đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș georges-fontenis-manifesto-of-libertarian-communism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:31:52. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Manifesto of Libertarian Communism
Author: Federation Communiste Libertaire
Date: 1953
Language: en
Topics: organization, platform, platformism, France, Anarchist Federation, Libertarian Communism, Communism
Source: Retrieved on 9 August 2014 from http://libcom.org/library/manifesto-of-libertarian-communism-georges-fontenis

Federation Communiste Libertaire

Manifesto of Libertarian Communism

Foreword

The ‘Manifesto of Libertarian Communism’ was written in 1953 by Georges

Fontenis for the Federation Communiste Libertaire of France. It is one

of the key texts of the anarchist-communist current.

It was preceeded by the best work of Bakunin, Guillaume, Malatesta,

Berneri, the organisational Platform of the Libertarian Communists

written by Makhno, Arshinov and Mett, which sprang from the defeats of

the Russian Revolution, and the statements of the Friends of Durruti,

also a result of another defeat, that of the Spanish Revolution.

Like the ‘Platform’ it pitted itself against the ‘Synthesis’ of Faure

and Voline which attempted a compromise between Stirnerite

individualism, anarcho-syndicalism, and libertarian communism. Like the

‘Platform’ it reaffirmed the class-struggle nature of anarchism and

showed how it had sprung from the struggles of the oppressed. It had the

experience of another thirty years of struggle and was a more developed

document than the ‘Platform’. However it failed to take account of the

role of women in capitalist society and offered no specific analysis of

women’s oppression. Whilst the F.C.L. was very active in the struggle

against French colonialism in North Africa, it failed to incorporate an

analysis of racism into its Manifesto.

It rejected, rightly, the concept of the ‘Dictatorship of the

Proletariat’ and the ‘Transitional Period’. Where it made mistakes was

in the use of the concepts of the ‘party’ and the ‘vanguard’. To be fair

the word ‘party’ had been used in the past by Malatesta to describe the

anarchist movement, but the association with social-democrats and

Leninists had given it connotations which can only be avoided by

dropping the term. Similarly, ‘vanguard’ had been used extensively, by

anarchists in the past to describe, not the Leninist vanguard, but a

group of workers with advanced ideas. The term was used, for example, in

this respect in the Spanish movement (see Bookchin’s writings on the

subject), and also by anarchist-communists in the United States who

named their paper ‘Vanguard’ (see the memoirs of Sam Dolgoff). However,

it has too many unhappy associations with Leninism. Whilst we recognise

that there exist advanced groups of workers, and that the anarchist

movement has ideas in advance of most of the class, we must recognise

fully the great creativity of the whole of the working class. There

exist contradictions between advanced groups and the class as a whole,

complex contradictions which cannot be explained in simple black and

white terms, which could lead to the Leninist danger of substituting a

group for the whole class. The anarchist-communist Organisation should

be aware of these problems and attempt to minimalise these

contradictions. True, the Manifesto sees this vanguard as internal to

the class, rather than an external vanguard of professional

revolutionaries as Lenin saw it. Nevertheless the term should be

regarded with great suspicion.

The Manifesto continued the arguments for effective libertarian

Organisation and ideological and tactical unity, based on the class

struggle. The supporters of the manifesto made a number of political

mistakes in the actions that they took. Unity was interpreted in a

narrow sense, and soon they strayed off into the fiasco of running

‘revolutionary’ candidates in the elections, which led to the break-up

of their Organisation.

Like the ‘Platform’ the ‘Manifesto’ is marred by a number of errors,

with the ‘Platform it was the idea of the ‘executive committee’, with

the ‘Manifesto’ it was the idea of the ‘vanguard’. Despite its

shortcomings it is still an important document, and its best features

must be taken notice of in developing an anarchist-communist theory and

strategy for today.

1. Libertarian Communism, A Social Doctrine

It was in the 19^(th) Century, when capitalism was developing and the

first great struggles of the working class were taking place — and to be

more precise it was within the First International (1861–1871) — that a

social doctrine appeared called ‘revolutionary socialism’ (as opposed to

reformist or statist legalist socialism). This was also known as

‘anti-authoritarian socialism’ or ‘collectivism’ and then later as

‘anarchism’, ‘anarchist communism’ or ‘libertarian communism’.

This doctrine, or theory, appears as a reaction of the organised

socialist workers. It is at all events linked to there being a

progressively sharpening class struggle. It is an historical product

which originates from certain conditions of history, from the

development of class societies — and not through the idealist critique

of a few specific thinkers.

The role of the founders of the doctrine, chiefly Bakunin, was to

express the true aspirations of the masses, their reactions and their

experiences, and not to artificially create a theory by relying on a

purely ideal abstract analysis or on earlier theories. Bakunin — and

with him James Guillaume, then Kropotkin, Reclus, J. Grave, Malatesta

and so on — started out by looking at the situation of the workers

associations and the peasant bodies, at how they organised and fought.

That anarchism originated in class struggles cannot be disputed.

How is it then that anarchism has very often been thought of as a

philosophy, a morality or ethic independent of the class struggle, and

so as a form of humanism detached from historical and social conditions?

We see several reasons for this. On the one hand, the first anarchist

theoreticians sometimes sought to trust to the opinions of writers,

economists and historians who had come before them (especially Proudhon,

many of whose writings do undoubtedly express anarchist ideas).

The theoreticians who followed them have even sometimes found in writers

like La Boetie, Spencer, Godwin, Stirner, etc. ideas which are analogous

to anarchism — in the sense that they demonstrate an opposition to the

forms of exploitative societies and to the principles of domination they

discovered in them. But the theories of Godwin, Stirner, Tucker and the

rest are simply observations on society — they don’t take account of

History and the forces which determine it, or of the objective

conditions which pose the problem of Revolution.

On the other hand, in all societies based on exploitation and domination

there have always been individual or collective acts of revolt,

sometimes with a communist and federalist or truly democratic content.

As a result, anarchism has sometimes been thought of as the expression

of peoples’ eternal struggle towards freedom and justice — a vague idea,

insufficiently grounded in sociology or history, and one that tends to

turn anarchism into a vague humanism based on abstract notions of

‘humanity’ and ‘freedom’. Bourgeois historians of the working class

movement are always ready to mix up anarchist communism with

individualist and idealist theories, and are to a great extent

responsible for the confusion. These are the ones who have attempted to

bring together Stirner and Bakunin.

By forgetting the conditions of anarchism’s birth, it has sometimes been

reduced to a kind of ultraliberalism and lost its materialist,

historical and revolutionary character.

But at any rate, even if revolts previous to the 19^(th) Century and

ideas of certain thinkers on the relations between individual people and

human groups did prepare the way for anarchism, there was no anarchism

and doctrine until Bakunin.

The works of Godwin for example express the existence of class society

very well, even if they do so in an idealist and confused way. And the

alienation of the individual by the group, the family, religion, the

state, morality, etc. is certainly of a social nature, is certainly the

expression of a society divided into castes or classes.

It can be said that attitudes, ideas and ways of acting of people we

could call rebels, non-conformers, or anarchists in the vague sense of

the term have always existed.

But the coherent formulation of an anarchist communist theory dates from

the end of the 19^(th) Century and is continued each day, perfecting

itself and becoming more precise.

So anarchism could not be assimilated to a philosophy or to an abstract

or individualist ethic.

It was born in and out of the social, and it had to wait for a given

historic period and a given state of class antagonism for anarchist

communist aspirations to show themselves clearly for the phenomenon or

revolt to result in a coherent and complete revolutionary conception.

Since anarchism is not an abstract philosophy or ethic it cannot address

itself to the abstract person, to the person in general. For anarchism

there does not exist in our societies the human being full stop: there

is the exploited person of the despoiled classes and there is the person

of the privileged groups, of the dominant class. To speak to the person

is to fall into the error or sophism of the liberals who speak to the

‘citizen’ without taking into account the economic and social conditions

of the citizens. And to speak to the person in general while, neglecting

the fact that there are classes and there is a class struggle, while

satisfying oneself with hollow rhetorical statements on Freedom and

Justice — in a general sense and with capital letters — is to allow all

the bourgeois philosophers who appear to be liberals but are in fact

conservatives or reactionaries to infiltrate anarchism, to pervert it

into a vague humanitarianism, to emasculate the doctrine, the

organisation and the militants. There was a time, and to be honest this

is still the case in some countries within certain groups, when

anarchism degenerated into the tear-shedding of absolute pacifism or of

a kind of sentimental Christianity. It had to react to this and now

anarchism is taking up the attack on the old world with something other

than woolley thoughts.

It is to the robbed, the exploited, the proletariat, the worker and

peasants that anarchism, as a social doctrine and revolutionary method,

speaks — because only the exploited class, as a social force, can make

the revolution.

Do we mean by this that the working class constitutes the messiah-class,

that the exploited have a providential clear-sightedness, every good

quality and no faults? That would be to fall into idolising the worker,

into a new kind of metaphysics.

But the class that is exploited, alienated, conned and defrauded, the

proletariat — taken in its broad sense and made up of both the

working-class as properly defined (composed of manual workers who have a

certain common psychology, a certain way of being and thinking) and

other waged people such as clerical workers; or to put it another way

the mass of individuals whose only function in production and in the

political order is to carry out orders and so who are removed from

control — this class alone can overthrow power and exploitation through

its economic and social position. The producers alone can bring about

workers control and what would the revolution be if it were not the

transition to control by all the producers?

The proletarian class is therefore the revolutionary class above all,

because the revolution it can bring about is a social and not just a

political revolution — in setting itself free it frees all humanity; in

breaking the power of the privileged class it abolishes classes.

Certainly nowadays there aren’t precise boundaries between the classes.

It is during various episodes of the class struggle that division

occurs. There are not precise boundaries but there are two poles —

proletariat and bourgeoisie (capitalists, bureaucrats etc.); the middle

classes are split in periods of crisis and move towards one pole or the

other; they are unable to provide a solution by themselves as they have

neither the revolutionary characteristics of the proletariat, nor real

control of contemporary society like the bourgeoisie as properly

defined. In strikes for example you may see that one section of the

technicians (especially those who are specialists, those in the research

departments for example) rejoins the working class while another

(technicians who fill higher staff positions and most people in

supervisory roles) moves away from the working-class, at least for a

time. Trade Union practice has always relied on trial-and-error, on

pragmatism, unionising certain sectors and not others according to their

role and occupation. In any case, it is occupation and attitude that

distinguish a class more than salary.

So there is the proletariat. There is its most determined, most active

part, the working class as properly defined. There is also something

wider than the proletariat and which includes other social strata that

must be won over to action: this is the mass of the people, which

comprises small peasants, poor artisans and so on as well as the

proletariat.

It’s not a question of falling for some kind of proletarian mystique but

of appreciating this specific fact: the proletariat, even though it is

slow to seize awareness and despite its retreats and defeats, is

ultimately the only real creator of Revolution.

Bakunin: ‘Understand that since the proletarian, the manual worker, the

common labourer, is the historic representative of the worlds last

slave-system, their emancipation is everyones emancipation, their

triumph the final triumph of humanity...’

Certainly it happens that people belonging to privileged social groups

break with their class, and with its ideology and its advantages, and

come to anarchism. Their contribution is considerable but in some sense

these people become proletarians.

For Bakunin again, the socialist revolutionaries, that is the

anarchists, speak to ‘the working masses in both town and country,

including all people of good will from the upper classes who, making a

clean break with their past, would join them unreservedly and accept

their programme in full.’

But for all that you can’t say that anarchism speaks to the abstract

person, to the person in general, without taking into account their

social status.

To deprive anarchism of its class character would be to condemn it to

formlessness, to an emptiness of content, so that it would become an

inconsistent philosophical pastime, a curiosity for intelligent

bourgeois, an object of sympathy for people longing to have an ideal, a

subject for academic discussion.

So we conclude: Anarchism is not a philosophy of the individual or of

the human being in a general sense.

Anarchism is if you like a philosophy or an ethic but in a very

specific, very concrete sense. It is so by the desires it represents, by

the goals that it gets: as Bakunin says — ’(The proletarians) triumph is

humanity’s final triumph...’

Proletarian, class based in origin, it is only in its goals that it is

universally human or, if you prefer, humanist.

It is a socialist doctrine, or to be more accurate the only true

socialism or communism, the only theory and method capable of achieving

a society without castes and classes, of bringing about freedom and

equality.

Social anarchism or anarchist communism, or again libertarian communism,

is a doctrine of social revolution which speaks to the proletariat whose

desires it represents, whose true ideology it demonstrates — an ideology

which the proletariat becomes aware of through its own experiences.

2. The Problem of the Programme

As anarchism is a social doctrine it makes itself known through an

ensemble of analyses and proposals which set out purposes and tasks, in

other words through a programme. And it’s this programme which

constitutes the shared platform for all militants in the anarchist

Organisation. Without the platform the only cooperation there could be

would be based on sentimental, vague and confused desires, and there

would not be any real unity of views. Then there would only be the

coming together under the same name of different and even opposing

ideas.

A questions arises: could the programme not be a synthesis, taking

account of what is common to people who refer to the same ideal, or more

accurately to the same or nearly the same label? That would be to seek

an artificial unity where to avoid conflicts you would only uphold most

of the time what isn’t really important: you’d find a common but almost

empty platform. The experiment has been tried too many times and out of

‘syntheses’ — unions, coalitions, alliances and understandings — has

only ever come ineffectiveness and a quick return to conflict: as

reality posed problems for which each offered different or opposite

solutions the old battles reappeared and the emptiness, the uselessness

of the shared pseudo-programme — which could only be a refusal to act —

were clearly shown.

And besides, the very idea of creating a patchwork programme, by looking

for small points held in common, supposes that all the points of view

put forward are correct, and that a programme can just spring out of

peoples minds, in the abstract.

Now, a revolutionary programme, the anarchist programme, cannot be one

that is created by a few people and then imposed on the masses. It’s the

opposite that must happen: the programme of the revolutionary vanguard,

of the active minority, can only be the expression — concise and

powerful, clear and rendered conscious and plain — of the desires of the

exploited masses summoned to make the Revolution. In other words: class

before party.

The programme should be determined by the study, the testing and the

tradition of what is constantly sought by the masses. So in working out

the programme a certain empiricism should prevail, one that avoids

dogmatism and does not substitute a plan drawn up by a small group of

revolutionaries for what is shown by the actions and thoughts of the

masses. In its turn, when the programme has been worked out and brought

to the knowledge of these masses it can only raise their awareness.

Finally, the programme as defined in this way can be modified as

analysis of the situation and the tendencies of the masses progresses,

and can be reformulated in clearer and more accurate terms.

Thought of in this way the programme is no longer a group of secondary

points which bring together — (or rather do not divide) people who may

think themselves nearly the same, but is instead a body of analyses and

propositions which is only adopted by those who believe in it and who

undertake to spread the work and make it into a reality.

But, you may say, this platform will have to be worked out, drawn up by

some individual or group. Of course, but since it’s not a question of

any old programme but of the programme of social anarchism, the only

propositions that will be accepted are those that accord with the

interests, desires, thinking and revolutionary ability of the exploited

class. Then you can properly speak of a synthesis because it is no

longer a question of discarding important things that cause division —

it is now a matter of blending into a new shared text propositions which

can unite on the essential point. It’s the role of study meetings,

assemblies and conferences of revolutionaries to identify a programme,

then gather together again and found their Organisation on this

programme.

The drama is that several organisations claim to truly represent the

working class — reformist socialist and authoritarian communist

organisations as well as the anarchist Organisation. Only experience can

settle the matter, can definitely decide which one is right.

There is no possible revolution unless the mass of people who will

create it gather together on the basis of a certain ideological unity,

unless they act with the same mind. This means for us that through their

own experiences the masses will end up by finding the path of

libertarian communism. This also means that anarchist doctrine is never

complete as far as its detailed views and application are concerned and

that it continuously creates and completes itself in the light of

historical events.

From partial trials such as the Paris Commune, the popular revolution in

Russia in 1917, the Makhnovists, the achievements in Spain, strikes, the

fact that the working class is experiencing the hard realities of total

or partial state socialism (from the USSR to nationalisations to the

treacheries of the political parties of the West) — from all this it

seems possible to state that the anarchist programme, with all the

modifications it is open to, represents the direction in which the

ideological unity of the masses will be revealed.

For the moment, let us content ourselves with summarising this programme

so — society without classes and without State.

3. Relations Between the Masses and the Revolutionary Vanguard

We have seen, with regard to the problem of the programme, what our

general idea is of the relation between the oppressed class and the

revolutionary Organisation defined by a programme (that is, the party in

the true sense of the word). But we can’t just say ‘class before party’

and leave it at that. We must expand on this, explain how the active

minority, the revolutionary vanguard, is necessary without it becoming a

military-type leadership, a dictatorship over the masses. In other

words, we must show that the anarchist idea of the active minority is in

no way elitist, oligarchical or hierarchical.

The Need for a Vanguard

There is an idea which says that the spontaneous initiative of the

masses is enough for every revolutionary possibility.

It’s true that history shows us some events that we can regard as

spontaneous mass advances, and these events are precious because they

show the abilities and resources of the masses. But that doesn’t lead at

all to a general concept of spontaneity — this would be fatalistic. Such

a myth leads to populist demagogy and justification of unprincipled

rebellism; it can be reactionary and end in a wait-and-see policy and

compromise.

Opposed to this we find a purely voluntarist idea which gives the

revolutionary initiative only to the vanguard Organisation. Such an idea

leads to a pessimistic evaluation of the role of the masses, to an

aristocratic contempt for their political ability to concealed direction

of revolutionary activity and so to defeat. This idea in fact contains

the germ of bureaucratic and Statist counter-revolution.

Close to the spontaneist idea we can see a theory according to which

mass organisations, unions for example, are not only sufficient for

themselves but suffice for everything. This idea, which calls itself

totally antipolitical, is in fact an economistic concept which is often

expressed as ‘pure syndicalism’. But we would point out that if the

theory wants to hold good then its supporters must refrain from

formulating any programme, any final statement. Otherwise they will be

constituting an ideological Organisation, in however small a way, or

forming a leadership sanctioning a given orientation. So this theory is

only coherent if it limits itself to a socially neutral understanding of

social problems, to empiricism.

Equally removed from spontaneism, empiricism and voluntarism we stress

the need for a specific revolutionary anarchist Organisation, understood

as the conscious and active vanguard of the people.

The Nature of the Role of the Revolutionary Vanguard

The revolutionary vanguard certainly exercises a guiding and leading

role in relations to the movement of the masses. Arguments about this

seem pointless to us as what other use could a revolutionary

Organisation have? Its very existence attests to its leading, guiding

character. The real questions is to know how this role is to be

understood, what meaning we give to the word ‘leading’.

The revolutionary Organisation tends to be created from the fact that

the most conscious workers feel its necessity when confronted by the

unequal progress and inadequate cohesion of the masses. What must be

made clear is that the revolutionary Organisation should not constitute

a power over the masses. its role as guide should be thought of as being

to formulate and express an ideological orientation, both organisational

and tactical — an orientation specified, elaborated and adapted on the

basis of the experiences and desires of the masses. In this way the

organisation’s directives are not orders from outside but rather the

mirrored expression of the general aspirations of the people. Since the

directing function of the revolutionary Organisation cannot possibly be

coercive it can only be revealed by its trying to get its ideas across

successfully, by its giving the mass of the people a thorough knowledge

of its theoretical principles and the main lines of its tactics. It is a

struggle through ideas and through example. And if it’s not forgotten

that the programme of the revolutionary Organisation, the path and the

means that it shows, reflect the experiences and desires of the masses —

that the organised vanguard is basically the mirror of the exploited

class — then it’s clear that leading is not dictating but coordinated

orientation, that on the contrary it opposes any bureaucratic

manipulation of the masses, military style discipline or unthinking

obedience.

The vanguard must set itself the task of developing the direct political

responsibility of the masses, it must aim to increase the masses ability

to organise themselves. So this concept of leadership is both natural

and raises awareness. In the same way the better prepared, more mature

militants inside the Organisation have the role of guide and educator to

other members, so that all may become well informed and alert in both

the theoretical and the practical field, so that all may become

animators in their turn.

The organised minority is the vanguard of a larger army and takes its

reason for being from that army — the masses. If the active minority,

the vanguard, breaks away from the mass then it can no longer carry out

its proper function and it becomes a clique or a tribe.

In the final analysis the revolutionary minority can only be the servant

of the oppressed. It has enormous responsibilities but no privileges.

Another feature of the revolutionary organisation’s character is its

permanence: there are times when it embodies and expresses a majority,

which in turn tends to recognise itself in the active minority, but

there are also periods of retreat when the revolutionary minority is no

more than a ship in a storm. Then it must hold out so that it can

quickly regain its audience — the masses — as soon as circumstances

become favourable again. Even when isolated and cut off from its popular

bases it acts according to the constants of the peoples desires, holding

onto its programme despite all difficulties. It may even be led to

certain isolated acts intended to awaken the masses (acts of violence

against specific targets, insurrections). The difficulty then is to

avoid cutting yourself off from reality and becoming a sect or an

authoritarian, military-type leadership — to avoid wasting away while

living on dreams or trying to act without being understood, driven on or

followed by the mass of the people.

To prevent such degeneration the minority must maintain contact with

events and with the milieu of the exploited — it must look out for the

smallest reactions, the smallest revolts or achievements, study

contemporary society in minute detail for its contradictions, weaknesses

and possibilities for change. In his way, since the minority takes part

in all forms of resistance and action which can range with events from

demands to sabotage, from secret resistance o open revolt) it keeps the

chance of guiding and developing even the smallest disturbances.

By striving to maintain, or acquire, a wide general vision of social

events and their development, by adapting its tactics to the conditions

of the day, by being on its guard — in this way the minority stays true

to its mission and voids the risk of trailing after events, of becoming

a mere spectacle outside of and stranger to the proletariat, of being

bypassed by it. It (the minority) avoids confusing abstract reckonings

and schemes for the true desires of the proletariat. It sticks to its

programme but adapts it and corrects its errors in the light of events.

Whatever the circumstances the minority must never forget that its final

aim is to disappear in becoming identical with the masses when they

reach their highest level of consciousness in achieving the revolution.

In What Forms Can The Revolutionary Vanguard Play Its Role

In practise there are two ways in which the revolutionary Organisation

can influence the masses: there is work in established mass

organisations and there is the work of direct propaganda. This second

sort of activity takes place through papers and magazines, campaigns of

demands and agitation, cultural debates, solidarity actions,

demonstrations, conferences and public meetings. This direct work, which

can sometimes be done through activities organised by others, is

essential for gaining strength and for reaching certain sections of

public opinion which are otherwise inaccessible. It’s of the utmost

importance in both workplace and community. But this sort of work

doesn’t pose the problem of knowing how ‘direction’ can avoid becoming

‘dictatorship’.

It is different for activity inside established mass organisations. But

first, what are these organisations?

They are generally of an economic character and based on the social

solidarity of their members but can have multiple functions — defence

(resistance, mutual aid), education (training for self-government)

offence (demands on the tactical level, expropriation on the strategic)

and administration. These organisations — unions, workers’ fight

committees and so on — even when taking on only one of these possible

functions offer a direct opportunity for work with the masses.

And as well as the economic structures there exist many popular

groupings through which the specific Organisation can make connections

with the masses.

These are, for example, cultural leisure and welfare associations in

which the specific Organisation may find energy, advice and experience.

Here it may spread its influence by putting across its orientation and

by fighting against the attempts of state and politicians to gain

hegemony and control: fighting for the defence of these organisations so

they can keep their own character and become centres of self government

and revolutionary mobilisation, seeds of the new society (for elements

of tomorrow’s society already exist in today’s).

Inside all these social and economic mass organisations influence must

be exercised and strengthened not through a system of external decisions

but through the active and coordinated presence of revolutionary

anarchist militants within them — and in the posts of responsibility to

which they’re called according to their abilities and their attitude. It

should be stressed though that militants should not let themselves get

stuck in absorbing but purely administrative duties which leave them

neither time nor opportunity to exercise a real influence. Political

opponents often try to make prisoners of militant revolutionaries in

this way.

This work of ‘infiltration’ as certain people call it should tend to

transform the specific Organisation from a minority to a majority one —

at least from the point of view of influence.

It also ought to avoid any monopolisation, which would end up having all

tasks — even those of the specific Organisation — taken over by the mass

organisation, or contrariwise would assign leadership of the mass

associations only to members of the specific Organisation, brushing

aside all other opinions. Here it must be made clear that the specific

Organisation shou@d promote and defend not just a democratic and

federalist structure and way of working in mass organisations but also

an open structure — that is, one that makes entry easy for all element&

that are not yet organised, so that the mass organisations can win over

new social forces, become more representative and more able to give to

the specific Organisation the closest possible contact with the people.

Internal Principles Of The Revolutionary Organisation Or Party

What we have said about the programme, and about the role of the

vanguard and its types of activity, clearly shows that this vanguard

must be organised. How?

Ideological Unity

It is obvious that in order to act you need a body of coherent ideas.

Contradictions and hesitations prevent ideas getting through. On the

other hand, the ‘synthesis’, or rather the conglomeration, of

ill-matched ideas which only agree on what isn’t of any real importance,

can only cause confusion and can’t stop itself being destroyed by the

differences which are crucial.

As well as the reasons we found in our analysis of the problem of the

programme, as well as deep ideological reasons concerning the nature of

that programme, there are practical reasons which demand that a genuine

Organisation be based on ideological unity.

The expression of this shared and unique ideology can be the product of

a synthesis — but only in the sense of the search for a single

expression of basically similar ideas with a common essential meaning.

Ideological unity is established by the programme which we looked at

earlier (and will define later on): a libertarian communist programme

which expresses the general desires of the exploited masses.

We should again make it clear the specific Organisation is not a union

or contractual understanding between individuals bringing their own

artificial ideological convictions. It arises and develops as an

organic, natural way because it corresponds to a real need. Its

development rests on a certain number of ideas which aren’t just created

all of a piece but which neglect the deep desires of the exploited. So

the Organisation has a class basis although it does accept people

originally from the privileged classes and in some way rejected by them.

Tactical Unity, A Collective Way Of Acting

Using the programme as its basis the Organisation works out a general

tactical direction. This allows it to exploit all the advantages of

structure: continuity and persistence in work, the abilities and

strengths of some making up for the weaknesses of others, concentration

of efforts, economy of strength, the ability to respond to needs and

circumstances with the utmost effectiveness at any time. Tactical unity

prevents everyone flying off in all directions, frees the movement of

the disastrous effects of several sets of tactics and fighting each

other.

It is here we get the problem of working out tactics. As far as ideology

is concerned — the basic programme, the principles if you like — there

is no problem: they are recognised by everyone in the Organisation. If

there is a difference of opinion on essential matters there is a split

and the newcomer to the Organisation accepts these basic principles,

which can only be modified by unanimous agreement or at the cost of a

separation.

It is quite another matter for questions of tactics. Unanimity may be

sought but only up to the point where for it to come about would mean

everyone agreeing by deciding nothing, leave an Organisation like an

empty shell, drained of substance (and of use since the organisation’s

exact purpose is to co-ordinate forces towards a common goal). So, when

all the arguments for the different proposals have been made, when

discussion can not usefully continue, when similar opinions that agree

in principle have merged and there still remains an irreducible

opposition between the tactics proposed then the Organisation must find

a way out. And there are only four possibilities:

(a) Decide nothing, so refuse to act, and then the Organisation loses

all reason for existing.

(b) Accept the tactical differences and leave everyone to their own

positions. The Organisation can allow this in certain cases on points

that are not of crucial importance.

(c) Consult the Organisation through a vote which will allow a majority

to break off, the minority accepted that it will give up its ideas as

far as public activity is concerned but keeping the right to develop its

argument inside the Organisation — judging that if its opinions accord

with reality more closely than the majority view then they will

eventually prevail by proof of events.

Sometimes the lack of objectivity of this procedure has been invoked,

number not necessarily indicating truth, but it is the only one

possible. It is in no way coercive as it only applies because the

members of the Organisation accept it as a rule, and because the

minority accept it as a necessity, which allows the tactical proposals

accepted to be put to the test.

(d) When no agreement between majority and minority proves possible on a

crucial issue which demands the Organisation take a position then there

is, naturally and inevitably, a split.

In all cases the goal is tactical unity and if they did not try to

achieve this then conferences would just be ineffective and profitless

confrontations. That’s why the first possible outcome (a) — to decide

nothing — is to be rejected in every case and the second (b) — to allow

several different tactics — can only be an exceptional choice.

Of course it is only meetings where the whole Organisation is

represented which can decide the tactical line to be laid down

(conferences, congresses, etc.).

Collective Action And Discipline

Once these general tactics (or orientation) have been decided the

problem of applying them comes up. It is obvious that if the

Organisation has laid down a line of collective action it is so that the

militant activities of every member and every group within the

Organisation will conform to this line. In cases where a majority and a

minority have drawn apart but the two sides have agreed to carry on

working together, no-one can find themselves bullied because all have

agreed to this way of acting beforehand and had a hand in the drawing up

of the ‘line’. This freely accepted discipline has nothing in common

with military discipline and passive obedience to orders. There is no

coercive machinery to impose a point of view that isn’t accepted by the

whole Organisation: there is simply respect for commitments freely made,

as much for the minority as for the majority.

Of course the militants and the different levels of the Organisation can

take initiatives but only in- so far as they do not contradict

agreements and arrangements made by the proper bodies: that is, if these

initiatives are in fact applications of collective decisions. But when

particular activities involve the whole Organisation each member must

consult the Organisation through liaison with its representative organs.

So, collective action and not action decided personally by separate

militants.

Each member takes part in the activity of the whole Organisation in the

same way as the Organisation is responsible for the revolutionary and

political activity of each of its members, since they do not act in the

political domain without consulting the Organisation.

Federation Or Internal Democracy

As opposed to centralism, which is the blind submission of the masses to

a centre, federalism both allows those centralisations which are

necessary and permits the autonomous decision-making of each member and

their control over the whole. It only involves the participants in what

is shared by them.

When federalism brings together groups based on material interests it

relies on an agreement and the basis for unity can sometimes be weak.

This is the case in certain sectors of union activity. But in the

revolutionary anarchist Organisation, where it’s a question of a

programme which represents the general desires of the masses, the basis

for coming together (the principles, the programme) is more important

than any differences and unity is very strong: rather than a pact or a

contract here we should speak of a functional, organic, natural unity.

So federalism must not be understood as the right to show off your

personal whims without considering the obligations to the Organisation

that you’ve taken on.

It means the understanding reached between members and groups with a

view to common work towards a shared goal — but a free understanding, a

considered union.

Such an understanding implies on the one hand that those who share it

fulfill the duties they’ve accepted completely and go along with

collective decisions; it implies on the other that the coordinating and

executive bodies be appointed and controlled by the whole Organisation

at its assemblies and congresses and that their obligations and

prerogatives be precisely established.

So it is on the following bases that an effective anarchist Organisation

can exist:

4. The Libertarian Communist Programme

Aspects Of Bourgeois Rule — Capitalism And The State

Before we show the goals and solutions of libertarian communism we must

examine what kind of enemy we’re faced with.

From what we can know of human history we see that ever since human

societies have been divided into classes (and especially since the

division of social labour), there have been conflicts between the social

classes and, from the earliest demands and revolts, as if a chain of

struggles fought for a better life and a more just society.

Anarchist analysis considers that modern day society, like all those

which came before it, is not a single unit — it is divided into two very

different camps, different as much in their situation as in their social

function: the proletariat (in the broad sense of the word) and the

bourgeoisie.

Added to this is the fact of the class struggle, whose character may

vary — sometimes complex and imperceptible, sometimes open, rapid and

easy to see.

This struggle is very often masked by clashes of secondary interests,

conflicts between groups of the same class, complex historical events

which at first sight don’t have any direct connection with the existence

of classes and their rivalry. Basically though this struggle is always

directed towards transforming contemporary society into a society which

would answer the needs wants and sense of justice of the oppressed and

through this, in a classless society, liberating the whole of humanity.

The structure of any society always expresses in its laws, morality and

culture the respective positions of the social classes — some exploited

and enslaved, the others holding property and authority. In modern

society economics, politics, law, morality and culture all rest on the

existence of the privileges and monopolies of one class and on the

violence organised by that class to maintain its supremacy..

Capitalism

The capitalist system is very often considered as the only form of

exploitative society. But capitalism is a relatively recent economic and

social form and human societies have certainly known other kinds of

slavery and exploitation since the clans, the barbarian empires, the

ancient cities, feudalism, the cities of the Renaissance and so on.

Analysis of the birth, development and evolution of capitalism was the

work of the movement of socialist theoreticians at the start of the

19^(th) Century (Marx and Engels did not more than systematise them),

but this analysis gives a poor account of the general phenomenon of

oppression by one class or another, and of its origin.

There is no point getting involved in debate as to whether authority

came before property or the other way round. The present state of

Sociology does not allow us to settle the matter absolutely, but it

seems clear that economic, political, religious and moral powers have

been closely linked from the very beginning. In any case, the role of

political power cannot be limited to its merely being the tool of

economic might powers. In that way analysis of the phenomenon of

capitalism was not accompanied by adequate analysis of the phenomenon of

the State, because people were concentrating on a very limited part of

history and only the anarchist theoreticians, especially Bakunin and

Kropotkin, strove to give its full importance to a phenomenon which too

often was limited to the State of the period of capitalism’s rise.

Today the evolution of capitalism, passing from classical capitalism to

monopoly capitalism, then to directed and to State capitalism, is giving

rise to new social forms which the summary analyses of the State can no

longer account for.

What is Capitalism?

(a) It is a society of rival classes where the exploiting class owns and

controls the means of production.

(b) In capitalist society all goods — including the power of waged

labour — are commodities.

(c) The supreme love of capitalism, the motive for the production of

goods, is not peoples needs but the increasing of profit, that is the

surplus produced by workers, the extra to what is absolutely necessary

for them to stay alive.

This surplus is also called plus-value.

(d) Increase in the productivity of labour is not followed by the

valorisation of capital which is limited (under-consumption). This

contradiction, which is expressed by the ‘tendency to fall of the rate

of profit’, creates periodic crises which lead the owners of capital to

all sorts of carry-ons: cut-backs in production, destruction of produce,

unemployment, wars and so on.

Capitalism Has Evolved:

(1) Pre-capitalist era: from the end of the Middle Ages the merchant and

banking bourgeoisie develops within the feudal economy.

(2) Classical or Liberalist or Private Capitalism: individualism of the

owners of capital, competition and expansion (after the early

accumulation of capital, by dispossession, pillage, ruin of the peasant

population etc. the capitalism which has established itself in Western

Europe has a world to conquer, enormous sources of wealth and markets

which appear to be vast).

The bourgeois revolutions, by getting rid of feudal restraints, help the

new system to develop.

It is industrialisation and technical progress which have been the basis

for the existence of the capitalist mode of production and for the

transition from the mercantile bourgeoisie of the 15^(th), 16^(th) and

17^(th) Centuries to the industrialist capitalist bourgeoisie. They

continue to develop.

Throughout this period crises are infrequent and not too serious. The

state plays a background role as competition gets rid of the weak — it

is the free play of the system. It is the time of gas and coal in the

technical sphere; of property, the individual boss, competition and free

trade in the economic; parliamentarianism in the political; total

exploitation and the most dreadful poverty of the wage-earners in the

social.

(3) Monopoly Capitalism or Imperialism: productivity increases but

markets constrict or don’t increase at their previous rate. Fall in the

rate of profit of over accumulated capital.

Agreements (trusts, cartels, etc.) replace competition, joint-stock

companies replace the individual boss, protectionism intervenes, the

export of capital comes to be added to that of commodities, financial

credit plays a major role, the merger of banking capital with industrial

capital creates financier capital which tames the state and calls on its

intervention.

It is the time of petrol and electricity in the technical sphere; of

agreements, protectionism, the over-accumulation of capital and the

tendency to fall of the rate of profit, of crises in the economic; of

wars, imperialism and the growth of the State in the political. War is

essential if crises are to overcome — destruction frees markets. In the

social sphere: poverty for the working class but social legislation

limits certain aspects of exploitation.

(4) State Capitalism: everything that characterised the previous stage

is accentuated. Wars are no longer enough to overcome crises. A

permanent war economy is needed which will invest huge amounts of

capital in the war industries while adding nothing to a market already

over-congested stuffed with goods; an appreciable profit is procured by

State orders.

This period is characterised by the State’s seizure of the most

important sections of the economy, of the labour market.

The State becomes capitalism — client, purveyor and overseer of works

and labour power — and so assures itself of every increasing control of

planning, culture and so on.

Bureaucracy develops, discipline and regulation are imposed on labour.

Exploitation and the wage earning class remain, as do the other

essential features of capitalism, but with the appearance of socialising

forms (regulations, Social Security, retirement pensions) which mark the

enslavement of more and more of the proletariat.

State capitalism has various forms: German National Socialism, Stalinist

National Socialism, ever increasing state control in the ‘democracies’

but appearing in a comparatively restricted form (due to a still vast

reserve of plus value from their colonies). Politically as economically

this period tends to take on a totalitarian form.

So Statism reveals itself in forms simultaneously political, economic

and cultural: State finance, war economy, huge public works, conscripted

labour, concentration camps, forced movement of populations, ideologies

which justify the totalitarian order of things (for example, a

counterfeit version of Marxist-Leninist ideology in the USSR, race in

Hitler’s National Socialism, Ancient Rome in Mussolini’s Fascism, etc.).

The State

If capitalism, despite its transformations, or its adaptations, helps

its permanent features (plus value, crises, competition, etc.) ... the

State can no longer be regarded simply as the public Organisation of

repression in the hands of the ruling class, the agent of the

bourgeoisie, capitalism’s copper.

An examination of the forms of the State previous to the period of the

rise of capitalism, and of the present day forms of the State, leads us

to see the State as being important other than just as an instrument.

The Mediaeval, the State of the absolute monarchies of Europe, the State

of the Pharaohs etc... were realities in their own right, they

constituted the ruling State — Class.

And the State of the imperialist stage of capitalism, the State of

today, is tending away from being superstructure to itself becoming

‘structure’.

For the ideologies of the bourgeoisie the State is the regulator organ

is modern society. This is true, but it is that because of a form of

society which is the enslavement of a majority to a minority. It is

therefore the organised violence of the bourgeoisie against the workers,

it is the tool of the ruling class. But alongside this instrumental

aspect it is tending to acquire a functional character, itself becoming

the organised ruling class. It is tending to overcome the conflicts

between the controlling groups on politics and economics. It is tending

to fuse the forces which hold political and economic power, the

different sectors of the bourgeoisie, into a single bloc, whether to

increase its capacity for internal repression or to add to its expansive

power abroad. It is moving towards the unity of politics and economics,

extending its hegemony over all activities, integrating the trade unions

etc ... transferring the waged worker as properly defined into a modern

serf, completely enslaved but with a minimum of safeguards (allowances,

Social Security, etc). It is no longer an instrument but a power in

itself.

At this stage, which is being brought about in every country, even the

U.S.A., was attempted by Nazism and almost perfectly attained in the

USSR, one may wonder if it is still correct to speak of capitalism:

perhaps this level of development of the imperialist stage of capitalism

should not rather be seen as a new form of exploitive society which is

already something other than capitalism? The difference then would be no

longer quantitative but qualitative: it would no longer be a question of

a degree of capitalism’s evolution but of something else, something

really quite new and different. But this is chiefly a matter of

appreciation, of terminology, which may seem premature and without real

importance at present.

It is enough for us to express as follows the form of exploitation and

slavery towards which bourgeois society is tending: the State as a class

apparatus and as Organisation of the class, simultaneously instrumental

and functional, superstructure and structure, is tending to unify all

the powers, every form of domination, of the bourgeoisie over the

proletariat.

5. The Qualities of Libertarian Communism

Libertarian Communist Programme

The Qualities of Libertarian Communism

We have tried to summarise as clearly as possible the characteristics of

the bourgeois society which the Revolution has the goal of doing away

with as it creates a new society: the anarchist communist society.

Before examining how we see the Revolution we must make clear the

essential qualities of this Libertarian Communist Society.

Communism: From the lower to the higher state or complete communism

You could not define communist society any better than by repeating the

old ‘From each according to their means, to each according to their

needs.’ First it affirms the total subordination of the economic to the

needs of human development in the abundance of goods, the reduction of

social labour and of each persons part in it to their own strengths, to

their actual abilities. So the formula expresses the possibility for

peoples total development.

Secondly, this formula implies the disappearance of classes and the

collective ownership and use of the means of production, as only such

use by the community can allow distribution according to needs.

But the complete communism of the formula ‘to each according to their

needs’ presupposes not only collective ownership (administered by

workers councils or ‘syndicates’ or ‘communes’) but equally an extended

growth in production, abundance in fact. Now, its for sure that when the

Revolution comes conditions won’t allow this higher stage of communism:

the situation of scarcity signifies the persistence of the economic over

the human and so a certain limit. Then the application of communism is

no longer that of the principle ‘to each according to their needs’, but

only equality of income or equality of conditions, which amounts to

equal rations or even distributing through the medium of monetary tokens

(of limited validity and having the sole function of distributing those

products which are neither so rare as to be strictly rationed nor so

plentiful as to be ‘help yourself’) — this system would allow the

consumers to decide for themselves how to spend their income. It has

even been envisaged that people might follow the formula ‘to each

according to their work’, taking account of the backwardness in thinking

of certain categories attached to ideas of hierarchy — considering it

necessary to carry on with differential wage rates or to give advantages

like cuts in work time so as to maintain or increase production in

certain ‘inferior’ or not very attractive activities, or to obtain the

maximum productive effort or again to bring about work force movements.

But the importance of these differentials would be minimal and even in

its lower stage (which some call socialism) the communist society tends

towards as great an equalisation as possible and an equivalence of

conditions.

Libertarian Communism

A society in which collective ownership and the principles of equality

have been realised cannot be a society where economic exploitation

persists or where there is a new form of class rule. It is precisely the

negation of those things.

And this is true even for the lower phase of communism which, even if it

shows a degree of economic constraint, in no way justifies the

persistence of exploitation. Otherwise, since it nearly always starts

off from a situation of scarcity the revolution would be automatically

utterly negated. The libertarian communist revolution does not realise

from the start a perfect society, or even a highly developed one, but it

does destroy the bases of exploitation and domination. It is in this

sense that Voline spoke of ‘immediate but progressive revolution.’

But there is another problem: the problem of the State, the problem of

what type of political, economic and social Organisation we’ll have.

Certainly the Marxist Leninist schools envisage the disappearance of the

State in the higher stage of communism but they consider the State a

necessity in its lower stage.

This so called ‘workers’ or ‘proletarian’ State is thought of as

organised coercion, made necessary by the inadequacy of economic

development, lack of progress of human abilities and — at least for an

initial period — the fight against the remnants of the former ruling

classes defeated by the Revolution, or more exactly the degree of

revolutionary territory within and without.

What is our idea of the kind of economic administration the communist

society could have?

Workers administration of course, administration by the whole body of

producers. Now we have seen that as the exploiting society was

increasingly realizing the unification of power, the conditions of

exploitation were decreasingly private property, the market,

competition, etc...and in this way economic exploitation political

coercion and ideological mystification were becoming intimately linked,

the essential basis of power and the line of class division between

exploiters and exploited being the administration of production.

In these conditions the essential act of revolution, the abolition of

exploitation, is brought about through workers control and this control

represents the system for replacing all authorities. It is the whole

body of producers which manages, which organises, which realises

self-administration, true democracy, freedom in economic equality, the

abolition of privileges and of minorities who direct and exploit, which

arranges for economic necessities and for the needs of the Revolution’s

defence. Administration of things replaces government of human beings.

If the abolition of the distinction in the economic field between those

who give orders and those who carry them out is accompanied by the

maintenance of this distinction in the political field, in the form of

the dictatorship of a party or a minority, then it will either not last

five minutes or will create a conflict between producers and political

bureaucrats. So workers control must realise the abolition of all power

held by a minority, of all manifestations of State. It can no longer be

a question of one class dominating and leading, but rather of management

and administration, in the political as much as the economic arena, by

the mass economic organisations, the communes, the people in arms. It is

the peoples direct power, it is not a State. If this is what some call

the dictatorship of the proletariat the term is of doubtful use (we’ll

come back to this) but it certainly has nothing in common with the

dictatorship of the Party or any bureaucracy. It is simply true

revolutionary democracy.

Libertarian Communism and Humanism

So anarchist communism, or libertarian communism, in realizing the

society,of humanity’s full development, a society of fully human women

and men, opens up an era of permanent progression, of gradual

transformation, of transitions.

It does then create a humanism of purpose, whose ideology originates

within class society, in the course of the class struggles’ development,

a humanism which has nothing in common with fraudulent pronouncements on

the abstract human being whom the liberal bourgeois try to point out to

us in their class society.

And so the Revolution — based on the power of the masses of the

proletariat as it frees the exploited class frees all humanity.

6. The Revolution: The Problem of Power, the Problem of State

The Libertarian Communist Programme

The Revolution: The Problem of Power, the Problem of State

Now that we have looked in broad outline at the forms in which the power

of the ruling class is expressed, and set out the essential

characteristics of libertarian communism, it remains for us to say in

detail how we see the passage of Revolution. Here we touch on a crucial

aspect of anarchism and one which differentiates it most clearly from

all other currents of socialism.

What is the Revolution?

Should the Revolution, that is the transition from the class society to

the classless libertarian communist society, be thought of as a slow

process of transformation or as an insurrection?

The foundations of the communist society are laid within the society

based on exploitation; new technical and economic conditions, new

relations between classes, new ideas, all come into conflict with the

old institutions and bring about a crisis which demands a quick and

decisive resolution. This brings a transformation which has long been

prepared for within the old society. The Revolution is the moment when

the new society is born as it smashes the framework of the old: State

capitalism and bourgeois ideologies. it is a real and concrete passage

between two worlds. So the Revolution can only happen in objective

conditions: the final crisis of the class regime.

This conception has nothing in common with the old romantic idea of the

insurrection, of change brought about from one day to the next without

any preparation. Nor has it anything to do with the gradualist, purely

evolutionary conception of the reformists or of the believers in

revolution as process.

Our conception of revolution, equally removed from insurrectionalism and

from gradualism, can be described by the idea of the revolutionary act

prepared over a long period from within the bourgeoisie and at its end

by the seizure and administration of the means of production and

exchange by the organisations of the people. And it is this result of

the revolutionary act which draws a clear line of demarcation between

the old society and the new.

So the Revolution destroys the economic and political power of the

bourgeoisie. This means that the Revolution does not limit itself to

physically suppressing the old rulers or to immobilising the machinery

of government but that it succeeds in destroying the legal institutions

of the State: its laws and custom, hierarchical methods and privileges,

tradition and the cult of the State as a collective psychological

reality.

The Period of Transition

This much being granted what meaning can we give to the commonly used

expression ‘period of transition’ which is so often seen as linked to

the idea of revolution? If it is the passage between class society and

classless society then it is being confused with the act of Revolution.

If it is the passage from the lower stage of communism to the higher

then the expression is inaccurate because the whole post-revolutionary

era constitutes a slow continuous progression, a transformation without

social upheavals, and communist society will continue to evolve.

All that can be said is what we have already made clear in connection

with libertarian communism: the act of Revolution brings an immediate

transformation in the sense that the foundations of society are

radically changed, but a progressive transformation in the sense that

communism is a constant development.

Indeed for the socialist parties and statist communists the ‘transitory

period’ represents a society which breaks with the old order of things

but keeps some elements and survivals from the capitalist an statist

system. It is therefore the negation of true revolution, since it

maintains elements of the exploitative system whose tendency is to grow

strong and expand.

The Dictatorship of the Proletariat

The formula ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ has been used to mean many

different things. If for no other reason it should be condemned as a

cause of confusion. With Marx it can just as easily mean the centralised

dictatorship of the party which claims to represent the proletariat as

it can the federalist conception of the Commune.

Can it mean the exercise of political power by the victorious working

class? No, because the exercise of political power in the recognised

sense of the term can only take place through the agency of an exclusive

group practising a monopoly of power, separating itself from the class

and oppressing it. And this is how the attempt to use a State apparatus

can reduce the dictatorship of the proletariat to the dictatorship of

the party over the masses.

But if by dictatorship of the proletariat is understood collective and

direct exercise of ‘political power’, this would mean the disappearance

of ‘political power’ since its distinctive characteristics are supremacy

exclusivity and monopoly. It is no longer a question of exercising or

seizing political power, it is about doing away with it all together!

If by dictatorship is meant the domination of the majority by a

minority, then it is not a question of giving power to the proletariat

but to a party, a distinct political group. If by dictatorship is meant

the domination of a minority by the majority (domination by the

victorious proletariat of the remnants of a bourgeoisie that has been

defeated as a class) then the setting up of dictatorship means nothing

but the need for the majority to efficiently arrange for its defence its

own social Organisation.

But in that case the expression is inaccurate, imprecise and a cause of

misunderstandings. If ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ is intended to

mean the supremacy of the working class over other exploited groups in

society (poor small owners, artisans, peasants, etc.) then the term does

not at all correspond to a reality which in fact has nothing to do with

mechanical relations between leaders and led such as the term

dictatorship implies.

To speak of ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ is to express a mechanical

reversal of the situation between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat.

Now, if the bourgeois class tends through power to maintain its class

character, to identify itself with the State and to become separated

from society as a whole, it is not at all the same as the subordinate

class, which tends to leave off its class character and to merge with

the classless society. If class rule and the State represent the

organised and codified power of a group which oppresses subordinate

groups they do not account in any way for the violent force exercised

directly by the proletariat.

The terms ‘domination’, ‘dictatorship’ and ‘state’ are as little

appropriate as the expression ‘taking power’ for the revolutionary act

of the seizure of the factories by the workers.

We reject then as inaccurate and causes of confusion the expressions

‘dictatorship of the proletariat’, ‘taking political power’, ‘workers

state’, ‘socialist state’ and ‘proletarian state’.

It remains for us to examine how we see the resolution of the problems

of struggles posed by the Revolution and by its defence.

Direct Workers Power

Through rejecting the idea of a State, which implies the existence and

rule of a exploiter class tending to continue as such, and rejecting the

idea of dictatorship, which implies mechanical relations between leaders

and led, we concede the need for coordination in revolutionary direct

action. (The means of production and exchange must be seized along with

the centres of administration, the revolution must be protected from

counter-revolutionary groups, from the undecided, and indeed from

backward exploited social groups (certain peasant categories for

example).

It certainly is then about exercising power but it is the rule of the

majority, of the proletariat in motion, of the armed people organising

effectively for attack and defence, establishing universal vigilance.

The experience of the Russian Revolution, of the machnovchina, of 1936

Spain is there as witness. And we cannot do better than go along with

the opinion of Camillo Berneri, who wrote from the thick of the Spanish

Revolution, refuting the Bolshevik idea of the State:

‘Anarchists acknowledge the use of direct power by the proletariat but

they see the instrument of this power as constituted by the sum total of

modes of communist Organisation — corporative bodies and communal

institutions, both regional and national — freely set up outside of and

opposed to any political monopoly by party, and endeavouring to reduce

organisational centralisation to a minimum.’

And so against the idea of State, where power is exercised by a

specialised group isolated from the masses, we put the idea of direct

workers power, where accountable and controlled elected delegates (who

can be recalled at any time and are remunerated at the same rate as

other workers) replace hierarchical, specialised and privileged

bureaucracy; where militias, controlled by adminstrative bodies such as

soviets, unions and communes, with no special privileges for military

technicians, realising the idea of the armed people, replace an army cut

off from the body of Society and subordinated to the arbitrary power of

a State or government; where peoples juries responsible for setting

disputes that arise in regard to the fulfillment of agreements and

obligations replace the judicial.

Defence of the Revolution

As far as defence of the Revolution of concerned we must make clear that

our theoretical conception of the Revolution is of an international

phenomenon destroying all basis for counter-attack by the bourgeoisie.

It is when the international Organisation of capitalism has exhausted

all its possibilities of survival, when it has reached its final crisis

point, that we find the optimum conditions for a successful

international revolution. In this case the problem of its defence only

arises as the problem of the complete disappearance of the bourgeoisie.

Totally cut off from its economic and political power this no longer

exists as a class. Once routed, its various elements are kept under

control by the armed organs of the proletariat then absorbed by a

society which will be moving towards the highest degree of homogeneity.

And this last job must be taken care of directly, without the help of

any special bureaucratic body.

The problem of delinquency may be linked up during the revolutionary

period with that of defence of the Revolution. The disappearance of

bourgeois law and of the judicial and prison systems of class society

should not make us forget that there remain asocial people (however few

compared to the appalling number of prisoners in bourgeois society,

produced in the main by the conditions they live under — social

injustice, poverty and exploitation) and that there is the problem of

some bourgeois who cannot in any way be assimilated. The agencies of

popular direct power which we have defined earlier are obliged to

prevent them doing harm.

With a murderer, a dangerous maniac or a saboteur you cannot on the

pretext of freedom let them run off and commit the same crime again. But

their putting out of harms way by the peoples security services has

nothing in common with class society’s degrading prison system. The

individual who is deprived of freedom should be treated more medically

than judicially until they can be safely returned into society.

However, the Revolution may not inevitably be realised everywhere at

once and there could actually be successive revolutions which will only

come together to make the universal revolution if they are spread

abroad, if the revolutionary infection catches hold, if at very least

the proletariat fights internationally for the defence and extension of

revolutionary which are at the outset limited.

Then, as well as internal defence of the Revolution, external defence

becomes necessary, but this can only take place if based on an armed

populace organised into militias and, we must emphasize, with the

support of the international proletariat and possibilities for the

revolution to expand. The Revolution dies if it lets itself be limited

and if on the pretext of defending itself it falls into restoring the

State and so class society.

But the best defence for the new society lies in it asserting its

revolutionary character because this quickly creates conditions in which

no attempt at a restoration of the bourgeoisie will find a solid base.

The total affirmation by the revolutionary territory of its socialist

character is in fact its best weapon because it creates energy and

enthusiasm at home and infection and solidarity abroad. It was perhaps

one of the most fatal errors of the Spanish Revolution that it played

down its achievements so as to devote itself above all else to the

military tasks of its defence.

Revolutionary Power and Freedom

The revolutionary struggle itself and then the consolidation of the

transformation created by the revolution both raise the question of the

freedom of political tendencies which lean towards the maintenance or

the restoration of exploitation. It is one of the aspects of the direct

power of the masses and of the defence of the Revolution.

It cannot be a question here of freedom as properly defined which (till

now existing only as something to be striven for) is precisely what the

Revolution brings about: the doing away with of exploitation and

alienation, government by everyone, and so active participation in

social life and true democracy for all. It cannot be a question either

of the right for all the partisan currents of classes (and so Stateless)

society to put forward their particular solutions and express their

differences of opinion. All that goes without saying.

But it is not at all the same when it’s a matter of groups and

organisations which are more or less openly opposing workers control an

the exercise of power by the masses’ organisations. And this problem is

just as, if not more, likely to come from bureaucratic pseudo-socialist

groups as from groups of the defeated bourgeoisie.

A distinction must be made. At first, during the violent phase of the

struggle, those structures and tendencies which are defending or seeking

to restore the exploitative society must be forcibly crushed. And the

enemy must not be allowed to artfully organise itself, either to

demoralise or to spy. That would be negation of the fight, surrender in

fact. Makhno and also the Spanish libertarians found themselves faced

with these problems and resolved them by suppressing the enemy’s

propaganda. But in cases where the expression of reactionary ideologies

can have no consequence for the outcome of the Revolution, as for

example when its achievements have been consolidated, these ideologies

can be expressed if they are still found interesting or if they retain

their power. They are then nothing more than a topic of curiosity and

the commitment of the people to the Revolution takes away any poison

left in them. If they are only expressed on the ideological level then

they can only be fought on that level, and not by prohibition. Total

freedom of expression, within a conscious, aware populace, can only be

creative of culture.

It remains to be made clear that the responsibility for judging and

deciding, on this question as on all others, rests with the peoples own

organisations, with the armed proletariat.

And it is in this sense that the essential freedom, that for which the

Revolution is made, is maintained and protected.

7. Respective Roles of the Specific Anarchist Organisation and of the

Masses

The idea of Revolution that we have just developed implies a certain

number of historical conditions: on the one hand an acute crisis of the

old society and on the other the existence of an aware mass movement and

an active minority that is well organised and well oriented.

It is the evolution of society itself which allows the development of

the proletariat’s awareness and abilities, the Organisation of its most

advanced strata and the progress of the revolutionary Organisation. But

this revolutionary Organisation reacts on the people as a whole and aims

to develop their capacity for self-government.

We have seen, in regard to relations between the revolutionary

Organisation and the masses, that in the pre-revolutionary period the

specific Organisation can only suggest ends and means and can only get

them accepted through ideological struggle and force of example.

In the revolutionary period it must be the same — otherwise the danger

is of degeneration into bureaucracy, the transformation of the anarchist

Organisation into a specialised body, into a political force separated

from the people, into a State.

The political vanguard, the active minority, can of course during the

making of the Revolution charge itself with special tasks (such as

liquidating enemy forces) but as a general rule it can only be the

consciousness of the proletariat. And it must finally be reabsorbed into

society, gradually as on the one hand its role is completed by the

consolidation of the classless society and its evolution from the lower

to the higher stage of communism, and as on the other the people as a

whole have acquired the necessary level of awareness.

Development of the people’s capacity for self government and

revolutionary vigilance — these must be the tasks of the specific

Organisation once the Revolution has been accomplished. The fate of the

Revolution rests to a great extent on the attitude of the specific

Organisation, on the way it sees its role. For the success of the

Revolution is not inevitable: the people may give up the fight; the

Organisation of the revolutionary minority may neglect its vigilance and

all the bases to be established for a restoration of the bourgeoisie or

a bureaucratic dictatorship — it may even transform itself into a

bureaucratic power. No use is served by hiding these dangers or by

refusing to undertake organised action to prevent them.

We must conduct the fight with a very clear head and it will be in

proportion to our clearheadedness and vigilance that the anarchist

Organisation will be able to fulfill its historic task.

Libertarian Communist Morality

When it sets out objectives to be reached, and when it specifies the

nature of the role the vanguard Organisation should take in relation to

the masses, revolutionary anarchist theory reflects a certain number of

rules of conduct. So we must clarify what we mean by ‘morality’.

We Oppose Moralities

The moralities of all societies reflect to a certain extent the way of

life and the level of development of those societies, and as a result

they are expressed in very strict rules which allow no deviation in any

sense (transgression, the will to change these rules being a crime). In

this way morals (which do express a certain need in the framework of

social life) and towards inertia.

So, they do not simply express a practical need for mediation as they

may come into contradiction with new conditions of existence that

appear. Moreover, they are marked by a religious, theological or

metaphysical character and put forward their rules as the expression of

a supernatural imperative — actions which conform to or break these

rules boast a mystical nature as virtue or sin. Resignation, which

really should only be a person’s recognition of their limits before

certain facts, becomes the primary virtue and can even impel a search

for suffering, itself becoming the supreme virtue. From this point of

view Christianity is one of the most hateful of moralities. So morality

is not simply a codification of external sanctions but is deeply rooted

in individuals in the form of ‘moral conscience’. This moral conscience

is acquired and maintained largely as a result of the religious nature

with which morality is imbued, and is itself marked by a religious,

supernatural nature. So it becomes quite foreign to the simple

translation into a person’s conscience of the needs of living socially.

Finally, and most importantly, even when moralities do not openly

express the division of societies into classes or castes they are used

by privileged groups to justify and guarantee their domination. Life law

and religion (religion, law and morality are simply expressions in

neighbouring spheres of the same social reality) morality sanctions the

existing conditions and relations of domination and exploitation.

Since moralities are expressions of people’s alienation in exploitative

societies, as are ideologies, laws, religions, etc... being

characterised by inertia, mystification, resignation and the

justification and maintenance of class privilege — you will understand

why anarchists have spent a lot of effort in denouncing their true

nature.

Do We Have a Morality?

It is often pointed out that moralities could evolve or be modified,

that one morality could replace another even within societies based on

exploitation. There have been faint differences, adaptations or

variations linked up with conditions of life but they (moralities) all

protected the same essential values — submissiveness and respect for

property for example. It remains no less true that these adaptations

were fought against, that their promoters (Socrates and Christ for

example) were often persecuted, than that morality tends towards

inertia.

in any case it does not seem that the enslaved have been able to

introduce their own values into these moralities.

But the important thing here is to know if the enslaved — and the

revolutionaries who express their desires — can have their own values,

their own morality.

If we do not wish to accept the morality of the society in which we

live, if we refuse this morality both because it recognises so as to

maintain a social system based on exploitation and domination, and

because it is imbued with abstractions and metaphysical ideals, then on

what can we base our morality? There is a solution to this apparent

contradiction: it is that thought and social science allow us to

envisage a process which would constitute the possibility for the human

race to blossom out in every way, and that this process is really

nothing other than the general desires of the oppressed, as expressed by

true socialism, by libertarian communism. So it is our revolutionary

goal which is our ideal, our imperative. It is certainly an ideal and an

imperative on which a morality can be based, but it is an ideal which

rests on the real and not on the religious revelation or a metaphysics

This deal is a kind of humanism, but a humanism based on a revolutionary

transformation of society and not a sentimental humanism resting on

nothing at all and camouflaging the realities of the social struggle.

Our Morality

What are the moral values which demonstrate this ideal in the

proletariat?

Is this morality expressed by rules and precepts?

It is clear that it can no longer be a question of acting, and of

judging moralities that we oppose, in terms of ideas of ‘good’ and evil,

any more than we can let ourselves be dragged into futile word games as

to whether the motive force for action should be called ‘egoism’ or

‘altruism’.

But between those actions normally assured by the play of affectivity

and feelings (maternal, love, empathy, saving someone who is in danger

and so on) and those which depend on contracts, on written or unwritten

agreements (and so on the law), there is a whole gamut of social

relations which rely on moral conceptions and a moral conscience.

Where is the guarantee of sincere respect in contract clauses? What

should a person’s attitude be towards their enemies? Which weapons do

they forbid themselves use of? There is only one morality which can act

as a guide, which can fix limits, which can prevent constant recourse to

litigation and juries.

It is in revolutionary practice and the lives of the aware proletariat

that we find values such as solidarity, courage, a sense of

responsibility, clearness of thought, tenacity, a federalism or true

democracy of working-class organisations and anarchists which realises

both discipline and a spirit of initiative, respect for revolutionary

democracy — that is to say the possibility for all currents which

sincerely seek the creation of communist society to put forward their

ideas, to criticise and so to perfect revolutionary theory and practice.

The revolutionary fundamental that we have established as an imperative

clearly exempts us from any morality in dealings with the enemy, the

bourgeoisie, which for its own defence would try to make revolutionaries

accept the prohibitions of its morality. It is quite clear that in this

field only the ends can dictate our conduct. This means that once the

ends are recognised and scientifically laid down, the means are simply a

matter of tactics and in consequence can only be valued as means if they

are suited to the ends, to the sought for goal. So this does not mean

any old means and there is no question of justifying means. We must

reject the equivocal formula ‘the ends justify the means’ and say more

simply — ‘the means only exist, are only chosen, with a view to the ends

to which they are tied and suited, and do not have to be justified

before the enemy and in terms of the enemy’s morality’

In contrast though, these means do inevitably come within the framework

of our morality, since they are appropriate to our ideal — an ideal,

libertarian communism, which implies the Revolution, which in turn

implies that the masses will grasp consciousness guided by the anarchist

Organisation. For example the means imply the solidarity, courage and

sense of responsibilities that we have cited earlier as virtues of our

morality.

There is one point that should make us pause, an aspect of our morality

which people might attach to the meaning of solidarity but which is

really the very epitome of our morality: truth. As much as it is normal

for us to cheat our enemy, the bourgeoisie, who themselves use all kinds

of deceit, so we must tell the truth not just between comrades but to

the masses.

How could we do otherwise when more than anything else, their awareness,

and so their understanding and their judgment, must be increased? Those

who have tried to behave otherwise have only succeeded in humiliating

and disheartening the people, making them all lose all sense of truth,

of analysis and of criticism.

There is nothing proletarian — or revolutionary about immoralist

cynicism. That is the style of decadent elements of the bourgeoisie who

declare the emptiness of the official morality but are incapable of

finding a healthy morality in any existing milieu.

The immoralist is outwardly free in all their movements. But they no

longer know where they’re going and when they have deceived other people

they deceive themselves.

It is not enough to have a goal you also need a way of getting there.

The working out of a morality within the aware masses and still more

within the libertarian communist movement — comes to strengthen the

structure of revolutionary ideology and to bring an important

contribution to the preparation of a new culture, at the same time as it

totally repudiates the culture of the bourgeoisie.