đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș jeff-ferrell-anarchy-against-the-discipline.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:15:22. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchy Against the Discipline Author: Jeff Ferrell Date: 1995 Language: en Topics: discipline, criminology, book review Source: Retrieved on December 21, 2019 from https://web.archive.org/web/20191221003320/https://www.albany.edu/scj/jcjpc/vol3is4/anarchy.html Notes: Published in Journal of Criminal Justice and Popular Culture, 3(4) (1995) 86â91.
Author: DiCristina, B.
Title: Method in criminology: A philosophical primer.
Publisher: New York: Harrow and Heston.
Year: 1995
Method in Criminology: A Philosophical Primer is a deceptively innocuous
title for a wonderfully outrageous enterprise: a thoroughgoing epistemic
attack which Bruce DiCristina launches on both the day-to-day operations
of criminology and the philosophical foundations on which these
operations rest. In this brief but engaging book, DiCristina carefully
and ruthlessly (Marx, 1972) dismantles the basic assumptions which
undergird scientific criminology. In so doing, he exposes not only their
internal illogic, but their external utility for the bureaucratic
control of both crime and criminology, and for the structural
maintenance of inequitable social relations. In place of the dangerous
fraud which is scientific criminology, then, DiCristina proposes an
anarchic criminology â a criminology which embraces alternative methods
and epistemologies, encourages imaginative solutions to social and
criminal problems, and in the process continually undermines encrusted
hierarchies of certainty, truth, and power.
DiCristina begins his decomposition of contemporary criminology by
posing a seemingly safe, simple question: âShould any research method be
granted a privileged status in criminology?â (p. vii). DiCristinaâs
pursuit of this question, though, quickly becomes the thread which, once
pulled, unravels the entire enterprise of contemporary scientific
criminology. The unravelling begins with a deconstruction of causality
and causal certainty as the goals of criminology. Pitting the radical
uncertainty of David Hume against the proto-scientific methods of John
Stuart Mill, DiCristina demonstrates that causal assertions are in fact
âlittle more than constructs of the imaginationâ (p. 15), with no firm
footing in external validation.
Having demonstrated the futility of causal analysis for criminology,
DiCristina generously offers those who would pursue a scientific
criminology a variety of less stringent options â probability,
prediction, falsification â and then proceeds to undermine these
possibilities as well. Drawing heavily on Feyerabendâs (1975) brilliant
attack on science and scientific method, and on philosophers of science
like Kuhn (1970), Lakatos (1968), and Rorty (1989), DiCristina dismisses
probability and prediction due to their reliance on wholly unreliable
methods of induction and inductive reasoning. He likewise exposes the
falsity of a falsification method which fails to understand that
theories and the facts by which they are allegedly falsified in reality
interpenetrate and intermingle. Finally, he considers the least
stringent of options â that certain methods are, if not scientifically
sound, at least the most plausible means for pursuing criminological
goals. Again, though, he finds that fundamental epistemic uncertainty
destroys any hierarchy of plausibility.
Significantly, DiCristina demonstrates that this consideration of
criminologyâs underlying principles constitutes much more than an
exercise in abstract philosophy. First, he shows that mainstream
criminology is carefully guarded by various gatekeepers of scientific
authority and methodological purity: journal and book editors and
reviewers, curriculum designers, granting agencies, and others. In
demanding that criminological work meet the standards of science, and
excluding that work which does not, these authorities shape the
discipline around narrow (and, as DiCristina argues, unfounded)
definitions of scholarship (see Vaughn, Sjoberg and Reynolds, 1993;
Feagin, Orum and Sjoberg, 1991; Williams, 1984). Beyond this, the
framing of criminology as objective science contributes to the
functional rationality of the modern criminal justice system, and is in
turn âespecially conducive to the maintenance of inequitable
distributions of powerâ (p. 67). As DiCristina persuasively argues, the
authority of allegedly objective knowledge, the sheen of scientific
method and quantification, both construct new realms of legal domination
and social control, and at the same time distance those in control from
responsibility for their actions.
Against a criminology which is both unjustifiably narrow in its scope
and overtly harmful in its consequences DiCristina, therefore, suggests
an anarchic criminology characterized by openness, creativity, and
inclusion (see Pepinsky, 1978; Tifft, 1979; Tifft and Sullivan, 1980;
Ferrell, 1993; Ferrell, 1994). In place of the stale straightjacket of
(pseudo)scientific criminology, anarchic criminology promotes the widest
possible range of theories and methods, values marginal and even
âunreasonableâ knowledge, and revitalizes the âcriminological
imaginationâ (Williams, 1984). In place of the false objectivity of
contemporary criminology, anarchic criminology employs a sort of
âreflexive hermeneuticsâ (p. 80 â 84) which encourages both interpretive
knowledge and critical awareness. In place of a criminology which is all
too useful for inequitable social and legal control, anarchic
criminology takes shape in humble conversation with those outside the
domains of criminology and criminal justice.
This notion of an open, anarchic criminology sheds light on a variety of
ongoing discussions within and beyond contemporary criminology. To begin
with, it provides a useful framework for making sense of the various
alternative criminologies which have emerged in recent years. The
Russian anarchist Michael Bakuninâs infamous injunction â that âthe
passion for destruction is a creative passion, tooâ (1974: 58) â here
reflects the notion that the destruction of paradigmatic hegemony in
criminology in fact opens up intellectual space for the creation of
various alternative criminologies. If the deconstruction of theoretical
certainty and methodological privilege by DiCristina and those who have
gone before him has created a sort of negative space, an epistemic void,
it is a void that has been quickly filled by a healthy tangle of fresh
perspectives. In this sense, the plethora of criminologies which have
blossomed in recent times â peacemaking, newsmaking, feminist,
narrative, cultural, anarchist â constitutes perhaps a crisis of
criminological certainty, but more so a measure of disciplinary life.
In unmasking the myth of an objectively scientific criminology â in
realizing that we are only discarding something we never had â we are
also pushed to reconceptualize research methods and methods of knowing.
The âreflexive hermeneuticâ which DiCristina proposes incorporates âboth
interactive analyses and historical-contextual analysesâ (p. 81), and
demands a certain degree of consensual agreement between researcher and
subjects; that is, it âtakes subjectivity seriouslyâ (p. 83). For
criminological researchers, this implies experiential closeness in place
of pseudo-scientific distance, and epistemic humility in place of
intellectual arrogance. In other words, it demands, as a requisite
feature of understanding and analysis, a sort of âcriminological
verstehenâ (Hamm and Ferrell, 1994; Ferrell and Sanders, 1995) between
criminological researchers and their subjects of study. And thus it is,
within this model, that criminological ethnographers, anarchic
criminologists, and others may know infinitely more about their subjects
of study than do survey researchers or statisticians, and at the same
time claim to know infinitely less.
Finally, anarchic criminology as sketched by DiCristina and others
clearly informs, and is informed by, those orientations grouped under
headings like âpostmodernismâ and âcultural studies.â DiCristina notes
that âperhaps the most refreshing anarchic developments in criminology
will be sifted from the work of postmodern criminologistsâ (p. 98), and
indeed anarchic and postmodern criminologies have much in common. The
epistemic assault on various forms of legal and intellectual authority;
the decentering of both centralized power and the certainty which
accompanies it; the rejection of metanarratives which position
themselves as true and universal accounts of social or criminal life â
these are the projects of postmodern and anarchic criminologies alike.
And as these projects open up the constricted intellectual space of
scientific criminology, they at the same time lead criminology into new
domains of research and analysis. DiCristina in this sense argues that
âcriminological inquiry is more than a question of logic. Questions of
aesthetics and morality are just as importantâ (p. xi). Like others (see
Ferrell and Sanders, 1995), he thus recognizes the importance of
aesthetic and stylistic processes in constituting both criminology and
criminal action, and attempts to reclaim this âcultural trashâ from the
dustbin of scientific, rationalist criminology.
DiCristina might have productively explored many of these issues more
fully; though he notes postmodern and aesthetic issues in the context of
anarchic criminology, for example, he all but fails to follow his own
lead. He might also have more thoroughly rooted his anarchic criminology
not only in prior anarchist work within criminology, but in the long
history of anarchist thought. Though brevity may be the soul of wit, a
hundred page book might well be expanded to include more thorough
exploration, and a few more pages. In addition, the book, though simply
and understandably written, would have benefited in places from a good
round of editing. Utilizing conventional language in new or
intentionally inappropriate ways certainly carries anarchic potential;
simply writing âand so forthâ or âetc.â into sentences seems more sloppy
than seditious. These, though, are minor criticisms of an exciting and
courageous contribution to criminological thinking. Method in
Criminology transcends its own limitations in inventing a far- reaching
critique of contemporary criminology, and imagining a humane and
flexible alternative to it.
And in this spirit of anarchist imagination, I offer a closing note as
to means and ends, process and product. Dicristina concludes that, given
anarchic criminologyâs promotion of âfreedom of thought and creativityâ
(p. 102), an anarchic criminology benefits criminology as a whole,
despite the fact that it may never be fully accomplished. I would agree,
but go a step further to argue that anarchic criminology is beneficial
precisely because it can never be fully realized. By its own logic,
anarchic criminology serves best, it seems, as an unfinished and
uncertain project, an emerging sensibility floating around and âagainst
criminologyâ (Cohen, 1988), a critique which folds back on itself so as
to undermine not only mainstream criminological rigidity but its own
encrustation as well. And in this sense, we arrive at an anarchic
criminology only as we continue to stumble toward it.
Jeff Ferrell
Department of Criminal Justice
Northern Arizona University
References
Cohen, S. (1988). Against criminology. New Brunswick: Transaction.
Feagin, J. R., Orum, A.M., & Sjoberg, G. (Eds.). (1991). A case for the
case study. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Ferrell, J. (1993). Crimes of style: Urban graffiti and the politics of
criminality. New York: Garland.
Ferrell, J. (1994). Confronting the agenda of authority: Critical
criminology, anarchism, and urban graffiti. In G. Barak (Ed.), Varieties
of criminology (pp.161â178). Westport, CT: Praeger.
Ferrell, J., & Sanders, C. R. (Eds.). (1995). Cultural criminology.
Boston: Northeastern University Press.
Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: Verso.
Hamm, M. S., & Ferrell, J. (1994). Rap, cops, and crime: Clarifying the
âCop Killerâ controversy. ACJS Today, 13, 1, 3, 29.
Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2^(nd) ed.).
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lakatos, I. (1968). Criticism and the methodology of scientific research
programmes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 69, 149â186.
Lehning, A. (Ed.). (1974). Michael Bakunin: Selected writings. New York:
Grove Press.
Marx, K. (1972). For a ruthless criticism of everything existing. In R.
Tucker (Ed.), The Marx- Engels Reader, (pp.7â10). New York: Norton.
Pepinsky, H. E. (1978). Communist anarchism as an alternative to the
rule of criminal law. Contemporary Crises, 2, 315â327.
Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Tifft, L. (1979). The coming redefinition of crime: An anarchist
perspective. Social Problems, 26, 392â402.
Tifft, L., & Sullivan, D. (1980). The struggle to be human: Crime,
criminology, and anarchism. Orkney, U.K.: Cienfuegos Press.
Vaughn, T. R., Sjoberg, G., & Reynolds, L. T. (Eds.). (1993). A critique
of contemporary American sociology. Dix Hill, NY: General Hall.
Williams, F. P. (1984). The demise of the criminological imagination: A
critique of recent criminology. Justice Quarterly, 1, 91â106.