đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș eric-hayes-imagining-the-future.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:35:57. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Imagining the Future
Author: Eric Hayes
Date: 20 October 2011
Language: en
Topics: participatory economics, Irish Anarchist Review
Source: Retrieved on 24th December 2021 from http://www.wsm.ie/c/introduction-participatory-economics
Notes: Published in the Irish Anarchist Review Issue 4.

Eric Hayes

Imagining the Future

In the last issue we had a missive from the future. It told us of the

great changes in the post-revolutionary anarchist world. In this article

of the future society series, I will focus solely upon an anarchist

vision of a future economy. This is called participatory economics,

often abbreviated parecon, a classless economic system proposed

primarily by activist and political theorist Michael Albert and, among

others, economist Robin Hahnel. The model was developed through the 70s

and 80s and the first exclusively parecon books were published in 1991.

Many of their early writings concentrated on what they perceived as

flaws in Marxist and Marxist-Leninist theory.

Unfortunately, for all its emphasis on class analysis, Marxism blinded

many fighting against the economics of competition and greed to

important antagonisms between the working class and the new,

professional managerial class – or as Albert and Hahnel termed it, the

coordinator class. While consumer and worker councils are familiar to

libertarian socialists, as are analyses of the poly-labelled managerial

class, Parecon’s round-by-round participatory planning, balanced

job-complexes, and a remunerative system not based upon output are less

familiar.

These institutions are designed to create a classless libertarian

socialist alternative where everyone will have the opportunity to

develop all of their creative capacities. To quote:

“We recognize that council communists, syndicalists, anarchists, and

guild socialists fell short of spelling out a coherent, theoretical

model explaining how such a system could work.”

They continue:

“Our predecessors frequently provided stirring comparisons of the

advantages of a libertarian, non-market, socialist alternative compared

to capitalism and authoritarian planning. But all too often they failed

to respond to difficult questions about how necessary decisions would be

made, why their procedures would yield a coherent plan, or why the

outcome would be efficient.”

The aims and values of participatory economics will be familiar to many

and are:

Solidarity

An economy should not produce anti-social behaviour or a lack of

empathy. This should not be controversial, so I won’t overdo it. I think

most people would agree with more solidarity from an economy, not less!

So our economy should actively promote solidarity, not only attempt to

provide structures for its expression.

Diversity

This essentially means valuing options – not narrowing options. Instead

of homogeneity we should have diversity. We can all benefit vicariously

from other peoples diverse activities, and there is not just one correct

way of doing things. People should have many choices.

Equity

There is no justification, neither in terms of efficiency or morality,

for remuneration of property, land or machines. It is theft from

everyone else. Power should not be remunerated for similar reasons. The

self-serving myth that such inequalities are justified based upon merit

are addressed in the words of Edward Bellamy in the 19^(th) Century:

“You may set it down as a rule that the rich, the possessors of great

wealth, had no moral right to it as based upon desert, for either their

fortunes belonged to the class of inherited wealth, or else, when

accumulated in a lifetime, necessarily represented chiefly the product

of others, more or less forcibly or fraudulently obtained.”

But output should also not be remunerated. Should we reward genetic

endowment? Should we reward better tools? Or more desired products? Well

no, it is also unfair. If two people are cutting corn with the same

tools and level of effort there is no reason, neither on the basis of

efficiency or morality, to reward them differently. It would reward a

host of things that people have no control over. So if we reward for

effort, then the coal-miner earns more, much more, than a manager in an

office, or say, a worker in a publishing house. If we are to reward

equitably, we should reward only effort at socially valued labour.

The way a parecon works, income differentials beyond average income

could not disrupt solidarity or self-management. But what if you’re sick

or if you can’t work? The answer is that a parecon is a mixed economy

which has distribution according to need for calamities, health, and

other related similar facets of consumption such as say, education,

housing, special needs, and so on.

Self-management

People should have an input into decisions in proportion that they are

affected by them. This doesn’t mean using the same system, for example,

one-person one vote, consensus or dictatorial, all the time. Rather, the

method is decided depending on the nature of the decisions.

Say, if someone puts up a picture of a family member in their workspace,

who decides? This is a dictatorial decision for that person. But, how

about a ghetto blaster where everyone can hear it nearby? Well those

people affected then decide. If we don’t do this then one person will

have more of a say than another person. I am the world’s foremost expert

on my own preferences, so we should each be responsible for expressing

them.

Efficiency

Many leftists are afraid of this word, but stripped from its capitalist

context, efficiency just means not wasting things. Under capitalism, it

means not wasting things capitalists desire. It doesn’t matter that you

destroy people’s lives, or that you pollute the environment. Efficiency

is a word whose meaning depends on the values and aims of the people

using the word. It is good not to waste things when producing socially

valued goods and services. In this context efficiency incorporates

environmental responsibility, and is in accord with our values.

These values are attained through the following institutions:

Worker and Consumer Councils (WCs and CCs)

An economy is a mixture of ingredients to fulfil production,

consumption, and allocation. Instead of money or power dictating the use

of resources, ordinary people would deliberate in relatively small

councils in order to decide what is best for their community.

This means democratic groups, called worker and consumer councils, using

self-managerial methods for decision-making. Say we start with

neighbourhood groups. Each is part of a bigger community, and larger

council, which will represent the councils within, when choices in one

affect more than just their members. Everyone has a say in services and

goods according to the impact on them through this federated system of

nested WCs and CCs. This ensures that power doesn’t come down from the

top but is nested up from the bottom: from the neighbourhood, to the

ward, city, county, province, continent and so on, with personal and

public consumption and production being addressed as appropriate.

Personal consumption is purely private and anonymous and can even be

transferred to a different council from where you live if you prefer.

While a type of credit card technology can aid consumption and updating.

Balanced Job Complexes (BJCs)

All economies need people to do work, and all workplaces tend to

organise this work into bundles of tasks we commonly refer to as “jobs”.

In a class-ridden society, jobs are organised to maintain a hierarchical

structure. People towards the top of the hierarchy (the coordinator

class) will have jobs composed of tasks that are empowering whilst those

towards the bottom of the hierarchy (the working class) have jobs made

up of dis-empowering tasks.

This corporate division of labour is an institutional feature found in

both capitalist and coordinator economies. A feature that systematically

maintains workplace hierarchy whilst undermining self-management through

a monopoly on empowering labour. If we want everyone to have an equal

opportunity to participate in economic decision-making, and that a

formal right to participate in meetings translates into an effective

right to participate; does this not require balancing work with

empowerment?

Parecon rejects the corporate division of labour as incompatible with

self-management. But what is the alternative? Parecon says:

“let’s make each job comparable to all others in its quality of life and

even more importantly in its empowerment effect ... From a corporate

division of labour that enshrines a coordinator class above workers, we

move to a classless division of labour that elevates all workers to

their fullest potentials.”

This classlessness is achieved with the creation of a new institutional

feature called “balanced job complexes”, meaning jobs are re-designed

throughout the economy so that they are balanced between, on the one

hand, skilled and design work, and, on the other, the physical, less

desirable and less empowering work. The education system is changed to

democratise access to expertise, information and training, and integrate

this with the system of production itself.

It should be noted that each individual’s job complex will contain a

very few tasks and, of course, there is a division of labour. People

would still be trained and educated to be doctors or engineers say.

However, nobody’s mixture of tasks will be significantly more empowering

than others, or significantly more desirable than others. The economy

would also have delegation (e.g., heads of work teams). But not people

who are always the order givers and others who are always the order

takers. Each person will experience both being in authority and being

under another’s authority in different situations and at different

times.

Job complexes are not balanced by a national bureaucracy but through

each WC balancing committee, just as they have an effort rating

committee. The time any individual spends on this committee is treated

as one task in their job complex. Balancing is not onerous and could be

done once a year. There is no outside agent who oversees this operation

with power to dictate or veto outcomes.

Remuneration for Effort and Sacrifice

In a parecon, private ownership of economic institutions no longer

exists. Effort and sacrifice is proposed as a morally sound alternative

criteria for remuneration: “If you work longer, and you do it

effectively, you are entitled to more of the social product. If you work

more intensely, to socially useful ends, again you are entitled to more

social product. If you work at a more onerous, dangerous or boring, but

still socially warranted, tasks; again, you are entitled to more social

product.”

But what about: “From each according to ability, to each according to

need.”? Albert and Hahnel think that this maxim has more to do with

compassion and humanity than economic justice and it “is our humanity

that compels us to provide for those in need”. In a parecon, those

unable to work receive a socially average income of items and services

of their choosing (of course those with special needs would get more,

such as medicine). In fact, everyone gets this socially average income.

So in a parecon, the criteria for remuneration are (1) how many hours

you work, (2) the intensity of your work effort (3) the onerous

circumstances or harshness of the type of work you do. Yet (3) is not

really relevant, due to the job balancing of BJCs. While (2),

remuneration, is best assessed by one’s work colleagues and peers,

there’s no one right way to do this. One workplace might assume everyone

is at average by default and just remunerate according to hours worked,

with deviations from it registered in only special cases, and only with

a minimal and few grades of ratings. Indeed while Albert is loath to

blueprint, this is the expectation he believes most workplaces would

take, and indeed favours.

Remuneration would also need to be regulated in terms of the total

compensation one workplace receives with what others receive. In effect,

this sets an objective standard for the assignment of effort ratings

while productive resources are taken into account. We will touch upon

the participatory planning process later where the socially planned

quota of the WC is set, in which, of course, the council participates

proportionally.

However, let’s look back at the slogan: “From each according to ability,

to each according to need.” The Wikipedia article, quoting Marx, claims

that the slogan, when used in this context, is originally Marxian, and

is meant for a society without onerous labour: “Marx delineated the

specific conditions under which such a creed would be applicable—a

society where technology and social organization had substantially

eliminated the need for physical labor in the production of things,

where “labor has become not only a means of life but life’s prime want”.

Marx explained that, in such a society, everyone is motivated to work

for the good of society because work would have become a pleasurable and

creative activity. Now unless we can automate every task and job, it is

perhaps unlikely we could ever remove all onerous, rote, and

dis-empowering labour. If that is the case – and we wish to achieve

classlessness and not violate our libertarian and participatory aims and

values – then those onerous jobs should surely be shared.

There is nothing new in socially valued work effort being a condition of

above average consumption entitlement. The Spanish CNT economic program

of the 1930s is an example. Similarly, libertarian communists like

Malatesta argued: “The only possible alternative to being the oppressed

or the oppressor is voluntary cooperation for the greatest good of all.”

The Italian argued that able-bodied people who refused to work, yet

consumed the benefits of people labouring for them, were probably

developing a taste for privilege!

In other words, our values are affected by this. Solidarity is reduced

through resentment, and likewise for efficiency by rewarding sloth. The

implications for self-management are to diminish it, giving non-workers

more say than they should have. Diversity does not appear to be

affected.

While the “according to need.” maxim was a part of the sentiment of

anarchist Spain, it was not the only or even the main operative norm; in

fact, it could not possibly have been. Some levels of work, timing of

participation, actual activity and so on, would have been found

acceptable, and others not acceptable.

In this sense, what many actually mean when they think of an economy

with remuneration “according to need”, actually equates with

remuneration according to effort and sacrifice, tempered by need.

Albert has also pointed out how having this remuneration to an economic

system without classes, and over a few generations, may have different

implications and is certainly not the same as doing so from the very

start. Both authors suggest an evolution towards more remuneration based

upon need as the economy moulds behaviour and endogenous preferences

over time. But even then, such an auditing/price mechanism and

round-by-round coordination may still be needed to have an efficient

modern and complex economy.

Participatory Planning

In addition to re-designing jobs to facilitate self-management, we also

need to abolish markets as a means of allocating goods and services.

This is because, like the corporate division of labour, markets destroy

solidarity and self-management; “This occurs not only due to disparities

in wealth translating into disparate power, but because market

competition compels even council based workplaces to cut costs and seek

market share regardless of the ensuing implications.” Workers will

eventually appoint un-recallable managers to compete and increase

output. For recent examples of this see market socialist Yugoslavia, the

occupied factory movement in Argentina, or the history of the MondragĂłn

co-operative in Spain.

As an alternative to both markets and central planning, parecon proposes

allocation through “participatory planning”. “We say that the

alternative is to have the entire population directly create the plan

themselves” and that “the education system and the availability of

information should be such as to facilitate this.”

Planning is conceptually quite simple, and is part of everyone’s BJC.

The participants are the workers councils (WCs) and federations, the

consumer councils (CCs) and federations, and an Iteration Facilitation

Board (IFB — a group of BJC workers providing information to

participants in each round).

This yearly planning procedure (say, two weeks or less) can be broken

down into 4 steps:

indicating the social costs and benefits associated with the use of

goods and services’ or preliminary estimates) for all final goods and

services, capital goods, natural resources, and categories of labour.

Worker councils and federations respond with production proposals.

good and service, capital good, natural resource, and category of

labour, and adjusts the indicative price for the good up, or down, in

light of the excess demand or supply.

federations revise and resubmit their proposals.

The planning process continues until there are no longer excess demands

for any goods, categories of labour, primary inputs, or capital stock;

in other words, until a feasible plan is reached.”

Classes of goods and services are grouped together into categories

according to the interchangeability of the resources, intermediate goods

and labour required to make them, as well as some of the easily

predicted variation of optional features. Producers provide quality

items that people will like. If people don’t like some, they don’t

provide more of that and this is recorded over time. If producers offer

up sweaters people don’t like, (despite using focus groups, or

statistics and sample sizes to obtain size, style, colour and so on),

people won’t purchase them at distribution centres, and styles will be

changed. Choices can be changed as the year progresses and producers can

adapt their products.

To simplify updating during the year and after the yearly planning

period, “slack” is used. Industries produce more and plan excess

capacity so they can expand output if needs be. The US has 15–25%

unutilised capacity; this is easily 2 to 3 times more than what would be

needed in a parecon. Only affected regions or federations of industries

need adjust for any change. Processing and meeting time is not zero in

capitalism and corporations are already planned economies, using

estimations of consumer demand and statistics in terms of fine detail of

final products.

So parecon does not take the “one big meeting” approach to economic

planning with endless large-scale meetings resulting in chaos and

stagnation. “Many of the procedures we recommended were motivated

precisely to avoid pitfalls in the naïve illusion that ‘the people’ can

make all economic decisions that affect them in what amounts to ‘one big

meeting’...Our participatory planning procedure is one that literally

involves no meetings at all.” So any meetings to decide on proposals

regarding one’s own activities are meetings within, not between,

councils and federations. Instead the proposal is a procedure in which

councils and federations submit proposals only for their own activities,

receive new information including revised estimates of social costs, and

resubmit proposals, again, only for their own activities. A parecon

might decide that people act individually during the majority of

planning rounds. Each production unit must only prepare detailed

proposals about its own self-activity; which any production unit must do

in any economy.

Parecon not only eliminates the perverse incentive inherent in central

planning to disguise one’s true capabilities, it provides all councils

with information to easily find if any work or consumption proposal is

socially responsible, i.e. fair and efficient. Because 99% of the votes

are “no brainers,” this does not need to be contentious or

time-consuming. If a WC’s social benefit to social cost ratio is one or

higher (SB/SC > 1), then we are better off if they are given permission

to do what they’ve proposed, otherwise we are worse off. There is a

similar “no brainer” rule for how to vote on CC proposals. Because, say,

99% of the voting can be done automatically, and 99% of the votes can be

taken care of by federations rather than individual councils, (votes

only have to be on proposals of councils within their worker and

consumer federation), all this voting really takes up very little time.

Nor do we have to do this for millions of different proposals from

councils in distant cities and states. If there are 10 neighbourhood CCs

in a ward federation, then only the other nine councils in that ward

federation need to vote on each of their proposals. If there are 10 ward

federations in a city federation, then only the other nine wards in that

city need to vote on each ward proposal. Wards will need to check on

other ward averages, and cities will need to check on other city

averages, but this still eliminates 99% of the proposals any single

entity must vote on. In other words, most of the voting can be

decentralized and taken care of within federations.

While computers would save more time facilitating planning and

credit-card technology can aid consumption and stock levels, computers

are not required by participatory planning making it more efficient than

central planning in this regard. The only calculations required are

adding individual proposals into aggregate proposals and comparing

aggregate supply and demand for each item. The percentage excess supply

or demand indicative prices could be adjusted without the aid of

computers.

I believe parecon warrants serious attention and investigation by those

who wish to see a coherent classless economy, where workers and

consumers cooperatively, and efficiently, negotiate economic outcomes

with no class divisions. The main advantage of parecon is that the power

to plan is no longer exclusive to elites, or, as in a market socialist

system, unevenly distributed among elite conceptual and manual workers,

but rather open to all. Participatory economics has the potential to

transcend capitalism and also market and centrally planned socialism by

establishing core institutions that promote solidarity, equity of

circumstance and income, diversity, participatory self-management,

classlessness, and efficiency in meeting human needs and developing

human potentials. To quote the late Howard Zinn, “Participatory

economics is an imaginative, carefully reasoned description, of how we

might live free from economic injustice.” There is an alternative.