💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › eric-hobsbawm-anarchists.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:35:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchists
Author: Eric Hobsbawm
Date: 1973
Language: en
Topics: anarchist movement, history of anarchism, history, Russian revolution, Spanish Revolution, not anarchist
Source: Retrieved on 8th June 2022 from http://www.ditext.com/hobsbawm/anarchists.html
Notes: From Volume II of Revolutionaries.

Eric Hobsbawm

Anarchists

Bolshevism and the Anarchists

The libertarian tradition of communism — anarchism — has been bitterly

hostile to the marxist ever since Bakunin, or for that matter Proudhon.

Marxism, and even more leninism, have been equally hostile to anarchism

as theory and programme and contemptuous of it as a political movement.

Yet if we investigate the history of the international communist

movement in the period of the Russian revolution and the Communist

International, we find a curious asymmetry. While the leading spokesmen

of anarchism maintained their hostility to bolshevism with, at best, a

momentary wavering during the actual revolution, or at the moment when

the news of October reached them, the attitude of the bolsheviks, in and

outside Russia, was for a time considerably more benevolent to the

anarchists. This is the subject of the present paper.

The theoretical attitude with which bolshevism approached anarchist and

anarcho-syndicalist movements after 1917, was quite clear. Marx, Engels

and Lenin had all written on the subject, and in general there seemed to

be no ambiguity or mutual inconsistency about their views, which may be

summarized as follows:

anarchists, i.e. a libertarian communism in which exploitation, classes

and the state will have ceased to exist.

overthrow of bourgeois power through proletarian revolution, by a more

or less protracted interval characterized by the ‘dictatorship of the

proletariat’ and other transitional arrangements, in which state power

would play some part. There was room for some argument about the precise

meaning of the classical marxist writings on these problems of

transition, but no ambiguity at all about the marxist view that the

proletarian revolution would not give rise immediately to communism, and

that the state could not be abolished, but would ‘wither away’. On this

point the conflict with anarchist doctrine was total and clearly

defined.

power of a revolutionary state used for revolutionary purposes, marxism

was actively committed to a firm belief in the superiority of

centralization to decentralization or federalism and (especially in the

leninist version), to a belief in the indispensability of leadership,

organization and discipline and the inadequacy of any movement based on

mere ‘spontaneity’.

marxists took it for granted that socialist and communist movements

would engage in it as much as in any other activities which could

contribute to advance the overthrow of capitalism.

authoritarian and/or bureaucratic tendencies of parties based on the

classical marxist tradition, none of these critics abandoned their

characteristic lack of sympathy for anarchist movements, so long as they

considered themselves to be marxists.

The record of the political relations between marxist movements and

anarchist or anarcho-syndicalist ones, appeared equally unambiguous in

1917. In fact, these relations had been considerably more acrimonious in

the lifetime of Marx, Engels and the Second International than they were

to be in that of the Comintern. Marx himself had fought and criticized

Proudhon and Bakunin, and the other way round. The major social

democratic parties had done their best to exclude anarchists, or been

obliged to do so. Unlike the First International, the Second no longer

included them, at all events after the London Congress of 1896. Where

marxist and anarchist movements coexisted, it was as rivals, if not as

enemies. However, though the marxists were intensely exasperated by the

anarchists in practice revolutionary marxists, who shared with them an

increasing hostility to the reformism of the Second International,

tended to regard them as revolutionaries, if misguided ones. This was in

line with the theoretical view summarized in (a) above. At least

anarchism and revolutionary syndicalism might be regarded as a

comprehensible reaction against reformism and opportunism. Indeed, it

might be — and was — argued that reformism and anarcho-syndicalism were

part of the same phenomenon: without the one, the other would not have

gained so much ground. It could further be argued that the collapse of

reformism would also automatically weaken anarcho-syndicalism.

It is not clear how far these views of the ideologists and political

leaders were shared by the rank-and-file militants and supporters of the

marxist movements. We may suppose that the differences were often much

less clearly felt at this level. It is a well-known fact that doctrinal,

ideological and programmatic distinctions which are of major importance

at one level, are of negligible importance at another- e.g. that as late

as 1917 ‘social democratic’ workers in many Russian towns were barely if

at all aware of the differences between bolsheviks and mensheviks. The

historian of labour movements and their doctrines forgets such facts at

his peril.

This general background must be supplemented by a discussion of the

differences between the situation in various parts of the world, in so

far as these affected the relations between communists and anarchists or

anarcho-syndicalists. No comprehensive survey can be made here, but at

least three different types of countries must be distinguished:

labour movement, e.g. most of north-western Europe (except the

Netherlands), and several colonial areas in which labour and socialist

movements had hardly developed before 1917.

diminished dramatically, and perhaps decisively, in the period 1914–36.

These must include part of the Latin world, e.g. France, Italy and some

Latin American countries, as also China, Japan and — for somewhat

different reasons — Russia.

dominant, until the latter part of the 1930s. Spain is the most obvious

case.

In regions of the first type relations with movements describing

themselves as anarchist or anarcho-syndicalist were of no significance

to communist movements. The existence of small numbers of anarchists,

mainly artists and intellectuals, raised no political problem, and

neither did the presence of anarchist political refugees, immigrant

communities in which anarchism might be influential, and other phenomena

marginal to the native labour movement. This appears to have been the

case in, say, Britain and Germany after the 1870s and 1880s, when

anarchist trends had played some part, mainly disruptive, in the special

circumstances of extremely small socialist movements or socialist

movements temporarily pressed into semi-illegality as by Bismarck’s

anti-socialist law. The struggles between centralized and decentralized

types of movement, between bureaucratic and anti-bureaucratic,

‘spontaneous’ and ‘disciplined’ movements were fought out without any

special reference (except by academic writers or a few very erudite

marxists) to the anarchists. This was the case in Britain in the period

corresponding to that of revolutionary syndicalism on the continent. The

extent to which communist parties showed themselves to be aware of

anarchism as a political problem in their countries, remains to be

seriously studied by a systematic analysis of their polemical

publications (in so far as these did not merely echo the preoccupations

of the International), of their translation and/or re-publication of

classical marxist writings on anarchism, etc. However, it may be

suggested with some confidence that they regarded the problem as

negligible, compared to that of reformism, doctrinal schisms within the

communist movement, or certain kinds of petty-bourgeois ideological

trends such as, in Britain, pacifism. It was certainly entirely possible

to be deeply involved in the communist movement in Germany in the early

1930s, in Britain in the later 1930s, without paying more than the most

cursory or academic attention to anarchism, or indeed without ever

having to discuss the subject.

The regions of the second type are in some respects the most interesting

from the point of view of the present discussion. We are here dealing

with countries or areas in which anarchism was an important, in some

periods or sectors a dominant influence in the trade unions or the

political movements of the extreme left.

The crucial historical fact here is the dramatic decline of anarchist

(or anarcho-syndicalist) influence in the decade after 1914. In the

belligerent countries of Europe this was a neglected aspect of the

general collapse of the prewar left. This is usually presented primarily

as a crisis of social democracy, and with much justification. At the

same time it was also a crisis of the libertarian or anti-bureaucratic

revolutionaries in two ways. First, many of them (e.g. among

‘revolutionary syndicalists’) joined the bulk of marxist social

democrats in the rush to the patriotic banners — at least for a time.

Second, those who did not, proved, on the whole, quite ineffective in

their opposition to the war, and even less effective at the end of the

war in their attempts to provide an alternative libertarian

revolutionary movement to the bolsheviks. To cite only one decisive

example. In France (as Professor Kriegel has shown), the ‘Carnet B’

drawn up by the Ministry of the Interior to include all those

‘consideres comme dangereux pour l’ordre social’, i.e. ‘les

revolutionnaires, les syndicalistes et les anarchistes’, in fact

contained mainly anarchists, or rather ‘la faction des anarchistes qui

milite dans le mouvement syndical’. On 1 August 1914 the Minister of the

Interior, Malvy, decided to pay no attention to the Carnet B, i.e. to

leave at liberty the very men who, in the government’s opinion, had

convincingly established their intention to oppose war by all means, and

who might presumably have become the cadres of a working-class anti-war

movement. In fact, few of them had made any concrete preparations for

resistance or sabotage, and none any preparation likely to worry the

authorities. In a word, Malvy decided that the entire body of men

accepted as being the most dangerous revolutionaries, was negligible. He

was, of course, quite correct.

The failure of the syndicalist and libertarian revolutionaries, further

confirmed in 1918–20, contrasted dramatically with the success of the

Russian bolsheviks. In fact, it sealed the fate of anarchism as a major

independent force on the left outside a few exceptional countries for

the next fifty years. It became hard to recall that in 1905–14 the

marxist left had in most countries been on the fringe of the

revolutionary movement, the main body of marxists had been identified

with a de facto non-revolutionary social democracy, while the bulk of

the revolutionary left was anarcho-syndicalist, or at least much closer

to the ideas and the mood of anarcho-syndicalism than to that of

classical marxism. Marxism was henceforth identified with actively

revolutionary movements, and with communist parties and groups, or with

social democratic parties which, like the Austrian, prided themselves on

being markedly left wing. Anarchism and anarcho-syndicalism entered upon

a dramatic and uninterrupted decline. In Italy the triumph of fascism

accelerated it, but where, in the France of 1924, let alone of 1929 or

1934 was the anarchist movement which had been the characteristic form

of the revolutionary left in 1914?

The question is not merely rhetorical. The answer is and must be:

largely in the new communist or communist-led movements. In the absence

of adequate research this can not yet be adequately documented, but the

broad facts seem clear. Even some of the leading figures or well-known

activists of the ‘bolshevized’ communist parties came from the former

libertarian movements or from the militant trade union movements with

their libertarian ambiance: thus in France Monmousseau and probably

Duclos. This is all the more striking, since it was rather unlikely that

leading members of marxist parties would be drawn from former

anarcho-syndicalists, and even less likely that leading figures in the

libertarian movement would opt for leninism.[1] It is indeed highly

likely that (as the leader of the Dutch cp, De Groot observes, perhaps

not without some parti pris) that ex-libertarian workers adapted

themselves better to life in the new cps than ex-libertarian

intellectuals or petty bourgeois. After all, at the level of the

working-class militant, the doctrinal or programmatic differences which

divide ideologists and political leaders so sharply, are often quite

unreal, and may have little significance, unless at this level — i.e. in

the worker’s specific locality or trade union — different organizations

or leaders have long-established patterns of rivalry.

Nothing is more likely, therefore, than that workers previously adhering

to the most militant or revolutionary union in their locality or

occupation should, after its disappearance shift without much difficulty

into the communist union which now represented militancy or

revolutionary attitudes. When old movements disappear, such a transfer

is common. The old movement may retain its mass influence here and

there, and the leaders and militants who have identified themselves with

it, may continue to hold it together on a diminishing scale as best they

can, in so far as they do not retire de jure or de facto into an

unreconciled inactivity. Some of the rank and file may also drop out.

But a large proportion must be expected to transfer to the most suitable

alternative, if one is available. Such transfers have not been

investigated seriously, so that we know no more about what happened to

ex-anarcho-syndicalists (and those who had followed their lead) than we

know about ex-members or followers of the Independent Labour Party in

Britain after the 1930s, or ex-communists in Western Germany after 1945.

If a large part of the rank and file of the new communist parties, and

more especially, the new revolutionary trade unions, was composed of

former libertarians, it would be natural to expect this to have had some

effect on them. On the whole there is little sign of this within the

communist parties. To take merely one representative example, the

discussions on ‘bolshevizing the Communist International’ in the

Enlarged Executive of that organization, March-April 1925, which dealt

specifically with the problem of non-communist influences within the

communist movement. There are little more than a half-dozen references

to syndicalist and none to anarchist influence in this document.[2] They

are confined entirely to the cases of France, Italy and the United

States. As for France, the loss ‘of the larger part of the former

leading officials [of social democratic origins in Germany], and of

petty-bourgeois syndicalist origins in France’ is noted (p. 38). Treint

reported that ‘our Party has eliminated all the errors of Trotskyism:

all the individualist quasi-anarchist errors, the errors of the belief

in legitimacy, of the coexistence of diverse factions in the Party. It

has also learned to know the Luxemburgist errors’ (p. 99). The ECCI

resolution recommended, as one of ten points concerning the French party

‘in spite of all former French traditions, establishment of a

well-organized Communist Mass Party’ (p. 160). As for Italy, ‘the

numerous and diverse origin of the deviations which have arisen in

Italy’ are noted, but without reference to any libertarian trends.

Bordiga’s similarity to ‘Italian syndicalism’ is mentioned, though it is

not claimed that he ‘identifies himself completely’ with this and other

analogous views. The Marxist-Syndicalist faction (Avanguardia group) is

mentioned as one of the reactions against the opportunism of the Second

International, as is its dissolution ‘into trade syndicalism’ after

leaving the party (pp. 192–3). The recruitment of the CPUSAU from two

sources — the Socialist Party and syndicalist organizations — is

mentioned (p. 45). If we compare these scattered references to the

preoccupation of the International in the same document with a variety

of other ideological deviations and other problems, the relatively minor

impact of libertarian-syndicalist traditions within communism, or at

least within the major communist parties of the middle 1920s, is

evident.

This may to some extent be an illusion, for it is clear that behind

several of the tendencies which troubled the International more

urgently, such traditions may be discerned. The insistence of the

dangers of ‘Luxemburgism’ with its stress on spontaneity, its hostility

to nationalism and other similar ideas, may well be aimed at the

attitudes of militants formed in the libertarian-syndicalist school, as

also the hostility — by this time no longer a matter of very serious

concern — to electoral abstentionism. Behind ‘Bordighism’, we can

certainly discern a preoccupation with such tendencies. In various

western parties Trotskyism and other marxist deviations probably

attracted communists of syndicalist origins, uncomfortable in the

‘bolshevized’ parties — e.g. Rosmer and Monatte. Yet it is significant

that the Cahiers du Bolchevisme (28 November 1924), in analyzing the

ideological trends within the French cp, make no allusion to

syndicalism. The journal divided the party into ’20 per cent

ofjauresism, 10 per cent of marxism, 20 per cent of leninism, 20 per

cent of Trotskyism, and 30 per cent of Confusionism’. Whatever the

actual strength of ideas and attitudes derived from the old syndicalist

tradition, that tradition itself had ceased to be significant, except as

a component of various left-wing, sectarian or schismatic versions of

marxism.

However, for obvious reasons, anarchist problems preoccupied the

communist movement more in those parts of the world where before the

October revolution the political labour movement had been almost

entirely anarchist and social democratic movements had been negligible,

or where the anarcho-syndicalists maintained their strength and

influence during the 1920s; as in large regions of Latin America. It is

not surprising that the Red International of Labour Unions in the 1920s

was much preoccupied with these problems in Latin America, or that as

late as 1935 the Communist International observed that ‘the remnants of

anarcho-syndicalism have not yet been completely overcome’ in the cp of

Brazil (whose original membership consisted overwhelmingly of former

anarchists). Nevertheless, when we consider the significance of

anarcho-syndicalism in this continent, the problems arising from it seem

to have caused the Comintern little real preoccupation after the Great

Depression of 1929–30. Its chief criticism of the local communist

parties in this respect appears to have been that they were unable to

benefit sufficiently from the rapid decline of the anarchist and

anarcho-syndicalist organizations and the growing sympathy for communism

of their members.[3]

In a word, the libertarian movements were now regarded as rapidly

declining forces which no longer posed major political problems.

Was this complacency entirely justified? We may suspect that the old

traditions were stronger than official communist literature suggests, at

any rate within the trade union movements. Thus it is fairly clear that

the transfer of the Cuban tobacco workers’ union from

anarcho-syndicalist to communist leadership made no substantial

difference either to its trade union activities or to the attitude of

its members and militants.[4] A good deal of research is needed to

discover how far, in former strongholds of anarcho-syndicalism the

subsequent communist trade union movement showed signs of the survival

of old habits and practices.

Spain was virtually the only country in which anarchism continued to be

a major force in the labour movement after the Great Depression, while

at the same time communism was — until the Civil War — comparatively

negligible. The problem of the communist attitude to Spanish anarchism

was of no international significance before the second republic, and in

the period of the Popular Front and Civil War became too vast and

complex for cursory treatment. I shall therefore omit discussion of it.

The fundamental attitude of the bolsheviks towards anarchists thus was

that they were misguided revolutionaries, as distinct from the social

democrats who were pillars of the bourgeoisie. As Zinoviev put it in

1920, in discussion with the Italians who were considerably less well

disposed towards their own anarchists: ‘In times of revolution Malatesta

is better than d’Aragona. They do stupid things, but they’re

revolutionaries. We fought side by side with the syndicalists and the

anarchists against Kerensky and the Mensheviks. We mobilized thousands

of workers in this way. In times of revolution one needs

revolutionaries. We have to approach them and form a bloc with them in

revolutionary periods.’[5] This comparatively lenient attitude of the

bolsheviks was probably determined by two factors: the relative

insignificance of anarchists in Russia, and the visible readiness of

anarchists and syndicalists after the October revolution to turn to

Moscow, at all events until it was clear that the terms for union were

unacceptable. It was no doubt reinforced later by the rapid decline of

anarchism and syndicalism, which — outside a small and diminishing

number of countries — made it seem increasingly insignificant as a trend

in the labour movement. ‘I have seen and talked to few anarchists in my

life’, said Lenin at the Third Congress of the ci (Protokoll, Hamburg,

1921, p. 510.) Anarchism had never been more than a minor or local

problem for the bolsheviks. An official ci annual for 1922–3 illustrates

this attitude. The appearance of anarchist groups in 1905 is mentioned,

as is the fact that they lacked all contact with the mass movement and

were ‘as good as annihilated’ by the victory of reaction. In 1917

anarchist groups appeared in all important centres of the country, but

in spite of various direct action they lacked contact with the masses in

most places and hardly anywhere succeeded in taking over leadership.

‘Against the bourgeois government they operated in practice as the

“left”, and incidentally disorganized, wing of the Bolsheviks.’ Their

struggle lacked independent significance. ‘Individuals who came from the

ranks of the anarchists, performed important services for the

revolution; many anarchists joined the Russian cp.’ The October

revolution split them into ‘sovietist’, some of whom joined the

bolsheviks while others remained benevolently neutral, and ‘consequent’

anarchists who rejected Soviet power, split into various and sometimes

eccentric factions, and are insignificant. The various illegal anarchist

groups active during the Kronstadt rising, have almost totally

disappeared.[6] Such was the background against which the leading party

of the Comintern judged the nature of the anarchist and syndicalist

problem.

It need hardly be said that neither the bolsheviks nor the communist

parties outside Russia were inclined to compromise their views in order

to draw the libertarians towards them. Angel Pestafia, who represented

the Spanish cnt at the Second Congress of the ci found himself isolated

and his views rejected. The Third Congress, which discussed relations

with syndicalists and anarchists at greater length, established the

distance between them and the communists even more clearly, under the

impact of some trends within the communist parties and what was believed

to be an increase in anarchist and syndicalist influence in Italy after

the occupation of the factories.[7] Lenin intervened on this point,

observing that agreement with anarchists might be possible on objectives

— i.e. the abolition of exploitation and classes — but not on principles

— i.e. ‘the dictatorship of the proletariat and the use of state power

during the transitional period’.[8] Nevertheless, the increasingly sharp

critique of anarcho-syndicalist views was combined with a positive

attitude towards the movement especially in France. Even in the Fourth

Congress the syndicalists were still, in France, contrasted to their

advantage not only with the social democrats, but with ex-social

democratic communists. ‘We have to look for quite a lot of elements for

a Communist Party in the ranks of the Syndicalists, in the ranks of the

best parts of the Syndicalists. This is strange but true’ (Zinoviev).[9]

Not until after the Fifth Congress — i.e. during the period of

‘bolshevization’ does the negative critique of anarcho-syndicalism

clearly begin to prevail over the positive appreciation of the movement

— but by then it is so far merged with the critique of Trotskyism,

Luxemburgism and other intra-communist deviations as to lose its

specific political point.[10] By this time, of course, anarchism and

syndicalism were in rapid decline, outside a few special areas.

It is therefore at first sight surprising that anti-anarchist propaganda

seems to have developed on a more systematic basis within the

international communist movement in the middle 1930s. This period saw

the publication of the pamphlet, Marx et Engels contre I’anarchisme, in

France (1935), in the series ‘Elements du communisme’, and an obviously

polemical History of Anarchism in Russia, by E. Yaroslavsky (English

edition 1937). It may also be worth noting the distinctly more negative

tone of the references to anarchism in Stalin’s Short History of the

CPSU (b) (1938),[11] compared to the account of the early 1920s, quoted

above.

The most obvious reason for this revival of anti-anarchist sentiment was

the situation in Spain, a country which became increasingly important in

international communist strategy from 1931, and certainly from 1934.

This is evident in the extended polemics of Lozovsky which are

specifically aimed at the Spanish cnt.[12] However, until the Civil War

the anarchist problem in Spain was considered much less urgent than the

social democratic problem, especially between 1928 and the turn in

Comintern policy after June-July 1934. The bulk of the references in

official ci documents in this period concentrates, as might be expected,

on the misdeeds of Spanish socialists. During the Civil War the

situation changed, and it is evident that, for instance, Yaroslavsky’s

book is aimed primarily at Spain: ‘The workers in those countries where

they now have to choose between the doctrine of the anarchists and those

of the Communists should know which of the two roads of revolution to

choose.’[13]

However, perhaps another — though perhaps relatively minor — element in

the revived anti-anarchist polemics should also be noted. It is evident

both from the basic text which is constantly quoted and reprinted —

Stalin’s critique of Bukharin’s alleged semi-anarchism, made in 1929 —

and from other references, that anarchizing tendencies are condemned

primarily because they ‘repudiate the state in the period of transition

from capitalism to socialism’ (Stalin). The classical critique of

anarchism by Marx, Engels and Lenin, tends to be identified with the

defence of the tendencies of state development in the Stalinist period.

To sum up:

The bolshevik hostility to anarchism and anarcho-syndicalism as a

theory, strategy or form of organized movement was clear and unwavering,

and all ‘deviations’ within the communist movement in this direction

were firmly rejected. For practical purposes such ‘deviations’ or what

could be regarded as such, ceased to be of significance in and outside

Russia from the early 1920s.

The bolshevik attitude to the actual anarchist and anarcho-syndicalist

movements was surprisingly benevolent. It was determined by three main

factors:

revolutionaries, and both objective and, given the right circumstances,

subjective allies of communism against social democracy, and potential

communist;

many syndicalists and even anarchists in the years immediately following

1917;

and anarcho-syndicalism as a mass movement in all but a very few of its

old centres.

For the reasons mentioned above, the bolsheviks devoted little attention

to the problem of anarchism outside the few areas in which it retained

its strength (and, in so far as the local communist parties were weak,

not much even within those areas) after the early 1920s. However, the

rise to international significance of Spain, and perhaps also the

attempt to give a theoretical legitimation to the Stalinist development

of a dictatorial and terrorist state, led to a revival of anti-anarchist

polemics in the period between the Great Slump and the end of the

Spanish Civil War.

(1969)

The Spanish Background

The Iberian peninsula has problems but no solutions, a state of affairs

which is common or even normal in the ‘third world’, but extremely rare

in Europe. For better or worse most states on our continent have a

stable and potentially permanent economic and social structure, an

established line of development. The problems of almost all of Europe,

serious and even fundamental though they may be, arise out of the

solution of earlier ones. In western and northern Europe they arose

mainly on the basis of successful capitalist development, in eastern

Europe (much of which was in a situation analogous to Spain until 1945)

on the basis of a soviet-type socialism. In neither case do the basic

economic and social patterns look provisional, as, for instance, the

patterns of national relations within and between states still so often

appear to be. Belgian capitalism or Yugoslav socialism may well change,

perhaps fundamentally; but both are obviously far less likely to

collapse at slight provocation than the complex ad hoc administrative

formulae for ensuring the coexistence of Flemings and Walloons, or of

various mutually suspicious Balkan nationalities.

Spain is different. Capitalism has persistently failed in that country

and so has social revolution, in spite of its constant imminence and

occasional eruption. The problems of Spain arise out of the failures,

not the successes, of the past. Its political structure is nothing if

not provisional. Even Franco’s regime, which has lasted longer than any

other since 1808 (it has beaten the record of the Canovas era 1875–97),

is patently temporary. Its future is so undetermined that even the

restoration of hereditary monarchy can be seriously considered as a

political prospect. Spain’s problems have been obvious to every

intelligent observer since the eighteenth century. A variety of

solutions have been proposed and occasionally applied. The point is that

all of them have failed. Spain has not by any means stood still. By its

own standards the economic and social changes of the nineteenth century

were substantial, and anyone who has watched the country’s evolution in

the past fifteen years knows how unrealistic it is to think of it as

essentially the same as in 1936. (An Aragonese pueblo demonstrates this

very clearly, if only in the increase of local tractors from two to

thirty-two, of motor vehicles from three to sixty-eight, of bank

branches from nought to six.) Nevertheless the fundamental economic and

social problems of the country remain unresolved, and the gap between it

and more developed (or more fundamentally transformed) European states

remains.

Raymond Carr, whose remarkable book probably supersedes all other

histories of nineteenth — and twentieth-century Spain for the time

being,[14] formulates the problem as that of the failure of Spanish

liberalism; that is to say of an essentially capitalist economic

development, a bourgeois-parliamentary political system, and a culture

and intellectual development of the familiar western kind. It might be

equally well, and perhaps more profitably, formulated as that of the

failure of Spanish social revolution. For if, as Carr admits, liberalism

never had serious chances of success, social revolution was, perhaps for

this reason, a much more serious prospect. Whatever we may think of the

upheavals of the Napoleonic period, the 1830s (which Carr analyzes with

particular brilliance), of 1854–6 or 1868–74, there can be no denying

that social revolution actually broke out in 1931–6, that it did so

without any significant assistance from the international situation, and

that the case is practically unique in western Europe since 1848.

Yet it failed; and not only, or even primarily because of the foreign

aid given to its enemies. One would not wish to underestimate the

importance of Italian and German aid or Anglo-French ‘non-intervention’

in the Civil War, the greater single-mindedness of Axis than of Soviet

support, or the remarkable military achievements of the Republic, which

Carr rightly recognizes. It is quite conceivable that, given a different

international configuration, the Republic could have won. But it is

equally undeniable that the Civil War was a double struggle against

armed counter-revolution and the gigantic, and in the last analysis

fatal, internal weaknesses of revolution. Successful revolutions, from

the French Jacobins to the Vietnamese, have shown a capacity to win

against equally long or even longer odds. The Spanish Republic did not.

There is no great mystery about the failure of Spanish liberalism,

though so much of the nineteenth-century history of the country and of

its basic social and economic situation is too little known for

excessively confident analysis. ‘The changes in the classic agricultural

structure of Spain between 1750 and 1850 were achieved by a

rearrangement of the traditional economy, by its expansion in space, not

by any fundamental change’ (p. 29). (Carr’s explanation that poverty of

soil and capital resources made this inevitable, is not entirely

convincing.) What it amounted to was that Spain maintained a rapidly

growing population, not by industrial and agricultural revolution, but

by a vast increase in the extensive cultivation of cereals, which in

time exhausted the soil and turned inland Spain into an even more

impoverished semi-desert than it already was. Logically, the politics of

agricultural inefficiency gave way to those of peasant revolution. ‘In

the nineties politicians were bullied by the powerfully organized wheat

interest; in the twentieth century they were alarmed by the threat of

revolution on the great estates.’ The alternative, intensive cash crops

for export (e.g. oranges) was not generally applicable without

prohibitively costly investment, perhaps not even with it; though Carr

seems ultra-sceptical of the possibilities of irrigation, though less so

of afforestation. Spanish industry was a marginal phenomenon,

uncompetitive on the world market, and therefore dependent on the feeble

domestic market and (notably in the case of Catalonia) the relics of the

empire. It was liberal Barcelona which resisted Cuban independence most

ferociously, since 60 per cent of its exports went there. The Catalan

and Basque bourgeoisie were not an adequate basis for Spanish

capitalism. As Vilar has shown, the Catalan businessmen failed to

capture the direction of the national economic policy, and therefore

retreated into the defensive posture of autonomism, which the Republic

eventually conceded to them and the Basques.

Under these circumstances the economic and social basis of liberalism

and its political striking-force, were feeble. As in so many

underdeveloped countries, there were two active forces in politics: the

urban petty-bourgeoisie, standing in the shadow of the urban plebs, and

the army, an institution for furthering the careers of energetic members

of the same stratum, and a militant trade union for the most powerfully

organized sector of the white-collar unemployed, who had to look to the

state because the economy could not employ them. The ‘pronunciamento’, a

curious Iberian invention whose rituals became highly traditional,

replaced liberal politics in the first half of the nineteenth century.

In the second half it became ‘a speculative business enterprise for

generals’ and in the twentieth century it ceased to have any connection

with liberalism.

Revolutions began with a pronunciamento or with what Carr calls the

‘primitive provincial revolution’ — plebeian risings spreading from town

to town by contagion — or both. The fighting poor were essential, but

perilous. Local notables, not to mention national ones, retreated from

the ever-present danger of social revolution into the ‘committee stage’,

when local power passed to juntas of notables with an optional

representative or two of the people, while the national government

collapsed. ‘The final stage was the reimposition, by a ministry that

“represented” the revolution, of central government control.’ Kiernan’s

monograph on 1854 describes and explains this process in full

detail.[15] Of course in the nineteenth century a proletariat barely

existed outside Barcelona, which consequently became the classical

revolutionary city of western Europe. The peasantry long remained

politically ineffective, or Carlist, i.e. attached to ultra-reactionary

politicians and hostile on principle to the towns.

Spanish liberalism was thus squeezed into the narrow space of manoeuvre

between the ‘primitive revolution’, without which nothing would change,

and the need to damp it down almost immediately. It was not surprising

that a vehicle obliged to brake almost as soon as the foot hit the

accelerator, could not get very far. The best hope of the bourgeois

moderates was to put some regime in power which would allow the forces

of capitalist development to develop; but they never developed enough.

Their most usual achievement was to find some formula which neutralized

social revolution or the ultra-reactionaries for a while by the

combination of at least two of the three forces of ‘official’ politics:

the army, the crown and the ‘official’ parties. As Carr shows, this was

the pattern of Spanish politics: army plus politicians in the 1840s,

crown plus politicians after 1875, army plus crown under Primo de Rivera

in the 1920s, and a collapse of the crown when it alienated the other

two, as in 1854, 1868 and 1931. When there was no crown there had to be

an ‘ad hoc military dictatorship’.

Yet Franco is not simply the successor of Alfonso. For in the twentieth

century the forces of social revolution grew stronger than they had been

in the nineteenth, because revolution retained its ‘primitive’ assets

while acquiring two new and formidable assets: peasant revolution and

the labour movement. It is their failure which poses the major problem

of Spanish history and may perhaps throw light on a number of other

underdeveloped countries. That failure was due to the anarchists.

This does not mean that the remarkable ineffectiveness of the Spanish

revolution is due merely to the historic accident that Spain was

colonized by Bakunin more than by Marx. (Even this is not quite an

accident. It is characteristic of the cultural isolation of

underdeveloped countries in the nineteenth century that so often ideas

which were unimportant in the wider world became immensely influential

there, like the philosophy of a certain Krause in Spain, or the politics

of August Comte in Mexico and Brazil.) The facts of Spanish geography

and history are against a nationally coordinated movement, but countries

with at least as much regional and more national diversity have achieved

one, like Yugoslavia. The self-contained universe of the Spanish pueblo

long made national changes the result of periodic plebiscites by direct

action of its municipalities. But other countries also know the

phenomenon of extreme localism, for instance Italy. All the Spanish

revolutions, as Carr shows, had an archaic house-style, irrespective of

the ideological labels they brandished. It is doubtful whether ‘Belmonte

de los Caballeros’ an Aragonese pueblo, would have behaved differently

in 1931–6 had it been organized by the CNT rather than by the socialist

UGT. Anarchism succeeded so well, because it was content to provide a

mere label for the traditional political habits of revolutionary

Spaniards. Yet political movements are not obliged to accept the

historic characteristics of their environment, though they will be

ineffective if they pay no attention to them. Anarchism was a disaster

because it made no attempt to change the style of primitive Spanish

revolt, and deliberately reinforced it.

It legitimized the traditional impotence of the poor. It turned

politics, which even in its revolutionary form is a practical activity,

into a form of moral gymnastics, a display of individual or collective

devotion, self-sacrifice, heroism or self-improvement which justified

its failure to achieve any concrete results by the argument that only

revolution was worth fighting for, and its failure in revolution by the

argument that anything which involved organization and discipline did

not deserve the name. Spanish anarchism is a profoundly moving spectacle

for the student of popular religion — it was really a form of secular

millennialism — but not, alas, for the student of politics. It threw

away political chances with a marvellously blind persistence. The

attempts to steer it into a less suicidal course succeeded too late,

though they were enough to defeat the generals’ rising in 1936. Even

then, they succeeded incompletely. The noble gunman Durruti, who

symbolized both the ideal of the anarchist militant and conversion to

the Organization and discipline of real war, was probably killed by one

of his own purist comrades.

This is not to deny the remarkable achievement of Spanish anarchism

which was to create a working-class movement that remained genuinely

revolutionary. Social democratic and in recent years even communist

trade unions have rarely been able to escape either schizophrenia or

betrayal of their socialist convictions, since for practical purposes —

i.e. when acting as trade union militants or leaders — they must usually

act on the assumption that the capitalist system is permanent. The CNT

did not, though this did not make it a particularly effective body for

trade unionist purposes, and on the whole it lost ground to the

socialist UGT from the trienio bolchevique of 1918–20 till after the

outbreak of the Civil War, except where the force of anarchist gunmen

and long tradition kept rivals out of the field, as in Catalonia and

Aragon. Still, Spanish workers as well as peasants remained

revolutionary and acted accordingly when the occasion arose. True, they

were not the only ones to retain the reflex of insurrection. In several

other countries workers brought up in the communist tradition, or in

that of maximalist socialism, reacted in a similiar way when nobody

stopped them, and it was not until the middle 1930s that this reflex was

actively discouraged in the international communist movement

Again, neither the Spanish socialists nor the communists can be

acquitted of responsibility for the failure of the Spanish revolution.

The communists were fettered by the extreme sectarianism of the

International’s policy in 1928–34, at the very moment when the fall of

the monarchy in 1931 opened up possibilities of strategies of alliance

which they were not permitted (and probably unwilling) to use until some

years later. Whether their weakness would have allowed them to use these

effectively at the time is another matter. The socialists veered from

opportunism to a strategically blind maximalism after 1934, which served

to strengthen the right rather than to unite the left. Since they were

visibly much more dangerous to the right than the anarchists (who were

never more than a routine police problem), both because they were better

organized and because they were in republican governments, the backlash

of reaction was much more serious.

Nevertheless, the anarchists cannot escape major responsibility.[16]

Theirs was the basic tradition of labour in most parts of the republic

which survived the initial military rising, and such deeply rooted

traditions are difficult to change. Moreover, theirs was potentially

still the majority movement of the left in the republic. They were in no

position to ‘make’ the revolution of which they dreamed. But when the

decision of the Popular Front government to resist the military rising

by all means, including arming the people, turned a situation of social

ferment into a revolution, they were its chief initial beneficiaries.

There seems little doubt about the initial preponderance of the

anarcho-syndicalists in the armed militia, and none about their

domination of the great process of ‘sovietization’ (in the original

sense of the word) in Catalonia, Aragon and the Mediterranean coast

which (with Madrid) formed the core of the republic.

The anarchists thus shaped or formulated the revolution which the

generals had risen to prevent, but had in fact provoked. But the war

against the generals remained to be fought, and they were incapable of

fighting it effectively either in the military or political sense. This

was evident to the great majority of foreign observers and volunteers,

especially in Catalonia and Aragon. There it proved impossible even to

get the sixty thousand rifles parading on the city streets, let alone

the available machine-guns and tanks, to the under-strength and

under-equipped units which actually went to the crucial Aragon front.

The inefficacy of the anarchist way of fighting the war has recently

been doubted by a new school of libertarian historians (including the

formidable intellect of Noam Chomsky), reluctant to admit that the

communists had the only practical and effective policy for this purpose,

and that their rapidly growing influence reflected this fact.

Unfortunately it cannot be denied. And the war had to be won, because

without this victory the Spanish revolution, however inspiring and

perhaps even workable, would merely turn into yet another episode of

heroic defeat, like the Paris Commune. And this is what actually

happened. The communists, whose policy was the one which could have won

the war, gained strength too late and never satisfactorily overcame the

handicap of their original lack of mass support.

For the student of politics in general, Spain may merely be a salutary

warning against libertarian gestures (with or without pistols and

dynamite), and against the sort of people who, like Ferrer, boasted that

‘plutot qu’un revolutionnaire je suis un revoke’. For the historian, the

abnormal strength of anarchism, or the ineffective ‘primitive’

revolutionism still needs some explanation. Was it due to the proverbial

neglect of the peasantry by the marxists of western Europe, which left

so much of the countryside to the Bakuninists? Was it the persistence of

small-scale industry and the pre-industrial sub-proletariat? These

explanations are not entirely satisfactory. Was it the isolation of

Spain, which saved Spanish libertarianism from the crisis of 1914–20

which bankrupted it in France and Italy, thus leaving the way open for

communist mass movements? Was it the curious absence of intellectuals

from the Spanish labour movement, so unusual in twentieth-century

underdeveloped countries? Intellectuals were democrats, republicans,

cultural populists, perhaps above all anti-clericals, and active enough

in some phases of opposition: but few of them were socialists and

virtually none anarchists. (Their role seems in any case to have been

limited — even educated Spain, as Carr says rightly, was not a reading

nation — and the cafe-table or Ateneo was not, except in Madrid, a form

of nation-wide political action.) At all events the leadership of

Spanish revolutionary movements suffered from their absence. At present

we cannot answer these questions except by speculation.

We can, however, place the spontaneous revolutionism of Spain in a wider

context, and recent writers like Malefakis[17] have begun to do so.

Social revolutions are not made: they occur and develop. To this extent

the metaphors of military organization, strategy and tactics, which are

so often applied to them both by marxists and their adversaries, can be

actively misleading. However, they cannot succeed without establishing

the capacity of a national army or government, i.e. to exercise

effective national coordination and direction. Where this is totally

absent, what might otherwise have turned into a social revolution may be

no more than a nationwide aggregate of waves of local social unrest (as

in Peru 1960–3), or it may collapse into an anarchic era of mutual

massacre (as in Colombia in the years after 1948). This is the crux of

the marxist critique of anarchism as a political strategy, whether such

a belief in the virtues of spontaneous militancy at all times and places

is held by nominal Bakuninists or by other ideologists. Spontaneity can

bring down regimes, or at least make them unworkable, but can provide no

alternative suitable to any society more advanced than an archaic

self-sufficient peasantry, and even then only on the assumption that the

forces of the state and of modern economic life will simply go away and

leave the self-governing village community in peace. This is unlikely.

There are various ways in which a revolutionary party or movement can

establish itself as a potentially national regime before the actual

taking of power or during it. The Chinese, Vietnamese and Yugoslav

Communist Parties were able to do so in the course of a prolonged

guerrilla war, from which they emerged as the state power, but on the

evidence of our century this seems to be exceptional. In Russia a

brilliantly led Bolshevik Party succeeded in establishing itself as the

leader of the decisive political force — the working class in the

capital cities and a section of the armed forces — between February and

October 1917, and as the only effective contender for state power, which

it then exercised as soon as it had taken over the national centre of

government, defeating — admittedly with great difficulty and at great

cost — the counter-revolutionary armies and local or regional dissidence

which lacked this coordination. This was essentially the pattern of the

successful French revolutions between 1789 and 1848 which rested on the

capture of the capital city combined with the collapse of the old

government and the failure to establish an effective alternative

national centre of counter-revolution. When the provinces failed to fall

into line and an alternative counter-revolutionary government did

establish itself, as in 1870–1, the commune of Paris was doomed.

A revolution may establish itself over a longer period of apparently

complex and opaque conflict by the combination of a fairly stable class

alliance (under the hegemony of one social force) with certain strong

regional bases of power. Thus the Mexican revolution emerged as a stable

regime after ten years of murderous civil strife, thanks to the alliance

of what was to become the national bourgeoisie with the (subaltern)

urban working class, conquering the country from a stable power-base in

the north.[18] Within this framework the necessary concessions were made

to the revolutionary peasant areas and several virtually independent

warlords, a stable national regime being constructed step by step during

the twenty years or so after the Sonora base had established itself.

The most difficult situation for revolution is probably that in which it

is expected to grow out of reforming politics, rather than the initial

shock of insurrectionary crisis combined with mass mobilization. The

fall of the Spanish monarchy in 1931 was not the result of social

revolution, but rather the public ratification of a very general shift

of opinion among the political classes of Spain away from the monarchy.

The new Republicans might have been pushed decisively towards the left —

more specifically, towards agrarian revolution — by the pressure of the

masses. But at the time when they were most susceptible to and afraid of

it, in 1931, this did not occur. The moderate socialists may or may not

have wanted to organize it, but the communists and anarchists who

certainly did, failed in their attempt to do so. One cannot simply blame

them for this failure. There were both avoidable and — perhaps

predominantly — inevitable reasons why ‘CNT and communist recruiters in

general were so distant from the prevailing peasant mood that both

organizations remained primarily urban based even so late as 1936’

(Malefakis). The fact remains that ‘peasant rebellion became a

significant force after 1933, not in 1931, when it might have been

politically more efficacious’. And after 1933 it served to mobilize

reaction as effectively as — in the long run more effectively than — the

forces of revolution. The Spanish revolution was unable to exploit the

historical moment when most successful revolutions establish their

hegemony: the spell of time during which its potential or actual enemies

are demoralized, disorganized and uncertain what to do.

When it broke out it met a mobilized enemy. Perhaps this was inevitable.

But it also faced the battle for survival, which it proved incapable of

winning. Probably this was not inevitable. And so we remember it,

especially those of us to whose lives it belongs, as a marvellous dream

of what might have been, an epic of heroism, the Iliad of those who were

young in the 1930s. But unless we think of revolutions merely as a

series of dreams and epics, the time for analysis must succeed that of

heroic memories.

(1966)

Reflections on Anarchism

The present revival of interest in anarchism is a curious and at first

sight unexpected phenomenon. Even ten years ago it would have seemed in

the highest degree unlikely. At that time anarchism, both as a movement

and as an ideology, looked like a chapter in the development of the

modern revolutionary and labour movements that had been definitely

closed.

As a movement it seemed to belong to the pre-industrial period, and in

any case to the era before the first world war and the October

revolution, except in Spain, where it can hardly be said to have

survived the Civil War of 1936–9. One might say that it disappeared with

the kings and emperors whom its militants had so often tried to

assassinate. Nothing seemed to be able to halt, or even to slow down,

its rapid and inevitable decline, even in those parts of the world in

which it had once constituted a major political force — in France,

Italy, Latin America. A careful searcher, who knew where to look, might

still discover some anarchists even in the 1950s, and very many more

ex-anarchists, easily recognizable by such signs as an interest in the

poet Shelley. (It is characteristic that this most romantic school of

revolutionaries has been more loyal than anyone else, including the

literary critics of his own country, to the most revolutionary among

English romantic poets.) When I tried to make contact, about this time,

with activists in the Spanish anarchist underground in Paris, I was

given a rendezvous at a cafe in Montmartre, by the Place Blanche, and

somehow this reminder of a long-lost era of bohemians, rebels and

avant-garde seemed only too characteristic.

As an ideology, anarchism did not decline so dramatically because it had

never had anything like as much success, at least among intellectuals

who are the social stratum most interested in ideas. There have probably

always been eminent figures in the world of culture who called

themselves anarchists (except, curiously enough, in Spain), but most of

them seem to have been artists in the wider — or like Pissarro and

Signac, the narrower — sense of the word. In any case, anarchism never

had an attraction comparable to, say marxism, for intellectuals even

before the October revolution. With the exception of Kropotkin, it is

not easy to think of an anarchist theorist who could be read with real

interest by non-anarchists. There seemed, indeed, no real intellectual

room for anarchist theory. The belief in the libertarian communism of

self-governing cooperatives as the final aim of revolutionaries, it

shared with marxism. The old Utopian socialists had thought more deeply

and concretely about the nature of such communities than most

anarchists. Even the strongest point in the anarchists’ intellectual

armoury, their awareness of the dangers of dictatorship and bureaucracy

implicit in marxism, was not peculiar to them. This type of critique was

made with equal effect and greater intellectual sophistication both by

‘unofficial’ marxists and by opponents of all kinds of socialism.

In brief, the main appeal of anarchism was emotional and not

intellectual. That appeal was not negligible. Everyone who has ever

studied, or had anything to do with the real anarchist movement, has

been deeply moved by the idealism, the heroism, the sacrifice, the

saintliness which it so often produced, side by side with the brutality

of the Ukrainian Makhnovshchina or the dedicated gunmen and

church-burners of Spain. The very extremism of the anarchist rejection

of state and organization, the totality of their commitment to the

overthrow of the present society, could not but arouse admiration;

except perhaps among those who had to be active in politics by the side

of the anarchists, and found them almost impossible to work with. It is

suitable that Spain, the country of Don Quixote, should have been their

last fortress.

The most touching epitaph I have heard on an anarchist terrorist, killed

a few years ago by the police in Catalonia, was spoken by one of his

comrades, without any sense of irony: ‘When we were young, and the

Republic was founded, we were knightly but also spiritual. We have grown

older, but not he. He was a guerrillero by instinct. Yes, he was one of

the Quixotes who come out of Spain.’

Admirable, but hopeless, It was almost certainly the monumental

ineffectiveness of anarchism which, for most people of my generation —

the one which came to maturity in the years of the Spanish Civil War —

determined our rejection of it. I still recall in the very earliest days

of that war, the small town of Puigcerda in the Pyrenees, a little

revolutionary republic, filled with free men and women, guns and an

immensity of discussion. A few trucks stood in the plaza. They were for

the war. When anyone felt like going to fight on the Aragonese front, he

went to the trucks. When a truck was full, it went to the front.

Presumably, when the volunteers wanted to come back, they came back. The

phrase C’est magnifique, mais ce nest pas la guerre should have been

invented for such a situation. It was marvellous, but the main effect of

this experience on me was, that it took me twenty years before I was

prepared to see Spanish anarchism as anything but a tragic farce.

It was much more than this. And yet, no amount of sympathy can alter the

fact that anarchism as a revolutionary movement has failed, that it has

almost been designed for failure.

As Gerald Brenan, the author of the best book on modern Spain, has put

it: a single strike of (socialist) miners in the Asturias shook the

Spanish government more than seventy years of massive anarchist

revolutionary activity, which presented little more than a routine

police problem. (Indeed, subsequent research has shown that in the era

of maximum bomb-throwing in Barcelona, there were probably not a hundred

policemen looking after public order in that city, and their number was

not notably reinforced.) The ineffectiveness of anarchist revolutionary

activities could be documented at length, and for all countries in which

this ideology played an important role in politics. This is not the

place for such a documentation. My point is simply to explain why the

revival of interest in anarchism today seems so unexpected, surprising

and — if I am to speak frankly — unjustified.

Unjustified, but not inexplicable. There are two powerful reasons which

explain the vogue for anarchism: the crisis of the world communist

movement after Stalin’s death and the rise of revolutionary discontent

among students and intellectuals, at a time when objective historical

factors in the developed countries do not make revolution appear very

probable.

For most revolutionaries the crisis of communism is essentially that of

the USSR and the regimes founded under its auspices in eastern Europe;

that is to say of socialist systems as understood in the years between

the October revolution and the fall of Hitler. Two aspects of these

regimes now seemed more vulnerable to the traditional anarchist critique

than before 1945, because the October revolution was no longer the only

successful revolution made by communists, the USSR was no longer

isolated, weak and threatened with destruction, and because the two most

powerful arguments for the USSR — its immunity to the economic crisis of

1929 and its resistance to fascism — lost their force after 1945.

Stalinism, that hypertrophy of the bureaucratized dictatorial state,

seemed to justify the Bakuninite argument that the dictatorship of the

proletariat would inevitably become simple dictatorship, and that

socialism could not be constructed on such a basis. At the same time the

removal of the worst excesses of Stalinism made it clear that even

without purges and labour camps the kind of socialism introduced in the

USSR was very far from what most socialists had had in mind before 1917,

and the major objectives of that country’s policy, rapid economic

growth, technological and scientific development, national security

etc., had no special connections with socialism, democracy or freedom.

Backward nations might see in the USSR a model of how to escape from

their backwardness, and might conclude from its experience and from

their own that the methods of economic development pioneered and

advocated by capitalism did not work in their conditions, whereas social

revolution followed by central planning did, but the main object was

‘development’. Socialism was the means to it and not the end. Developed

nations, which already enjoyed the material level of production to which

the USSR still aspired, and in many cases far more freedom and cultural

variety for their citizens, could hardly take it as their model, and

when they did (as in Czechoslovakia and the gdr) the results were

distinctly disappointing.

Here again it seemed reasonable to conclude that this was not the way to

build socialism. Extremist critics — and they became increasingly

numerous — concluded that it was not socialism at all, however distorted

or degenerate. The anarchists were among those revolutionaries who had

always held this view, and their ideas therefore became more attractive.

All the more so as the crucial argument of the 1917–45 period, that

Soviet Russia however imperfect, was the only successful revolutionary

regime and the essential basis for the success of revolution elsewhere,

sounded much less convincing in the 1950s and hardly convincing at all

in the 1960s.

The second and more powerful reason for the vogue of anarchism has

nothing to do with the USSR, except in so far as it was fairly clear

after 1945 that its government did not encourage revolutionary seizures

of power in other countries. It arose out of the predicament of

revolutionaries in non-revolutionary situations. As in the years before

1914, so in the 1950s and early 1960s western capitalism was stable and

looked like remaining stable. The most powerful argument of classic

marxist analysis, the historic inevitability of proletarian revolution,

therefore lost its force; at least in the developed countries. But if

history was not likely to bring revolution nearer, how would it come

about?

Both before 1914 and again in our time anarchism provided an apparent

answer. The very primitiveness of its theory became an asset. Revolution

would come because revolutionaries wanted it with such passion, and

undertook acts of revolt constantly, one of which would, sooner or

later, turn out to be the spark which would set the world on fire. The

appeal of this simple belief lay not in its more sophisticated

formulations, though such extreme voluntarism could be given a

philosophical basis (the pre-1914 anarchists often tended to admire

Nietzsche as well as Stirner) or founded on social psychology as with

Sorel. (It is a not altogether accidental irony of history that such

theoretical justifications of anarchist irrationalism were soon to be

adapted into theoretical justifications of fascism.) The strength of the

anarchist belief lay in the fact that there seemed to be no alternative

other than to give up the hope of revolution.

Of course neither before 1914 nor today were anarchists the only

revolutionary voluntarists. All revolutionaries must always believe in

the necessity of taking the initiative, the refusal to wait upon events

to make the revolution for them. At some times — as in the Kautsky era

of social democracy and the comparable era of postponed hope in the

orthodox communist movement of the 1950s and 1960s — a dose of

voluntarism is particularly salutary. Lenin was accused of Blanquism,

just as Guevara and Regis Debray have been, with somewhat greater

justification. At first sight such non-anarchist versions of the revolt

against ‘historic inevitability’ seem much the more attractive since

they do not deny the importance of objective factors in the making of

revolution, of organization, discipline, strategy and tactics.

Nevertheless, and paradoxically, the anarchists may today have an

occasional advantage over these more systematic revolutionaries. It has

recently become fairly clear that the analysis on which most intelligent

observers based their assessment of political prospects in the world

must be badly deficient. There is no other explanation for the fact that

several of the most dramatic and far-reaching developments in world

politics recently have been not merely unpredicted, but so unexpected as

to appear almost incredible at first sight. The events of May 1968 in

France are probably the most striking example. When rational analysis

and prediction leads so many astray, including even most marxists, the

irrational belief that anything is possible at any moment may seem to

have some advantages. After all, on 1 May 1968, not even in Peking or

Havana did anyone seriously expect that within a matter of days

barricades would rise in Paris, soon to be followed by the greatest

general strike in living memory. On the night of 9 May it was not only

the official communists who opposed the building of barricades, but a

good many of the Trotskyist and Maoist students also, for the apparently

sound reason that if the police really had orders to fire, the result

would be a brief but substantial massacre. Those who went ahead without

hesitation were the anarchists, the anarchizers, the situationnistes.

There are moments when simple revolutionary or Napoleonic phrases like

del’audace, encore de l’audace or on s’engage etpuis on voit work. This

was one of them. One might even say that this was an occasion when only

the blind chicken was in a position to find the grain of corn.

No doubt, statistically speaking, such moments are bound to be rare. The

failure of Latin American guerrilla movements and the death of Guevara

are reminders that it is not enough to want a revolution, however

passionately, or even to start guerrilla war. No doubt the limits of

anarchism became evident within a few days, even in Paris. Yet the fact

that once or twice pure voluntarism has produced results cannot be

denied. Inevitably it has increased the appeal of anarchism.

Anarchism is therefore today once again a political force. Probably it

has no mass basis outside the movement of students and intellectuals and

even within the movement it is influential rather as a persistent

current of ‘spontaneity’ and activism rather than through the relatively

few people who claim to be anarchists. The question is therefore once

again worth asking what is the value of the anarchist tradition today?

In terms of ideology, theory and programmes, that value remains

marginal. Anarchism is a critique of the dangers of authoritarianism and

bureaucracy in states, parties and movements, but this is primarily a

symptom that these dangers are widely recognized. If all anarchists had

disappeared from the face of the earth the discussion about these

problems would go on much as it does. Anarchism also suggests a solution

in terms of direct democracy and small self-governing groups, but I do

not think its own proposals for the future have so far been either very

valuable or very fully thought out. To mention only two considerations.

First, small self-governing direct democracies are unfortunately not

necessarily libertarian. They may indeed function only because they

establish a consensus so powerful that those who do not share it

voluntarily refrain from expressing their dissent; alternatively,

because those who do not share the prevailing view leave the community,

or are expelled. There is a good deal of information about the operation

of such small communities, which I have not seen realistically discussed

in anarchist literature. Second, both the nature of the modern social

economy and of modern scientific technology raise problems of

considerable complexity for those who see the future as a world of

self-governing small groups. These may not be insoluble, but

unfortunately they are certainly not solved by the simple call for the

abolition of the state and bureaucracy, nor by the suspicion of

technology and the natural sciences which so often goes with modern

anarchism.[19] It is possible to construct a theoretical model of

libertarian anarchism which will be compatible with modern scientific

technology, but unfortunately it will not be socialist. It will be much

closer to the views of Mr Goldwater and his economic adviser Professor

Milton Friedman of Chicago than to the views of Kropotkin. For (as

Bernard Shaw pointed out long ago in his pamphlet on the Impossibilities

of Anarchism), the extreme versions of individualist liberalism are

logically as anarchist as Bakunin.

It will be clear that in my view anarchism has no significant

contribution to socialist theory to make, though it is a useful critical

element. If socialists want theories about the present and the future,

they will still have to look elsewhere, to Marx and his followers, and

probably also to the earlier Utopian socialists, such as Fourier. To be

more precise: if anarchists want to make a significant contribution they

will have to do much more serious thinking than most of them have

recently done.

The contribution of anarchism to revolutionary strategy and tactics

cannot be so easily dismissed. It is true that anarchists are as

unlikely to make successful revolutions in the future as they have been

in the past. To adapt a phrase used by Bakunin of the peasantry: they

may be invaluable on the first day of a revolution, but they are almost

certain to be an obstacle on the second day. Nevertheless, historically

their insistence on spontaneity has much to teach us. For it is the

great weakness of revolutionaries brought up in any of the versions

derived from classical marxism, that they tend to think of revolutions

as occurring under conditions which can be specified in advance, as

things which can be, at least in outline, foreseen, planned and

organized. But in practice this is not so.

Or rather, most of the great revolutions which have occurred and

succeeded, have begun as ‘happenings’ rather than as planned

productions. Sometimes they have grown rapidly and unexpectedly out of

what looked like ordinary mass demonstrations, sometimes out of

resistance to the acts of their enemies, sometimes in other ways — but

rarely if ever did they take the form expected by organized

revolutionary movements, even when these had predicted the imminent

occurrence of revolution. That is why the test of greatness in

revolutionaries has always been their capacity to discover the new and

unexpected characteristics of revolutionary situations and to adapt

their tactics to them. Like the surfer, the revolutionary does not

create the waves on which he rides, but balances on them. Unlike the

surfer — and here serious revolutionary theory diverges from anarchist

practice — sooner or later he stops riding on the wave and must control

its direction and movement.

Anarchism has valuable lessons to teach, because it has — in practice

rather than in theory — been unusually sensitive to the spontaneous

elements in mass movements. Any large and disciplined movement can order

a strike or demonstration to take place, and if it is sufficiently large

and disciplined, it can make a reasonably impressive showing. Yet there

is all the difference between the CGT’s token general strike of 13 May

1968 and the ten millions who occupied their places of work a few days

later without a national directive. The very organizational feebleness

of anarchist and anarchizing movements has forced them to explore the

means of discovering or securing that spontaneous consensus among

militants and masses which produces action. (Admittedly it has also led

them to experiment with ineffective tactics such as individual or

small-group terrorism which can be practised without mobilizing any

masses and for which, incidentally, the organizational defects of

anarchism do not suit anarchists.)

The student movements of the past few years have been like anarchist

movements, at least in their early stages, in so far as they have

consisted not of mass organizations but of small groups of militants

mobilizing the masses of their fellow students from time to time. They

have been obliged to make themselves sensitive to the mood of these

masses, to the times and issues which will permit mass mobilization.

In the United States, for instance they belong to a primitive kind of

movement, and its weaknesses are evident — a lack of theory, of agreed

strategic perspectives, of quick tactical reaction on a national scale.

At the same time it is doubtful whether any other form of mobilization

could have created, maintained and developed so powerful a national

student movement in the United States in the 1960s. Quite certainly this

could not have bden done by the disciplined small groups of

revolutionaries in the old tradition — communist, Trotskyist or Maoist —

who constantly seek to impose their specific ideas and perspectives on

the masses and in doing so isolate themselves more often than they

mobilize them.

These are lessons to be learned not so much from the actual anarchists

of today whose practice is rarely impressive, as from a study of the

historic experience of anarchist movements. They are particularly

valuable in the present situation, in which new revolutionary movements

have often had to be built on and out of the ruins of the older ones.

For let us not be under any illusions. The impressive ‘new left’ of

recent years is admirable, but in many respects it is not only new, but

also a regression to an earlier weaker, less developed form of the

socialist movement, unwilling or unable to benefit from the major

achievements of the international working-class and revolutionary

movements in the century between the Communist Manifesto and the Cold

War.

Tactics derived from anarchist experience are a reflection of this

relative primitiveness and weakness, but in such circumstances they may

be the best ones to pursue for a time. The important thing is to know

when the limits of such tactics have been reached. What happened in

France in May 1968 was less like 1917 than like 1830 or 1848. It is

inspiring to discover that, in the developed countries of western

Europe, any kind of revolutionary situation, however momentary, is

possible once again. But it would be equally unwise to forget that 1848

is at the same time the great example of a successful spontaneous

European revolution, and of its rapid and unmitigated failure.

(1969)

[1] Of a small random sample of French communist MPS between the wars,

the Dictionnaire des Parlementaires Francais 1889–1940, gives the

following indications about their pre-communist past: Socialist 5;

‘Sillon’, then socialist 1; trade union activity (tendency unknown) 3;

libertarian 1; no pre-communist past 1.

[2] Bolshevising the Communist International, London, 1925.

[3] ‘The growth of discontent among the masses and of their resistance

to the attacks of the ruling classes and of imperialism have sharpened

the process of disintegration among socialist, anarchist and

anarcho-syndicalist organizations. In the most recent period the

recognition of the need for a united front with the communists has sunk

quite deep roots among rather wide strata of their rank and file. At the

same time the tendency for a direct entry into the ranks of the

revolutionary unions and communist parties has grown stronger

(especially in Cuba, Brazil, Paraguay). After the sixth World Congress

there has been a marked drop in the specific weight of

anarcho-syndicalism within the labour movements of South and Caribbean

America. In some countries the best elements of the anarcho-syndicalist

movement have joined the Communist Party, e.g. in Argentina, Brazil,

Paraguay and Cuba [...]. In other countries the weakening of

anarcho-syndicalist influence was accompanied by a strengthening of

socialist and reformist organizations (Argentina), the

“national-reformist parties” (Mexico, Cuba)’: Die Kommunistische

Internationale vor dem 7. Weltkongress, p. 472.

[4] I owe this point to Miss Jean Stubbs, who is preparing a doctoral

thesis on the Cuban tobacco workers.

[5] P.Spriano, Storia del Partito Comunista Italiano, vol. 1, p. 77.

[6] ‘Jahrbuch für Wirschaft, Politik und Arbeiterbewegung’ (Hamburg),

1922–3, pp. 247, 250, 481–2.

[7] Decisions of the Third Congress of the Communist International,

London, 1921, p. 10.

[8] Protokoll, p. 510.

[9] Fourth Congress of the Communist International. Abridged Report.

London, 1923, p. 18.

[10] Cf. Manuilsky. ‘We think, for instance, that so-called Trotskyism

has a great deal in common with individualistic Proudhonism [... ] It is

not by accident that Rosmer and Monatte, in their new organ directed

against the Communist Party, resuscitate theoretically the ideas of the

old revolutionary syndicalism, mixed with a defence of Russian

Trotskyism’: The Communist International, English edition, no. 10, new

series, p. 58.

[11] ‘As to the Anarchists, a group whose influence was insignificant to

start with, they now definitely disintegrated into minute groups, some

of which merged with criminal elements, thieves and provocateurs, the

dregs of society; others became expropriators “by conviction”, robbing

the peasants and small townsfolk, and appropriating the premises and

funds of workers’ clubs; while others still openly went over to the camp

of the counter-revolutionaries, and devoted themselves to feathering

their own nests as menials of the bourgeoisie. They were all opposed to

authority of any kind, particularly and especially to the revolutionary

authority of the workers and peasants, for they knew that a

revolutionary government would not allow them to rob the people and

steal public property’, p. 203.

[12]

A. Lozovsky, Marx and the Trade Unions, London, 1935 (first edn. 1933),

pp. 35h5 and especially pp. 146–54.

[13] Op. cit., p. 10.

[14] Raymond Carr, Spain 1808–1939, Oxford, 1966.

[15]

V. G. Kiernan, The Revolution of 1854 in Spanish History, Oxford,

1966.

[16] They can be criticized not only for lending themselves to the

irrelevant vendettas of Stalin’s secret police, but for discouraging not

merely the unpopular or counterproductive excesses of the revolution,

but the revolution itself, whose existence they preferred not to stress

in their propaganda. But the basic point is that they fought to win the

war and that without victory the revolution was dead anyway. Had the

republic survived, there might be more point to criticisms of their

policy which, alas, remain academic.

[17]

E. Malefakis, Agrarian Reform and Peasant Revolution in Spain, New

Haven and London, 1970. This book ought to be required reading for

all students of the Spanish revolution.

[18] From the days of Obregon until 1934 the presidents came almost

without exception from the state of Sonora.

[19] An illustration of this complexity may be given from the history of

anarchism. I take it from J. Martinez Alier’s valuable study of landless

labourers in Andalusia in 1964–5. From the author’s careful questioning

it is clear that the landless labourers of Cordova, traditionally the

mass basis of Spanish rural anarchism, have not changed their ideas

since 1936 — except in one respect. The social and economic activities

of even the Franco regime have convinced them that the state cannot

simply be rejected, but has some positive functions. This may help to

explain why they no longer seem to be anarchists.