of things, we generally
conceive of a singularity rather than a multiplicity. That is, when we
contemplate âtwenty dogs,â we typically consider this as a single group
of twenty rather than thinking the twenty-ness of the twenty itself.
Levinas expresses this problem through meditations on plurality and
multiplicity âThe plural is given to a number. Unity alone is
ontologically privileged. Multiple is, but in synthesis is no moreâ (TI
274).
At the risk of implicating Emmanuel Levinas in paganism or kabbalah, let
me state that there is something almost Pythagorean in his thought, in
the sense that numbers are not used merely for counting, but themselves
describe certain configurations of Being. A thorough investigation will
require additional study, but we can begin to account for his numbers
here.
Levinas thinks the ânegativeâ in tension with the skeptical negations of
Descartes (TI 92â93), the dialectical negation of Hegelâs Aufhebung (TI
305), and the negation of Daseinâs death (TI 56). He invokes the
terrible quality of the negative as the il y a, that which exists after
the negation of all particular, positive entities (TI 190, cf. EE
57â64). On the other hand, I establish my own positive, separated
selfhood by negating alterity through labor and integrating it back into
the Same (TI 40â41). Against this murderous violence that âproceeds from
unlimited negationâ (TI 225), the Other can âsovereignly say noâ (TI
199). Negation occurs not only in this masculine confrontation, but also
through the feminine âless than nothingâ (TI 258) encountered in Eros
which has âreference --be it negative--to the socialâ (TI 262).
Closely related to but distinct from the negative is the zero. Before
the positive singularity of selfhood, zero occurs as anarchy (OTB 99),
the zero point (TI 159), the null site (OTB 10), creation ex nihilo (TI
104), freedom originally null (TI 224). More generally, zero describes a
boundary surrounding positive existence as the elemental menace of
nowhere (TI 141), the void of illumination (TI 189), the nothingness of
the future (TI 146), and the âno manâs land.â[17] Relationships through
the zero occur as the erotic caress âseizing upon nothingâ (TI 257), the
ethical âexteriority coming from nothingnessâ (TI 293), substituting
oneself in a ânull placeâ (OTB 116), and fraternity as âa complicity for
nothingâ (OTB 150).
Now that we have begun to work through the negative and the zero, we can
think through the positive, in which we can already hear spatial
âposition,â cognitive âpositing,â and philosophical âpositivism.â The
social and political are produced as a âmultiplicityâ or âpluralityâ (TI
220â2), which is related to but distinct from the âthird partyâ who
calls for justice (TI 157). Alterity itself can be considered as the
greatest positive of all, âinfinityâ (TI 41).
Arithmetical transformations can be illustrated most clearly through the
number one. One is invoked as zero, as the neutralizing, nullifying
singularities of the âunity of the systemâ (TI 150) and
âuniversalizationâ (TI 247). One occurs as singular masculine
subjectivity in the âsolitudeâ of âmanâ (TI 119), as well as in the
âhappiness [that] comes for the first timeâ (TI 114), and the apologetic
âspeech in the first personâ (TI 242). Doubling into one occurs in the
âdual solitudeâ (TI 265) of Eros. Dialogically, it manifests in the
ethical relation to the Other because the neighbor is âthe first one on
the sceneâ (OTB 11), whose âfirst teachingâ of ethical height (TI 171)
expresses âthe first wordâyou shall not commit murderââ (TI 199).
Because the Other is âfrom the first the brother of all menâ (OTB 158),
a âcommunityâ (TI 214) can arise in which âthe unity of plurality is
peaceâ (TI 306).
It is necessary to meditate on this entire network encompassed by the
motif of âoneâ before evaluating Levinasâs assertion that morality is
âfirst philosophyâ (TI 304) or to address the problem that he
âprivilegesâ masculinity.
Just as there is a certain masculinity associated with the single,
femininity is typically manifested as double. Levinas most explicitly
refers to the duality of gender in his Judaic writings. âDid not God
give the nameâAdamâ to man and woman joined together as if the two were
one, as if the unity of the person were able to triumph over the dangers
lying in wait for it only by virtue of a duality inscribed in its
essenceâ (DF 33). Levinas distinguishes yet relates this biblical story
of gender division from the tale of sexual mitosis and nostalgia that
Aristophanes recounts in the Symposium, which he instead uses to
illustrate the âincestuousâ character of Eros (TI 254). Beyond this, 2,
by being the first plural after the singular 1, first opens up plurality
as such. Thus, Levinas asserts that the vital impulse âpresupposes the
intervals of sexuality and a specific dualism in its articulation.
Sexuality is in us neither knowledge nor power, but the very plurality
of our existenceâ (TI 276).
This theme of doubleness applies not only to gender but to absolutely
every movement in Levinasâs thought--the very notion of alterity implies
secondariness.[18] Levinasâs entire analysis is built upon changes in
direction, so duality enters any time he uses the Latin root verter, to
turn,[19] in terms such as âreversionâ and âinversion.â This structure
of doubling is already within all terms prefixed by âequi,â âambi,â
âamphi,â or âdia,â such as âequivocation,â âambiguity,â âamphibology,â
âambiguity,â and âdiachrony.â The double indicates the dynamic tension
of the ânon-assemblable dualityâ (OTB 69), and of the diachronic
interval âbetween two timesâ (TI 58). Doubleness articulates the
orientation between every trope, such as the relation between masculine
Height and its hyperbolic correlate, feminine Depth. This dynamic
reversal occurs not just between the genders in sexuality, but also as
the homosocial âman to man,â the ethical âface to faceâ (TI 79â81).
Through enjoyment and recursion, this doubling is produced even in the
relationship between the ego and the self, the moi and the soi (TO 56),
the nominative âIâ and the accusative âmeâ (OTB 112).
Now that we have a better understanding of the binary character of
gender and the importance of duality throughout Levinasâs work, we can
begin to think more carefully about the problem of the âFeminineâ in
Levinas. Not only does Levinas explicitly discuss the feminine and
masculine aspects of the Other, a careful reading of his texts indicates
that these structures of masculinity and femininity are also present
within the Self. This is most evident in his description of the Home,
whose condition is the Woman.[20] The principal role of the feminine
dwelling is to provide the site for reversion, the base of welcoming
(accueil) for recollection (recueillement) (TI 155; TeI 165), of
acceptance for receptivity. Levinas describes this phenomenological
production, saying âthis refers us to its essential interiority, and to
the inhabitant that inhabits it before every inhabitant, the welcoming
par excellence, welcome in itself â the feminine beingâ (TI 157). If
Levinas here characterizes feminine alterity by the âwelcomeâ it offers,
then we can only conclude that I am figured as a woman only a few pages
later. âI welcome the Other who presents himself in my home by opening
my home to himâ (TI 171, my italics). In fact, my identification as a
welcoming woman is the very basis of Levinasian ethics: âmetaphysics,
transcendence, the welcoming of the other by the same, of the other by
me, is concretely produced as the calling into question of the same by
the other, that is, as ethics that accomplishes the critical essence of
knowledgeâ (TI 43).
Even more than his linking of womanhood with domesticity, Levinasâs
description of the erotic feminine Beloved in âThe Phenomenology of
Erosâ has incurred condemnation from feminist critics for its usage of
stereotypical motifs. It is easiest to conceptualize this section if we
remember that the French slang for orgasm is âla petite mort,â the
little death. When we read Totality and Infinityâs central narrative as
being about continuous creation and recreation, we see that the story
has brought the subject from childhood enjoyment (147â51), to matrimony
(154â56), to adult labor and mastery (158â62), and then to an awareness
of temporal mortality (226â36). After this, the storyline of the
âPhenomenology of Erosâ transits through the arc of death and rebirth,
from âdying without murderâ (258), to sexual âvoluptuosity as a pure
experienceâ (260), to the womblike âcommunity of sentient and sensedâ
(265), and then to the âengendering of the childâ (266). Within this
narrative, Levinas employs several characterizations of the feminine
Beloved (aimee) that have given rise to considerable controversy,
especially his description of âthe beloved return[ing] to the stage of
infancy ... [like] a young animalâ (TI 263, see Walsh 80â82 for a
critique). In response, one should first point out that the motifs
Levinas employs in this section also relate to the wider metaphorical
networks that constitute his thought: the âfrailtyâ of the Beloved
relates to the dynamics of âdestitution;â her âforeignness to the worldâ
relates to the âalterityâ of the Other; her secrecy and profanation,
hiddenness and monstrousness relate to the question of expression and
appearance; her ânudityâ relates to the tropes of embodiment and
exposure; her âultramaterialityâ relates to âmatterâ and the âbody;â her
âvirginityâ and âviolabilityâ relate to the problematics of âviolenceâ
and âmurder.â As mentioned above, the motif of âinfancyâ partakes in the
network of terms connoting birth, which Levinas describes in the
phenomenology of separated enjoyment. In this section, Levinas also
introduces an almost-Bergsonian notion of âanimal need liberated from
vegetable dependence.â[21]
This explication does not necessarily blunt the feminist critique of his
thought, but it complicates the issue considerably. Simone De Beauvoir
is precisely correct: Levinas does âprivilegeâ the masculine. For him,
tropes signifying one-ness and first-ness refer to the masculine, and
tropes signifying duality and two-ness refer to the feminine. However,
it is unclear whether we should necessarily reach from these facts the
conservative conclusion that primacy is âbetterâ than secondariness or
that masculinity is âbetterâ than femininity.
In Gender Trouble, Judith Butler takes this problem of gender even
further by questioning the very binary division of sexuality. âPower
appeared to operate in the production of that very binary frame for
thinking about gender that binary relation betweenâmenâ andâwomenââ
(xxviii). Those attempting to overcome binary gender divisions will find
that, in many ways, gender is the binarism of binarisms for Levinas,
that it could perhaps be considered the paradigm for all other
binarisms. I would argue, however, that sexuality is already so
overdetermined for Levinas that it already anticipates or includes
within it the movements of deconstruction and dialectic, and thus a
deconstructive or dialectical critique must proceed carefully.[22]
Levinas explains repeatedly that the dualism of gender is related to but
not reducible to the biological division between the sexes. Thus, we
could perhaps use his thought to open up the categories of âmasculinityâ
and âfemininityâ for various biological genders; to oppose, along with
Judith âJackâ Halberstam, the fact that âmasculinity has been reserved
for people with male bodies and has been actively denied to people with
female bodiesâ (269). Ultimately, for Levinas, no matter the biological
or ontological gender, both the Self and the Other always embody both
feminine and masculine traits in a state of metaphysical ambisexuality.
(do not penetrate me, oh my angel)
A perverter of philosophy, Emmanuel Levinas continuously corrupts
ontological relationships, demonstrating how ethical ambiguity prevents
the copula, the third-person âisâ of a neutral Being, from reducing the
essential Saying to a nominal Said (OTB 41â4). According to him, the
being of the Self is not a straightforward self-relation but rather a
âfundamental inversion, not of just some function of being, a function
turned from his end, but an inversion in his very exercise of beingâ (TI
63, translation modified). The Self does not relate to itself through a
reflection of selfhood, but rather through the Other, both through an
actual human Other and also through the Other that the Self was in the
past and the Other that it will be in the future. Magnetized by the
displacement that separates the Self from the Other, the ethical
relationship perverts Being from any simple, straight union. Just as
Freud describes perversion as a deviation of the normal sexual aim, âthe
union of the genitals in the act known as copulationâ (15), Levinas
explains how the âreturn to oneselfâ (TI 266) of copulation is perverted
in the âPhenomenology of Erosâ (TI 256â266).
Levinasâs description of the very site of the dual relationship, Eros,
is profoundly ambiguous. It is often unclear how to distinguish the
Lover from the Beloved and the I from the Other; to figure out who is
who and who is doing what to whom; to understand which is feminine and
which masculine. Even more explicitly than the case of welcoming home,
Eros affects a gender transformation. In a statement that can read
heterosexually, homosexually, transsexually, or completely otherwise,
Levinas explains, âThe relation with the carnal and the tender precisely
makes this self arise incessantly: the subjectâs trouble is not assumed
by his mastery as a subject, but in his entenderment [attendrissement],
his effemination, which the heroic and virile I will remember as one of
those things that stand apart fromâserious thingsââ (TI 270, TeI 303,
translation modified).
Reading perversely, I would argue that the section âSubstitutionâ in
Otherwise than Being is Levinasâs return, reversion, and reversal of
Totality and Infinityâs analysis of Eros, a more developed account of
the âeffeminationâ of the âvirile I.â Levinas claims in this chapter
that the approach of the neighbor is experienced as a ânon-erotic
proximity, a desire of the non-desirable, a desire of the stranger in
the neighborâ (OTB 123). We should not let ourselves be misled by these
negations: Levinas repeatedly distinguishes his philosophy from âformal
logic,â which would deduce a complete absence from a negative operation.
Negation is never simple elimination but rather the enactment of a
certain type of relationship. Derrida emphasizes the importance of these
reversals: âIt could doubtless be shown that it is in the nature of
Levinasâs writing, at its decisive moments, to move along these cracks,
masterfully progressing by negations and by negation against negationâ
(WD 90).
When we ourselves explore these cracks, working backwards from the
ânon-eroticâ moment, we can see how extraordinarily sexual
âSubstitutionâ is. The description ânon-eroticâ occurs in the sixth
subsection of the chapter (âFinite Freedomâ), in which Levinas contrasts
âinfantile spontaneityâ with the created âsubject come late into the
worldâ (OTB 122). Previous to this, Levinas seems to be describing a
process of maternal childbirth â not merely in his explicit reference to
âmaternityâ (OTB 104), but also âthe self as a creature is conceived in
a passivityâ (OTB 113, my italics), and âits recurrence is the
contracting of an egoâ (OTB 114, my italics).
Previous to this description of birthing, Levinas seems to describe
metaphorically a process of fornication, in which I am situated as the
recipient of the Otherâs thrusts. I am posited as an open orifice, an
event of being which is the âfolding backâ (OTB 110) or the âhollowing
out the fold of inwardness, in which knowledge is deposited, accumulated
and is formulatedâ (OTB 28). Levinas explains that the for-itself is
ânot the germinal modelâ (OTB 106), but rather occurs in the accusative
as my âpure surrender to the logosâ (OTB 110) â the logos which is
perhaps the logos spermatikos, the fertilizing power of reason.
Similarly, Levinas explains my loss of sovereignty as an experience of
being pricked from the rear. âBacked up against itself the self in its
skin is both exposed to the exterior and obsessed by the others in this
naked exposureâ (OTB 112). In contrast, the Other seems to be getting an
erection: whereas my soul is not âthickening and tumefyingâ (OTB 109),
the Good is a âfirmness more firm than firmâ (112). Ultimately, the
Other is experienced as an âentry inwardsâ (OTB 108); a diachrony that
signifies âthe one-penetrated-by the-otherâ (OTB 49).
Levinasâs description is suggestive enough that this penetration may be
interpreted in a heterosexual âbiblicalâ manner, or in the âGreekâ way
so beloved by Platoâs symposiasts. In many ways a homosexual
interpretation seems more plausible. In Totality and Infinity, Eros can
be read as heterosexual because it occurs between a masculine lover
(lâamant) (TI 257, TeI 288) and a feminine Beloved (lâAimee) (TI 256,
TeI 286), who Levinas characterized as a âsister soulâ that
âself-presents as incestâ (TI 254, translation modified).
âSubstitution,â however, makes no mention of this feminine Beloved.
Instead, she has been substituted by a past conditional subjunctive
perfect âwould have liked to pair up a sister soul [of] substitution and
sacrificeâ (OTB 126), a figure more reminiscent of Sophoclesâ Antigone
than Aristophanesâ fable.
Our interpretation will become even more blasphemous once we examine the
radical turning that determines Levinasâs orientation, sexual and
otherwise, the root verter. Levinas uses the language of inversion in
âSubstitution,â describing obsession as an âinversion of consciousness
[that] is no doubt a passivity â but it is a passivity beneath all
passivityâ (OTB 101). This âinversionâ can perhaps be understood as a
rethematization of the Erotic âeffemination;â in his seminal work,
Havelock Ellis defined inversion as âsexual instinct turned by inborn
constitutional abnormality toward persons of the same sexâ (1). The
invocation of passivity can similarly remind us of Foucaultâs discussion
of the Greek polis. According to Foucault, the Greeks juxtaposed âan
ethos of male superiorityâ with âa conception of all sexual intercourse
in terms of the schema of penetration and male domination.â Thus,
Athenian democracy was compelled to maintain the principles of political
equality among male citizens while still recognizing one as the active,
masculine sexual partner and the other as passive and âfeminizedâ
(220â22).
For Levinas, does not the ethical itself emerge as this very
reconciliation of a dual Eros and a fraternal community? Levinas seems
to highlight the Foucaultian problematic of homosociality, of sociality
and homosexuality, by referring to the âwillâ-- my virile
self-assertion--as âthe psyche backed up against itself,â exposing its
hindquarters. He draws attention to this issue by using the
conspicuously obscure term âtergiversationâ (OTB 112), turning us back
to the same Latin root, tergum (back) + verter (turn).
The thematic of the backside seems to be a Levinasian reversal of the
motif of the visage or face.[23] As many authors including Derrida (WD
108) and Cohen (EHG 244 n5) have commented, Levinasâs reflections on
this figure should return us back to the biblical description of the
face-to-face in Exodus 33:11â23. Interestingly, the Hebrew term for
face, ×¤ÖźÖ¸× Ö´××, derives etymologically from the root ×¤× ×, to turn. Thus,
this same passage of Torah again reverts to a primordial turning. In
this strange narrative, God first speaks âface-to-faceâ (×¤ÖźÖ¸× Ö´×× ×Öś×-×¤ÖźÖ¸× Ö´××)
with Moses, and then the âpresenceâ (×¤ÖźÖ¸× Öˇ×, from the root ×¤× ×) goes with
the Jewish people. After Moses asks not just to speak to the Lord but to
actually see âYour Gloryâ (×ÖźÖ°×Öš×Öś×Ö¸, from the root ×××, to burden or to
respect) God replies that no one may see his face (×¤ÖźÖ¸× Öˇ×, from the root
×¤× ×) and live. Instead, God asks Moses to stand upon a rock. âAnd it
shall come to pass, while My Glory (×ÖźÖ°×Öš×Ö´×, from the root ×××) passeth by,
that I will put thee in a cleft of the rock, and will cover thee with My
hand until I have passed by. And I will take away My hand, and thou
shalt see My backside (×Ö˛×֚רָ×, from the root ××ר, to come after, to differ
or defer); but My face (×¤Ö¸× Öˇ×) shall not be seen.â Although we do not
necessarily agree with the Freudian interpretation of this verse as a
proof of Jewish anal eroticism (Dundes 125), we must admire here how odd
it is to have this Jewish patriarch, this first Messiah of the Jewish
people, this leader of the exodus from slavery, to have Moses looking at
the Glory through a cleft, a crack â we would dare say a âgloryholeâ â
gazing at the rear end of God.
When we try to get to the bottom of Levinasâs views on gender, on the
Cheek-to-Cheek relationship between the sexes, we are still left with an
abyss, a gap inter urinas et faeces, between the manifold creativities
of ejaculation, defecation, and parturition. For Levinas, this is the
very hole that separates the masculine from the feminine, a difference
that corresponds most apparently to heterosexual positions but that
perhaps can be also perverted for homosexuality, lesbianism,
transgender, and other forms of queer sexuality.
Gender and sexuality for Levinas constitute some of the most fundamental
ways that difference is produced in experience, the most important ways
that Otherness resists neutral universalization. However, as many
critics have objected and as this paper has affirmed throughout, Levinas
problematically employs patriarchal themes in his argument. We still who
find value in Levinasâs work must accept responsibility for this
rhetoric, and must carefully consider creative ways to respond to the
protests it has engendered.
Derrida suggest that perhaps one may try to read Levinasâs texts as âa
sort of feminist manifestoâ (1999, 44). Precisely because Levinas so
deliberately exposes patriarchy in his writing, feminist and queer
interpreters can perhaps use his thought to critique patriarchyâs
legacy, to foster more gender openness, and to reconsider the gender and
sexual dimensions of various ethical relationships as well as the
ethical dimensions of various gender and sexual relationships.
In the end, however, this author of this paper you are right now reading
can offer no final answer to these problems, but instead, as both a
Levinas scholar and an anarcha-feminist, can only thank you for your
time and welcome your responses.
de Beauvoir, Simone. The Second Sex, trans. H. M. Parshley. New York:
Knopf, 1968.
Bergo, Bettina. Levinas between ethics and politics. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne UP, 2003.
Bergson, Henri. Creative evolution, trans. Arthur Mitchell. New York:
Random House, 1994.
Butler, Judith. Gender trouble. New York: Routledge, 1990.
Chanter, Tina. âAntigoneâs Dilemma.â In Re-reading Levinas, ed. R.
Bernasconi and S. Critchley. Bloomington: Indiana UP, 1991.
Cohen, Richard A. Elevations: The Height of the Good in Rosenzweig and
Levinas [EHG]. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1994.
--- Ethics, Exegesis and Philosophy [EEP]. Cambridge: Cambridge UP,
2001.
--- âIntroduction.â In Humanism of the Other, ed. R. A. Cohen. Urbana:
University of Illinois Press, 2003.
Critchley, Simon. âFive problems in Levinasâs view of politics and a
sketch of a solution to them.â Political Theory 32 (2004), 172â185.
Deleuze, Gilles. Bergsonism, trans. H. Tomlinson and B. Habberjam. New
York: Zone, 1998.
Derrida, Jacques. Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas, trans. Pascale-Anne Brault
and Michael Naas. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1999.
---. Margins of philosophy [MP], trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: University
of Chicago, 1982.
---. Politics of Friendship [PF], trans. George Collins. London: Verso,
1997.
---. Writing and difference [WD], trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: University
of Chicago, 1978.
Dundes, Alan. The Shabbat elevator. Lanham, MD: Rowhan & Littlefield,
2002.
Ellis, Havelock and John Symonds. Sexual Inversion. New York: Arno
Press, 1975.
Foucault, Michel. The use of pleasure, trans. Robert Hurley. New York:
Pantheon, 1985.
Freud, Sigmund. Three essays on sexuality, trans. James Strachey.
London: Hogarth, 1970.
Handelman, Susan. The Slayers of Moses. Albany: SUNY, 1982.
Heidegger, Martin. Basic Writings [BW], ed. D.F. Krell. San Francisco:
Harper, 1977.
---. Being and Time</em> [BT], trans. J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson. San
Francisco: Harper, 1962.
Hitler, Adolf. Mein Kampf, ed. J. Chamberlain et al. New York: Reynal &
Hitchcock, 1939.
Husserl, Edmund. Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis,
trans. Anthony Steinbock. Boston: Kluwer, 2001.
---. Ideas, first book, trans. Fred Kersten. Boston: Kluwer, 1983.
Juno, Andrea and V. Vale. Angry Women. San Francisco: RE/SEARCH, 1991.
Kant, Immanuel. The Moral Law: Kantâs Groundwork of the Metaphysic of
Morals, ed. H. J. Paton. New York: Barnes & Noble, 1963.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Difficult freedom [DF], trans. SeĂÂĄn Hand. Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins UP, 1990.
---. Existence and Existents [EE], trans. Alphonso Lingis. The Hague:
Martinus Nijoff, 1978.
---. âIs Ontology Fundamentalâ [IOF], trans. Peter Atterton. Philosophy
Today 33:2 (Summer 1989), 121â29.
---. Otherwise than being [OTB], trans. Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne UP, 1998.
---. Time and the Other [TO], trans Richard A. Cohen. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne UP, 1987.
---. Totalite et Infini [TeI]. Paris: Librairie General Francaise â
Livre de Poche, 1990.
---. Totality and Infinity [TI], trans. Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne UP, 1969.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo, trans.
Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage, 1968.
Riemann, Bernhard. âOn the hypotheses which lie at the foundation of
geometry.â In From Kant to Hilbert, ed. William Ewald. Vol 2, 652â661.
Oxford: Oxford UP, 1996.
Scholem, Gershom. Major trends in Jewish mysticism. New York: Schocken,
1954.
Sokal, Alan and Jean Bricmont. Fashionable Nonsense: New York: Picador,
1999.
Steinbock, Anthony. Home and Beyond: Generative Phenomenology after
Husserl. Evanston, IL: Northwestern UP, 1995.
Verter, Mitchell. âViewing Power in Heidegger and Levinas.â Retrieved
August 23, 2007 from <
http://www.waste.org/~roadrunner/writing/thesis.htm
.>
Wahl, Jean. A short history of existentialism, trans. F. Williams and S.
Maron. New York: Philosophical Library, 1949.
Walsh, Lisa. âBetween Maternity and Paternity: Figuring Ethical
Subjectivity,â differences 12.1 (2001), 79â111.
AN OPEN LETTER TO RICHARD A. COHEN AND DUQUENSE PRESS:
In the final chapter of Elevations, âDerridaâs (Mal)Reading of Levinas,â
Richard A. Cohen transforms Levinasâs eschatology of peace into a
declaration of combat. In Cohenâs words, he âpasses over the details of
Derridaâs 99 page deconstructionâ (EHG 305) and instead picks a fight
between Derrida and Levinas: âmy intent is to explain why and with what
good reason Derridaâs essay has been construed as an attack on Levinasâ
(EHG 314 n10). Cohen figures the âLevinas-Derrida conflictâ (EHG 306) as
the very site of an original polemos that âon this ultimate question,
Athens or Jerusalem the true or the good one must take sidesâ (EHG 315).
Cohen argues that Derrida takes Heideggerâs side. Failing to recognize
how Derrida rearticulates the problematic of philosophy and its Other in
order to return to Levinasâs own problematic of Reason and its Other
(TI, 82â101), Cohen claims that âDerridaâs ultimate response to Levinas
is ostracism, exile, exclusion, excisionâ from the philosophical
community.
Cohen regularly attacks Derrida for being Heideggerâs âmost faithful and
cleverâ (EEP 4) disciple dangerously evoking the anti-Semitic
disparagement of the Jew for being merely âcleverâ (for example, Hitler
412 ff.) Worse yet, because Cohen believes Derrida to be a âsycophantic
followerâ (EEP 121) of Heidegger, he refuses to accept the mutual
respect between Derrida and Levinas. Alluding to Adieu, Derridaâs
funeral oration to Levinas, Cohen accuses Derrida of, âhiding behind the
masks and ruses of language, language reduced to rhetoric, escaping
responsibilities and obligations by sayingâadieuâ to Levinasâ (EEP 160).
It is almost impossible to read a line so dense with cruelty. One
trembles with anger and sadness at the demeaning of this friendâs
grievance for the loss of his friend, of this philosopherâs mourning for
another member of the philosophical fraternity, of this motherâs
hospitality that welcomes her child into death, of this sisterâs
obedience to the divine law of ÎÎÎźÎšĎ that urges her towards the anarchic
responsibility of burying her beloved brother.
Claiming that Levinas âsides withâ Jerusalem over Athens, Cohen turns
Levinas into a murderer, claiming that âLevinas cannot live with either
Hegel or Derridaâ (EHG 319). I often wonder whether Cohen has read the
same Levinas that I have. How could an interpreter of Levinas bring such
violence into the field of Levinas studies? How could a reader of
Levinas so willfully ignore his prefatory quest to separate thought from
war (TI 21)? Yet Cohen repeatedly describes philosophical conversation
in the most combative terms, employing the language of fighting,
applying Carl Schmittâs logic of friend and enemy, and transforming
intellectuals into armies.
Is philosophy the same as pugilism and thinking the same as war? Are we
who pretend to be thinkers mere bullies who use ideas as if they were
gloves to beat down opponents? Wouldnât these blows knock us out, numb
us into dogmatism, the slumber from which Kant awoke us over two
centuries ago?
Do philosophers fight or, as Levinas wonders, is âreason constituted
rather in a situation whereâone chats,â where the resistance of a being
as a being is not broken, but pacified?â (IOF 126â27) Hasnât philosophy
been the opportunity to consider what calls for thinking and to whom the
intellectual is responsible? Can we philosophers be what Derrida in his
essay on Levinas refers to as âa community of the question about the
possibility of the question? This is very little â almost nothing â but
within it, today, is sheltered and encapsulated an unbreachable
responsibilityâ (WD 80). Canât we hear Levinasâs direct response to
Derridaâs call to responsibility in the conclusion of the introduction
to Otherwise than Being: âthe naivete of the philosopher calls, beyond
the reflection for oneself, for the critique exercised by another
philosopher Philosophy thus arouses a drama between philosophers and an
intersubjective movementâ?(OTB 20)?
In its new publication of Otherwise than Being, Duquesne Press has
allowed Richard A. Cohen to insert his Foreword before Alphonso Lingisâs
thoughtful, analytic, and often-translated Translatorâs Introduction
(for example, in Cahier de LâHerne: Emmanuel Levinas, edited by
Catherine Chalier and Miguel Abensour.) In this essay, Cohen recruits
Levinas as a warrior in âa new and future gigantomachia that has arisen
in the twentieth centuryâ (OTB xiii). It is unbelievable that such a
veritable call for the fratricide of Cain could enter a book written by
Levinas. Right here and right now, in the very Saying of this very text,
I am please requesting that Richard A. Cohen recant this violence, and
that he and Duquesne Press agree to remove this Foreword from all future
reprints
Thank you for your time. I look forward to your response.
Sincerely Yours,
Mitchell Verter
Even more ambitiously, perhaps we could account for the multiplicity of
tangent vectors by attempting parallel transport between Levinasâs
notion of curvature and the definition of curvature proposed by
mathematician Bernhard Riemann, âthe measure of the deviation of the
manifold from flatness at the given point in the given
surface-directionâ (657). The analogy between Levinas and Riemann could
be perhaps extended as well to Einsteinâs ideas on how gravitational
mass-energy curves space-time.
Although we are mindful of Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmontâs warning to be
cautious when employing technical language, I would assert that there
has always been a fruitful interchange between the natural sciences and
philosophy, even when they donât entirely understand each other.
Levinas rarely makes ambitious claims about mathematics, but he must
have been familiar with basic concepts, especially because at least two
of his earliest philosophical influences, Henri Bergson and Edmund
Husserl, were former mathematicians who wrote about mathematical
concepts. It seems likely that Levinas would have learned about Bernhard
Riemann through these authors. Deleuze remarks, âHusserl too gained
inspiration from Riemannâs theory of multiplicities, although in a
different way from Bergsonâ (118n4). Perhaps we could even trace a path
from Riemann manifolds, through Bergson and Husserl, to correlate the
anarchic âmultiplicitiesâ discussed by both Deleuze and Levinas.
Although this âwomanâ and the home she makes can most evidently be
conceived as a wife for the mature male self, it also implicates the
phallus and the cavity that receives it, the mother and the womb, as
well as the counterpart of the Master: âthe enjoyment that becomes
mistress of the world interiorizing it with respect to its dwellingâ (TI
141, my italics).
Given the ambiguity inherent in the ethical situation, how can we
philosophers then avoid Cohenâs relentless urging to âtake sidesâ and to
treat thinking like a fight between Athens and Jerusalem, a battle on
the Western Front?
[1] Lisa Walsh asserts that â[Levinasâs] assumptions as to the nature of
the maternal and paternal functions draw on the same Greek sensibilities
[as psychoanalysis.]â (80). Although the Greek mythical and
philosophical traditions have influenced Levinas, another distinct but
often interrelated tradition of patriarchy, the Judaic, seems equally if
not more important for him â and arguably for psychoanalysis as well.
[2] The very writer of this very paper is also identified as a white
male. To what extent should any of these words of
identification--subject copula adjective noun--be placed under erasure?
[3] FROM THE BOTTOM,
[4] Genesis Rabbah 38:14. A similar story is told about the same yet
Islamic patriarch Ibrahim in the Qurâan 21:51â59
[5] Scholem 287â324. Seviâs antinomian acts were finally consummated
when, threatened with execution by the Turkish Sultan, he converted to
Islam.
[6] Indeed, Levinas implicates himself as such a blasphemer by daring to
speak against the most infamous blasphemer in philosophy, Friedrich
Nietzsche (OTB, 177).
[7] Derrida writes, beautifully, âLevinas recommends the good usage of
prose which breaks Dionysiac charm or violence, and forbids poetic
rapture, but to no avail. In Totality and Infinity, the use of metaphor,
remaining admirable and most often --if not always--beyond rhetorical
abuse, shelters within its pathos the most decisive movements of the
discourseâ (WD 312 n7).
[8] Thanks to Helen Douglas for this apt wordplay.
[9] Like many other philosophers, most notably Heidegger in Being and
Time, Levinas writes in a prismatic manner. His language is packed so
tightly with words that have been chosen so carefully and that
reverberate against each other in such particular ways that, perhaps if
we meditated upon and fully analyzed just one sentence, it would reveal
the entire complexity of Levinasâs thought. Conversely, almost
Talmudically, we need entire sections from other essays and books to
interpret the placement of each particular word in each particular
sentence.
[10] Nietzsche writes, âThere is only a perspective seeing, only a
perspective knowing.â
http://www.waste.org/%7Eroadrunner/writing/ViewingPower/DescartesAndNietzsche.htm#_ftn42
In many ways, Nietzscheâs critique of a Kantian âeye turned in no
particular directionâ (119) anticipates Levinasâs critique of Hegelian
âpanoramicâ (TI 15) or âsynopticâ (TI 53) thought.
[11] See my paper âViewing Powerâ for an extended exploration of visual
motifs in Descartes, Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Levinas.
[12] Levinas develops his viewpoint on perspective through the motif of
âthe curvature of intersubjective space [that] inflects distance into
elevationâ (TI 291). This curvature occurs through a distortion of
length and height, a warping of vertical and horizontal dimensions, and
a perversion of lateral and hierarchical relationships. Levinasâs notion
of âheightâ has inspired Cohen to discuss his hierarchical âelevationsâ
and Bettina Bergo to look at his stratified âlevels of beingâ (Bergo
55â81). In addition, Levinas also describes the singular ethical
confrontation as various angularities. I would suggest that the âschema
of beingâ in Totality and Infinity does not, as Bergo states, âresemble
the figure of two parabolas intersecting at their basesâ (59). Instead,
his self-described âhyperbolicâ (OTB 49) phenomenology resembles a
hyperbola, the eccentric set of points defined by the difference between
two separated points. Perhaps each of his analyses could be considered
as describing the tangency of infinitely unapproachable asymptotes?
Could this perhaps be compared to Lucretius and Deleuzeâs âclinamen,â
the infinitesimal deviation from a straight path?
[13] Husserl himself seems to recognize the flexibility of this root by
associating essential âgenusâ and âgeneraâ with logical âgeneralityâ
(Ideas 24â25), as well as âgeneticâ and âgenerativeâ phenomenology
(Analyses 628). Even more deliberately, Bergson argues that that a vital
genesis ultimately generates the neutral generality of a priori Kantian
laws (245â46).
[14] In addition, this idea of continuous creation can be found in the
Jewish religion, both in the Talmud and in the morning blessing for the
Lord who ârenews every day the work of creation.â Levinas also finds the
idea in the Greek philosophy of Heraclitus and Cratylus who describe a
âbecoming radically opposed to the idea of being the resistance to every
integration destructive of Parmedian monismâ (TI 59â60). The difference
is often described as a distinction between Parmenidean áźá˝¸Î˝, Being /
Sein / etre and Heraclitean γξνÎĎΚĎ, which is generally translated
either as genesis / Genese / genèse or becoming / Werden / devenir. The
divergence and convergence of these two sets of translations again
announces intriguing proximities between Levinas and Deleuze.
[15] Perhaps we can consider Otherwise than Being as ×Öś×Ö°-×Ö°×Ö¸, the story of
Abrahamâs departure?
[16] Lingis takes care to translate the infantâs practically âoceanicâ
relationship to the element, ânourriture,â into English as
ânourishment,â thus drawing attention etymologically to the way that
maternal âmaterialityâ (133) of the infinitive nourrice, to nurse,
becomes âsubstantialâ (133) and nominal in the infant.
[17] Historically, this phrase was used during the First World War to
refer to the neutral or the disputed territory between battle lines.
Metaphorically, it connotes negativity and femininity, as well as
placement, territoriality, nationalism, and utopia.
[18] In his discussion of Husserl, Anthony Steinbock explains, âAs the
expression of an ordinal number, both terms ander and autre used to mean
and can still meanâsecondââ (58).
[19] Perhaps related to Heideggerâs Kehre?
[20] Because the woman makes the world âfamiliarâ (TI 154â56), she is
the key to all of Levinasâs family tropes.
[21] Compare Bergson 105â35. Throughout Totality and Infinity, Levinas
takes pains to distinguish humanity from mere animality. In Otherwise
than Being, Levinas extends these tropes by employing the motif of
âanimationâ (OTB 69) while analyzing spirit (anima in Greek).
[22] To my knowledge, Luce Irigaray and Jacques Derrida have done the
best work confronting this problem.
[23] Isnât the face already two-sided? The English word âfaceâ can
translate two French, visage and face. Lingis translates le visage as
âthe faceâ of the transcendent Other (TI 25), and la face as âthe sideâ
(TI 131) of the immanent element. Following this logic, le face-Ă -face
should perhaps not be translated as âthe face to face,â but rather as
the opposite, âthe side-to-side.â The ethical encounter occurs only
between two persons, two persona, two masks, two nobodies (deux
personnes); I confront only a front of the Other.