đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș duane-rousselle-post-anarchism-and-psychoanalysis.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:16:55. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Post-Anarchism and Psychoanalysis Author: Duane Rousselle Date: 2022 Language: en Topics: post-anarchism, postanarchy, psychoanalysis Notes: The following text consists of a transcription of a series of free seminars conducted by Duane Rousselle in the early part of 2022.
Iâd like to begin with a statement that I made a few months ago while
nearing the end of a seminar for some students in Russia. You know, when
I speak, I frequently surprise myself. This happens because I permit
myself every opportunity to ramble. Maybe thatâs not exactly what you
might call âteaching,â but it certainly has its pedagogical effects.
When I speak as a teacher it is as if I am involved in a psychoanalytic
session. I am surprised--as typically happens in an analysis--by my own
speech. This was an important aspect of undergoing psychoanalysis for
Freud. He named it the âparapraxis.â And in his work on dreams he also
discussed the âlatentâ content, discoverable through interpretation of
the âmanifest content.â Lacan even made a distinction like that in his
earlier teaching between âemptyâ and âfullâ speech. The latter invokes a
meaning that is susceptible to psychoanalytic interpretation. In any
case, what I said to those Russian students was surprising but it didnât
imply that there was some deeper meaning to be interpreted inside of it.
I remain committed to the statement that surprised me. What I said was
that there are no genuine revolutionaries without melancholia. Iâm sure
that this statement will irritate some clinicians. For many of them,
melancholia is a very serious condition that involves, among other
things, suicidal ideation. I respect that it is important to have what
is called a âdifferential clinic.â So Iâm not intended to challenge this
position by playing loose with the definition. In any case, I donât want
to repeat all of the heavy lifting that brought me to make that claim.
But what is melancholia? Put simply, it exists, not, as one might
expect, when one discovers that the world has collapsed, but rather when
one realizes that one never existed in the world from the very
beginning. In such circumstances, in some sense, there is nothing but
âworld.â It is a world of profound subjective destitution, to put it
mildly. The melancholic cannot seem to conquer a place for itself in the
world. (I am here repurposing Lacanâs statement on psychosis.)
I would even claim that the melancholic experience is one of only
ârevolution.â Lacan once reminded his students that the word
ârevolutionâ means âto return to the same.â Hence, in the 1970s, he
said: âthis term ârevolutionâ in the use made of it in the mechanics of
heavenly bodies, means a return to the state.â He added: âthe masterâs
discourse accomplishes its own revolution in the sense of doing a
complete circle.â How should we read this? I take it to imply that there
was something ârealâ at stake in his conception of revolution. I am
surprised, therefore, to discover that Lacan was actually quite
interested in revolutions. The concept of the ârealâ was for him
pivotal. And perhaps you already know that he once gave a definition of
the ârealâ as that which âalways returns to its place.â His example was
precisely the movement of heavenly bodies. It would therefore seem as
though the concept of the ârealâ and that of ârevolutionâ are in some
ways homologous. There is a ârealâ at stake in melancholia that is
revolutionary and that forces us to reflect also upon the concepts of
repetition, circularity, and even fixation. The melancholic is therefore
the one for whom there is most certainly a revolution, but without there
being any place for herself in the world.
This is what differentiates the melancholic from the hysteric. The
latter, in the first instance, confronts a world. The hysterical subject
situates her revolutionary aspirations in some relation to the world. It
doesnât imply that it works out well for her. But she demands something
from the world. She demands that there be a transgression of the laws
which sustain it. She is not necessarily the instrument of the world, as
in perversion, but she does aim to expose the worldâs inadequacies and
to force it to take stock. Yet, for all of that, to put it simply, she
remains subjected to that world. For example, the hysteric will come
inside of the walls of your world for no other reason than to demand
that you go outside of the world. In fact, this is what one
revolutionary student did during one of Lacanâs seminars. The student
interrupted Lacan in order to demand that he stop teaching, that he stop
speaking. The demand was for him to go outside of speech. Iâll quote the
incident:
Student: If we are to overthrow the University, it will be from the
outside, with others who are on the outside.
Intervention: So why are you inside?
Student: I am inside, comrade, because if I want people to leave, I have
to come inside to tell them.
Lacan: Ah! You see... Everything is there, my friend. In order to get
them to go out, you come in.
It is a rather interesting dialogue. Perhaps the hysteric goes inside so
that she can preach the gospel of going outside. Yet, this is not true
of the melancholic. The melancholic experiences revolution without a
place for herself in the world and without aspirations. The concept of
revolution is therefore a real pivot between hysteria and melancholia.
This is what will eventually lead us toward some real surprises. For
example, Lacan once said to the revolutionary students: âas
revolutionaries, what you aspire to is a master.â After all the years
since I first read this statement, it continues to lead me to be
surprised. In fact, I was surprised yet again, just last night, when one
of you provided me with another reading of the statement. Hugh know who
you are! In any case, it is likely that the statement also surprised
Lacan since he didnât plan on saying what he said. The point is that
hysteria is precisely that: a big surprise! But, for whom is it a
surprise? On the one hand, it is a surprise for those who attempt to
relate to the hysteric. I wouldnât recommend that. On the other hand, it
is a surprise, precisely, for the hysteric herself.
It was a point made many years ago by Jacques-Alain Miller. He said,
quite simply: âhysteria is the surprise package!â It doesnât work out
well for partners who do not like surprises. Truthfully, there are many
people today who donât like to be surprised. It is probably a part of
our contemporary condition. My concern is that anarchists stopped being
surprised by the world as well. In any case, Miller went on to remind us
that the hysteric is never where her partner expects her to be, based
upon what he believes he knows about her. It was a fundamental point. A
clear point. It helped to orient me on the question of the hystericâs
truth. However, it didnât make things understood. It only leads me
toward more confusion. This expression -- the hystericâs truth -- ⊠Iâm
not sure if Lacan ever said it quite like that. It was Ellie Ragland who
put it clearly like that in an essay of the same title. Sheâs never
where you expect her to be because she is not entirely captured by the
world of meaning, by speech.
There can be no psychoanalysis without surprises. Psychoanalysis has
been fundamentally oriented by surprises of all sorts. It is why we
might claim that psychoanalysis really began as an outcome of the
hysterical revolution. And psychoanalysts attempted to make the surprise
a motor of their discourse, the âanalytic discourse,â by beginning with
what is called the objet petit a. That is what Lacan called it: the
objet petit a. It is a confusing concept because it took different
shapes during different periods of his teaching. To get a sense of some
of these shifts you might read Millerâs âSix Paradigms of Jouissance.â
At around the time of the impromptu session with the revolutionary
students, not long after the uprisings began in France, the objet petit
a was resituated to account for a renewed interest in the relationship
of the unconscious to what is called the drives or what today I will
simply call, and it is not quite correct, the impulse. It is not long
after this that the objet petit a became understood as a âvoid,â which
means that it was something missing from within the symbolic order. Put
another way, it was related to that which resists being inscripted
within the symbolic world. That was what happened to the little object
âcauseâ of desire. So, I say that the hysterical subject is the one for
whom jouissance is resolutely and inescapably enigmatic from the
standpoint of the world.
Itâs not exactly clear to me. Iâm not sure where I am going with all of
this. But something nonetheless has become cleared away. Incidentally, I
quite like the word âclear.â I like it because one of you told me
yesterday in Dublin that it is one of the Cartesian virtues. I didnât
know about that. I like it, but, nonetheless, nothing is really clear to
me yet with regard to the point of this lecture. Iâm confused in-Clare,
unclear. In any case, what Iâve mentioned so far does nonetheless
produce a clearing away of knowledge from jouissance. There is a
disjuncture of knowledge, the sort of knowledge that might be
interpreted in terms of meaning, and jouissance. Maybe what Iâm saying
is not altogether virtuous but perhaps I can learn to speak-well of it
as the course proceeds. Iâm working on it. For now, Iâll continue
rambling.
I was thinking that it would be difficult for psychoanalysis to continue
if not for the fact that they like surprises. There are even some
psychoanalysts on facebook who really enjoy them. You will find them
endlessly playing with language, making jokes, producing double
entendres, and so on. For them, there is nothing but the playfulness of
language. That is not my way. However, this point about the disjuncture
of knowledge and jouissance allows us to advance a little further than
some âso-called anarchistsâ (which sounds a lot like âpsycho-analysts,â
doesnât it?). They offered readings of psychoanalysis and revolution by
focusing on hysteria and desire without at all plunging into the
darkness of the drives, the revolutionary impulses, and enigmatic
jouissance. Some of them have claimed that theyâve isolated the basic
ontological presuppositions of classical anarchism and that they have
revealed an uncritical âessentialist positionâ with respect to human
nature.
This led them toward a claim that classical anarchists had a simplistic
or reductive account of political revolution: if human nature is
essentially good and creative, and if the master is essentially
repressive, then one just has to get rid of the master and we can all
hold hands and join a communist fraternity. What I find interesting
about this moment in anarchist thinking was that it nonetheless produced
an initial surprise among anarchists around the world. They were
surprised by what we revealed to them about what they were saying. So,
suddenly, when the post-anarchist critique of classical anarchist
ontology and epistemology occurred, there was a jolt of surprise among
anarchists. It was perhaps most surprising, though, because the
post-anarchists were anarchists who defined themselves, their
orientation, precisely in fidelity to that surprise. It was most
surprising for the anarchists themselves! And just like that most
anarchists began to work hard to demonstrate that there was already this
other âsceneâ within anarchist theory.
They busied themselves to show us that the classical texts are not at
all homogeneous like many of the post-anarchists seemed to be claiming.
They aimed to show us that there was always another reading of the
anarchist theory of power, subjectivity, and so on. It was already there
within the classical tradition. It means that the post-anarchists and
the anarchists were fighting with each other but nonetheless both
pursuing the consequences of the same surprising moment. It was an
engagement with the unconscious, truthfully. What mattered at that
moment wasnât about who had the correct reading of anarchist texts but
rather the fact that we were all surprised by what he had already been
saying within the anarchist tradition. I wonder if today there are any
of such surprises left for anarchists.
Not much has been said about the incompatibility or the non-rapport of
jouissance and the world. The mystery of hysteria was thought to be
mastered by many of the post-anarchists. I propose to you that we
instead begin to move backward from mastery to mystery, from meaningful
knowledge back to the enigma. You know, the word âsurpriseâ carries two
meanings: first, it means to be captured or mastered, and, second, it
means that you are astonished by something unexpected. On the one hand,
you could say that you are mastered by the symbolic unconscious. So,
when some post-anarchists wrote about hysteria and revolution they
focused only on the unacknowledged dependence upon the world of mastery.
For example, it was the position of Saul Newman in his exploration of
the Nietzschean concept of ressentiment and âslave morality.â It was
also the position of Richard J. F. Day, in a way, when he discussed what
he called the âloopback structureâ of âreform and revolutionâ within
counter-hegemonic social movements. For him, these movements were
captured by what he named the circular âpolitics of demand.â For Lacan,
it is only the analystâs discourse that offers a revolution without the
world of mastery.
The big secret of hysteria is that she is ultimately not entirely in the
world. This is why Lacan seemed to retain a link among hysteria and
femininity. This will probably upset those of you who are not in favor
of surprises: he located a link among hysteria and the essence of the
feminine position and it was in a logic of the ânot-allâ (pas-toute).
The ânot-allâ highlights an exception to the laws of the world. It is
not a universal position, since that would make it an âAll.â The
ânot-allâ remains enigmatic. Marie-Helene Brousse pointed out that in
hysteria it is important to think not only about a revolutionary
response to the world of mastery. Hysteria is also a response to the
âreal.â In other words, hysteria is also a defense against revolution.
Put differently, hysteria is a response to the master just as much as
the mystery. In both cases there is something like a ravage.
Psychoanalysts often mitsake hysterical and melancholic or psychotic
ravage. The key difference, I think, is that the hysteric makes
victimization the point of departure upon which to launch her
interrogation of the master, while the melancholic remains within the
mystery. There are no secrets or surprises.
You get my point? What is at stake in hysteria? Ultimately, it concerns
this enigmatic and unspeakable jouissance. It is a jouissance that is
anarchic and revolutionary. It is a jouissance uncoupled from the world.
The melancholic understands the big secret, the hystericâs truth: the
world is radically without foundation. The melancholic knows very well
about the profound violence of the world and of speech. For the
melancholic, the secret is truly out. This is why knowing the big secret
doesnât make life any easier. You know, I am currently in Ireland, and I
was reminded recently that in Catholicism there is the âmystery of
faith.â I remember hearing it every Sunday while I was in the church:
âlet us proclaim the mystery of faith.â What is the mystery of faith?
Quite simply, it is the secret as such, something radically without
meaning. The mystery of faith is not some meaning to be solved, it is
just that: a pure enigma. However, there was some theosopher, I donât
know his name, who claimed that he found a way to grasp the mystery of
faith and it was in the pure writing of the tetragrammaton. In any case,
I digress.
None of this stops the melancholic from engaging in what seems to be
self-sabotaging behavior. However, that happens along a different track
than what we see in hysteria. The hysteric sabotages her desire in order
to sustain the very space within which her subjectivity has been split
in relation to the world. It is a possible solution. However, the
melancholic, as you know, sabotages this very split of subjectivity. The
cut that should have occurred from the world into jouissance didnât
happen, and so it sometimes happens instead with a razor blade or with a
pill. In such cases, the revolution overcomes her. I imagine those monks
who sit out in the streets in protest and burn themselves to death. It
is definitely a type of ârevolutionaryâ activity. In this case, the
molotov cocktail isnât thrown at the world but is thrown at oneself.
Lacan once defined jouissance in the following way: âit begins with a
tickle and ends in a blaze of petrol.â Lacan reminded us that this
behavior has been popular among Buddhists for a while, and he related it
to the melancholic position. However, this is a revolution that outlives
the subject.
This is why it is important to understand that there are revolutionary
aspirations but also revolutions of jouissance, or what we might call
the revolutionary activity of death drive. What the melancholic
demonstrates is that there is a revolution of jouissance which burns
away at the subject. It reveals that the subject is refused in this
world and that the world can easily go on about its business without him
or her. The subject is revealed as this refuse, this piece of trash. The
melancholic subject will state this quite clearly. I was thinking that
it is an interesting position to imagine oneself since that is what the
psychoanalyst ultimately becomes for a patient in psychoanalysis: cast
off, rejected, refused at the end of analysis. The analyst is also a
piece of trash, truth be told.
Maybe there are just a few more things that I would like to say.
There is a possible reading of the legend of Orpheus and Eurydice. I
hope you know something about this narrative. What Orpheus learned upon
losing Eurydice in the underworld was that he needed to lose her
precisely to convince himself that he ever had her from the beginning.
He was trying to trick himself, I think. He wanted to be duped. He
wanted to forget that he already knew the big secret. In the end, after
losing her, he realized, I think, that he never had her from the
beginning. He sat all alone, beneath a tree, like the Buddha, absolutely
dedicated to her long after she vanished. This is what we are often
told: his dedication to her never waned, long after she was gone. He
nonetheless refused all possible relationships to others. He could not
substitute her. I will quote Ovid: âhe abstained from the love of women
[...]. Yet, many felt a desire to be joined with him, and many grieved
at being rejected.â What happened in the end? Precisely, the world tore
him to pieces, limb by limb. It wasnât petrol but it had the same
effect.
Perhaps another reading exists, one which thinks that he was a
melancholic. He could not separate from Eurydice, he could not find a
position from which to properly mourn her. The paradox was that she was
all the more proximate precisely after her vanishing. It is perhaps also
a way to read the lesson of Antigone. Many people believe that Antigone
was a hysteric who performed a truly ethical act. Judith Butler noted
that she couldnât have been hysterical. She agreed with Julia Kristeva
in claiming that she must have been melancholic. Kristeva advanced this
point a bit further: Antigone was melancholic because she could not
separate from the familial bond with her brother. She was closer to him
precisely in his absence. She nonetheless seemed like a revolutionary
figure, ungovernable by the laws of the world. But what kind of
revolution was that? The revolution went on without them.
Hence, I really like how clearly Russell Grigg put the matter several
years ago. He said something like: in melancholic psychosis, it is not a
process of mourning the loss of an object/person that is at stake. It is
not a process of mourning. Rather, melancholia is about the unbearable
presence of the object/person. He referred to the âunabandoned object.â
Letâs return to our thread after this long detour. I want to return to
this moment when Lacan was speaking to the revolutionary students of
France. Lacanâs statement really did surprise me. Iâll explain why.
First of all, it occurred during an impromptu session. Lacan frequently
permitted himself the freedom to ramble. But at that time his students
challenged that space. They challenged the very space within which
rambling could have occurred. On the one hand, they demanded that he
respond to their provocations and accusations; and, on the other hand,
they interrupted him, and, in fact, spoke for him. When he did find a
moment to speak it was clear that they only heard what they were already
prepared to hear. They already knew all of the answers to the questions
that they were asking. Perhaps that offers us another way to understand
what it means to work at an âimpossible profession.â (Thatâs what Freud
called them, impossible professions: teaching, politics, and
psychoanalysis.) Perhaps teaching is an âimpossible professionâ because
there never was a world within which the teacher could have possibly
been permitted to ramble. Lacan probably knew this better than most
since there was always a question of where it was that he would speak.
But that didnât stop him from speaking and from saying things that
continue to astonish us.
As for Antigone, she was not able to make use of a world after hers
clearly disappeared. There is something ethically wrong, I would say, in
claiming that Antigoneâs action was revolutionary and that tragedy is at
the heart of what psychoanalysis and anarchism can offer the world. We
might think it is courageous when she says: âI will bury him myself even
if I die in the act, that death will be a blory. I will sleep with the
one I love and be loved by him.â You know what is interesting -- I will
have to go back to the ethics seminar to confirm this -- Lacan described
Antigone as having the âtrue secret.â She possessed the mystery. Yet,
for Lacan, she was also âinflexible,â which means, quite fixated, stuck.
At one point Lacan even claims that it might be the case that she was a
fascist. She goes beyond the limits of the world. It was an act of
rebellion and transgression. However, when did the transgression happen?
Well, it didnât happen suddenly, because of an injustice. She said
somewhere that âher soul died a long time ago.â She didnât say that the
world died but rather that her soul died. In the same seminar, before
discussing Antigone, Lacan spoke of another melancholic woman who acted
in relation to an overly proximate object, her brother-in-law. It shows
that he had something of melancholia in mind when speaking of Antigone.
The melancholic doesnât know how to find a place for herself in relation
to the world. And it has something to do with the fact that she has a
strange access to the hystericâs truth. I made a distinction last week
when speaking about something else: idiot, moron, and stupid person.
When one does not see the way in which one is implicated in the world of
mastery, we can speak about a person who is duped as if they are an
idiot. The hysteric is clearly an idiot. The idiot is always determined
by the world. I call that idiot-ology, which means that one remains
trapped within the field of mastery. This is a different position than
that of living without a world. Those who live without a world are
morons. We might claim that the moron is an elevated idiot. The moron
isnât duped at all. But canât live properly without being duped. The
psychoanalyst is interested in a revolution that is neither moronic nor
idiotic. I think that it says something about our âstupidity.â Perhaps
it is about not being without a world, which means making use of a
world. The stupid person really likes surprises, it stunned him. I want
to quote Natalie Wulfing, who I think put it exceptionally well:
[For the melancholic, there is] nothing to be gained from the World.
Freud in fact thought that the melancholic had an uncharacteristic
access to the truth [...] It would cast him as a non-dupe [in other
words, a moron].
It is a terrible thing to say because I advise you to never call a
melancholic a moron. It will have catastrophic consequences. I would
conclude only by reminding you that some anarchists knew about the big
secret. I admire them very much. Take Max Stirner who wrote that
ârevolutions aim at new arrangements, but insurrections lead us to no
longer allow ourselves to be arranged by the social order.â You know,
when you look at the painting that Engels drew of the young Hegelians,
stirner was always off to the side, at a distance from the world.
Stirner wasnât essentially aiming to provoke a master. He was
confronting the world as such. His books and essays basically say the
following: âI resolve to speak of revolutions without the need of a
world.â He finds himself, therefore, all alone. He is this void, this
piece of waste. For example, how does Stirner open his famous book The
Ego and Its Own? He writes: âAll things are nothing to me.â He
continues:
What is not supposed to be my thing! First and foremost, the Good thing,
then Godâs thing, the thing of mankind, of truth, of freedom, of
humanity, of justice; further, the thing of my people, my prince, my
fatherland; finally even the thing of Mind, and a thousand other things.
Only my cause, my thing, is never to be my concern.
I take from this that there is a fundamental rejection of the world, of
the entire field of âworld.â There is nothing left except the pure
revolutionary impulse. He destroys all objects. This is how he put it in
a small essay on art and religion: âart makes the Object, and religion
lives only in its many ties to that Object.â He continues to explain
that he âclearly sets himself apart from both [...]. Neither enmeshed
with an Object, as religion, nor making one, as in art, but rather [he]
places his pulverizing hand upon all the business of making Objects as
well as the whole of objectivity itself, and so breathes the air of
freedom.â Finally, it is a rejection of the world, and hence, a
rejection of himself as being represented in that world. He resists
being an object of the world. So, where does that leave him? Precisely
with the truth!
His solution was to produce a self-enclosed circuit of autistic
jouissance. He is ânothing.â Yet, when he says he is nothing, it is not
as âlack,â as something missing. He is not nothing in the sense of
emptiness, as he puts it, but rather as a creative nothing. He is this
void of an anarchic jouissance which is overflowing, lawless, and
enigmatic. The ânothingâ was an enigma and not an object. It gives us a
reason to presume that there has always been something like a
revolutionary impulse in the anarchist tradition. But these melancholics
do not know how to live without a world. It was why so many melancholics
of history left us too soon. Yet, there have been attempts to form a
social bond, however paradoxical, from the melancholic position. Stirner
spoke of the âunion of egoists,â but never gave it any meaning. A
particularly good example comes from Sergey Nechayev, a young companion
of Mikhail Bakunin. Nechayev claimed to have built a very large
revolutionary secret society.
Three is no evidence that he did do that. But his manifesto highlighted
what was at stake. I quote from the Revolutionary Catechism:
The revolutionary is a doomed man. He has no personal interests, no
business affairs, no emotions, no attachments, no property, and no name.
Everything in him is wholly absorbed in the single thought and the
single passion for revolution.
The revolutionary knows that in the very depths of his being, not only
in words but also in deeds, he has broken all the bonds which tie him to
the social order and the civilized world with all its laws, moralities,
and customs, and with all its generally accepted conventions. He is
their implacable enemy, and if he continues to live with them it is only
in order to destroy them more speedily.
And then he proceeded to discuss justifications for the muder of whole
groups of society. But, more importantly, the revolutionary subject, he
insisted, must be prepared to end his own life as a part of the
revolutionary process. The revolution is a pure consequence, even if it
means the loss of space of subjectivity.
Well, Iâm not sure I agree with anything that Iâve said today. But what
I really wanted to do was simply to set the stage for another
discussion. Next week I want to focus not on hysteria, necessarily; nor
on melancholy, or the improper ways in which Iâve discussed it today. I
am interested in the world that an anarchist might make use of, or in,
rather, what sort of social bond is at stake for anarchists. It is clear
to me that revolutionaries cannot be without a world. Hence, if the
hystericâs world was governed by what Lacan called the âname of the
father,â said ânon-du-pere,â then the revolutionary anarchist might be
governed by a principle of âauto-non-me,â which is another strange
homophony since it bridges the French and English. Auto-non-me, it is
another way to âsay no to the subject,â to make use of the non-du-pere
precisely when it has gone missing. Maybe auto-non-me can help us clear
a path forward for those of us who want to live beyond the consequences
of the revolutionary impulse.
Iâll stop here.
I ask you for this week to write your questions and comments into the
chat for the Facebook group. I will look at them and see what can be
made from them for next week.
I am no more prepared this week than I was last week. However, this time
I find myself oriented by some of our confusions. I also discovered a
title for last weekâs lecture, which I quite like: âThe Revolutionary
Impulse of Melancholia.â In any case, I want to thank you again for
being here. It is because you are here that I have a position from which
to speak. And thatâs not nothing. Itâs what I call a world. I didnât say
that it is the world because that would imply something more definite,
something more predictable. One should really not be without a world,
one should not be without a place from which to speak. Perhaps it also
provides an opportunity for speaking-well. Incidentally, when we speak
about the ethics of psychoanalysis, as we did last week with Antigone,
we should remember that the real statement on psychoanalytic ethics
didnât come from Lacanâs ethics seminar. I think that it was described
in his later teaching, for example in Television: it concerns a duty to
be well-spoken. And he claimed that depression, melancholy, occurs when
one fails in oneâs ethical duty of speaking-well.
I am oriented by the question of melancholy, anarchism, and the social
bond. However I am led toward a discussion, today, of the moronic One,
that is, the One who is without a world; or who has, paradoxically,
become nothing in the world. It is an important point because the
collapse of the world, or rather, the realization of the inexistence of
the world, as is the case for melancholics, can lead one to feel
surrounded by the world. When taken to its extreme, the world shifts
into a different register. It is a movement from the symbolic world of
meaning toward a ârealâ world, the mystery. It is possible in such
circumstances that the space of the subject becomes eclipsed. You know,
perhaps the beautiful soul retreats from the world, into four walls,
disappearing even in her attempt to produce a space for herself, like
Julian of Norwich. It means, finally, that there are revolutions of the
One. The revolution of the One is not-at-all what was foregrounded
during the modern revolutionary aspirations of anarchists. Itâs why I
made a distinction last week between revolutionary impulses and
revolutionary aspirations. The One can be detached from the Other, from
the world. In fact, the direction toward which all revolutionary
aspirations lead, as hysteria shows, is a decoupling of the One and
World.
This was precisely the case with Antigone. I begin my rambling for today
with Antigone. I didnât say that I will begin against Antigone. In fact,
I am with the revolutionary melancholics, the depressed revolutionaries:
melancholics without a world, unite! However, to be clear, Antigone
wasnât much of a rambler. She preferred to solicit the ramblings of the
world. I imagine that it could be a soul-crushing position from which to
engage with the world. Perhaps what Antigone died of was âsoul muder.â
That was the expression used by Schreber, the most cited psychotic in
the Freudian field. It was always a matter of her silence, and prolonged
silence is, I discovered, an essential ingredient in Greek tragedy. I
was just reading about this in some idiotic literature journal:
Antigoneâs silence demonstrated a stubborn refusal of speech -- âfull
speechâ -- in relation to the world. It was a stubborn defiance of the
worldâs determinations. Prolonged silence indicates that the subject is
not situated within idiot-ology, and thatâs why I call her a moron.
It is also why I would claim that she doesnât deliver us the ethics of
psychoanalysis. She was a figure of profound silence, but this does not
mean that she didnât experience the soul-murdering ramblings of the
world. The world always went on rambling without any need of her; in
fact, she solicited the world to speak in her place. Yet, to be fair,
thatâs what speaking is, anyway. In this case, though, the signifier
fills in the place of the subject, a void, a place that should have
remained âempty.â You know, for the earlier Lacan, the subject is split
by one signifier for another signifier. This is because, ultimately, the
subject is not entirely there in language except through her
representation by a signifier, which, in of itself, never touches the
real. The signifier never at the real but only at another signifier.
Antigoneâs was a different position than the one demonstrated by the
interjections of revolutionary students toward Lacan. Those students
attempted to speak in Lacanâs place. Whereas Antigone preferred that the
world speak in her place, the students preferred to speak in Lacanâs
place.
Polynieces pleaded with Antigone. He requested that Antigone speak with
his father, a father who had gone silent. For her part, Antigone
stubbornly refused to speak to the father. She preferred, in fact, to be
left alone. Yet, at the same time, she provided Polynieces precise
instructions about how to solicit speech in the father, that is, how to
make him speak using an âabundance of words.â Thatâs her expression:
âabundance of words.â I imagine, when there is an âabundance of wordsâ
coming at you from the world, that most of you would prefer the world to
just shut up. It wasnât Antigoneâs way. Antigone preferred for the world
to simply go on rambling without her. We can call this Antigoneâs
jouissance. Itâs not a molotov cocktail tossed onto a burning monk but
it has the same effect. Antigone even preferred that others discuss her
marital prospects. She preferred to have no say in these matters.
Whatâs more is that she confessed that it would be better for the world
to focus on their own concerns. You will remember that this was also
Stirnerâs conviction: âwhat is not supposed to be my concern?â Stirner,
like Antigone, felt the demands of the world on his shoulders. She
likewise asked, why should these be her concerns? In the end, it is a
similar question. The solution for both was simply to let them concern
themselves with themselves, the world should concern itself with the
world. It is a decoupling of the One from the world. Antigone and
Stirner decoupled themselves from all of that, preferring to have no
part for themselves in the world. The word we have for that process is
foreclosure. It would have been different had the world determined them
without them even realizing it, which presumes that there is a position
of the subject within the totality of his or her signifying relations.
In such circumstances, we could discuss ideas like the âsociological
imaginationâ or âideological critique.â This can only occur when one is
inside of the world.
And Antigone had no intention to go inside of the world. She really
preferred at all times to remain on the outside; outside of the walls of
the city, outside of the world. In fact, this position ran in her
family. It is the feminine way, and it is the melancholic way. If I am
being honest with you, I believe that we are now in a feminine world. It
means that the world has shifted into another register, and we have
moved from the âAllâ to that of the âNot-Allâ as the governing function.
The contemporary world is no longer one that would give rise to modern
revolutionary aspirations. Rather, we are in a world of revolutionary
impulses that are capable of outliving the subject, threatening the
subject: it is a world of particular affirmations of jouissance. The
problem is not therefore âhow do we instigate a revolution?,â âhow can
we overthrow the world of mastery?,â but rather: âhow can we sustain a
space for ourselves in a world without burning ourselves alive?â It is
why I claim that the psychoanalyst is not exclusively a product of
revolutionary aspirations nor of revolutionary impulses. The revolution
that is at stake in the formation of a psychoanalyst is something
different.
Shortly after concluding our seminar last week I reread an important
passage from a pivotal text by Jacques-Alain Miller, titled âThe Turin
Theory of the Subject of the School.â I wasnât looking for anything in
particular. But a sentence jumped out at me. Maybe itâs better to say
that it floated above the page like a bubble. I donât have the quotation
with me, but what I remember was that he pointed at Antigoneâs âact.â He
reminded us that she was ultimately situated beyond the laws of the
world. And then he claimed that at some point she must have met up with
the object âcauseâ of her desire, objet petit a. Beyond the world of
mastery, she meets up with the truth, the hystericâs truth; and, in that
place, she would have found out that she was not-at-all made for the
world. Or, rather, the world was not the place for her. Hence, in this
case, Antigone, the âbeautiful soulâ of Greek tragedy, who is also often
thought to be the exemplary subject of hysteria, went beyond the bar of
her truth. For Lacan, at one point, he constructed a formula of
hysteria, the âhystericâs discourse:â
There is a barrier between the objet petit a, which is in the position
of unconscious truth, and the agent of her discourse, her own
victimization, s-barred, $. So, for Antigone (it is a really technical
point) the s-barred, $, meets up with the truth, objet petit a. It means
that the truth of the hystericâs discourse is, in a word: the real,
jouissance. We could write it out like this: $-->a. That makes it look a
bit like the âmatheme of fantasy,â which, for Lacan, was {body}lt;>a. This is
precisely what the hysteric would have surpassed in her act: the
fantasy, which is a separation from the real of jouissance. This
traversal of the fundamental fantasy is, for many Lacanians, an
important and revolutionary moment because it involves a transgression
beyond the governing fantasmatic frame that sustains the position of the
hysteric. There was even a time when psychoanalysts believed that this
revolution would lead the hysteric toward the analystâs position. Some
people still believe that psychoanalystâs believe this. It is not my
position. A traversal of the fantasy is no guarantee that there is
before you a psychoanalyst. A different revolution is at stake. However,
the point is that the hystericâs crossing beyond the bar, into the
position of her truth, implies a passage toward objet petit a. This
could mean that it is a passage to the position of the real, that is,
either as waste or as One, which means, as a bubble floating above the
pages of the world.
Iâm sorry for all of the technical details today. Iâm doing it so that I
can try to clear away some of the noise that keeps me from orienting
myself on this question of the melancholicâs revolutionary impulse (as
opposed to the hystericâs revolutionary aspirations). However, now, it
seems to me, there is also a third term: the revolution of
psychoanalysis, which is the revolution that makes One a psychoanalyst.
So, I need to turn my attention to the technical concepts that were
tripping us up last week. I realize that we tend to use these concepts
interchangeably. There is even a good reason for it: in Lacanâs late
teaching, many of these concepts were similar, perhaps grouped under the
heading of semblant. Semblant was a concept that meant âstand-inâ or
âsubstitute object.â Russell Grigg reminded us a few years ago that
during Lacnaâs late teaching the concept of semblant meant almost
anything. For Grigg this was a problem. Iâm less convinced that itâs a
problem. I see it as a clearing. What it demonstrates is that the Other,
as such, became much more important, in relation to the One. Semblant,
then, was what would be there as a means of forming a couple with the
Other. Hence, in using the concept, quickly, we deprioritize the
concepts of objet petit a, lack, nothing, and so many other concepts --
even phallus and non-du-pere.
So, it serves a function. It produces a clearing. And every now and then
thatâs what we need to do so that these concepts do not get routinized
and reified; so that we can continue to think about the contemporary
condition with fresh attention, which means, with the attitude of a
stupid person. However, this point wonât keep me, today, from wasting a
lot of your time by saying some words about these concepts that tripped
us up. It is my way of addressing the discussion that happened last
week, particularly between Volkan and Mark. The concepts that tripped us
up a bit were lack, hole, nothing, void, and objet petit a. Why donât we
begin with the most well-known concept: lack. Already I can sense the
relief that some of you feel now that youâve heard this concept, lack.
It is odd when âlackâ is viewed as a comfort, but thatâs how it is
sometimes. Some people have presumed that its the central concept in
Lacanâs teaching, even going on to pronounce, as if it were clever,
lack-on. It doesnât surprise me. For my part, I think that Lacan was
more of a con, or la-con, which, in French, means âthe cunt.â In any
case, people feel attuned to this concept, âlack,â even those at the
outermost peripherals of psychoanalytic circles. Itâs especially true
for those in the university. There was even a popular article, as well
as an edited collection, that was making it rounds several years ago,
which introduced--no, presupposed--a distinction between what they named
âphilosophies of immanence or abundance,â to which we might include the
exemplary work of Deleuze, Bataille, Spinoza, and others, and, on the
other hand, âphilosophies of lack or constitutive lack,â which includes
Lacan, as alone as he ever was.
Itâs a moronic distinction. Itâs not clear to me that beginning from
within the philosophical position orients us very well in Lacanâs
teaching. It is also not clear to me that âlackâ is a foundational
concept of psychoanalysis for Lacan. If we return to the seminar titled
âThe Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysisâ then we can see what the
four fundamental concepts were: the unconscious, desire, repetition, and
transference. Lack was not one of the fundamental concepts. However,
there is the unconscious, which, from the French, might even be
pronounced une-conscious, the One, unsubscribed from the unconscious.
Itâs not all word play, donât worry. When it comes to matters of the One
there can be no funny business! In any case, this seminar, on the
fundamental concepts, also serves as a reminder that ârepetitionâ and
âtransferenceâ were conceptually distinct. Transference was not a
particularly revolutionary category for Lacan. Repetition wasnât meant
to be the key for thinking about the transference. Rather, repetition is
at stake in the drive. It implies a revolution of the One, without
transference.
For some reason I opened up the question of the objet petit a and the
void last week. Maybe it was a mistake. Because now we are in the middle
of some very technical stuff. Maybe it wonât be of interest to those of
you who expect more talk of what you think you know about anarchism. But
I can promise you that itâs relevant to you. Miller made a point to
distinguish between void and nothing, and so did Lacan. Yet Miller
seemed a bit confused by the distinction. He opened the question up to
his audience: âwhat is the difference between void and nothing?â This is
what he asked them. What he gathered from it was that the void has no
limits. So, void is limitless, and yet the ânothingâ is limited by its
place. For ânothing,â the limit is the place within which it is
situated. So, nothing is limited by its place. Hence, the ânothingâ was
for Lacan one of the objet petit a, one of the objects, since the objet
petit a, as semblant, is limited by the world. Unless, of course, we
transgress those laws. An example of this ânothingâ can be found in
Lacanâs Ecrits. He invites us to suppose ourselves to be looking for a
book at the library. It is in the library catalog, it hasnât been
checked out, and yet there is nothing in its place on the shelf where we
expect to know it to be. Thatâs nothing.
The void is something different, since it is not limited by its place.
Suppose for the moment that you expect to find Max Stirner in the world.
Well, you wonât find him there, except as nothing, as missing from that
world. He is not in the library of the world, he is not in the books, he
is not on the pages of the books. That is why we can claim that Stirner
is nothing within the world. Perhaps you expect to find Sergey
Nechayevâs secret society or revolutionary âmanâ in the world. Both are
absent. So they are not in the place we might expect to know them to be
found. Itâs a surprise when that happens. As for the void, it is on the
side of jouissance. It means that it is on the side of the revolutionary
impulse. There is something in the concept of the nothing that
nonetheless connects us to the void. Stirner wrote: âI am not nothing in
the sense of emptiness, which means âlack,â but the creative nothing out
of which I myself as creator create everything [world].â Lacan actually
said something very similar: âthe nothing, a hole in the Real, from
which the Signifier, creates the world.â And then Lacan added: âIt is
the place of deadly jouissance.â The void is on the side of this deadly
jouissance, this revolutionary impulse. The revolutionary impulses are
linked to the void, then; and, with thanks to ânothing,â a âholeâ can be
produced into that deadly jouissance.
This is where the three terms come together. There is a lot of work to
do on these three terms. I wonât be able to do it today. I have a
different agenda. For now, though, we can say that the ânothing,â as an
object, produces a hole in the void of jouissance. The ânothingâ
produces a âholeâ in the real, such that, as semblant, nothing functions
as if it were a non-du-pere. Miller made this very clear for me: âthe
name-of-the-father is an instrument, a semblance. It is a signifier as a
semblant that has the advantage of allowing us to find ourselves in
relation to signifiers and signifieds.â So we can say that without the
non-du-pere, there is no hole in the real, and hence, the void becomes
limitless and revolutionary. We can therefore situate the place of
Stirnerâs âlimitless creativity of jouissance,â the jouissance out of
which he as creator creates a world: it is the revolution of the One,
the revolution of the Ego and Its Own, all alone. It is a bit much for
some of you to follow, but nothing stops us from going a bit further for
today. Miller discussed the void and nothing in relation to hysteria.
His claim was that in hysteria there is âa passage from void to
nothing.â I really like this expression. It highlights the point that
hysteria is also a defense against the real. But Miller did not claim
that the passage from âvoid to nothingâ in hysteria is a transgression
because that would imply that one goes in the opposite direction: from
ânothing to void,â that is, from semblant to real. Put another way, it
would imply that one moves beyond the limits of the world of mastery.
Itâs a key difference.
Hysteria is a defense against the real. So, it is a solution against the
revolution of the One. The solution never works out well for the
hysteric. This is even how psychoanalysis learned about hysteria in the
clinic: through the solution not working out. We can learn about this
other movement, from ânothing to void,â according to Miller, when
hystericâs experience what is called âdepersonalization.â It is a moment
when she becomes Other to herself, but in an extreme sense. It happens,
then, when she is more-than surprised, that is, when she is shocked! It
is not a comfortable feeling when you are surprised too-much. I would
say that shock is âtoo-muchâ surprise. While there are some who canât
get enough surprises, and so they go in search of them, there are others
who get too many surprises in life. In any case, the movement from
nothing to void is difficult to visualize at the conceptual level. This
is why Lacan favored topology. In his âethics seminar,â he discussed --
like Heidegger before him -- the simple topology of a vase.
For Lacan, the vase was perhaps the first signifier. It was a signifier
fabricated in such a way as to construct a space missing. Lacan said
that the vase âintroduces the possibility of filling it.â It led him to
claim that âit is on the basis of the fabricated signifier, this vase,
that emptiness and fullness as such enter the world.â You can even, if
you like, exchange the words âemptyâ and âfullâ for âinsideâ and
âoutside.â The hysteric goes âinsideâ only to demand that you go
âoutside.â Thatâs what the hysterics demanded of Lacan, after 1968. But
it was also what we heard as demands from those who stormed the American
White House with their confederate flags not so long ago. It serves as a
reminder that those who occupy this position are not only anarchists,
and that revolutionaries are diverse, the revolutionary aspiration
offers no guarantee of the world you might imagine for yourself. Lacan
went on: âif the vase may be filled, it is because in the first place,
in its essence, it is empty. And it is exactly in the same sense that
speech may be full or empty.â It forces a return to what I said at the
beginning, last week, about empty and full speech. You cannot be
surprised enough unless you have a vase, and with it, a world.
Incidentally, the person who writes so well about melancholia, the one
who introduced this expression âdepressive realism,â as well as its
theory, long before I began to think about it, namely Julie Reshe,
recently found some flowers outside. To me they looked a bit morbid.
They are nonetheless beautiful, in their way. Especially when they are
placed inside of the nice little vase that she found for them. She
always seems to find a vase for her dark flowers and colorless plants.
Some of these flowers populate the sides of the roads in Ireland. They
are called âspeedwells,â I learned. It sounds almost like âspeak-well.â
I suppose that itâs not that far from it, in fact. However, I prefer my
coffee mug to a vase, because, topologically speaking, a coffee mug has
a hole, whereas a vase, from the standpoint of topology, doesnât. The
coffee mug has a hole, and you can place your finger through it like a
wedding ring. But the vase does not have a hole. Anyway, look at the
time: Iâll continue forward just a bit more.
What I wanted to say today is simply that when we speak of the One, we
are speaking of that part of jouissance that has not been subjected to
the non-du-pere. This means that it is the part of jouissance which was
not prohibited by the signifier. Furthermore, it means that it is the
part of jouissance that is not-all to the world, and which, because of
that, may also be taken on its own, independent of that world and any of
the laws that might attempt to govern or master it. Hence, to summarize
this long detour that brought me to these final thoughts for today, I
would say the following: revolutionary aspirations have to do with the
world of mastery, and the attempt to transgress beyond those laws. It is
a world of jouissance that has been negativized by the signifier, so
that the subject can emerge along the differential network of signifiers
as s-barred. In such cases, the subject is split: the subject is
represented by a signifier for another signifier. Okay, but
revolutionary impulses have to do with what subsists, without
negatization by any non-du-pere, that is, what repeats, as a bubble, as
One, of jouissance.
Finally, we can say that we are ultimately interested in the One and
World. If we are to advance any further as post-anarchists then we
should concern ourselves with the revolutions of the One. The revolution
of the One exists under the thesis of âgeneralized foreclosure.â We can
say that where the world ceases to exist there is One. This is precisely
how Lacan put it in his seminar â... Or Worse,â whose title could be
read as: âthe Master ⊠or Worse.â He said that where the âworld,â that
is, the big Other, ceases to exist, there exists, instead, the One. And
there really is a difficult revolution at stake here. I quote Miller:
â[T]he repetition of the One commemorates an unforgettable irruption of
jouissance. The subject finds himself bound to a cycle of repetitions
[...]. This repetition of jouissance takes place outside of meaning, and
we complain about it.â
When we speak of revolutions of the One there is no reason to discuss
lack, because, quite precisely, lack is lacking. There is a question of
semblances, finally. The semblant is auto-non-mous from the real, and it
involves, for the speaking-being, a modality of dupery. In relation to
âsemblant,â one can be an idiot or a moron. However, I choose stupidity.
Iâll stop.
I hope that I wonât disappoint you too much today. I know that some of
you have been participating in these seminars because youâve been
expecting a more explicit (and perhaps pointed) discussion about
anarchism. In fact, I have a plan for today that involves speaking more
directly on the topic. However, I want to first provide you with a broad
overview of some of the discoveries that Iâve made during the last two
sessions. I began the first day by claiming that there is some
melancholia in each one of us. However, âsomeâ is already âtoo-much.â We
cannot seem to relinquish this âtoo-muchness.â It led to a further claim
that there is another revolution at stake in melancholia, other than the
one frequently discussed within modern anarchist discourses.
Incidentally, if I have been defending this concept of ârevolutionâ then
it is because, quite precisely, it is a Lacanian concept. Perhaps it is
even one of the fundamental concepts, since it implies a logic of
ârepetition.â What I discovered was that Lacanâs definition of
ârevolutionâ was synonymous at one time with his definition of the
âreal,â namely âthat which always returns to its place.â
I was led to think about a revolution that does not have its point of
departure within the world of mastery. When we speak of these sorts of
revolutions we are in essence returning to the Freudian theory of âdeath
drive.â Moreover, we are broaching it as a logic of ârepetitionâ and
âfixation,â the latter being another term for âstubbornness.â Hence,
weâve spoken of the stubbornness of Antigone and Stirner. It permitted
me to separate ârevolutionary aspirationsâ from ârevolutionary
impulses.â Anarchists havenât spoken very well about ârevolutionary
impulsesâ within anarchism because, frankly, theyâve always been
enigmatic to the anarchists themselves. Put simply, the enigmatic
impulses demonstrate that revolutions can outlive the subject. Moreover,
they show us that it is not necessary, at this level, to raise questions
about ârepresentation.â Although modern anarchists were concerned with
epistemic and political representation, revolutionary impulses open us
up to another problem: there are revolutions which repeat without any
representation.
It was a different point of departure than those of the ârevolutionary
aspirations,â which seek to transgress the laws of the world of mastery
and to challenge its modes of epistemic and political representation. We
see it clearly with the hystericâs discourse: the split-subject stages a
confrontation with the master signifier, the anchoring principle of the
world. Lacanâs claim was that the signifier represents the subject for
another signifier. The agent of the hystericâs discourse, the split or
barred subject -- I did not say the âburied subject,â because that would
bring us back to melancholia -- is symbolically torn by signifiers. The
impulses do not partake in this logic because the subject is not-at-all
split by a master signifier at that level; so there are no pitfalls of
representation. Itâs a worse situation!: the subject is set ablaze by
the cold flame, a black flame, of revolution: jouissance. Lacan said:
âthe flame is the real [and it] sets fire to everything. But itâs a cold
flame. There is no limit to the high temperatures one may imagine.â It
reminds me of a point made by Russell Grigg: the real trauma of
jouissance occurs as a consequence of enigmatic status; an enigma
outside of the pitfalls of representation.
There is a shift: from a subject torn at either end by signifiers toward
One which is not torn by signifiers. The One is a bubble, a bubble of
jouissance, not barred by any signifier. Put simply: there is, on the
one hand, a split-subject, and there is, on the other hand, a subject
without splitting. It implies that there are different subjects at stake
in the âaspirationsâ and in the âimpulses.â On the one hand, there is
the subject split by signifiers whose truth might be revealed as being
implicated in the totality of the signifying system, and, on the other
hand, there is the speaking-being taken outside of that totality, what
Lacan named the parletre. The parletre is a being who speaks, yes, but
with its jouissance. She is not torn apart from within by signifiers of
the symbolic, which doesnât mean that there isnât a traumatic encounter
with the signifier. The point is that our point of departure changes: we
no longer begin from the victimized or split subject of representation
but rather from the tragically triumphant subject of enjoyment, the
parletre. It is also a movement from suffering to trauma. I make a
distinction then: the split-subject suffers but the parletre is
traumatized.
It is why I have found that a vase is a much more interesting object
than a coffee cup. There is something quite remarkable about the
practice of placing dead flowers into a vase. Maybe every psychoanalyst
should have dead flowers in a vase placed onto the bookshelves or desks
in their consulting rooms to remind them of this point. For every
consulting room, as for every home, a vase. Why? Well, remember that a
vase is not a coffee cup. That really makes a difference. When the
subject is not split then it means that there is no home for that
subject as a speaking-being in the world. It doesnât mean that it cannot
be without a home, since not being without a home is quite different
from being homeless as well as having a home. Julie reminded us last
week that the unheimlich, variously translated as âuncannyâ or
âunhomely,â for Freud, but also for Heidegger, is, basically, a
topological device. She said that the vase is like a home. It is
brilliant. It is why I would claim that Julie is a vase to me. In any
case, during this commentary she reminded us that a home has holes. I
find it interesting because today there are more vases than homes in the
world. But from the standpoint of topology a vase does not have any
holes. This is why the vase is closer to the Buenaventura Hotel than a
home; remember that Fredric Jameson described the hotel in his essay on
postmodern ideology. In any case, with the Beneventura Hotel, like the
vase, you do not know if it is possible to enter the space, or leave it.
Where is the inside and where is the outside? Is the distinction
traceable at the level of structure? It is fascinating to me, because,
for example, we are told that postmodern architecture is produced in
such a way that it reflects the world back at itself. On a sunny day, or
even during the evening, you cannot see the hotel because it reflects
the world back at you. Finally, there is only the world, which overtakes
the hotel, such that there is only âworld.â I can imagine that the
Buenaventura Hotel disappears into the world like Antigone disappeared
into the world: that is why, ultimately, it is a piece of melancholic
architecture. In any case, if you play with the surface of a vase,
melting down the surfaces while retaining all âthru-holes,â it becomes
reducible to a disc or a sphere. Finally, it becomes a ball: a surface
without a hole, One. It is not like my coffee cup because there is a
little space for your finger on the side and this means that it can be
reduced to a donut or a torus, which has a hole. That is the difference
between a vase and a coffee cup: âno-holeâ and âhole.â It is also the
difference between, on the one hand, my childhood home, which has a
front door that can bring you, without any obstructions, right out the
back door, and, on the other hand, the Buenaventura Hotel.
I apologize for the tangent, but I have something else to say about
melancholic architecture. While working in Russia as a professor at the
School of Advanced Studies, University of Tyumen, I remember having
dreams about being trapped inside of the campus building. Iâm not sure
that it was a dream. In fact, it was a nightmare, which means,
precisely, that I wasnât dreaming. Most of the people who worked there
felt the same way. We would talk privately about how we would each wake
up in the middle of the night and check our emails and text messages to
be sure that we didnât miss a request from the institution. So, it was a
nightmare. The building was designed in such a way that you never really
feel outside of it, and yet, upon entering it, you feel endlessly
reflected back outside: you are not wanted by this building or by this
school. We couldnât leave the fucking place, even though it took a
grueling few weeks of proving oneself in initiations, âproject design
sessions,â as they called them, which are really just hazing rituals,
just to get âinside,â to get hired. Even when we left, tried to go
outside, due to the war, fleeing Russia because of the war, the building
and some of its people followed us around like a bad nightmare: taunting
us, provoking my family on social media, and so on. Well, I learned that
the building design was inspired by another one, from Moscow City, a
part of the infamous Skokovo campus, named âthe hypercube.â Perhaps it
was designed by the same architect. Anyway, if you are Canadian then you
no doubt recognize this word âhypercubeâ because it was also the name of
a popular horror film franchise.
The film is about the horror of getting outside of the cube once you are
found mysteriously inside of it. You canât seem to find a way out. The
students at the aforementioned university have even given wonderful
presentations showcasing the similarities between the âhypercubeâ of the
film and the actual world of the School of Advanced Studies, University
of Tyumen. What fascinated me was that one could only ever find a way
outside of the hypercube, in the film, through mathematics, through
formulae, and so on. It is a way to break through the verbosity of
knowledge in order to arrive at a hard kernel, what Lacan called the
âletter.â It is a point of convergence between the real and the
symbolic; a pact, something like a quilting point against the terror of
not having an âinsideâ or an âoutside.â It is a point that we can
explore another time. For now, the point is simply that when there is no
hole you experience the world as if it were a vase rather than a torus.
Finally, when you live in that sort of nightmare you might have a vase
but that doesnât mean that you have a home.
As I see it, one of the fundamental problems in the West began several
decades ago, roughly corresponding with a transitional moment in its
social history, has been radical homelessness. There is even a dimension
of radical homelessness at play in Freudâs essay on the unheimlich. It
seems to me that the âdoubleâ appears there often as something in the
real that was foreclosed in the symbolic. Hence, the dolls whose eyes
feel threatening to children, the sandman delusions, and so on, occur
when the signifier does not castrate, but the real does. In any case,
there are more than enough vases in the world today. I am reminded,
suddenly, that you can find some vases inside of the Kabbah in Mecca,
Godâs home, giving the impression that the congregations there, the
umma, are circumambulating not around the home but rather around the
vases. The vases are nested inside of the Kabbah, and the revolutions
there keep you spinning, returning to the same place. In any case, a
nightmare is a disc, or a navel of the dream-house, and it goes on and
on. You wake up only to find yourself repeating the nightmare again.
I would say that it is only by permitting yourself to be a dupe, by
believing in the semblant, or in what Stirner named a âspook,â that you
are capable of producing a hole in jouissance. Otherwise the hole turns
on the symbolic such that a hole occurs on the very space that would
have housed the signifier, in which case one wouldnât have a home with
holes but a hole in the place of a home. So, it is a vase without a
home. The revolutions of the One, which involve repetitions not-at-all
in the world, are revolutions that occur without a home. So the key
question is this: how can one speak when there is a housing crisis?
Anarchists might propose that you squat the homes of oligarchs and
masters but it will not solve the problem. You only move into the space
of mastery, demonstrating, for the time being, that you can pretend to
be the king of the castle. I begin from a different perspective, with
the presumption that we all have some homelessness within ourselves. And
even some homelessness is âtoo-much.â Therefore, even a king who
believes that he has a castle is homeless.
I said something last week that made some of you uncomfortable. Iâm not
necessarily concerned. You know, I canât exactly be âcanceledâ because
Russia already canceled me. I take this very clever point from Julie who
said in a recent interview that Russia has been trying to âcancelâ
Ukraine. However, Iâve already been âcanceled.â It is why I am giving
this lecture to you from a bedroom that is not my own. I am in a period
of homelessness. Yet, for all that I would claim that I am not without a
home. I do have access to this bedroom, and access to this home, which
provides me with certain luxuries, despite the circumstances. Anyway,
the uncomfortable claim that I made was that we moved from the
âall-worldâ to the ânot-all world,â which are two different governing
principles. Finally, it is a shift into a feminine world. Itâs not
exactly good news. It means, for example, that our social movements have
become like bubbles disjointed from the world. This is why it is
necessary to speak of anarchist social movements.
Lacan had a name for these ânewest social movements:â âfraternities.â A
few weeks ago I gave a lecture to a different audience where I tried to
convince some people that Althusserâs logic of ideological
interpellation was actually a way of âfraternizingâ with police
officers, rather than subjection to a symbolic master, splitting the
subject. It helped me to explain Althusserâs melancholia. In any case,
Lacan was, in fact, a bit of a sociologist, perhaps more sociological
than sociologists themselves, and he was even a scholar of the newest
social movements. What he named âfraternitiesâ were a group orientation.
Psychoanalysts have always been suspicious of groups, but that doesnât
mean that we are incapable of working alongside one another -- even if
it proves difficult. After all, the group is also a subject.
Psychoanalysts have a different orientation to the group, a position
closer to Max Stirnerâs âunion of egoistsâ but not reducible to it. It
is close also to the anarchist logic of the âaffinity group.â Except
Lacan called his âaffinity groupâ a âcartel.â However, there are key
differences between an âaffinity groupâ and a âcartel.â
The âcartelâ does not pretend to eradicate the place of power. Rather,
it effects a separation of knowledge and power. We can see this clearly
in the function of the âplus oneâ in the psychoanalytic cartel. The
âplus oneâ is not a place of representation. Quite the opposite. The
âplus oneâ of the psychoanalytic âcartelâ is a place of
âhystericization,â a place that functions to disrupt the group effects
that lead us toward either âhierarchyâ or else âfraternity.â This is how
I read the cartel as a group. The cartel, which is an âorganâ of the
psychoanalytic School,â was capable of producing what anarchists have
never been capable of producing: a group that is anti-authoritarian,
anti-representation, but also anti-fraternity, and yet, for all that,
without killing the world or the space that would house the loneliness
of the subject. The cartel is an answer to the question: âhow can we
live with the consequences of the revolutionary impulsesâ without in the
process producing a device that would bury the subject in his or her own
revolutionary impulses. In any case, there is more to say about these
ânewest social movements,â which are not at all the stuff of
psychoanalytic âgroups.â
I have named these newest social movements, these fraternities,
âsingularities.â We can trace a history of the emergence of
singularities in the Western world. Many have done so, in each their own
way and with each their own assessment of the consequences. Most have
claimed that the transition began in the last part of the 1960s or in
the early 1970s. Slavoj Zizek took his bearings from Lacan and described
the transition as a being characterized by a âdecline of symbolic
efficiency.â It means that the function of the name-of-the-father, as
master signifier, weakened, no longer being the lynchpin of Western
social bonds. There have been an assortment of names to describe this
new logic: âpost-patriarchal,â âneoliberal,â âpostmodern, âpostmodern
capitalism,â âliquid modernity,â ârisk society,â âthe society of the
spectacle,â âprosumer capitalism,â and so on. Each position constructs a
narrative for itself concerning the mortification of the master
signifier as the lynchpin of the social bond. In other words, these
narratives concern the mortification of the place of power, which is the
signifier. The traditional way of thinking about this was to claim that
a master signifier would have prohibited jouissance, which means that it
would have negated jouissance. Admittedly, Lacanians discovered that
there was always this bit of surplus jouissance, this residue of
positive jouissance that could not be negated.
Finally, not-all of it would have been negated. We can say that
jouissance is therefore the source of a certain toxic positivity. There
is a positivity to jouissance because at its root it refuses to be
relinquished, negated. The subject, by accepting the prohibition of
jouissance, would have emerged split from within the totality of its
social relations, split from its cause. For example, the subject would
have been split off from other workers, other women, and so on. This was
even the foundation upon which much of the earlier Marxist criticism
aimed, particularly before the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts.
The subject was thought to be split from the totality of its symbolic
relationships. In a word, the subject was represented by one-signifier
for another signifier, and this was the price of admission into the
Western social order. Freud named âneurosisâ that condition resulting
from not accepting the prior mortification of jouissance. Neurosis is
the inability to live with the consequences of the part that was
not-at-all made for civilization.
Neurotics suffered because they cannot live with the consequences of
having paid the price, so they went to psychoanalysts to find reprieve
from their symptoms. However, singularities have not paid the price from
the beginning and therefore have no need of psychoanalysts. They are not
in search of any surprises because they already have too-much. But it
doesnât stop singularities from forming groups, fraternizing with one
another. What some anarchists have referred to as the ânewest social
movementsâ are precisely these singularities: bubbles without
castration.
The revolutionary aspirations of modern anarchism have led to a
proliferation of relatively autonomous social movements whose
confrontation with the master became postponed, or, at the extreme,
abandoned. Raymond Williams would have described it as a âlong
revolution.â But all revolutions are âlongâ when you begin from the
position of the slaveâs aspirations. The slave postpones a confrontation
with the master out of fear of death, about which he is certain. This is
what begins the long revolution from the standpoint of the slaveâs
revolutionary aspirations. Autonomous social movements demonstrate a
problem that exists beyond political representation and the long
revolution: jouissance. The key problem of these singularities is not
âhow can we live without a masterâ but rather âhow can we live within
the mystery?â And in his ethics seminar, Lacan reminded us that âthe
thing,â the âcause,â is the real secret. When you make the thing your
cause, when you make the cause your own, you become the secret, the
enigma, the mystery. But how to live with this unbearable mystery of
jouissance?
A Canadian anarchist professor named Richard J. F. Day wrote an
incredible book titled Gramsci is Dead: Anarchist Currents in the Newest
Social Movements. It was an important book for me before I discovered
clinical psychoanalysis. I left my hometown and traveled to the other
side of Canada to study with him. His work showcases attempts to live
beyond revolutionary aspirations. What he named âthe logic of hegemonyâ
is in our language the world of the âall.â For him, it is a logic whose
political tendencies are oriented by either âreformâ or ârevolution.â
These twin tendencies are traps because they remain within a totalizing
principle, the âall.â It is clear to me that the book discovered a
secret: how to locate the spaces of the ânot-all.â However, it did not
offer a way to sustain that space. I can imagine these as melancholic
communities, spaces of suicidal ideation. His claim, put simply, was
that anarchists discovered an alternative political logic not-at-all
trapped within the logic of hegemony. What was his logic? It was a logic
beyond the determinations of the world of mastery.
It is a logic of âautonomyâ or âsingularity.â Those are the words he
used. His idea was that the future world could be experienced today,
here and now. It was also the position of some of the more peripheral
anarchists, including Gustav Landeaur and Hakim Bey. It is a call to
experience the future today and to ârender redundant,â as he put it, the
world of mastery. I never quite understood what it meant to ârender
redundantâ the world ⊠until I saw the Beneventura Hotel. It is as if
the world of mastery would defeat itself if only you allowed it to go on
living without you, to go on rambling without you. It is an uncoupling
of oneself from the world, the displacement of the subject from the
world into the autonomous zones of the ones-all-all. These singular
communities are described as âthe coming communities,â a phrase borrowed
from Giorgio Agamben. How are these ones-all-alone organized? He used
the anarchist and autonomous Marxist language of âaffinity,â ânetwork,â
and âvoluntary association.â
This latter phrase -- âvoluntary associationâ -- has been very important
for some anarchists, particularly those in the United States of America,
but also those in the United Kingdom. It was also an important concept
for Benjamin Tucker, Emma Goldman, and who knows how many of the earlier
classical anarchists. They insisted upon principles of voluntary
associations, voluntary social bonds formed of oneâs own free
motivation. It is different from the alienation described by Marx: where
one is forced into social bonds at the workplace not of oneâs own
choosing. It seems to presume, then, a social bond entirely independent
of the world of mastery. So: either it is a goal to be achieved and
hence an aspiration or else we must presume that it is to be achieved
here and now, spontaneously. This raises some problems. If we cannot
have a voluntary association until we are prepared for it, that is,
until we are capable of forming fair and equal bonds with one another
without various strata of mastery or ideology, then it is a
revolutionary aspiration. But if you think you can begin in the here and
now then you must presume that there are no systems of mastery already
in place for those subjects.
Take, for example, the related psychoanalytic concept of âfree
association,â one of the golden rules of traditional psychoanalysis. You
are told by your psychoanalyst to speak freely in your analytic work
with your psychoanalyst. But then, after months or decades you begin to
recognize that you had certain unconscious presuppositions that had been
motivating all of your speech, and that hadnât yet been interrogated.
So, you move into âfull speech,â as Lacan once called it. In the final
instance, it is an aspiration, it is based upon free association which,
like free speech, is governed by the contours of your linguistic world.
It is why I maintain that revolutionary impulses are neither reducible
to aspirations toward the future nor are they merely in the âhere and
now.â Rather, they come to us from the future. Melancholia is a view
from the future. I gave a lecture on this a few weeks ago so I wonât
repeat all of my reasoning today. However, I will add that revolutionary
aspirations are a view toward an impossible future. In any case, I
return to my thread. Autonomous organizations are meant to exist outside
of the logic of totality, outside of the âall,â and hence, as a view
from the future. Anarchists pride themselves often on suggesting that
they have at least one foot in the future. They prefigure the future
they would like to see, here and now.
What is also surprising to me is that Richard J. F. Day described his
autonomous logic as being a ârevolutionary impulse.â It is just a
coincidence, but a convenient one. I'll share a quote from his book:
â[t]he radical impulse of post-1968 French theory [was] the impulse to
create alternatives to the state and corporate forms rather than just
work within them.â Once again, it is not a call to go outside but rather
a call from the outside. It is for this reason that I claim that
autonomy is the work of radical homelessness. How can the autonomous
movement grow in influence if not without finding a means to not be
without a world, that is, to write a book or enter a lecture hall to
remind everybody that they must go outside. It is only during moments of
particular lucidity that these âalternativesâ presume themselves to be
independent of the world of mastery. The problem is that the
contemporary world is also increasingly independent of the world of
mastery, which doesnât mean that this world is inhabitable.
It also doesnât mean that fascism and tyranny do not exist, or that we
do not have in our midst dangerous new forms of radical authoritarianism
across all corners of the globe. It just means that they function
according to a different, more singular, and hence more cunning, logic.
Perhaps, to provoke you, I will claim that the logic of âautonomyâ has
become the dominant principle of our world. Lacan warned us about this
when he spoke about the rise of âfraternities,â which are societies of
âbrothersâ and âcomrades.â They come after the weakening of the paternal
metaphor, the weakening of the organizational capacity of the
âname-of-the-father.â This rise of the logic of autonomy, voluntary
association, characteristic of the newest social movements can be quite
accurately described as being predicated upon a more primordial logic of
âsegregation.â I remember it quite clearly, when I was at Queenâs
University organizing with the revolutionary anarchist students. These
were fraternal activities. The principle of âvoluntary associationâ was
taken very seriously by most of them, and used, precisely, as a means of
âsegregation.â
I even remember pointing out to them that it seemed to be an easy way to
justify segregation from âpeople of color.â I was quite moronic at the
time. So I said: âwhat stops you from voluntarily associating only with
men, implicitly excluding women?â You could say, simply: âvoluntary
association, it is freedom! Iâm not excluding anybody, Iâm just freely
choosing who to include.â Of course, racism has a very particular
meaning, but for Lacan it took on a characteristic logic of our time. We
can call it âLacanian racism,â or, as Eric Laurent put it: âracism 2.0.â
It is not âreverse racismâ but rather a logic of âsegregationâ that
inevitably occurs among singularities. When they spit out antagonisms,
ruptures, fissures, constitutive lack, and so on, so that nothing is
lacking from within the group, there is a segregation from the world.
The singularity segregates itself from the world, and from other
singularities whose jouissance is insulting or traumatizing to them.
When castration is not accepted, when foreclosure is generalized, the
split which would have made internal relations difficult and produced
aspirations of overcoming them, gets rejected. It returns with a
vengeance from without, outside of the singularity, from the real.
Suddenly, because castration shifts into the real, one experiences the
world as a truly threatening place. The signifier no longer represents
the group but rather triggers the group.
This was Lacanâs early definition of foreclosure, taken from his third
seminar: what gets rejected from the symbolic, namely castration,
returns in the real. It came from Freudâs discussion of psychosis: what
is rejected returns from without. What is outside of the singularity
becomes quite precisely a potential source of trauma or insult for
everything inside the singularity. This is what the principle of
fraternity entials (I will quote Lacan):
Fraternity is founded on segregation. No fraternity is conceivable, has
even the slightest foundation [...] except through the fact that people
are isolated together, isolated from the rest [...].
We could have said: â... isolated from the world.â This quotation comes
from the later teaching of Lacan, but, already in the third seminar
there was an interest in the concept of fraternity among the psychotic
figure of Schreber, whose earliest manifestation of psychosis was
perhaps melancholic. Lacan focused on Schreberâs âsoul murder,â citing a
âsoul fragment,â which might have later been referred to as a semblant,
or, why not, a âspook.â The semblant was established by Schreber by way
of a fraternity named âThe brotherâs of Cassiopeia.â I will quote a long
passage from Lacanâs third seminar:
A soul fragment thus ties itself on somewhere. Cassiopeia, the brothers
of Cassiopeia, play a major role here. [...] It is the name of a student
confederation from the time of Schreberâs studies. An attachment to such
a fraternity, whose narcissitic, even homosexual, character is brought
out in the analysis, is moreover a characteristic mark of Schreberâs
imaginary antecedents. It is suggestive to see how this network, which
is symbolic by nature and maintains the image in a degree of stability
in interhuman relationships, is necessary so that everything doesnât
suddenly reduce to nothing, so that the entire veil of the imaginary
relation does not suddenly draw back and disappear in the yawning
blackness that Scrhreber was not so very far away from at the outside.
It goes to show you that the future teachings of Lacan have their way of
producing effects precisely in his past teaching.
Let me be straightforward: we used to doubt our knowledge. Consequently,
we supposed that there were âexpertsâ out there (e.g., doctors, police
officers, judges, presidents, professors, psychoanalysts). Today there
is a general incredulity toward meta-narratives. That is how Lyotard put
it. It means that there is an intense suspicion of the world of mastery
and of the knowledge generated by constituents of that world.
Singularities do not overthrow that world but rather find themselves
uncoupled from it. This produces the paradoxical result of an ever more
cruel, disgusting, and insulting world. The problem shifts into another
register: for example, we have not become âpost-patriarchal,â as some
suggest today; rather, we have displaced the âsymbolic patriarchyâ into
a âreal patriarchy.â This is worse! We got out of patriarchy only to
experience it in a much more devastating way. Moreover, we have not
actually conquered our doubts, we have merely replaced them with
certainties and discovered that it is the world that doubts us.
It is a fundamental change. Today, more than ever, the voices that are
foregrounded in political and social commentary begin with
presuppositions regarding their singular group. It belies a fear of
falling into the depths of uncertainty, of losing the space within which
we are capable of speaking. The problem is that the world doubts our
presuppositions, our certainty. Hence, the world becomes threatening to
the integrity of the singularity. So, we attempt to defend, at all
costs, the certainty of a semblant that sustains our fraternal group and
that threatens to take away the space of our speech, leaving us,
essentially, destitute, homeless. Hence the stubbornness of todayâs
newest social movements testifies more generally to the cancellation of
the dwelling space of language and speech. It leads us to a problem: the
newest social movements, by practicing tactical political philosophy,
cannot seem to escape the pitfalls of the revolution of the One. This
expression âtactical political philosophyâ comes out of the
post-anarchist political philosophy of Todd May. I should bring our
discussion to a close today by speaking a bit about his political
framework.
Todd May is against psychoanalysis, as well as the Lacanian tradition.
He sees it as being too focused on the individual rather than the
collective, which amounts to, I would say, the fraternity. The problem
is quite the opposite: the fraternity leaves no space for the subject.
It is the fraternity which is in-dividual, without division. In any
case, May famously distinguished between three types of political
philosophies: âformal,â âstrategic,â and, his brand, âtactical.â In a
word, according to him, formal political philosophy cleaves stubborning
either to what is or else to what should be. It is a stubborn position
because it refuses the tension between what is and what should be, and
therefore refuses work in the tension of is or ought. For example: you
can focus on preserving the political order as it currently is without
concerning oneself at all with what ought to be. Or, perhaps you could
go the other way: focus on the political order that ought to exist
without recognizing that you must, nonetheless, relate oneself to the
world as it actually is. This is how Todd May plots formal politics, in
a nutshell.
Strategic political philosophy was thought to be an advancement because
there is a concern with the tension between the is and the ought. The
problem is that it remains tethered to what he names a âunitary analysis
of power.â In other words, there is a concern with what Saul Newman,
whose work to which I am much more closely aligned, refers to as âthe
place of power.â It is a central idea in modern revolutionary political
philosophy that there is a âplace of power,â and that the abolition of
this âunitaryâ place, produces an effect of liberation. The revolution
is therefore against the place of power. Hence, overcoming the âplace of
powerâ implies that one can live in the great totality of signifying
relations: workers join hands with workers, and so on. So, strategic
political philosophy has a central agenda around which all political
aspirations lead: it is the âunitâ or the âobject,â or what we would
call a master signifier, or signifier-One. The problem is manifold:
first, it is clear that the anarchists complicated the Marxist
conception of power. It is a point that Saul Newman once made very
clearly: if it were only about removing the place of power then we must
have presumed something about the ârealâ that is hiding outside of
power. In other words, we must rely upon presuppositions, certainties,
that the real subject is basically good, social, creative, and so on.
The anarchist challenge to Marxism was at a very early time to suggest
that there are multiple âregisters of power.â This was how Todd May put
it: multiple nodes or registers of power. It means that there is not a
âunitary analysis,â since that would imply a centralization of the power
within the master. Anarchists demonstrated very early that power is not
centralized in one location or object (e.g., the state, or the economy).
There is also patriarchy, racism, the ideological manipulation of the
church, and so on. Finally, we recognize that there are multiple
registers of power. At this point we are led toward what Todd May called
âtactical political philosophy,â which is informed by post-structuralism
and anarchism. It is a politics oriented by the multiplicitous registers
of power rather than one particular location of power. What is
interesting to me is that it means that there can always be one more
place of power. This is what Todd Mayâs challenge leads us to consider.
It means that no matter how many places of power are registered ⊠there
can always be one more. There is always another possible site of capture
for the subject. We can call this the âplus one,â if you like: it is the
infinity of registers of power that tactical political philosophy
demonstrates.
Finally, we confront what is beyond the places of power: the real. It
can be discussed in many ways. Perhaps we could say -- some people
thought they were clever in their critique of Foucault by saying this --
âif power is everywhere, then power is nowhere and nothing.â But that
was, precisely, Stirnerâs point: the ânothingâ is the only âsemblantâ
that can still hold it all together, a last defense against the âreal.â
An overlooked point with Todd Mayâs analysis is that he believes that
the proliferation of networks of power, the constant reinvention of
power in different nodal points, conglomerations of power, implies that
there is an infinitely constituted space of resistance and revolution.
The revolution becomes infinite, or, as Simon Critchley once put it, one
of the subjectâs âinfinite demands to power.â In other words, we end up
precisely in the surprising place of the âplus one:â power is never
where âwe expect to know itâ to be. In this conception, power is a
surprise package. And from the future possibilities of power, there is
an endless resistance, an endless revolution. Put another way, power
continuously changes, domineering within certain registers, and then
receding, inventing new unforeseen registers, and so on. Saul Newman
recognized this, briefly, when he said that there is a âshopping listâ
of oppressions which anarchists are supposed to pay homage to - and
there is always a new one we didnât see coming.
Revolution therefore becomes transformed into the repetition of an
encounter with mastery, without end: it becomes the revolution of the
One.
At this point I think it is fruitful to adopt a topological approach.
The strategic approach is akin to hysterical revolutions. Yet, the
post-structuralist anarchist approach, it seems to me, surprises us by
discovering the space of singularity and the revolutions of the One. It
is an approach of singularity because there is no single master. Rather,
there exists a series, a repetition, of encounters with the master, that
is, with the signifier: each one is traumatic and triggering. Todd May
wrote:
[F]or tactical political philosophy, there is no center within which
power is to be located. Otherwise put, power, and consequently politics,
are irreducible. There are many different sites from which it arises,
and there is an interplay among these various sites in the creation of
the social world.
It is clear that the movement away from the âunitary analysisâ (which is
an analysis of a confrontation with the master signifier, that is, the
name-of-the-father) transforms into a tactical confrontation without a
name-of-the-father, that is, without the master signifier. At this
point, one confronts the world as such, never knowing when or where
power might next launch its attack. This is why I caution against the
approach which begins from a celebration of the newest social movements,
as well as the approaches that have hitherto been classified as formal,
strategic, and/or tactical political philosophy. It seems to me that we
need to invent another position.
This is what psychoanalytic anarchism opens us up into: if
post-anarchism is to continue to be relevant today then it should be
taken as a moment of surprise for anarchism and not as a
post-structuralist position. It must find itself surprised by what
anarchism has become, by what weâve been saying and doing within our
social movements. Finally, it should be prepared to invent an anarchism
that is not without a world. It is this point that I hope to develop and
conclude with, in a more concise way, next week. I hope that you will
all join me for that final session.
[Mark Gerard Murphy introduces Duane]
Thank you Mark, for your spark.
I want to begin with a joke. It was told to me by a friend named
Zuleykha, and Iâll repeat it here in my own way. A man goes to the
grocery store and asks the clerk for 1000 eggs. It is a small shop, so
the clerk informed the customer that he only had a few dozen eggs in
stock. The customer seemed disappointed, and left the store. But he
returned the next day and asked again: âdo you have 1000 eggs?â The
clerk, even more surprised, gave the same response: âIâm sorry, we only
have a few dozen eggs in stock.â This continued day after day for months
until, finally, the clerk realized that he was missing out on an
important business opportunity. He collects together 1000 eggs to sell
to the man. The man returns to the shop the next morning and asks, âdo
you have 1000 eggs?â The clerk responds: âyes, as a matter of fact, we
do have 1000 eggs.â The customer smiles and says: âOkay, will you sell
me one of them?â
It is clear that the customer would have kept returning, day after day.
There was a repetition at stake in the joke. Yet, precisely when the
clerk thought he found a way to benefit from the repetition, to put an
end to it, he discovered that there was behind all of that a
stubbornness to continue.
I cannot promise that todayâs lecture will be altogether easy to follow.
Iâll be developing and perhaps even summarizing thoughts that were
introduced in prior lectures. If you feel a bit lost then you might at
some point return to watch those lectures, which are available on
YouTube. Today I am offering a final lecture for this series on
âpost-anarchism and psychoanalysis.â That makes this lecture a
particularly serious one. Anyway, thatâs precisely what I provided, a
lecture series. And today I will attempt to circumscribe what it was
within this lecture series that was most serious. The first seminar was
framed by a discussion of ârevolutionary melancholia,â and it led me to
introduce a distinction between ârevolutionary aspirationsâ and
ârevolutionary impulses.â Post-anarchists have written already about the
former, the aspirations. For example, there was an excellent essay by
Saul Newman that you might go and read on The Anarchist Library titled
âInterrogating the Master.â These aspirations operate along the pathways
of desire, and they are exemplified by those hysterics who interrogated
Jacques Lacan during the French uprisings of the late 1960s. You already
know his response: â... as revolutionaries, what you aspire to is a
master. You will get it.â
Okay, I donât think it was a threat. He wasnât threatening them. It was
a prophecy. In fact, I do believe that prophets âexistâ (which is to say
nothing about their âbeing,â but that is a discussion for another
lecture). Perhaps it is one that Mark and I might have one day: âwhat is
a prophecy?â In any case, what those revolutionaries demonstrated was
that their desires were supported by the world. In his way, Lacan
proposed that they remained fundamentally committed to the world, which
was, truth be told, a world of mastery. So much for the revolutionary
aspirations, there are also revolutionary impulses, which operate along
the circuit of the drive. It is a movement from âdesireâ toward what
Freud called the âdrive.â These impulses operate outside of the symbolic
and imaginary coordinates of the world, and this is why we can claim
that they are lawless. Lawlessness occurs when there is a more
fundamental resistance to the world, when, in the final instance, one
resists incorporation into the world. Incidentally, for a very long time
there have been critical debates, mostly originating within Lacanian
circles, about the proper translation of Freudâs various words:
âdrives,â âinstincts,â âimpulses.â The thought occurred to them that the
standard translation conflated these concepts, and so it is important to
effect a separation of concepts. I donât see why we canât maintain the
conflation, since impulses have a non-discursive, almost biological,
locus.
In any case, I stumbled upon a point that really fascinated me. I even
wondered why nobody else noticed it. Why hasnât Daniel Colson, when he
was researching for his paper on Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and Jacques
Lacan, noticed the homology within Lacanâs teaching on the concept of
ârevolutionâ and âreal.â It is a point within Lacanâs teaching: he
provided the same definition for both concepts. Itâs remarkable. It
means that Lacan was in fact a bit of a revolutionary, since he
committed to the concept of the ârealâ and to the ârevolutionâ that
would not return the subject back into the world of mastery. What was at
stake in each concept? In both cases, we are told to take the rotations
of the heavenly bodies as our example, as in, for example, early
science: a ârealâ which revolves. These heavenly bodies always return to
their place. The ârealâ and ârevolutionâ are synonymous concepts which
target a logic of âreturning to its placeâ and âresisting the symbolic.â
Well, it points toward what Freud named âfixation.â At this point, we
reach something that is quite stubborn.
This fixation at the core of the ârealâ of ârevolutionâ forces us to be
very serious, stubborn, perhaps even stern. We also find this in a
psychoanalytic session: as the time passes--month after month, year
after year--there are therapeutic effects, but still, in the final
instance, something of our suffering or enjoyment, our âjouissance,â
remains, persists. It is stubborn, fixed. And the sessions go on like
that, demonstrating that we only ever become more and more stern, âŠ
sterner. For us, it necessitates a theory of repetition and fixation
concerning the revolutionary impulses: what is it that repeats in these
impulses? The stubborn fixation we take as âone,â and it is the âoneâ of
an enigmatic jouissance. This âoneâ of enigmatic jouissance, which we
can isolate from the series of repetitions, as Lacan did in his later
teaching, it localizes something of trauma. There is a trauma at the
core of any law, representation, meaning, or image. Perhaps we can be
led to believe that there is even a âpoliticalâ jouissance that bears
some relation to this stubborn âone.â It was a point under-developed in
the work of Slavoj Zizek, who, in the 1990s, was among the first, though
it was still long after Jacques Lacan and Jacques-Alain Miller, to argue
that enjoyment, or jouissance, is a political factor.
Ultimately, I follow Slavoj in this direction. But I do it in my own
way. He was always fond of saying: âwe should be willing to go to the
end!â Slavoj, who always supports my work and who is a friend, should
nonetheless be asked: well, why didnât you go to the end of your
analysis with Miller? It is a discussion concerning the end of analysis,
and, indeed, the end of the world. If there is a political trauma that
we might isolate in the domain of politics then what those
revolutionaries demonstrated was that their hysteria was a mode of
defense against that trauma. In the end, hysterics prefer to maintain
their relationship to the world, and to the master. The hysteric is not
entirely willing to go to the end! It is perhaps why there are so very
few who have in fact gone to the end of their analysis, and even those
who do, they often return again. The goal of analysis is quite simply to
transform the hysteric into an analyst, that is, into one who does go
beyond the end of analysis. In any case, the anarchist is the one for
whom politics also consists of contingent encounters with what exists
outside of the world of mastery. So, there are really two anarchist
traditions, and they do not necessarily operate in isolation from one
another.
What I want to convince you of today is that itâs not exactly progress
when the anarchist overcomes the world of mastery. The situation can
become much worse: the world itself can become a cruel master, the
master becomes real. It is a movement from a world that was
characterized by internal problems and inconsistencies toward a world
that is fundamentally suffering: a trauma without a world to house it.
So: from suffering to trauma, which is not progress. Itâs worse. And it
was why Lacanâs seminar, which occurred during a period of uprisings,
was titled â... Or Worse.â We all know that it was supposed to be called
âthe father, or worse.â Yet, the father is missing from the seminar
title, missing from that symbolic place. So you just have to imagine
that the father is there, which is precisely what we seem to be doing.
It was a point that led me to provide a third lecture on the topic of
what precisely is worse today. So, I spoke about âsingularities.â Thatâs
what I call them. And I examined their logic, with particular attention
to the ânewest social movements.â
I turned to the work of Todd May and Richard J. F. Day to show how
post-anarchist theory succumbed to the temptation to remain complicit
with the contemporary political world: a world of weakening
prohibitions. Itâs not a discovery that Iâm happy to report. I was
inspired by the work of May and Day, but now it is June and it is Night:
May Day is over. Things have changed in the years that have passed: the
world has gone dark. It is surprising to me. Again, I donât mind being
surprised. However, it is clear to me that many people donât like to
feel surprised anymore. I have even claimed that what was so essential
about post-anarchist theory was that it surprised anarchists. We became
surprised by what it was that we have been saying for over 150 years.
Anarchism was also at one time a surprise to the modern world,
especially to the Marxists who they were often provoking. What was most
important about post-anarchist was that it surprised us. Itâs a
fundamental point because post-anarchism surprised us by demonstrating
that the modern or classical anarchist tradition was a defense against
our revolution impulses: we preferred to remain within the world of
mastery. Learning that was surprising to us.
Some of our critics described these theories as a joke. It might even
surprise you to learn that I prefer that it be understood as a joke.
Freud showed us where a joke leads: toward the unconscious. Today, of
course, it is very difficult to tell a joke. And it is why we must learn
how to be surprised again. But singularities are too serious for jokes:
there is nothing to laugh about. The joke can only exist in a world
within which one aspires toward liberation. However, we seemed to
witness the comedians move from aspiration toward perspiration, sweating
on stage rather than laughing. When you are outside of the world, jokes
might become insulting to you. I know that it doesnât make any of this
easier for you to accept but I am not trying to insult any of you: my
feeling is that we are in the worst of times. It is not that we are
approaching some apocalypse-to-come but rather that the apocalypse has
already happened. Maybe Iâm holding my lantern today, whispering to you
that the world is already dead, that you have killed it. We have already
lost our world. Consequently, I would say, our social bonds are
increasingly structured according to a logic of segregation.
The newest social movements have demonstrated this point very well. They
are not alone in showing it to us. These are fraternal social bonds,
singularities. When the paternal function weakens, when there is, as
Slavoj Zizek has put it, âa decline in symbolic or paternal efficiency,â
we can begin to see the real cunning of the father, of the master. The
pere [father] becomes the peer, or pair. The organizing principle of the
non-dup-pere is replaced by the principle of âauto-non-me,â which
institutes a new lonely mode of traumatic unspeakable suffering. The
fraternal function replaces the paternal function: oppression and
exploitation operate less explicitly and more implicitly, through a
logic of segregation. And Lacan insisted upon the fact that
psychoanalysis is the only counterpoint to the world of mastery,
patriarchy. And why? It is because psychoanalysis disrupts the tendency
toward hierarchy and fraternity.
I risk the claim that our problem today is not at all what some notable
psychologists seem to be lamenting: the end of patriarchy. I donât care
much about the fact that hierarchies might exist in nature, as Jordan
Peterson has maintained, because it really doesnât get to what is truly
at stake: patriarchy has become worse. It has shifted from the symbolic
into the real. On the one hand, there are âverticalâ social bonds, which
make up the âsymbolicâ patriarchy; and, on the other hand, there is
something of the father which exists outside of this vertical world: a
real father. It is a father whose presence is felt more severely.
Perhaps we might claim that the father becomes the world, and it is from
this world-father that the subject stages her retreat. Patriarchy can
therefore continue to exist according to the horizontal principle of
fraternity. I donât see why we canât claim that class functions
according to a fraternal logic as well. In any case, the fraternity
without a master exists outside of the world. When the symbolic
prohibition against jouissance becomes ineffective, the cut perhaps
comes from the real: not the signifier but the razor blade or the
insult.
Paradoxically, one feels prohibitions even more. The fraternal group
really feels the weight of the world. The internal consistency and
integrity of the group is secured not by prohibitions but also by
segregations: the group segregates together, in isolation from the
world. Thatâs how Lacan put it: âisolates, together.â It is a lonely
segregation of âones.â How is it possible, then, that it is when
patriarchy is most under attack that fathers also seem to be felt as
more tyrannical? In any case, this other mode of social organization led
me toward a discussion of the psychoanalytic cartel. I hope you know
this word, cartel. The word emerged, long before Lacan picked it up, in
the context of war. As formulated by Lacan, the cartel was meant to be a
social bond that would not be predicated upon the principles of
prohibition or affirmation: neither hierarchy nor fraternity, neither
exploitation nor segregation. Many people assume that a cartel is simply
a Lacanian reading group, but what it really elaborates, and this is its
politics, is the necessity of a ânon-hierarchicalâ and
ânon-fraternizingâ social bond. I might claim that the cartel is a post-
anarchist mode of social organization. It goes further than the
anarchists themselves were often willing to go: to the end. Lacan began
to formulate the basic coordinates of the âcartelâ very early in his
teaching. There was even a great essay by Eric Laurent about this which
was published some twenty years ago, titled âThe Real and the Group.â
Lacanâs report, presented in 1947, titled âBritish Psychiatry and the
War,â examined the formation of small groups of soldiers during the
second world war whose direction was ensured by psychiatrists and
inspired by psychoanalysis. We might imagine that the cartel is roughly
homologous with the anarchist âaffinity groupâ or âcollective.â Why not?
Murray Bookchin, who I met many years ago in Vermont, reasoned,
persuasively, that the anarchist affinity group model was transported
into American anarchist practice from idealistic militants fighting
within the Spanish Civil War. There is something about the war--the
trauma that it reveals, and the subsequent dissolution of the social
bond--that necessitates social inventions of these sorts. Iâm not
without realizing it myself, having now fled Russia, and finding myself
in small groups such as this one. The war led Freud to conceptualize a
notion of âdeath drive,â Lacan to develop the basic coordinates of the
âcartel,â and, as for the anarchists, the development of an âaffinity
groupâ model. Finally, Stirner, who wrote about the âunion of egoists,â
as we shall see, thought of this during a moment when the German social
bond began to erode, shortly before the revolutions of the 1840s.
I would like to quote Bookchin on the affinity group:
The term âaffinity groupâ is the English translation of the Spanish grup
de afinidad, which was the name of an organizational form devised [...]
as the basis of the [...] Iberian Anarchist Federation (FAI). [...] [It]
could easily be regarded as a new type of extended family, in which
kinship ties are replaced by deeply empathetic human relationships
[...]. Long before the word âtribeâ gained popularity in the American
counterculture, the Spanish anarchists called their congresses
âassemblies of the tribes.â Each affinity group is deliberately kept
small to allow for the greatest degree of intimacy between those who
compose it. Autonomous, communal, and directly democratic, the group
combines revolution theory with revolutionary lifestyle [and] creates a
free space in which revolutionaries can remake themselves individually,
and also as social beings.
There are clear differences between the affinity group model and the
cartel. Both are small and intimate social groups, arranged according to
some work or cause, and developed, from the beginning, within times of
war. But the affinity group operates in much closer proximity to the
horizontal principle of fraternity: it is auto-non-mous. From the
beginning, it does not propose to eradicate the internal inclinations
toward group identification, nor does it eliminate the principle of
segregation. The cartel functions according to a fundamentally different
point of departure. It retains the âplace of power.â I quite like this
expression, which Iâve extracted from Saul Newmanâs book From Bakunin to
Lacan: place of power. The cartel retains the place of power, but
empties it of its potency. The place of power remains, but its function
serves a different cause. Rather than affirming the segregation of the
group, the âplus oneâ functions to produce, as Laurent Dupont has put
it: a certain function of desire, which is a draining of the jouissance
at play in the affirmative impulses. It is why the âplus oneâ is neither
a master nor a care-taker, but rather an agent provocateur. This is how
Miller has put it. I quote him:
The plus-one must come with question marks [...] and make holes in
heads. This implies that he refuses to be a master who puts to work; to
be the one who knows; to be an analyst in the cartel; and this in order
to be that agent provocateur from where there is a teaching.
You know, Miller was only interested, at this time, in the 1980s, with
the cartel in terms of producing knowledge. Thatâs not my interest. My
interest is in the invention of the cartel, which is, in times of war,
an invention of a social link. In any case, the âplus oneâ of a cartel
occupies the supposed âplace of powerâ but serves the cause of
disrupting the hierarchical aspirations and fraternal impulses, thereby
returning each member back into the loneliness of their relation to
their revolutionary cause: it isolates the fixation in the impulses. I
claim that Miller highlighted this later in his teaching of the School,
in 2000.
And it is why Max Stirnerâs proposal, which he called the âunion of
egoists,â has been an extremely important intervention within the
history of anarchism. Youâll find that even Friedrich Engels and Karl
Marx were surprised by his intervention. I happen to like surprises.
Stirner offered a fundamental challenge not only to the communist
tradition but also to the anarchist tradition. And not everybody likes
surprises, so the anarchists still do not know what to do about Stirner:
they call him an âindividualist anarchist.â Itâs not a charitable
designation because there is in fact nothing more in-dividual than a
singularity, a fraternity ⊠a social bond or group. It is clear that
Stirner did not offer us a blueprint for the âunion of egoists.â It is a
point that commentators on his work never fail to mention. He offered a
concept, but he left it empty. The union of egoists is an empty space
reserved for a social link still possible after the annihilation of the
world.
Thatâs already quite a bit, though, because it implies that he emptied
the social bond of its fraternal relations, thereby insisting that each
member pursue their own singular cause, unshackled from oppressive
hierarchies and moralistic fraternities. Allan Antliff, a friend of
mine, reminded me not so long ago that Stirnerâs âunion of egoistsâ was
supposed to be made up of insurrectionaries or insurgents who âno longer
let themselves be arranged by the world.â It could mean that they
fundamentally refuse the determinations of their world: a refusal of
surprises. It is a foreclosure of the world, a rejection of any
constitution. That makes it quite a bit different from the social order
proposed by Sergei Nacheyev in his âCatechisms of a Revolutionary,â
which established precisely that: a constitution for the union of
egoists, point by point, as a condition of membership into his secret
society. Now, here is the big secret: it has been said that his
fraternity had no members except for himself. It was a fraternity, but a
strange one because its constitution had only one function: to empty out
all of the meaning that makes up a world. The revolutionary is a doomed
man: he has no religion, identity, name, friends, morality, father, âŠ
nothing. Ultimately, he is without a world. His only cause is
ârevolution,â which means, finally: his revolutionary impulses. His
conviction is certainly a stubborn one.
It is interesting to think about all of this in relation to a passage
that Iâve extracted from Jacques-Alain Millerâs âTurin Theory of the
Subject of the School,â which I will read now:
Lacan returns each one to his loneliness as a subject, to the relation
that each one has with the master-signifier of the Ideal beneath which
he places himself. In the very moment when Lacan institutes a collective
formation, his first words are to dissociate, and bring forward
subjective loneliness.
It was the same with Stirnerâs âunion of egoists,â because the aim was
to dissociate from fixed ideas, from what Stirner called âspooks,â
which, for him, structured the entire world. Hence, Stirnerâs first
suggestion, when instituting a social link, was to dissociate. It was
therefore a principle of dissolution.
Okay, Iâve lost my thread.
You know, it has been a month or two since this lecture series ended,
and here we are again. As Lacan put it: encore! You should think of
todayâs lecture as an encore! It would seem that Iâve only reestablished
the series, returned to the same place, perpetuating the repetition. But
I am not offering you four lectures. Iâm offering three, ⊠plus one. I
thereby isolate this final lecture from the series, and I take it all by
itself, alone. This stubborn one should therefore receive more serious
attention. As you know, Stirner was also a very serious thinker, which
is why, perhaps, he was given the nickname âStirner.â Okay: Iâve asked
my friend, Roman Aslamov, to speak for 2-3 minutes about Stirner. Iâve
asked him for an important reason which he will not perhaps realize
today. But, anyway, hopefully he can quickly, in 2-3 minutes, tell us
what he believes to be Stirnerâs significance, and, moreover, what we
should know about Stirnerâs reading of the young Hegelian Ludwig
Feuerbach. After he speaks, for 2 minutes, we will return to our thread
and try to bring the lecture to a conclusion.
[Roman Speaks]
Ah! Perhaps Stirner discovered something that weâve been overlooking,
namely a repetition that was occurring within the history of ideas. It
is a question -- one perhaps we could pursue another day -- of the
difference between dialectics and repetition. In any case, a repetition,
and he underlined it in the dialectical philosophy of the Left Hegelian
Ludwig Feuerbach. Within Ludwig Feuerbachâs dialectical work there was
nonetheless a repetition. Stirner was very clear about it when he wrote:
What [Feuerbach] took from God has been superadded to Man, and the power
of humanity grew greater in proportion to the degree of piety that was
lost: âManâ is the God of today, and fear of Man has taken the place of
the old fear of God.
It was perhaps by underlining this repetition that was at stake in the
dialectic that he was able to move from repetition to fixation. Stirner
isolated something outside of the âdialectics of desireâ which can be
found inside of the ârepetition compulsion,â which was, to put it in
Freudian terms: a fixation. I quote Alexander Stevens concerning this
repetition compulsion: âit is repetition compulsion that, according to
Freud, puts us on the trail of the death drive on the basis of the
repetition of the traumatic element.â What Stirner demonstrated was that
Feuerbach only exchanged a religious conception of âGod,â which
pre-existed his work, for a humanistic conception of âMan.â In fact,
itâs not exactly progress. It returns us back to the same place, and
thatâs what makes it revolutionary: âManâ increases the potency of the
âplace of power,â but it does not evacuate it--clear it--of jouissance.
Not only does the âplace of powerâ remain intact but its function
improves, it becomes more cunning. The situation becomes worse with the
category of âman.â So we move from God, the father, to man, or men, the
brothers.
Todayâs social movements effectuate a similar effect: through
cancellation, do they not place the âun-humanâ outside of their social
bond, to further consolidate the internal consistency of their own
group: âmoralistic human.â Eric Laurent, in his short piece âRacism
2.0,â reminds us that, I quote him: â[w]hen Lacan constructed the logic
of the social bond, he does not begin with the [vertical] identification
with the leader.â He continues by claiming that the logic proceeds in
the following way:
1. âA man knows what is not a man.
2. Men recognize themselves among themselves.
3. I declare myself to be a man for fear of being convinced by men that
I am not a man.â
In other words, it begins from segregation: isolation from the âholeâ
that one confronts in the place of the Other. In any case, Stirner
located within this repetition an enigmatic and stubborn point of
fixation. He was that stubborn fixation within the Hegelian movement.
If, for example, Godâs cause is his own, a countryâs cause is its own,
and so on, then each presents an âauto-eroticâ fixation. Stirner saw
singularities, âislands of jouissance,â of self-enclosure and
self-interest. And he resolved to dissociate against the fixed ideas,
spooks, and so on. In the end, the problem with Stirner is that he
simply has nothing to believe in. He gives up on all fictions: fiction
not fixation. There is a deflation of desire. He retains the fixation
but dismisses all fictions. Unfortunately, he did not have a âplus one.â
As for me, I believe in psychoanalysis. And it was anarchism and my
revolutionary aspirations that led me to it. So, I brought myself, and
now all of you, to the end. What you do beyond the end is up to you. To
go to the end, I would claim that the cartel is a type of post-
anarchist politics. So, what can I still say about anarchism, after the
end? It might surprise you to learn that post-anarchism persists when
you go to the end. But it is up to each of you, one by one, all alone,
to find your way with it. I hope that you will make something of what
Iâve presented in these four lectures. But I hope you do it in your own
way.
Iâll stop here.