💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › jon-bekken-an-anarchist-faq.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:03:52. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: An Anarchist FAQ
Author: Jon Bekken
Date: 2013
Language: en
Topics: book review, An Anarchist FAQ, Iain McKay, Anarcho-Syndicalist Review
Source: Retrieved on 28th January 2021 from https://syndicalist.us/2013/05/08/an-anarchist-faq/
Notes: From Anarcho-Syndicalist Review #59, Winter 2013

Jon Bekken

An Anarchist FAQ

Iain McKay, An Anarchist FAQ Volume 1 (AK Press, 2008), 555 pages, $25

paper. Volume 2 (AK Press, 2012), 561 pages, $25 paper.

This two-volume compilation includes the great bulk of the material

assembled online in the Anarchist FAQ by ASR contributor Iain McKay and

other comrades over more than a decade. Established to confront

misrepresentations of anarchism that have proliferated particularly in

the online universe (allegedly anarchist tendencies exist there that

have no apparent manifestation in the material world in which the rest

of us live), AFAQ quickly evolved into a much broader overview of

anarchism, as a social movement and as a set of ideas.

It is impossible to do justice to the 1,136 pages in these two volumes.

Volume 1 opens (after three introductions which explain the origins and

evolution of the project) with an overview of anarchism, followed by

sections explaining why anarchists oppose hierarchy, capitalism and the

state; summarizing the anarchist critique of capitalist economics;

reviewing how statism and capitalism operate as an intertwined system of

exploitation and oppression; offering an anarchist analysis of the

ecological crisis, and refuting the notion that there could be some sort

of “anarcho”-capitalism. An appendix reviews the origins of three major

anarchist symbols: the black flag, the red-and-black flag and the

circled A. Volume 2 opens with a survey of individualist anarchism,

which remains implacably hostile to capitalism despite its differences

with the social anarchism embraced by most anarchists; followed by an

explanation of why anarchists (who McKay rightly insists are part of the

broader socialist movement) reject state socialism; an overview of

anarchist thinking about the shape of a future, free society; a section

addressing contemporary anarchist practice (involvement in social

struggles, direct action, organizational approaches, alternative social

organizations, child rearing, and social revolution); followed by a

brief bibliography.

Each major section is divided into smaller sections and subsections

(presented in question form and using an outline numbering system that

probably works better online) addressing specific aspects of the topic.

The writing and organization are clear, if rarely captivating, and the

tone is reasoned and constructive. However, at times, McKay does show

his exasperation with the persistent misrepresentations of the Marxists

and the “anarcho”-capitalists (who, as he rightly points out, have

nothing whatsoever to do with anarchism and receive attention here far

out of proportion to their actual significance in the world in large

part because of their early adoption of and highly vocal presence on the

Internet). Evidently, the ravings of the “anarcho”-primitivists have

received less attention online and so they pass unmentioned here. As the

book is devoted to political and social thought and action, there is

also virtually no attention given to anarchist tendencies in art and

literature, or to the post-modern “anarchisms” which dominate so much

academic publishing on the subject of late.

McKay and his fellow contributors give serious consideration even to

anarchist tendencies with which they clearly disagree. Thus,

platformism, syndicalism and synthesis all receive respectful treatment,

presenting the arguments proffered for and against. Thus, Bookchin’s

libertarian municipalism is presented on its own terms before a short

critical assessment (1092–93). (This tolerant policy can extend too far,

as with the citations to the notorious police informer Bob Black, who

can evidently be excerpted to make it appear as if he has a coherent

social analysis, though nothing could be further from the truth.) Here

and throughout the two volumes there is heavy reliance on direct

quotations. The FAQ draws upon and tends to synthesize a wide array of

(primarily anarchist) sources, in keeping with its broader mission of

presenting a broad anarchist approach to a general public, rather than

exploring differences within the movement or advocating for a particular

school of thought. The emphasis is definitely upon the classics of

anarchist thought, but McKay and his contributors have read widely and

include citations not only to anarchist writers but also to social

scientists and historians whose work tends (whether intended to or not)

to bolster the anarchist position.

By way of summation, and to give a bit of the flavor of the whole, I

will briefly discuss Section I: What would an anarchist society look

like? This 168-page section is broken up into subsections on libertarian

socialism, a discussion of the balance between the insanity of drafting

blueprints for the future and thinking about the sort of society we wish

to build, considerations of the structural aspects of an anarchist

economy and an anarchist society, consideration of how an anarchist

economy might function, a review of the Spanish Revolution as an example

of anarchism in practice (if also under severe constraints), and short

discussions of the balance between individualism and society and the

so-called Tragedy of the Commons.

This is a lot of terrain to cover, but the questions are essential.

McKay’s discussion is grounded in the classics, and (correctly)

presuppose that anarchism represents a particular strand of socialism,

quoting Bakunin:

We are convinced that freedom without socialism is privilege and

injustice, and that socialism without freedom is slavery and brutality.

(839)

The text then methodically establishes the necessity of socialism, the

practicality of our vision, explains why any lover of freedom must

reject markets, and refutes the absurd (but oft-preached) notion that

capitalism distributes social resources efficiently. And that’s just the

first 30 pages. The section refutes mainstream economists’ critiques of

self-management (critiques based not on examining actual practice but

rather on mental exercises based on assumptions that nowhere exist), and

reviews the long history of self-management in practice.

However, as McKay argues, social ownership of the means of life, and of

production, is essential to any meaningful freedom. While anarchists

have advocated for different methods for distributing the product of our

necessarily social labor, and hence for different systems for organizing

the economy, all anarchist visions are necessarily based upon social

ownership and free access to the means of production. McKay explores the

ways in which overlapping federations of syndicates and associations

(most organized for specific purposes, as anarchists have generally been

skeptical of schemes which try to centralize the entire sphere of human

life into a single, totalized organization) can cooperate to meet the

incredibly varied range of human needs and desires.

Throughout, McKay raises and refutes the objections we have all heard a

thousand times, not only theoretically but with extensive examples from

real life (something far more congenial to anarchist theory than to the

doctrines of either the capitalists or the state socialists). Anarchism,

he shows (like Kropotkin and Dolgoff before) offers an eminently

practical approach ideally suited to coordinating large, complex

societies.

My main objection to this section is the part where McKay suggests (to

quote the title) that “anarchists desire to abolish work.” In the actual

text, he is more clear, noting that

Work (in the sense of doing necessary things or productive activity)

will always be with us. There is no getting away from it; crops need to

be grown, schools built, homes fixed, and so on. No, work in this

context means any form of labor in which the worker does not control his

or her own activity.

But what purpose is served by using commonly understood terms such as

“work” in so technical a way? It must necessarily lead to confusion, on

the one hand, and on the other enable charlatans such as the

aforementioned Bob Black to sneak their obfuscations into the anarchist

camp. Far better to speak of wage slavery, or, as Chomsky often does, to

authoritarianism in the economic sphere.

Far too much of our labor is of course wasted under present

arrangements, and our workplaces are sites of subjugation and misery. In

an economy controlled by workers and organized around meeting human

needs, we could soon slash the work week to 16 hour or less, reorganize

workplaces to make them both safer and more fulfilling, abolish the

ruthless division of labor that has some think and others serving as the

minions of those who decide, and redirect the entire sphere of

production in fundamental ways. This would transform our relation to our

work, as well as to the products of our labor. But while we might well

take genuine pleasure from joining with our fellow workers to fulfill

our needs and our desires, not all work will be pleasurable in and of

itself, as is suggested here.

Anarchists have not come to agreement as to how production will be

coordinated and social priorities decided upon, and so McKay leaves

these questions open (while discussing some of the leading proposals).

This is an issue ASR has been exploring in our series on anarchist

economics, and which I suspect is at the root of the otherwise

inexplicable attraction many feel to the Parecon scheme. Personally, I

find Kropotkin’s treatment of these issues more compelling, even if it

is a century old. AFAQ does effectively integrate the experience of the

Spanish Revolution (also presented in a well-crafted 31-page section

that concludes this chapter) into the discussion. But in general, I fear

the pluralistic approach embraced in this treatment – while capturing

the diversity of the movement – undermines the coherence of the

argument, as well as eliding the congruence between our broader social

visions and the means we advocate that is one of the unique strengths of

the anarcho-syndicalist approach.

In short, McKay and his fellow contributors have made a substantial

contribution in creating and maintaining the online introduction to

anarchism, and refutation of the endless objections of those who can not

conceive of a society free of oppression and exploitation. It will serve

as an invaluable reference to those unfamiliar with our ideas and our

movement, or to those who have recently embraced anarchism but have yet

to explore and reflect upon the tradition. However, its breadth and

pluralism are both its greatest strength and its most notable weakness.