💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-the-meaning-of-confederalism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:35:18. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Meaning of Confederalism
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: 1990
Language: en
Topics: federalism, social ecology
Source: Retrieved on April 28, 2009 from http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/anarchist_archives/bookchin/gp/perspectives20.html
Notes: From Green Perspectives, #20

Murray Bookchin

The Meaning of Confederalism

Few arguments have been used more effectively to challenge the case for

face-to-face participatory democracy than the claim that we live in a

“complex society.” Modern population centers, we are told, are too large

and too concentrated to allow for direct decision-making at a grassroots

level. And our economy is too “global,” presumably, to unravel the

intricacies of production and commerce. In our present transnational,

often highly centralized social system, it is better to enhance

representation in the state, to increase the efficiency of bureaucratic

institutions, we are advised, than to advance utopian “localist” schemes

of popular control over political and economic life.

After all, such arguments often run, centralists are all really

“localists” in the sense that they believe in “more power to the people”

— or at least, to their representatives. And surely a good

representative is always eager to know the wishes of his or her

“constituents” (to use another of those arrogant substitutes for

“citizens”).

But face-to-face democracy? Forget the dream that in our “complex”

modern world we can have any democratic alternative to the nation-state!

Many pragmatic people, including socialists, often dismiss arguments for

that kind of “localism” as otherworldly — with good-natured

condescension at best and outright derision at worst. Indeed, some years

back, in 1972, I was challenged in the periodical Root and Branch by

Jeremy Brecher, a democratic socialist, to explain how the decentralist

views I expressed in Post-Scarcity Anarchism would prevent, say, Troy,

New York, from dumping its untreated wastes into the Hudson River, from

which downstream cities like Perth Amboy draw their drinking water.

On the surface of things, arguments like Brecher’s for centralized

government seem rather compelling. A structure that is “democratic,” to

be sure, but still largely top-down is assumed as necessary to prevent

one locality from afflicting another ecologically. But conventional

economic and political arguments against decentralization, ranging from

the fate of Perth Amboy’s drinking water to our alleged “addiction” to

petroleum, rest on a number of very problematical assumptions. Most

disturbingly, they rest on an unconscious acceptance of the economic

status quo.

Decentralism and Self-Sustainability

The assumption that what currently exists must necessarily exist is the

acid that corrodes all visionary thinking (as witness the recent

tendency of radicals to espouse “market socialism” rather than deal with

the failings of the market economy as well as state socialism).

Doubtless we will have to import coffee for those people who need a

morning fix at the breakfast table or exotic metals for people who want

their wares to be more lasting than the junk produced by a consciously

engineered throwaway economy. But aside from the utter irrationality of

crowding tens of millions of people into congested, indeed suffocating

urban belts, must the present-day extravagant international division of

labor necessarily exist in order to satisfy human needs? Or has it been

created to provide extravagant profits for multinational corporations?

Are we to ignore the ecological consequences of plundering the Third

World of its resources, insanely interlocking modern economic life with

petroleum-rich areas whose ultimate products include air pollutants and

petroleum-derived carcinogens? To ignore the fact that our “global

economy” is the result of burgeoning industrial bureaucracies and a

competitive grow-or-die market economy is incredibly myopic.

It is hardly necessary to explore the sound ecological reasons for

achieving a certain measure of self-sustainability. Most environmentally

oriented people are aware that a massive national and international

division of labor is extremly wasteful in the literal sense of that

term. Not only does an excessive division of labor make for

overorganization in the form of huge bureaucracies and tremendous

expenditures of resources in transporting materials over great

distances; it reduces the possibilities of effectively recycling wastes,

avoiding pollution that may have its source in highly concentrated

industrial and population centers, and making sound use of local or

regional raw materials.

On the other hand, we cannot ignore the fact that relatively

self-sustaining communities in which crafts, agriculture, and industries

serve definable networks of confederally organized communities enrich

the opportunities and stimuli to which individuals are exposed and make

for more rounded personalities with a rich sense of selfhood and

competence. The Greek ideal of the rounded citizen in a rounded

environment — one that reappeared in Charles Fourier’s utopian works —

was long cherished by the anarchists and socialists of the last century.

The opportunity of the individual to devote his or her productive

activity to many different tasks over an attenuated work week (or in

Fourier’s ideal society, over a given day) was seen as a vital factor in

overcoming the division between manual and intellectual activity, in

transcending status differences that this major division of work

created, and in enhancing the wealth of experiences that came with a

free movement from industry through crafts to food cultivation. Hence

self-sustainability made for a richer self, one strengthened by

variegated experiences, competencies, and assurances. Alas, this vision

has been lost by leftists and many environmentalists today, with their

shift toward a pragmatic liberalism and the radical movement’s tragic

ignorance of its own visionary past.

We should not, I believe, lose sight of what it means to live an

ecological way of life, not merely follow sound ecological practices.

The multitude of handbooks that teach us how to conserve, invest, eat,

and buy in an “ecologically responsible” manner are a travesty of the

more basic need to reflect on what it means to think — yes, to reason —

and to live ecologically in the full meaning of the term. Thus, I would

hold that to garden organically is more than a good form of husbandry

and a good source of nutrients; it is above all a way to place oneself

directly in the food web by personally cultivating the very substances

one consumes to live and by returning to one’s environment what one

elicits from it.

Food thus becomes more than a form of material nutririent. The soil one

tills, the living things one cultivates and consumes, the compost one

prepares all unite in an ecological continuum to feed the spirit as well

as the body, sharpening one’s sensitivity to the nonhuman and human

world around us. I am often amused by zealous “spiritualists,” many of

whom are either passive viewers of seemingly “natural” landscapes or

devotees of rituals, magic, and pagan deities (or all of these) who fail

to realize that one of the most eminently human activities — namely,

food cultivation — can do more to foster an ecological sensibility (and

spirituality, if you please) than all the incantations and mantras

devised in the name of ecological spiritualism.

Such monumental changes as the dissolution of the nation-state and its

substitution by a participatory democracy, then, do not occur in a

psychological vacuum where the political structure alone is changed. I

argued against Jeremy Brecher that in a society that was radically

veering toward decentralistic, participatory democracy, guided by

communitarian and ecological principles, it is only reasonable to

suppose that people would not choose such an irresponsible social

dispensation as would allow the waters of the Hudson to be so polluted.

Decentralism, a face-to-face participatory democracy, and a localist

emphasis on community values should be viewed as all of one piece — they

most assuredly have been so in the vision I have been advocating for

more than thirty years. This “one piece” involves not only a new

politics but a new political culture that embraces new ways of thinking

and feeling, and new human interrelationships, including the ways we

experience the natural world. Words like“politics” and “citizenship”

would be redefined by the rich meanings they acquired in the past, and

enlarged for the present.

It is not very difficult to show — item by item — how the international

division of labor can be greatly attenuated by using local and regional

resources, implementing ecotechnologies, resealing human consumption

along rational (indeed, healthful) lines, and emphasizing quality

production that provides lasting (instead of throwaway) means of life.

It is unfortunate that the very considerable inventory of these

possibilities, which I partly assembled and evaluated in my 1965 essay

“Toward a Liberatory Technology,” suffers from the burden of having been

written too long ago to be accessible to the present generation of

ecologically oriented people. Indeed, in that essay I also argued for

regional integration and the need to interlink resources among

ecocommunities. For decentralized communities are inevitably

interdependent upon one another.

Problems of Decentralism

If many pragmatic people are blind to the importance of decentralism,

many in the ecology movement tend to ignore very real problems with

“localism” — problems that are no less troubling than the problems

raised by a globalism that fosters a total interlocking of economic and

political life on a worldwide basis. Without such wholistic cultural and

political changes as I have advocated, notions of decentralism that

emphasize localist isolation and a degree of self-sufficiency may lead

to cultural parochialism and chauvinism. Parochialism can lead to

problems that are as serious as a “global” mentality that overlooks the

uniqueness of cultures, the peculiarities of ecosystems and ecoregions,

and the need for a humanly scaled community life that makes a

participatory democracy possible. This is no minor issue today, in an

ecology movement that tends to swing toward very well-meaning but rather

naive extremes. I cannot repeat too emphatically that we must find a way

of sharing the world with other humans and with nonhuman forms of life,

a view that is often difficult to attain in overly “self-sufficient”

communities.

Much as I respect the intentions of those who advocate local

self-reliance and self-sustainabilty, these concepts can be highly

misleading. I can certainly agree with David Morris of the Institute for

Local Self-Reliance, for example, that if a community can produce the

things it needs, it should probably do so. But self-sustaining

communities cannot produce all the things they need — unless it involves

a return to a back-breaking way of village life that historically often

prematurely aged its men and women with hard work and allowed them very

little time for political life beyond the immediate confines of the

community itself.

I regret to say that there are people in the ecology movement who do, in

fact, advocate a return to a highly labor-intensive economy, not to

speak of Stone Age deities. Clearly, we must give the ideals of

localism, decentralism, and self-sustainability greater and fuller

meaning.

Today we can produce the basic means of life — and a good deal more — in

an ecological society that is focused on the production of high-quality

useful goods. Yet still others in the ecology movement too often end up

advocating a kind of “collective” capitalism, in which one community

functions like a single entrepreneur, with a sense of proprietorship

toward its resources. Such a system of cooperatives once again marks the

beginnings of a market system of distribution, as cooperatives become

entangled in the web of “bourgeois rights” — that is, in contracts and

bookkeeping that focus on the exact amounts a community will receive in

“exchange” for what it delivers to others. This deterioration occurred

among some of the worker-controlled enterprises that functioned like

capitalistic enterprises in Barcelona after the workers expropriated

them in July 1936 — a practice that the anarcho-syndicalist CNT fought

early in the Spanish Revolution.

It is a troubling fact that neither decentralization nor

self-sufficiency in itself is necessarily democratic. Plato’s ideal city

in the Republic was indeed designed to be self-sufficient, but its

self-sufficiency was meant to maintain a warrior as well as a

philosophical elite. Indeed, its capacity to preserve its

self-sufficiency depended upon its ability, like Sparta, to resist the

seemingly “corruptive” influence of outside cultures (a characteristic,

I may say, that still appears in many closed societies in the East).

Similarly, decentralization in itself provides no assurance that we will

have an ecological society. A decentralized society can easily co-exist

with extremely rigid hierarchies. A striking example is European and

Oriental feudalism, a social order in which princely, ducal, and

baronial hierarchies were based on highly decentralized communities.

With all due respect to Fritz Schumacher, small is not necessarily

beautiful.

Nor does it follow that humanly scaled communities and “appropriate

technologies” in themselves constitute guarantees against domineering

societies. In fact, for centuries humanity lived in villages and small

towns, often with tightly organized social ties and even communistic

forms of property. But these provided the material basis for highly

despotic imperial states. Considered on economic and property terms,

they might earn a high place in the “no-growth” outlook of economists

like Herman Daly, but they were the hard bricks that were used to build

the most awesome Oriental despotisms in India and China. What these

self-sufficient, decentralized communities feared almost as much as the

armies that ravaged them were the imperial tax-gatherers that plundered

them.

If we extol such communities because of the extent to which they were

decentralized, self-sufficient, or small, or employed “appropriate

technologies,” we would be obliged to ignore the extent to which they

were also culturally stagnant and easily dominated by exogenous elites.

Their seemingly organic but tradition-bound division of labor may very

well have formed the bases for highly oppressive and degrading caste

systems in different parts of the world-caste systems that plague the

social life of India to this very day.

At the risk of seeming contrary, I feel obliged to emphasize that

decentralization, localism, self-sufficiency, and even confederation

each taken singly — do not constitute a guarantee that we will achieve a

rational ecological society. In fact, all of them have at one time or

another supported parochial communities, oligarchies, and even despotic

regimes. To be sure, without the institutional structures that cluster

around our use of these terms and without taking them in combination

with each other, we cannot hope to achieve a free ecologically oriented

society.

Confederalism and Interdependence

Decentralism and self-sustainability must involve a much broader

principle of social organization than mere localism. Together with

decentralization, approximations to self-sufficiency, humanly scaled

communities, ecotechnologies, and the like, there is a compelling need

for democratic and truly communitarian forms of interdependence — in

short, for libertarian forms of confederalism.

I have detailed at length in many articles and books (particularly The

Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship) the history of

confederal structures from ancient and medieval to modern confederations

such as the Comuneros in Spain during the early sixteenth century

through the Parisian sectional movement of 1793 and more recent attempts

at confederation, particularly by the Anarchists in the Spanish

Revolution of the 1930s. Today, what often leads to serious

misunderstandings among decentralists is their failure in all too many

cases to see the need for confederation — which at least tends to

counteract the tendency of decentralized communities to drift toward

exclusivity and parochialism. If we lack a clear understanding of what

confederalism means — indeed, the fact that it forms a key principle and

gives fuller meaning to decentralism — the agenda of a libertarian

municipalism can easily become vacuous at best or be used for highly

parochial ends at worst.

What, then, is confederalism? It is above all a network of

administrative councils whose members or delegates are elected from

popular face-to-face democratic assemblies, in the various villages,

towns, and even neighborhoods of large cities. The members of these

confederal councils are strictly mandated, recallable, and responsible

to the assemblies that choose them for the purpose of coordinating and

administering the policies formulated by the assemblies themselves.

Their function is thus a purely administrative and practical one, not a

policy making one like the function of representatives in republican

systems of government.

A confederalist view involves a clear distinction between policymaking

and the coordination and execution of adopted policies. Policymaking is

exclusively the right of popular community assemblies based on the

practices of participatory democracy. Administratiom and coordination

are the responsibility of confederal councils, which become the means

for interlinking villages, towns, neighborhoods, and cities into

confederal networks. Power thus flows from the bottom up instead of from

the top down, and in confederations, the flow of power from the bottom

up diminishes with the scope of the federal council ranging

territorially from localities to regions and from regions to

ever-broader territorial areas.

A crucial element in giving reality to confederalism is the

interdependence of communities for an authentic mutualism based on

shared resources, produce, and policymaking. If one community is not

obliged to count on another or others generally to satisfy important

material needs and realize common political goals in such a way that it

is interlinked to a greater whole, exclusivity and parochialism are

genuine possibilities. Only insofar as we recognize that confederation

must be conceived as an extension of a form of participatory

administration — by means of confederal networks — can decentralization

and localism prevent the communities that compose larger bodies of

association from parochially withdrawing into themselves at the expense

of wider areas of human consociation.

Confederalism is thus a way of perpetuating the interdependence that

should exist among communities and regions — indeed, it is a way of

democratizing that interdependence without surrendering the principle of

local control. While a reasonable measure of self-sufficiency is

desirable for every locality and region, confederalism is a means for

avoiding local parochialism on the one hand and an extravagant national

and global division of labor on the other. In short, it is a way in

which a community can retain its identity and roundedness while

participating in a sharing way with the larger whole that makes up a

balanced ecological society.

Confederalism as a principle of social organization reaches its fullest

development when the economy itself is confederalized by placing local

farms, factories, and other needed enterprises in local municipal hands

— that is, when a community, however large or small, begins to manage

its own economic resources in an interlinked network with other

communities. To force a choice between either self-sufficiency on the

one hand or a market system of exchange on the other is a simplistic and

unnecessary dichotomy. I would like to think that a confederal

ecological society would be a sharing one, one based on the pleasure

that is felt in distributing among communities according to their needs,

not one in which “cooperative” capitalistic communities mire themselves

in the quid pro quo of exchange relationships.

Impossible? Unless we are to believe that nationalized property (which

reinforces the political power of the centralized state with economic

power) or a private market economy (whose law of “grow or die” threatens

to undermine the ecological stability of the entire planet) is more

workable, I fail to see what viable altemative we have to the

confederated municipalization of the economy. At any rate, for once it

will no longer be privileged state bureaucrats or grasping bourgeois

entrepreneurs — or even “collective” capitalists in so-called

workers-controlled enterprises — all with their special to promote who

are faced with a community’s problems, but citizens, irrespective of

their occupations or workplaces. For once, it will be necessary to

transcend the traditional special interests of work, workplace, status,

and property relations, and create a general interest based on shared

community problems.

Confederation is thus the ensemble of decentralization, localism,

self-sufficiency, interdependence — and more. This more is the

indispensable moral education and character building — what the Greeks

called paideia — that makes for rational active citizenship in a

participatory democracy, unlike the passive constituents and consumers

that we have today. In the end, there is no substitute for a conscious

reconstruction of our relationship to each other and the natural world.

To argue that the remaking of society and our relationship with the

natural world can be achieved only by decentralization or localism or

self-sustainabilty leaves us with an incomplete collection of solutions.

Whatever we omit among these presuppositions for a society based on

confederated municipalities, to be sure, would leave a yawning hole in

the entire social fabric we hope to create. That hole would grow and

eventually destroy the fabric itself — just as a market economy,

cojoined with “socialism,” “anarchism,” or whatever concept one has of

the good society, would eventually dominate the society as a whole. Nor

can we omit the distinction between policy making and administration,

for once policy making slips from the hands of the people, it is

devoured by its delegates, who quickly become bureaucrats.

Confederalism, in effect, must be conceived as a whole: a consciously

formed body of interdependencies that unites participatory democracy in

municipalities with a scrupulously supervised system of coordination. It

involves the dialectical development of independence and dependence into

a more richly articulated form of interdependence, just as the

individual in a free society grows from dependence in childhood to

independence in youth, only to sublate the two into a conscious form of

interdependence between individuals and between the individual and

society.

Confederalism is thus a fluid and ever-developing kind of social

metabolism in which the identity of an ecological society is preserved

through its differences and by virtue of its potential for ever-greater

differentiation. Confederalism, in fact, does not mark a closure of

social history (as the “end of history” ideologists of recent years

would have us believe about liberal capitalism) but rather the point of

departure for a new eco-social history marked by a participatory

evolution within society and between society and the natural world.

Confederation as Dual Power

Above all, I have tried to show in my previous writings how

confederation on a municipal basis has existed in sharp tension with the

centralized state generally, and the nation-state of recent times.

Confederalism, I have tried to emphasize, is not simply a unique

societal, particularly civic or municipal, form of administration. It is

a vibrant tradition in the affairs of humanity, one that has a

centuries-long history behind it. Confederations for generations tried

to countervail a nearly equally long historical tendency toward

centralization and the creation of the nation-state.

If the two — confederalism and statism — are not seen as being in

tension with each other, a tension in which the nation-state has used a

variety of intermediaries like provincial governments in Canada and

state governments in the United States to create the illusion of “local

control,” then the concept of confederation loses all meaning.

Provincial autonomy in Canada and states’ rights in the United States

are no more confederal than “soviets” or councils were the medium for

popular control that existed in tension with Stalin’s totalitarian

state. The Russian soviets were taken over by the Bolsheviks, who

supplanted them with their party within a year or two of the October

Revolution. To weaken the role of confederal municipalities as a

countervailing power to the nation-state by opportunistically running

“confederalist” candidates for state govemment — or, more nightmarishly,

for governorship in seemingly democratic states (as some U.S. Greens

have proposed) is to blur the importance of the need for tension between

confederations and nation-states — indeed, they obscure the fact that

the two cannot co-exist over the long term.

In describing confederalism as a whole — as a structure for

decentralization, participatory democracy, and localism — and as a

potentiality for an ever-greater differentiation along new lines of

development, I would like to emphasize that this same concept of

wholeness that applies to the interdependencies between municipalities

also applies to the muncipality itself. The municipality, as I pointed

out in earlier writings, is the most immediate political arena of the

individual, the world that is literally a doorstep beyond the privacy of

the family and the intimacy of personal friendships. In that primary

political arena, where politics should be conceived in the Hellenic

sense of literally managing the polls or community, the individual can

be transformed from a mere person into an active citizen, from a private

being into a public being. Given this crucial arena that literally

renders the citizen a functional being who can participate directly in

the future of society, we are dealing with a level of human interaction

that is more basic (apart from the family itself) than any level that is

expressed in representative forms of governance, where collective power

is literally transmuted into power embodied by one or a few individuals.

The municipality is thus the most authentic arena of public life,

however much it may have been distorted over the course of history.

By contrast, delegated or authoritarian levels of “politics” presuppose

the abdication of municipal and citizen power to one degree or another.

The municipality must always be understood as this truly authentic

public world. To compare even executive positions like a mayor with a

govemor in representative realms of power is to grossly misunderstand

the basic political nature of civic life itself, all its malformations

notwithstanding. Thus, for Greens to contend in a purely formal and

analytical manner — as modern logic instructs that terms like

“executive” make the two positions interchangeable is to totally remove

the notion of executive power from its context, to reify it, to make it

into a mere lifeless category because of the extemal trappings we attach

to the word. If the city is to be seen as a whole, and its

potentialities for creating a participatory democracy are to be fully

recognized, so provincial governments and state governments in Canada

and the United States must be seen as clearly established small

republics organized entirely around representation at best and

oligarchical rule at worst. They provide the channels of expression for

the nation-state — and constitute obstacles to the development of a

genuine public realm.

To run a Green for a mayor on a libertarian municipalist program, in

short, is qualitatively different from running a provincial or state

governor on a presumably libertarian muncipalist program. It amounts to

decontextualizing the institutions that exist in a municipality, in a

province or state, and in the nation-state itself, thereby placing all

three of these executive positions under a purely formal rubric. One

might with equal imprecision say that because human beings and dinosaurs

both have spinal cords, that they belong to the same species or even to

the same genus. In each such case, an institution — be it a mayoral,

councillor, or selectperson — must be seen in a municipal context as a

whole, just as a president, prime minister, congressperson, or member of

parliament, in turn, must be seen in the state context as a whole. From

this standpoint, for Greens to run mayors is fundamentally different

from running provincial and state offices. One can go into endless

detailed reasons why the powers of a mayor are far more controlled and

under closer public purview than those of state and provincial

office-holders.

At the risk of repetition, let me say that to ignore this fact is to

simply abandon any sense of contextuality and the environment in which

issues like policy, administration, participation, and representation

must be placed. Simply, a city hall in a town or city is not a capital

in a province, state, or nation-state.

Unquestionably, there are now cities that are so large that they verge

on being quasi-republics in their own right. One thinks for example of

such megalopolitan areas as New York City and Los Angeles. In such

cases, the minimal program of a Green movement can demand that

confederations be established within the urban area — namely, among

neighborhoods or definable districts — not only among the urban areas

themselves. In a very real sense, these highly populated, sprawling, and

oversized entities must ultimately be broken down institutionally into

authentic muncipalities that are scaled to human dimensions and that

lend themselves to participatory democracy. These entities are not yet

fully formed state powers, either institutionally or in reality, such as

we find even in sparsely populated American states. The mayor is not yet

a governor, with the enormous coercive powers that a govemor has, nor is

the city council a parliament or statehouse that can literally legislate

the death penalty into existence, such as is occurring in the United

States today.

In cities that are transforming themselves into quasi-states, there is

still a good deal of leeway in which politics can be conducted along

libertarian lines. Already, the executive branches of these urban

entities constitute a highly precarious ground — burdened by enormous

bureaucracies, police powers, tax powers, and juridical systems that

raise serious problems for a libertarian municipal approach. We must

always ask ourselves in all frankness what form the concrete situation

takes. Where city councils and mayoral offices in large cities provide

an arena for battling the concentration of power in an increasingly s

trong state or provincial executive, and even worse, in regional

jurisdictions that may cut across many such cities (Los Angeles is a

notable example), to run candidates for the city council may be the only

recourse we have, in fact, for arresting the development of increasingly

authoritarian state institutions and helping to restore an

institutionally decentralized democracy.

It will no doubt take a long time to physically decentralize an urban

entity such as New York City into authentic municipalities and

ultimately communes. Such an effort is part of the maximum program of a

Green movement. But there is no reason why an urban entity of such a

huge magnitude cannot be slowly decentralized institutionally. The

distinction between physical decentralization and institutional

decentralization must always be kept in mind. Time and again excellent

proposals have been advanced by radicals and even city planners to

localize democracy in such huge urban entities and literally give

greater power to the people, only to be cynically shot down by

centralists who invoke physical impediments to such an endeavor.

It confuses the arguments of advocates for decentralization to make

institutional decentralization congruent with the physical breakup of

such a large entity. There is a certain treachery on the part of

centralists in making these two very distinct lines of development

identical or entangling them with each other. Libertarian municipalists

must always keep the distinction between institutional and physical

decentralization clearly in mind, and recognize that the former is

entirely achievable even while the latter may take years to attain.

November 3, 1990