đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş amedeo-bertolo-power-authority-and-domination.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 19:51:55. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âŹ ď¸ Previous capture (2023-01-29)
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Power, Authority and Domination Author: Amedeo Bertolo Date: 1983 Language: en Topics: power, authority, domination, definitions Source: Retrieved on 17th May 2021 from https://autonomies.org/2020/10/amedeo-bertolo-authority-power-and-domination/ Notes: This text was originally presented at the seminar âIl Potere e la sua negazioneâ, SaignelĂŠgier (Switzerland), 8â10 of July, 1983, and latter published in VolontĂ , nÂş 2, 1983. References in square brackets are to works in the Bilbiography and in round brackets to works cited in the Endnotes
In the course of my studies of techno-bureaucracy, self-management and
utopia (6), (7), (8), I found myself up against the problem of defining
âpowerâ. On different occasions I defined it more or less explicitly, to
suit the needs of the particular situation but these definitions were
always partial and provisional, serving only to avoid possible
misunderstanding in a discussion of other ideas. The basic problem
remained and, for me, it became ever more pressing as my thinking went
both deeper and wider (or at least so I was convinced).
The problem is, in fact, the need, if not necessarily to resolve, at
least to focus clearly on a conceptual âknotâ of extreme complexity â
and not merely to agree on the words â a knot which is central to
anarchist thought. Paradoxically, anarchism, which can be considered the
most radical critique of domination to date both in theory and practice,
has not yet produced a theory of power that is more subtle and highly
developed than the apologies of domination.
There has been no further reflection to do justice to the brilliant
âinsightsâ of the âfounding fathersâ of anarchism. Those insights are
still rich in promise and our anarchism, mine included, is built around
them but, from the scientific point of view, they have remained little
more than insights and, more than a century later, are running a serious
risk of becoming mere stereotyped formulae, beliefs or taboos, thereby
losing a large part of their value as fundamental hypotheses for the
interpretation and transformation of reality. These insights have become
petrified and the relative vagueness, of both concept and terminology,
however inevitable and perhaps necessary it may have been in the early
stages of reflection, become an obstacle to further thought and action;
the source of both unjustifiable âorthodoxiesâ and of equally
unjustifiable âheresiesâ of both âtraditionalâ immobility and of
âinnovativeâ absurdities, of both discussions that are purely semantic
and socially impotent.
Anarchists may find a certain consolation in the knowledge that orthodox
science, in the last century, has thrown little light on that âwholeâ
(made up of relationships, behavior, social structures âŚ) that goes
under the name of âpowerâ (or authority or domination). While power is
not only a central element in the anarchist critique of existing
reality, but also an undeniably central element to every system of
social and political thought,[1] the concept of power is, at present,
one of the most controversial and at the same time one of the least
debated, being virtually excluded from the field of application of those
analytic subtleties of which academics are so proud. Although it can be
said that the analysis of power is sophisticated, this is more in the
rather negative sense of falsification than in the positive one of
refinement.
Even a quick reading of the literature on the subject will bring into
evidence not only the considerable terminological confusion (Weberâs
term Herrschaft is translated into Italian both as potere [power] and
autoritĂ [authority]), but also an equal conceptual vagueness. As far as
the interpretation and justification of the functions and genesis of
power are concerned, academics seem to have more or less come to a halt
at Hobbes and Locke, or even Plato and Aristotle.
This is, however, small consolation. The ruling science can well permit
itself the luxury of being unconvincing on the level of pure logic,
since it is supported by the force of both reality and of the
unconscious imaginary which both shapes and is shaped by it.
Furthermore, a certain level of confusion is useful to it as it renders
the identification of social domination in theory and its destruction in
practice difficult, if not impossible. Anarchist thought, on the other
hand, must aim at the highest level of clarity if it wishes, as indeed
it does, to be a subversive science, that is, an instrument for the
understanding and subverting of the existing reality.
This essay puts forward certain definitions which the author feels could
be of great use, not only in the debate among anarchists but also in the
confrontation between anarchists and non-anarchists, which otherwise
threaten to remain forever a dialogue of the deaf. It will be obvious
that the work of definition is aimed not so much at the terms, as at the
contents of these terms. In the same way the written (and verbal) symbol
âhouseâ may represent the concept of âa man-made shelterâ, the content
underlying this concept may vary from the hut to the skyscraper. In this
present essay I will limit myself to the definition of wide categories
of contents (and of concepts) which will be useful for an initial,
provisional reply to the following question: to what extent is that
which is known as power made up of universal social functions and to
what extent does it include functions which belong specifically to a
relationship of domination?
It is normal usage, not only among academics, to begin a discussion on
semantics with 1) a consideration of the etymological aspects and/or 2)
of the historical ones. In the case under discussion neither would be of
any particular value. The etymology of the terms that interest us here
stretches too far back into the past to be more than linguistic
archaeology and, moreover, two of the three terms under consideration
originally had meanings that were virtually indistinguishable. And as
for the historical use of the terms, this reveals a level of polyvalence
and interchangeability over time that renders any such analysis
irrelevant to our purposes.[2]
To put it briefly, the examination of the origins and use of the words
that interest us here, over time and in differing socio-economic
contexts, only tells us that, if we imagine a spectrum of meanings
stretching from a positive to a negative pole with reference to the
values of freedom and equality, the term authority comes in a midway
position of neutrality, the term domination is generally placed towards
the negative pole and the term power covers the entire spectrum thanks
to its particular double meaning of âpower to doâ and of âpower to make
someone else doâ.
An examination of the use of the three terms on the part of anarchists
is of equally limited value (definitely more useful is an examination of
the underlying concepts): whether we consider the âclassicâ writings or
contemporary ones, whether in reflections or in propaganda, we usually
find power/authority/domination used as synonyms (and thus with negative
connotations).
It is true that we can probably identify a certain distinction, more or
less explicit, between power and authority, but this is not unequivocal.
For Proudhon, for example, power is a collective force whereas authority
is alienation (monopolistic appropriation) of this collective force (28)
(although he also uses the term âpolitical powerâ to define this
expropriation of social might). For Proudhon, therefore, authority could
be seen as a negative term while power is, or could be termed, neutral.
Bakunin, on the other hand, recognised the existence of a âneutralâ
authority.[3] And â moving from the classics to our contemporaries â
Giovanni Baldelli gives a decidedly positive meaning to the word
âauthorityâ (5), which he generally uses in the sense of moral and
intellectual influence. The examination of the use of the three words
today, both in common parlance and in scientific terminology, has a
little (although not much) more meaning.
In everyday language, the two adjectives âauthoritativeâ and
âauthoritarianâ demonstrate the use, both positive and negative, of the
noun âauthorityâ from which they come, a noun which can indicate a role
of political power or a particular competency or moral excellence. And,
still in everyday language, the term power is applied to a whole range
of situations from the ability to be or do, to the structure of social
hierarchy. Only the word âdominationâ is almost unequivocally used in
the sense of the power to impose (de jure or de facto) oneâs will on
others by means of physical or psychological coercion. This lesser
ambiguity of the term domination (and of the relative verbs and
adjectives) in comparison with those of authority and power also extends
to the terminology of the social sciences. Perhaps because of the
self-same negative emotional value that is so widespread in current
usage, the term is rarely used or else is used with an explicit and
negative moral value judgement.[4] As far as definitions of power and
authority are concerned, they can be found to suit all tastes. What, for
some, is called authority, for others is influence or prestige, or â in
another sense â that which some call authority is, for others, power, or
rather legitimate or formal power ⌠[5]
It is for these reasons that I feel that it is necessary to attempt, yet
again, to define these terms; and our first step must be the
identification of the underlying concepts, even if this naturally
presents certain lexical difficulties. At times I will try to overcome
these by an âintuitiveâ use of certain terms (depending on the
particular context), at other times by paraphrasing, whether elegantly
or no, and again at other times by anticipating the definitions to be
presented at a later point. I will also resort to the frequent use of
âbanalitiesâ, that is, of concepts which are taken for granted by
anarchists or which are widely known and accepted in the field of
non-anarchist scientific and philosophical thought; from an unusual
combination of different banalities we may discover something new.
Let us begin in an (apparently) roundabout way. The freedom of the
individual, understood as the possibility of choice between alternative
actions, is not, has never been and could never be unlimited. It
operates in the presence of limits and restrictions arising from both
nature and culture. Any choice can only exist between certain determined
possibilities. Even those fanatics of freedom that anarchists are agree
on this (with the possible exception â more apparent than real â of some
frantic individualists). But this definition is nevertheless incomplete
and immediately sends us back to a higher level of freedom,
paradoxically via the attribution of determining restrictions to the
behaviour of the individual.
I am not concerned, here, with the limits (whether external or internal)
imposed by nature because these in fact limit the choice of
possibilities rather than determine behaviour and are, therefore,
irrelevant to the present discussion. For example, physiology and
anatomy certainly limit the frequency and the modes of sexual coupling
but the factors which, within those limits, lead to specific models of
erotic behaviour are entirely cultural. And yet another example: in the
game of chess, the chessboard can be seen to represent the natural
limits (in fact the sixty-four squares are obviously an artificial
limit, being part of the rules, but let us imagine that they are imposed
by nature); the rules of the game represent the cultural limits (the
bishop can only move diagonally, etc.); the moves of the players
represent the freedom of choice between determined possibilities.
The aspect that interests me here is, to be precise, these determining
factors imposed by culture. Those two elements that, together, play such
a considerable, if varying, role in the behaviour of animals, instinct
and environment, do not have an analogous influence on the behaviour of
that strange animal that is man. Man is not governed by instincts in the
pure sense (that is, as precise and specific, genetically determined
behavioural reactions to given environmental stimuli) but only shows
traces or residues of instincts which have little or no social
significance. Such are for example, the instinct of a new-born baby to
suck or the pseudo-instincts such as the sexual âinstinctâ which, in
reality, is a need which can be satisfied in ways (that is behavior or
an overall series of actions) that are not necessarily determined. And,
furthermore, manâs âenvironmentâ is considerably more cultural than
natural, not only in the sense that he has transformed and is
transforming nature but also in the sense that manâs environment
consists, above all, of relationships with other men and even his
relationships with the world of âthingsâ undergo a symbolic mediation.
During his long evolution into âhumanâ form, man has lost those
instinctual factors which determine his actions and has replaced them
with cultural factors, that is, with norms, rules, codes of
communication and interaction. It is precisely in this substitution that
manâs special freedom is to be found at its highest level:
self-determination. In fact, those culturally determined factors are not
given to man (by God or nature) but man takes them for himself. Norms do
not merely reflect natural necessities but create arbitrary ones. That
is to say that the creation of norms is necessary because it is
âwrittenâ in manâs nature (in manâs freedom which paradoxically imposes
his self-determination), but the individual elements of these norms are
not necessary. Man must create norms, but he can create those norms that
he wishes. The production of norms is therefore the central, founding
operation of human society and so of âhumanityâ itself, as man only
exists as such to the extent that he is a product of culture, that is,
of society.
The function of creating and recreating the âsocialâ dimension by
inventing, transmitting and modifying norms is, by definition, a
collective function of the human species (that is, of the groups and
subgroups that make it up). Just as, by definition, there is no
individual code of communication, so too there is no individual norm of
social interaction. Therefore in the very moment that cultural
determination decides the highest expression of manâs freedom, his
faculty of self-determination, it opens the way for a permanent
asymmetry between the individual and the collective which means that the
role of society in determining the individual is always greater than the
individualâs role in determining society. Man produces society
collectively but is individually shaped by it.
The creation of norms obviously implies the application of these norms
(a rule that is not applied is not a rule). On the other hand, since the
norm does not possess the same overriding force as instinctive
bio-chemical mechanisms, and nor does the general consensus (which is
infrequent except for certain norms and in certain highly homogeneous
and static societies) give it this compelling strength, sanction comes
into play to render adherence to the norm, if not certain and universal,
at least statistically probable. In this way every human group and
subgroup produces models of behavior and related sanctions to induce its
members to conform to these; sanctions, the severity of which
corresponds to the degree to which the norm safeguarded by them is
considered as fundamental for the group.
As Lasswell and Kaplan point out, these sanctions are severe âin terms
of the prevalent values of the group being considered. While violence is
certainly a sanction of extreme severity, there are, none the less, many
situations in which dishonour, that is the drastic withdrawal of
respect, can play an even more important roleâ. Thus a sanction is
severe if it is conceived as such in the collective imaginary of the
particular group. And, naturally, the same applies to the gravity of the
infraction. It is well known that the same behavior may be judged very
differently in different cultural contexts with a consequent difference
in the sanctions that are applied. A loud belch may be considered a
minor offence and so be greeted with only mild disapproval or it may be
considered a serious infraction and so give rise to a correspondingly
severe sanction (for example, to expulsion from an exclusive club) or it
may even be judged positively and receive a âpositiveâ sanction
(laughter, satisfactionâŚ). We must, in fact, remember that there are not
only negative sanctions which discourage behaviour that is disapproved
of, but also positive sanctions which encourage approved behaviour. It
is even possible, at least in theory, to conceive of a society in which
individual behaviour is determined purely by means of positive sanctions
(although in this case the absence of positive sanctions could be
considered a negative one).
The production and application of norms and sanctions, therefore, make
up the social regulatory function; a function which I propose to call
power.[6]
Power is thus defined as a socially âneutralâ function which is
necessary not only to the existence of society, culture and of man
himself, but also to the exercising of that freedom as freedom to choose
between determined possibilities from which this discussion began. The
absence of cultural determination would mean, in fact, a meaningless
vacuum in which there would be no choice but only pure chance. Freedom,
as choice, can only be exercised in the presence of determining factors,
just as the friction of the air is necessary for birds to fly.
However, the fact that human behaviour can never be completely
undetermined (nor, fortunately, completely determined)[7] and that the
cultural determination of manâs behavior is not only inevitable but, in
its turn, an expression of freedom, does not mean that the ways and
means of the social regulating function are neutral with respect to
freedom itself. It is fundamental for freedom as choice that the mesh of
the determining factors be both wide and elastic and modifiable as, the
greater is the range of possibilities left open by this âmeshâ, the
freer is the individual. And equally fundamental for freedom as
self-determination is the level of participation in the regulatory
process, as the freedom of the individual is greater, in this sense,
when he has greater access to power. Equal access to power for all
members of a society is, therefore, the first unavoidable condition for
equal freedom for all; a condition necessary to equal freedom for all
but not sufficient for a high level of freedom for each. Power can
oppress all in the same degree and remain oppressive. There are examples
of so-called âprimitiveâ societies in which all have more or less equal
access to power but in which those forces determining behaviour are so
all-pervasive and/or traditionally exempt from modification that they
give rise to a situation of socially diffuse âtotalitarianismâ.
A situation of âequal power for allâ is not only conceivable but has
also been documented by more than one anthropologist. It is, however,
far from being the norm, either geographically or historically. It is
far more common to find social systems in which the regulating function
is exercised, not by the collective upon itself but by one part of the
collective (generally but not necessarily a small minority) over another
(generally the great majority); that is, systems in which the access to
power is the monopoly of one part of society (individuals, groups,
classes, castesâŚ).
This brings us now to another conceptual category which we could call
domination. Domination, therefore, defines the relationship between
unequals, those unequal in terms of power and so of freedom; it defines
the situation of superordination/subordination; it defines the systems
of permanent asymmetry between social groups.
The relationship of domination typically manifests itself in
relationships of command/obedience in which the command regulates the
behavior of the person who obeys. The command/obedience relationship
does not in itself represent the regulating function. One does not
âobeyâ a norm (for example that which forbids killing or requires us to
drive on the right side of the road), rather one follows it. One obeys a
command, that is the form in which the norm is presented in a society of
domination. The fact that respect for the norm is seen in terms of
obedience is, in fact, a result of the expropriation of the regulating
function by one part of society which must therefore impose it on the
rest of society. And the lower the level of access, whether real or
fictional, to power in society, the more explicitly must this be
imposed.
If, in order that the cultural determination may not only give meaning
to behavior but also make it regular and foreseeable, the social norm
has, by its very nature, a compelling aspect (that is, relevant social
behaviour must be fitted to the norm if it is to be such), then it
becomes coercive in a situation of domination. Thus it is imposed
through a hierarchical chain of subordination along which there is one
general rule: command/obedience as a fundamental social relationship.
âFrom its origins,â writes Clastres in Society Against the State, âour
culture has thought of political power in terms of hierarchical and
authoritarian relationships of command/obedience. Every form of power,
actual or possible, can consequently be reduced to this privileged
relationship which expresses, a priori, its essenceâ [10, p. 16]. But,
âif there is one thing that is foreign to an American Indian it is the
idea of having to give or obey an order, except in very particular
circumstancesâ [10, p. 13]. âTherefore the model of coercive power is
only accepted in exceptional circumstances, when the group has to
confront a threat from outside⌠Normal civil power is based not on
constriction but on concensus omnium and so is profoundly pacific.â [10,
p. 27].
Evans-Pritchard also described a culture (the Nuer of Sudan) in which
obedience is not conceived of, where command is an offence and where no
one obeys anyone else. It is not by chance that these are societies in
which the regulating function is collective, where âthe word of the
chief does not have the force of lawâ, where the chief can be an
âarbiterâ and express an âauthoritativeâ opinion (of this we shall see
more when we consider authority and influence) but cannot act as judge
or apply sanctions. And even the Amba, whom Dahrendorf (12) considers in
his attempt to show the universality of the âauthority structureâ (by
which he means, with an ease which goes ill with his usual accuracy,
both that which I have termed power and that to which I have given the
term domination) show, like the Nuer, the Tupinamba, the GuaraniâŚ, the
very non-universality of domination, demonstrating that the regulating
function need not necessarily assume the coercive form of hierarchy and
the relationship of command/obedience.[8]
Domination, as we have said, is the privilege of power. The holders of
domination reserve to themselves the control of the process of
production of the âsocialâ, expropriating it from the others. This
phenomenon is similar to that of the privileged possession of the means
of material production (to which it is often, although not necessarily,
related)[9], but is still more serious as it concerns manâs very nature:
domination is the denial of the humanity of the expropriated, of those
excluded from the dominant roles of the social structure.
Power, understood as the regulating function of society, is not the only
form of cultural determination of behavior. There is a vast range of
asymmetric relationships between individuals in which certain behavioral
choices are totally determined by the opinions or decisions of others,
decisions to which are given a particular and determining weight.
These relationships may be either personal or functional. By personal I
mean those relationships in which the subjects interact as persons; by
functional those in which the subjects interact on the basis of roles
which define social functions (the distinction, as usual, is partly
arbitrary, insofar as all personal relationships are, in some degree,
also interactions of roles and vice versa). In the case of personal
relationships, we can define the asymmetry as influence, while for those
functional roles, it can be defined as authority.
In the first case the asymmetry can be attributed to differences â
moral, intellectual or of character â between individuals due to which
one personality is in some way âstrongerâ than another and influences
the other more than he or she is influenced.[10]
In the second case there is a type of delegation of decision-making,
tied to the expectations of a role and justified (explicitly or
implicitly) by âcompetenceâ. The ambivalence of this term (which can
mean ability or decisional capacity) makes it well-suited to the
ambivalent nature of the asymmetry of ability and of the faculty of
decision-making which is typical of a complete social division of labor
into differing functions and roles.[11]
Now, neither influence nor authority, as defined above, necessarily
implies a permanent social asymmetry. It is perfectly possible to
imagine a social system in which a multiplicity of single asymmetrical
relationships results in an overall equilibrium of influence and
authority for each individual (or, at least, for the latter, which is
conceptually closer to power and so to domination). The asymmetric
parent/child relationship is reshaped over a lifetime in an
âegalitarianâ cycle: the asymmetry of professional roles between
individuals of differing professions can adjust itself through
reciprocal services; a function of coordination can be carried out in
rotation⌠The authority of a role does not infringe the freedom of one
who accepts it voluntarily and critically; it can even be complementary
by helping to avoid dispersion into a thousand insignificant rivulets:
by simplifying a large number of individual choices we can render it
possible to âconcentrateâ freedom on those choices that the individual
holds truly important (the individual himself and not others on his or
her behalf). And, analogously, by choosing not to participate, or to do
so only passively, in certain social decision-making processes (which is
very different from being excluded from them) an individual is able to
take a full part in those which interest him most.
It is, however, true that in a society with a hierarchical division of
social activity, there is, necessarily, a corresponding hierarchy of
authority and therefore a permanent asymmetry between the holders of
different roles. And it is also true that certain roles are
âauthoritativeâ insofar as they are articulations of the power to
regulate society and so, in a system of domination, are hierarchic
articulations of domination itself and so, by definition, permanently
asymmetric. Thus the diversity of roles becomes social inequality.
In the same way, the existence of domination as a central category of
the social imaginary determines permanent asymmetries of influence,
since personal relationships are also perceived in terms of the
hierarchy of domination. Thus individual differences also contribute to
social inequality.
Therefore, while in the abstract those relationships which we have
termed influence and authority can be âneutralâ categories, in the
concrete situation of existing society of domination they take on a more
or less pronounced value of domination and so they too often manifest
themselves in relationships of command/obedience.
To sum up, I have identified four conceptual categories which, in
current and scientific usage, all fall more or less under the umbrella
of the same term: power. I have proposed that this term should be
retained only for the first category: the social regulatory function,
the sum of those processes by which a society regulates itself by
producing and applying norms and ensuring their observance. If this
function is carried out by only one part of society, that is, if one
privileged (dominant) sector has a monopoly of power, it gives rise to a
second category, to a set of hierarchical relationships of
command/obedience which I propose to call domination. And, finally, I
propose the term authority for those asymmetries of roles which cause
asymmetries of reciprocal determination, and influence for those
asymmetries arising from personal natures.
I must reiterate that my main interest is not the terminology, the
formal aspect of a proposal of definition, but its substance, the
identification of concepts. It is not the name that we give to colors
that is important (even if it is useful to agree on these names if we
wish to understand each other quickly, without having to resort to long
paraphrasing) but rather that we agree on the existence of different
colors, which correspond to different bands of frequencies of the
visible range of light.
My proposal is intended as an initial differentiation and identification
of the groups of concepts which can then serve for a general analysis of
social phenomena. Further and differing differentiations (corresponding
to various forms and contents of power, domination and authority) will
of course be necessary for deeper and/or more detailed analyses, but I
believe that the four categories proposed above will suffice for an
initial anarchist approach to the problem.
In any case, it seems to me to be necessary to differentiate between
that which I have called power and that which I have called domination.
This is a fundamental qualitative difference which anarchists have
always perceived more or less clearly (when, for example, they
distinguish between society and the State); indeed it is this that is
the hard core of the insights central to their thought. But they have
not always been successful in making this difference explicit in their
analyses, in clearly identifying the two conceptual categories. This has
led them to theoretical and practical aberrations in widely differing
directions (as for example to the rejection in theory and practice of
all norms and sanctions or â as with their participation in the
Republican Government during the Spanish Civil War â to practise and, at
least partly, theorise a form of domination).
Non-anarchist thinkers have generally shown themselves to be incapable
of perceiving the difference between power and domination and, in any
case, have not been willing or able to explicitly differentiate between
them either in concept or terminology. But this, as we said above, is
not a defect in their case, given their institutional role of providers
of rationality within an ideology of domination.
As I have already said, what I have offered here is a proposal for the
identification of concepts rather than for a definition of terms. And
for this reason I would hope that the discussion â which I profoundly
hope will be provoked â will concern the concepts rather than the terms.
I would like these concepts and the contents of the proposed categories
to be analysed critically and contested. For example, if a norm must
needs be supported by severe sanctions is it âsimpleâ power or does it
fall into the category of domination? Or, again, is it necessary, at
this point in the debate, to distinguish between that which I have
called influence and that which I have called authority? Or would it be
useful to distinguish between the asymmetries of effective ability and
those of formal roles?
I do believe, nevertheless, that it is worth spending some time on the
proposal for the terminology which could be âdelicateâ among anarchists,
in view of my use of two labels (âpowerâ and âauthorityâ) which are not
neutral for anarchists, and for concepts which are, or at least which
seem to me to be, neutral. As I said at the beginning of this article,
anarchists use the terms power, domination and authority, particularly
the first two, as synonyms, obviously with negative connotations (they
stand for the â-archyâ which they deny and oppose).
Why then am I proposing an anarchically neutral use of power and
authority? In part it is to be provocative, to let a small semantic
scandal focus more attention on the substance of a debate, to underline
what seems to me to be a certain conceptual originality (small or
great!) with a linguistic novelty. And also because it seems to me
absurd that our terminology, the anarchist terminology, has three terms
for one concept and none for the two others. But, above all, because I
believe that what are termed power and authority in both common and
specialist terminology are in fact what I earlier defined as power and
authority plus domination. So if we take away domination from power and
authority, making it a conceptually distinct category on its own, even
if in all existing societies (except the residual forms of primitive
societies) it is in fact superimposed on the other two, we are left with
those types of relationships which I have proposed calling power and
authority.
On the other hand, no anarchist would give a positive use to the term
âpowerlessnessâ (political, social, economicâŚ) as a synonym of the
absence of domination, as the power whose absence is indicated by this
word has the positive connotation of âthe power to doâ, to exercise
oneâs own freedom.[12] And I am sure that the expression âpower for
everyoneâ[13] does not sound heretical to most anarchists as, in this
case, it is the individualâs capacity to decide and/or participate in
the social decision-making processes that is meant.
Let us now leave the nominal question and turn our attention to that of
the substance. In what way can the proposed conceptual definition be
useful to anarchist thought?
They (or any other definitions which distinguish two or three or ten
colours in that undifferentiated or barely differentiated area that we
call power) allow us to understand and express better the central
negation of anarchist philosophy (that is of the anarchist
interpretation of the world) and so of its central affirmation, of its
founding value: freedom. Furthermore, this definition paves the way for
a better formulation of an infinite number of problems for anarchist
âscienceâ which studies both the âlawsâ (uniformity, constantly
recurring relationships, causal connections, necessary conditions) of
domination and the âlawsâ of freedom.
To give just a few examples.
In the field of politics, this allows us to think more clearly about the
gap between norms and the law, to bring into evidence the substantial
difference between the freedom of the liberals and the freedom of the
anarchists, to analyse the social decision-making processes, to go
deeper into all that âhas already been saidâ about assemblies, rotation
of responsibilities, delegation, revocable mandates, etc. It could be
said that these definitions, or at least a definition that distinguishes
the regulating function from its possession by a privileged section of
society is a necessary starting point for the construction of an
anarchist political science (and for the working out of an anarchist
âlawâ). It is certainly not by chance that anarchists have generally
rejected âpoliticsâ, maintaining that it is the science and practice of
power and identifying power with domination (an identification which is
in fact the rule in existing societies).
In the realm of sociology these definitions could serve to distinguish
better between the differences and the inequalities between individuals,
roles and social categories; it could be useful for the identification
of the institutions and mechanisms of domination, differentiating them
from the structures of power; it could throw new light on the forms and
contents of cooperation and conflict.
In economics these definitions will allow a more effective formulation
of economic power (and domination). They allow us to see economic power
as distinct from economic domination and so to distinguish more clearly
between general economic âlawsâ, the economic âlawsâ which are common to
all societies of domination and those which are peculiar to particular
societies of domination.
In the field of psychology, they will allow us to distinguish between
those asymmetries between individuals which are unavoidable and those
which could be avoided, between personal and role differences (positive
or neutral in terms of freedom) and inequalities which deny freedom. It
will allow us a more effective study of the âlibertarian personalityâ
and the âauthoritarian personalityâ.[14] It may also help us to
understand why, except in very particular periods, the anarchist message
is incomprehensible for the great majority of people, why the
Kropotkinian âspirit of revoltâ is normally not as strong as social
conformism.
In the field of education, these definitions may permit us to resolve
the contradiction between the authority of the adult and the freedom of
the minor[15] and to understand why âpermissivenessâ, understood as the
acceptance of anomie, is no more suited to libertarian education, that
is, to the process of constructing the libertarian personality, than is
discipline imposed through coercion.
And, furthermore, (speaking among anarchists) how many of our useless
diatribes could be avoided, how many arguments between the deaf, could
be resolved in rational confrontation? We need only think of the
recurrent discussion on anarchist organisation in which, for a century
now, the lack of understanding on a semantic level has been at least as
relevant as the disagreement on the substance.
There are many questions to which my proposal could help in
reformulating the problem (and the examples I have given above refer to
the conventional subdivisions of the study of man and society) and among
these there is one in particular which arises almost inevitably in the
course of any reflections on power and which, in particular, is evident
in more than one of the steps of logic in the process of identification
and division which I have followed. How, why and when are power,
authority and domination born?
With the definitions that I have proposed this question only arises, in
fact, in the case of domination. For authority and for power the answer
is implicit in the respective definitions. If we accept the
anthropological assumption that man is devoid of instinctual
determination and that, vice versa, he is, thanks to the particular
evolution of his cerebral organ, capable of producing a normative
symbolic universe, it follows that the cultural regulating function is
both possible and essential for him.[16] In the same way, in my
definitions, authority follows as a corollary of the postulate that
society structures itself in functional roles.
Domination, on the other hand, has no inevitable foundation in the
nature of man and his society. And it is for this that its origin
becomes a problem in my definitions.
Let us see, first of all, what solutions non-anarchist thinkers have put
forward. As we have already seen, they do not distinguish clearly
between power and domination. Even when they hint at a conceptual
difference they see the passage from one to the other as automatic â and
do not deem it necessary to demonstrate this. This passage is frequently
from domination to power (that is, the contrary of my logical process)
and there are only a few who see it moving in the opposite direction.
But even for them the process is indisputable and, in consequence, the
two are born together: from the necessity for one comes the necessity
for the other.
Let us now consider those âexplanationsâ which seem to me, from my
reading, to exemplify the main approaches to the justification of
domination. One approach is that which, proceeding from domination to
power, justifies the former with innate ânaturalâ psychological
mechanisms: there are some personalities naturally endowed for
domination and some naturally endowed for subjugation.[17] After laying
this first stone in the theoretical edifice, the apologists of
power-domination hasten to vest it with more attractive structural
elements and we are told that this ânaturalâ subdivision of man into two
categories (the potential masters and the potential slaves) is
beneficial to both parties and that, basically, it is an admirable
artifice of nature or providence to bestow on mankind the consequent
advantages.[18] Sennetâs explanation can also be seen to fall into this
type of approach although it formally starts from influence, then moving
through authority to power and domination.[19]
The second type of approach is the cultural one, of which Dahrendorf
(12) is exemplar, with his thesis that no ânaturalâ explanation of
power-domination can be sustained: it is not the effect of a
pre-existing inequality but, on the contrary, it is the cause of the
first fundamental inequality between men. But as he does not distinguish
between power and domination, for him the necessity of domination
derives logically from the necessity of power (which he terms
authority), that is from the regulating function. For him the regulating
function and the privileged possession of it are one and the same thing.
The approaches to the problem of the genesis of power-domination can
also be classified from another point of view: into those who assume,
explicitly or implicitly, that they are contemporary with man and/or his
society and those who postulate their appearance at a certain point in
history. For the latter it is not, curiously (in the case of those
theories which distinguish between power and domination),
power-domination that appears but, generally, only domination that
breaks into a social space which is undefined and is defined as the
state of nature.[20]
Where does the problem of the genesis of domination enter into the logic
of my proposed hypothetical definitions? Since, within that logic,
everything begins from the postulate of manâs cultural plasticity, it
excludes any hypothesis based on innate bio-psychological elements such
as the âwill to ruleâ or the âinstinct of dominationâ, etc. (and as a
necessary counterpart the propensity to obey, will to be ruled, etc.).
In the perspective of manâs cultural self-determination, his behavioral
models are not inscribed in his nature, and no more in the
gregarious-authoritarian one than in the anarchist one. (It is not that
I wish to deny with this last statement that a ânaturalisticâ
interpretation of anarchism is possible â it is in fact considerably
diffuse. There is a form of anarchism which postulates manâs natural
âgoodnessâ in the sense of a natural self-regulative potential of human
society which does not require normative limits. However even this
anarchism cannot explain domination ânaturalisticallyâ but only
âculturallyâ, that is, as arising from manâs intervention).
Following a totally cultural interpretation of man, it is not strange
that we find, in cultural situations of domination, character traits
modeled on and for domination. Nor should we be surprised at not finding
those traits in cultures characterised by the absence of domination (the
already-mentioned inconceivability of command and of obedience, the fact
that, as Clastres writes, âno one feels the absurd desire to do, have or
seem more than oneâs neighbourâŚâ). It is the cultural context that gives
meaning to the differences of character that serve it. It is thus
evident that, in a context of domination, the individual character
differences are forced into models leading to either pole of the
command/obedience relationship.
But this still does not tell us when and how domination came into being.
And I certainly do not pretend to be able to answer this here. The
problem is perhaps destined to remain forever open, scientifically, if,
as seems likely at least in our present state of knowledge, the possible
answers are unprovable suppositions, since they are empirically
ânon-falsifiableâ. We are therefore less likely to develop scientific
theories about the origins of domination than âmythsâ (apologetic or
critical).
For now, I will limit myself to a sketch of an explanatory hypothesis
from an anarchist and âculture-basedâ point of view. My hypothesis is
that domination appeared at a certain point in the history of the human
race as a âcultural mutationâ. We have recently begun to apply the
principles of natural evolution (chance mutations and the positive
selection of those characteristics best fitted to survival) to manâs
cultural evolution.[21] Domination could be seen to be a mutation (that
is as a cultural innovation which, in certain conditions, proved
advantageous, in terms of survival, for those social groups that adopted
it, for example for greater military efficiency, and so it was imposed
as a model either by conquest or by imitation for defensive purposes.
One variant of this hypothesis, which I find reasonably convincing, is
to suppose that the domination mutation did not appear completely ex
abrupto but rather that elements of domination (that is to say, social
relationships partly or temporarily modeled on the command/obedience
relationship and on the inequality of power that this implies) have
always existed, or at least pre-dated the society of domination, as for
example in the man/woman, old/young, warrior/non-warrior, chief/tribe
relationships. (In these relationships domination could have existed as
a cultural imitation of asymmetries seen in â or rather interpreted from
â nature, that is in the âsocialâ animal hunted or reared or otherwise
observed.[22] But this is yet another hypothesis.) These elements of
domination would have been kept âunder controlâ in the earliest human
societies and so could not become generalised as elements central to
culture and society, until changed âenvironmentalâ conditions allowed
their transformation into dominant regulatory models. At this point came
the mutation from which only those groups which were geographically
and/or culturally isolated were immune.
This hypothesis of mutation opens (or, better, restates) a whole series
of problems related to the project of abolishing domination, which is
the central, identifying feature of anarchism, since, in this light, the
anarchist transformation of society can also be seen as, essentially, a
cultural mutation. In that project, the anarchists are mutants who tend
to multiply or to transmit their cultural âanomalyâ (in the face that is
of the normality of the dominant model) and, at the same time, to create
the âenvironmentalâ conditions which will favor their mutation, that is
the generalisation of the mutant character. This could open up the way
for a whole new interpretation of the relationship between existential
anarchism and its educational, revolutionary or other forms.
But all this is taking us too far from the original aim of this article
which was begun with the idea of offering some preliminary reflections
on power, limiting these to the ambit of a proposal of definitions. So,
at least for now, that is all.
Bibliography
No. 4.
rivoluzione, Antistato, Milan, 1977.
Antistato, Milan, 1977; Anarchici e orgogliosi di esserlo, elèuthera,
Milan, 2017.
1979; Anarchici e orgogliosi di esserlo, elèuthera, Milan, 2017.
93, 1981; Anarchici e orgogliosi di esserlo, elèuthera, Milan, 2017.
Evolution: a Quantitative Approach, Princeton University Press,
Princeton, 1981.
No. 4.
Laterza, Bari, 1970.
Bologna, 1971.
Bompiani, Milan, 1970.
3.
XXXVI [1982], No. 3.
Milan, 1978.
sociali, in AA.VV, Marxismo e non violenza, Lanterna, Genoa, 1977.
Laterza, Bari, 1972.
Berti (ed.), La dimensione libertaria di Proudhon, CittĂ Nuova, Rome,
1982.
[1] âPower is the decisive formal category in both the analysis of the
structures and the analysis of the processes in societyâ [14, p. 155];
âIn the entire lexicon of political science it is power that is,
perhaps, the most fundamental concept, the political process is the
formation, the distribution and the exercise of powerâ [22, p. 90]; âThe
study of power is the principle of the science of sociologyâ [18, p.
20].
[2] For example, see (6).
[3] âWhen I have to do with boots I bow to the authority of the
shoemaker; when I have to do with a house, a canal or a railway I
consult the authority of the architect or the engineer⌠I bow to the
authority of specialists because it is this that my own reason dictatesâŚ
We accept all natural authority and all the influences of fact but none
of law or those which are imposed on us by officialsâ (3).
[4] Among the cases when domination is used with a âneutralâ meaning
there are three which are particularly relevant: Simmel (31), for whom
domination is a universal category of social interaction and power is
one particular form of this; Dahrendorf (12), who proposes a definition
of domination understood as âthe possession of authority and thus as a
right to give authoritative commandsâ; Lasswell and Kaplan (22), for
whom domination (in the Italian edition the term is dominio, but the
word actually used by the authors is âruleâ, not âdominationâ) is the
model of effective power.
[5] The following are a few, rather random, examples: POWER. âPower is
a) ability or natural faculty of action; b) legal or moral faculty, the
right to do something; c) authority, especially in the concrete sense,
the constituted body exercising that authority, the governmentâ (19);
âPower is the participation in decision makingâ and âA decision is a
line of behavior which carries with it severe sanctionsâ [22, pp.
89â90]; âWe can designate as power the ability of a social class to
realise its specific objectivesâ [27, p. 410] . Power is âthe ability to
make and carry out decisions even when others are opposed to themâ [33,
p. 18]; Power is âa permanent body which one is used to obeying, which
possesses material means of constraint and which is supported by the
general opinion of its force, by the belief in its right to command,
that is, in its legitimacy and in the hope for its beneficenceâ; âBy
power we can understand all the means by which a man can bend the will
of other menâ [25, p. 9]; âPower can be defined as the ability to
realise oneâs desiresâ [29, p. 29]; âBy power we must understand (âŚ) the
possibility that certain commands (or that any command) will be obeyed
by a certain group of menâ (3); âPower is communication regulated by a
codeâ (25). AUTHORITY: Authority is âany power exercised by one man or
group of men over another man or groupâ (1); âAuthority is a bond
between unequalsâ [30, p. 15]; âAuthority is a way of defining and
interpreting difference in strengthâ [30, p. 118]; âAuthority is a
search for stability and security in the strength of othersâ [30, p.
178]; Authority is âan accepted dependenceâ: M. Horkheimer quoted in
[16, p. 9]; âAuthority is (psychol.) personal superiority or ascendancy
⌠and (sociolog.) the right to decide or commandâ (19); âThe essence of
authority⌠is to give a human being that security and that respect for
his decisions that is logically given only to a super-individual and
effectual axiom or to a deductionâ [31, p. 41]; âAuthority is the
expected and legitimate possession of powerâ (22).
[6] This proposed meaning corresponds to a certain degree with
Proudhonâs power as a collective force and resembles Lasswell and
Kaplanâs definition, cited in footnote 5, which does however refer to
individual decision-making processes and not to the overall function
considered here. Clastres also seems to mean something similar when he
talks about power. âIt is our view (âŚ) that political power is
universal, immanent to social reality (âŚ); and that it manifests itself
in two primary modes: coercive power and non-coercive power. Political
power as coercion (or the relationship of command/obedience) is not the
model of true power, but simply a particular caseâ [10, p. 21] and also:
âthe social cannot be conceived without the political. In other words,
there are no societies without powerâ (ibid). Clastresâ coercive power
seems to correspond to that which I will later define as âdominationâ.
[7] Crespi would say that man âoscillatesâ between the determined and
the undetermined (11).
[8] As Lasswell and Kaplan write [22, p. 24], âThe closer it moves to
anarchy, domination ceases to be such. The sphere of power is restricted
to a minimum; moving to the point where compulsion ceases to exist.
Social control, naturally, still continues to be, under different forms
of influence, but it is not coercive controlâ.
[9] It could be better said that the privileged appropriation of the
means of production is in fact the appropriation of the power of
regulating one sector of social life: it is therefore one case and one
form of the more general phenomenon of domination. With reference to
this see (20) and (21).
[10] This definition of influence is approximately the same as Sennetâs,
cited in footnote 5, although he extends it also to asymmetric
interactions of role (including the roles of power and domination).
[11] This definition of authority is approximately the same as Sennetâs,
cited in footnote 5, although he applies it only to roles of power and
domination.
[12] With regard to the relationship between will and freedom (which
are, emblematically, defined in Russian with the single term volija) see
(2).
[13] As, for example, in the following: âThe power of all⌠means that
each individual must hold sufficient (real) power to influence and
control political decisions concerning his life, to the degree that this
is compatible with an equal power for every other individual in society,
so that everyone has, in every moment, the maximum possibility that is
compatible with the maximum possibility of every other person, to
realise the best life he can.â (26)
[14] Or, as De Jouvenal says, the libertarian personality and the
securitarian personality. âAt every moment in any society there exist
individuals who do not feel sufficiently protected and others who do not
feel sufficiently free. Let us call the former securitarian and the
latter libertarianâ [15, p. 352]. The âsecuritariansâ are those who need
the highest possible level of cultural determination. âOnce the
âlibertarianâ and âsecuritarianâ sentiments have been conceived (âŚ) we
can represent any society (âŚ) as a multiplicity of points that can be
ordered hierarchically according to their libertarian index. The most
âsecuritarianâ will be situated towards the bottom and the âlibertarianâ
ones higher upâ [15, p. 358]. (And so, voilĂ , we have domination and the
âlibertariansâ become members of the dominant social groups. And thus an
interesting idea turns into the same old story!).
[15] We can consider, in this light, Bakuninâs contribution (14). For
Bakunin, the educative process is a progressive movement from
âauthorityâ to âfreedomâ: the smaller the child, the greater is his need
for external determination, as he grows the asymmetry between him and
the adult decreases and with maturity he becomes a man in the full sense
of the word and as such can and must reach the highest possible level of
self-determination.
[16] âThe primordial role of culture is to ensure the existence of the
group as a group, and so to replace chance by organisationâ [23, p. 75].
Culture provides a normative regulation for that which nature has
âforgottenâ to regulate through biology: manâs social behavior. In this
it seems that there is no clear-cut gap between man and the other
animals; âeverything seems to take place as if the great apes, already
able to disassociate themselves from the behavior of the species, did
not however succeed in re-establishing a norm on a new level.
Instinctual behavior loses that clarity and precision that it has for
the majority of mammals; but the difference is completely negative, and
the ground) abandoned by nature remains unoccupied territoryâ [23, p.
45].
[17] âThe majority of men are timid, modest, passive beings, who
represent the plastic material of Power, being born to obey. The race of
masters is a minority with a more intense vital force; they are the
ambitious, the active, the imperious ones who need to affirm their
superiority in thought and in actionâ [17, p. 301]. This vulgar
commonplace with its racist overtones follows, surprisingly enough,
observations of a very different quality, such as the following: âThe
beginnings of legitimacy are the justification of the right to command
since, of all the inequalities between humans there is none that has
such important consequences and so such a need for justification as the
inequality deriving from powerâ [17, p. 27]. And âif, apart from some
rare exceptions, all men have the same worth why should one have the
right to command and the others the duty of obeying?â [17, p. 28].
Analogously, but more âdialecticallyâ, Simmel speaks of the âwill to
dominateâ and writes that âthe human beingâs feelings with respect to
subordination are twofold. On the one hand he, in fact, wants to be
dominated. Most men cannot only not exist without a guide but also feel
this: they seek a superior force which will free them from
responsibility (âŚ) Nevertheless they have no lesser need to oppose this
power of direction (âŚ) Thus it could be said that obedience and
opposition are the two aspects or elements of what is in fact coherent
human behaviorâ [31, p. 55].
[18] âThis polarisation of man into masters and servants seems admirably
suited to the pre-arranged order in human natureâ [17, p. 40]; âAt its
origins, power (âŚ) is originally a form of defense against the two
greatest terrors afflicting man: anarchy and warâ [17, p. 30]. âPower is
a social necessity. It is thanks to the order which it imposes and the
agreement which it institutes that men can live a better lifeâ [15, p.
29].
[19] âAuthority is a way of defining and interpreting differences in
force. In a certain sense, the feeling of authority is actually the
recognition that such differences do exist. In another and more complex
sense it is one way of remaining aware of the needs and wishes of the
weak and the strongâ [30, p. 118]. Then âthe synonym of force in
political terminology (is) powerâ [30, p. 25]. Finally, âthe existence
of power between two people means that the will of one intends to
prevail over that of the otherâ and âthe chain of command is the
structure through which this disequilibrium of will can be extended to
thousands or millions of peopleâ [30, p. 155].
[20] One example: âThe natural society is small and the passage from the
small society to the big cannot come about by the same process. Some
factor is required to produce coagulation and in most cases this is not
the instinct of association but the instinct of domination (my italics)
(âŚ) The creative principle behind the great aggregates of conquest:
sometimes the work of one of the elementary societies of the social
whole but more often of a warrior band coming from afarâ [15, p. 103].
And again: âThus the State has its origins, essentially, in the
successes of a âband of brigandsâ which suppresses individual small
societies; a band which (âŚ) exhibits an attitude of pure power with
respect to the conquered, the subduedâ [15, p. 104].
[21] See (9).
[22] This is one point of view from which we can consider Clastresâ
observation that the politics of the primitive societies studied by him
was organised around the understanding that coercive power in itself âis
nothing other than a surreptitious alibi of natureâ [10, p. 38].