đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș karl-klien-contemporary-platformism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:52:25. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Contemporary Platformism Author: Karl Klien Date: 2010 Language: en Topics: platformism, Anarchist Federation Source: Retrieved on 10th December 2021 from https://libcom.org/library/contemporary-platformism-critical-study Notes: A discussion document published by the Anarchist Federation in Sheffield. It analyses Platformism as both a valuable tradition within anarchist communism, along with looking critically at the practice of contemporary Platformist groups.
The following should be considered a discussion document and not the
collective position of either the Sheffield group or the national
federation as a whole. The ideas presented here have been developed
through much formal and informal internal debate and discussion within
the federation. It is intended as a contribution to a wider debate
concerning the current composition of the international anarchist
movement. Many thanks to all those who assisted in its development.
There has perhaps never been such a controversial contribution to the
theory and practice of the anarchist movement than those ideas forwarded
by the Dielo Truda (âWorkersâ Causeâ) group in the âOrganisational
Platform of the General Union of Anarchists (Draft)â. The document has
been both praised as a âvaluable historical referenceâ for
class-struggle anarchists seeking âgreater effectiveness and a way out
of political isolation, stagnation and confusionâ (Heath, 1989), while
also been denounced outright as an attempt to âBolsheviseâ anarchism
(Voline et al., 1927). Yet âPlatformismâ, as contemporary adherence to
the principles of the Platform is generally referred to, continues to be
a vibrant tradition within the global anarchist movement. The Anarkismo
Statement, for example, which is widely considered to be the most
contemporary expression of Platformist principles, has signatories
spanning the globe. Especifismo, an organisational programme emerging
out of Latin American anarchism, although not directly linked to the
Platform, also shares many of the priorities of Platformist groups
-theoretical and tactical unity, collective responsibility and
federalism â and has gained greater influence in recent years within the
global anarchist community. Platformism also continues to be a divisive
issue for our movement. Anarchists will typically position themselves on
either side of the divide, as against or in favour of the positions
outlined by the Platform. Since its publication there has been a great
deal of suspicion and sectarianism between the two parties. Platformists
will be denounced as âauthoritarianâ or âLeninistâ, while Platformists
will routinely accuse other anarchists of being âineffectiveâ or
âdisorganisedâ. It is the purpose of this paper to attempt to cut across
this divide and to reconcile these two images of Platformism. To, at the
same time as appraising the theory and practice of contemporary
Platformist groups, emphasise that which should be considered and
valuable and useful within the perspectives of Platformism to all social
anarchists. This, I hope, will be part of a broader, more constructive
dialogue within our movement and instigate some open and honest
appraisal of our own values regardless of the labels that we may attach
to ourselves.
Notes on this enquiry: Unfortunately this paper is restricted to
documents that exist in, or have been translated into, the English
language only. I realise that some of the groups I will be discussing do
not speak English as a first language and this may restrict my
understanding of them. I have, given the materials available to me,
endeavoured to represent them in the most accurate way possible. I
welcome criticism and additional sources on any of these points. My
analysis will also largely be framed by the British experience and the
British and Irish anarchist movement, given that this is the context in
which I am politically active as a member of the Anarchist Federation.
The discussion will also be largely limited to contemporary Platformist
groups only. This decision was made due to obvious limitations on space
and time in terms of the scale of this work but also on the basis that
there are already well researched histories of the Platform and
Platformist groups available[1].
To understand contemporary Platformism it is important to first
understand the context in which those ideas have developed as an
independent tradition within the anarchist movement. Following
counter-revolution in Russian in the wake of the October revolution, two
strains of thought emerged from Russian and Ukrainian exiles on the
perceived failures of the anarchist movement in those countries. For the
Dielo Truda group it was the lack of organisational principles that had
led to the general weakness and lack of influence of anarchist ideas.
The seminal contribution of the Platform document was, therefore, to
stress the importance of tactical and theoretical unity and a shared
understanding of theory and goals across any future anarchist
organisation. The Platform also argued for the primacy of class-struggle
anarchism, indeed, that anarchism as a political philosophy owed its
origins in the struggle of working people. Platformists, consequently,
argue that anything other than this is a recipe for disunity and
organisational paralysis as different tendencies struggle to reconcile
their own values into the common practice of the organisation.
These ideas were in opposition to those ideas emerging from another
group of Russian exiles around Voline and those of the âsynthesistâ
position. For Voline and his comrades, the Dielo Truda group over-stated
the influence of organisation in the failures of the anarchists and
attributed the problems more to the difficulty of propagating anarchist
ideas within the population and to Bolshevik-led, state repression
(although they also did acknowledge a lack of theoretical coherence
within the Russian movement at the time). They rejected the notion that
anarchist communism was the only valid expression of anarchism and were
keen to emphasise the holistic character of the philosophy as
represented in its different traditions â communism, syndicalism,
mutualism, individualism etc. Voline, accordingly, advocated the
development of synthesist federations which aimed to unite all
self-identifying anarchists â individualist, syndicalist, mutualist,
collectivist, religious etc. â under one banner on the basis of their
shared opposition to the state and their desire for human freedom. The
central idea was that unity and non-sectarian co-operation were the best
means to strengthen the existing anarchist movement. Although it should
also be noted that many synthesist groups were much more limited in
scope, for example, advocating the unity of all âsocialâ anarchists
(-syndicalist, -communist, -collectivist), potentially providing greater
common ground and space for co-operation than there would be with those
activists simply opposed to the state.
Disputes over who, Voline and the syntheists or Makhno and the Dielo
Truda Group, had taken the greater lesson from the Bolshevik experience
were, and continue to be, a source of bitter division for anarchists in
both continental Europe and the Americas over the greater part of the
last Century. In this respect both Platformism and Synthesism are
clearly identifiable and well-established traditions within these
respective movements. In Britain, however, the situation has been
slightly different. Synthesism, for example, is a school of anarchist
thought that has traditionally developed within the context of great
factional disputes within strong, established anarchist movements. The
early contributions of the Cuban-born anarchists Fernando Tarrida del
MĂĄrmol and Ricardo Mella, of anarquismo sin adjetivos (an âanarchism
without adjectivesâ) to the Spanish anarchist movement were meant to
repair the divide between the warring factions of collectivist and
communist anarchists. Likewise, Malatesta would advocate a âwait and
seeâ attitude to questions on post-revolutionary economic organisation
as a means of advocating greater tolerance between the various strands
of social anarchism he encountered throughout his lifetime. Voltairine
de Cleyre would also emphasise post-revolutionary experimentation with
different forms of social organisation as a means of finding common
ground between groups of individualist and communist anarchists in North
America. Britain has, however, never really enjoyed a comparatively
large or diverse anarchist movement. The individualist philosophy of Max
Stirner, in particular, while gaining great influence in the early
French, Spanish and German anarchist movements, was never as widely read
or as influential in Britain, aside from in the writings of a few
noteworthy artists and intellectuals[2]. Similarly, despite a number of
native socialist movements sharing similar goals to that of the
anarchist traditions of collectivism and mutualism neither really
enjoyed a sustained influence as a philosophy in its own right. Early
proponents of anarchism in Britain â Charles Mowbray, Fred Charles, Guy
Aldred â emerged largely out of the communist movement and were,
therefore, largely drawn towards anarchist communism or
anarcho-syndicalism as the best organisational expression of anarchist
ideals. Where British groups have incorporated anarchists from a variety
of traditions it was largely the result of geographical isolation as
opposed to any formal ideological commitment[3].
The key assertion of the Platform, therefore â that anarchism is a
political philosophy foremost associated with the struggles of working
people for free communism â has been a strong and lasting tradition
within the organised British anarchist movement. Accordingly, in the
British context, Platformism has not been foremost a critique of
synthesism or other economic theories of post-revolutionary organisation
(as it has been in Europe and in the Americas), but a reference point
for the need for greater coherence and tactical unity to an already
fairly ideologically coherent social anarchist movement. We can see
this, for example, in Heathâs (1996) account of the formation of
Britainâs first Platformist group â the Organisation of Revolutionary
Anarchists (ORA);
ORAâs objections to the traditional anarchist movement then, were more
on the level of organisation than of theory. Their advocacy of
collective responsibility, the use of a Chair and voting to take
decisions at meetings, formal membership and a paper under the control
of its âwriters, sellers and readersâ (Heath, 1996)
Likewise where oppositional currents have existed it has not been on
points of principle, i.e. for non-sectarianism or anarchist unity, but
over tactics, for example, local over national organisation or, more
recently, the influence of insurrectionalist ideas. The question,
therefore, has been largely one of tactics and organisation than
theoretical commitment[4]. Accordingly, the rest of this enquiry will
largely focus on the âOrganisational Sectionâ of the Platform, also the
most commonly cited section, and the organisational principles of
tactical and theoretical unity, collective responsibility and
ideological leadership. While debates over Synthesism and non-sectarian
practice are important, this is not an issue of particular relevance to
the experience of the majority of British anarchists (having unlikely
ever encountered a collectivist/individualist/mutualist anarchist).
It is all the more important then, in order to come to a true
understanding of the existing Platformist tradition to also avoid the
often quite crude, but quite frequent, divisions presented in many
contemporary accounts of the British anarchist movement. Depending on
the authorsâ sympathies, all non-Platformist strains of anarchism will
be presented as inherently disorganised and/or a failing to appreciate
the necessity of organisational coherence and unity. Or Platformism will
be presented as a rigidly enforced revolutionary doctrine and
Platformists as needlessly preoccupied with questions of organisational
form[5]. Both positions are not only over-simplifications but obvious
misrepresentations. The picture of the âBolshevisedâ Platformists on one
hand and the disorganised âsmall-a anarchistsâ on the other in the end
does justice to neither party. All anarchists will, to some degree,
address the important issue of revolutionary organisation. Similarly,
all strains of anarchism, even insurrectional ones, acknowledge the
benefits and necessity of some principled unity in practice. To argue
that the Platform stands alone on this point is to in fact sell it far
short of its true value as a guide for organisational praxis. What
Platformists do argue for, and what makes the tradition unique, is the
necessity of a certain method of reaching this organisational coherence
â namely the process of theoretical and tactical unity. That is, of
course, also not to acknowledge how contentious this particular idea has
been.
Franks (2006) in his history of the contemporary British anarchist
movement disparagingly compares theoretical and tactical unity with
Leninism arguing that it leads to âcentralisationâ, a âpaternalistic
attitudeâ and, ultimately, the âformation of revolutionary cadreâ[6].
This is not a particularly new criticism, the process has also often
been characterised as a desire for âmono-thinkâ, a point that Malatesta
first touches on in his exchange with Makhno;
the authors of the Platform say that it is the âUnionâ that wills and
disposes. But when mention is made of the will of the Union, does this
perhaps mean the will of all its members? In that case, for the Union to
be able to operate it would be necessary for everyone, always and on
every subject, to have the same opinion. (Malatesta, 1927)
Clarity on this issue is not aided by the fact that the Organisational
Section of the Platform, the bit which deals with theoretical and
tactical unity, is quite short and not particularly detailed in its
exposition of these key ideas; it was, after all, originally only
intended as a discussion document. Contemporary groups, however, have
been pretty unequivocal on this issue. The North American-based North
Eastern Federation of Anarchist Communists (NEFAC), for example, state
that;
Theoretical Unity meant simply that if you donât agree with someone,
donât be in a political group with them! This doesnât mean that everyone
has to agree all the time (they wonât) but there does need to be a
certain amount of ideological unity. Everyone being âanarchistsâ or
âlibertarianâ isnât enough. (NEFAC, 2003)
Moreover they also explicitly reject a âmajoritarianâ approach to the
development of the theory and tactics of the organisation. A commitment
which is designed to encourage criticism of established positions and,
subsequently, avoid a stagnant and conservative political culture. In
other words, they argue that dissident and minority positions are to be
considered to be as valuable as, and not necessarily in conflict with,
the overarching aims of an organisation that strives for unity;
Anarchists are fully aware that the presence of a minority and a
majority does not mean at all that the majority is inherently right.
Thatâs why any anarchist organization needs to have mechanisms that
enable a minority, while still bound by the decisions taken by the
organization, to defend itâs point of view inside the organization, even
if it was beaten at a conference or in the federation council. In any
case, an anarchist organization must be an environment where
sectarianism is discouraged and dialogue promoted, and where an
atmosphere of camaraderie reigns. (NEFAC, 2002)
In other words, a Platformist organisation needs to find an appropriate
balance between both respecting the collective decision of the majority
and the right to dissent of the minority.
Accusations of theoretical and tactical unity as âmono-thinkâ generally
derive from an understanding of theoretical and tactical unity as
static, as a goal to be achieved and not, as should be the case with
healthy Platformist groups, a continuing process during the course of
activity. It is also, as NEFAC argue, not necessary to reach unanimous
agreement on every single issue. Rather the aim should be to always aim
for common understanding and interpretation on those issues most central
to organisational praxis. This has to happen within the context of a
dialogue existing between all members on both the most valuable ideas
that each holds and on the best common course of action for the future.
This process should be participative and dissent actively encouraged as
both a means to achieve better consensus and as a valuable personal
capacity in itself. Even agreed positions should be open to renewed
debate and re-evaluation. An organisation that attempts to set all of
its analysis in stone is ultimately inflexible, out-of-touch and highly
vulnerable to the entrenchment of hierarchies of experience.
Moreover, formal and established channels of decision-making should not
be perceived as bureaucratic or lacking dynamism. They are actually a
powerful tool to undermine the kind of informal hierarchies that
frequently crop up in other activist groups where there arenât such
clear-cut channels of accountability and communication. As Thomas (2010)
argues;
Societal influences, from oppressive socialisation such as racism and
sexism, to personality differences such as being shy or being talkative
are likely to create informal hierarchies that reintroduce domination
and hierarchy within the group if clear, explicit, collectively-
established democratic practices are not established and followed.
(Thomas, 2010)
Platformists encourage, or at least should encourage, deep and critical
re-appraisal of the actions that their organisations take. An
organisation should exist to enable those within it to carry out
activity, share ideas and experience and inspire confidence within each
member
The importance of these principles is also underlined by the context
(the British anarchist movement) in which they are being encouraged,
where there is a general absence of sustained, critical reflection
within the movement as a whole. Many anarchist initiatives are sporadic
and dependent on the admirable efforts of dedicated individuals for
their longevity. In the very worst instances this can and has led to
ghettoising tendencies, of anarchists shrinking back into the comfort
zones of organising inside small groups of like-minded and approving
individuals. Platformism puts forward a credible alternative to the
repertoire of localised activist âscenesâ which too often exhibit a
short-lived, under-theorised and, often uncritical, approach to
political action â a practice that easily degenerates into an endless
cycle of self-referential activity justified as an end unto itself.
Undoubtedly related to this, Platformists also take far more seriously
the challenge that working class activists face in terms of the
authoritarian and reformist tendencies faced in everyday organising.
Often anarchists will retreat into a scene either out of a desire for
organisational purity, in order to better embody the ideals and
practices they advocate, or simply through lack of an alternative. In
reality, until there is a revolutionary reconstruction of our current
society, there can be no space untouched by the influence of capitalism,
patriarchy, hetero-normativity and the State. These things permeate
every aspect of our lives, at work, in the homes, even amongst partners
and within friendship groups. The response should not be to retreat, but
to strengthen our ideals through action towards the society we hope to
create. The reality is that there is no perfect or pure struggle.
Everywhere anarchists will face reformists and authoritarians (from the
Left and Right) who will attempt to control or subdue struggles.
Individuals involved in these struggles will also often exhibit
contradictory ideas, or have ideas that may seem to conflict with those
we wish to advocate (many people are nationalist, or religious, for
example). Against this, Platformists argue that we need to be well
organised, we need to have confidence in our own ideas and we need to
act on a common programme. Being an organised anarchist means having
trust in your comrades, being able to put forward a coherent strategy
and embodying a common set of ideals that inspires others to do the
same.
The strategy by which this is achieved is, to bring in two more
important concepts from the original document, is by principles of
collective responsibility and through ideological leadership. These,
again, have been controversial propositions. For example, to return to
Franksâ (2006) criticisms, collective responsibility is described as a
âcontractual obligationâ that is âcontrary to the aims of anarchismâ
(p.223). It is clear from the document, however, that this was far from
the Dielo Truda groupâs interpretation. Instead, I would argue, the
notion of collective responsibility develops from their understanding of
âthe areas of revolutionary lifeâ as âabove all profoundly collective by
natureâ. That is, that while the organisation should recognise âeach
memberâs rights to independence, free opinion, individual liberty and
initiativeâ, it is also not merely an accumulation of individuals but,
just like a revolutionary society, communal in nature. As such a degree
of collective thinking, acting and, ultimately, responsibility is an
important component of organisational praxis. As Thomas explains;
Holding each other accountable also means getting used to letting each
other know â in a comradely way â when commitments and obligations
arenât being fulfilled. This is a practice that must be built through an
organisational culture where comradely honesty and constructive
criticism replaces competitive and individualistic
passive-aggressiveness or talking behind peopleâs backs. The flip side
of giving comradely feedback is learning how to receive it, using it to
help you and your organisation grow and becoming more self-disciplined.
This is difficult sometimes since the vast majority of the times weâre
being called to task for something, it is coming from top-down
relations; but the practice of holding others accountable and being held
accountable is fundamental to learn, practice and promote if we want to
destroy and replace these top-down relations with horizontal and
egalitarian relations. (Thomas, 2006)
Put more simply, and applied more practically, in essence this is the
very basic idea that if a group of people come to an agreement that
something should be done then they should do it! Accusations that this
implies some form of contractual obligation ignores the emphasis on
voluntarism and free association, not least the fact that in the
Platform itself there is no mention of any kind of disciplinary
mechanism or system of coercion. Of course, many of these disagreements
may ultimately boil down to language and a matter of interpretation[7].
Malatesta, for example, was happy to concede comradeship as essential to
anarchist organisation while also feeling that âcollective
responsibilityâ was too vague a concept invoking anything from strict
military discipline to voluntary association.
Anarchists have always considered âleadershipâ to some degree synonymous
with the exercise of authority. Accordingly a âleadership of ideasâ or
ideological leadership needs to be carefully articulated. The Platform
document, for its part, is pretty clear in its criticism of the
ârevolutionary leadershipâ of the Leninist organisations which
considered the masses backward and incapable of social change alone;
While Bolshevism and its related tendencies consider that the masses
possess only destructionary revolutionary instincts, being incapable of
creative and constructive activity â the principle reason why the latter
activity should be concentrated in the hands of the men forming the
government of the State of the Central Committee of the party â
anarchists on the contrary think that the labouring masses have inherent
creative and constructive possibilities which are enormous, and
anarchists aspire to suppress the obstacles impeding the manifestation
of these possibilities. (Dielo Truda, 1926)
The need for âideological leadershipâ derives from an understanding that
social struggle does not represent a vacuum of ideas and the presence of
a clear, revolutionary perspective is the anarchistâs responsibility.
Likewise, the absence of such a perspective can be disastrous for social
struggle, a position that Arshinov states more clearly in his âReply to
Anarchismâs Confusionistsâ;
Direction of the masses from the âideasâ point of view simply means the
existence of a guiding idea in their movement. In the world of socialist
struggle and socialist demands, such ideas are not numerous. But it is
natural that we anarchists wanted the toilersâ guiding idea to be the
anarchist idea and not that of the social democrats for example, of
those who have only recently betrayed the Viennese workersâ
revolutionary movement. (Arshinov, 1927)
Looking at a more contemporary example within the British context, Heath
(2006), when outlining the history of the movement throughout the 1960s,
emphasises that anarchist failings, in terms of both organisation and
ideological leadership, were quickly translated into the Leftâs gains;
It was no surprise that many who had been initially attracted to
anarchism were deterred by its chronic disorganisation and lack of
effectiveness. Some of these turned to groups like International
Socialism (precursor of the Socialist Workers Party) and the
International Marxist Group. Digger Walsh, active in the Black Flag
group of the period, was to be quoted in a national paper as lamenting
the fact that 800 militants had gone over to the Trotskyists. (Heath,
2006)
This example also serves to neatly illustrate the inter-connected nature
of all of the components of the Organisational Section. That without a
combination of ideological leadership, tactical and theoretical
responsibility and collective responsibility the anarchist organisation
is rendered less effective than its competitors. That a revolutionary
strategy and a unified tactical response go hand in hand with building
credibility for anarchist ideas. Yet, regardless of these qualifications
over the nature of âideological leadershipâ there have been lingering
and legitimate concerns over whether this is a âleadership from withinâ
or a âleadership from withoutâ. In other words, whether these ideas
emerge in the course and through dialogue with instances of social
struggle or whether they develop from external and independent study and
deliberation, a form of Marxian âproletarian scienceâ. This is a key
issue and one which I will explore in greater detail in the critical
section.
Finally, it is important to emphasise that many contemporary Platformist
groups do not hold to all the organisational prescriptions of the
original document. For example, many contemporary Platformists have
distanced themselves from the idea of âoneâ General Union, effectively
conceding Malatestaâs point, out of practicality if anything, in his
exchange with Makhno over the preference for many vs. one anarchist
organisation. The Dielo Truda Groupâs position is unclear in the
original document as to what will become of the âunhealthy elementsâ (as
Malatesta puts is) of the anarchist movement, i.e. those not convinced
of the wisdom of the ideas of the Platform. The practice of the modern
Platformist movement would suggest, however, that those âdisorganisedâ
and âchaoticâ elements would continue to be just that. Rather than
attempting to âexcommunicate them from the anarchist movementâ, as
Malatesta suggested would be the case, the preferred outcome would be
that these disparate elements would become eventually superseded in both
size and reputation by the successes of a well organised libertarian
communist organisation (or amalgamation of organisations).
An underlying idea here, and a point that all Platformists are keen to
emphasise, is Platformism as a tradition embodying shared organisational
goals, not simply the prescriptions of a single document. The âFriends
of Durrutiâ Group are, for example, often cited by Platformists as an
inspiration for the tradition in spite of making no reference to the
Platform or the Dielo Truda Group in their revolutionary programme.
After all, the Platform itself never claimed to be definitive and made
clear that it was up to the movement to enrich the tradition and
principles associated with it through practice. As is stated in the
original document;
We have no doubts that there are gaps in the present platform. It has
such gaps, as do all new, practical steps of any importance. It is
possible that certain important positions have been missed, or that
others are inadequately treated, or that still others are too detailed
or repetitive. All this is possible, but not of vital importance. What
is important is to lay the foundations of a general organisation, and it
is this end which is attained, to a necessary degree, by the present
platform. It is up to the entire collective, the General Union of
Anarchists, to enlarge it, to later give it depth, to make of it a
definite platform for the whole anarchist movement. (Dielo Truda, 1926)
And the âgapsâ are all too obvious to a modern reader. Issues concerning
race, gender and sexuality are absent from the document â a weakness
that shouldnât be attributed to the documentâs age alone given the
activity and analysis of anarchists present on these subjects at the
time. Thankfully this is not an absence that has been replicated in the
practice of contemporary groups, with many publishing theory and
analysis on, and involving themselves in, the struggle of women,
homosexuals, Trans and Genderqueer people and people of colour. In
addition, it would also be fair to say that most existing groups would
place greater emphasis than in the original document on building and
strengthening localised struggle as much as national organisation, a
point which Malatesta also makes. An example would be Zabalazaâs
involvement in the Landless and Shack dwellers movement.
The fact that the original document overlooks such important issues
should not, however, be perceived as a weakness but embraced as a
positive strength. Anarchists reject the rigid formulations and
insistence on adherence to orthodoxy common within Marxism. They embrace
an open-ended, libertarian practice that places far less importance on
âheroic figuresâ and âgreat textsâ and more on the lessons derived and
developed from practical struggle. While it is always important to look
back at historic debates and what they can tell us about our current
practice it also important to acknowledge the âlivingâ qualities of any
anarchist tradition. Accordingly Platformism, like all anarchist
traditions, will undoubtedly richen and shape itself anew as it is
confronted with new struggles and new possibilities over the coming
decades. This is not, however, to go so far as to say that the
contemporary Platformist movement is in any way undeserving of
criticism. There have been persistent problems and controversies
surrounding this tradition that it would be equally remiss to ignore.
There has been, and continues to be, a tension within many contemporary
Platformist groups between what I would call an (anti)political and a
representationalist model of activity. I believe there are a number of
potential causes for this, but before delving into this further it may
be necessary to clarify what these terms mean.
By (anti)political, I mean practices that subvert, and eventually render
unnecessary, the hierarchical and authoritarian means of communication
and social organisation existing in statist, capitalist, patriarchal,
racist and hetero-normative society. (Anti)political activity will,
therefore, be typically constructed via direct, face-to-face
communication, participatory decision-making structures and, of course,
the organisation of tasks without the need for hierarchy. Expressions of
(anti)political behaviour have been a continuing inspiration for the
libertarian communist tradition from the soviets and factory councils of
Russia, through the anarcho-syndicalist unions of Spain to the
grassroots movements emerging out of the contemporary, global justice
movement. These methods are also considered to be consistent with what
is termed the anarchist âprefigurative ethicâ, described by Goldman in
the following terms;
All human experience teaches that methods and means cannot be separated
from the ultimate aim. The means employed become, through individual
habit and social practice, part and parcel of the final purpose; they
influence it, modify it, and presently the aims and means become
identical. (Goldman, 1923: 260)
The insistence on such an inseparability of ends and means, a
âprefigurativeâ practice, is a key and defining characteristic of
anarchist political thought and practice.
By representationalism, I refer to the many facets of capitalist
democracy that bar active participation in the processes that govern our
lives and reinforce social hierarchy. In capitalism this process is
multi-faceted and can be anything from the election of representatives
who will make decisions for us, to the strict social control of the
prison and criminal justice system right through to the manipulation of
the very language and information we use to interpret our social
reality. It is experienced through our condition of alienation in
capitalist society. It aims to foster in the social mass a psychological
state that continually reinforces the dividing lines between the
âgovernorsâ and the âgovernedâ, ârulersâ and âruledâ, âproducerâ and
âconsumerâ, even âauthorâ and âreaderâ. It serves to obscure the
fundamentally communal and holistic qualities of human community and
ensure that the working class is reduced to looking everywhere but to
itself and its own capabilities for alleviation of our social condition.
Representationalism has, unfortunately, its counterparts in
ârevolutionaryâ practice. The concern of anarchists has traditionally
been with the vanguardist practice of the authoritarian Left who will
downplay or deny the constructive capacities of working class
communities. Leftist groups attempt to appropriate this constructive
potential by assuming the power to represent others, judging themselves
to have abilities that âtheirâ constituencies are supposed to lack. This
is justified by varying means, for example, having a privileged,
âscientificâ understanding of objective forces, the âcorrectâ formula
for revolutionary struggle or even just a willingness âto go furtherâ
than the âdocileâ masses. Representatives, most importantly, cannot be
social revolutionaries. Representationalism necessarily depends on a
passive and institutionalised social mass that the representative can
reflect (and hope to mediate in any ensuing conflicts). It denies the
constructive part the working class has to play in forming its own
future and as such is antithetical to self-organisation and the practice
of social revolution.
Both representationalism and the (anti)political have been a constant
concern for libertarians when debating the issue of revolutionary
organisation and it is between these two poles that we often see
political organisations oscillate â between revolutionary and reformist
methods and goals. (Anti)political action is obviously the best
embodiment of anarchist values, but holding oneself to all but the
purest expression of âprefigurativeâ ideals clearly leads to very little
in terms of available practical action that can be taken. Truly
(anti)political actions only tend to develop at high-points of social
struggle, in the meantime they will often be small and/or isolated from
the condition of the majority of people, e.g. small communal
experiments, minority groups of revolutionaries. This is while there is
still a pressing need for propaganda and activism outside of these
periods of social upheaval. Revolutionary upsurges owe as much of their
origin to the diligent and long-standing work of revolutionaries as they
do to periodic crises. This does imply that a degree of pragmatism, when
it comes to decisions over engagement at least, is required.
The rationale runs close to the following; that given the frequent
impossibility of organising an (anti)political alternative to, for
example, an election or a union it makes more sense to critically
intervene in these processes and push individuals towards anarchist
ideas. The fact that a great number of people will already be invested
in these institutions of capitalist democracy means it makes more sense
to opt for engagement than elect to exclude oneself from them
completely. Contemporary Platformists have commonly advocated this
approach, especially given the emphasis in the original document on
pushing ideological leadership within popular sections of the worker and
peasant movement. A controversial, but obvious, contemporary example of
this would be the Workerâs Solidarity Movement (WSM) campaign for a âNoâ
vote in the Irish national referendum on the Lisbon treaty.
Suspending, for the moment, any judgement on what kind of âideological
leadershipâ a âNoâ vote in a national referendum represents, the
justification behind this strategy â of the need for popular, political
engagement â is in itself not completely out-of-touch with many other
examples of anarchist practice outside of the Platformist tradition.
Malatesta, for example, would argue along very similar lines in favour
of anarchist participation in the reformist unions over building
specifically (anti)political, anarchist ones. Similarly Aldred argued in
favour of taking a platform during elections, but refusing to take
office, as a vehicle to better spread libertarian ideals. There is
nothing distinctly Platformist about this position. The success of past
anarchist organisations has always depended on a commitment to a
diversity of tactics. Moreover, the question as to whether an individual
or a group begins the creep into representationalism and Leftism should
not be judged by the use of these methods alone. Such questions are
related to far deeper issues concerning a complex interplay of the
content, form and level of social struggle; issues that cannot possibly
be de-contextualised or so easily formed into clear-cut points of
principle. The success of revolutionary struggle can depend as much upon
the vigilance of struggling workers as much as it does the correct
position of revolutionaries (if, indeed, it is even possible to separate
these two categories). There are simply no easy answers here. However,
it would also be equally fair to say that the common perception of
Platformism as a âBolshevisedâ anarchist practice has, unfortunately,
been bolstered by the fact that a disproportionate number of these
groups have degenerated into representationalist and
counter-revolutionary theory and activity. There are numerous examples
to support this from the Anarchist Worker Groupâs support for the Iraqi
state during the first Gulf War, to Alternative Libertaireâs (France)
statement in favour of Kosovan nationalism and United Nations military
intervention, to even the highly manipulative internal practices of the
French Platformists in vying for influential positions within their
national Anarchist Federation. So, why Platformism? Why has this creep
into Leftism been persistently the case with these groups?
As I have tried to make clear in the first section, I do not believe
there is any validity to the claim that Platformism is an attempt to
âBolksheviseâ anarchism. I do believe, however, that there are a number
of aspects of Platformist praxis that can, but donât necessarily have
to, lend themselves to representationalism and Leftism. However, that is
also not to say that these are problems exclusive to Platformism but
that all revolutionary organisations are potentially vulnerable in some
way to these tendencies; all the more important, then, to have a
clear-sight of oneâs weaknesses to build upon oneâs strengths.
One aspect of contemporary Platformist strategy that I have only lightly
touched upon so far is the emphasis that is often placed on the need for
âstrategic thinkingâ. That is, it is assumed that when the organisation
is attempting to form tactical unity on the best course of action, it
will aim to take full account of its resources and aim to apply them
most effectively. There are a number of potential problems leading from
this proposition. First off, it is probably important to make clear that
a stress on capabilities and prioritisation when it comes to resources
is a valuable exercise for any organisation. The drive for efficiency
and expediency is, however, a double-edged sword. While there may be
better ways of allocating oneâs resources there are, to put it simply,
no short-cuts when it comes to revolutionary change. The Platform
itself, despite having been written following a great period of
revolutionary defeat (the Bolshevik consolidation of power in Russia and
the defeat and dissolution of the Makhnovtchina in the Ukraine) is
surprisingly optimistic, and as a result perhaps overly naive, in its
recommendations for revolutionary activity. Becoming the âpioneer and
theoretical mentorâ of the trade unions, as the Platform advocates, was
a drastically different task in revolutionary Ukraine or Russia, even in
France in the 1920s, than it is in Britain in 2010. As a result, the
type of expediency and efficiency that can be expected from
revolutionary organisations now, especially in Britain where the working
class has been ravaged from almost thirty years of Neo-Liberal economic
policy, has changed.
It is tempting, therefore, but ultimately misguided, to be drawn to the
lingering expressions of working class militancy, or maybe just the
collective organisation of the working class full stop, that exist in
the trade union movement or perhaps in the struggle of nationalities in
search for real, meaningful influence. Unfortunately this has indeed
been the practice of many, old and contemporary, Platformist groups.
Although Platformists have successfully plugged the âgapsâ in the
original document when it comes to gender and race, they have largely
failed to deal with its weaknesses and ambiguities when it comes to the
trade unions. Alternative interpretations of âthe âanarchizationâ of the
trade union movementâ, as is recommended in the original Platform, can
be made; Whether that means arguing for participation or simply
agitation within, transformation of the union structure or breaking away
from the trade unions altogether. In this regard, it is unfortunate that
Platformists have largely failed to engage with the other important
tradition emerging out of the Bolshevik experience and clarified this
very issue â the Dutch and German Left. Their analysis, emerging out of
the practical experience of mass revolutionary engagement with the trade
unions, is invaluable to any communist today. Such an unequivocal
perspective, as if the the experience of the TUC in Britain was not
enough, should put an end to all doubts concerning the mediating, and
ultimately bourgeois, role of trade unions and the tasks of
revolutionaries within them.
Undoubtedly related to this issue is the question of where revolutionary
strategy, and from this ideological leadership, is being formulated.
Platformist methods have, above all, to be framed by the experience of
class struggle. An âideological leadershipâ isolated from working class
resistance will quickly degenerate into representationalism â an
assumed, or de facto, position of leadership over the class. Theoretical
debate and development must be rooted in the experience of the class,
developing out of the actual needs and issues emerging from struggle.
There is, of course, a responsibility to look beyond these struggles
also, as well as a need to combat reformism, Leninism and the multitude
of sins inflicted upon any workers movement. However, this should come
in the form, not of dictat, but of a continuing and evolving dialogue
existing between revolutionaries rooted in the class and the class as a
whole. Most importantly, it should be acknowledged that, although
combating Leftist and authoritarian ideas is important, the âwar of
ideasâ with the Left should not supplant the class war between worker
and boss. To shift the organisations focus too far in the direction of
âideological leadershipâ, is to move closer to the standard operating
practice of the various Trotskyist grouplets. Aping them will only
replicate their over-concentration on the current composition of the
Left and neglect of the shop-floor. In practical terms, and over the
long-term, as Doyle (1991) argues, such a singular focus will lead to an
eventual, âdrift away from a day-to-day understanding of where real
class politics are atâ.
National liberation and trade unionism, for example, derive from
positions of representation, ideologies that attempt to manage the
condition of the working class. It has been extensively documented how
common culprits for Leftist support, the Palestine Liberation
Organisation (see, for example, Aufheben, 2001) and the early Trade
Unions (see, Wildcat) for example, were not only derived from the
political machinations of the bourgeoisie but had working class defeat
as their goal from the offset. These movements, and the ideas emerging
from them, tell us little about neither the experience of class struggle
nor our real potentialities as a class â not for greater workers
ârightsâ, or independent nationhood, or a greater slice of the pie but
for the creation of a free, international communist society. If sections
of the class invested in these movements appear militant it is only a
testament to the extent that these structures have been successful in
co-opting genuine class struggle. All the more imperative, therefore,
that those anarchists within them push a clear and unwavering
internationalist, communist analysis.
There has often been an undue emphasis in Platformist literature on the
final two-pages of the Platform (the Organisational Section) in a
document that deals extensively with the principles of anarchist
communism (what the Anarchist Workers Association appropriately called
the âmissing bitsâ). Effective anarchist praxis must be based on sound
libertarian communist principles and this, in turn, has to arise from a
self-educating and participatory process within the organisation itself
(one that is simultaneously engaged with the class). Playing fast and
loose with theoretical principles is a recipe for disaster. In the very
worst cases it has led to the kind of analysis put forward by groups
such as Liberty and Solidarity which have removed politics from the
equation completely, looking to managerial theory (of all things!) as a
guide to a more âeffectiveâ organisational praxis, completely ignoring
the highly alienating capitalist practice that such theory embodies (and
undoubtedly perpetuates). Engagement with representationalist
institutions should not mean the adoption of representationalist
practice.
Anarchist organisations will, and should, issue manifestos, political
statements, theoretical analysis etc. However, these should also be done
with the recognition of the real limitations, from a libertarian
perspective, of this medium for spreading our ideas. The real struggle,
the struggle that we should be engaging with, is not happening in the
world of political ideas alone but amongst our friends, our families, in
our workplaces and in our communities. To not just gain âsupportâ for a
political philosophy or a specific programme but to spread an idea and
method that is ultimately self-empowering. Itâs about communicating the
ideas of direct action and self-organisation so it is possible for
thousands, maybe even millions, of manifestos to emerge from popular,
grassroots bodies. Itâs also about acknowledging that the
class-as-a-whole has as much to tell revolutionaries, perhaps even more,
as we do it. Accordingly, our analysis should always be part of a
dialogue â one that both speaks to and reflects the wider struggle
within our class. The point is that anarchist organisation should be
about both substance and form â a factor that Makhno and the Dielo Truda
Group, appropriately, recognised by stressing the importance of both
tactical and theoretical unity.
And finally, a note on camaraderie. For all the emphasis that
Platformists have historically placed on building unity and common
action, Platformists organisations have had an unfortunate habit of
being either relatively small, in relation to the rest of the anarchist
movement or periodically, and quite spectacularly, falling apart. There
is no catch-all answer to the reasons behind this and obviously the
internal culture of specific groups and the individuals within them will
have their part to play. Doyleâs (1991) (of the WSM) account of the
AWGâs disastrous adoption of the âCadre Organisation Documentâ, which
effectively formalised a privileged stratum of theoreticians and
knowledge specialists within the organisation, is a particularly extreme
illustration of this. The confusions of the AWG aside, I believe there
may be some weight to the claim that the Platformist conception of
âcollective responsibilityâ is perhaps too thin. That an organisation
ought to be as supportive and enabling as it is reliant on the
acceptance of tasks and duties by the membership. Indeed that a concern
for the support and well-being towards other members ought to form a
part of this collective responsibility. Again, this is not something
particularly exclusive to Platformism and good analysis on comradely
behaviour is lacking in much anarchist communist literature.
Interestingly, it is Insurrectionalist authors who have tended to
provide the most revealing writings on the subject of comradely
behaviour. This may be due to the fact that Insurrectionalism, as a
theory of praxis, depends almost entirely on informal, fraternal links
between comrades in struggle. Links that should be present but that we
also perhaps take for granted inside of a formal, membership
organisation. As such, Insurrectionalists tend to have a much better
understanding of what these informal relationships should practically
entail. The bond that brings us together here, it is argued, is the
process of building affinity. Affinity should not be confused with the
idea of sentiment, although these things can co-exist as well. There
could be comrades, for example, with whom we consider having affinity
but whom we do not find sympathetic and vice versa. Rather, to have
affinity with a comrade means to know them and to aim to deepen oneâs
knowledge of them. As the knowledge grows, the affinity can increase to
the point of making an action together possible. Most importantly, this
is understood to be an infinite process, a permanent negotiation between
each otherâs values and understanding of the circumstances present. This
process can help cement more formal channels of organisational cohesion.
If there are, for example, tasks which need doing in the organisation
that may be tedious or boring (but are, nonetheless, useful) it is often
not, in reality, the abstract relationship one has to the organisational
collective that creates a sense of responsibility but a sense of
obligation based on affinity with oneâs comrades. Likewise, internal
debates and discussions that aim to build tactical and theoretical unity
should be conducted via collective deliberation. For this communication
to occur requires efforts towards understanding and trust in other
members and attempts to overcome misunderstandings and disagreements
should they occur. There is no real âend-gameâ to this process. In fact,
an organisation that does have such a static conception of its own
identity is ultimately a stagnant one also. Plurality, difference and
disagreement are ultimately features of all human life; as libertarian
communists, as those who argue in favour of the best capacities of the
human character we should be embracing this also.
I always felt that there was something very un-libertarian about
concluding arguments. As the Anarchist Federation stateâs in our
âIntroduction to Anarchist Communismâ, when it comes to anarchist
communism, there is no real conclusion, itâs a necessarily open-ended
practice. Accordingly, the arguments I have made here should not be
taken to be definitive or final in any sense. Rather, as I stated at the
beginning, they are intended to be part of a wider process, and I
believe a great tradition within the anarchist movement also, of
exercising self-criticism of the way we organise. I will âconcludeâ this
paper, therefore, by instead looking to the reasons as to why I believe
these debates are important.
I am a Platformist. I do, however, feel completely unrepresented by many
of the organisations that claim to be acting in the spirit of the
Organisational Platform. While I feel that many tenets of Platformism â
particularly building tactical and theoretical unity and the centrality
of class struggle â are the remedy to the localised, short-term and
ghettoised activity of large portions of the anarchist movement today, I
do also, however, feel a somewhat uncomfortable Platformist as one who
greatly values the importance of our core libertarian communist
principles for successful praxis. I guess writing this paper was an
effort to find that middle-ground, to tease out the useful and
interesting ideas from both sides of the Platformist/anti-Platformist
divide. Along with this, it was also important, I believe, to explore
the notion that we can learn something more valuable about our own
traditions by looking to the values of others. That such a process leads
to a re-affirming, modification or even outright rejection of our own
ideals. This, I believe, is a very healthy activity for a movement that
intends to stay true to its revolutionary mission. In this respect, and
I hope that this sentiment has also been expressed through my analysis,
it is the values and the ideas that are the most important things to me,
not the labels that come attached to them.
Arshinov, P. (1927) Reply to Anarchismâs Confusionists: A Response to
the âReply to the Platformâ by Several Russian Anarchists. [online]
(Updated 7^(th) April 2010) Available at:
(Accessed 19^(th) October 2010)
Aufheben (2001) Behind the 21^(st) Century Intifada. [online] (Updated
5^(th) January 2006) Available at:
(Accessed 19^(th) October 2010)
Dielo Truda (1926) Organisational Platform of the General Union of
Anarchists (Draft) [online] (Updated 20^(th) April 2010) Available at:
anarchistplatform.wordpress.com
(Accessed 19^(th) October 2010)
Doyle, K. (1991) What Went Wrong with the AWG? [online] (Updated date
unknown) Available at:
(Accessed 19^(th) October 2010)
Franks, B. (2006) Rebel Alliances: The Means and Ends of Contemporary
British anarchisms. AK Press and Dark Star: Edinburgh
Goldman, E. (1923) My Disillusionment in Russia. Dover Publications: New
York, 2003.
Gordon, U. (2008). Anarchy Alive! Anti-authoritarian Politics from
Practice to Theory. Pluto Press: London.
Heath, N. (1989) Platform: Historical Introduction. [online] (Updated
7^(th) April 2010) Available at:
(Accessed 19^(th) October 2010)
Heath, N. (1996) âAnarchist Communism in Britain, 1870â1991â, Organise!
Heath, N. (2006) âLooking Back and Forwardâ Black Flag.
Malatesta, E. (1927) A Project of Anarchist Organisation. [online]
(Updated 21^(st) April 2010) Available at:
anarchistplatform.wordpress.com
</span> [Accessed 19^(th) October 2010]
North Eastern Federation of Anarchist Communists (2002) The Question of
Revolutionary Organisation: A NEFAC Position Paper. [online] (Updated
27^(th) December 2002) Available at:
[Accessed 19^(th) October 2010]
North Eastern Federation of Anarchist Communists (2003) Anarchism and
the Platformist Tradition. [online] (Updated 30^(th) July 2003)Available
at:
[Accessed 19^(th) October 2010]
Thomas (2010) Anarchist Accountability [online] (Updated 16^(th) March
2010) Available at:
miamiautonomyandsolidarity.wordpress.com
[Accessed 19^(th) October 2010]
Voline, Sobol, Fleshin, Steimer, Roman and Ervantian (1927) ââReplyâ by
several Russian Anarchists to the âPlatformââ Available in: Maximoff,
G.P. (1930) Constructive Anarchism â The Debate on the Platform. Monty
Miller Press: Sydney, 1988.
Wildcat (date unknown) âGood Old-Fashioned Trade Unionismâ, Wildcat #16.
Retrieved March 15^(th), 2010 from
[1] Skirda, A. (2001) Facing the Enemy: A History of Anarchist
Organisation from Proudhon to May 1968. AK Press: Edinburgh; Maximoff,
G.P. (1930) Constructive Anarchism â The Debate on the Platform. Monty
Miller Press: Sydney, 1988; Anarchism and the Platformist Tradition: An
Archive of Writings on the Platformist Tradition Within Anarchism â
anarchistplatform.wordpress.com
/
[2] The notable exception is a persistent, and particularly radical,
interpretation of Stirnerite thought developed by anarchists in Glasgow
who took Stirnerâs âUnion of Egoistsâ literally as the basis for their
syndicalist and communist organising from the 1940s onwards.
[3] The Anarchist Federation of Britain (1963â72), could technically be
described as a structurally âsynthesistâ grouping, bringing together
âmembersâ (it had no formal membership list) from a variety of anarchist
traditions. This, however, was more by virtue of its lack of commitment
to any organisational principles as opposed to any theoretical
commitment to synthesism. Christie in his Edward Heath Made Me Angry
remarks that the Anarchist Federation of Britain âwasnât really a
federation at all, more an ad hoc body convened for a particular purpose
then disbanded againâ.
[4] Summarised by Doyle (1991) as the following;
(1) A general lack of organisation in the anarchist movement.
(2) Its poor quality where it does exist.
(3) Confusion over the role of the anarchist organisation.
[5] See, for example, Graebarâs description of the US anarchist movement
as split between,
âa minority tendency of âsectarianâ or âcapital-A anarchist groups,ââ
which have developed, dogmatic, political programs, and âa majority
tendency of âsmall-a anarchistsââŠwho âare the real locus of historical
dynamism right nowââ and who are much looser programmatically. (quoted
in Gordon, 2008: 23â4)
[6] He also states,
The Platformâs other shared characteristics with Leninism are a
paternalistic attitude towards subjugated groups, which designates a
universal vanguard, and the repressive character of this representative
body, the centralised Anarchist union, which is to lead the social
revolution. (Franks, 2006: 220)
Although it should also be noted that Franksâ quite hostile reading is
likely to also be strongly influenced by the history of the âAnarchist
Workers Groupâ (AWG) and their understanding of the Platform. The AWG
was a small Platformist group that existed in Britain from 1988 to 1992,
it led a controversial existence and eventually dissolved when a large
proportion of its membership joined Trotskyist organisations. Franks
acknowledges the criticisms the A(C)F levelled at the AWG at the time
but (erroneously) assumes this to be a break with Platformism in favour
of George Fontenisâ âManifesto of Libertarian Communismâ (p.224).
[7] Language is an important thing. The use of the term âexecutive
committeeâ, for example, in the original Platform has been a source of
contention for many years. The phrase has obvious resonance with the
highly vanguardist practice advocated by Lenin and has made it all too
easy for detractors to denounce Platformism as an attempt to
âBolsheviseâ anarchism. The highly loaded nature of the language
obscures the actual context in which the Dielo Truda group were writing.
Makhnoâs memoirs, for example, mention numerous âexecutive committeesâ
within the Ukrainian peasant and workers movement -â Makhno, M. (1929)
The Russian Revolution in Ukraine. Black Cat Press: Edmonton, 2007.
These were, however, contrary to the Bolshevik way of organising,
largely functional and always filled with recallable delegates directly
accountable to the organisations that appointed them. Makhno even, in
spite of this limited function, personally declined a place on the
executive committee of a peasant soviet on the basis that the tasks
should be fulfilled by the peasants themselves (only to relent and join
after much lobbying on the part of the soviet). Arshinov, for his part,
also attempts to lay rest any doubts that the âexecutive committeeâ is
Bolshevik-inspired in his reply to the Russian anarchists;
Anybody in the least degree slightest conversant with politics knows
well that an executive committee and a central committee are two quite
different ideas. The executive committee may very well be an anarchist
agency; indeed, such an organ exists in many anarchist and
anarcho-syndicalist organizations. (Arshinov, 1927)