đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș dennis-william-brogan-proudhon.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:25:31. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Proudhon
Author: Dennis William Brogan
Date: 1934
Language: en
Topics: Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, biography
Source: Retrieved on May 16, 2008 from https://web.archive.org/web/20080516081107/http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu:16080/Anarchist_Archives/proudhon/brogan/brogan_toc.html

Dennis William Brogan

Proudhon

CHAPTER I: THE EDUCATION OF PROUDHON

PIERRE-JOSEPH PROUDHON was born on the 15^(th) of January, 1809, and

thus grew up in the shadow of two great events, the French and the

industrial revolutions; both of these he felt profoundly; the first of

them he understood. He was born in Battant, a suburb of Besancon, the

capital of the Free County of Burgundy, and his intense local patriotism

remained a living force in his life and thought to the day of his death.

His ‘little country’, Franche-Comte’, had only been part of France for

one hundred and fifty years when Proudhon was born; Besancon was a real

local capital, and some of the seeds of Proudhon’s federalism, of his

dislike of Paris, and of centralisation, were sown in those early years.

He was a citizen of no mean city, a child of no mere department; and,

whether he was defending the intellectual independence of the County of

Burgundy against the pretensions of the Duchy of Burgundy, or looking

forward with delight to the reconstitution of the thirty submerged

nationalities which he believed existed in France, he was fighting, not

merely for a general principle,but for the memories and loyalties of his

youth.

More important still was his parentage. ‘My ancestors on both sides were

free peasants, exempt from feudal servitude from time immemorial’; there

remained to Proudhon all his life a family pride as great as that of a

Guerinantes; be was born of no proletarian or servile stock. Had not his

maternal grandfather, the old soldier, withstood before the revolution

die local tyrannical squire, and was not his mother ‘noted for her

virtues and for her republican ideas’? ‘This is real nobility of race. I

myself am a noble.’ His father’s family, the Proudhons, was noted for

obstinacy; one branch had risen in the world, had entered the middle

classes and produced an eminent lawyer, but the poorer connections were

far from playing the role of poor relations; they had their share of the

pride, that was to be so marked in their most famous kinsman. Proudhon’s

father was a cooper and, for a time, a brewer. He was, doubtless, an

honest and industrious man, but unsuccessful in his business. Later,

Proudhon attributed his father’s financial disasters to his incorrigible

habit of selling his beer at the ‘just price’, that is, at the cost of

production, instead of imitating the rest of the brewers who sold at a

profit. Not only that, the elder Proudhon was careful about the

character of his customers, and so lost money by refusing to let women

enter his shop. Others were not so scrupulous, and ‘having grown rich by

prostitution ... married their children off to the best people, while my

father’s children have found nobody’. The lesson learned here was never

forgotten; there was a morally right way of doing business; there was a

morally wrong way of doing business; but in modern society the right way

led straight to bankruptcy, the wrong way to wealth and honour. Society

must be made safe for honesty and a world be created in which the

children of an honest man like Claude-Francois Proudhon should not be

embittered by having their father’s honesty in hunger and humiliation.

Although Proudhon considered himself a nativeof Besancon, the suburb

where he was born, preserved, as M. Daniel Halevy tells us, a rural

character. ‘Many market-gardeners, peasants, wine-growers, found it

convenient to lodge there, not far from the city-folk. Thus they could

make their living without changing their way of life, keeping

faithfully, in the shadow of the town, to their rural customs and their

rural speech.’ This, again, was of great importance to Proudhon, for he

learned to know and sympathise with the peasants, to feel with the

peasants in his heart, to share their land-hunger; their rigid views of

right-living; their deep conservatism; all combined with their passion

for equality; their class-consciousness; and their savage resolution to

be each master of his own fields and his own household.

Not only did Proudhon know the peasant life; he lived it. Until he was

twelve, he was constantly engaged in farm-work, especially in herding

cattle, and late in life, he declared that there, in the grass, looking

at the sky, he learned un-Christian lessons of trust in nature, and

distrust of ‘that absurd spiritualism which is at the basis of Christian

life and education’. When he had become a famous antagonist or the

Church, both he and his enemies were inclined to exaggerate the heresies

of his childhood; and one pious antagonist declared that prayer found no

echo in the Proudhon household. It was never safe to assume anything

about Proudhon, and he was indignant at this charge, for he was, in

fact, brought up in matter-of-fact orthodoxy by his parents. They were

good Catholics of the old French peasant school and so was their son. He

believed in God and the saints; he also believed in nymphs and fairies.

Proudhon owed his chance of formal education to the Abbe Sirebon, the

parish priest, next, to his father’s employer, but, above all, to his

mother, Catherine, who was the mainstay of the poor household. The

Proudhons were going down in the world. Claude-Francois was no longer

his own master, the future was dark but the boy was to be given his

chance. The entry to the local college (high school) was the greatest

event of Proudhon’s youth; more important than the siege of Besancon,

than his father failure, than the birth of a younger brother. He now

learned of delights as keen as any he had known as a herd-boy; he

displayed the prodigious industry that was to remain with him all his

life and an appetite for learning that startled his teachers. But he

studied under great difficulties; his family was desperately poor, and

he had to borrow school books from more fortunate boys, he had no hat;

he wore wooden shoes; and he learned the truth of the local proverb,

‘Poverty is no crime; it is worse.’

The studies were almost entirely mathematics and Latin. He was a poor

mathematician (and that is worth remembering), but he was an excellent

Latinist. He mastered the language and shone in it and, until his death,

language fascinated him. He won prizes and one of them was Fenelon’s

Demonstration of the Existence of God. He read it, and it shook his

faith. ‘After that,’ he said, ‘I was a metaphysician’ -a belief which M.

Daniel Halevy notes, was an illusion.

His school life was difficult, and its difficulties nourished his sombre

pride; be was religious, but be saw, or thought he saw, that his zeal

was ill-rewarded, that the Church was a respecter of persons. When he

was sixteen he abandoned the practice of his religion, although be was

to return to it again. The family fortunes grew worse and worse. On the

day he was to receive a prize, there was no one of his family present,

and the presiding official had to take the place of the missing

kinsfolk. He went home to find his father in consternation, his mother

in tears; a lawsuit had ended in a decision against his father. ‘That

evening we supped on bread and water.’ The strain on the family

resources of keeping Pierre Joseph at school was unbearable. “At

eighteen,” said his father, “I earned my keep and I hadn’t had so long

an apprenticeship”-“I thought he was right.”’ What trade to adopt was

now the question? If he could have got access to the land, he might have

become a farmer, but the want of capital barred that road. ‘Perhaps it

was only the want of a good organisation of rural credit that kept me

from remaining all my life a peasant and a conservative.’ Another

lesson, the exclusion of the poor from property and independence, was

now learned.

The trade chosen was printing, and he never forgot the lessons he

learned in his apprenticeship. He was proud to have a trade and believed

that it was a sure shield against want, that he was now independent of

everybody. He also became convinced that the competent artisan received

a more fruitful training than the bookworm; and he was always irritated

by the claims of an intellectual elite to lead the workers for their own

good. His conviction of the necessity, and the possibility, of equality

was given a secure basis in his mind by his memories of the printer’s

chapel. He learned the force of trade practice, of the way in which a

customary code can keep the sluggards up to the mark and prevent the

strong from racing ahead too fast. He learned a trade morality, and the

need for and the possibility of mutual loyalty. He never lost the

conviction that he knew the minds, the needs, the natures of the

workers, and of the peasants, as no academics, fortified with formal

doctrine, could know them. The workers never became for him a

homogeneous class of which any thousand were worth any other thousand;

their salvation must come from within. Any leadership from the outside,

no matter what were its claims to superior knowledge or

disinterestedness, was simply another form of tyranny. There were more

modes of exploitation than those created by formal property relations.

Besides learning his trade he fell in love, violently, as he was never

to fall in love again, and he returned to his religion with a passionate

enthusiasm. The work of the printing-shop was largely concerned with

theology; Proudhou read widely in the fathers of the Church as well as

more in modern writers. He thought of himself as an apologist for the

faith, for if he was already suspicious of the political side of

Catholicism, his faith in the theory, if not in the practice, of the

Church was still warm. Already he was perplexed by the problem of

inequality, of worldly injustice. Was the Church right, was there no

remedy for these evils in this world, or was it possible to organise

society on new lines, to harmonise the desires and passions of men? Was

man the maimed creature, marked by original sin as the Church described

him, or was the escape from his prison house in his own hands once he

found the key? He was tempted by the heresy of Socinianism, by the

denial of original sin. He was unwittingly on his way out of the Church

and on to another faith.

He was now a proof-reader and, through his corrections of a Latin Lives

of the Saints, he made the acquaintance and won the friendship of its

young editor, Gustave Fallot, destined to be the first great personal

influence in Proudhon’s life. Fallot was, or hoped to be, a philologist;

he infected Proudhon with his enthusiasm, an enthusiasm which, with

Proudhon, took the form of learning Hebrew. This study left permanent

marks on his mind. He retained to his death what was, for a Frenchman,

an astonishing familiarity with the Bible. It was a weapon of fact, of

argument, of rhetorical appeal, and he ranked it with Adam Smith and

Hegel among the three sources of his ideas. Not only the Bible, but

philology attracted him. It is hard to realize now the prestige of

philological studies in that age; new vistas were opened up by it,

vistas not only in the history of language, but in the general history

of mankind. It was a clue to the nature of things which, if strenuously

held to, would lead its owner into the heart of the labyrinth where lay

the secret of human misery to be remedied by the application of the true

laws of man’s nature, laws which language could illuminate. This

illusion, that linguistic knowledge was the key to all or to most

problems, never wholly left Proudhon. It, as much as any borrowed

dialectic, was his method of research and of argument. On the whole,

this belief did him harm. It is worth saying once that the Hebrew text

of the commandment does not say ‘Thou shalt not steal’, but ‘Thou shalt

not put aside’, but Lo thignob recurs too often, not as an illustration,

but as an argument. Again and again arguments are interrupted or

eloquence is allowed to cool off, while the etymology of a word is

pursued through bold and often erroneous guesses. It is not of

first-class importance to know (or to think you know) that all the world

is wrong in believing that religio at bottom means binding , when it

really means bending. In any case, even if philology had been as

powerful and adequate a weapon as Proudhon thought, he was unfitted to

use it. He knew a good deal of Latin, Greek, Hebrew, but be knew nothing

of language, or nothing to the point. He pained friends, who knew

better, by his bold guesses. He had neither the scholar’s equipment nor

temperament. Words had the meanings Proudhon wanted them to have, and if

modern philology gave him no support, so much the worse for it! It is in

vain that his patient friend, Professor Bergmann, tries to tame him; the

bee keeps buzzing in the bonnet. He had valid reasons for disliking

Renan’s methods, but, in any case, the professional superiority of Renan

in philological equipment would have made Proudhon suspicious of his

rival author of a Life of Jesus.

Another key to knowledge of society was now put into his hands, for a

fellow-citizen of Franche-Comte, just becoming famous, had his book

printed at Besancon. The book was The New Industrial World of Charles

Fourier, and it helped to open the world of economic speculation to the

young proof-corrector. Later in life Proudhon, as was his wont, was less

and less willing to admit his debt to Fourier, especially as he got to

be on worse and worse terms with Fourier’s disciples, but the influence

was great. It is most obvious in the first edition of the Creation of

Order in Humanity, where the system of series is made to do all sorts of

wonders, but this was chiefly a matter of words. But Fourier’s

scepticism of the state his view that the social revolution could be

brought about within the existing society by setting an example of a

more efficient economy (the Phalanstery) has point of affinity with the

later anarchical doctrines of Proudhon, although the effect of the

example given in Proudbon’s system is moral, not economic. Proudhon

admitted six weeks of infatuation with Fourier, but the influence lasted

longer than that. Proudhon came to scorn all ‘Utopias’ as Marx did; the

optimism of Saint-Simon, of Cabet, and of the Foutierists infuriated

him; all these promises of increased wealth to be generally distributed

by ingenious manipulations, by improved productive methods, were deceit

in his eyes, for the best that could be hoped for was decent poverty for

everyone, instead of wealth for some and wretchedness for the rest. It

is a source of his strength that the satisfactions he promises his

disciples are moral rather than material, but if he abandoned the path

opened by Fourier, he was for long enough in the debt of his

fellow-countryman, and in his own later years he thought more kindly of

the speculator whom he had been used to attack.

While this interior revolution was under way, an exterior revolution

broke out. The ‘three glorious days of July’ (1830) overthrew the

restored Bourbons and made it evident to the world that the

revolutionary spirit was again on the march. That revolutionary spirit

filled the mind and still more the heart of Proudhon. He never wavered

in his belief that the French Revolution was a turning point in human

history. That Revolution might be, for Marx, merely a triumph of the new

capitalist over the old feudal order, but for Proudhon it was the

beginning of the reign of Justice, or, at any rate, it made possible the

institution of the reign of Justice. What the content of Justice was, in

Proudbon’s system, will be described later, but Proudhon never regretted

for a moment the Revolution. He could be bitter about its betrayal by

leaders who were heroes of the revolutionary legend, but whom he

condemned for misunderstanding the great moment of deliverance, but none

of his sneers at democracy and, still more, at democrats, can make of

him (despite the ingenious special pleading of M. Louis Dimier) a

‘master of the counter-revolution’. Nowhere more clearly than in

Proudhon, can one feel the unshakable devotion of the French peasant and

worker to the memory of those days ‘when Death was on thy drums,

Democracy, and, with one rush of slaves, the world was free’. Is a man,

a book, a project, counter-revolutionary? It is thereby condemned. Does

a law or an idea seem to attempt to damn up the revolutionary flood; it

is futile. The future is, must be with the Revolution: the old obedience

to traditional authority, in politics and in religion, has received a

mortal wound. Any society based on these ideas is bleeding to death; it

may be bandaged up for a time, but the bleeding cannot be stopped, As

much as Marx, Proudhon believed and preached the inevitable victory of

his cause, the making of the world safe for the idea of Justice brought

into it by the French Revolution. It is the theme of his greatest book,

Justice in the Revolution and the Church. It shapes all his economic

arguments, so that Walras is startled to find an economic doctrine

refuted as being against the spirit of the Revolution. The Re- volution,

though side-tracked and betrayed, is ever on the march. Crises like 1830

and 1848 are bred by the instability of all institutions which do not

frankly take as their base the revolutionary idea of Justice, that is to

say, equality. There are now no authorities of tradition or of divine

right; all such authorities died in 1789; although their rotting corpses

may yet cumber the ground.

The immediate effect of the revolution of 1830 was not to provide

Proudbon with a philosophy, but to deprive him of his job, for the

upheaval was bad for business, Proudhon learned that even being master

of a trade did not (as it should have done) guarantee a living. Fallot

did his best for the friend to whom he predicted that ‘you will be a

writer, a philosopher, you will be one of the lights of the age ... you

cannot escape your destiny’. The destiny was still fugitive, however; a

livelihood of any kind, as a teacher, as a printer, was the first

necessity. Fallot had an idea. Why not apply for the Suard Scholarship?

It was tenable for three years; it was the very thing that would enable

Proudhon to complete his education. But Proudhon was far less ambitious

for himself than his friend was for him. At last he succumbed to

Fallot’s pleadings, to the offer to share their resources in Paris. He

set off for the capital on foot; Paris did not please him, neither the

place nor the people; and Fallot fell ill. He recovered, but Proudhon

would not be a drag on his friend any longer; there was no work to be

had in the city, so he set out, on foot, for the South, with ÂŁ2 in his

pocket.

He was, if not disappointed, for the moment at least, defeated; he was

to be a worker, not a writer — and he was a worker without work. The

times continued bad; the helplessness of the mere worker was taught to

Proudhon. He arrived at Toulon with three and a half francs left; he

found no work, but had he not a passport which promised help and

protection? He applied to the mayor to give him work, and the mayor, one

of the now triumphant bourgeoisie which the recent revolution had put

into power, told him that he had misunderstood his passport; all he

could claim was enough money to take him home. The official having

failed, he appealed to the man; again he was repulsed. ‘Very well ‘I

said between clenche teeth, ‘I promise you to remember this interview.’

And remember it he did, more than twenty years later when he told the

story.

There was nothing for it but to return to Besancon, where his family had

just lost the third son, called up to the army, which the sons of the

prosperous could escape by a money payment, and where Jean- Etienne was

to die, another victim of society. For a brief moment Proudhon was

editor of a new paper, an organ of ‘advanced ideas’; but, in a day, he

learned that the ideas must not be more advanced than those of the

proprietor. The job was thrown up at once, and a lesson on the necessary

compromises of party journalism taught — but not learned.

He worked for a while in the country at Arbois, aiding in a lawsuit

against a great proprietor and drinking deeply at the popular traditions

of the Revolution; and then returned to Besancon to work for his old

employers as a proof-reader. He had ÂŁ6 a month; it was wealth! Among his

jobs was the seeing through the press of a Latin Bible — and of a new

edition of the theological dictionary of Bergier. To the latter he owed

much of that command of theological learning that made many think he had

studied for the priesthood. It reinforced his contempt for vagueness or

for compromise; between Catholicism and Atheism, or, as he was to

insist, ‘anti-theism, there is nothing that a sober man can rest on.

There must be certainty, and one side or the other must be chosen. He

hated the Church and many of its servants, but he never ceased to

respect it; it was the greatest, most respectable of errors, not to be

assailed with the feeble and corrupt methods of Voltaire — for although

Voltaire was on the right side, the Bible and the Church were not to be

replaced by the lewd jesting of La Pucelle or the sentimental

religiosity of Rousseau.

Meantime, he attempted to escape from dependence, not by learning, but

by his trade. He set up in partnership as a printer. It was a moment of

hope and joy; a short moment, for his friend Fallot died, his great

schemes unfinished, and he had left his fame to Proudhon as a charge —

and, indeed, if Fallot is at all remembered to-day, it is as one who

helped Proudhon! But Proudhon’s ambitions were not purely those of a

printer; he had something to say; perhaps it was, as M. Daniel Halevy

suggests, a way of carrying on Fallot’s work. In any case, Proudhon

began his first book, an essay in philology, the science whose

possibilities had dazzled him when Fallot first displayed them before

his eyes. In form, the book was an appendix to a philological essay of

Bergier, but in essence it was the search after eternal truth by the

road of language; the science of language will lead man to the truth he

is made to know. The essay fell entirely flat; it did not bear

Proudhon’s name and, in any case, no one noticed it. As a serious study

in philology it was worthless; Proudhon, like Bergier, lived in a world

where modem scientific philology was unknown. Later, Proudhon recognised

this, and was as scornful of his first efforts as any critic could

desire. For the moment the lost chance of fame was less important than

the decline of the printing business. Proudhon was repeating his

father’s experience, an effort to secure independence by hard work and

honest dealing was proving fruitless. The death of his brother, of

Fallot, the failure of his writings, of his business, all embittered

him. He had,dreamcd of private vengeance, of the enforcement of justice,

or, at least, the avenging of wrong by a secret court of honest men,

only there were so few honest men! A hundred men in France devoted

to.justice would suffice, but out of 34,000,000 where to find the

hundred? And meanwhile, the prison-gates were again closing round him.

He had failed to escape by his learning; he had failed, it appeared, to

escape by his trade; he must resign himself to a life as the servant of

others. Why?

There was a last chance open to find an answer to this problem, the

Suard Scholarship. It was about to be offered by the Academy of

Besancon; he would be a candidate, and in the meantime he had a job as a

proof-reader in Paris. This was a change from his last stay in the

capital, a change for the better; but Fallot was dead and there was

nothing in Paris to touch his heart, although he made a few new

acquaintances, some of whom were in time to be friends.

Meanwhile, the negotiations and the necessary tactical moves in the

campaign for the scholarship were under way. Proudhon had won respect

for his character, and admiration for his talent, in Besancon, but he

was not always a help to his sponsors. One of the electors (and he was

no bad judge) thought highly of Proudhon’s ability, but declared ‘that

fellow is bound to be a troublesome customer’ — and refused to vote for

him. Not only was Proudhon a rather intimidating candidate, but he had

odd views of what he would do with the scholarship if he gained it. The

Academy wanted its nominee to go to Paris and study in order that he

might rise in the world. Proudhon wanted to stay on in Besancon; he

would study, indeed, but he did not want to abandon his trade (he was

more and more involved in the illfortune of his partners) and he did not

want to rise in the world, for such an ambition was incompatible with

his new religion, that of equality. Despite his views he was chosen,

being supported by ‘all the most distinguished and influential members’,

notably by the Abbe Doney, who had been a disciple of Lammenais.

Proudhon was still an amateur philologist, and he had sent in an essay

for the Volney Prize, offered by the Institute of France. His Researches

on the Crammatical Categories and on some Origins of the French Language

got an honourable mention, and some of it appeared in a learned journal.

This ended philology for Proudhon, but when he was famous, some enemies

reprinted his Appendix to Bergier, to show that Proudhon was

inconsistent or hypocritical, a malicious trick which infuriated him,

and for which he blamed the Church. Proudhon’s project was ambitious

enough. He proposed to write Researches on Revelation, or Philo — sophy

serving as an Introduction to Universal History, a work designed to

demonstrate that evangelical morality represented eternal truths lost to

sight today. Evangelical truths soon lost their attraction for him, but

the belief in eternal truths which he could demonstrate for the

salvation of the world, remained a Proudhonian doctrine to the end.

The letter of application was equally characteristic. In the first

draft, it contained a profession of faith which alarmed his cautious

sponsor, Perennes. ‘Born and brought up in the working-class, belonging

to it still, to-day, and for ever, by feelings, intellect and habits

and, above all, by the community of interests and wishes’ Proudhon

promised, if chosen, to toil, ‘by philosophy and science, with all the

energy of his will and all the powers of his mind, towards complete

emancipation of his brothers and fellows’. Such a programme, it was

feared, would not appeal to the academicians, and the text was amended.

The ‘community of interests and of wishes’ became ‘the community of

suffering and of wishes’ and, more important, ‘the complete

emancipation’ of the workers become their ‘moral and intellectual

betterment’. The campaign was over; he was chosen and he was inundated

by congratulations; congratulations which infuriated him, for they

showed that to the world he was a worker who was now given the chance of

escaping from his class; that few or none saw him as he saw himself, a

worker taking a chance to be trained to serve his class. He dared not

declare his intentions; his scorn of worldly success; ‘people would

think me cracked’. Nevertheless, he was resolved to devote himself to

the cause of the poor and helpless, though thereby he might be ‘an

abomination to the rich and powerful; those who hold the keys of science

and of wealth might curse him, yet he would pursue the path of the

reformer through persecution, calumny, sorrow and death itself’. It was

not to have a knapsack with a marshal’s baton in it, not to have a

career open to his talents, that Proudhon sought the scholarship. He was

resolved to be a La Tour d’Auvergne of his class; to remain in the ranks

and fight with his brethren. It was a resolution that he never broke;

all his life, despite all his faults of temper and of understanding, he

fought for the good cause as he conceived it.

CHAPTER II: THE PAMPHLETEER

Proudhon returned to Paris in 1838, supporting himself by writing

articles for a Catholic encyclopedia and correcting proofs for a

royalist journal. These jobs did not last long; and he was ready to

plunge into his studies, supported by the scholarship. He had dreamed of

founding a review; he now wanted to express the ideas fermenting in him,

and he took the first opportunity offered by sending in an essay for a

prize offered by the Academy of Besancon, on the question of The

Usefulness of the Celebration of Sunday. His essay got an honorable

mention, but, more important, it revealed the essential Proudhon. The

social usefulness of the Mosaic law is stressed; but for us, the most

interesting themes are those that Proudhon was to spend his life in

elaborating. ‘Is equality of conditions an institution of nature, is it

equitable, is it possible? On each of these points I dare decide for the

affirmative.’ There is a declaration of the absolute character of the

moral law, for Rousseau had erred ‘in submitting justice and morality to

the decision of numbers and to the opinion of the majority.’ Lo thignob

is stressed; for it means not, ‘Thou shalt not steal’, but ‘Thou shalt

not lay anything aside for thyself’, There must exist a science of

society which it is the work of the economist not to invent, but to

find. If the form and, in the main, the language of the essay are

innocuous enough, to any reader who knows the later Proudhon, it is

obvious that the Celebration of Sunday, for all its formal piety, shows

that the Academy had caught a tartar, and in 1840 appeared the work

which put this beyond doubt.

It was a very human touch in Proudhon to regard almost every book of

his, while be was writing it, as epoch-making, new, final. Of none of

them were these hopes better founded than the essay on property, which

he was convinced might prove ‘the most remarkable event of 1840’. Into

it he put all his bitterness, all his delight in verbal analysis, and,

he thought, the result, free from all rhetoric, had nothing like itself

in all philosophy. What is Property? was the title, and the answer was

given in the first few lines. ‘If I had to answer the following

question: What is Slavery? and answering in a single word, I replied: It

is Murder, my meaning would be understood at once. I should have no need

of a long discourse to show that the power to take from a man thought,

will, personality, is a power of life and death, and that to enslave a

man is to murder him. Why then, in answer to this other question: What

is Property? can I not reply, It is Theft without having the assurance

of not being understood, although this second proposition is only the

first transformed?’

Property is Theft. To most of his own countrymen Proudhon, for the rest

of his life, was capable of anything because of his epigram. In vain he

elaborated his doctrine, explained, for twenty years, that he was a

defender, not an enemy of property; he could never live down or live up

to the too successful,opening lines. But he never recanted what he had

written; he was indeed inordinately proud of his phrase — and there was

no quicker way to earn his hate than to assert that he had not invented

it or, at least, that he had not given it its first real interpretation.

It was one of the crimes of Louis Blanc that he said Brissot had

preceded Proudhon in this assertion, and the property in the

phrase,‘Property is Theft’ was fought over with an acerbity that has its

comic side.

The attack on property was made in three tracts. The first caused a

terrific scandal and embroiled him with the Academy. The second, however

(The Letter to M. Blanqui) was written in milder style to explain the

first, which might have led to Proudhon’s arrest had not M. Blanqui, a

distinguished economist, assured the Minister of justice, M. Vivien,

that Proudhon was a serious student, not a mere agitator -a good office

for which Proudhon remained grateful both to the academician and the

minister. The third tract was the Letter to Considerant or the Warning

to Proprietors, and this was as inflammatory as the first. What are the

arguments brought forward to justify the declaration that Property is

Theft? No time need be lost in confuting the critics who point out that

the idea of theft necessarily implies property. For Proudhon, property

was private property. Much of his argument reads oddly to-day, if it is

not remembered when he was writing and against what antagonists. In the

lifetime of Proudhon’s father and mother, there had been an immense

transference of property rights from the Church and the nobility,

chiefly to the middle classes; at any rate, not to the Proudhon family.

As fast as possible, the new owners began to demand a religious

reverence for all property rights, including those so recently acquired!

Property, indeed, had been declared to be one of the ‘Rights of Man’. It

is against these defences that Proudhon launches his most formidable

attacks. If ‘the right to property’, is to have any meaning relating it

to the other natural rights, it must mean the right of every man to have

property, not the right of some men to exclude their less fortunate

fellows from enjoyment of this ‘natural right’. But property is not a

natural right at all; if it were, why all the argument? ‘Who,’ he asks

audaciously, ‘ever inquires into the origin of the rights of liberty,

security, equality?’ All attempts to demonstrate that property has any

rights, other than those based on formal law, break down. Jurists, like

Grotius and Pothier, philosophers like Reid, ‘chief of the Edinburgh

school’, produce arguments that either keep to the surface or involve

deep contradictions. In short, property is impossible!

The first retort of the unmetaphysically-minded reader is to ask that if

property is impossible, why make such a fuss about it? But by impossible

Proudhon means that the idea of absolute property, as understood by the

lawyers, is contradictory, is a Utopia. By property, Proudhon almost

always at this stage means property in land and property in land not

worked by the owner. It is rent in the common meaning of the word, not

the Ricardian economic rent, that is the first great grievance of the

propertyless classes, for the mere landlord is paid for something he has

not created; his relation to the economic exploitation of the land is

purely parasitic. It is useless for Charles Comte to ask what about the

owner who improves the land? The making of two blades of grass grow

where one grew before creates rights, (very limited rights indeed), but

they are apart from ownership. If a tenant improves the land he farms,

the law does not give him the increased value; it goes to the landlord

whose essential character is to draw an income without adding in the

least to the wealth of society. This parasitic drain on labour means

that production costs more than it is worth, ‘for the landlord’s part

represents no economic reality. Proudhon’s views of production were

pessimistic and, if a large part of the total product of society went to

non-producers, production must fall. At its best it is barely sufficient

for the maintenance of the race; property cuts down this meagre return

from labour and so property tends to kill itself, to produce

impoverishment in the very exercise of its rights. As for the worker,

the farmer, his lot is far worse; he has to work harder and harder,

while the worker in industry is forced to undercut big fellows. As the

workers without property cannot buy what they produce, and since

production does not produce a surplus which can be seized with impunity

by non-producers, ‘property is murderous’. Moreover, property is

incompatible with political liberty. If you have political equality and

economic inequality, property will be attacked under cover of law, by

taxation, for instance, and such attacks are inconsistent with the

absolute property rights of the lawyers. Property and equality cannot

co-exist; but equality is just and what is just is what should determine

the Organisation of society; justice is the criterion.

It was natural for Proudhon’s enemies and for hasty readers to conclude

that the author of this indictment was not only a socialist but a

communist. But he never gave any grounds for this view, and both Marx

and Considerant absolved Proudhon from the charge of being a renegade to

his earlier convictions. If the public bad been taken-in and believed

this fanatical individualist to have been a communist, the fault was the

public’s for looking to the form rather than to the substance. In fact,

Proudhon was a defender of property; but property could not survive in

the post-revolutionary world if it could not be harmonised with Justice,

that is to say, with equality. Already governments, for all their

lip-service to property rights, are invading them. The conversion of the

national debt is an attack on property, even though the conversion is

formally voluntary. The holders of the debt have a right to their 5 per

cent -or property rights are empty, an argument that one might have

thought silly if it had not been used in our own time by Sir Ernest

Benn. What is good, in property, the possibility it offers of escape

from the slavery and degradation of communism, is only to be secured by

equality.

Proudhon pushes the argument for equality very hard. Even the farmer who

has increased wealth by his improvements on the land he tills is not

entitled to appropriate the increased wealth. After all, the fisherman

whose extra skill results in a catch twice as great as that of his

fellows is content with the reward of one double catch; he does not

claim a double catch for ever! Proudhon had always a weakness for

analogy, not as illustration, but as argument; and his attempt to limit

the rights of the improving farmer to a pre-emption and yet to preserve

equality are not very happy. He is hard, indeed, on all claims to

superior reward, for every member of society is its debtor; no matter

how hard or skilfully a man works, he dies as he is bom, overdrawn at

the Bank of Society. The great source of wealth is the community, and

this conviction is at the basis of what M. Bougle calls ‘the sociology

of Proudhon’. It is useless to say that high talents ought to be better

paid, for the difference between man and man is slight and more

education will reduce it further; while the scarcity of some talents

merely shows that they are not much needed. Nature provides as many of

each class of worker as society needs, so there is gross injustice in

paying an actress like Rachel more than a seamstress; any payment of

that kind must be taken from the workers. A poet who spends thirty years

on a masterpiece is, at the end of it, entitled to thirty years pay as a

worker, and any out-of-pocket expenses he may have incurred for books

and travel. After all, there are occupations which are luxuries, one

professor of philosophy is quite enough for the whole of France and one

economist for every two thousand million people! Naturally, some workmen

do in six hours what others take eight to do, but they must not make use

of those two hours to earn more. If others can only do four hours work

in eight hours, they must not get more than half pay. The average

product of., the average worker, that is what should be the standard. It

is easy here to see the former printer, used to the discipline of the

workshop! But the real solution is to secure land for everybody who

wants it, and to secure equality of resources in this way. For,

Proudhon, at this stage, and later, property is land and gold and

silver; they must be distributed equally, or society organised so that

the special privileges of their owners disappear.

The main doctrines of Proudhon are present in these three tracts — and

the main fancies. Commencing a revolutionary campaign, he fires on his

own side as well as on the common enemy. Not only the rich, but other

rebel writers and leaders are assailed. Cabet, Saint-Simon, Fourier,

Louis Blanc, the radicals of the National as well as the supporters of

the bourgeois monarchy, are bludgeoned. The passion for equality which

animates the author does not go as far as equality between the sexes,

man and woman are not in a common society, so the necessity of equality

which arises between man and man is absent! In this first appearance

before the great public, Proudhon was sublimely confident that he saw

further into the heart of things than anyone else, and that his writings

were of immense immediate importance. Property was like a criminal

trying to escape cross-examination and, in the Second Memoir, he

declares that he ‘is sworn to an immense relvolution, terrible to

charlatans and despots’! Pelletan was later to say that Proudhon fired a

musket off in the street to attract attention, and, in this case, he

succeeded in his, publicity methods. It was not for nothing that he had

known the young romantics of Paris; where Gautier had worn a red

waistcoat to startle the middle classes, Proudhon relied on violent

language, language which often concealed far from violent thought. He

now received the very thing he needed to maintain the impression he had

made, a prosecution, at Besancon, for the seditious character of the

Warning to Proprietors, a prosecution which failed and gave Proudhon an

advertisement and what prove to be a dangerously high opinion of his

power over an audience. The unknown printer and obscure student who had

been so ill-at-ease in the houses of his teachers in Paris, was now a

famous, or at least a notorious man. What were the causes of his

success?

The greatest of Proudhon’s assets was his admirable mastery of the

French tongue. He professed to despise mere literature and mere men, of

letters, but, at his best, there was no contemporary writer of French

prose who had a surer command of the language. This mastery he

displayed, above all, in attack and, at moments, his verve and force

made him not unworthy of comparison with the master who he admired so

much, Paul Louis Courier. In the first Memoir on Property, as in his

last posthumous fragments, there are passages of invective whose

technical excellence wins the admiration even of the most hostile

reader. When Marx praised the literary force displayed in the first

great pamphlet he, however grudgingly, recognised a polemical power in

this line at least equal to his own ; and the most enthusiastic tribute

to Proudhon’s literary ability comes from his rigorous critic, Arthur

Desjardins. ‘This plebeian carves out his phrases with profound art, the

art of the great classical authors; he is descendant of the writers whom

Louis XIV protected and who perfected our tongue. He, no less than

Moliere, ought to have been a member of the Fren Academy.’

But not all of Proudhon’s literary skill was spent on invective. There

are in his letters, and scattered through his writings, especially in

the autobiographical fragments of Justice in the Revolution and the

Church, pages of pure description, of reminiscence, sketches of his

early days in Franche-Comte, which make on realise that he sacrificed

the chance of giving Renan’s Memories of Childhood and youth a more

fomidable rival than his Life of Jesus was to Renan’s best-seller. He

gave up to his cause, to his loves and hates, the possibility of a

literary career of the first order. Even when his publishers would not

publish his political books, when the Press was barred to him and when

literature invited him with open arms to escape from dire poverty by

entering her service, he was not tempted. He dallied with the idea of

literary criticism; his friends, like Sainte-Beuve, his well-meaning

timid publishers, the Garniers, tried to persuade him; but his vocation

had been chosen twenty years before, when the delights and duties of

controversy, of expounding the truth and of confuting error had taken

possession of him. His ‘one talent which was death to hide’ was for

public affairs, his duty was to aid the deliverance of the poor from the

chains in which ignorance of the true cause of their ills bound them.

Proudhon was content to be a pamphleteer.

He was a great pamphleteer, but the uncritical praises of big admirers

have made it harder for the world to appreciate his greatness. He was

only occasionally, and for brief periods, a keen reasoner. He was not,

despite repeated assertions of disciples, in his own lifetime and since,

a master of rigid logical demonstration. He himself was, indeed, under

the illusion that logic was his strong point. He was excessively fond of

casting argument into logical forms and having brought his demonstration

to a triumphant conclusion, he was prone to regard any critic who

demurred to his results, as wilfully blind — or merely incapable of

rational thought. In his long and barren controversy with Bastiat, over

the nature of interest, he was at last provoked into declaring that ‘I

have to do with a man whose intelligence is hermetically sealed and for

whom logic does not exist.’ Bastiat was not a profound thinker, and his

share of the controversy earned him the contempt of Walras, but he was

not as stupid as Proudhon made out. In fact, Proudhon’s devotion to

logic was very superficial. A logical method, the series of Fourier, the

antimonies of Kant, the dialectic of Hegel, the syllogism of the

scholastics, was, for Proudhon, not a means of testing truth, or of

finding it, but a device for persuading his readers of truths which he

held on intuitional grounds. This is no doubt true of many more writers

than Proudhon, but few writers of his ability have relied on more

childish fallacies with more naive confidence than he. The pain with

which Walras disentangles some of the less flagrant sophistries, the

repeated bold transitions from a moral to an economic category which is

the great Proudhonian trick, is unconsciously funny. In the Proudhonian

world, ‘equality of respect’ and ‘equality of incomes’ were terms in the

same syllogism, for Proudhon had no understanding of an intellectual

world in which non-moral categories existed. For all his parade of rigid

demonstration of truths which would save the world, Proudhon was never

asking ‘Is this True?’ but always ‘Is this Right?’ If his opponents had

been notably more clear-headed than Proudhon, he would have been a less

formidable controversialist than, in fact, he was; but in the middle of

the nineteenth century, orthodox economists had not acquired their

present self-denying attitude and, consciously or unconsciously, mixed

their own categories. Even Walras, who was fighting at a higher level

than Bastiat or Thiers, committed himself to the view that it was

impudent for Say (and Proudhon) to attack the psychological results of

the division of labour, since division of labour had, or would, reduce

working hours, so that the worker who had spent ten hours making the

twelfth part of a pin could restore his mutilated personality by any

form of recreation he liked! The assumption, that the monotony or

variety of work was in itself unimportant, came more easily to the

mathematician than to the former printer who remained to his death so

proud that he had mastered a whole trade, not a mere part of a process.

But what was an occasional slip with Walras, was frequent with lesser

men, and the legal apologists for property, who mixed up implicit

utilitarianism, legal dogma hazardous anthropology, in one stout

affirmation of the property system as defined by the Code Napoleon, were

easy marks for Proudhon’s logical devices.

Naturally, such readers as were not taken-in by the parade of logical

rigour, were sometimes inclined to doubt Proudhon’s good faith. They

pointed out (it was not very hard) contradictions and inconsistencies.

Critics on the left thought his adoption of the role of the candid

friend an expression of spleen as well as of intellectual disagreement;

critics on the right thought he was, in another sense, a traitor to the

workers by filling them with half-baked and chimerical ideas which

distracted their attention from practicable reforms. Both can find

apparently conclusive texts, but Proudhon was both honest and

disinterested, only he had mistaken his abilities; he was not a

philosopher; he was not an economist; he was a moralist, for whom the

object of all social and economic arrangements was not the increasing of

the level of material well-being, but the creation of a society in which

the great law of the universe, the subordination of all ends to the rule

of Justice, embodied in independent and equal men (or, more strictly,

heads of families) was, at last, after thousands of years of error, to

be given free play. This preoccupation with right saved Proudhon from

difficulties which assailed other socialist leaders, for he did not

promise to increase production. His arguments against capitalism were

not arguments, based on its inefficiency, but on its injustice.

Occasionally, he does make optimistic prophecies; when he is trying to

refute Malthus, he makes bold assertions of the greater rapidity of the

growth of production compared with human fertility, but his heart is not

in such demonstrations. He believed, that the human race was destined to

work harder and harder and, indeed, it was this increasing burden of

labour that would solve the population problems by making continence

easy to the weary labourers. The most that Proudhon promises is the

diversion to useful work of the soldiers, officials and other

unproductive members of society made necessary by the present state

system and, in addition, the equalisation of property rights will force

the idle rich into productive activities. This is something but not

much, for even when the rich and their political parasites have got off

the backs of the poor, those backs will still be bent by the natural

necessity of unceasing toil. Although Proudhon talked a great deal about

the division of labour, he was really doubtful of its economic efficacy.

He thinks that the labour saved is merely diverted into other equally

unproductive channels, and this is the basis of his persistent objection

to free trade. On his own principles, he was bound to oppose free trade.

One of the few legitimate activities of the state was to even out the

different factors of production. The owner of a hundred acres in the

Beauce should not thereby be allowed to ruin the owner of a hundred

acres in the Cantal; and, still less, should the producers of France be

rained by American wheat and Lancashire cotton. But Proudhon is not

content with this application of his equalitarian theories. At the end

of his life he tried to show that the Cobden Treaty was wholly

deceptive, because even if the price of cotton goods went down, the

price of wine would go up equally! Bordeaux and Manchester would benefit

at the expense of the cotton spinners of Rouen and of the French worker

who would no longer be able to afford his native wine. Without going

very far into the argument, it is easy to see that Proudhon did not

understand or refused to consider what the free trade case was and he

would have been well advised not to plunge into a controversy for which

he was ill-fitted.

If his pamphlets and his trial brought Proudhon fame, they did not bring

him fortune. With a simplicity which never left him, he thought that the

government and social order which he had been assailing would give him a

job. Needless to say, the two official posts he had hoped for, were not

wasted on so incorrigible an agitator; and he had to shoulder the debts

of his unfortunate printing business, the burden of his parents without

an income with the ending of his ÂŁ 6o a year from his three years

scholarship. He had never been so poor as he was just after he had

become famous. He found an employer in a judge who had a desire to win a

reputation as a criminologist and for whom Proudhon was to furnish

information and ideas. It was not a dignified post, but he thought he

could smuggle his ideas into the work of the eminently respectable

judge. Even a judge could see through this trick, for Proudhon, in his

Machiavellian moments, had a marked resemblance to the villain of

melodrama who hisses behind his hand, ‘I don’t mean a word of what I am

telling this simpleton.’ The collaboration and the income came to an

end, but Proudhon was now deep in the writing of a great philosophical

work of which he had, in advance, the highest possible opinion, seeing

himself as another Newton. He had got rid of his printing business at a

loss of ÂŁ 4oo, a terrible burden of debt for one in his position and his

livelihood was a most urgent problem. An old school friend took him into

his firm, Gauthier Brothers; the business was that of transporting coal

on the Rhone-Saone system and Proudhon became an expert on river

transportation, and, in his own eyes, a master of business method. As

was usual with him, all his experience was worked into his philosophy.

It reinforced his belief that other revolutionaries who knew nothing of

book-keeping were unworthy of attention, for book-keeping by double

entry applied to society was the solution of all social problems; so

arithmetical arguments now begin to come in at suitable and unsuitable

moments. Gauthier’s business was beginning to suffer from the

competition of railways; and Proudhon began to write on railway

economics. Theorists might talk about savings in time and money, but he

knew, that if it were not for the double-dealing of the government under

the influence of the speculators, the canals and rivers of France would

hold their own and departments which had river communications in their

territory would not have their vested interests ruined by the selfish

greed of the other departments which cared nothing for the bargemen or

stevedores of Lyons, if only they could get their goods carried cheaply

and quickly from Paris to Marseilles! It is difficult to decide if he

detested railways more for being so often under the control of

Saint-Simonists (who were also Jews), than he detested Saint-Simonists

for being builders and exploiters of railways! When Proudhon tries to

discuss railways and canals the ‘fallacy of misplaced concreteness’ is

seldom far away!

But business was only a means of livelihood; the passion for preaching

was as strong as ever. He dreamed of editing a newspaper; he engaged in

an attack on the famous Dominican preacher, Lacordaire; and he published

his treatise On the Creation of Order in Humanity, or Principles of

Political Organisation. This is a confused work which its author

afterwards regretted. It shows the high-water mark of Fourier’s

influence and some of Proudhon’s disillusionment with it may be due to

this inconvenient fact; but there is a good deal of essential Proudhon

scattered through these ill-planned pages, most characteristic, perhaps,

in the announcement of the true object of political economy. ‘Either

political economy is a hoax and those who teach it are liars: or it

really has as its object, the centralisation of industrial forces, and

the disciplining of the market.’

If The Creation of Order was ambitious, the book which grew out of it

was more ambitious still, for Proudhon was convinced that he had

discovered fundamental contradictions in the writings of the classical

economists. He proposed to show the existence of these contradictions

and, later, to harmonise them. So the motto of his new book was Destruam

et Aedificabo (I shall destroy and build up). He secured as publishers,

Guillaumin, the leading economic publishers, and they insisted in

tempering the vigour of his assaults on the orthodox economists. The

book appeared on October 15, 1846, under the title of The System of

Economic Contradictions or the Philosophy of Poverty.

Although there are still writers who regard this book, highly, its main

importance, to-day, is that it marked the occasion of Proudhon’s break

with Marx. The latter, as a refugee in Paris, had made Proudhon’s

acquaintance and, for a time there was a brisk exchange of ideas between

them. Marx later professed to have indoctrinated Proudhon with Hegel-

and to regret it, since Proudhon was incapable of using the dialectical

method successfully and was only led further astray by his attempts to

do so. This Proudhon would not admit and, indeed, the question was

little moment, for Hegel, like Kant, was mere topdressing for Proudhon’s

ideas and he was quit capable of getting a smattering of Hegelian

language from other sources than Marx. A rupture was bound to come; each

was a born teacher, but a poor disciple; each was jealous of fame and of

authority. Sorel suggests that Marx came to resent the influence which

Proudhon had acquired in Germany at a time when he, the learned doctor,

was still unknown and there are some evidences of this in the

confutation of Proudhon which Marx hastened to publish. Bo apart from

personal differences, the doctrinal positions of the two men were widely

apart. For Proudhon, socialism was primarily a solution for moral

problem, the deliverance of the individual from the fetters imposed on

him by the industrial system; he was not, and never pretended to be,

communist. For Marx, there were no absolute moral truths which had

existed from the beginning of time and which the French Revolution had

revealed; the fundamental force was the organisation of the methods of

production. A clash between the materialist and the spiritualist views

of history was inevitable. In any case, Proudhon, for all his

pretensions, was not a system builder, he repeated, in various forms,

what he considered a few fundamental truths, but he recoiled from a new

orthodoxy, especially one coming from another source and animated by

another spirit. Before he broke with Marx, he appealed to him ‘to give

an example of a learned and foresighted tolerance .. don’t let us pose

as apostles of a new religion, even of the religion of logic, the

religion of reason.’ On these terms, he thought it possible to

co-operate with Marx, and he willingly awaited Marx’s criticisms of his

book. ‘I am willing to accept the rod from your hands, if there is

reason for it, and with good grace, waiting for my revenge.’ The rod did

descend, but not on a grateful victim!

Marx’s criticism took the form of a long, able, hostile and angry tract

called The Poverty of Philosophy. Proudhon would not have been Proudhon

-or a human being — if he had remained passive under this assault. Marx

was still obscure, (twenty years later, for Proudhon’s first biographer,

Saint-Beuve, he had remained obscure), and he hurt Proudhon’s pride as

well as his doctrines. He declared that Proudhon owed his reputation in

France to the belief that he was a master of German philosophy and, in

Germany to the belief that he was a master of French economics; both of

these beliefs, as Marx proposed to show, were erroneous. Proudhon was a

clever pamphleteer who had overestimated his strength and, far from

being a leader of the social revolution, was a champion of the most

backward class of all, that of the ‘lesser bourgeoisie’ to which he

belonged, a class doomed to disappear, and one whose wriggles under the

harrow of modem capitalism had no permanent historical interest and

could in no way affect the movement of society. In attempting to erect

the prejudices of this class into eternal laws of nature, in his

preoccupation with ‘right’ and ‘wrong’, instead of with the dialectical

movement of history, Proudhon showed his incapacity for understanding

either philosophy or economics; he neither understood, Hegel nor could

apply Ricardo. ‘The work of M. Proudhon is not simply a treatise on

political economy, an ordinary book, it is a Bible. “Mysteries”,

“Secrets dragged from the bosom of God”, “Revelations”, nothing is

lacking.’ These rhetorical passages are irrelevant, but they are

symptomatic of Proudhon’s mind, for he thinks of economic activity as

subordinated to ethical activity, but if the work of one man is now

worth that of another, ‘it is not the doing of M. Proudhon’s “eternal

justice”, it is solely the accomplishment of modern industry’.

This assault, when it came, infuriated Proudhon. He had expected attacks

from the right. His patient friend, Bergmann, had reproached him with

the pamphleteering character he had given to what passed for a work of

science, but Proudhon defended his personalities. ‘To my mind, in

politics, in practical morals, in social science, in all that concerns

active life and the actuality of societies, theories are not merely

ideas, abstractions of the mind; they are interests, influences,

alliances, intrigues, persons as well.’ But what was sauce for the goose

was not sauce for the gander; and the ‘libel of a Doctor Marx’ was ‘a

tissue of insults, abuse, calumnies, falsifications and plagiarisms’. As

the notes he made on his copy show, Proudhon thought that The Poverty of

Philosophy was merely an expression of jealousy on Marx’s part. ‘The

real meaning of Marx’s work is that he regrets that, all through, I have

thought like him and that I have said it before him’. Whatever Marx’s

motives may have been (and he was not altogether an amiable man!) this

was not one of them, for the two, men differed profoundly as to method

and as to object.

But even to-day it is still not enough to say of a book, to dispose of

it, that Marx did not approve. The merits of the two men were very

different and Proudhon might have incurred just criticism and yet the

book be, in the main, a good one. To one reader, at least, it seems a

bad one. It loses, by its length and diffuseness, the fighting point of

the Memoirs on Property; if it has dropped much of the terminology, it

preserves much of the confusion of The Creation Of Order; it has more

than the usual share of rhetoric and less than the usual share of

eloquence. God is brought in and then asmued as the origin of evil. The

refusal, or inability, to understand what the classical economists were

driving at, makes long passages mere verbiage. There is the customary

assault on railways and the usual philology, ingeniously defended to

Bergmann, who thought it irrelevant — and, as philology, bad. But if

Proudhon’s genius is often hidden, it sometimes flashes out. He wins a

few verbal, if not substantial, victories over his antagonists; and

there are momentary triumphs of his irony. ‘What need have we now of the

dietary rules of the Church? Thanks to taxes, all the year is Lent for

the worker; and his Easter dinner is not equal to the Bishop’s Good

Friday collation.’ But there were people whom the book impressed and

events were soon to make of its author, an actor, instead of merely an

observer.

CHAPTER III: THE REVOLUTIONARY LEADER

PROUDHON had grown more and more discontented with his job; it kept him

away from Paris, in Lyons and travelling round the provinces. Even at

the best of times he was not easy to get on with. ‘I felt,’ he wrote to

Bergmann, ‘something that was unsuitable and, above all, in the way they

carried it on’; so, in October, 1847, he settled in Paris, hoping to

make a place for himself, to start a newspaper, The People, which ‘will

be the first act of the economic revolution, the plan of campaign of

work against capital....I hope the editing will be as original as the

position is exceptional.’ He made his preparations, badly shaken by the

death of his mother,‘worn out, like my father, by age, difficulties,

toil, weariness....I cannot accustom myself to the idea that nobody

cares about me, that my old mother is gone.’ the temperature of the

political battle was rising; but Proudhon looked on the parliamentary

battle with scorn. ‘The best thing that could happen for the French

people, would be the throwing of a hundred members of the opposition

into the Seine with millstones round their necks.....They are worth a

hundred times less than the conservatives, for they are hypocrites into

the bargain.’ But this was not the solution that was found; for, on

February 24, the bourgeois monarchy fell, with less resistance and far

less dignity than had the elder line of the Bourbons. The sceptical

observer of politics had taken part in the overthrow. Proudhon had gone

out when the fighting was taking place and had been called on by Flocon,

one of the leaders of the revolt, to serve the revolution with his

trade. He had set up the manifesto: ‘Citizens, Louis-Philippe is having

you murdered as did Charles X; send him to rejoin revolution triumph;

and he was filled with contempt both for the government which had

collapsed so feebly and for the leaders of the revolt who were being

carried to power on a wave of popular feeling. The workers were all

right, gay, brave, joking, honest. But, on the morning after the

victory, when all Paris had lost its head with enthusiasm, Proudhon kept

his. The revolution had no plan. ‘It must be given a direction and

already I see it perishing in a flood of speeches.’ However, ‘I should

prefer to believe that my point of view is false, rather than accuse

everybody else of folly.’ Proudhon was no a model of prudence and , when

he was engaged in conflict, he often lost all sense of proportion, but

to have written this diagnosis of the Revolution of February 24, on

February 25, was an astonishing feat of penetration for it was Proudhon

who was right — and the naive enthusiasts who were wrong.

The early illusions were natural enough; the bourgeois monarch had gone,

with hardly a show of resistance, why should the bourgeoisie itself not

be as easily displaced? As for the society which should be built on the

ruins of the old order, were there not plenty of acute critics and bold

constructors to be pressed into service? Was there not Louis Blanc? Were

there not the Fourierists and the Saint -Simonists, and Cabetians? Was

there not Proudhon who had promised to provide a solution of the

contradictions of the old system? Some of the workers remembered

Proudhon; they called on him and pressed him into service on February

26; two days after the fall of the monarchy. They offered to provide

paper and a printer. Proudhon consented; he was to have his journal at

last and he was launched on the dangerous career of a party leader; he

had now both to preach his doctrine and get it accepted. He stood as a

candidate for the Doubs (Franche-Comté) and for Paris. He appealed to

Louis Blanc, who represented socialism in the Provisional Government, in

an effort to find common ground. Despite his avowed intentions of

conciliating masters and workers, he was not elected — and Louis Blanc

snubbed him. He had for the moment, to preach his doctrine through

pamphlets and through his newspaper, The Representative of the People.

What did he preach?

The essential doctrine in Proudhon is the identification of Justice with

equality and the coercion of economic life into accord with Justice. The

necessity and possibility of equality was taken as obviously true; all

economic reasoning had to end with equality. So, for the theory of

value, Proudhon substitutes a theory of the just price. If the orthodox

economists say that value is not fixed, but is a relation between supply

and demand, they are condemned out of their own mouths, for what meaning

can ‘value’ have if it is not certain? Room is left for the ‘higgling of

the market’, but, for Proudhon, this is no metaphor; he really means the

higgling of the market, the chaffering in the village square between the

man selling a cow and the man selling fodder. The just price is revealed

by this higgling; the two parties discover, by higgling, what is the

real price of a cow and of fodder in terms of each other; it will lie

between the highest demand and the lowest offer in each case, but the

range of variation is small, for value is based on the cost of

production. It is doubtful if Proudhon appreciated all the ambiguities

hidden under his ‘cost of production’, but he saw some of them. The cost

of production is that of the average producer, a price fixed by the

practice of the trade. How that customary price is to be fixed without

‘market-anarchy’ we are not clearly told. A healthy society is that in

which all production is organized on a basis of mutuality, when

producers agree to be consumers of the goods produced by each other.

When that occurs, all prices will be ‘constituted’; the present anarchy,

in which all goods are priced in money will be ended; and the monopoly

of money, and of credit, which is the stronghold of

counter-revolutionary capitalism, will fall.

Proudhon’s immediate object was to persuade the workers — and the

government — that it was easy to bring about this state of affairs, to

give the revolution a real social content. What is needed is cheap, or

rather , free credit. It is impossible to understand Proudhon’s views on

this question without knowing what he believed about money. Money (gold

and silver) were the only commodities whose value was constituted; this

gave their possessors an unfair advantage over the producers of

unconstituted values. It is doubtful how far Proudhon realised that gold

and silver had a variable price like all other goods. He talks of a

happy time if gold and silver were as plentiful as iron and copper and

so no more valuable, but it is doubtful if he saw the implications of

this remark. A price level was not interpreted by him as an aspect of

the price of money. Marx had asked him if he really believed that

everything could be dear at the same time and it seems probable that he

did! Gold and goods could both be dear. In form, at any rate, Proudhon

was a fanatical deflationist. He believed that there was some social

gain in an absolutely uniform and symmetrical reduction of prices. All

his life he thought of low prices, not as a sign of abundance, but as a

good in themselves; the Restoration became a golden age in retrospect,

because prices had been so low. ‘Real wages’ is a conception which is

seldom traceable in Proudhon’s work. The first measure he advocated, was

a rigorous deflation of all costs, not to meet world competition, not to

shift a burden from one class to another, but simply to make the meagre

supply of money go further. There was to be a general reduction of

interest charges, the bank-rate, salaries and wages. Proudhon thought

this programme quite practicable, and in some forms of it, he argued

that no one would lose, that the total result would be to have everybody

where they started — except that all goods would be cheaper. When he

advocated this, in his debate with Thiers, the latter asked, naturally

enough, what was the good of going to all that trouble? In fact, of

course, as Thiers pointed out, Proudhon’s schemes would not result in a

uniform reduction, but in a reduction of the returns from one kind of

property, that based on fixed-interest charges: it was fixed interest,

not property as such, that Proudhon, at this moment of his career,

regarded as theft. Marx, Bastiat, Thiers, Walras, all in vain pointed

out that interest was only an aspect of property; that it was

inseparable from property. Proudhon was adamant, interest was wrong

because only labour could create wealth; the owner of capital did no

work when he lent it, so that any interest on it was stolen from the

borrower of the capital.

There are two classes of writers on credit, those who believe that a

bird in the hand is always worth a bird plus something in the bush; and

those who regard this supposed axiom as a superstition. Proudhon

belonged to the second class. For him, lending was no hardship, you only

lent something for which you had no immediate use and you got it back

intact after the period agreed upon. Where, then, was the privation for

which Bastiat and the other preachers of orthodoxy said you had to be

compensated? At times, pressed in formal controversy, Proudhon hesitated

and allowed various charges to be made for loans, but interest as such

was wrong. It was one of the errors of the Church that having once

grasped the moral and economic truth that interest was wrong, she had

wavered and tried to make distinctions between banking and usury; there

was no distinction, all interest for the use of money or goods was

usury. In Proudhon’s money market, only demand counted; usury would

stop. That lending might stop too; and that a credit structure, based on

loans which were no privation to the lender, might be rather inadequate

for the needs of society did not occur to him, for the time element was

disregarded. He seems, at moments, to regard the importance attached to

immediate possession as a counter-revolutionary superstition and when he

reflects that what prevents a farmer who, over thirty years, pays the

total value of his farm in rent, from thereby becoming its owner, is the

insistence of the proprietor of the land on money down, his indignation

is at least as much directed at the stupidity, as at the cupidity of the

landlord! To declare that all rent should be deemed part purchase and

that the rent of money could thus be avoided seemed simple enough. It

was this illusion that property could be left intact and prevented from

having its fruits that infuriated Marx, who could find nothing worse to

say of Proudhon, as an economic controversialist, than that even Bastiat

was too much for him.

The bank-rate declared by the Bank of France seemed to Proudhon, not an

example of the general power of capital, but a result of the legal

monopoly given the bank. Let the state order the reduction of the

bank-rate and of all fixed charges to one percent or half percent and

the usurers would be defeated. Who, he asked, would borrow at five

percent if they could get money at a half percent if they could get

money at a half percent, this being a charge made merely to cover

book-keeping expenses? Who would lend at that price when by buying

property, instead of titles to money, they could evade this legislation,

was a question he did not answer! If he did not answer the question who

would lend money, he did answer the question, how would credit be

provided? By mutuality. The monopoly of capital could be broken if all

producers ignored the monetary system and exchanged the goods at just

prices, guaranteed by mutual confidence. As time was unimportant, the

knowledge that, at some time in the future, you would get a bag of flour

in return for the immediate delivery of three pairs of shoes, was all

that you could want. If all classes of producers were united in these

mutual agreements, money would be unnecessary and the entries on the

books of the bank would take their place. Book-keeping without money,

that was the panacea.

He demanded, therefore, that the government should decree that ‘since

direct exchange without money and without interest, is both part of

natural right and of public utility’, interest should be cut down and

free credit established. Failure to realise both the desirability and

practicability of this reform, was a sign of wickedness, or of

stupidity, or of both. Most left-wing leaders fell under this ban. Some

were communists and so enemies of liberty and the family; others were

absorbed in mere politics, in universal suffrage and other devices for

rendering harmless what was necessarily harmful, the authoritarian

state. In pursuit of these chimeras, they needlessly alienated the

middle classes who could be shown that they had as much interest in the

abolition of the credit monopoly as any worker. In the hectic atmosphere

of die spring and summer of 1848, when the old order seemed to be

collapsing everywhere, Proudhon, like many others, acquired a following.

At a by-election in June, he was elected to the assembly from Paris with

a very handsome majority. He now had to play the part of the statesman,

and his conduct in the next few months alienated him from most of his

political allies, and so drove him further towards his natural goal,

anarchy.

By the time Proudhon entered the assembly the revolution was obviously

ebbing. The crushing of the revolt of the workers in the days of June

showed that bourgeois society was stronger than had seemed possible in

March. The countryside had sent an immense conservative majority to the

assembly, and reaction grew stronger every day. Proudhon, despite some

rash words, was against trying to remedy this state of affairs by armed

revolt, but he was himself a scarecrow to right-thinking people. A play

was put on called Property is Theft, and Proudhon was daily abused as a

monster, inspired by the Devil. His newspaper was suppressed again and

again, and Proudhon was a liability to the left-wing parties who were

now trying to save something out of the wreck. When Proudhon, on July

31, declared his policy to the assembly, that body voted that ‘the

preposition of Citizen Proudhon is an odious attack on the principles of

public morals’. There were only two disentient votes, that of Proudhou

himself and of Greppo. The rift with the left-wing leaders continued to

grow. Proudhou refused to vote against the reactionary ministry of which

his old protector, Vivien, was a member. He fought a duel with FĂ©lix

Pyat, and would have had to fight others had he not refused to be bound

by the conventions of French politics. He was a leader of the extreme

left section which broke up party unity in the presidential election by

running Raspail against Ledru-Rollin. Out of seven million votes cast,

Raspail got thirty thousand. The unknown Louis Napoleon Bonaparte, whom

Proudbon had tried to indoctrinate, was elected, and Proudhon poured out

abuse on the new head of France whom many critics felt he had done much

to elect. The assembly was not slow to take its chance to reprove

sedition in the person of the enemy of society, and it allowed Proudhon

to be tried for his attacks on the head of the state. He was sentenced

to three years’ imprisonment and three thousand francs fine. He had just

started his ‘Bank of the People’, but the chance of trying out his

theories was lost. He escaped to Belgium, but was rash enough to return

to Paris, was denounced, and sent to prison.

His life as an active politician was at an end; and he had the leisure

to think out his system and digest the experience of the past year. He

had also a new tie to take the place left vacant by his mother, for he

had married a poor seamstress, Euphrasie PiĂ©gard, ‘with premeditation,

without passion, to be a father of a family, to have a complete life,

and to have by me, in the vortex into which I have cast myself, an image

of maternal simplicity and modesty’. His wife was a fit companion for an

agitator; ill-educated, but an excellent manager and resolute in all

difficulties. He married outside the Church, a great triumph for him,

for his wife’s father was a royalist of the extreme right. The

inconveniences of such a connection were to be made evident when his

father-in-law was sentenced to two years’ imprisonment for a royalist

conspiracy after a trial, of which the most interesting document was a

petition to the Pretender, the Comte de Chambord, written by Proudhon;

himself ! It was, said Proudhon, a hoax, but by that time (1853), he had

enough enemies to rub it in to him that there are follies which look

like crimes. For the moment, marriage calmed him. His wife lived

opposite the prison, Sainte-PĂ©lagie, and in November, 1850, Proudhon was

delighted by the birth of daughter.

For the greater part of his prison life, he was very leniently treated,

by British standards, allowed daily visits from his wife, and allowed to

go out of prison. He wrote for his paper, now a weekly called The

People, and even managed to get tried and acquitted for another violent

piece of journalism. As the reaction got stronger, and as the resistance

of the left took the criminally foolish form of the insurrection of

June, 1849, Proudhon’s prison liberties were restricted. He was, for a

period, sent to Doullens and to Bourges, where he met most of the other

left-wing leaders and was characteristically scornful of them. ‘The one

thing I dislike more than persecutors,’ he was reported to say, ‘are

martyrs.’ He had himself been a victim of June, for the National Guard,

now the storm-troopers of reaction, had destroyed his printing plant.

The futile appeals to more rebellion which came from the exiles

infuriated him and, when the dying Republic was snuffed out by the

President’s coup d’ etat of December 2, 1851, Proudhon’s dislike of the

victors was considerably tempered by his scorn of the vanquished. By

sweeping away the debris of democracy, the dictator was leaving the way

clear for the prophet of the true revolutionary doctrine — anarchy.

Proudhon’s place in the history of anarchy is secure; there were moments

of inconsistency; moments of wavering when he looked to the state and

even to mere politics for deliverance, but, as he announced in the First

Memoir, ‘I am an anarchist’ -and he remained one. Anarchy was in the

air; many reformers besides Proudhon were anxious to carry out the

Saint-Simonist programme and to substitute ‘the administration of things

for the administration of men’. By anarchy, Proudhon meant the absence

of a master and of subjects. He was always sceptical of mere differences

in political form. He was a republican by temperament; his devotion to

the revolution as the dawn of equality made it hard for him to tolerate

such a glaring exception to equality as hereditary monarchy; but he

never attached a sufficient importance to the sacred word ‘republic’ to

qualify as quite orthodox among the writers and politicians of the left.

What he wanted of a government was that it should commit suicide

gracefully, giving way to the free anarchical society without trying to

make the birth of the new order difficult. If the House of Orleans would

put itself at the disposal of the Revolution, Proudhon would put up with

the anomaly of hereditary political power. He was willing, later, to

make the same bargain with the House of Bonaparte, and he saw nothing to

choose between a monarchical and a democratic tyranny. Indeed, he was a

blasphemer of revolutionary orthodoxy; at times a defender of the memory

of the Bourbons, even of Charles X, a praiser of the Charter of 1814,

and an assailant of the Jacobins whose divine right of the majority was

as outrageous in theory and far more dangerous in fact than the divine

right of ‘Henry V’. When personally infuriated he was willing to believe

any nonsense about Napoleon III, ready to credit his imminent deposition

at the hands of palace conspirators, but never willing to put his

differences with the imperial government on the ground of political

illegitimacy. Universal suffrage was a delusion; but a government

professing to be based on it should not be allowed to tamper with its

working, yet the obsession of ‘the Jacobins’ with mere politics, the

attempt to get the state into their own hands, was a deception of the

people, for if property was theft, the state was tyranny, be it empire

or republic. The ideal to be aimed at in matters of government is not

‘direct legislation or direct government or simplified government, but

no more government’. As early as 1840, Proudhon had declared that most

of the functions of government will disappear, and those which remain

will take on a scientific character, a science of which the data are

statistics (for the belief in book-keeping was present before the

experience of it); but, if the basis of anarchy is present in What is

Property?, it is in the books written after the death of the illusions

of 1848 that the doctrine is set forth in most detail and with most

enthusiasm. A state, Proudhon had finally learned, could only be an evil

whether it was ruled by Ledru-Rollin or by Louis Napoleon. Government

was always for the governors, never for the governed. No democratic

machinery could alter the fact that those who detained power were

masters and those who had to obey, servants. All sophisms of the general

will, all social contracts in the manner of Rousseau which attempted to

explain away the necessary surrender of liberty involved in any powerful

state, were enemies of the rights of every man to rule ‘himself, not in

fiction, but in fact. Not only was the state an evil, it was not a

necessary evil. ‘The social constitution,’ he wrote in The Confessions

of a Revolutionary, ‘is bound up with human nature, liberal, necessary

... its development consists above all in weakening and getting rid of

the political constitution which is essentially artificial, restrictive

and transitory.’ How was the state to be replaced and society given its

constitution? By the magic power of contract. No lawyer, not even Sir

Henry Maine, had a more lyrical conception of the glories of contract

than had Proudhon. Mutual contracts were to solve the problem of

exchange and of credit,” they were also to solve the problem of

political organisation. The General Idea of the Revolution in the

Nineteenth Century is a hymn to contract. ‘The idea of contract excludes

that of government.... What characterises the contract, the mutual

convention, is that in virtue of this convention man’s liberty and

wellbeing increase, whilst by the institution of an authority, both

necessarily diminish.’ The object of social science is ‘to find a form

of bargin which, bringing to unity the divergence of interests,

identifying the private and the general good, effacing the inequality of

nature by that of education, resolves all political and economic

contradictions; where each individual is equally and synonymously

producer and consumer; citizen and prince; administrator and

administered; where his liberty always increases, without any need ever

to alienate any part of it; where his wellbeing grows indefinitely,

without his experiencing, from society or from his fellow-citizens, any

injury either in his property or his work or in his income or in his

connections of interest or affection with his kind’.

How was this paradise to be reached? Not by the aid of government, that

was Louis Blanc’s error. A government cannot be paternal if it is

limited, for, asks Proudhon, ‘what father ever thought of a bargain with

his family.... The authority whose seat is in the family is a mystical

principle, anterior and superior to the will of the people concerned’,

but society has no such basis for its authority. On the other hand, an

unlimited authority in the state is inequality, tyranny....‘The rule of

contracts substituted for the rule of laws would constitute ... the real

sovereignty of the people, the REPUBLIC.’ Proudhon was conscious that

his faith in contract was not universally shared. ‘You imagine that it

is impossible to fulfil these conditions. The social contract, when you

consider the frightful number of relations it ought to regulate ... seem

something like squaring the circle or perpetual motion. That is why,

worn out with the fight, you relapse into despotism and force...

Realise, however, that if the social contract can be concluded between

two producers -and who doubts that, in this simple form, there is a

solution? — it can equally be concluded between millions since the

undertaking is the same, and the number of signatures — while they make

it more and more effective — do not add an article [to the agreement].

Your alleged inability is non-existent then; it is ridiculous and makes

you inexcusable.’

Given the practicability of a society so organised, it must be

understood that the contractual basis of society does not create rights

and obligations not set out in the bond. All this talk about

‘association’ is dangerous, for it implies that there is a common will

in the associates, that the body they create has a life of its own

outside the narrow objects for which it has been created. But such

theories are conducive to tyranny. A society for production creates no

bond between its members outside those indispensable for the economic

activity of the society. The absolute independence of each member must

be observed. No social food is worth the price of liberty. Naturally,

such a doctrine made its author suspicious of trade unions, and strikes

he abhorred from the beginning to the end of his life.

As was usual with Proudhon, he destroyed before he built up. Even in the

comparatively early expositions (The General Idea of the Revolution: The

Confessions of a Revolutionary), written under the shadow of the

disasters of 1848–49, Proudhon recognises that the state will not

disappear at once, although, for obvious reasons, he is convinced that

if other state institutions may have a little life in them, the judicial

system must be immiediately abolished for the state has no right to

punish, although a man may ask to be punished.

The apparent necessity of the state is due to economic inequality,

because of the absence of justice. When all men have bound themselves to

mutual justice, the need for the coercive apparatus of the state will

vanish. Even in the present system, the claims of the state are

exaggerated. France has to endure an immense army, hordes of officials,

a splendid court, all necessitating an overwhelming burden of taxation,

because Frenchmen are vain; because they want their country to make a

great impression in the world. They are the victims of any skilful

jingo. What good does it do them? They are worse off than the Swiss, who

have no such illusions.Their vast and expnsive army ought to be replaced

by a militia which would be competent for defence, but not for tyranny.

In any case, there is not one French nation; there are thirty submerged

nationalities in France, and, in a rationally organised society, these

‘nations’ would be the natural unitsof government. The deadly

centralisation beloved of tyrants, Bonapartes and Jacobins, with their

fetish of ‘indivisible France’ would be destroyed, to the benefit of all

concerned, even of Paris. As long as Paris has concentrated within her

walls, the government, the financial and educational institutions of the

country; as long as the whole of France is taxed to adorn the capital

with splendid buildings; so long it will be impossible to permit Paris

to have any active political life of her own.

The solution to this, as to other governmental problems, was federalism.

This was the answer to the contradictions Proudhon thought he had shown

to exist in the political sphere, the clash between government, even

‘democratic’ government and liberty. The smaller the unit, the greater

degree of freedom in government. The great industrial units should rule

themselves and a federalism, based on the free cooperation of the

communes and provinces, would solve the purely governmental problems.

The commune (the parish or town) should rule itself, provide for its own

justice and its own educational needs. The intrusion of the central

government into these fields should cease. The commune should even

provide and control its own church. The great day of the Revolution was

the day of the Federation, before Jacobin absolutism had diverted the

Revolution from the true path.

This enthusiasm for federalism affected Proudhon’s judgment of current

events in odd ways. He bitterly regretted the annexation of Savoy to

France. What fools the Saveyards were to let themselves be tricked by

their clergy into voting for annexation to France when they might have

become a free Swiss Canton! In any case, how disgusting was the

spectacle of Victor Emmanuel abandoning the land of his ancestors!

Italian unity is only a hoax for is not the destruction of Tuscan

nationality a great disaster? The real greatness of Italy is only

possible in a federal state. So we find Proudhen defending the projected

Italian confederation against the blind admirers of Mazzini and

lamenting the defeat of the armies of King Francis of Naples! The

spectacle of the great revolutionary fostering the same sacred flame as

Cardinal Antonelli and ‘King Bomba’s Lazzaroni’ was startling enough,

but Proudhon even asserted that the Lombard peasants were quite

indifferent whether their oppressors were Italians or Austrians. Indeed,

Austria, by moving in the path of federalism, was making her place in

the forefront of civilisation secure, while Italy was going back!

Real unity, he was to write at the end of his life, ‘was in inverse

proportion to size; so, in every collectivity, organic power loses in

intensity what it gains in extension and reciprocally.... Apply this law

to politics; a state is essentially one, indivisible, inviolable: the

bigger her population and area grow, the further force of cohesion and

the unity of the government will decrease .... Let branches be formed,

let colonies be formed... these will form a federal bond with the mother

state — or even will have no connection at all.’ Small states or

communes, directly ruled by freemen, who were economically equal, each

master of his trade or of his farm — and of his family, that was

Proudhon’s ideal community; a community like the Battant of his youth,

but not under the guns of the citadel of Besancon nor at the disposal of

a prefect sent from Paris! In a federal organisation for each country

and for Europe as a whole, Proudhon, at the end of his life, asserted

that he had found the solution of the political problem he had posed in

1840. He had destroyed — he now built up. ‘I began by anarchy, the

conclusion of my criticism of the idea of government, to finish by

federation, as the necessary base of European public law and, later on,

of the organisation of all states. On all this question, it is easy to

see that logic, right and liberty are dominant; so that public order

basing itself directly on the liberty and conscience of the citizen,

anarchy, the absence of all restraint, of all police, authority, judges,

legal rules, etc., is discovered to be the correlative of the highest

social virtue and the ideal of human government. No doubt we are far

away from it, and it will take centuries before we reach this ideal; but

our LAW is to advance in that direction.’

CHAPTER IV: PROUDHON AND JUSTICE

While Proudhon was formulating his doctrine of anarchy, he was watching

the political situation with impatience and with hope. He was lucky to

be imprisoned when the conflict between the assembly and the president

was coming to a head. He had not to choose between a reactionary

parliament and a probably reactionary dictator. Proudhon made no point

of political orthodoxy. He had always been sceptical of universal

suffrage, and if the sight of millions of Frenchmen putting their

destinies in the hands of Louis Napoleon disgusted him, it did not

surprise him. He had not thought France ready for revolution in 1848;

now it was obvious she was not; but having had to ‘jump out of the

first-floor window instead of coming downstairs one at a time’, Proudhon

was willing to make the best of a bad job. He saw clearly the dilemma in

which the President found himself. On the one hand, Louis Napoleon had

appealed to the conservative elements as the saviour of society; on the

other, he had dissolved the assembly which had limited the right to

vote, and was supposed to be preparing a monarchist restoration. All

governments were alike to Proudhon, dangerous institutions, but the new

one need not be any worse than the last. Let Louis Napoleon give proof

that he was with the Revolution and his ambition, his broken oath, and

the blood of December would be forgiven him. That proof above all, lay

in his religious policy. Proudhon was now a most determined

anti-clerical. In 1847 he had replied to the ritual question asked of

him when he was admitted as a Freemason. ‘What does man owe to God?’ by

the startling answer ‘War’; but not until the combination of the Church

with the conservatives in 1848, did he resolve on war to the death

against the clerical party. There were, in the Prince-President’s

circle, men as rigorously anti-clerical as Proudhon; notably Prince

Napoleon. Through common friends, Proudhon kept in touch with the

prince; he even visited him from time to time at the Palais Royal, to

the horror of the exiles in London and Brussels, to whom the crime of

the coup d’etat was inexpiable. Proudhon refused to leave France; he

refused, for instance, to take refuge in Sardinia. ‘Who the devil,’ he

asked, ‘expects enlightenment From Cagliari?’ He refused a more tempting

offer, for Albert Brisbane, the populariser of Fourier’s doctrines in

America, friend of all new ideas, and father of Mr. Hearst’s chief

leaderwriter, wanted to bring Proudhon to New York. He was free in his

denunciations of the allies of December 2, the ‘sabre and the holy-water

sprinkler’; but he believed he could make a bargain with the new rulers

of France. He would devote himself exclusively to science ‘with its

axioms, its determinations, its method, its own certainty, a science

which is neither mathematics nor jurisprudence, nor anything that is

called science at present .... After economic science a Philosophy of

History... and, later, a General Philosophy .... All this can be done in

France, in spite of despotism.’ Proudhon hoped, above all, to get

permission to start a journal in which he could assail the clericals and

induce the new regime to move to the left, but he was too notorious and

not tactful enough to be worth conciliating. His hopes were dashed again

and again; he was told that the Jesuits were behind the refusal of

permission; but he came to realise, slowly, that his days as a

journalist were over. He had his living to make, and he was full of

literary projects, among them being a History of Democracy, which

remained a fragment. In the meantime, he put together a potboiler called

The Manual of the Stock Exchange Speculator. Proudhon usually had the

highest opinion of his books while he was writing them, but grew

disillusioned after they were published; but he reversed this history in

the case of the Manual. Most of it was the work of Duchene, the former

manager of The People, but, as the book sold well, Proudhon put his own

name on the title-page of the third edition. The Manual is chiefly

devoted to describing various companies then quoted on the Paris Bourse

and has a limited interest to-day, but Proudhon was incapable of

writing, or even of revising anything and not marking it with his

personality. The Manual is a very characteristic work. Proudhoh displays

his scepticism about railways; his dislike of Saint-Simonisto who are

both capitalists and Jews; his belief in the immense possibilities of

mutuality and of the reform of credit; his hostility to the

possibilities of monopoly working through railway rebates, and a rather

pathetically optimistic belief in the future of co-operative societies

of production as a step towards a reformed society. His Railway Reform

was a vigorous assault on the imperial policy of creating vested

interests in the railways by giving concessions. By leaving the railways

too much freedom in fixing their charges, they are permitted to ruin

water transport and then to plunder the defenseless public. He believed,

however, that the growth of railways would lead to a decentralisation of

industry and the decay of the great towns — a prediction in the spirit

of his most distinguished disciple, Kropotkin. In any case when the

railways had completed their destuctive work, the old methods of

transport would come into their own!

Proudhon’s hopes of founding a review were now vanishing and he had

public and private motives to resent his enforced silence, for he had no

regular income and he thought his market-value as a journalist was high.

In any case, the Emperor was going over to the counter-revolution

embodied in the Church. Proudhon almost despaired of the French, during

the Crimean War he was ready to believe any bad news and sceptical about

good news. The rapid progress of the industrial system in France under

the Second Empire and the growth of speculation deceived this frivolous

people into thinking it was well off. The national debt kept rising and

the moral tone of the nation kept falling.

Bad temper and genuine indignation found a vent in the publication of

Proudhon’s greatest and most characteristic book. Of Justice in the

Revolution and the Church was ostensibly provoked by a clerical

journalist, Eugéne de Mirecourt, who had publish a brief sketch of

Proudhon. Proudhon had a horror of any intrusion into his private life,

and he flattered himself that he never introduced any personal animus or

scandal into his own writing. Mirecourt, indeed, could not find any

serious flaws in Proudhon’s morals, but, in any case, it was nobody’s

business if the revolutionary was a model husband and father. When

Proudhon learned that it was to Cardinal Mathieu, the Archbishop of

Besançon, that Mirecourt owed some of his information and that the

Cardinal had attributed Proudhon’s opinions to poverty and pride, his

rage boiled over. A fellow-citizen of Franche-Comté had so far forgotten

the obligations of that bond as to make Proudhon the victim of a

Parisian scribbler! A reply to the Cardinal was begun, a reply which

grew from a pamphlet into a book of over two thousand pages in which

Proudhon repeated almost all he had said, but with a fervour and an

eloquence that he had never equalled before. The main theme of the book

is declared in the title, Of Justice in the Revolution and the Church.

It is not merely a reply to Mirecourt or to the Cardinal; it is a

declaration of war against the Church, a demonstration of the

fundamental incompatibility of the teaching of the Church and the

teaching of the Revolution.

What is the nature of this incompatibility? It lies in the place given

to God in Catholic theology. Proudhon does not deny the existence of

God; but he is hostile to any idea of God which makes human action

depend on His action or which puts off to the next world the remedy for

the injustices of this. The central achievement of the Revolution was

that it brought down Justice from the sky to the earth. Where Christian

teaching had stressed charity, an idea involving more or less than

Justice, the Revolution asserts that Justice is the greatest need of man

-and that it is attainable. To look to God for aid in its achievement is

to corrupt the essential truth that all men hunger after Justice before

all other earthly goods; that Justice is immanent, not transcendental.

Christianity obscures this truth. It has many merits; it is the only

possible alternative to the rule of Justice; but whatever its services

in the past, since the Revolution abolished government by divine right,

all authorities depending on divine right, the Church, and even the

state, substituting the divine right of the people for the divine right

of the king, are condemned. They are a barrier in the way of progress,

the realisation of Justice on earth, Justice revealed in mutual respect,

in economic equality, and in the political equality that will follow

from it.

Most writers would not take two thousand pages to assert these dogmas,

and to illustrate them, but in the course of his argument, Proudhon is

not hampered by relevance. He is able to attack communism, both in the

form of early Christian communities and in that of the Fourierist

phalanstery. The closest reasoning of Bentham may make him a great

economist, but what avails that if he contemn Justice? But he is not

content with attacking opinions; he forgets his own sound principles and

assails persons. His outrageous assault on the memory of Heine shows him

at his worst; and his ostentatious refusal to indulge in mere

anti-clerical scandal mongering did not last long. The wickedness of

bishops who listen too readily to charges made against the morals of

their clergy is stressed in one place- and the truth of those charges

asserted in another. The Cardinal is asked to be grateful that Proudhon

does not dwell on ‘that bishop recently dead who became father to a

whole company of national guards; nor on that parish priest who, to the

sight and knowledge of his parishioners, had ten children by three

women’. This moderation was not as well received as Proudhon professed

to expect and, when he was asked for his authority, he had to write

furiously to a friend that ‘the two cases were told me by a naval

officer, or admiral, who was a witness of them in Spanish America or in

Brazil, I don’t know which .... This is called calumny.’ As Proudhon had

taken great pains to put his scandals on ‘this side of the Atlantic’,

the charge of calumny was not ill-founded; and it is easy to imagine the

fury with which any similar trick, played by Mirecourt, would have been

received!

In addition to philosophy, economics, morals and scandals, Proudhon

demonstrates his literary principles in Justice. They are not always

consistent. BĂ©ranger is ranked above Pindar, David, Horace. At another

time he is merely one of the greatest poets of the nineteenth century;

at another he is very mediocre. Most of the leading contemporary French

writers are relegated to inferior places because of their preoccupation

with art, instead of with teaching. Didactic poetry is the only poetry

worth writing or reading, so the future of Victor Hugo depends on his

abandoning La LĂ©gende des SiĂšcles for more pamphlets. The erotic novels

of George Sand naturally come off badly; English literature has long

been dead; French is now dead; but, not only in prose but in poetry,

French is the best of languages and literatures. That he had no

qualifications for passing on the merits of German or English literature

did not modify Proudhon’s confidence.

Not only does Proudhon wander; some of his old faults of pointless

logical jargon recur: ‘x being the average value of genius in the human

being, possibly there will be found exceptional individuals whose genius

equals x x 2; there are no geniuses equalling x x 3.’ ‘If, in strength,

man is to woman as 3 to 2; woman, in beauty, is in turn to man as 3 to

2. Neither the argument for natural equality, the suspicions of any

special claim for talent nor the firmly rooted belief that equality

between men does not involve equality between the sexes, are really

helped by the intrusion of crude mathematical proportions in fields of

judgrnent unfitted for them. More mathematics in his economics and less

in his aesthetics and morals would have improved Proudhon’s books!

If Proudhon’s rivals reproached him with terrifying the middle classes

by his association with the abolition of property, Proudhon was equally

angry with those who gave ground for the belief that socialism and free

love went together. For one thing, he had a low estimate of the

importance of sexual love. It was one of the detestable fruits of the

‘romantic scrofula’ that love was made essential to marriage. Marriage

had higher aims than the gratification of love or lust. Proudhon was

very proud of his own chastity, a form of pride singular enough in the

literary and reforming circles of that day. His own sexual passions do

not seem to have been strong, and he had no sympathy with those whose

passions were stronger. He could do without love as he could do without

tobacco, and the slaves of either of these bad habits had only to

imitate him to their profit. On this subject he was never tired of

preaching, preaching at its best worthy of Massillon, at its not

infrequent worst, rather recalling the powerful articles of Mr. James

Douglas. This enthusiasm for morality made Proudhon the victim of a

celebrated hoax, for he was led to send a letter of advice to a female

circus rider who was repenting an ill-spent life. The advice, if

rigorous, was good, but in the Paris of that time the joke was thought

even better-except by Proudhon, who was furious at the trick played on

him.

In nothing was Proudhon’s position more determinedly maintained than in

his attacks on feminism. His passion for equality was limited. If there

were races which could not be raised to the level of Frenchmen — let

them disappear, but he did not want woman to disappear or to claim

political or social equality with man. The outside world only reached a

woman, in a properly constituted society, through her husband or father.

She was always in tutelage, for she was in body and mind inferior to

man. No doubt she had high qualities of her own which man could not

imitate, but she reached them through man. In Paris corrupt through and

through, where woman novelists were allowed to sap the foundations of

morality and prostitutes flaunted the spoil that their keepers had

stolen on the Stock Exchange, these healthy truths were neglected, but

the traditional peasant view of woman’s place was unflinchingly asserted

by Proudhon and practised by him at home. He did not want of his wife,

or daughters, intellectual equality; he even thought religion a good

thing in its place for a sex incapable of rising to the high conception

af immanent Justice and of taking a place in the life of society in

their own right.

This sexual conservatism did not save Proudhon from prosecution, for the

drift of imperial policy from right to left had been interrupted by the

attempt to murder the emperor made by Orsini. In the reaction that

followed, Proudhon was a victim. Justice had had a great success; it was

seized and its author prosecuted for ‘attacks on public and religious

morals... defence of crimes... attacks against the respect due to law...

incitement of citizens to mutual hate and scorn ... publication of false

news.’ He fought back by ingenious petitions to the Senate, but was

condemned to three years imprisonment and 4,ooo francs fine. His

publisher got one month — and it proved a lesson to him. Appeals were

useless, and Proudhon had to flee to Belgium, where he learned the hard

lessons of life as an exile.

He settled down in Brussels in 1858, full of rage at his plight,

although candid friends pointed out that he had his own violence of

language to thank for it; it was folly to imagine that the imperial

government would let pass so good a chance of conciliating the Church by

sacrificing a pamphleteer who was as troublesome a friend as an enemy.

The first troubles of the exile were financial. Garnier had learned his

lesson. He would publish no more polemical works for Proudhon;

literature, yes, but politics and economics, no! Proudhon had calculated

on the profits of his books to free him from the constant money worries

that he had endured since he had left Lyons. Now he was cut off from his

market. He could write more freely in Belgium than in France, but he

could not reach the French public, or turn his writings into a means of

livelihood. He suffered from constant catarrh, which he blamed on the

Belgian climate; he objected to the high price of wine and to his forced

addiction to beer. Moreover, he made enemies in Belgium. He preached

against centralisation, thus annoying the politicians of Brussels; he,

the great anti-clerical, poured scorn on the Belgian liberals, saying he

preferred the Catholic party; and, if in France he was always attacking

the naive pride of his countrymen, he made it clear to his Belgian hosts

that France was still at the head of civilization. Events were moving

fast in France — and in the direction that Proudhon had advocated. The

Emperor decided, in 1859, to make war on Austria to free Italy. It was a

swerve to the left, to the party of the Revolution and it was so

regarded by observers on both sides. The left rejoiced; the right grew

more and more suspicious, for any upset of the status quo in Italy could

only harm the Pope. Proudhon refused to believe in the war; he refused

to believe in French victories; he refused to rejoice in them; and the

world was soon treated to the spectacle of the great revolutionary

praising the work of the Congress of Vienna; casting cold water on the

idea of Italian nationality; regretting the triumphs of Garibaldi;

abusing Mazzini; burning all the idols of the democratic party in

Europe. He asked, in the spirit of a modern French royalist, what was

the gain for France in creating another great power on her southern

frontier and abandoning the great political asset of being the

hereditary protector of the Pope? He added to his crimes by asserting

that Austria and Russia were truly progressive countries and by

attacking Poland. At that time, an ill-informed and sentimental sympathy

for Poland was as much the mark of a good radical as ill-informed and

sentimental hostility to Poland was the mark of a good modern radical —

until 1933. Poland, said Proudhon, was an aristocratic republic, which

died of her own vices; it should not be revived at the expense of the

future freedom of Russia. Russia, under an enlightened Tsar, is capable

of progress; Catholic Poland is not. The scandal caused was immense;

here was a lost leader indeed, but worse was to come when the apostle of

Justice preached the right of force in the last of his great treatises,

War and Peace.

The argument of this lengthy essay on international law is simple

enough. The great good of human society is equilibrium as a consequence

of the rule of justice, but force has its rights, which have to be

allowed for before a just equilibrium can be reached. Moreover, in war

man develops his personality and learns indispensable lessons of social

organisation: there are passages to the glory of war which would be in

place in a speech by Herr yon Papen, and Proudhon, who had attacked his

fellow-radicals for their jingoism, appeared as a defender of war when,

at long last, the French left parties were turning pacifist! It is true

that the age of war is asserted to be over, that ‘war, for every

attentive mind, has held its last assize from ’92 to 1815 . The

constitutional system, expression of the politics of interest, corollary

of the famous treaties of 1815, have given it notice to quit... Cursed

then be the nation which, forgetting herself, shall ask from war what

only science, work and liberty can give.’ But the conclusions of the

book are not altogether in accordance with its spirit. In his enthusiasm

for the ordeal by battle, Proudhon becomes a victim of what Mr. J. B. S.

Haldane has called ‘Bayardism’. He objects to strategy and deceit in

war. The object of battle is to discover which of the two parties to a

dispute is the stronger. If, by a stratagem or trick the less strong

side wins, the whole object of war is nullified, since what matters is

the relative strength and a victory of the weaker side over the stronger

is a deplorable falsification of judgment.

War and Peace is a natural pendant of Justice; it is an attempt to

discover how, in fact, rights have been created in the past. That much

of what we take to to be our national rights has been created by war;

that force has fights as well as possession; are truths that sentimental

democrats sometimes neglect, but, as usual, Proudhon was better in

criticism than in construction, and his picture of honourable war giving

place in the new society to equally honourable forms of peaceful

competition, is decidedly Utopian.

His exile came to an end in a most characteristic way. Having refused to

take advantage of an imperial amnesty, Proudhon was living in Brussels

in a dignified exile, when an article which he had written seemed to

advocate the annexation of Belgium to France. The Freemasons, according

to Proudhon, were at the bottom of the agitation which made Belgium too

hot to hold him, for he opposed the evacuation of Rome by the French

garrison. Whatever the cause, he hurriedly took refuge in France on

December 17, 1862; his wanderings were over and his doctrine, in the

main, complete.

He had been an indefatigable writer during his exile and had had the

triumph of winning a prize offered by the Swiss Canton of Vaud for the

best essay on taxation. That the free Swiss, that a state should thus

honour the exile, delighted him, and illustrated again the folly of the

French. According to Proudhon taxation is simply the share each citizeny

has to pay of the cost of providing state services. The state, like any

individual or corporation, ought to sell its services at cost price. Of

these services some citizens will use a bigger share than others, the

rich will get more than the poor, so ought to pay more. But, although an

income tax seems just at first sight, it is added to the cost of goods,

and so is spread over the community, like an ordinary tax on

consumption. He attacks a progressive income tax as tyrannical and

futile, for all taxes become indirect taxes on consumption, the ‘result

is zero’. A tax on land values, even if the state took only a third of

the revenue from this source, would pay all legitimate expenses of

government. In a well-organised state, government services should not be

more than a tenth of the gross revenue of the community, but until that

happy deflation of the state is achieved, most taxes should be left

alone for most reforms are fictitious! There can be no real justice in

taxation in a society which permits economic inequality, there is the

root of the matter. There are, of course, obvious improvements to be

made in detail; the duties on wines should be reduced, but those on

tobacco kept, (Proudhon was fond of wine and a non-smoker); houses

should be taxed, so as to break up the great towns. It was, indeed, an

eminently conservative essay; apart from its hostility to state action

and its hints of equality as a remedy, there is nothing in it to alarm

the most timid.

One other work of this last period showed Proudhon’s resolute

independence, for living by his pen, he attacked the claims for

perpetual or lengthy copyright made by his fellow-authors, with a zeal

more natural, as Émile Faguet says, in a publisher than in an author.

Literary Entails is, if not of first-class importance as a contribution

to the theory of property in ideas, at least worthy of Proudhon’s

spirit. Indeed, he repeatedly gave proofs of disinterestedness of a more

immediately practical type than his assault on copyright. With the

ending of his journalistic career, his means of livelihood became very

limited. He thought of going back to business, but that project came to

nothing. He worked for a projected railroad, but the concession went by

favour, and Proudhon refused compensation for his lost time. His own

health and that of his wife and children was not good, and serious

privation, if not actual starvation, came very close. He hoped to be

able to give his two surviving daughters dots, but, should they have to

fend for themselves, they would have the benefit of a severe training;

they were to expect everything from work, nothing from favour. When they

were still children of about ten, he saw signs in them of ‘dissipation,

vanity and impertinence’-vices to be stamped out and when well-meaning

friends sent them too handsome Christmas presents they were rebuked for

spoiling them! But Proudhon was equally severe on himself, and was hurt

by gifts of wine from admirers, gifts he insisted on paying for and, if

he underestimated the risks run by lenders, he may have forgotten that

not all men had his horror of debt or his zeal in repaying money only

borrowed under the pressure of dire necessity!

In his final years, Proudhon again attempted to lead the workers of

Paris into the true revolutionary path. Having made embittered enemies

in the past by his willingness to co-operate with the empire, he now led

the movement for rigid abstention from political life as long as the

imperial administration falsified the working of universal suffrage. He

wished the party of the Revolution to protest against the system by

abstaining from voting or by casting blank ballot papers. The election

of deputies was a tacit approval of the imperial régime and, as

candidates had to take an oath to the Emperor, the crime either of

perjury or of treason to the revolutionary cause, was made inevitable.

To active politidans, anxious to maintain a united front against the

government party, Proudhon was as big a nuisance as he had been in 1848

for he never wrote better than he did in his protest of the Non-Furing

Democrats, and in his advocacy of a declaration of political

independence by the working-classes, the Manifesto of the Sixty, a claim

for working-class representation, a denial of the representative

character of the bourgeois radicals. He left, in his last completed

work, The Political Capacity of the Working-Classes, an exposition of

the same theme. The Revolution had torn the worker out of a stratified

society; it had placed him opposite the bourgeoisie. What does this

class of wage earners bring to the problems of state? It brings a

solution of the problem of justice and equality; the magic formula of

mutuality will solve the economic problem, not communism: federalism

will solve the political problem, not the fantasies of the professional

democrats with their parliaments and armies of voters.

But if the working-class is called to a consciousness of its mission, it

is preached at as well as praised. Its fondness for strikes is

vigorously attacked, and so are the outrageous claims of the trade

unions to interfere with workshop management! An alliance with the

bourgeoisie is advocated; and the workers are reminded that they have

been too busy with their own wrongs to understand the sorrows of the

middle classes. Only a working-class whose moral character frees them

from mere passion can live up to its mission.

The last formal message of the great contradictor was thus harmony, but

Proudhon did not live to see the book through the press. He died on

January 19, 1865. The imperial government, anxious to frighten the

Church, permitted Proudhon’s funeral to be made a great anti-clerical

demonstration, but sent the publisher and printer of his posthumous

Annotated Gospels to prison, a contradiction worthy of Proudhon himself.

CHAPTER V: THE INFLUENCE OF PROUDHON

If there are real inconsistencies in Proudhon’s work- and there are not

a few- there are more apparent ones. His temper was too hot; he wrote

too much under the influence of immediate events; and these events gave

his prophetic powers the lie too often; for him to escape having to

curse what he had blessed and to bless what he had cursed. He judged

events, and men, by their fitness to aid in the work of the Revolution

and his judgment of what would aid the Revolution was too easily

affected by irrelevant circumstances of personal importance. He was, in

short, a man, not a thinking machine. But he was fundamentally very

consistent, although he concealed his consistency under verbal

extravagances. He grew, it is true, more conservative as he grew older,

less scornful of bourgeois virtues once he had become a bourgeois

himself, and more inclined to scepticism of the virtues of a populace

which paid so little attention to the advice he gave it. Then his

refusal to understand what his opponents meant sometimes had surprising

results. To read in War and Peace that even ‘if production is doubled,

population will not be long in being doubled in its turn, which means

there is no change’ -and to reflect that this pessimism comes from a

writer who used the name of Malthus as a term of abuse, is to suspect

inconsistencies. But Proudhon had never been really very far away from

Malthus; it was the inequality of working the law of population in the

present society, not its truth, that he had attacked.

The most common cause of his apparent variations was his spirit of

contradiction. He may not have been the Mephistopheles which Mazzini

called him, but he was certainly a denier. What was usually a

temperamental reluctance to agree with the truths or falsehoods in

common circulation, was erected by Proudhon into a system of dialectic;

he pushed, he asserted, a thesis to its ultimate conclusion, then

rebuilt on a sound foundation what he had destroyed. Thus he annihilated

property and then gave it a real life in the form of mutuality.

Sometimes this explanation covers the facts, sometimes it does not. Any

assertion was likely to provoke Proudhon to contradiction and to violent

contradiction at that, but, at heart, he was moderate, conservative in

almost all matters, sceptical of fundamental improvments in human life

and willing to take half a loaf, or even less, as an instalment of

justice. Out of his pros and cons it is possible to construct any number

of systems — and impossible to explain the whole of human institutions

and social history. Proudhon is a quarry, not one of the rival

symmetrical buildings for the future residence of mankind that are

declared to have been built by Marx; and, consequently, Proudhon, other

difficulties apart, could not compete with Marx as a founder of a

school. Indeed, he resembled such preachers of genius as Cobbett and

PĂ©guy, (in substance as well as in form), rather than systern-makers

like Marx. Proudhon’s influence was considerable, but it was the

influence of his spirit rather than of any consistent body of doctrine

that made him important in the history of revolutionary Europe in the

years following his death.

There is one possible exception to this view of Proudhon’s importance.

He was, as Kropotkin said ‘the father of anarchy’. The anarchists at

least preserved his memory and circulated his writings; as was fitting,

for anarchy, as a positive doctrine of free order, was formulated by

him.

The immediate connection between Proudhon and anarchy as a movement was

furnished by Bakunin, who was lavish in praise of his master and

developed some of the Proudhonian theses with a rigour which was foreign

to the essentially compromising spirit of their author. In the First

International, the cleavage between the anarchists and the Marxists

seemed to carry an old quarrel beyond the grave and, dead, Proudhon’s

name was powerful enough to serve as a rallying cry for the enemies of

the authoritarian doctrines of Marx. On this rock, indeed, the

International split; and there seemed for a time to be a chance that the

socialist movement would remain sundered by the doctrinal differences of

the communist and anarchist schools. The Commune of Paris was, in verbal

form, a Proudhonian rising. His ideas were powerful in giving to the

patriotic and social indignation of the Parisian workers, a federalist

form; and the commemoration of the martyrs of the ‘Wall of the

Federalists’ is a tribute to one side of Proudhon’s teaching. On the

other hand, the orthodox Marxian criticism of the tactics of the

Communards is severe on the part played by Proudhon’s disciples; their

lower middle class superstitions about right and legality, it is

asserted, ruined whatever chance of success the revolt had.

The crushing of the Commune drove anarchist propaganda underground; and,

when it was able to come out into the open again, the field had been

occupied by the orthodox socialists. To the French anarchists, Marxian

leaden like Guesde and Lafargue were deceiving the workers, leading them

into the old political paths where they had been led and betrayed by the

men of 1848. Despite energetic leaders, the anarchist agitation, moving

far from the ideas of the later Proudhun, failed to win a permanent

place for itself. There was some truth in the Marxist criticism of the

followers of Proudhun in the First International that they were mostly

workers in the Paris luxury trades, parasites — as their enemies

insisted- on the capitalist society they professed to wish to destroy.

Indeed, Proudhun was never closely in touch with the new industrial

proletariat. Apart from vague syndicalist solutions, he had little to

say to the worker who was not a possible peasant proprietor or possible

master of his own workshop. He did not like, and did not understand,

large-scale industry; and he had, by his hostility to strikes, left the

workers in such industries helpless until the far-distant date when the

present system should have been replaced. Naturally enough, the men who

were in revolt against the wrongs of the system of industry, which was

daily strengthening its hold on society, could hardly be expected to

wait on the ultimate deliverance of the Proudhonian revolution, and went

over to Marxian socialism or to a more active anarchy, to ‘propaganda by

the deed’. In his youth, Proudhon himself had dreamed of a wild justice

exercised by a select and virtuous minority who should punish the

innumerable unpunished crimes of the present social order but although

his temper occasionally boiled up, he became more sceptical of the

merits of this private punishment, and he devoted a part of, Justice to

confuting the defenders of tyrannicide. It was not enough that the

tyrant should deserve death; the assassin himself should, morally, be

above reproach, and in a corrupt society, where are such men to be

found? Where in sixteenth-century Italy would you find a man worthy to

slay a Borgia? Moreover, tyrannicide is as likely to find its victims

among the worthy as among the unworthy. William the Silent and Henri

Quatre were victims not of bad men, but of good men, of saints indeed!

So high a standard of political morality was incompatible with a good

deal of later anarchist activity, with murders and robberies committed

by men who were less than perfect, by men who were scornful of bourgeois

morality; and it is unfair to both sides to make Proudhon the inspirer

of Vaillant or Ravachol.

The eclipse of Proudhon seemed complete by the end of the nineteenth

century, except in an anarchist movement of decreasing practical

importance. The orthodox French socialists were inclined to remember

Proudhon’s indiscipline in the crisis of 1848, and spokesmen for Marxian

doctrines were patronising, if not hostile, to the untamed genius who

had misled the French workers for so many years.

It was a new generation that restored Proudhon to his pride of place.

The inevitable revolution was less imminent in 1890 than in 1880. Ten

years had been given the old order by a zealot in 1880; the ten years

had elapsed; the revolution was now far off -and revolutionary zeal had

cooled off. Socialists sent to parliament as a means of propaganda, were

beginning to demonstrate the psychological truth later to be formulated

by Robert de Jouvenel. ‘There is more in common between two members of

parliament, one of whom is a revolutionary, than between two

revolutionaries, one of whom is a member of parliament.’ Millerand, who

had used Proudhonian arguments against the Bank of France, came to

represent the cornpromising necessities of parliamentary politics. In

his speech at Saint-Mandé in 1896, he repeated the side-tracking of the

Revolution against which Proudhon had protested in 1848; when he entered

the cabinet to ‘defend the republic’, the parallel with the ‘Jacobins’

of fifty years before was evident. The republic was saved, socialist

discipline improved, and politics and party unity, twin evils against

which Proudhon had protested, seemed enthroned. But events fought for

Proudhonian ideas. The old order was not dying easily. The concentration

of property in a few hands had not gone far enough to create,

automatically, a unified working-class, ready to expropriate the

expropriators. The Dreyfus case had shown that there was life in the old

liberal doctrines of the rights of man; that the principles of the

French Revolution were still thought to be worth fighting about.

The idea of a working-class, conscious of its mission, not tied to any

academic orthodoxy, but creating its own weapons of combat and

spontaneously producing its own leaders, suspicious of state socialism

and of party creeds, found its vehicle in the syndicalist movement and

its prophet in Georges Sorel.

Against the current superstitions, Sorel declared war. He attacked the

‘unlimited confidence in the economic capacities of the state’. ‘The

democrats allow themselves to be trapped by dialectic ... academic

manipulations of abstractions inspire them with an extreme confidence

because such exercises serve to deceive the people which does not

understand what it is being led to applaud.’ The Marxian class war was

asserted to be an intellectual construction and its preachers thought

themselves free from any obligation to explain further what they meant

by it in a given situation.

Sorel was an enthusiastic and influential advertiser of Proudhon, but he

was himself, in his intuitionslist philosophy, opposed to the formal

rationalism of Proudhon. But in his insistence on the value of ideas

worked out, for the workers by the workers, he is in the spirit of The

Political Capacity of the Working-Classes. Proudhon would, probably,

have been less indifferent to the ‘mythical’ character of the general

strike; less willing to let the workers test their will-power without a

cool examination of the forces they would have to combat, not all of

them forces which could be altered by a mere effort of willing- however

hard! But in the insistence of Sorel and his disciples on effort; on the

refusal to await the inevitable working of history; in the insistence on

the role of the will in society; the apostles of syadicalism were in the

line of descent from Proudhon.

Other theses of Proudhon gained, from the necessities of the time, a

more respectful hearing than had seemed likely when the first Marxian

wave swept over France. The insight into the feelings of the French

peasant, which was one of Proudhon’s chief assets, was justified by the

increasing scepticism with which mere industrial socialism was preached

to peasants, who were not in the least anxious to destroy property, as

long as they had a chance of acquiring some themselves. Proudhon had

declared that no one who knew the French peasant would think of trying

to communise him and, indeed, there is hardly any less tractable human

raw material for orthodox communism than a French peasant hoping to

become a kulak. As a preacher of ‘socialism for peasants’, Proudhon

became respectable in French socialist circles and his violent hostility

to collectivism was forgotten or watered down. The war, the Russian

Revolution and the establishing of Party orthodoxy of the kind Proudhon

detested, have again eclipsed Proudhon. It is true that, in a gallant

attempt to lind a common ground, French Socialist orators appeal to the

doctrines of Proudhon, but as they also appeal to the doctrines of

Saint-Simon and are reluctant to abandon their claims on Marx, the value

of this praise is not great. Needless to say, the regular communists in

France pay not even lip service to the great heretic whose economic

doctrine is the ‘New Economic Policy’ made permanent and whose hostility

to revolutions, run from a safe distance by professional leaders, would

certainly not be diminished by the assertion that there was an

infallible party in Moscow on the job, in the place of his old enemies,

the London exiles! Proudhon had, if not a sceptical, a suspicious mind,

and that would have been enough to disqualify as a good party member.

Proudhon was, indeed, too various a writer to be a good founder of a

school, Syndicalist, anarchhts, royalists, have all been able to find

support for their views somewhere in Proudhon. None of these schools can

claim the whole of Proudhon and, as far as he has a spiritual heir, it

is Mr. Belloc whose ‘distributism’ expresses peffectly the essential

economic doctrine of Proudhon. To spread property in fairly even doses,

over most of the community; to regard equality in separate property

rights, not in common property rights, as the goal to be aimed at; and

to be sceptical about the forms of production which are not easily

reduced to individual equal property holdings are Proudhonian remedies

for social evils, as they are those of Mr. Belloc and the violent

anti-clericalism of Proudhon’s later life must not blind us to the

degree in which he represented French tradition. He said indeed, that

there was not enough religion in France to make the country Protestant,

but he had in fact little or no sympathy with the Reformation. In his

views of the family, of the place of woman, of sexual morals and of the

rationality of the universe, he might have agreed with his clerical

enemies — if only they would have agreed to put immanent Justice in the

place of God and the Revolution in the place of the Bible and the

Church!

It is as a representative of the French peasant and worker that Proudhon

is of first-rate importance. His passion for equality; his suspicion of

any bonds imposed on the individual, even in the flattering form of a

doctrine of fraternity or of association; his ingrained suspicion of

superior people, whether their superiority is based on wealth, birth, or

dogmatic infallibity; his willingness to sacrifice immediate material

gains for ideal satisfactions; his devotion to principles rather than

palpable ‘reforms’ as the motive of his political action; all are

commonplaces of French life. In his suspicion of authorities of all

kinds; in his conviction that they are almost always wrong; in his

realisation that if the state (or the party) is made powerful, its power

will be used for the rulers always — and often against the ruled;

Proudhon is a good radical and the radical is the typical Frenchman. In

his fondness for violent extremes of language, covering what is often

moderate or even timid thought, Proudhon is again a typical French

radical. He is willing to compromise, in fact if not in words; he even

offers at the end of his great polemic against the Church, to make a

bargain with it! But on one subject he was never ready to compromise; he

would never abandon his belief that Justice was not only the first of

goods, but was attainable. He would have scorned the moral pessimism of

the practical politician or of his apologists, with their belief that

since the rich are sure to plunder the community, the best the political

agents of the poor can do for their clients is to get a meagre share of

the spoil. Such a doctrine may keep alive the party machine; it may

invite the ingenious apologetic of ‘Alain’; but it would not be good

enough for Proudhon. He would have had Lazarus starve rather than let

him be bought off by crumbs from the rich man’s table. Such scepticism

he detested. ‘When doubt, secretly awakened in the souls of men, strikes

Justice: when man comes to regard laws and institutiom as bonds imposed

by force or necessity, but without roots in his conscience; when in

presence of social defects, incredulity shakes religion, then society is

done for; it is on the way to decadence and can only recover by a

revolution. No one says to himself that there are mistakes in the

established order, inadequacy in recopised rights, that the ideas behind

the laws must be rectified, the formulas corrected, that men must set

themselves bravely in search of truth and Justice, enduring the while,

with resignation and devotion, the effect of evil institutions.... No

one has faith any longer in the legislator or in men; men say to

themselves, as did Brutus, that human nature is corrupt, that Justice is

but a word, since experience has shown her to be inequal, contradictory

and there is no security that she will become better. Men see in the

state henceforward, simply an arbitrary coustitution, which profits only

the ambitious and the cunning; men see in religion only a conjuring

trick, an instrument of despotism. Every man keeps to himself, the good

virtuously, the bad, and the men of no faith, selfishly .... Society has

passed insensibly from Justice to despair.’

Nearly seventy years have passed since Proudhon foresaw the modern

dilemma as a moral dilemma, as a crisis in faith. He set up the banner

of Justice as one to which all men of good will should rally; as a

standard by which faiths, religious and political, should be tested. It

is an unfashionable banner and the faith Proudhon preached seems to have

even fewer adherents in our time than it had in his. It may be that his

truth was fiction; that the surrender of a belief in ethical values

transcending the economic structure and the class struggle and the

surrender of liberty into the hands of individuals or parties, remotely

responsible, if at all, to the multitudes that they rule, are inevitable

phenomena of historical development. But in the making of the brave new

worlds of Russia and Italy, sacrifices of truths (or of illusions) have

been made that Prouahon would have thought ill-compensated for by

punctual trains or abundant tractors. What value this nostalgia for the

illusions of ’89 may have is a matter of opinion, but no one who is sure

he can separate Justice and Revolution, Justice and Society, will find

much of value in Proudhon.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

The chief source for the life of Proudhon is his Correspondence

published in fourteen volumes after his death; more recent publications

have added to this mass of letters and others, still unpublished, are

known to exist. Proudhon’s works were published after his death and in

1923 a new and admirable edition was begun under the editorship of MM.

Bogglé and Moysset. This edition, very fully annotated, is

indispensable, but it is as yet only half-finished. Some of Proudhon’s

works have been translated into English under anarchist auspices: the

first two, Memoirs on Property in 1876 and The System of Economic

Contradictions in 1888, by Benjamin Tucker. The General Idea of the

Revolution in the Nineteenth Century was translated by John Beverley

Robinson in 1923. The chief works of Proudhon are: