💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › jon-bekken-nationalism-or-freedom.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:05:12. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Nationalism or Freedom?
Author: Jon Bekken
Date: 2001
Language: en
Topics: anti-nationalism, anarchist analysis
Source: Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 32 (Sep 30, 2001): page 26
Notes: Scanned from original.

Jon Bekken

Nationalism or Freedom?

Writing in the most recent Arsenal, a well-produced "magazine of

anarchist strategy and culture," Mike Staudenmaier devotes one of the

leading articles to a critique of ASR's "extensive and influential

writings opposing nationalism and advocating working-class

internationalist revolution." (Unfortunately, he cannot be troubled to

cite any of them, perhaps recognizing that his muddled argument could

not stand up to any anarchist writings on the subject.)

According to Staudenmaier, we follow the "people, not nations" analysis

he attributes to Rudolf Rocker, "combin[ing] the sort of economic

reductionism that is often the hallmark of syndicalism with careful

analysis of the harsh experiences of the Cuban revolution." Our

color-blind position that "working people have no country" was

revolutionary a century ago, he continues, but today is a manifestation

of white supremacy responsible for the overwhelmingly white membership

of "one of the best-recruiting and most steadily growing segments North

American anarchism."

Citing our criticism of Chomsky's suggestion that in this era of

globalization, the nation-state can serve as a mechanism for popular

self-defense (and strangely arguing that the Brazilian nation-state,

which routinely murders homeless children on the street, aids and abets

transnational corporations in despoiling Brazil's abundant natural

resources, and forces landless peasants into debt peonage, is less

repressive than the IMF), Staudenmaier says we fail to acknowledge the

substantial divisions within global economic classes posed by racial and

national identities. These divisions, he argues, create the possibility

of "meaningful cross-class alliances ... difficult to assimilate into a

syndicalist world view." (13)

In a typically confused passage he then conflates race, culture and

nation, and claims that syndicalists say that the struggle for racial

justice must be put off until after the anti-capitalist revolution

(which, Staudenmaier suggests, is exactly backward). Conceding that

syndicalists are "sincerely anti-racist," he argues that we

"underestimate the importance of cultural identity to people's lives and

to social struggles," thereby leading revolutionaries into a dead-end.

After some muted criticisms of anarcho-nationalist tendencies, which

have led many who consider (or once considered) themselves anarchists

into backing a variety of Marxist-Leninist groupings (a significant

fraction of the now-dissolved Love & Rage Federation recently joined the

Maoist Freedom Road Socialist Organization) for ignoring class struggle,

the author turns from setting up his straw men to putting forward his

own perspective:

"Where ASR offers the false dichotomy between people and nations, the

ABCF upholds a similarly questionable opposition between `oppressor

nationalism' ... and `nationalism of the oppressed' ...[But] in both

cases, the social experience at a grassroots level is the same -

cultural identity rooted in geography, language and assorted historical

intangibles, producing a broad-based love and prioritization of a

community of communities." (15) Staudenmaier rejects this attempt to

separate what he sees as inextricably intertwined positive and negative

aspects of national identity. Instead he champions what he admits is an

ad hoc analysis, skeptical of national liberation struggles while

supporting them, "recit[ing] rhetoric about class struggle" while

working with radicals of all class backgrounds (he apparently believes

there are significant numbers of the employing class to be found in the

anarchists' ranks, something I have never observed), and calling upon

activists to embrace the contradictions.

Anarchist support for the EZLN (the Zapatistas) is offered as an example

"of this promising new anarchist response to nationalism," (16) citing

Marcos' embrace of "the nation" in a typically incoherent quote. But for

Staudenmaier the Zapatistas embody an anti-statist nationalism,

apparently because they have recognized that they are in no position to

seize state power and so instead negotiate with the state and pressure

it to change its policies. Unwilling to embrace nationalism fully,

Staudenmaier instead urges us to "participate in and/or lend support to

anti-colonial struggles in a principled and critical way ... Anarchists

must become involved in a critical way in what Marcos calls the

`reconstruction' of the nation, which can only happen if we avoid the

twin pitfalls of knee-jerk anti-nationalism and uncritical acquiescence

to national liberation. By balancing the competing claims of race and

class, we can develop a new anarchist understanding of nations and

nationalism." (17)

I apologize if this summary seems incoherent; while I have endeavored to

distill a coherent argument from seven pages of confusion, this is at

best a difficult task. I undertake this thankless task only because

Staudenmaier is quite mistaken when he describes our writings on this

question as "influential." In fact, most North American anarchists today

embrace the muddled thinking he advocates, with devastating results. In

upholding the traditional anarchist opposition to nationalism (although

our recent writings on the subject have hardly been extensive, and have

tended to discuss the Middle East far more than Cuba), we have waged a

difficult and usually lonely struggle for fundamental anarchist

principles.

Staudenmaier's argument relies upon an almost total exclusion of

evidence, allowing patently false claims such as that syndicalists argue

that the struggle for racial justice must be postponed until after The

Revolution to stand cheek by jowl with highly questionable

characterizations of various nation-states and nationalist movements.

Failing to critically engage the one example of "progressive"

nationalism he discusses (the Zapatistas), he leaves readers with no

concrete sense of what this "new anarchist understanding" might look

like in actual practice, or why we might consider it to be in any way

anarchist.

Staudenmaier is unable even to keep his core concept clear. He offers

two definitions of nationalism: a common language and shared geography

(11) and cultural identity rooted in geography, language and historical

intangibles (15). These definitions are quite useless in understanding

actually existing nationalism. In the Balkans, for example, the

allegedly intractable nationalisms there (we leave aside the high levels

of intermarriage and other such inconvenient facts) have nothing

whatever to do with language (Serbian and Croatian are the same

language, only the script in which they are written differs) or

geography (the populations are completely intermingled, thus the

necessity for "ethnic cleansing"). This confusion is not entirely his

fault. The "nation" is an essentially mythic concept, its signifiers

chosen arbitrarily by ideologues seeking to unite followers against the

"other" or to conceal real conflicting interests behind a facade of

national unity.

As Mikhail Bakunin (whose understanding of nationalism was far more

complex than Staudenmaier's), noted: "There is nothing more absurd and

at the same time more harmful, more deadly, for the people than to

uphold the fictitious principle of nationalism as the ideal of all the

people's aspirations. Nationality is not a universal human principle; it

is a historic, local fact. ... We should place human, universal justice

above all national interests." While consistently defending the

principle of self-determination, Bakunin (whose political activity began

in pan-Slavism) came to see nationalism (and its corollary, patriotism)

as a manifestation of backwardness. "The less developed a civilization

is, and the less complex the basis of its social life, the stronger the

manifestation of natural patriotism."

Bakunin also termed nationalism a "natural fact" that had to be reckoned

with. Indeed, nationalism does exist, in precisely the same sense that

dementia does. There are many people in the world who hear God giving

them orders - sometimes cruel, sometimes bizarre, sometimes quite

humane - or who see hallucinations. While these unfortunates insist upon

the reality of their visions, we know better. Such things simply do not

exist, for all that thousands of our fellow humans act upon them. But

the mental disorder that sparks these delusions quite certainly exists.

Sometimes it is relatively harmless and can perhaps be ignored, though I

tend to believe symptoms should be responded to before the disease gets

worse. Sometimes the derangement is quite serious, and must be

confronted forcefully.

In precisely the same way, we can say that nationalism exists, even

though there is no useful sense in which "nations" can be said to exist,

except as an artificial construct imposed by states, churches and other

powers to suit their own interests.

Nations are in fact inventions of relatively recent origin. Five hundred

years ago, the language we now know as "French" was a family of loosely

related regional tongues that were not mutually intelligible. The

"Italian" nation was invented in the 1800s, and a significant fraction

of the Italian right now seems determined to uninvent it. In Chicago, in

the early 1900s, there was a prolonged struggle over the national

identity of the people now known as Ukrainian immigrants, with competing

networks of institutions seeking to construct national identities as

Poles, Ruthenians, Little Russians, Russians, and Ukrainians. With the

defeat of the claimants in the diaspora, the Ruthenian nation vanished

without a trace, aside from some old buildings where it was engraved

into the stone. Similarly, there was heated debate within the Polish

community over whether Jews, atheists, socialists, and members of the

Polish National Alliance could be considered members of the Polish

nation. Such debates had little to do with language or culture, rather

they represented efforts by competing leaderships to establish dominance

and to exclude those who subscribed to competing identities from

inclusion in the fold of "the people."

But Staudenmaier's confusion does not end with his definition of

nationalism. Throughout his essay, he treats the concepts of "nation"

and "race" as if they were synonyms. There are, of course, important

similarities between the two concepts: Both lack any basis in the real,

material world, but are instead ideological constructs invented to

justify oppression and domination. Although their boundaries are porous,

subject to constant reinterpretation and redefinition (as are all

arbitrary categorization schemes), many people have internalized these

constructs, making them part of their own self-identification. Both are

poisonous, pernicious ideologies; there is no crime too heinous to be

"justified" under the cloak of race or nation. And, of course, both are

manifested in social arrangements that reflect not only relations of

power (which have their own historic weight), but have also implanted

themselves in the consciousness even of those sincerely committed to the

cause of human emancipation.

But despite these similarities, there are also important distinctions

between race and nation. While no one can define either with any

precision, given their wholly mythic character, race certainly does not

involve questions of geography or language - the only two generally

agreed-upon markers of nationality. (That nation is not in fact defined

in any way by these markers is a different question.)

There are certainly people who have historically been - and continue to

be - oppressed in particular ways, justified in part by alleged

differences in skin color and/or physical build. (Such differences have

relatively little explanatory power; in the 1790s there was a debate in

this country over whether Germans were "white" or "black"; in the 1800s

the same question was raised about the Irish; in the early 1900s Finns

were widely considered an "Asiatic" people by specialists in racial

categorization. Physical characteristics are purely incidental to such

arguments, which are fundamentally about power and domination.) This

history of oppression manifests itself in many ways, from the jobs

workers are able to obtain, to the schools their children are enrolled

in, to the accumulated resources they have at their disposal to see them

through hard times or enable them to secure a viable economic foothold,

to their likelihood of being shot by police. Syndicalists have always

recognized the importance of racial oppression, fighting against

discrimination on the job and in the broader society, demanding equal

access to jobs, and putting our bodies on the line in the struggle for

racial justice. "Race" has been used both to divide the working class

and to subject one segment of our class to particularly brutal

oppression and exploitation, and as such it can not be ignored. But its

manifestation is radically different than that of "nation," and to treat

them as interchangeable is a dangerous confusion.

It is particularly dangerous when Staudenmaier swings between race and

nation, arguing that anarchists should build cross-class alliances - an

anarchist version of the Popular Front which has sucked so many radicals

into pallid reformism. While there is a certain logic to cross-class

alliances for those who seek state power above all else, there is

absolutely no reason why anarchists should be making common cause with

our exploiters. It is not only wrong in principle, it not only feeds

illusions among our fellow workers, but it is tactically stupid to boot.

As we noted earlier this year, "The right of a people to

self-determination is a long-standing anarchist principle. Nationalism,

however, is a fraud whereby would-be rulers `self-determine' to impose

their vision of nationhood on an entire community. Nationalism is an

ideology of separation, of hatred for the 'other.' It is a creed of

violence and war and oppression. And it has absolutely nothing to offer

the world's oppressed. What is necessary is to develop human solidarity,

the instincts of mutual aid that enable us to survive and which have

fueled all human progress..."

Even many Marxists are at long last recognizing the folly of their long

detour into nationalism. In a recent essay, George Kateb describes

nationalism (and its close cousin, patriotism) as "a grave moral error"

arising out of "a state of mental confusion." Noting that the nation is

an amalgam "of a few actual and many imaginary ingredients," he notes

that patriotism, in its essence, "is a readiness to die and to kill for

an abstraction ... for what is largely a figment of the imagination."

(907) Necessarily constructed to exclude the vast majority of humanity

from its imagined community, patriotism - the celebration of the nation

armed-needs external enemies. "Patriotism is on a permanent moral

holiday, and once it is made dynamic, it invariably becomes criminal."

(914) But not only does nationalism define itself in opposition to the

whole of humanity, Kateb argues, it also requires that the individual

surrender her moral authority and individuality, abandoning her own

dignity and individuality to embrace submersion into an ideology of

hatred, a life of criminality. Quoting Thoreau, he concludes that only

those who surrender their "self-respect, and sacrifice the greater to

the less" can be patriotic. "They love the soil which makes their

graves, but have no sympathy with the spirit which may still animate

their clay. Patriotism is a maggot in their heads."

As Rudolf Rocker noted, "the change of human groups into nations, that

is, State peoples, has not opened out a new outlook... It is today one

of the most dangerous hindrances to social liberation." (202) Peoples

with common history, language and cultural backgrounds evolved over long

periods of living together in free (and sometimes not so free) social

alliances. No anarchist would propose that such communities should be

forced to dissolve themselves into some invented social identity. But

this is precisely what nationalism, the political theology of the state,

attempts. "Nations" are in no sense natural communities; they stand in

stark opposition to human autonomy, to the right of self-organization

and self-determination, and to the principles of mutual aid and

solidarity upon which our very survival depends.

References:

ASR: The Folly of Nationalism, #30 (Winter 2000/01), 1-2.

Mikhail Bakunin, Statism and Anarchism, Letters on Patriotism, A

Circular Letter to My Friends in Italy, The Knouto-Germanic Empire and

the Social Revolution. Excerpted in G.P. Maximoff, ed. The Political

Philosophy of Bakunin.

Jon Bekken, Negotiating Class and Ethnicity: The Polish-Language Press

in Chicago. Polish-American Studies (Autumn 2000), 5-29. George Kateb,

Is Patriotism a Mistake? Social Research 67(4) (Winter 2000), 901-24.

Rudolf Rocker, Nationalism and Culture.

Werner Sollors (ed.), The Invention of Ethnicity.

Mike Staudenmaier, What Good are Nations? Arsenal 3 (2001), 11-17. 1573

Milwaukee Ave., PMB 420, Chicago IL 60622