đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș friedrich-nietzsche-the-genealogy-of-morals.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:13:45. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Genealogy of Morals Author: Friedrich Nietzsche Date: 1887 Language: en Topics: not anarchist, nihilism Source: https://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/52319 Notes: Edited by Oscar Levy, translated by Horace B. Samuel & J. M. Kennedy
FIRST ESSAY. âGOOD AND EVIL,â âGOOD AND BAD.â
SECOND ESSAY. âGUILT,â âBAD CONSCIENCE,â AND THE LIKE.
In 1887, with the view of amplifying and completing certain new
doctrines which he had merely sketched in Beyond Good and Evil (see
especially aphorism 260), Nietzsche published The Genealogy of Morals.
This work is perhaps the least aphoristic, in form, of all Nietzscheâs
productions. For analytical power, more especially in those parts where
Nietzsche examines the ascetic ideal, The Genealogy of Morals is
unequalled by any other of his works; and, in the light which it throws
upon the attitude of the ecclesiast to the man of resentment and
misfortune, it is one of the most valuable contributions to sacerdotal
psychology.
1.
We are unknown, we knowers, ourselves to ourselves: this has its own
good reason. We have never searched for ourselvesâhow should it then
come to pass, that we should ever find ourselves? Rightly has it been
said: âWhere your treasure is, there will your heart be also.â Our
treasure is there, where stand the hives of our knowledge. It is to
those hives that we are always striving; as born creatures of flight,
and as the honey-gatherers of the spirit, we care really in our hearts
only for one thingâto bring something âhome to the hive!â
As far as the rest of life with its so-called âexperiencesâ is
concerned, which of us has even sufficient serious interest? or
sufficient time? In our dealings with such points of life, we are, I
fear, never properly to the point; to be precise, our heart is not
there, and certainly not our ear. Rather like one who, delighting in a
divine distraction, or sunken in the seas of his own soul, in whose ear
the clock has just thundered with all its force its twelve strokes of
noon, suddenly wakes up, and asks himself, âWhat has in point of fact
just struck?â so do we at times rub afterwards, as it were, our puzzled
ears, and ask in complete astonishment and complete embarrassment,
âThrough what have we in point of fact just lived?â further, âWho are we
in point of fact?â and count, after they have struck, as I have
explained, all the twelve throbbing beats of the clock of our
experience, of our life, of our beingâah!âand count wrong in the
endeavour. Of necessity we remain strangers to ourselves, we understand
ourselves not, in ourselves we are bound to be mistaken, for of us holds
good to all eternity the motto, âEach one is the farthest away from
himselfââas far as ourselves are concerned we are not âknowers.â
2.
My thoughts concerning the genealogy of our moral prejudicesâfor they
constitute the issue in this polemicâhave their first, bald, and
provisional expression in that collection of aphorisms entitled Human,
all-too-Human, a Book for Free Minds, the writing of which was begun in
Sorrento, during a winter which allowed me to gaze over the broad and
dangerous territory through which my mind had up to that time wandered.
This took place in the winter of 1876â77; the thoughts themselves are
older. They were in their substance already the same thoughts which I
take up again in the following treatises:âwe hope that they have derived
benefit from the long interval, that they have grown riper, clearer,
stronger, more complete. The fact, however, that I still cling to them
even now, that in the meanwhile they have always held faster by each
other, have, in fact, grown out of their original shape and into each
other, all this strengthens in my mind the joyous confidence that they
must have been originally neither separate disconnected capricious nor
sporadic phenomena, but have sprung from a common root, from a
fundamental âfiatâ of knowledge, whose empire reached to the soulâs
depth, and that ever grew more definite in its voice, and more definite
in its demands. That is the only state of affairs that is proper in the
case of a philosopher.
We have no right to be âdisconnectedâ; we must neither err
âdisconnectedlyâ nor strike the truth âdisconnectedly.â Rather with the
necessity with which a tree bears its fruit, so do our thoughts, our
values, our Yesâs and Noâs and Ifâs and Whetherâs, grow connected and
interrelated, mutual witnesses of one will, one health, one kingdom, one
sunâas to whether they are to your taste, these fruits of ours?âBut what
matters that to the trees? What matters that to us, us the philosophers?
3.
Owing to a scrupulosity peculiar to myself, which I confess
reluctantly,âit concerns indeed morality,âa scrupulosity, which
manifests itself in my life at such an early period, with so much
spontaneity, with so chronic a persistence and so keen an opposition to
environment, epoch, precedent, and ancestry that I should have been
almost entitled to style it my âĂą prioriââmy curiosity and my suspicion
felt themselves betimes bound to halt at the question, of what in point
of actual fact was the origin of our âGoodâ and of our âEvil.â Indeed,
at the boyish age of thirteen the problem of the origin of Evil already
haunted me: at an age âwhen games and God divide oneâs heart,â I devoted
to that problem my first childish attempt at the literary game, my first
philosophic essayâand as regards my infantile solution of the problem,
well, I gave quite properly the honour to God, and made him the father
of evil. Did my own âĂą prioriâ demand that precise solution from me?
that new, immoral, or at least âamoralâ âĂą prioriâ and that âcategorical
imperativeâ which was its voice (but oh! how hostile to the Kantian
article, and how pregnant with problems!), to which since then I have
given more and more attention, and indeed what is more than attention.
Fortunately I soon learned to separate theological from moral
prejudices, and I gave up looking for a supernatural origin of evil. A
certain amount of historical and philological education, to say nothing
of an innate faculty of psychological discrimination par excellence
succeeded in transforming almost immediately my original problem into
the following one:âUnder what conditions did Man invent for himself
those judgments of values, âGoodâ and âEvilâ? And what intrinsic value
do they possess in themselves? Have they up to the present hindered or
advanced human well-being? Are they a symptom of the distress,
impoverishment, and degeneration of Human Life? Or, conversely, is it in
them that is manifested the fulness, the strength, and the will of Life,
its courage, its self-confidence, its future? On this point I found and
hazarded in my mind the most diverse answers, I established distinctions
in periods, peoples, and castes, I became a specialist in my problem,
and from my answers grew new questions, new investigations, new
conjectures, new probabilities; until at last I had a land of my own and
a soil of my own, a whole secret world growing and flowering, like
hidden gardens of whose existence no one could have an inklingâoh, how
happy are we, we finders of knowledge, provided that we know how to keep
silent sufficiently long.
4.
My first impulse to publish some of my hypotheses concerning the origin
of morality I owe to a clear, well-written, and even precocious little
book, in which a perverse and vicious kind of moral philosophy (your
real English kind) was definitely presented to me for the first time;
and this attracted meâwith that magnetic attraction, inherent in that
which is diametrically opposed and antithetical to oneâs own ideas. The
title of the book was The Origin of the Moral Emotions; its author, Dr.
Paul RĂ©e; the year of its appearance, 1877. I may almost say that I have
never read anything in which every single dogma and conclusion has
called forth from me so emphatic a negation as did that book; albeit a
negation tainted by either pique or intolerance. I referred accordingly
both in season and out of season in the previous works, at which I was
then working, to the arguments of that book, not to refute themâfor what
have I got to do with mere refutations but substituting, as is natural
to a positive mind, for an improbable theory one which is more probable,
and occasionally no doubt, for one philosophic error, another. In that
early period I gave, as I have said, the first public expression to
those theories of origin to which these essays are devoted, but with a
clumsiness which I was the last to conceal from myself, for I was as yet
cramped, being still without a special language for these special
subjects, still frequently liable to relapse and to vacillation. To go
into details, compare what I say in Human, all-too-Human, part i., about
the parallel early history of Good and Evil, Aph. 45 (namely, their
origin from the castes of the aristocrats and the slaves); similarly,
Aph. 136 et seq., concerning the birth and value of ascetic morality;
similarly, Aphs. 96, 99, vol. ii., Aph. 89, concerning the Morality of
Custom, that far older and more original kind of morality which is toto
cĆlo different from the altruistic ethics (in which Dr. RĂ©e, like all
the English moral philosophers, sees the ethical âThing-in-itselfâ);
finally, Aph. 92. Similarly, Aph. 26 in Human, all-too-Human, part ii.,
and Aph. 112, the Dawn of Day, concerning the origin of Justice as a
balance between persons of approximately equal power (equilibrium as the
hypothesis of all contract, consequently of all law); similarly,
concerning the origin of Punishment, Human, all-too-Human, part ii.,
Aphs. 22, 23, in regard to which the deterrent object is neither
essential nor original (as Dr. RĂ©e thinks:ârather is it that this object
is only imported, under certain definite conditions, and always as
something extra and additional).
5.
In reality I had set my heart at that time on something much more
important than the nature of the theories of myself or others concerning
the origin of morality (or, more precisely, the real function from my
view of these theories was to point an end to which they were one among
many means). The issue for me was the value of morality, and on that
subject I had to place myself in a state of abstraction, in which I was
almost alone with my great teacher Schopenhauer, to whom that book, with
all its passion and inherent contradiction (for that book also was a
polemic), turned for present help as though he were still alive. The
issue was, strangely enough, the value of the âun-egoisticâ instincts,
the instincts of pity, self-denial, and self-sacrifice which
Schopenhauer had so persistently painted in golden colours, deified and
etherealised, that eventually they appeared to him, as it were, high and
dry, as âintrinsic values in themselves,â on the strength of which he
uttered both to Life and to himself his own negation. But against these
very instincts there voiced itself in my soul a more and more
fundamental mistrust, a scepticism that dug ever deeper and deeper: and
in this very instinct I saw the great danger of mankind, its most
sublime temptation and seductionâseduction to what? to nothingness?âin
these very instincts I saw the beginning of the end, stability, the
exhaustion that gazes backwards, the will turning against Life, the last
illness announcing itself with its own mincing melancholy: I realised
that the morality of pity which spread wider and wider, and whose grip
infected even philosophers with its disease, was the most sinister
symptom of our modern European civilisation; I realised that it was the
route along which that civilisation slid on its way toâa new Buddhism?âa
European Buddhism?âNihilism? This exaggerated estimation in which modern
philosophers have held pity, is quite a new phenomenon: up to that time
philosophers were absolutely unanimous as to the worthlessness of pity.
I need only mention Plato, Spinoza, La Rochefoucauld, and Kantâfour
minds as mutually different as is possible, but united on one point;
their contempt of pity.
6.
This problem of the value of pity and of the pity-morality (I am an
opponent of the modern infamous emasculation of our emotions) seems at
the first blush a mere isolated problem, a note of interrogation for
itself; he, however, who once halts at this problem, and learns how to
put questions, will experience what I experienced:âa new and immense
vista unfolds itself before him, a sense of potentiality seizes him like
a vertigo, every species of doubt, mistrust, and fear springs up, the
belief in morality, nay, in all morality, totters,âfinally a new demand
voices itself. Let us speak out this new demand: we need a critique of
moral values, the value of these values is for the first time to be
called into questionâand for this purpose a knowledge is necessary of
the conditions and circumstances out of which these values grew, and
under which they experienced their evolution and their distortion
(morality as a result, as a symptom, as a mask, as Tartuffism, as
disease, as a misunderstanding; but also morality as a cause, as a
remedy, as a stimulant, as a fetter, as a drug), especially as such a
knowledge has neither existed up to the present time nor is even now
generally desired. The value of these âvaluesâ was taken for granted as
an indisputable fact, which was beyond all question. No one has, up to
the present, exhibited the faintest doubt or hesitation in judging the
âgood manâ to be of a higher value than the âevil man,â of a higher
value with regard specifically to human progress, utility, and
prosperity generally, not forgetting the future. What? Suppose the
converse were the truth! What? Suppose there lurked in the âgood manâ a
symptom of retrogression, such as a danger, a temptation, a poison, a
narcotic, by means of which the present battened on the future! More
comfortable and less risky perhaps than its opposite, but also pettier,
meaner! So that morality would really be saddled with the guilt, if the
maximum potentiality of the power and splendour of the human species
were never to be attained? So that really morality would be the danger
of dangers?
7.
Enough, that after this vista had disclosed itself to me, I myself had
reason to search for learned, bold, and industrious colleagues (I am
doing it even to this very day). It means traversing with new clamorous
questions, and at the same time with new eyes, the immense, distant, and
completely unexplored land of moralityâof a morality which has actually
existed and been actually lived! and is this not practically equivalent
to first discovering that land? If, in this context, I thought, amongst
others, of the aforesaid Dr. RĂ©e, I did so because I had no doubt that
from the very nature of his questions he would be compelled to have
recourse to a truer method, in order to obtain his answers. Have I
deceived myself on that score? I wished at all events to give a better
direction of vision to an eye of such keenness, and such impartiality. I
wished to direct him to the real history of morality, and to warn him,
while there was yet time, against a world of English theories that
culminated in the blue vacuum of heaven. Other colours, of course, rise
immediately to oneâs mind as being a hundred times more potent than blue
for a genealogy of morals:âfor instance, grey, by which I mean authentic
facts capable of definite proof and having actually existed, or, to put
it shortly, the whole of that long hieroglyphic script (which is so hard
to decipher) about the past history of human morals. This script was
unknown to Dr. RĂ©e; but he had read Darwin:âand so in his philosophy the
Darwinian beast and that pink of modernity, the demure weakling and
dilettante, who âbites no longer,â shake hands politely in a fashion
that is at least instructive, the latter exhibiting a certain facial
expression of refined and good-humoured indolence, tinged with a touch
of pessimism and exhaustion; as if it really did not pay to take all
these thingsâI mean moral problemsâso seriously. I, on the other hand,
think that there are no subjects which pay better for being taken
seriously; part of this payment is, that perhaps eventually they admit
of being taken gaily. This gaiety indeed, or, to use my own language,
this joyful wisdom, is a payment; a payment for a protracted, brave,
laborious, and burrowing seriousness, which, it goes without saying, is
the attribute of but a few. But on that day on which we say from the
fullness of our hearts, âForward! our old morality too is fit material
for Comedy,â we shall have discovered a new plot, and a new possibility
for the Dionysian drama entitled The Soulâs Fateâand he will speedily
utilise it, one can wager safely, he, the great ancient eternal
dramatist of the comedy of our existence.
8.
If this writing be obscure to any individual, and jar on his ears, I do
not think that it is necessarily I who am to blame. It is clear enough,
on the hypothesis which I presuppose, namely, that the reader has first
read my previous writings and has not grudged them a certain amount of
trouble: it is not, indeed, a simple matter to get really at their
essence. Take, for instance, my Zarathustra; I allow no one to pass
muster as knowing that book, unless every single word therein has at
some time wrought in him a profound wound, and at some time exercised on
him a profound enchantment: then and not till then can he enjoy the
privilege of participating reverently in the halcyon element, from which
that work is born, in its sunny brilliance, its distance, its
spaciousness, its certainty. In other cases the aphoristic form produces
difficulty, but this is only because this form is treated too casually.
An aphorism properly coined and cast into its final mould is far from
being âdecipheredâ as soon as it has been read; on the contrary, it is
then that it first requires to be expoundedâof course for that purpose
an art of exposition is necessary. The third essay in this book provides
an example of what is offered, of what in such cases I call exposition:
an aphorism is prefixed to that essay, the essay itself is its
commentary. Certainly one quality which nowadays has been best
forgottenâand that is why it will take some time yet for my writings to
become readableâis essential in order to practise reading as an artâa
quality for the exercise of which it is necessary to be a cow, and under
no circumstances a modern man!â rumination.
Sils-Maria, Upper Engadine,
July 1887.
1.
Those English psychologists, who up to the present are the only
philosophers who are to be thanked for any endeavour to get as far as a
history of the origin of moralityâthese men, I say, offer us in their
own personalities no paltry problem;âthey even have, if I am to be quite
frank about it, in their capacity of living riddles, an advantage over
their booksâthey themselves are interesting! These English
psychologistsâwhat do they really mean? We always find them voluntarily
or involuntarily at the same task of pushing to the front the partie
honteuse of our inner world, and looking for the efficient, governing,
and decisive principle in that precise quarter where the intellectual
self-respect of the race would be the most reluctant to find it (for
example, in the vis inertiĂŠ of habit, or in forgetfulness, or in a blind
and fortuitous mechanism and association of ideas, or in some factor
that is purely passive, reflex, molecular, or fundamentally stupid)âwhat
is the real motive power which always impels these psychologists in
precisely this direction? Is it an instinct for human disparagement
somewhat sinister, vulgar, and malignant, or perhaps incomprehensible
even to itself? or perhaps a touch of pessimistic jealousy, the mistrust
of disillusioned idealists who have become gloomy, poisoned, and bitter?
or a petty subconscious enmity and rancour against Christianity (and
Plato), that has conceivably never crossed the threshold of
consciousness? or just a vicious taste for those elements of life which
are bizarre, painfully paradoxical, mystical, and illogical? or, as a
final alternative, a dash of each of these motivesâa little vulgarity, a
little gloominess, a little anti-Christianity, a little craving for the
necessary piquancy?
But I am told that it is simply a case of old frigid and tedious frogs
crawling and hopping around men and inside men, as if they were as
thoroughly at home there, as they would be in a swamp.
I am opposed to this statement, nay, I do not believe it; and if, in the
impossibility of knowledge, one is permitted to wish, so do I wish from
my heart that just the converse metaphor should apply, and that these
analysts with their psychological microscopes should be, at bottom,
brave, proud, and magnanimous animals who know how to bridle both their
hearts and their smarts, and have specifically trained themselves to
sacrifice what is desirable to what is true, any truth in fact, even the
simple, bitter, ugly, repulsive, unchristian, and immoral truthsâfor
there are truths of that description.
2.
All honour, then, to the noble spirits who would fain dominate these
historians of morality. But it is certainly a pity that they lack the
historical sense itself, that they themselves are quite deserted by all
the beneficent spirits of history. The whole train of their thought
runs, as was always the way of old-fashioned philosophers, on thoroughly
unhistorical lines: there is no doubt on this point. The crass
ineptitude of their genealogy of morals is immediately apparent when the
question arises of ascertaining the origin of the idea and judgment of
âgood.â âMan had originally,â so speaks their decree, âpraised and
called âgoodâ altruistic acts from the standpoint of those on whom they
were conferred, that is, those to whom they were useful; subsequently
the origin of this praise was forgotten, and altruistic acts, simply
because, as a sheer matter of habit, they were praised as good, came
also to be felt as goodâas though they contained in themselves some
intrinsic goodness.â The thing is obvious:âthis initial derivation
contains already all the typical and idiosyncratic traits of the English
psychologistsâwe have âutility,â âforgetting,â âhabit,â and finally
âerror,â the whole assemblage forming the basis of a system of values,
on which the higher man has up to the present prided himself as though
it were a kind of privilege of man in general. This pride must be
brought low, this system of values must lose its values: is that
attained?
Now the first argument that comes ready to my hand is that the real
homestead of the concept âgoodâ is sought and located in the wrong
place: the judgment âgoodâ did not originate among those to whom
goodness was shown. Much rather has it been the good themselves, that
is, the aristocratic, the powerful, the high-stationed, the high-minded,
who have felt that they themselves were good, and that their actions
were good, that is to say of the first order, in contradistinction to
all the low, the low-minded, the vulgar, and the plebeian. It was out of
this pathos of distance that they first arrogated the right to create
values for their own profit, and to coin the names of such values: what
had they to do with utility? The standpoint of utility is as alien and
as inapplicable as it could possibly be, when we have to deal with so
volcanic an effervescence of supreme values, creating and demarcating as
they do a hierarchy within themselves: it is at this juncture that one
arrives at an appreciation of the contrast to that tepid temperature,
which is the presupposition on which every combination of worldly wisdom
and every calculation of practical expediency is always basedâand not
for one occasional, not for one exceptional instance, but chronically.
The pathos of nobility and distance, as I have said, the chronic and
despotic esprit de corps and fundamental instinct of a higher dominant
race coming into association with a meaner race, an âunder race,â this
is the origin of the antithesis of good and bad.
(The mastersâ right of giving names goes so far that it is permissible
to look upon language itself as the expression of the power of the
masters: they say âthis is that, and that,â they seal finally every
object and every event with a sound, and thereby at the same time take
possession of it.) It is because of this origin that the word âgoodâ is
far from having any necessary connection with altruistic acts, in
accordance with the superstitious belief of these moral philosophers. On
the contrary, it is on the occasion of the decay of aristocratic values,
that the antitheses between âegoisticâ and âaltruisticâ presses more and
more heavily on the human conscienceâit is, to use my own language, the
herd instinct which finds in this antithesis an expression in many ways.
And even then it takes a considerable time for this instinct to become
sufficiently dominant, for the valuation to be inextricably dependent on
this antithesis (as is the case in contemporary Europe); for to-day that
prejudice is predominant, which, acting even now with all the intensity
of an obsession and brain disease, holds that âmoral,â âaltruistic,â and
âdĂ©sintĂ©ressĂ©â are concepts of equal value.
3.
In the second place, quite apart from the fact that this hypothesis as
to the genesis of the value âgoodâ cannot be historically upheld, it
suffers from an inherent psychological contradiction. The utility of
altruistic conduct has presumably been the origin of its being praised,
and this origin has become forgotten:âBut in what conceivable way is
this forgetting possible! Has perchance the utility of such conduct
ceased at some given moment? The contrary is the case. This utility has
rather been experienced every day at all times, and is consequently a
feature that obtains a new and regular emphasis with every fresh day; it
follows that, so far from vanishing from the consciousness, so far
indeed from being forgotten, it must necessarily become impressed on the
consciousness with ever-increasing distinctness. How much more logical
is that contrary theory (it is not the truer for that) which is
represented, for instance, by Herbert Spencer, who places the concept
âgoodâ as essentially similar to the concept âuseful,â âpurposive,â so
that in the judgments âgoodâ and âbadâ mankind is simply summarising and
investing with a sanction its unforgotten and unforgettable experiences
concerning the âuseful-purposiveâ and the âmischievous-non-purposive.â
According to this theory, âgoodâ is the attribute of that which has
previously shown itself useful; and so is able to claim to be considered
âvaluable in the highest degree,â âvaluable in itself.â This method of
explanation is also, as I have said, wrong, but at any rate the
explanation itself is coherent, and psychologically tenable.
4.
The guide-post which first put me on the right track was this
questionâwhat is the true etymological significance of the various
symbols for the idea âgoodâ which have been coined in the various
languages? I then found that they all led back to the same evolution of
the same ideaâthat everywhere âaristocrat,â ânobleâ (in the social
sense), is the root idea, out of which have necessarily developed âgoodâ
in the sense of âwith aristocratic soul,â ânoble,â in the sense of âwith
a soul of high calibre,â âwith a privileged soulââa development which
invariably runs parallel with that other evolution by which âvulgar,â
âplebeian,â âlow,â are made to change finally into âbad.â The most
eloquent proof of this last contention is the German word âschlechtâ
itself: this word is identical with âschlichtââ(compare âschlechtwegâ
and âschlechterdingsâ)âwhich, originally and as yet without any sinister
innuendo, simply denoted the plebeian man in contrast to the
aristocratic man. It is at the sufficiently late period of the Thirty
Yearsâ War that this sense becomes changed to the sense now current.
From the standpoint of the Genealogy of Morals this discovery seems to
be substantial: the lateness of it is to be attributed to the retarding
influence exercised in the modern world by democratic prejudice in the
sphere of all questions of origin. This extends, as will shortly be
shown, even to the province of natural science and physiology, which,
prima facie is the most objective. The extent of the mischief which is
caused by this prejudice (once it is free of all trammels except those
of its own malice), particularly to Ethics and History, is shown by the
notorious case of Buckle: it was in Buckle that that plebeianism of the
modern spirit, which is of English origin, broke out once again from its
malignant soil with all the violence of a slimy volcano, and with that
salted, rampant, and vulgar eloquence with which up to the present time
all volcanoes have spoken.
5.
With regard to our problem, which can justly be called an intimate
problem, and which elects to appeal to only a limited number of ears: it
is of no small interest to ascertain that in those words and roots which
denote âgoodâ we catch glimpses of that arch-trait, on the strength of
which the aristocrats feel themselves to be beings of a higher order
than their fellows. Indeed, they call themselves in perhaps the most
frequent instances simply after their superiority in power (e.g. âthe
powerful,â âthe lords,â âthe commandersâ), or after the most obvious
sign of their superiority, as for example âthe rich,â âthe possessorsâ
(that is the meaning of arya; and the Iranian and Slav languages
correspond). But they also call themselves after some characteristic
idiosyncrasy; and this is the case which now concerns us. They name
themselves, for instance, âthe truthfulâ: this is first done by the
Greek nobility whose mouthpiece is found in Theognis, the Megarian poet.
The word áŒÏΞλοÏ, which is coined for the purpose, signifies
etymologically âone who is,â who has reality, who is real, who is true;
and then with a subjective twist, the âtrue,â as the âtruthfulâ: at this
stage in the evolution of the idea, it becomes the motto and party cry
of the nobility, and quite completes the transition to the meaning
ânoble,â so as to place outside the pale the lying, vulgar man, as
Theognis conceives and portrays himâtill finally the word after the
decay of the nobility is left to delineate psychological noblesse, and
becomes as it were ripe and mellow. In the word ÎșαÎșÏÏ as in ΎΔÎčλÏÏ (the
plebeian in contrast to the áŒÎłÎ±ÎžÏÏ) the cowardice is emphasised. This
affords perhaps an inkling on what lines the etymological origin of the
very ambiguous áŒÎłÎ±ÎžÏÏ is to be investigated. In the Latin malus (which I
place side by side with ÎŒÎλαÏ) the vulgar man can be distinguished as
the dark-coloured, and above all as the black-haired (âhic niger estâ),
as the pre-Aryan inhabitants of the Italian soil, whose complexion
formed the clearest feature of distinction from the dominant blondes,
namely, the Aryan conquering race:âat any rate Gaelic has afforded me
the exact analogueâFin (for instance, in the name Fin-Gal), the
distinctive word of the nobility, finallyâgood, noble, clean, but
originally the blonde-haired man in contrast to the dark black-haired
aboriginals. The Celts, if I may make a parenthetic statement, were
throughout a blonde race; and it is wrong to connect, as Virchow still
connects, those traces of an essentially dark-haired population which
are to be seen on the more elaborate ethnographical maps of Germany with
any Celtic ancestry or with any admixture of Celtic blood: in this
context it is rather the pre-Aryan population of Germany which surges up
to these districts. (The same is true substantially of the whole of
Europe: in point of fact, the subject race has finally again obtained
the upper hand, in complexion and the shortness of the skull, and
perhaps in the intellectual and social qualities. Who can guarantee that
modern democracy, still more modern anarchy, and indeed that tendency to
the âCommune,â the most primitive form of society, which is now common
to all the Socialists in Europe, does not in its real essence signify a
monstrous reversionâand that the conquering and master raceâthe Aryan
race, is not also becoming inferior physiologically?) I believe that I
can explain the Latin bonus as the âwarriorâ: my hypothesis is that I am
right in deriving bonus from an older duonus (compare bellum = duellum =
duen-lum, in which the word duonus appears to me to be contained). Bonus
accordingly as the man of discord, of variance, âentzweiungâ (duo), as
the warrior: one sees what in ancient Rome âthe goodâ meant for a man.
Must not our actual German word gut mean âthe godlike, the man of
godlike raceâ? and be identical with the national name (originally the
noblesâ name) of the Goths?
The grounds for this supposition do not appertain to this work.
6.
Above all, there is no exception (though there are opportunities for
exceptions) to this rule, that the idea of political superiority always
resolves itself into the idea of psychological superiority, in those
cases where the highest caste is at the same time the priestly caste,
and in accordance with its general characteristics confers on itself the
privilege of a title which alludes specifically to its priestly
function. It is in these cases, for instance, that âcleanâ and âuncleanâ
confront each other for the first time as badges of class distinction;
here again there develops a âgoodâ and a âbad,â in a sense which has
ceased to be merely social. Moreover, care should be taken not to take
these ideas of âcleanâ and âuncleanâ too seriously, too broadly, or too
symbolically: all the ideas of ancient man have, on the contrary, got to
be understood in their initial stages, in a sense which is, to an almost
inconceivable extent, crude, coarse, physical, and narrow, and above all
essentially unsymbolical. The âclean manâ is originally only a man who
washes himself, who abstains from certain foods which are conducive to
skin diseases, who does not sleep with the unclean women of the lower
classes, who has a horror of bloodânot more, not much more! On the other
hand, the very nature of a priestly aristocracy shows the reasons why
just at such an early juncture there should ensue a really dangerous
sharpening and intensification of opposed values: it is, in fact,
through these opposed values that gulfs are cleft in the social plane,
which a veritable Achilles of free thought would shudder to cross. There
is from the outset a certain diseased taint in such sacerdotal
aristocracies, and in the habits which prevail in such societiesâhabits
which, averse as they are to action, constitute a compound of
introspection and explosive emotionalism, as a result of which there
appears that introspective morbidity and neurasthenia, which adheres
almost inevitably to all priests at all times: with regard, however, to
the remedy which they themselves have invented for this diseaseâthe
philosopher has no option but to state, that it has proved itself in its
effects a hundred times more dangerous than the disease, from which it
should have been the deliverer. Humanity itself is still diseased from
the effects of the naïvetés of this priestly cure. Take, for instance,
certain kinds of diet (abstention from flesh), fasts, sexual continence,
flight into the wilderness (a kind of Weir-Mitchell isolation, though of
course without that system of excessive feeding and fattening which is
the most efficient antidote to all the hysteria of the ascetic ideal);
consider too the whole metaphysic of the priests, with its war on the
senses, its enervation, its hair-splitting; consider its self-hypnotism
on the fakir and Brahman principles (it uses Brahman as a glass disc and
obsession), and that climax which we can understand only too well of an
unusual satiety with its panacea of nothingness (or God:âthe demand for
a unio mystica with God is the demand of the Buddhist for nothingness,
Nirvanaâand nothing else!). In sacerdotal societies every element is on
a more dangerous scale, not merely cures and remedies, but also pride,
revenge, cunning, exaltation, love, ambition, virtue,
morbidity:âfurther, it can fairly be stated that it is on the soil of
this essentially dangerous form of human society, the sacerdotal form,
that man really becomes for the first time an interesting animal, that
it is in this form that the soul of man has in a higher sense attained
depths and become evilâand those are the two fundamental forms of the
superiority which up to the present man has exhibited over every other
animal.
7.
The reader will have already surmised with what ease the priestly mode
of valuation can branch off from the knightly aristocratic mode, and
then develop into the very antithesis of the latter: special impetus is
given to this opposition, by every occasion when the castes of the
priests and warriors confront each other with mutual jealousy and cannot
agree over the prize. The knightly-aristocratic âvaluesâ are based on a
careful cult of the physical, on a flowering, rich, and even
effervescing healthiness, that goes considerably beyond what is
necessary for maintaining life, on war, adventure, the chase, the dance,
the tourneyâon everything, in fact, which is contained in strong, free,
and joyous action. The priestly-aristocratic mode of valuation isâwe
have seenâbased on other hypotheses: it is bad enough for this class
when it is a question of war! Yet the priests are, as is notorious, the
worst enemiesâwhy? Because they are the weakest. Their weakness causes
their hate to expand into a monstrous and sinister shape, a shape which
is most crafty and most poisonous. The really great haters in the
history of the world have always been priests, who are also the
cleverest hatersâin comparison with the cleverness of priestly revenge,
every other piece of cleverness is practically negligible. Human history
would be too fatuous for anything were it not for the cleverness
imported into it by the weakâtake at once the most important instance.
All the worldâs efforts against the âaristocrats,â the âmighty,â the
âmasters,â the âholders of power,â are negligible by comparison with
what has been accomplished against those classes by the Jewsâthe Jews,
that priestly nation which eventually realised that the one method of
effecting satisfaction on its enemies and tyrants was by means of a
radical transvaluation of values, which was at the same time an act of
the cleverest revenge. Yet the method was only appropriate to a nation
of priests, to a nation of the most jealously nursed priestly
revengefulness. It was the Jews who, in opposition to the aristocratic
equation (good = aristocratic = beautiful = happy = loved by the gods),
dared with a terrifying logic to suggest the contrary equation, and
indeed to maintain with the teeth of the most profound hatred (the
hatred of weakness) this contrary equation, namely, âthe wretched are
alone the good; the poor, the weak, the lowly, are alone the good; the
suffering, the needy, the sick, the loathsome, are the only ones who are
pious, the only ones who are blessed, for them alone is salvationâbut
you, on the other hand, you aristocrats, you men of power, you are to
all eternity the evil, the horrible, the covetous, the insatiate, the
godless; eternally also shall you be the unblessed, the cursed, the
damned!â We know who it was who reaped the heritage of this Jewish
transvaluation. In the context of the monstrous and inordinately fateful
initiative which the Jews have exhibited in connection with this most
fundamental of all declarations of war, I remember the passage which
came to my pen on another occasion (Beyond Good and Evil, Aph. 195)âthat
it was, in fact, with the Jews that the revolt of the slaves begins in
the sphere of morals; that revolt which has behind it a history of two
millennia, and which at the present day has only moved out of our sight,
because itâhas achieved victory.
8.
But you understand this not? You have no eyes for a force which has
taken two thousand years to achieve victory?âThere is nothing wonderful
in this: all lengthy processes are hard to see and to realise. But this
is what took place: from the trunk of that tree of revenge and hate,
Jewish hate,âthat most profound and sublime hate, which creates ideals
and changes old values to new creations, the like of which has never
been on earth,âthere grew a phenomenon which was equally incomparable, a
new love, the most profound and sublime of all kinds of love;âand from
what other trunk could it have grown? But beware of supposing that this
love has soared on its upward growth, as in any way a real negation of
that thirst for revenge, as an antithesis to the Jewish hate! No, the
contrary is the truth! This love grew out of that hate, as its crown, as
its triumphant crown, circling wider and wider amid the clarity and
fulness of the sun, and pursuing in the very kingdom of light and height
its goal of hatred, its victory, its spoil, its strategy, with the same
intensity with which the roots of that tree of hate sank into everything
which was deep and evil with increasing stability and increasing desire.
This Jesus of Nazareth, the incarnate gospel of love, this âRedeemerâ
bringing salvation and victory to the poor, the sick, the sinfulâwas he
not really temptation in its most sinister and irresistible form,
temptation to take the tortuous path to those very Jewish values and
those very Jewish ideals? Has not Israel really obtained the final goal
of its sublime revenge, by the tortuous paths of this âRedeemer,â for
all that he might pose as Israelâs adversary and Israelâs destroyer? Is
it not due to the black magic of a really great policy of revenge, of a
far-seeing, burrowing revenge, both acting and calculating with
slowness, that Israel himself must repudiate before all the world the
actual instrument of his own revenge and nail it to the cross, so that
all the worldâthat is, all the enemies of Israelâcould nibble without
suspicion at this very bait? Could, moreover, any human mind with all
its elaborate ingenuity invent a bait that was more truly dangerous?
Anything that was even equivalent in the power of its seductive,
intoxicating, defiling, and corrupting influence to that symbol of the
holy cross, to that awful paradox of a âgod on the cross,â to that
mystery of the unthinkable, supreme, and utter horror of the
self-crucifixion of a god for the salvation of man? It is at least
certain that sub hoc signo Israel, with its revenge and transvaluation
of all values, has up to the present always triumphed again over all
other ideals, over all more aristocratic ideals.
9.
âBut why do you talk of nobler ideals? Let us submit to the facts; that
the people have triumphedâor the slaves, or the populace, or the herd,
or whatever name you care to give themâif this has happened through the
Jews, so be it! In that case no nation ever had a greater mission in the
worldâs history. The âmastersâ have been done away with; the morality of
the vulgar man has triumphed. This triumph may also be called a
blood-poisoning (it has mutually fused the races)âI do not dispute it;
but there is no doubt but that this intoxication has succeeded. The
âredemptionâ of the human race (that is, from the masters) is
progressing swimmingly; everything is obviously becoming Judaised, or
Christianised, or vulgarised (what is there in the words?). It seems
impossible to stop the course of this poisoning through the whole body
politic of mankindâbut its tempo and pace may from the present time be
slower, more delicate, quieter, more discreetâthere is time enough. In
view of this context has the Church nowadays any necessary purpose? has
it, in fact, a right to live? Or could man get on without it? QuĂŠritur.
It seems that it fetters and retards this tendency, instead of
accelerating it. Well, even that might be its utility. The Church
certainly is a crude and boorish institution, that is repugnant to an
intelligence with any pretence at delicacy, to a really modern taste.
Should it not at any rate learn to be somewhat more subtle? It alienates
nowadays, more than it allures. Which of us would, forsooth, be a
freethinker if there were no Church? It is the Church which repels us,
not its poisonâapart from the Church we like the poison.â This is the
epilogue of a freethinker to my discourse, of an honourable animal (as
he has given abundant proof), and a democrat to boot; he had up to that
time listened to me, and could not endure my silence, but for me,
indeed, with regard to this topic there is much on which to be silent.
10.
The revolt of the slaves in morals begins in the very principle of
resentment becoming creative and giving birth to valuesâa resentment
experienced by creatures who, deprived as they are of the proper outlet
of action, are forced to find their compensation in an imaginary
revenge. While every aristocratic morality springs from a triumphant
affirmation of its own demands, the slave morality says ânoâ from the
very outset to what is âoutside itself,â âdifferent from itself,â and
ânot itselfâ: and this ânoâ is its creative deed. This volte-face of the
valuing standpointâthis inevitable gravitation to the objective instead
of back to the subjectiveâis typical of âresentmentâ: the slave-morality
requires as the condition of its existence an external and objective
world, to employ physiological terminology, it requires objective
stimuli to be capable of action at allâits action is fundamentally a
reaction. The contrary is the case when we come to the aristocratâs
system of values: it acts and grows spontaneously, it merely seeks its
antithesis in order to pronounce a more grateful and exultant âyesâ to
its own self;âits negative conception, âlow,â âvulgar,â âbad,â is merely
a pale late-born foil in comparison with its positive and fundamental
conception (saturated as it is with life and passion), of âwe
aristocrats, we good ones, we beautiful ones, we happy ones.â
When the aristocratic morality goes astray and commits sacrilege on
reality, this is limited to that particular sphere with which it is not
sufficiently acquaintedâa sphere, in fact, from the real knowledge of
which it disdainfully defends itself. It misjudges, in some cases, the
sphere which it despises, the sphere of the common vulgar man and the
low people: on the other hand, due weight should be given to the
consideration that in any case the mood of contempt, of disdain, of
superciliousness, even on the supposition that it falsely portrays the
object of its contempt, will always be far removed from that degree of
falsity which will always characterise the attacksâin effigy, of
courseâof the vindictive hatred and revengefulness of the weak in
onslaughts on their enemies. In point of fact, there is in contempt too
strong an admixture of nonchalance, of casualness, of boredom, of
impatience, even of personal exultation, for it to be capable of
distorting its victim into a real caricature or a real monstrosity.
Attention again should be paid to the almost benevolent nuances which,
for instance, the Greek nobility imports into all the words by which it
distinguishes the common people from itself; note how continuously a
kind of pity, care, and consideration imparts its honeyed flavour, until
at last almost all the words which are applied to the vulgar man survive
finally as expressions for âunhappy,â âworthy of pityâ (compare ΎΔÎčλο,
ΎΔίλαÎčÎżÏ, ÏÎżÎœÎ·ÏÏÏ, ÎŒÎżÏΞηÏÏÏ]; the latter two names really denoting the
vulgar man as labour-slave and beast of burden)âand how, conversely,
âbad,â âlow,â âunhappyâ have never ceased to ring in the Greek ear with
a tone in which âunhappyâ is the predominant note: this is a heritage of
the old noble aristocratic morality, which remains true to itself even
in contempt (let philologists remember the sense in which áœÎčÎ¶Ï ÏÏÏ,
áŒÎœÎżÎ»ÎČÎżÏ, ÏÎ»ÎźÎŒÏÎœ, ÎŽÏ ÏÏÏ ÏΔáżÎœ, ÎŸÏ ÎŒÏÎżÏÎŹ used to be employed). The
âwell-bornâ simply felt themselves the âhappyâ; they did not have to
manufacture their happiness artificially through looking at their
enemies, or in cases to talk and lie themselves into happiness (as is
the custom with all resentful men); and similarly, complete men as they
were, exuberant with strength, and consequently necessarily energetic,
they were too wise to dissociate happiness from actionâactivity becomes
in their minds necessarily counted as happiness (that is the etymology
of ΔᜠÏÏáŒÏÏΔÎčÎœ)âall in sharp contrast to the âhappinessâ of the weak and
the oppressed, with their festering venom and malignity, among whom
happiness appears essentially as a narcotic, a deadening, a quietude, a
peace, a âSabbath,â an enervation of the mind and relaxation of the
limbs,âin short, a purely passive phenomenon. While the aristocratic man
lived in confidence and openness with himself (ÎłÎ”ÎœÎœÎ±áżÎżÏ, ânobleΔ-born,â
emphasises the nuance âsincere,â and perhaps also ânaĂŻfâ), the resentful
man, on the other hand, is neither sincere nor naĂŻf, nor honest and
candid with himself. His soul squints; his mind loves hidden crannies,
tortuous paths and back-doors, everything secret appeals to him as his
world, his safety, his balm; he is past master in silence, in not
forgetting, in waiting, in provisional self-depreciation and
self-abasement. A race of such resentful men will of necessity
eventually prove more prudent than any aristocratic race, it will honour
prudence on quite a distinct scale, as, in fact, a paramount condition
of existence, while prudence among aristocratic men is apt to be tinged
with a delicate flavour of luxury and refinement; so among them it plays
nothing like so integral a part as that complete certainty of function
of the governing unconscious instincts, or as indeed a certain lack of
prudence, such as a vehement and valiant charge, whether against danger
or the enemy, or as those ecstatic bursts of rage, love, reverence,
gratitude, by which at all times noble souls have recognised each other.
When the resentment of the aristocratic man manifests itself, it fulfils
and exhausts itself in an immediate reaction, and consequently instills
no venom: on the other hand, it never manifests itself at all in
countless instances, when in the case of the feeble and weak it would be
inevitable. An inability to take seriously for any length of time their
enemies, their disasters, their misdeedsâthat is the sign of the full
strong natures who possess a superfluity of moulding plastic force, that
heals completely and produces forgetfulness: a good example of this in
the modern world is Mirabeau, who had no memory for any insults and
meannesses which were practised on him, and who was only incapable of
forgiving because he forgot. Such a man indeed shakes off with a shrug
many a worm which would have buried itself in another; it is only in
characters like these that we see the possibility (supposing, of course,
that there is such a possibility in the world) of the real âlove of
oneâs enemies.â What respect for his enemies is found, forsooth, in an
aristocratic manâand such a reverence is already a bridge to love! He
insists on having his enemy to himself as his distinction. He tolerates
no other enemy but a man in whose character there is nothing to despise
and much to honour! On the other hand, imagine the âenemyâ as the
resentful man conceives himâand it is here exactly that we see his work,
his creativeness; he has conceived âthe evil enemy,â the âevil one,â and
indeed that is the root idea from which he now evolves as a contrasting
and corresponding figure a âgood one,â himselfâhis very self!
11
The method of this man is quite contrary to that of the aristocratic
man, who conceives the root idea âgoodâ spontaneously and straight away,
that is to say, out of himself, and from that material then creates for
himself a concept of âbadâ! This âbadâ of aristocratic origin and that
âevilâ out of the cauldron of unsatisfied hatredâthe former an
imitation, an âextra,â an additional nuance; the latter, on the other
hand, the original, the beginning, the essential act in the conception
of a slave-moralityâthese two words âbadâ and âevil,â how great a
difference do they mark, in spite of the fact that they have an
identical contrary in the idea âgood.â But the idea âgoodâ is not the
same: much rather let the question be asked, âWho is really evil
according to the meaning of the morality of resentment?â In all
sternness let it be answered thus:âjust the good man of the other
morality, just the aristocrat, the powerful one, the one who rules, but
who is distorted by the venomous eye of resentfulness, into a new
colour, a new signification, a new appearance. This particular point we
would be the last to deny: the man who learnt to know those âgoodâ ones
only as enemies, learnt at the same time not to know them only as âevil
enemiesâ and the same men who inter pares were kept so rigorously in
bounds through convention, respect, custom, and gratitude, though much
more through mutual vigilance and jealousy inter pares, these men who in
their relations with each other find so many new ways of manifesting
consideration, self-control, delicacy, loyalty, pride, and friendship,
these men are in reference to what is outside their circle (where the
foreign element, a foreign country, begins), not much better than beasts
of prey, which have been let loose. They enjoy there freedom from all
social control, they feel that in the wilderness they can give vent with
impunity to that tension which is produced by enclosure and imprisonment
in the peace of society, they revert to the innocence of the
beast-of-prey conscience, like jubilant monsters, who perhaps come from
a ghastly bout of murder, arson, rape, and torture, with bravado and a
moral equanimity, as though merely some wild studentâs prank had been
played, perfectly convinced that the poets have now an ample theme to
sing and celebrate. It is impossible not to recognise at the core of all
these aristocratic races the beast of prey; the magnificent blonde
brute, avidly rampant for spoil and victory; this hidden core needed an
outlet from time to time, the beast must get loose again, must return
into the wildernessâthe Roman, Arabic, German, and Japanese nobility,
the Homeric heroes, the Scandinavian Vikings, are all alike in this
need. It is the aristocratic races who have left the idea âBarbarianâ on
all the tracks in which they have marched; nay, a consciousness of this
very barbarianism, and even a pride in it, manifests itself even in
their highest civilisation (for example, when Pericles says to his
Athenians in that celebrated funeral oration, âOur audacity has forced a
way over every land and sea, rearing everywhere imperishable memorials
of itself for good and for evilâ). This audacity of aristocratic races,
mad, absurd, and spasmodic as may be its expression; the incalculable
and fantastic nature of their enterprises, Pericles sets in special
relief and glory the ៜÏÎ±ÎžÏ ÎŒÎŻÎ± of the Athenians, their nonchalance and
contempt for safety, body, life, and comfort, their awful joy and
intense delight in all destruction, in all the ecstasies of victory and
cruelty,âall these features become crystallised, for those who suffered
thereby in the picture of the âbarbarian,â of the âevil enemy,â perhaps
of the âGothâ and of the âVandal.â The profound, icy mistrust which the
German provokes, as soon as he arrives at power,âeven at the present
time,âis always still an aftermath of that inextinguishable horror with
which for whole centuries Europe has regarded the wrath of the blonde
Teuton beast (although between the old Germans and ourselves there
exists scarcely a psychological, let alone a physical, relationship). I
have once called attention to the embarrassment of Hesiod, when he
conceived the series of social ages, and endeavoured to express them in
gold, silver, and bronze. He could only dispose of the contradiction,
with which he was confronted, by the Homeric world, an age magnificent
indeed, but at the same time so awful and so violent, by making two ages
out of one, which he henceforth placed one behind each otherâfirst, the
age of the heroes and demigods, as that world had remained in the
memories of the aristocratic families, who found therein their own
ancestors; secondly, the bronze age, as that corresponding age appeared
to the descendants of the oppressed, spoiled, ill-treated, exiled,
enslaved; namely, as an age of bronze, as I have said, hard, cold,
terrible, without feelings and without conscience, crushing everything,
and bespattering everything with blood. Granted the truth of the theory
now believed to be true, that the very essence of all civilisation is to
train out of man, the beast of prey, a tame and civilised animal, a
domesticated animal, it follows indubitably that we must regard as the
real tools of civilisation all those instincts of reaction and
resentment, by the help of which the aristocratic races, together with
their ideals, were finally degraded and overpowered; though that has not
yet come to be synonymous with saying that the bearers of those tools
also represented the civilisation. It is rather the contrary that is not
only probableânay, it is palpable to-day; these bearers of vindictive
instincts that have to be bottled up, these descendants of all European
and non-European slavery, especially of the pre-Aryan populationâthese
people, I say, represent the decline of humanity! These âtools of
civilisationâ are a disgrace to humanity, and constitute in reality more
of an argument against civilisation, more of a reason why civilisation
should be suspected. One may be perfectly justified in being always
afraid of the blonde beast that lies at the core of all aristocratic
races, and in being on oneâs guard: but who would not a hundred times
prefer to be afraid, when one at the same time admires, than to be
immune from fear, at the cost of being perpetually obsessed with the
loathsome spectacle of the distorted, the dwarfed, the stunted, the
envenomed? And is that not our fate? What produces to-day our repulsion
towards âmanâ?âfor we suffer from âman,â there is no doubt about it. It
is not fear; it is rather that we have nothing more to fear from men; it
is that the worm âmanâ is in the foreground and pullulates; it is that
the âtame man,â the wretched mediocre and unedifying creature, has
learnt to consider himself a goal and a pinnacle, an inner meaning, an
historic principle, a âhigher manâ; yes, it is that he has a certain
right so to consider himself, in so far as he feels that in contrast to
that excess of deformity, disease, exhaustion, and effeteness whose
odour is beginning to pollute present-day Europe, he at any rate has
achieved a relative success, he at any rate still says âyesâ to life.
12.
I cannot refrain at this juncture from uttering a sigh and one last
hope. What is it precisely which I find intolerable? That which I alone
cannot get rid of, which makes me choke and faint? Bad air! bad air!
That something misbegotten comes near me; that I must inhale the odour
of the entrails of a misbegotten soul!âThat excepted, what can one not
endure in the way of need, privation, bad weather, sickness, toil,
solitude? In point of fact, one manages to get over everything, born as
one is to a burrowing and battling existence; one always returns once
again to the light, one always lives again oneâs golden hour of
victoryâand then one stands as one was born, unbreakable, tense, ready
for something more difficult, for something more distant, like a bow
stretched but the tauter by every strain. But from time to time do ye
grant meâassuming that âbeyond good and evilâ there are goddesses who
can grantâone glimpse, grant me but one glimpse only, of something
perfect, fully realised, happy, mighty, triumphant, of something that
still gives cause for fear! A glimpse of a man that justifies the
existence of man, a glimpse of an incarnate human happiness that
realises and redeems, for the sake of which one may hold fast to the
belief in man! For the position is this: in the dwarfing and levelling
of the European man lurks our greatest peril, for it is this outlook
which fatiguesâwe see to-day nothing which wishes to be greater, we
surmise that the process is always still backwards, still backwards
towards something more attenuated, more inoffensive, more cunning, more
comfortable, more mediocre, more indifferent, more Chinese, more
Christianâman, there is no doubt about it, grows always âbetterâ âthe
destiny of Europe lies even in thisâthat in losing the fear of man, we
have also lost the hope in man, yea, the will to be man. The sight of
man now fatigues.âWhat is present-day Nihilism if it is not that?âWe are
tired of man.
13.
But let us come back to it; the problem of another origin of the goodâof
the good, as the resentful man has thought it outâdemands its solution.
It is not surprising that the lambs should bear a grudge against the
great birds of prey, but that is no reason for blaming the great birds
of prey for taking the little lambs. And when the lambs say among
themselves, âThese birds of prey are evil, and he who is as far removed
from being a bird of prey, who is rather its opposite, a lamb,âis he not
good?â then there is nothing to cavil at in the setting up of this
ideal, though it may also be that the birds of prey will regard it a
little sneeringly, and perchance say to themselves, âWe bear no grudge
against them, these good lambs, we even like them: nothing is tastier
than a tender lamb.â To require of strength that it should not express
itself as strength, that it should not be a wish to overpower, a wish to
overthrow, a wish to become master, a thirst for enemies and antagonisms
and triumphs, is just as absurd as to require of weakness that it should
express itself as strength. A quantum of force is just such a quantum of
movement, will, actionârather it is nothing else than just those very
phenomena of moving, willing, acting, and can only appear otherwise in
the misleading errors of language (and the fundamental fallacies of
reason which have become petrified therein), which understands, and
understands wrongly, all working as conditioned by a worker, by a
âsubject.â And just exactly as the people separate the lightning from
its flash, and interpret the latter as a thing done, as the working of a
subject which is called lightning, so also does the popular morality
separate strength from the expression of strength, as though behind the
strong man there existed some indifferent neutral substratum, which
enjoyed a caprice and option as to whether or not it should express
strength. But there is no such substratum, there is no âbeingâ behind
doing, working, becoming; âthe doerâ is a mere appanage to the action.
The action is everything. In point of fact, the people duplicate the
doing, when they make the lightning lighten, that is a âdoing-doingâ:
they make the same phenomenon first a cause, and then, secondly, the
effect of that cause. The scientists fail to improve matters when they
say, âForce moves, force causes,â and so on. Our whole science is still,
in spite of all its coldness, of all its freedom from passion, a dupe of
the tricks of language, and has never succeeded in getting rid of that
superstitious changeling âthe subjectâ (the atom, to give another
instance, is such a changeling, just as the Kantian âThing-in-itselfâ).
What wonder, if the suppressed and stealthily simmering passions of
revenge and hatred exploit for their own advantage this belief, and
indeed hold no belief with a more steadfast enthusiasm than thisââthat
the strong has the option of being weak, and the bird of prey of being a
lamb.â Thereby do they win for themselves the right of attributing to
the birds of prey the responsibility for being birds of prey: when the
oppressed, down-trodden, and overpowered say to themselves with the
vindictive guile of weakness, âLet us be otherwise than the evil,
namely, good! and good is every one who does not oppress, who hurts no
one, who does not attack, who does not pay back, who hands over revenge
to God, who holds himself, as we do, in hiding; who goes out of the way
of evil, and demands, in short, little from life; like ourselves the
patient, the meek, the just,ââyet all this, in its cold and unprejudiced
interpretation, means nothing more than âonce for all, the weak are
weak; it is good to do nothing for which we are not strong enoughâ; but
this dismal state of affairs, this prudence of the lowest order, which
even insects possess (which in a great danger are fain to sham death so
as to avoid doing âtoo muchâ), has, thanks to the counterfeiting and
self-deception of weakness, come to masquerade in the pomp of an
ascetic, mute, and expectant virtue, just as though the very weakness of
the weakâthat is, forsooth, its being, its working, its whole unique
inevitable inseparable realityâwere a voluntary result, something
wished, chosen, a deed, an act of merit. This kind of man finds the
belief in a neutral, free-choosing âsubjectâ necessary from an instinct
of self-preservation, of self-assertion, in which every lie is fain to
sanctify itself. The subject (or, to use popular language, the soul) has
perhaps proved itself the best dogma in the world simply because it
rendered possible to the horde of mortal, weak, and oppressed
individuals of every kind, that most sublime specimen of self-deception,
the interpretation of weakness as freedom, of being this, or being that,
as merit.
14.
Will any one look a little intoâright intoâthe mystery of how ideals are
manufactured in this world? Who has the courage to do it? Come!
Here we have a vista opened into these grimy workshops. Wait just a
moment, dear Mr. Inquisitive and Foolhardy; your eye must first grow
accustomed to this false changing lightâYes! Enough! Now speak! What is
happening below down yonder? Speak out that what you see, man of the
most dangerous curiosityâfor now I am the listener.
âI see nothing, I hear the more. It is a cautious, spiteful, gentle
whispering and muttering together in all the corners and crannies. It
seems to me that they are lying; a sugary softness adheres to every
sound. Weakness is turned to merit, there is no doubt about itâit is
just as you say.â
Further!
âAnd the impotence which requites not, is turned to âgoodness,â craven
baseness to meekness, submission to those whom one hates, to obedience
(namely, obedience to one of whom they say that he ordered this
submissionâthey call him God). The inoffensive character of the weak,
the very cowardice in which he is rich, his standing at the door, his
forced necessity of waiting, gain here fine names, such as âpatience,â
which is also called âvirtueâ; not being able to avenge oneâs self, is
called not wishing to avenge oneâs self, perhaps even forgiveness (for
they know not what they doâwe alone know what they do). They also talk
of the âlove of their enemiesâ and sweat thereby.â
Further!
âThey are miserable, there is no doubt about it, all these whisperers
and counterfeiters in the corners, although they try to get warm by
crouching close to each other, but they tell me that their misery is a
favour and distinction given to them by God, just as one beats the dogs
one likes best; that perhaps this misery is also a preparation, a
probation, a training; that perhaps it is still more something which
will one day be compensated and paid back with a tremendous interest in
gold, nay in happiness. This they call âBlessedness.ââ
Further!
âThey are now giving me to understand, that not only are they better men
than the mighty, the lords of the earth, whose spittle they have got to
lick (not out of fear, not at all out of fear! But because God ordains
that one should honour all authority)ânot only are they better men, but
that they also have a âbetter time,â at any rate, will one day have a
âbetter time.â But enough! Enough! I can endure it no longer. Bad air!
Bad air! These workshops where ideals are manufacturedâverily they reek
with the crassest lies.â
Nay. Just one minute! You are saying nothing about the masterpieces of
these virtuosos of black magic, who can produce whiteness, milk, and
innocence out of any black you like: have you not noticed what a pitch
of refinement is attained by their chef dâĆuvre, their most audacious,
subtle, ingenious, and lying artist-trick? Take care! These
cellar-beasts, full of revenge and hateâwhat do they make, forsooth, out
of their revenge and hate? Do you hear these words? Would you suspect,
if you trusted only their words, that you are among men of resentment
and nothing else?
âI understand, I prick my ears up again (ah! ah! ah! and I hold my
nose). Now do I hear for the first time that which they have said so
often: âWe good, we are the righteousââwhat they demand they call not
revenge but âthe triumph of righteousnessâ; what they hate is not their
enemy, no, they hate âunrighteousness,â âgodlessnessâ; what they believe
in and hope is not the hope of revenge, the intoxication of sweet
revenge (ââsweeter than honey,â did Homer call it?), but the victory of
God, of the righteous God over the âgodlessâ; what is left for them to
love in this world is not their brothers in hate, but their âbrothers in
love,â as they say, all the good and righteous on the earth.â
And how do they name that which serves them as a solace against all the
troubles of lifeâtheir phantasmagoria of their anticipated future
blessedness?
âHow? Do I hear right? They call it âthe last judgment,â the advent of
their kingdom, âthe kingdom of Godââbut in the meanwhile they live âin
faith,â âin love,â âin hope.ââ
Enough! Enough!
15.
In the faith in what? In the love for what? In the hope of what? These
weaklings!âthey also, forsooth, wish to be the strong some time; there
is no doubt about it, some time their kingdom also must comeââthe
kingdom of Godâ is their name for it, as has been mentioned: they are so
meek in everything! Yet in order to experience that kingdom it is
necessary to live long, to live beyond death,âyes, eternal life is
necessary so that one can make up for ever for that earthly life âin
faith,â âin love,â âin hope.â Make up for what? Make up by what? Dante,
as it seems to me, made a crass mistake when with awe-inspiring
ingenuity he placed that inscription over the gate of his hell, âMe too
made eternal loveâ: at any rate the following inscription would have a
much better right to stand over the gate of the Christian Paradise and
its âeternal blessednessâââMe too made eternal hateââgranted of course
that a truth may rightly stand over the gate to a lie! For what is the
blessedness of that Paradise? Possibly we could quickly surmise it; but
it is better that it should be explicitly attested by an authority who
in such matters is not to be disparaged, Thomas of Aquinas, the great
teacher and saint. âBeati in regno celestiâ says he, as gently as a
lamb, âvidebunt pĆnas damnatorum, ut beatitudo illis magis complaceat.â
Or if we wish to hear a stronger tone, a word from the mouth of a
triumphant father of the Church, who warned his disciples against the
cruel ecstasies of the public spectaclesâBut why? Faith offers us much
more,âsays he, de Spectac., c. 29 ss.,âsomething much stronger; thanks
to the redemption, joys of quite another kind stand at our disposal;
instead of athletes we have our martyrs; we wish for blood, well, we
have the blood of Christâbut what then awaits us on the day of his
return, of his triumph. And then does he proceed, does this enraptured
visionary: âat enim supersunt alia spectacula, ille ultimas et perpetuus
judicii dies, ille nationibus insperatus, ille derisus, cum tanta sĂŠculi
vetustas et tot ejus nativitates uno igne haurientur. QuĂŠ tunc
spectaculi latitudo! Quid admirer! quid rideam! Ubigaudeam! Ubi exultem,
spectans tot et tantos reges, qui in cĆlum recepti nuntiabantur, cum
ipso Jove et ipsis suis testibus in imis tenebris congemescentes! Item
prĂŠsidesâ (the provincial governors) âpersecutores dominici nominis
sĂŠvioribus quam ipsi flammis sĂŠvierunt insultantibus contra Christianos
liquescentes! Quos prĂŠterea sapientes illos philosophos coram discipulis
suis una conflagrantibus erubescentes, quibus nihil ad deum pertinere
suadebant, quibus animas aut nullas aut non in pristina corpora
redituras affirmabant! Etiam poetas non ad Rhadamanti nec ad Minois, sed
ad inopinati Christi tribunal palpitantes! Tunc magis tragĆdi audiendi,
magis scilicet vocalesâ (with louder tones and more violent shrieks) âin
sua propria calamitate; tunc histriones cognoscendi, solutiores multo
per ignem; tunc spectandus auriga in flammea rota totus rubens, tunc
xystici contemplandi non in gymnasiis, sed in igne jaculati, nisi quod
ne tunc quidem illos velim vivos, ut qui malim ad eos potius conspectum
insatiabilem conferre, qui in dominum scevierunt. Hic est ille, dicam
fabri aut quĂŠstuariĂŠ filiusâ (as is shown by the whole of the following,
and in particular by this well-known description of the mother of Jesus
from the Talmud, Tertullian is henceforth referring to the Jews),
âsabbati destructor, Samarites et dĂŠmonium habens. Hic est quem a Juda
redemistis, hic est ille arundine et colaphis diverberatus, sputamentis
de decoratus, felle et acete potatus. Hic est, quem clam discentes
subripuerunt, ut resurrexisse dicatur vel hortulanus detraxit, ne
lactucĂŠ suĂŠ frequentia commeantium laderentur. Ut talia species, ut
talibus exultes, quis tibi prĂŠtor aut consul aut sacerdos de sua
liberalitate prastabit? Et tamen hĂŠc jam habemus quodammodo per fidem
spiritu imaginante reprĂŠsentata. Ceterum qualia illa sunt, quĂŠ nec
oculus vidit nec auris audivit nec in cor hominis ascenderunt?â (I Cor.
ii. 9.) âCredo circo et utraque caveaâ (first and fourth row, or,
according to others, the comic and the tragic stage) âet omni studio
gratiora.â Per fidem: so stands it written.
16.
Let us come to a conclusion. The two opposing values, âgood and bad,â
âgood and evil,â have fought a dreadful, thousand-year fight in the
world, and though indubitably the second value has been for a long time
in the preponderance, there are not wanting places where the fortune of
the fight is still undecisive. It can almost be said that in the
meanwhile the fight reaches a higher and higher level, and that in the
meanwhile it has become more and more intense, and always more and more
psychological; so that nowadays there is perhaps no more decisive mark
of the higher nature, of the more psychological nature, than to be in
that sense self-contradictory, and to be actually still a battleground
for those two opposites. The symbol of this fight, written in a writing
which has remained worthy of perusal throughout the course of history up
to the present time, is called âRome against JudĂŠa, JudĂŠa against Rome.â
Hitherto there has been no greater event than that fight, the putting of
that question, that deadly antagonism. Rome found in the Jew the
incarnation of the unnatural, as though it were its diametrically
opposed monstrosity, and in Rome the Jew was held to be convicted of
hatred of the whole human race: and rightly so, in so far as it is right
to link the well-being and the future of the human race to the
unconditional mastery of the aristocratic values, of the Roman values.
What, conversely, did the Jews feel against Rome? One can surmise it
from a thousand symptoms, but it is sufficient to carry oneâs mind back
to the Johannian Apocalypse, that most obscene of all the written
outbursts, which has revenge on its conscience. (One should also
appraise at its full value the profound logic of the Christian instinct,
when over this very book of hate it wrote the name of the Disciple of
Love, that self-same disciple to whom it attributed that impassioned and
ecstatic Gospelâtherein lurks a portion of truth, however much literary
forging may have been necessary for this purpose.) The Romans were the
strong and aristocratic; a nation stronger and more aristocratic has
never existed in the world, has never even been dreamed of; every relic
of them, every inscription enraptures, granted that one can divine what
it is that writes the inscription. The Jews, conversely, were that
priestly nation of resentment par excellence, possessed by a unique
genius for popular morals: just compare with the Jews the nations with
analogous gifts, such as the Chinese or the Germans, so as to realise
afterwards what is first rate, and what is fifth rate.
Which of them has been provisionally victorious, Rome or JudĂŠa? but
there is not a shadow of doubt; just consider to whom in Rome itself
nowadays you bow down, as though before the quintessence of all the
highest valuesâand not only in Rome, but almost over half the world,
everywhere where man has been tamed or is about to be tamedâto three
Jews, as we know, and one Jewess (to Jesus of Nazareth, to Peter the
fisher, to Paul the tent-maker, and to the mother of the aforesaid
Jesus, named Mary). This is very remarkable: Rome is undoubtedly
defeated. At any rate there took place in the Renaissance a brilliantly
sinister revival of the classical ideal, of the aristocratic valuation
of all things: Rome herself, like a man waking up from a trance, stirred
beneath the burden of the new Judaised Rome that had been built over
her, which presented the appearance of an Ćcumenical synagogue and was
called the âChurchâ: but immediately JudĂŠa triumphed again, thanks to
that fundamentally popular (German and English) movement of revenge,
which is called the Reformation, and taking also into account its
inevitable corollary, the restoration of the Churchâthe restoration also
of the ancient graveyard peace of classical Rome. JudĂŠa proved yet once
more victorious over the classical ideal in the French Revolution, and
in a sense which was even more crucial and even more profound: the last
political aristocracy that existed in Europe, that of the French
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, broke into pieces beneath the
instincts of a resentful populaceânever had the world heard a greater
jubilation, a more uproarious enthusiasm: indeed, there took place in
the midst of it the most monstrous and unexpected phenomenon; the
ancient ideal itself swept before the eyes and conscience of humanity
with all its life and with unheard-of splendour, and in opposition to
resentmentâs lying war-cry of the prerogative of the most, in opposition
to the will to lowliness, abasement, and equalisation, the will to a
retrogression and twilight of humanity, there rang out once again,
stronger, simpler, more penetrating than ever, the terrible and
enchanting counter-warcry of the prerogative of the few! Like a final
signpost to other ways, there appeared Napoleon, the most unique and
violent anachronism that ever existed, and in him the incarnate problem
of the aristocratic ideal in itselfâconsider well what a problem it
is:âNapoleon, that synthesis of Monster and Superman.
17.
Was it therewith over? Was that greatest of all antitheses of ideals
thereby relegated ad acta for all time? Or only postponed, postponed for
a long time? May there not take place at some time or other a much more
awful, much more carefully prepared flaring up of the old conflagration?
Further! Should not one wish that consummation with all oneâs
strength?âwill it oneâs self? demand it oneâs self? He who at this
juncture begins, like my readers, to reflect, to think further, will
have difficulty in coming quickly to a conclusion,âground enough for me
to come myself to a conclusion, taking it for granted that for some time
past what I mean has been sufficiently clear, what I exactly mean by
that dangerous motto which is inscribed on the body of my last book:
Beyond Good and Evilâat any rate that is not the same as âBeyond Good
and Bad.â
Note.âI avail myself of the opportunity offered by this treatise to
express, openly and formally, a wish which up to the present has only
been expressed in occasional conversations with scholars, namely, that
some Faculty of philosophy should, by means of a series of prize essays,
gain the glory of having promoted the further study of the history of
moralsâperhaps this book may serve to give forcible impetus in such a
direction. With regard to a possibility of this character, the following
question deserves consideration. It merits quite as much the attention
of philologists and historians as of actual professional philosophers.
âWhat indication of the history of the evolution of the moral ideas is
afforded by philology, and especially by etymological investigation?â
On the other hand, it is of course equally necessary to induce
physiologists and doctors to be interested in these problems (of the
value of the valuations which have prevailed up to the present): in this
connection the professional philosophers may be trusted to act as the
spokesmen and intermediaries in these particular instances, after, of
course, they have quite succeeded in transforming the relationship
between philosophy and physiology and medicine, which is originally one
of coldness and suspicion, into the most friendly and fruitful
reciprocity. In point of fact, all tables of values, all the âthou
shaltsâ known to history and ethnology, need primarily a physiological,
at any rate in preference to a psychological, elucidation and
interpretation; all equally require a critique from medical science. The
question, âWhat is the value of this or that table of âvaluesâ and
morality?â will be asked from the most varied standpoints. For instance,
the question of âvaluable for whatâ can never be analysed with
sufficient nicety. That, for instance, which would evidently have value
with regard to promoting in a race the greatest possible powers of
endurance (or with regard to increasing its adaptability to a specific
climate, or with regard to the preservation of the greatest number)
would have nothing like the same value, if it were a question of
evolving a stronger species. In gauging values, the good of the majority
and the good of the minority are opposed standpoints: we leave it to the
naïveté of English biologists to regard the former standpoint as
intrinsically superior. All the sciences have now to pave the way for
the future task of the philosopher; this task being understood to mean,
that he must solve the problem of value, that he has to fix the
hierarchy of values.
1.
The breeding of an animal that can promiseâis not this just that very
paradox of a task which nature has set itself in regard to man? Is not
this the very problem of man? The fact that this problem has been to a
great extent solved, must appear all the more phenomenal to one who can
estimate at its full value that force of forgetfulness which works in
opposition to it. Forgetfulness is no mere vis inertiĂŠ, as the
superficial believe, rather is it a power of obstruction, active and, in
the strictest sense of the word, positiveâa power responsible for the
fact that what we have lived, experienced, taken into ourselves, no more
enters into consciousness during the process of digestion (it might be
called psychic absorption) than all the whole manifold process by which
our physical nutrition, the so-called âincorporation,â is carried on.
The temporary shutting of the doors and windows of consciousness, the
relief from the clamant alarums and excursions, with which our
subconscious world of servant organs works in mutual co-operation and
antagonism; a little quietude, a little tabula rasa of the
consciousness, so as to make room again for the new, and above all for
the more noble functions and functionaries, room for government,
foresight, predetermination (for our organism is on an oligarchic
model)âthis is the utility, as I have said, of the active forgetfulness,
which is a very sentinel and nurse of psychic order, repose, etiquette;
and this shows at once why it is that there can exist no happiness, no
gladness, no hope, no pride, no real present, without forgetfulness. The
man in whom this preventative apparatus is damaged and discarded, is to
be compared to a dyspeptic, and it is something more than a
comparisonâhe can âget rid ofâ nothing. But this very animal who finds
it necessary to be forgetful, in whom, in fact, forgetfulness represents
a force and a form of robust health, has reared for himself an
opposition-power, a memory, with whose help forgetfulness is, in certain
instances, kept in checkâin the cases, namely, where promises have to be
made;âso that it is by no means a mere passive inability to get rid of a
once indented impression, not merely the indigestion occasioned by a
once pledged word, which one cannot dispose of, but an active refusal to
get rid of it, a continuing and a wish to continue what has once been
willed, an actual memory of the will; so that between the original âI
will,â âI shall do,â and the actual discharge of the will, its act, we
can easily interpose a world of new strange phenomena, circumstances,
veritable volitions, without the snapping of this long chain of the
will. But what is the underlying hypothesis of all this? How thoroughly,
in order to be able to regulate the future in this way, must man have
first learnt to distinguish between necessitated and accidental
phenomena, to think causally, to see the distant as present and to
anticipate it, to fix with certainty what is the end, and what is the
means to that end; above all, to reckon, to have power to calculateâhow
thoroughly must man have first become calculable, disciplined,
necessitated even for himself and his own conception of himself, that,
like a man entering into a promise, he could guarantee himself as a
future.
2.
This is simply the long history of the origin of responsibility. That
task of breeding an animal which can make promises, includes, as we have
already grasped, as its condition and preliminary, the more immediate
task of first making man to a certain extent, necessitated, uniform,
like among his like, regular, and consequently calculable. The immense
work of what I have called, âmorality of customâ[1] (cp. Dawn of Day,
Aphs. 9, 14, and 16), the actual work of man on himself during the
longest period of the human race, his whole prehistoric work, finds its
meaning, its great justification (in spite of all its innate hardness,
despotism, stupidity, and idiocy) in this fact: man, with the help of
the morality of customs and of social strait-waistcoats, was made
genuinely calculable. If, however, we place ourselves at the end of this
colossal process, at the point where the tree finally matures its
fruits, when society and its morality of custom finally bring to light
that to which it was only the means, then do we find as the ripest fruit
on its tree the sovereign individual, that resembles only himself, that
has got loose from the morality of custom, the autonomous âsuper-moralâ
individual (for âautonomousâ and âmoralâ are mutually-exclusive
terms),âin short, the man of the personal, long, and independent will,
competent to promise, and we find in him a proud consciousness
(vibrating in every fibre), of what has been at last achieved and become
vivified in him, a genuine consciousness of power and freedom, a feeling
of human perfection in general. And this man who has grown to freedom,
who is really competent to promise, this lord of the free will, this
sovereignâhow is it possible for him not to know how great is his
superiority over everything incapable of binding itself by promises, or
of being its own security, how great is the trust, the awe, the
reverence that he awakesâhe âdeservesâ all threeânot to know that with
this mastery over himself he is necessarily also given the mastery over
circumstances, over nature, over all creatures with shorter wills, less
reliable characters? The âfreeâ man, the owner of a long unbreakable
will, finds in this possession his standard of value: looking out from
himself upon the others, he honours or he despises, and just as
necessarily as he honours his peers, the strong and the reliable (those
who can bind themselves by promises),âthat is, every one who promises
like a sovereign, with difficulty, rarely and slowly, who is sparing
with his trusts but confers honour by the very fact of trusting, who
gives his word as something that can be relied on, because he knows
himself strong enough to keep it even in the teeth of disasters, even in
the âteeth of fate,ââso with equal necessity will he have the heel of
his foot ready for the lean and empty jackasses, who promise when they
have no business to do so, and his rod of chastisement ready for the
liar, who already breaks his word at the very minute when it is on his
lips. The proud knowledge of the extraordinary privilege of
responsibility, the consciousness of this rare freedom, of this power
over himself and over fate, has sunk right down to his innermost depths,
and has become an instinct, a dominating instinctâwhat name will he give
to it, to this dominating instinct, if he needs to have a word for it?
But there is no doubt about itâthe sovereign man calls it his
conscience.
3.
His conscience?âOne apprehends at once that the idea âconscience,â which
is here seen in its supreme manifestation, supreme in fact to almost the
point of strangeness, should already have behind it a long history and
evolution. The ability to guarantee oneâs self with all due pride, and
also at the same time to say yes to oneâs selfâthat is, as has been
said, a ripe fruit, but also a late fruit:âHow long must needs this
fruit hang sour and bitter on the tree! And for an even longer period
there was not a glimpse of such a fruit to to be hadâno one had taken it
on himself to promise it, although everything on the tree was quite
ready for it, and everything was maturing for that very consummation.
âHow is a memory to be made for the man-animal? How is an impression to
be so deeply fixed upon this ephemeral understanding, half dense, and
half silly, upon this incarnate forgetfulness, that it will be
permanently present?â As one may imagine, this primeval problem was not
solved by exactly gentle answers and gentle means; perhaps there is
nothing more awful and more sinister in the early history of man than
his system of mnemonics. âSomething is burnt in so as to remain in his
memory: only that which never stops hurting remains in his memory.â This
is an axiom of the oldest (unfortunately also the longest) psychology in
the world. It might even be said that wherever solemnity, seriousness,
mystery, and gloomy colours are now found in the life of the men and of
nations of the world, there is some survival of that horror which was
once the universal concomitant of all promises, pledges, and
obligations. The past, the past with all its length, depth, and
hardness, wafts to us its breath, and bubbles up in us again, when we
become âserious.â When man thinks it necessary to make for himself a
memory, he never accomplishes it without blood, tortures, and sacrifice;
the most dreadful sacrifices and forfeitures (among them the sacrifice
of the first-born), the most loathsome mutilation (for instance,
castration), the most cruel rituals of all the religious cults (for all
religions are really at bottom systems of cruelty)âall these things
originate from that instinct which found in pain its most potent
mnemonic. In a certain sense the whole of asceticism is to be ascribed
to this: certain ideas have got to be made inextinguishable,
omnipresent, âfixed,â with the object of hypnotising the whole nervous
and intellectual system through these âfixed ideasââand the ascetic
methods and modes of life are the means of freeing those ideas from the
competition of all other ideas so as to make them âunforgettable.â The
worse memory man had, the ghastlier the signs presented by his customs;
the severity of the penal laws affords in particular a gauge of the
extent of manâs difficulty in conquering forgetfulness, and in keeping a
few primal postulates of social intercourse ever present to the minds of
those who were the slaves of every momentary emotion and every momentary
desire. We Germans do certainly not regard ourselves as an especially
cruel and hard-hearted nation, still less as an especially casual and
happy-go-lucky one; but one has only to look at our old penal ordinances
in order to realise what a lot of trouble it takes in the world to
evolve a ânation of thinkersâ (I mean: the European nation which
exhibits at this very day the maximum of reliability, seriousness, bad
taste, and positiveness, which has on the strength of these qualities a
right to train every kind of European mandarin). These Germans employed
terrible means to make for themselves a memory, to enable them to master
their rooted plebeian instincts and the brutal crudity of those
instincts: think of the old German punishments, for instance, stoning
(as far back as the legend, the millstone falls on the head of the
guilty man), breaking on the wheel (the most original invention and
speciality of the German genius in the sphere of punishment),
dart-throwing, tearing, or trampling by horses (âquarteringâ), boiling
the criminal in oil or wine (still prevalent in the fourteenth and
fifteenth centuries), the highly popular flaying (âslicing into
stripsâ), cutting the flesh out of the breast; think also of the
evil-doer being besmeared with honey, and then exposed to the flies in a
blazing sun. It was by the help of such images and precedents that man
eventually kept in his memory five or six âI will notsâ with regard to
which he had already given his promise, so as to be able to enjoy the
advantages of societyâand verily with the help of this kind of memory
man eventually attained âreasonâ! Alas! reason, seriousness, mastery
over the emotions, all these gloomy, dismal things which are called
reflection, all these privileges and pageantries of humanity: how dear
is the price that they have exacted! How much blood and cruelty is the
foundation of all âgood thingsâ!
4.
But how is it that that other melancholy object, the consciousness of
sin, the whole âbad conscience,â came into the world? And it is here
that we turn back to our genealogists of morals. For the second time I
sayâor have I not said it yet?âthat they are worth nothing. Just their
own five-spans-long limited modern experience; no knowledge of the past,
and no wish to know it; still less a historic instinct, a power of
âsecond sightâ (which is what is really required in this case)âand
despite this to go in for the history of morals. It stands to reason
that this must needs produce results which are removed from the truth by
something more than a respectful distance.
Have these current genealogists of morals ever allowed themselves to
have even the vaguest notion, for instance, that the cardinal moral idea
of âoughtâ[2] originates from the very material idea of âoweâ? Or that
punishment developed as a retaliation absolutely independently of any
preliminary hypothesis of the freedom or determination of the will?âAnd
this to such an extent, that a high degree of civilisation was always
first necessary for the animal man to begin to make those much more
primitive distinctions of âintentional,â ânegligent,â âaccidental,â
âresponsible,â and their contraries, and apply them in the assessing of
punishment. That ideaââthe wrong-doer deserves punishment because he
might have acted otherwise,â in spite of the fact that it is nowadays so
cheap, obvious, natural, and inevitable, and that it has had to serve as
an illustration of the way in which the sentiment of justice appeared on
earth, is in point of fact an exceedingly late, and even refined form of
human judgment and inference; the placing of this idea back at the
beginning of the world is simply a clumsy violation of the principles of
primitive psychology. Throughout the longest period of human history
punishment was never based on the responsibility of the evil-doer for
his action, and was consequently not based on the hypothesis that only
the guilty should be punished;âon the contrary, punishment was inflicted
in those days for the same reason that parents punish their children
even nowadays, out of anger at an injury that they have suffered, an
anger which vents itself mechanically on the author of the injuryâbut
this anger is kept in bounds and modified through the idea that every
injury has somewhere or other its equivalent price, and can really be
paid off, even though it be by means of pain to the author. Whence is it
that this ancient deep-rooted and now perhaps ineradicable idea has
drawn its strength, this idea of an equivalency between injury and pain?
I have already revealed its origin, in the contractual relationship
between creditor and ower, that is as old as the existence of legal
rights at all, and in its turn points back to the primary forms of
purchase, sale, barter, and trade.
5.
The realisation of these contractual relations excites, of course (as
would be already expected from our previous observations), a great deal
of suspicion and opposition towards the primitive society which made or
sanctioned them. In this society promises will be made; in this society
the object is to provide the promiser with a memory; in this society, so
may we suspect, there will be full scope for hardness, cruelty, and
pain: the âower,â in order to induce credit in his promise of repayment,
in order to give a guarantee of the earnestness and sanctity of his
promise, in order to drill into his own conscience the duty, the solemn
duty, of repayment, will, by virtue of a contract with his creditor to
meet the contingency of his not paying, pledge something that he still
possesses, something that he still has in his power, for instance, his
life or his wife, or his freedom or his body (or under certain religious
conditions even his salvation, his soulâs welfare, even his peace in the
grave; so in Egypt, where the corpse of the ower found even in the grave
no rest from the creditorâof course, from the Egyptian standpoint, this
peace was a matter of particular importance). But especially has the
creditor the power of inflicting on the body of the ower all kinds of
pain and tortureâthe power, for instance, of cutting off from it an
amount that appeared proportionate to the greatness of the debt;âthis
point of view resulted in the universal prevalence at an early date of
precise schemes of valuation, frequently horrible in the minuteness and
meticulosity of their application, legally sanctioned schemes of
valuation for individual limbs and parts of the body. I consider it as
already a progress, as a proof of a freer, less petty, and more Roman
conception of law, when the Roman Code of the Twelve Tables decreed that
it was immaterial how much or how little the creditors in such a
contingency cut off, âsi plus minusve secuerunt, ne fraude esto.â Let us
make the logic of the whole of this equalisation process clear; it is
strange enough. The equivalence consists in this: instead of an
advantage directly compensatory of his injury (that is, instead of an
equalisation in money, lands, or some kind of chattel), the creditor is
granted by way of repayment and compensation a certain sensation of
satisfactionâthe satisfaction of being able to vent, without any
trouble, his power on one who is powerless, the delight âde faire le mal
pour le plaisir de le faire,â the joy in sheer violence: and this joy
will be relished in proportion to the lowness and humbleness of the
creditor in the social scale, and is quite apt to have the effect of the
most delicious dainty, and even seem the foretaste of a higher social
position. Thanks to the punishment of the âower,â the creditor
participates in the rights of the masters. At last he too, for once in a
way, attains the edifying consciousness of being able to despise and
ill-treat a creatureâas an âinferiorââor at any rate of seeing him being
despised and ill-treated, in case the actual power of punishment, the
administration of punishment, has already become transferred to the
âauthorities.â The compensation consequently consists in a claim on
cruelty and a right to draw thereon.
6.
It is then in this sphere of the law of contract that we find the cradle
of the whole moral world of the ideas of âguilt,â âconscience,â âduty,â
the âsacredness of duty,ââtheir commencement, like the commencement of
all great things in the world, is thoroughly and continuously saturated
with blood. And should we not add that this world has never really lost
a certain savour of blood and torture (not even in old Kant; the
categorical imperative reeks of cruelty). It was in this sphere likewise
that there first became formed that sinister and perhaps now
indissoluble association of the ideas of âguiltâ and âsuffering.â To put
the question yet again, why can suffering be a compensation for
âowingâ?âBecause the infliction of suffering produces the highest degree
of happiness, because the injured party will get in exchange for his
loss (including his vexation at his loss) an extraordinary
counter-pleasure: the infliction of sufferingâa real feast, something
that, as I have said, was all the more appreciated the greater the
paradox created by the rank and social status of the creditor. These
observations are purely conjectural; for, apart from the painful nature
of the task, it is hard to plumb such profound depths: the clumsy
introduction of the idea of ârevengeâ as a connecting-link simply hides
and obscures the view instead of rendering it clearer (revenge itself
simply leads back again to the identical problemââHow can the infliction
of suffering be a satisfaction?â). In my opinion it is repugnant to the
delicacy, and still more to the hypocrisy of tame domestic animals (that
is, modern men; that is, ourselves), to realise with all their energy
the extent to which cruelty constituted the great joy and delight of
ancient man, was an ingredient which seasoned nearly all his pleasures,
and conversely the extent of the naïveté and innocence with which he
manifested his need for cruelty, when he actually made as a matter of
principle âdisinterested maliceâ (or, to use Spinozaâs expression, the
sympathia malevolens) into a normal characteristic of manâas
consequently something to which the conscience says a hearty yes. The
more profound observer has perhaps already had sufficient opportunity
for noticing this most ancient and radical joy and delight of mankind;
in Beyond Good and Evil, Aph. 188 (and even earlier, in The Dawn of Day,
Aphs. 18, 77, 113), I have cautiously indicated the continually growing
spiritualisation and âdeificationâ of cruelty, which pervades the whole
history of the higher civilisation (and in the larger sense even
constitutes it). At any rate the time is not so long past when it was
impossible to conceive of royal weddings and national festivals on a
grand scale, without executions, tortures, or perhaps an auto-da-fĂ©â, or
similarly to conceive of an aristocratic household, without a creature
to serve as a butt for the cruel and malicious baiting of the inmates.
(The reader will perhaps remember Don Quixote at the court of the
Duchess: we read nowadays the whole of Don Quixote with a bitter taste
in the mouth, almost with a sensation of torture, a fact which would
appear very strange and very incomprehensible to the author and his
contemporariesâthey read it with the best conscience in the world as the
gayest of books; they almost died with laughing at it.) The sight of
suffering does one good, the infliction of suffering does one more
goodâthis is a hard maxim, but none the less a fundamental maxim, old,
powerful, and âhuman, all-too-humanâ; one, moreover, to which perhaps
even the apes as well would subscribe: for it is said that in inventing
bizarre cruelties they are giving abundant proof of their future
humanity, to which, as it were, they are playing the prelude. Without
cruelty, no feast: so teaches the oldest and longest history of manâand
in punishment too is there so much of the festive.
7.
Entertaining, as I do, these thoughts, I am, let me say in parenthesis,
fundamentally opposed to helping our pessimists to new water for the
discordant and groaning mills of their disgust with life; on the
contrary, it should be shown specifically that, at the time when mankind
was not yet ashamed of its cruelty, life in the world was brighter than
it is nowadays when there are pessimists. The darkening of the heavens
over man has always increased in proportion to the growth of manâs shame
before man. The tired pessimistic outlook, the mistrust of the riddle of
life, the icy negation of disgusted ennui, all those are not the signs
of the most evil age of the human race: much rather do they come first
to the light of day, as the swamp-flowers, which they are, when the
swamp to which they belong, comes into existenceâI mean the diseased
refinement and moralisation, thanks to which the âanimal manâ has at
last learnt to be ashamed of all his instincts. On the road to angelhood
(not to use in this context a harder word) man has developed that
dyspeptic stomach and coated tongue, which have made not only the joy
and innocence of the animal repulsive to him, but also life itself:âso
that sometimes he stands with stopped nostrils before his own self, and,
like Pope Innocent the Third, makes a black list of his own horrors
(âunclean generation, loathsome nutrition when in the maternal body,
badness of the matter out of which man develops, awful stench, secretion
of saliva, urine, and excrementâ). Nowadays, when suffering is always
trotted out as the first argument against existence, as its most
sinister query, it is well to remember the times when men judged on
converse principles because they could not dispense with the infliction
of suffering, and saw therein a magic of the first order, a veritable
bait of seduction to life.
Perhaps in those days (this is to solace the weaklings) pain did not
hurt so much as it does nowadays: any physician who has treated negroes
(granted that these are taken as representative of the prehistoric man)
suffering from severe internal inflammations which would bring a
European, even though he had the soundest constitution, almost to
despair, would be in a position to come to this conclusion. Pain has not
the same effect with negroes. (The curve of human sensibilities to pain
seems indeed to sink in an extraordinary and almost sudden fashion, as
soon as one has passed the upper ten thousand or ten millions of
over-civilised humanity, and I personally have no doubt that, by
comparison with one painful night passed by one single hysterical chit
of a cultured woman, the suffering of all the animals taken together who
have been put to the question of the knife, so as to give scientific
answers, are simply negligible.) We may perhaps be allowed to admit the
possibility of the craving for cruelty not necessarily having become
really extinct: it only requires, in view of the fact that pain hurts
more nowadays, a certain sublimation and subtilisation, it must
especially be translated to the imaginative and psychic plane, and be
adorned with such smug euphemisms, that even the most fastidious and
hypocritical conscience could never grow suspicious of their real nature
(âTragic pityâ is one of these euphemisms: another is âles nostalgies de
la croixâ). What really raises oneâs indignation against suffering is
not suffering intrinsically, but the senselessness of suffering; such a
senselessness, however, existed neither in Christianity, which
interpreted suffering into a whole mysterious salvation-apparatus, nor
in the beliefs of the naive ancient man, who only knew how to find a
meaning in suffering from the standpoint of the spectator, or the
inflictor of the suffering. In order to get the secret, undiscovered,
and unwitnessed suffering out of the world it was almost compulsory to
invent gods and a hierarchy of intermediate beings, in short, something
which wanders even among secret places, sees even in the dark, and makes
a point of never missing an interesting and painful spectacle. It was
with the help of such inventions that life got to learn the tour de
force, which has become part of its stock-in-trade, the tour de force of
self-justification, of the justification of evil; nowadays this would
perhaps require other auxiliary devices (for instance, life as a riddle,
life as a problem of knowledge). âEvery evil is justified in the sight
of which a god finds edification,â so rang the logic of primitive
sentimentâand, indeed, was it only of primitive? The gods conceived as
friends of spectacles of crueltyâoh how far does this primeval
conception extend even nowadays into our European civilisation! One
would perhaps like in this context to consult Luther and Calvin. It is
at any rate certain that even the Greeks knew no more piquant seasoning
for the happiness of their gods than the joys of cruelty. What, do you
think, was the mood with which Homer makes his gods look down upon the
fates of men? What final meaning have at bottom the Trojan War and
similar tragic horrors? It is impossible to entertain any doubt on the
point: they were intended as festival games for the gods, and, in so far
as the poet is of a more godlike breed than other men, as festival games
also for the poets. It was in just this spirit and no other, that at a
later date the moral philosophers of Greece conceived the eyes of God as
still looking down on the moral struggle, the heroism, and the
self-torture of the virtuous; the Heracles of duty was on a stage, and
was conscious of the fact; virtue without witnesses was something quite
unthinkable for this nation of actors. Must not that philosophic
invention, so audacious and so fatal, which was then absolutely new to
Europe, the invention of âfree will,â of the absolute spontaneity of man
in good and evil, simply have been made for the specific purpose of
justifying the idea, that the interest of the gods in humanity and human
virtue was inexhaustible?
There would never on the stage of this free-will world be a dearth of
really new, really novel and exciting situations, plots, catastrophes. A
world thought out on completely deterministic lines would be easily
guessed by the gods, and would consequently soon bore themâsufficient
reason for these friends of the gods, the philosophers, not to ascribe
to their gods such a deterministic world. The whole of ancient humanity
is full of delicate consideration for the spectator, being as it is a
world of thorough publicity and theatricality, which could not conceive
of happiness without spectacles and festivals.âAnd, as has already been
said, even in great punishment there is so much which is festive.
8.
The feeling of âought,â of personal obligation (to take up again the
train of our inquiry), has had, as we saw, its origin in the oldest and
most original personal relationship that there is, the relationship
between buyer and seller, creditor and ower: here it was that individual
confronted individual, and that individual matched himself against
individual. There has not yet been found a grade of civilisation so low,
as not to manifest some trace of this relationship. Making prices,
assessing values, thinking out equivalents, exchangingâall this
preoccupied the primal thoughts of man to such an extent that in a
certain sense it constituted thinking itself: it was here that was
trained the oldest form of sagacity, it was here in this sphere that we
can perhaps trace the first commencement of manâs pride, of his feeling
of superiority over other animals. Perhaps our word âMenschâ (manas)
still expresses just something of this self-pride: man denoted himself
as the being who measures values, who values and measures, as the
âassessingâ animal par excellence. Sale and purchase, together with
their psychological concomitants, are older than the origins of any form
of social organisation and union: it is rather from the most rudimentary
form of individual right that the budding consciousness of exchange,
commerce, debt, right, obligation, compensation was first transferred to
the rudest and most elementary of the social complexes (in their
relation to similar complexes), the habit of comparing force with force,
together with that of measuring, of calculating. His eye was now
focussed to this perspective; and with that ponderous consistency
characteristic of ancient thought, which, though set in motion with
difficulty, yet proceeds inflexibly along the line on which it has
started, man soon arrived at the great generalisation, âeverything has
its price, all can be paid for,â the oldest and most naive moral canon
of justice, the beginning of all âkindness,â of all âequity,â of all
âgoodwill,â of all âobjectivityâ in the world. Justice in this initial
phase is the goodwill among people of about equal power to come to terms
with each other, to come to an understanding again by means of a
settlement, and with regard to the less powerful, to compel them to
agree among themselves to a settlement.
9.
Measured always by the standard of antiquity (this antiquity, moreover,
is present or again possible at all periods), the community stands to
its members in that important and radical relationship of creditor to
his âowers.â Man lives in a community, man enjoys the advantages of a
community (and what advantages! we occasionally underestimate them
nowadays), man lives protected, spared, in peace and trust, secure from
certain injuries and enmities, to which the man outside the community,
the âpeacelessâ man, is exposed,âa German understands the original
meaning of âElendâ (ĂȘlend),âsecure because he has entered into pledges
and obligations to the community in respect of these very injuries and
enmities. What happens when this is not the case? The community, the
defrauded creditor, will get itself paid, as well as it can, one can
reckon on that. In this case the question of the direct damage done by
the offender is quite subsidiary: quite apart from this the criminal[3]
is above all a breaker, a breaker of word and covenant to the whole, as
regards all the advantages and amenities of the communal life in which
up to that time he had participated. The criminal is an âowerâ who not
only fails to repay the advances and advantages that have been given to
him, but even sets out to attack his creditor: consequently he is in the
future not only, as is fair, deprived of all these advantages and
amenitiesâhe is in addition reminded of the importance of those
advantages. The wrath of the injured creditor, of the community, puts
him back in the wild and outlawed status from which he was previously
protected: the community repudiates himâand now every kind of enmity can
vent itself on him. Punishment is in this stage of civilisation simply
the copy, the mimic, of the normal treatment of the hated, disdained,
and conquered enemy, who is not only deprived of every right and
protection but of every mercy; so we have the martial law and triumphant
festival of the vĂŠ victis! in all its mercilessness and cruelty. This
shows why war itself (counting the sacrificial cult of war) has produced
all the forms under which punishment has manifested itself in history.
10.
As it grows more powerful, the community tends to take the offences of
the individual less seriously, because they are now regarded as being
much less revolutionary and dangerous to the corporate existence: the
evil-doer is no more outlawed and put outside the pale, the common wrath
can no longer vent itself upon him with its old licence,âon the
contrary, from this very time it is against this wrath, and particularly
against the wrath of those directly injured, that the evil-doer is
carefully shielded and protected by the community. As, in fact, the
penal law develops, the following characteristics become more and more
clearly marked: compromise with the wrath of those directly affected by
the misdeed; a consequent endeavour to localise the matter and to
prevent a further, or indeed a general spread of the disturbance;
attempts to find equivalents and to settle the whole matter
(compositio); above all, the will, which manifests itself with
increasing definiteness, to treat every offence as in a certain degree
capable of being paid off, and consequently, at any rate up to a certain
point, to isolate the offender from his act. As the power and the
self-consciousness of a community increases, so proportionately does the
penal law become mitigated; conversely every weakening and jeopardising
of the community revives the harshest forms of that law. The creditor
has always grown more humane proportionately as he has grown more rich;
finally the amount of injury he can endure without really suffering
becomes the criterion of his wealth. It is possible to conceive of a
society blessed with so great a consciousness of its own power as to
indulge in the most aristocratic luxury of letting its wrong-doers go
scot-free.ââWhat do my parasites matter to me?â might society say. âLet
them live and flourish! I am strong enough for it.ââThe justice which
began with the maxim, âEverything can be paid off, everything must be
paid off,â ends with connivance at the escape of those who cannot pay to
escapeâit ends, like every good thing on earth, by destroying
itself.âThe self-destruction of Justice! we know the pretty name it
calls itselfâGrace! it remains, as is obvious, the privilege of the
strongest, better still, their super-law.
11.
A deprecatory word here against the attempts, that have lately been
made, to find the origin of justice on quite another basisânamely, on
that of resentment. Let me whisper a word in the ear of the
psychologists, if they would fain study revenge itself at close
quarters: this plant blooms its prettiest at present among Anarchists
and anti-Semites, a hidden flower, as it has ever been, like the violet,
though, forsooth, with another perfume. And as like must necessarily
emanate from like, it will not be a matter for surprise that it is just
in such circles that we see the birth of endeavours (it is their old
birthplaceâcompare above, First Essay, paragraph 14), to sanctify
revenge under the name of justice (as though Justice were at bottom
merely a development of the consciousness of injury), and thus with the
rehabilitation of revenge to reinstate generally and collectively all
the reactive emotions. I object to this last point least of all. It even
seems meritorious when regarded from the standpoint of the whole problem
of biology (from which standpoint the value of these emotions has up to
the present been underestimated). And that to which I alone call
attention, is the circumstance that it is the spirit of revenge itself,
from which develops this new nuance of scientific equity (for the
benefit of hate, envy, mistrust, jealousy, suspicion, rancour, revenge).
This scientific âequityâ stops immediately and makes way for the accents
of deadly enmity and prejudice, so soon as another group of emotions
comes on the scene, which in my opinion are of a much higher biological
value than these reactions, and consequently have a paramount claim to
the valuation and appreciation of science: I mean the really active
emotions, such as personal and material ambition, and so forth. (E.
DĂŒhring, Value of Life; Course of Philosophy, and passim.) So much
against this tendency in general: but as for the particular maxim of
DĂŒhringâs, that the home of Justice is to be found in the sphere of the
reactive feelings, our love of truth compels us drastically to invert
his own proposition and to oppose to him this other maxim: the last
sphere conquered by the spirit of justice is the sphere of the feeling
of reaction! When it really comes about that the just man remains just
even as regards his injurer (and not merely cold, moderate, reserved,
indifferent: being just is always a positive state); when, in spite of
the strong provocation of personal insult, contempt, and calumny, the
lofty and clear objectivity of the just and judging eye (whose glance is
as profound as it is gentle) is untroubled, why then we have a piece of
perfection, a past master of the worldâsomething, in fact, which it
would not be wise to expect, and which should not at any rate be too
easily believed. Speaking generally, there is no doubt but that even the
justest individual only requires a little dose of hostility, malice, or
innuendo to drive the blood into his brain and the fairness from it. The
active man, the attacking, aggressive man is always a hundred degrees
nearer to justice than the man who merely reacts; he certainly has no
need to adopt the tactics, necessary in the case of the reacting man, of
making false and biassed valuations of his object. It is, in point of
fact, for this reason that the aggressive man has at all times enjoyed
the stronger, bolder, more aristocratic, and also freer outlook, the
better conscience. On the other hand, we already surmise who it really
is that has on his conscience the invention of the âbad conscience,ââthe
resentful man! Finally, let man look at himself in history. In what
sphere up to the present has the whole administration of law, the actual
need of law, found its earthly home? Perchance in the sphere of the
reacting man? Not for a minute: rather in that of the active, strong,
spontaneous, aggressive man? I deliberately defy the above-mentioned
agitator (who himself makes this self-confession, âthe creed of revenge
has run through all my works and endeavours like the red thread of
Justiceâ), and say, that judged historically law in the world represents
the very war against the reactive feelings, the very war waged on those
feelings by the powers of activity and aggression, which devote some of
their strength to damming and keeping within bounds this effervescence
of hysterical reactivity, and to forcing it to some compromise.
Everywhere where justice is practised and justice is maintained, it is
to be observed that the stronger power, when confronted with the weaker
powers which are inferior to it (whether they be groups, or
individuals), searches for weapons to put an end to the senseless fury
of resentment, while it carries on its object, partly by taking the
victim of resentment out of the clutches of revenge, partly by
substituting for revenge a campaign of its own against the enemies of
peace and order, partly by finding, suggesting, and occasionally
enforcing settlements, partly by standardising certain equivalents for
injuries, to which equivalents the element of resentment is henceforth
finally referred. The most drastic measure, however, taken and
effectuated by the supreme power, to combat the preponderance of the
feelings of spite and vindictivenessâit takes this measure as soon as it
is at all strong enough to do soâis the foundation of law, the
imperative declaration of what in its eyes is to be regarded as just and
lawful, and what unjust and unlawful: and while, after the foundation of
law, the supreme power treats the aggressive and arbitrary acts of
individuals, or of whole groups, as a violation of law, and a revolt
against itself, it distracts the feelings of its subjects from the
immediate injury inflicted by such a violation, and thus eventually
attains the very opposite result to that always desired by revenge,
which sees and recognises nothing but the standpoint of the injured
party. From henceforth the eye becomes trained to a more and more
impersonal valuation of the deed, even the eye of the injured party
himself (though this is in the final stage of all, as has been
previously remarked)âon this principle ârightâ and âwrongâ first
manifest themselves after the foundation of law (and not, as DĂŒhring
maintains, only after the act of violation). To talk of intrinsic right
and intrinsic wrong is absolutely non-sensical; intrinsically, an
injury, an oppression, an exploitation, an annihilation can be nothing
wrong, inasmuch as life is essentially (that is, in its cardinal
functions) something which functions by injuring, oppressing,
exploiting, and annihilating, and is absolutely inconceivable without
such a character. It is necessary to make an even more serious
confession:âviewed from the most advanced biological standpoint,
conditions of legality can be only exceptional conditions, in that they
are partial restrictions of the real life-will, which makes for power,
and in that they are subordinated to the life-willâs general end as
particular means, that is, as means to create larger units of strength.
A legal organisation, conceived of as sovereign and universal, not as a
weapon in a fight of complexes of power, but as a weapon against
fighting, generally something after the style of DĂŒhringâs communistic
model of treating every will as equal with every other will, would be a
principle hostile to life, a destroyer and dissolver of man, an outrage
on the future of man, a symptom of fatigue, a secret cut to
Nothingness.â
12.
A word more on the origin and end of punishmentâtwo problems which are
or ought to be kept distinct, but which unfortunately are usually lumped
into one. And what tactics have our moral genealogists employed up to
the present in these cases? Their inveterate naïveté. They find out some
âendâ in the punishment, for instance, revenge and deterrence, and then
in all their innocence set this end at the beginning, as the causa
fiendi of the punishment, andâthey have done the trick. But the patching
up of a history of the origin of law is the last use to which the âEnd
in Lawâ[4] ought to be put. Perhaps there is no more pregnant principle
for any kind of history than the following, which, difficult though it
is to master, should none the less be mastered in every detail.âThe
origin of the existence of a thing and its final utility, its practical
application and incorporation in a system of ends, are toto cĆlo opposed
to each otherâeverything, anything, which exists and which prevails
anywhere, will always be put to new purposes by a force superior to
itself, will be commandeered afresh, will be turned and transformed to
new uses; all âhappeningâ in the organic world consists of overpowering
and dominating, and again all overpowering and domination is a new
interpretation and adjustment, which must necessarily obscure or
absolutely extinguish the subsisting âmeaningâ and âend.â The most
perfect comprehension of the utility of any physiological organ (or also
of a legal institution, social custom, political habit, form in art or
in religious worship) does not for a minute imply any simultaneous
comprehension of its origin: this may seem uncomfortable and unpalatable
to the older men,âfor it has been the immemorial belief that
understanding the final cause or the utility of a thing, a form, an
institution, means also understanding the reason for its origin: to give
an example of this logic, the eye was made to see, the hand was made to
grasp. So even punishment was conceived as invented with a view to
punishing. But all ends and all utilities are only signs that a Will to
Power has mastered a less powerful force, has impressed thereon out of
its own self the meaning of a function; and the whole history of a
âThing,â an organ, a custom, can on the same principle be regarded as a
continuous âsign-chainâ of perpetually new interpretations and
adjustments, whose causes, so far from needing to have even a mutual
connection, sometimes follow and alternate with each other absolutely
haphazard. Similarly, the evolution of a âthing,â of a custom, is
anything but its progressus to an end, still less a logical and direct
progressus attained with the minimum expenditure of energy and cost: it
is rather the succession of processes of subjugation, more or less
profound, more or less mutually independent, which operate on the thing
itself; it is, further, the resistance which in each case invariably
displayed this subjugation, the Protean wriggles by way of defence and
reaction, and, further, the results of successful counter-efforts. The
form is fluid, but the meaning is even more soâeven inside every
individual organism the case is the same: with every genuine growth of
the whole, the âfunctionâ of the individual organs becomes shifted,âin
certain cases a partial perishing of these organs, a diminution of their
numbers (for instance, through annihilation of the connecting members),
can be a symptom of growing strength and perfection. What I mean is
this: even partial loss of utility, decay, and degeneration, loss of
function and purpose, in a word, death, appertain to the conditions of
the genuine progressus; which always appears in the shape of a will and
way to greater power, and is always realised at the expense of
innumerable smaller powers. The magnitude of a âprogressâ is gauged by
the greatness of the sacrifice that it requires: humanity as a mass
sacrificed to the prosperity of the one stronger species of Manâthat
would be a progress. I emphasise all the more this cardinal
characteristic of the historic method, for the reason that in its
essence it runs counter to predominant instincts and prevailing taste,
which much prefer to put up with absolute casualness, even with the
mechanical senselessness of all phenomena, than with the theory of a
power-will, in exhaustive play throughout all phenomena. The democratic
idiosyncrasy against everything which rules and wishes to rule, the
modern misarchism (to coin a bad word for a bad thing), has gradually
but so thoroughly transformed itself into the guise of intellectualism,
the most abstract intellectualism, that even nowadays it penetrates and
has the right to penetrate step by step into the most exact and
apparently the most objective sciences: this tendency has, in fact, in
my view already dominated the whole of physiology and biology, and to
their detriment, as is obvious, in so far as it has spirited away a
radical idea, the idea of true activity. The tyranny of this
idiosyncrasy, however, results in the theory of âadaptationâ being
pushed forward into the van of the argument, exploited; adaptationâthat
means to say, a second-class activity, a mere capacity for âreactingâ;
in fact, life itself has been defined (by Herbert Spencer) as an
increasingly effective internal adaptation to external circumstances.
This definition, however, fails to realise the real essence of life, its
will to power. It fails to appreciate the paramount superiority enjoyed
by those plastic forces of spontaneity, aggression, and encroachment
with their new interpretations and tendencies, to the operation of which
adaptation is only a natural corollary: consequently the sovereign
office of the highest functionaries in the organism itself (among which
the life-will appears as an active and formative principle) is
repudiated. One remembers Huxleyâs reproach to Spencer of his
âadministrative Nihilismâ: but it is a case of something much more than
âadministration.â
13.
To return to our subject, namely punishment, we must make consequently a
double distinction: first, the relatively permanent element, the custom,
the act, the âdrama,â a certain rigid sequence of methods of procedure;
on the other hand, the fluid element, the meaning, the end, the
expectation which is attached to the operation of such procedure. At
this point we immediately assume, per analogiam (in accordance with the
theory of the historic method, which we have elaborated above), that the
procedure itself is something older and earlier than its utilisation in
punishment, that this utilisation was introduced and interpreted into
the procedure (which had existed for a long time, but whose employment
had another meaning), in short, that the case is different from that
hitherto supposed by our naĂŻf genealogists of morals and of law, who
thought that the procedure was invented for the purpose of punishment,
in the same way that the hand had been previously thought to have been
invented for the purpose of grasping. With regard to the other element
in punishment, its fluid element, its meaning, the idea of punishment in
a very late stage of civilisation (for instance, contemporary Europe) is
not content with manifesting merely one meaning, but manifests a whole
synthesis âof meanings.â The past general history of punishment, the
history of its employment for the most diverse ends, crystallises
eventually into a kind of unity, which is difficult to analyse into its
parts, and which, it is necessary to emphasise, absolutely defies
definition. (It is nowadays impossible to say definitely the precise
reason for punishment: all ideas, in which a whole process is
promiscuously comprehended, elude definition; it is only that which has
no history, which can be defined.) At an earlier stage, on the contrary,
that synthesis of meanings appears much less rigid and much more
elastic; we can realise how in each individual case the elements of the
synthesis change their value and their position, so that now one element
and now another stands out and predominates over the others, nay, in
certain cases one element (perhaps the end of deterrence) seems to
eliminate all the rest. At any rate, so as to give some idea of the
uncertain, supplementary, and accidental nature of the meaning of
punishment and of the manner in which one identical procedure can be
employed and adapted for the most diametrically opposed objects, I will
at this point give a scheme that has suggested itself to me, a scheme
itself based on comparatively small and accidental material.âPunishment,
as rendering the criminal harmless and incapable of further
injury.âPunishment, as compensation for the injury sustained by the
injured party, in any form whatsoever (including the form of sentimental
compensation).âPunishment, as an isolation of that which disturbs the
equilibrium, so as to prevent the further spreading of the
disturbance.âPunishment as a means of inspiring fear of those who
determine and execute the punishment.âPunishment as a kind of
compensation for advantages which the wrong-doer has up to that time
enjoyed (for example, when he is utilised as a slave in the
mines).âPunishment, as the elimination of an element of decay (sometimes
of a whole branch, as according to the Chinese laws, consequently as a
means to the purification of the race, or the preservation of a social
type).â-Punishment as a festival, as the violent oppression and
humiliation of an enemy that has at last been subdued.âPunishment as a
mnemonic, whether for him who suffers the punishmentâthe so-called
âcorrection,â or for the witnesses of its administration. Punishment, as
the payment of a fee stipulated for by the power which protects the
evil-doer from the excesses of revenge.âPunishment, as a compromise with
the natural phenomenon of revenge, in so far as revenge is still
maintained and claimed as a privilege by the stronger races.âPunishment
as a declaration and measure of war against an enemy of peace, of law,
of order, of authority, who is fought by society with the weapons which
war provides, as a spirit dangerous to the community, as a breaker of
the contract on which the community is based, as a rebel, a traitor, and
a breaker of the peace.
14.
This list is certainly not complete; it is obvious that punishment is
overloaded with utilities of all kinds. This makes it all the more
permissible to eliminate one supposed utility, which passes, at any rate
in the popular mind, for its most essential utility, and which is just
what even now provides the strongest support for that faith in
punishment which is nowadays for many reasons tottering. Punishment is
supposed to have the value of exciting in the guilty the consciousness
of guilt; in punishment is sought the proper instrumentum of that
psychic reaction which becomes known as a âbad conscience,â âremorse.â
But this theory is even, from the point of view of the present, a
violation of reality and psychology: and how much more so is the case
when we have to deal with the longest period of manâs history, his
primitive history! Genuine remorse is certainly extremely rare among
wrong-doers and the victims of punishment; prisons and houses of
correction are not the soil on which this worm of remorse pullulates for
choiceâthis is the unanimous opinion of all conscientious observers, who
in many cases arrive at such a judgment with enough reluctance and
against their own personal wishes. Speaking generally, punishment
hardens and numbs, it produces concentration, it sharpens the
consciousness of alienation, it strengthens the power of resistance.
When it happens that it breaks the manâs energy and brings about a
piteous prostration and abjectness, such a result is certainly even less
salutary than the average effect of punishment, which is characterised
by a harsh and sinister doggedness. The thought of those prehistoric
millennia brings us to the unhesitating conclusion, that it was simply
through punishment that the evolution of the consciousness of guilt was
most forcibly retardedâat any rate in the victims of the punishing
power. In particular, let us not underestimate the extent to which, by
the very sight of the judicial and executive procedure, the wrong-doer
is himself prevented from feeling that his deed, the character of his
act, is intrinsically reprehensible: for he sees clearly the same kind
of acts practised in the service of justice, and then called good, and
practised with a good conscience; acts such as espionage, trickery,
bribery, trapping, the whole intriguing and insidious art of the
policeman and the informerâthe whole system, in fact, manifested in the
different kinds of punishment (a system not excused by passion, but
based on principle), of robbing, oppressing, insulting, imprisoning,
racking, murdering.âAll this he sees treated by his judges, not as acts
meriting censure and condemnation in themselves, but only in a
particular context and application. It was not on this soil that grew
the âbad conscience,â that most sinister and interesting plant of our
earthly vegetationâ in point of fact, throughout a most lengthy period,
no suggestion of having to do with a âguilty manâ manifested itself in
the consciousness of the man who judged and punished. One had merely to
deal with an author of an injury, an irresponsible piece of fate. And
the man himself, on whom the punishment subsequently fell like a piece
of fate, was occasioned no more of an âinner painâ than would be
occasioned by the sudden approach of some uncalculated event, some
terrible natural catastrophe, a rushing, crushing avalanche against
which there is no resistance.
15.
This truth came insidiously enough to the consciousness of Spinoza (to
the disgust of his commentators, who (like Kuno Fischer, for instance)
give themselves no end of trouble to misunderstand him on this point),
when one afternoon (as he sat raking up who knows what memory) he
indulged in the question of what was really left for him personally of
the celebrated morsus conscientiĂŠâSpinoza, who had relegated âgood and
evilâ to the sphere of human imagination, and indignantly defended the
honour of his âfreeâ God against those blasphemers who affirmed that God
did everything sub ratione boni (âbut this was tantamount to
subordinating God to fate, and would really be the greatest of all
absurditiesâ). For Spinoza the world had returned again to that
innocence in which it lay before the discovery of the bad conscience:
what, then, had happened to the morsus conscientiĂŠ? âThe antithesis of
gaudium,â said he at last to himself,ââA sadness accompanied by the
recollection of a past event which has turned out contrary to all
expectationâ (Eth. III., Propos. XVIII. Schol. i. ii.). Evil-doers have
throughout thousands of years felt when overtaken by punishment exactly
like Spinoza, on the subject of their âoffenceâ: âhere is something
which went wrong contrary to my anticipation,â not âI ought not to have
done this.ââThey submitted themselves to punishment, just as one submits
oneâs self to a disease, to a misfortune, or to death, with that
stubborn and resigned fatalism which gives the Russians, for instance,
even nowadays, the advantage over us Westerners, in the handling of
life. If at that period there was a critique of action, the criterion
was prudence: the real effect of punishment is unquestionably chiefly to
be found in a sharpening of the sense of prudence, in a lengthening of
the memory, in a will to adopt more of a policy of caution, suspicion,
and secrecy; in the recognition that there are many things which are
unquestionably beyond oneâs capacity; in a kind of improvement in
self-criticism. The broad effects which can be obtained by punishment in
man and beast, are the increase of fear, the sharpening of the sense of
cunning, the mastery of the desires: so it is that punishment tames man,
but does not make him âbetterââit would be more correct even to go so
far as to assert the contrary (âInjury makes a man cunning,â says a
popular proverb: so far as it makes him cunning, it makes him also bad.
Fortunately, it often enough makes him stupid).
16.
At this juncture I cannot avoid trying to give a tentative and
provisional expression to my own hypothesis concerning the origin of the
bad conscience: it is difficult to make it fully appreciated, and it
requires continuous meditation, attention, and digestion. I regard the
bad conscience as the serious illness which man was bound to contract
under the stress of the most radical change which he has ever
experiencedâthat change, when he found himself finally imprisoned within
the pale of society and of peace.
Just like the plight of the water-animals, when they were compelled
either to become land-animals or to perish, so was the plight of these
half-animals, perfectly adapted as they were to the savage life of war,
prowling, and adventureâsuddenly all their instincts were rendered
worthless and âswitched off.â Henceforward they had to walk on their
feetââcarry themselves,â whereas heretofore they had been carried by the
water: a terrible heaviness oppressed them. They found themselves clumsy
in obeying the simplest directions, confronted with this new and unknown
world they had no longer their old guidesâthe regulative instincts that
had led them unconsciously to safetyâthey were reduced, were those
unhappy creatures, to thinking, inferring, calculating, putting together
causes and results, reduced to that poorest and most erratic organ of
theirs, their âconsciousness.â I do not believe there was ever in the
world such a feeling of misery, such a leaden discomfortâfurther, those
old instincts had not immediately ceased their demands! Only it was
difficult and rarely possible to gratify them: speaking broadly, they
were compelled to satisfy themselves by new and, as it were,
hole-and-corner methods. All instincts which do not find a vent without,
turn inwardsâthis is what I mean by the growing âinternalisationâ of
man: consequently we have the first growth in man, of what subsequently
was called his soul. The whole inner world, originally as thin as if it
had been stretched between two layers of skin, burst apart and expanded
proportionately, and obtained depth, breadth, and height, when manâs
external outlet became obstructed. These terrible bulwarks, with which
the social organisation protected itself against the old instincts of
freedom (punishments belong pre-eminently to these bulwarks), brought it
about that all those instincts of wild, free, prowling man became turned
backwards against man himself. Enmity, cruelty, the delight in
persecution, in surprises, change, destructionâthe turning all these
instincts against their own possessors: this is the origin of the âbad
conscience.â It was man, who, lacking external enemies and obstacles,
and imprisoned as he was in the oppressive narrowness and monotony of
custom, in his own impatience lacerated, persecuted, gnawed, frightened,
and ill-treated himself; it was this animal in the hands of the tamer,
which beat itself against the bars of its cage; it was this being who,
pining and yearning for that desert home of which it had been deprived,
was compelled to create out of its own self, an adventure, a
torture-chamber, a hazardous and perilous desertâit was this fool, this
homesick and desperate prisonerâwho invented the âbad conscience.â But
thereby he introduced that most grave and sinister illness, from which
mankind has not yet recovered, the suffering of man from the disease
called man, as the result of a violent breaking from his animal past,
the result, as it were, of a spasmodic plunge into a new environment and
new conditions of existence, the result of a declaration of war against
the old instincts, which up to that time had been the staple of his
power, his joy, his formidableness. Let us immediately add that this
fact of an animal ego turning against itself, taking part against
itself, produced in the world so novel, profound, unheard-of,
problematic, inconsistent, and pregnant a phenomenon, that the aspect of
the world was radically altered thereby. In sooth, only divine
spectators could have appreciated the drama that then began, and whose
end baffles conjecture as yetâa drama too subtle, too wonderful, too
paradoxical to warrant its undergoing a non-sensical and unheeded
performance on some random grotesque planet! Henceforth man is to be
counted as one of the most unexpected and sensational lucky shots in the
game of the âbig babyâ of Heracleitus, whether he be called Zeus or
Chanceâhe awakens on his behalf the interest, excitement, hope, almost
the confidence, of his being the harbinger and forerunner of something,
of man being no end, but only a stage, an interlude, a bridge, a great
promise.
17.
It is primarily involved in this hypothesis of the origin of the bad
conscience, that that alteration was no gradual and no voluntary
alteration, and that it did not manifest itself as an organic adaptation
to new conditions, but as a break, a jump, a necessity, an inevitable
fate, against which there was no resistance and never a spark of
resentment. And secondarily, that the fitting of a hitherto unchecked
and amorphous population into a fixed form, starting as it had done in
an act of violence, could only be accomplished by acts of violence and
nothing elseâthat the oldest âStateâ appeared consequently as a ghastly
tyranny, a grinding ruthless piece of machinery, which went on working,
till this raw material of a semi-animal populace was not only thoroughly
kneaded and elastic, but also moulded. I used the word âStateâ: my
meaning is self-evident, namely, a herd of blonde beasts of prey, a race
of conquerors and masters, which with all its warlike organisation and
all its organising power pounces with its terrible claws on a
population, in numbers possibly tremendously superior, but as yet
formless, as yet nomad. Such is the origin of the âState.â That
fantastic theory that makes it begin with a contract is, I think,
disposed of. He who can command, he who is a master by ânature,â he who
comes on the scene forceful in deed and gestureâwhat has he to do with
contracts? Such beings defy calculation, they come like fate, without
cause, reason, notice, excuse, they are there like the lightning is
there, too terrible, too sudden, too convincing, too âdifferent,â to be
personally even hated. Their work is an instinctive creating and
impressing of forms, they are the most involuntary, unconscious artists
that there are:âtheir appearance produces instantaneously a scheme of
sovereignty which is live, in which the functions are partitioned and
apportioned, in which above all no part is received or finds a place,
until pregnant with a âmeaningâ in regard to the whole. They are
ignorant of the meaning of guilt, responsibility, consideration, are
these born organisers; in them predominates that terrible artist-egoism,
that gleams like brass, and that knows itself justified to all eternity,
in its work, even as a mother in her child. It is not in them that there
grew the bad conscience, that is elementaryâbut it would not have grown
without them, repulsive growth as it was, it would be missing, had not a
tremendous quantity of freedom been expelled from the world by the
stress of their hammer-strokes, their artist violence, or been at any
rate made invisible and, as it were, latent. This instinct of freedom
forced into being latentâit is already clearâthis instinct of freedom
forced back, trodden back, imprisoned within itself, and finally only
able to find vent and relief in itself; this, only this, is the
beginning of the âbad conscience.â
18.
Beware of thinking lightly of this phenomenon, by reason of its initial
painful ugliness. At bottom it is the same active force which is at work
on a more grandiose scale in those potent artists and organisers, and
builds states, which here, internally, on a smaller and pettier scale
and with a retrogressive tendency, makes itself a bad science in the
âlabyrinth of the breast,â to use Goetheâs phrase, and which builds
negative ideals; it is, I repeat, that identical instinct of freedom (to
use my own language, the will to power): only the material, on which
this force with all its constructive and tyrannous nature is let loose,
is here man himself, his whole old animal selfâand not as in the case of
that more grandiose and sensational phenomenon, the other man, other
men. This secret self-tyranny, this cruelty of the artist, this delight
in giving a form to oneâs self as a piece of difficult, refractory, and
suffering material, in burning in a will, a critique, a contradiction, a
contempt, a negation; this sinister and ghastly labour of love on the
part of a soul, whose will is cloven in two within itself, which makes
itself suffer from delight in the infliction of suffering; this wholly
active bad conscience has finally (as one already anticipates)âtrue
fountainhead as it is of idealism and imaginationâproduced an abundance
of novel and amazing beauty and affirmation, and perhaps has really been
the first to give birth to beauty at all. What would beauty be,
forsooth, if its contradiction had not first been presented to
consciousness, if the ugly had not first said to itself, âI am uglyâ? At
any rate, after this hint the problem of how far idealism and beauty can
be traced in such opposite ideas as âselflessness,â self-denial,
self-sacrifice, becomes less problematical; and indubitably in future we
shall certainly know the real and original character of the delight
experienced by the self-less, the self-denying, the self-sacrificing:
this delight is a phase of cruelty.âSo much provisionally for the origin
of âaltruismâ as a moral value, and the marking out the ground from
which this value has grown: it is only the bad conscience, only the will
for self-abuse, that provides the necessary conditions for the existence
of altruism as a value.
19.
Undoubtedly the bad conscience is an illness, but an illness like
pregnancy is an illness. If we search out the conditions under which
this illness reaches its most terrible and sublime zenith, we shall see
what really first brought about its entry into the world. But to do this
we must take a long breath, and we must first of all go back once again
to an earlier point of view. The relation at civil law of the ower to
his creditor (which has already been discussed in detail), has been
interpreted once again (and indeed in a manner which historically is
exceedingly remarkable and suspicious) into a relationship, which is
perhaps more incomprehensible to us moderns than to any other era; that
is, into the relationship of the existing generation to its ancestors.
Within the original tribal associationâwe are talking of primitive
timesâeach living generation recognises a legal obligation towards the
earlier generation, and particularly towards the earliest, which founded
the family (and this is something much more than a mere sentimental
obligation, the existence of which, during the longest period of manâs
history, is by no means indisputable). There prevails in them the
conviction that it is only thanks to sacrifices and efforts of their
ancestors, that the race persists at allâand that this has to be paid
back to them by sacrifices and services. Thus is recognised the owing of
a debt, which accumulates continually by reason of these ancestors never
ceasing in their subsequent life as potent spirits to secure by their
power new privileges and advantages to the race. Gratis, perchance? But
there is no gratis for that raw and âmean-souledâ age. What return can
be made?âSacrifice (at first, nourishment, in its crudest sense),
festivals, temples, tributes of veneration, above all, obedienceâsince
all customs are, quĂą works of the ancestors, equally their precepts and
commandsâare the ancestors ever given enough? This suspicion remains and
grows: from time to time it extorts a great wholesale ransom, something
monstrous in the way of repayment of the creditor (the notorious
sacrifice of the first-born, for example, blood, human blood in any
case). The fear of ancestors and their power, the consciousness of owing
debts to them, necessarily increases, according to this kind of logic,
in the exact proportion that the race itself increases, that the race
itself becomes more victorious, more independent, more honoured, more
feared. This, and not the contrary, is the fact. Each step towards race
decay, all disastrous events, all symptoms of degeneration, of
approaching disintegration, always diminish the fear of the foundersâ
spirit, and whittle away the idea of his sagacity, providence, and
potent presence. Conceive this crude kind of logic carried to its
climax: it follows that the ancestors of the most powerful races must,
through the growing fear that they exercise on the imaginations, grow
themselves into monstrous dimensions, and become relegated to the gloom
of a divine mystery that transcends imaginationâthe ancestor becomes at
last necessarily transfigured into a god. Perhaps this is the very
origin of the gods, that is, an origin from fear! And those who feel
bound to add, âbut from piety also,â will have difficulty in maintaining
this theory, with regard to the primeval and longest period of the human
race. And of course this is even more the case as regards the middle
period, the formative period of the aristocratic racesâthe aristocratic
races which have given back with interest to their founders, the
ancestors (heroes, gods), all those qualities which in the meanwhile
have appeared in themselves, that is, the aristocratic qualities. We
will later on glance again at the ennobling and promotion of the gods
(which of course is totally distinct from their âsanctificationâ): let
us now provisionally follow to its end the course of the whole of this
development of the consciousness of âowing.â
20.
According to the teaching of history, the consciousness of owing debts
to the deity by no means came to an end with the decay of the clan
organisation of society; just as mankind has inherited the ideas of
âgoodâ and âbadâ from the race-nobility (together with its fundamental
tendency towards establishing social distinctions), so with the heritage
of the racial and tribal gods it has also inherited the incubus of debts
as yet unpaid and the desire to discharge them. The transition is
effected by those large populations of slaves and bondsmen, who, whether
through compulsion or through submission and âmimicry,â have
accommodated themselves to the religion of their masters; through this
channel these inherited tendencies inundate the world. The feeling of
owing a debt to the deity has grown continuously for several centuries,
always in the same proportion in which the idea of God and the
consciousness of God have grown and become exalted among mankind. (The
whole history of ethnic fights, victories, reconciliations,
amalgamations, everything, in fact, which precedes the eventual classing
of all the social elements in each great race-synthesis, are mirrored in
the hotch-potch genealogy of their gods, in the legends of their fights,
victories, and reconciliations. Progress towards universal empires
invariably means progress towards universal deities; despotism, with its
subjugation of the independent nobility, always paves the way for some
system or other of monotheism.) The appearance of the Christian god, as
the record god up to this time, has for that very reason brought equally
into the world the record amount of guilt consciousness. Granted that we
have gradually started on the reverse movement, there is no little
probability in the deduction, based on the continuous decay in the
belief in the Christian god, to the effect that there also already
exists a considerable decay in the human consciousness of owing (ought);
in fact, we cannot shut our eyes to the prospect of the complete and
eventual triumph of atheism freeing mankind from all this feeling of
obligation to their origin, their causa prima. Atheism and a kind of
second innocence complement and supplement each other.
21.
So much for my rough and preliminary sketch of the interrelation of the
ideas âoughtâ (owe) and âdutyâ with the postulates of religion. I have
intentionally shelved up to the present the actual moralisation of these
ideas (their being pushed back into the conscience, or more precisely
the interweaving of the bad conscience with the idea of God), and at the
end of the last paragraph used language to the effect that this
moralisation did not exist, and that consequently these ideas had
necessarily come to an end, by reason of what had happened to their
hypothesis, the credence in our âcreditor,â in God. The actual facts
differ terribly from this theory. It is with the moralisation of the
ideas âoughtâ and âduty,â and with their being pushed back into the bad
conscience, that comes the first actual attempt to reverse the direction
of the development we have just described, or at any rate to arrest its
evolution; it is just at this juncture that the very hope of an eventual
redemption has to put itself once for all into the prison of pessimism,
it is at this juncture that the eye has to recoil and rebound in despair
from off an adamantine impossibility, it is at this juncture that the
ideas âguiltâ and âdutyâ have to turn backwardsâturn backwards against
whom? There is no doubt about it; primarily against the âower,â in whom
the bad conscience now establishes itself, eats, extends, and grows like
a polypus throughout its length and breadth, all with such virulence,
that at last, with the impossibility of paying the debt, there becomes
conceived the idea of the impossibility of paying the penalty, the
thought of its inexpiability (the idea of âeternal punishmentâ)âfinally,
too, it turns against the âcreditor,â whether found in the causa prima
of man, the origin of the human race, its sire, who henceforth becomes
burdened with a curse (âAdam,â âoriginal sin,â âdetermination of the
willâ), or in Nature from whose womb man springs, and on whom the
responsibility for the principle of evil is now cast (âDiabolisation of
Natureâ), or in existence generally, on this logic an absolute white
elephant, with which mankind is landed (the Nihilistic flight from life,
the demand for Nothingness, or for the opposite of existence, for some
other existence, Buddhism and the like)âtill suddenly we stand before
that paradoxical and awful expedient, through which a tortured humanity
has found a temporary alleviation, that stroke of genius called
Christianity:âGod personally immolating himself for the debt of man, God
paying himself personally out of a pound of his own flesh, God as the
one being who can deliver man from what man had become unable to deliver
himselfâthe creditor playing scapegoat for his debtor, from love (can
you believe it?), from love of his debtor!...
22.
The reader will already have conjectured what took place on the stage
and behind the scenes of this drama. That will for self-torture, that
inverted cruelty of the animal man, who, turned subjective and scared
into introspection (encaged as he was in âthe State,â as part of his
taming process), invented the bad conscience so as to hurt himself,
after the natural outlet for this will to hurt, became blockedâin other
words, this man of the bad conscience exploited the religious hypothesis
so as to carry his martyrdom to the ghastliest pitch of agonised
intensity. Owing something to God: this thought becomes his instrument
of torture. He apprehends in God the most extreme antitheses that he can
find to his own characteristic and ineradicable animal instincts, he
himself gives a new interpretation to these animal instincts as being
against what he âowesâ to God (as enmity, rebellion, and revolt against
the âLord,â the âFather,â the âSire,â the âBeginning of the worldâ), he
places himself between the horns of the dilemma, âGodâ and âDevil.â
Every negation which he is inclined to utter to himself, to the nature,
naturalness, and reality of his being, he whips into an ejaculation of
âyes,â uttering it as something existing, living, efficient, as being
God, as the holiness of God, the judgment of God, as the hangmanship of
God, as transcendence, as eternity, as unending torment, as hell, as
infinity of punishment and guilt. This is a kind of madness of the will
in the sphere of psychological cruelty which is absolutely
unparalleled:âmanâs will to find himself guilty and blameworthy to the
point of inexpiability, his will to think of himself as punished,
without the punishment ever being able to balance the guilt, his will to
infect and to poison the fundamental basis of the universe with the
problem of punishment and guilt, in order to cut off once and for all
any escape out of this labyrinth of âfixed ideas,â his will for rearing
an idealâthat of the âholy Godââface to face with which he can have
tangible proof of his own un-worthiness. Alas for this mad melancholy
beast man! What phantasies invade it, what paroxysms of perversity,
hysterical senselessness, and mental bestiality break out immediately,
at the very slightest check on its being the beast of action. All this
is excessively interesting, but at the same time tainted with a black,
gloomy, enervating melancholy, so that a forcible veto must be invoked
against looking too long into these abysses. Here is disease,
undubitably, the most ghastly disease that has as yet played havoc among
men: and he who can still hear (but man turns now deaf ears to such
sounds), how in this night of torment and nonsense there has rung out
the cry of love, the cry of the most passionate ecstasy, of redemption
in love, he turns away gripped by an invincible horrorâin man there is
so much that is ghastlyâtoo long has the world been a mad-house.
23.
Let this suffice once for all concerning the origin of the âholy God.â
The fact that in itself the conception of gods is not bound to lead
necessarily to this degradation of the imagination (a temporary
representation of whose vagaries we felt bound give), the fact that
there exist nobler methods of utilising the invention of gods than in
this self-crucifixion and self-degradation of man, in which the last two
thousand years of Europe have been past mastersâthese facts can
fortunately be still perceived from every glance that we cast at the
Grecian gods, these mirrors of noble and grandiose men, in which the
animal in man felt itself deified, and did not devour itself in
subjective frenzy. These Greeks long utilised their gods as simple
buffers against the âbad conscienceââso that they could continue to
enjoy their freedom of soul: this, of course, is diametrically opposed
to Christianityâs theory of its god. They went very far on this
principle, did these splendid and lion-hearted children; and there is no
lesser authority than that of the Homeric Zeus for making them realise
occasionally that they are taking life too casually. âWonderful,â says
he on one occasionâit has to do with the case of Ăgistheus, a very bad
case indeedâ
âWonderful how they grumble, the mortals against the immortals,
Only from us, they presume, comes evil, but in their folly,
Fashion they, spite of fate, the doom of their own disaster.â
Yet the reader will note and observe that this Olympian spectator and
judge is far from being angry with them and thinking evil of them on
this score. âHow foolish they are,â so thinks he of the misdeeds of
mortalsâand âfolly,â âimprudence,â âa little brain disturbance,â and
nothing more, are what the Greeks, even of the strongest, bravest
period, have admitted to be the ground of much that is evil and
fatal.âFolly, not sin, do you understand?... But even this brain
disturbance was a problemââCome, how is it even possible? How could it
have really got in brains like ours, the brains of men of aristocratic
ancestry, of men of fortune, of men of good natural endowments, of men
of the best society, of men of nobility and virtue?â This was the
question that for century on century the aristocratic Greek put to
himself when confronted with every (to him incomprehensible) outrage and
sacrilege with which one of his peers had polluted himself. âIt must be
that a god had infatuated him,â he would say at last, nodding his
head.âThis solution is typical of the Greeks, ... accordingly the gods
in those times subserved the functions of justifying man to a certain
extent even in evilâin those days they took upon themselves not the
punishment, but, what is more noble, the guilt.
24.
I conclude with three queries, as you will see. âIs an ideal actually
set up here, or is one pulled down?â I am perhaps asked.... But have ye
sufficiently asked yourselves how dear a payment has the setting up of
every ideal in the world exacted? To achieve that consummation how much
truth must always be traduced and misunderstood, how many lies must be
sanctified, how much conscience has got to be disturbed, how many pounds
of âGodâ have got to be sacrificed every time? To enable a sanctuary to
be set up a sanctuary has got to be destroyed: that is a lawâshow me an
instance where it has not been fulfilled!... We modern men, we inherit
the immemorial tradition of vivisecting the conscience, and practising
cruelty to our animal selves. That is the sphere of our most protracted
training, perhaps of our artistic prowess, at any rate of our
dilettantism and our perverted taste. Man has for too long regarded his
natural proclivities with an âevil eye,â so that eventually they have
become in his system affiliated to a bad conscience. A converse
endeavour would be intrinsically feasibleâbut who is strong enough to
attempt it?ânamely, to affiliate to the âbad conscienceâ all those
unnatural proclivities, all those transcendental aspirations, contrary
to sense, instinct, nature, and animalismâin short, all past and present
ideals, which are all ideals opposed to life, and traducing the world.
To whom is one to turn nowadays with such hopes and pretensions?âIt is
just the good men that we should thus bring about our ears; and in
addition, as stands to reason, the indolent, the hedgers, the vain, the
hysterical, the tired.... What is more offensive or more thoroughly
calculated to alienate, than giving any hint of the exalted severity
with which we treat ourselves? And again how conciliatory, how full of
love does all the world show itself towards us so soon as we do as all
the world docs, and âlet ourselves goâ like all the world. For such a
consummation we need spirits of different calibre than seems really
feasible in this age; spirits rendered potent through wars and
victories, to whom conquest, adventure, danger, even pain, have become a
need; for such a consummation we need habituation to sharp, rare air, to
winter wanderings, to literal and metaphorical ice and mountains; we
even need a kind of sublime malice, a supreme and most self-conscious
insolence of knowledge, which is the appanage of great health; we need
(to summarise the awful truth) just this great health!
Is this even feasible to-day?... But some day, in a stronger age than
this rotting and introspective present, must he in sooth come to us,
even the redeemer of great love and scorn, the creative spirit,
rebounding by the impetus of his own force back again away from every
transcendental plane and dimension, he whose solitude is misunderstanded
(sic) of the people, as though it were a flight from reality;âwhile
actually it is only his diving, burrowing, and penetrating into reality,
so that when he comes again to the light he can at once bring about by
these means the redemption of this reality; its redemption from the
curse which the old ideal has laid upon it. This man of the future, who
in this wise will redeem us from the old ideal, as he will from that
idealâs necessary corollary of great nausea, will to nothingness, and
Nihilism; this tocsin of noon and of the great verdict, which renders
the will again free, who gives back to the world its goal and to man his
hope, this Antichrist and Antinihilist, this conqueror of God and of
Nothingnessâhe must one day come.
25.
But what am I talking of? Enough! Enough? At this juncture I have only
one proper course, silence: otherwise tresspass on a domain open alone
to one who is younger than I, one stronger, more âfutureâ than Iâopen
alone to Zarathustra, Zarathustra the godless.
âCareless, mocking, forcefulâso does wisdom wish us: she is a woman, and
never loves any one but a warrior.â
Thus Spake Zarathustra.
1.
What is the meaning of ascetic ideals? In artists, nothing, or too much;
in philosophers and scholars, a kind of âflairâ and instinct for the
conditions most favourable to advanced intellectualism; in women, at
best an additional seductive fascination, a little morbidezza on a fine
piece of flesh, the angelhood of a fat, pretty animal; in physiological
failures and whiners (in the majority of mortals), an attempt to pose as
âtoo goodâ for this world, a holy form of debauchery, their chief weapon
in the battle with lingering pain and ennui; in priests, the actual
priestly faith, their best engine of power, and also the supreme
authority for power; in saints, finally a pretext for hibernation, their
novissima gloriĂŠ cupido, their peace in nothingness (âGodâ), their form
of madness.
But in the very fact that the ascetic ideal has meant so much to man,
lies expressed the fundamental feature of manâs will, his horror vacui:
he needs a goalâand he will sooner will nothingness than not will at
all.âAm I not understood?âHave I not been understood?ââCertainly not,
sir?ââWell, let us begin at the beginning.
2.
What is the meaning of ascetic ideals? Or, to take an individual case in
regard to which I have often been consulted, what is the meaning, for
example, of an artist like Richard Wagner paying homage to chastity in
his old age? He had always done so, of course, in a certain sense, but
it was not till quite the end, that he did so in an ascetic sense. What
is the meaning of this âchange of attitude,â this radical revolution in
his attitudeâfor that was what it was? Wagner veered thereby straight
round into his own opposite. What is the meaning of an artist veering
round into his own opposite? At this point (granted that we do not mind
stopping a little over this question), we immediately call to mind the
best, strongest, gayest, and boldest period, that there perhaps ever was
in Wagnerâs life: that was the period, when he was genuinely and deeply
occupied with the idea of âLutherâs Wedding.â Who knows what chance is
responsible for our now having the Meistersingers instead of this
wedding music? And how much in the latter is perhaps just an echo of the
former? But there is no doubt but that the theme would have dealt with
the praise of chastity. And certainly it would also have dealt with the
praise of sensuality, and even so, it would seem quite in order, and
even so, it would have been equally Wagnerian. For there is no necessary
antithesis between chastity and sensuality: every good marriage, every
authentic heart-felt love transcends this antithesis. Wagner would, it
seems to me, have done well to have brought this pleasing reality home
once again to his Germans, by means of a bold and graceful âLuther
Comedy,â for there were and are among the Germans many revilers of
sensuality; and perhaps Lutherâs greatest merit lies just in the fact of
his having had the courage of his sensuality (it used to be called,
prettily enough, âevangelistic freedom â). But even in those cases where
that antithesis between chastity and sensuality does exist, there has
fortunately been for some time no necessity for it to be in any way a
tragic antithesis. This should, at any rate, be the case with all beings
who are sound in mind and body, who are far from reckoning their
delicate balance between âanimalâ and âangel,â as being on the face of
it one of the principles opposed to existenceâthe most subtle and
brilliant spirits, such as Goethe, such as Hafiz, have even seen in this
a further charm of life. Such âconflictsâ actually allure one to life.
On the other hand, it is only too clear that when once these ruined
swine are reduced to worshipping chastityâand there are such swineâthey
only see and worship in it the antithesis to themselves, the antithesis
to ruined swine. Oh what a tragic grunting and eagerness! You can just
think of itâthey worship that painful and superfluous contrast, which
Richard Wagner in his latter days undoubtedly wished to set to music,
and to place on the stage! âFor what purpose, forsooth?â as we may
reasonably ask. What did the swine matter to him; what do they matter to
us?
3.
At this point it is impossible to beg the further question of what he
really had to do with that manly (ah, so unmanly) country bumpkin, that
poor devil and natural, Parsifal, whom he eventually made a Catholic by
such fraudulent devices. What? Was this Parsifal really meant seriously?
One might be tempted to suppose the contrary, even to wish itâthat the
Wagnerian Parsifal was meant joyously, like a concluding play of a
trilogy or satyric drama, in which Wagner the tragedian wished to take
farewell of us, of himself, above all of tragedy, and to do so in a
manner that should be quite fitting and worthy, that is, with an excess
of the most extreme and flippant parody of the tragic itself, of the
ghastly earthly seriousness and earthly woe of oldâa parody of that most
crude phase in the unnaturalness of the ascetic ideal, that had at
length been overcome. That, as I have said, would have been quite worthy
of a great tragedian; who like every artist first attains the supreme
pinnacle of his greatness when he can look down into himself and his
art, when he can laugh at himself. Is Wagnerâs Parsifal his secret laugh
of superiority over himself, the triumph of that supreme artistic
freedom and artistic transcendency which he has at length attained. We
might, I repeat, wish it were so, for what can Parsifal, taken
seriously, amount to? Is it really necessary to see in it (according to
an expression once used against me) the product of an insane hate of
knowledge, mind, and flesh? A curse on flesh and spirit in one breath of
hate? An apostasy and reversion to the morbid Christian and obscurantist
ideals? And finally a self-negation and self-elimination on the part of
an artist, who till then had devoted all the strength of his will to the
contrary, namely, the highest artistic expression of soul and body. And
not only of his art; of his life as well. Just remember with what
enthusiasm Wagner followed in the footsteps of Feuerbach. Feuerbachâs
motto of âhealthy sensualityâ rang in the ears of Wagner during the
thirties and forties of the century, as it did in the ears of many
Germans (they dubbed themselves âYoung Germansâ), like the word of
redemption. Did he eventually change his mind on the subject? For it
seems at any rate that he eventually wished to change his teaching on
that subject ... and not only is that the case with the Parsifal
trumpets on the stage: in the melancholy, cramped, and embarrassed
lucubrations of his later years, there are a hundred places in which
there are manifestations of a secret wish and will, a despondent,
uncertain, unavowed will to preach actual retrogression, conversion,
Christianity, mediĂŠvalism, and to say to his disciples, âAll is vanity!
Seek salvation elsewhere!â Even the âblood of the Redeemerâ is once
invoked.
4.
Let me speak out my mind in a case like this, which has many painful
elementsâand it is a typical case: it is certainly best to separate an
artist from his work so completely that he cannot be taken as seriously
as his work. He is after all merely the presupposition of his work, the
womb, the soil, in certain cases the dung and manure, on which and out
of which it growsâand consequently, in most cases, something that must
be forgotten if the work itself is to be enjoyed. The insight into the
origin of a work is a matter for psychologists and vivisectors, but
never either in the present or the future for the ĂŠsthetes, the artists.
The author and creator of Parsifal was as little spared the necessity of
sinking and living himself into the terrible depths and foundations of
mediĂŠval soul-contrasts, the necessity of a malignant abstraction from
all intellectual elevation, severity, and discipline, the necessity of a
kind of mental perversity (if the reader will pardon me such a word), as
little as a pregnant woman is spared the horrors and marvels of
pregnancy, which, as I have said, must be forgotten if the child is to
be enjoyed. We must guard ourselves against the confusion, into which an
artist himself would fall only too easily (to employ the English
terminology) out of psychological âcontiguityâ; as though the artist
himself actually were the object which he is able to represent, imagine,
and express. In point of fact, the position is that even if he conceived
he were such an object, he would certainly not represent, conceive,
express it. Homer would not have created an Achilles, nor Goethe a
Faust, if Homer had been an Achilles or if Goethe had been a Faust. A
complete and perfect artist is to all eternity separated from the
âreal,â from the actual; on the other hand, it will be appreciated that
he can at times get tired to the point of despair of this eternal
âunrealityâ and falseness of his innermost beingâand that he then
sometimes attempts to trespass on to the most forbidden ground, on
reality, and attempts to have real existence. With what success? The
success will be guessedâit is the typical velleity of the artist; the
same velleity to which Wagner fell a victim in his old age, and for
which he had to pay so dearly and so fatally (he lost thereby his most
valuable friends). But after all, quite apart from this velleity, who
would not wish emphatically for Wagnerâs own sake that he had taken
farewell of us and of his art in a different manner, not with a
Parsifal, but in more victorious, more self-confident, more Wagnerian
styleâa style less misleading, a style less ambiguous with regard to his
whole meaning, less Schopenhauerian, less Nihilistic?...
5.
What, then, is the meaning of ascetic ideals? In the case of an artist
we are getting to understand their meaning: Nothing at all ... or so
much that it is as good as nothing at all. Indeed, what is the use of
them? Our artists have for a long time past not taken up a sufficiently
independent attitude, either in the world or against it, to warrant
their valuations and the changes in these valuations exciting interest.
At all times they have played the valet of some morality, philosophy, or
religion, quite apart from the fact that unfortunately they have often
enough been the inordinately supple courtiers of their clients and
patrons, and the inquisitive toadies of the powers that are existing, or
even of the new powers to come. To put it at the lowest, they always
need a rampart, a support, an already constituted authority: artists
never stand by themselves, standing alone is opposed to their deepest
instincts. So, for example, did Richard Wagner take, âwhen the time had
come,â the philosopher Schopenhauer for his covering man in front, for
his rampart. Who would consider it even thinkable, that he would have
had the courage for an ascetic ideal, without the support afforded him
by the philosophy of Schopenhauer, without the authority of
Schopenhauer, which dominated Europe in the seventies? (This is without
consideration of the question whether an artist without the milk[5] of
an orthodoxy would have been possible at all.) This brings us to the
more serious question: What is the meaning of a real philosopher paying
homage to the ascetic ideal, a really self-dependent intellect like
Schopenhauer, a man and knight with a glance of bronze, who has the
courage to be himself, who knows how to stand alone without first
waiting for men who cover him in front, and the nods of his superiors?
Let us now consider at once the remarkable attitude of Schopenhauer
towards art, an attitude which has even a fascination for certain types.
For that is obviously the reason why Richard Wagner all at once went
over to Schopenhauer (persuaded thereto, as one knows, by a poet,
Herwegh), went over so completely that there ensued the cleavage of a
complete theoretic contradiction between his earlier and his later
ĂŠsthetic faithsâthe earlier, for example, being expressed in Opera and
Drama, the later in the writings which he published from 1870 onwards.
In particular, Wagner from that time onwards (and this is the volte-face
which alienates us the most) had no scruples about changing his judgment
concerning the value and position of music itself. What did he care if
up to that time he had made of music a means, a medium, a âwoman,â that
in order to thrive needed an end, a manâthat is, the drama? He suddenly
realised that more could be effected by the novelty of the
Schopenhauerian theory in majorem musicĂŠ gloriamâthat is to say, by
means of the sovereignty of music, as Schopenhauer understood it; music
abstracted from and opposed to all the other arts, music as the
independent art-in-itself, not like the other arts, affording
reflections of the phenomenal world, but rather the language of the will
itself, speaking straight out of the âabyssâ as its most personal,
original, and direct manifestation. This extraordinary rise in the value
of music (a rise which seemed to grow out of the Schopenhauerian
philosophy) was at once accompanied by an unprecedented rise in the
estimation in which the musician himself was held: he became now an
oracle, a priest, nay, more than a priest, a kind of mouthpiece for the
âintrinsic essence of things,â a telephone from the other worldâfrom
henceforward he talked not only music, did this ventriloquist of God, he
talked metaphysic; what wonder that one day he eventually talked ascetic
ideals.
6.
Schopenhauer has made use of the Kantian treatment of the ĂŠsthetic
problemâthough he certainly did not regard it with the Kantian eyes.
Kant thought that he showed honour to art when he favoured and placed in
the foreground those of the predicates of the beautiful, which
constitute the honour of knowledge: impersonality and universality. This
is not the place to discuss whether this was not a complete mistake; all
that I wish to emphasise is that Kant, just like other philosophers,
instead of envisaging the ĂŠsthetic problem from the standpoint of the
experiences of the artist (the creator), has only considered art and
beauty from the standpoint of the spectator, and has thereby
imperceptibly imported the spectator himself into the idea of the
âbeautifulâ! But if only the philosophers of the beautiful had
sufficient knowledge of this âspectatorâ!âKnowledge of him as a great
fact of personality, as a great experience, as a wealth of strong and
most individual events, desires, surprises, and raptures in the sphere
of beauty! But, as I feared, the contrary was always the case. And so we
get from our philosophers, from the very beginning, definitions on which
the lack of a subtler personal experience squats like a fat worm of
crass error, as it does on Kantâs famous definition of the beautiful.
âThat is beautiful,â says Kant, âwhich pleases without interesting.â
Without interesting! Compare this definition with this other one, made
by a real âspectatorâ and âartistââby Stendhal, who once called the
beautiful une promesse de bonheur. Here, at any rate, the one point
which Kant makes prominent in the ĂŠsthetic position is repudiated and
eliminatedâle dĂ©sintĂ©ressement. Who is right, Kant or Stendhal? When,
forsooth, our ĂŠsthetes never get tired of throwing into the scales in
Kantâs favour the fact that under the magic of beauty men can look at
even naked female statues âwithout interest,â we can certainly laugh a
little at their expense:âin regard to this ticklish point the
experiences of artists are more âinteresting,â and at any rate Pygmalion
was not necessarily an âunĂŠsthetic man.â Let us think all the better of
the innocence of our ĂŠsthetes, reflected as it is in such arguments; let
us, for instance, count to Kantâs honour the country-parson naĂŻvetĂ© of
his doctrine concerning the peculiar character of the sense of touch!
And here we come back to Schopenhauer, who stood in much closer
neighbourhood to the arts than did Kant, and yet never escaped outside
the pale of the Kantian definition; how was that? The circumstance is
marvellous enough: he interprets the expression, âwithout interest,â in
the most personal fashion, out of an experience which must in his case
have been part and parcel of his regular routine. On few subjects does
Schopenhauer speak with such certainty as on the working of ĂŠsthetic
contemplation: he says of it that it simply counteracts sexual interest,
like lupulin and camphor; he never gets tired of glorifying this escape
from the âLife-willâ as the great advantage and utility of the ĂŠsthetic
state. In fact, one is tempted to ask if his fundamental conception of
Will and Idea, the thought that there can only exist freedom from the
âwillâ by means of âidea,â did not originate in a generalisation from
this sexual experience. (In all questions concerning the Schopenhauerian
philosophy, one should, by the bye, never lose sight of the
consideration that it is the conception of a youth of twenty-six, so
that it participates not only in what is peculiar to Schopenhauerâs
life, but in what is peculiar to that special period of his life.) Let
us listen, for instance, to one of the most expressive among the
countless passages which he has written in honour of the ĂŠsthetic state
(World as Will and Idea, i. 231); let us listen to the tone, the
suffering, the happiness, the gratitude, with which such words are
uttered: âThis is the painless state which Epicurus praised as the
highest good and as the state of the gods; we are during that moment
freed from the vile pressure of the will, we celebrate the Sabbath of
the willâs hard labour, the wheel of Ixion stands still.â What vehemence
of language! What images of anguish and protracted revulsion! How almost
pathological is that temporal antithesis between âthat momentâ and
everything else, the âwheel of Ixion,â âthe hard labour of the will,â
âthe vile pressure of the will.â But granted that Schopenhauer was a
hundred times right for himself personally, how does that help our
insight into the nature of the beautiful? Schopenhauer has described one
effect of the beautiful,âthe calming of the will,âbut is this effect
really normal? As has been mentioned, Stendhal, an equally sensual but
more happily constituted nature than Schopenhauer, gives prominence to
another effect of the âbeautiful.â âThe beautiful promises happiness.â
To him it is just the excitement of the âwillâ (the âinterestâ) by the
beauty that seems the essential fact. And does not Schopenhauer
ultimately lay himself open to the objection, that he is quite wrong in
regarding himself as a Kantian on this point, that he has absolutely
failed to understand in a Kantian sense the Kantian definition of the
beautifulâ;that the beautiful pleased him as well by means of an
interest, by means, in fact, of the strongest and most personal interest
of all, that: of the victim of torture who escapes from his torture?âAnd
to come back again to our first question, âWhat is the meaning of a
philosopher paying homage to ascetic ideals?â We get now, at any rate, a
first hint; he wishes to escape from a torture.
7.
Let us beware of making dismal faces at the word âtortureââthere is
certainly in this case enough to deduct, enough to discountâthere is
even something to laugh at. For we must certainly not underestimate the
fact that Schopenhauer, who in practice treated sexuality as a personal
enemy (including its tool, woman, that âinstrumentum diaboliâ), needed
enemies to keep him in a good humour; that he loved grim, bitter,
blackish-green words; that he raged for the sake of raging, out of
passion; that he would have grown ill, would have become a pessimist
(for he was not a pessimist, however much he wished to be), without his
enemies, without Hegel, woman, sensuality, and the whole âwill for
existenceâ âkeeping on.â Without them Schopenhauer would not have âkept
on,â that is a safe wager; he would have run away: but his enemies held
him fast, his enemies always enticed him back again to existence, his
wrath was just as theirsâ was to the ancient Cynics, his balm, his
recreation, his recompense, his remedium against disgust, his happiness.
So much with regard to what is most personal in the case of
Schopenhauer; on the other hand, there is still much which is typical in
himâand only now we come back to our problem. It is an accepted and
indisputable fact, so long as there are philosophers in the world and
wherever philosophers have existed (from India to England, to take the
opposite poles of philosophic ability), that there exists a real
irritation and rancour on the part of philosophers towards sensuality.
Schopenhauer is merely the most eloquent, and if one has the ear for it,
also the most fascinating and enchanting outburst. There similarly
exists a real philosophic bias and affection for the whole ascetic
ideal; there should be no illusions on this score. Both these feelings,
as has been said, belong to the type; if a philosopher lacks both of
them, then he isâyou may be certain of itânever anything but a âpseudo.â
What does this mean? For this state of affairs must first be,
interpreted: in itself it stands there stupid, to all eternity, like any
âThing-in-itself.â Every animal, including la bĂȘte philosophe, strives
instinctively after an optimum of favourable conditions, under which he
can let his whole strength have play, and achieves his maximum
consciousness of power; with equal instinctiveness, and with a fine
perceptive flair which is superior to any reason, every animal shudders
mortally at every kind of disturbance and hindrance which obstructs or
could obstruct his way to that optimum (it is not his way to happiness
of which I am talking, but his way to power, to action, the most
powerful action, and in point of fact in many cases his way to
unhappiness). Similarly, the philosopher shudders mortally at marriage,
together with all that could persuade him to itâmarriage as a fatal
hindrance on the way to the optimum. Up to the present what great
philosophers have been married? Heracleitus, Plato, Descartes, Spinoza,
Leibnitz, Kant, Schopenhauerâthey were not married, and, further, one
cannot imagine them as married. A married philosopher belongs to comedy,
that is my rule; as for that exception of a Socratesâthe malicious
Socrates married himself, it seems, ironice, just to prove this very
rule. Every philosopher would say, as Buddha said, when the birth of a
son was announced to him: âRĂąhoula has been born to me, a fetter has
been forged for meâ (RĂąhoula means here âa little demonâ); there must
come an hour of reflection to every âfree spiritâ (granted that he has
had previously an hour of thoughtlessness), just as one came once to the
same Buddha: âNarrowly cramped,â he reflected, âis life in the house; it
is a place of uncleanness; freedom is found in leaving the house.â
Because he thought like this, he left the house. So many bridges to
independence are shown in the ascetic idea], that the philosopher cannot
refrain from exultation and clapping of hands when he hears the history
of all those resolute ones, who on one day uttered a nay to all
servitude and went into some desert; even granting that they were only
strong asses, and the absolute opposite of strong minds. What, then,
does the ascetic ideal mean in a philosopher? This is my answerâit will
have been guessed long ago: when he sees this ideal the philosopher
smiles because he sees therein an optimum of the conditions of the
highest and boldest intellectuality; he does not thereby deny
âexistence,â he rather affirms thereby his existence and only his
existence, and this perhaps to the point of not being far off the
blasphemous wish, pereat mundus, fiat philosophia, fiat philosophus,
fiam!
8.
These philosophers, you see, are by no means uncorrupted witnesses and
judges of the value of the ascetic ideal. They think of themselves âwhat
is the âsaintâ to them? They think of that which to them personally is
most indispensable; of freedom from compulsion, disturbance, noise:
freedom from business, duties, cares; of clear head; of the dance,
spring, and flight of thoughts; of good airârare, clear, free, dry, as
is the air on the heights, in which every animal creature becomes more
intellectual and gains wings; they think of peace in every cellar; all
the hounds neatly chained; no baying of enmity and uncouth rancour; no
remorse of wounded ambition; quiet and submissive internal organs, busy
as mills, but unnoticed; the heart alien, transcendent, future,
posthumousâto summarise, they mean by the ascetic ideal the joyous
asceticism of a deified and newly fledged animal, sweeping over life
rather than resting. We know what are the three great catch-words of the
ascetic ideal: poverty, humility, chastity; and now just look closely at
the life of all the great fruitful inventive spiritsâyou will always
find again and again these three qualities up to a certain extent. Not
for a minute, as is self-evident, as though, perchance, they were part
of their virtuesâwhat has this type of man to do with virtues?âbut as
the most essential and natural conditions of their best existence, their
finest fruitfulness. In this connection it is quite possible that their
predominant intellectualism had first to curb an unruly and irritable
pride, or an insolent sensualism, or that it had all its work cut out to
maintain its wish for the âdesertâ against perhaps an inclination to
luxury and dilettantism, or similarly against an extravagant liberality
of heart and hand. But their intellect did effect all this, simply
because it was the dominant instinct, which carried through its orders
in the case of all the other instincts. It effects it still; if it
ceased to do so, it would simply not be dominant. But there is not one
iota of âvirtueâ in all this. Further, the desert, of which I just
spoke, in which the strong, independent, and well-equipped spirits
retreat into their hermitageâoh, how different is it from the cultured
classesâ dream of a desert! In certain cases, in fact, the cultured
classes themselves are the desert. And it is certain that all the actors
of the intellect would not endure this desert for a minute. It is
nothing like romantic and Syrian enough for them, nothing like enough of
a stage desert! Here as well there are plenty of asses, but at this
point the resemblance ceases. But a desert nowadays is something like
thisâperhaps a deliberate obscurity; a getting-out-of the way of oneâs
self; a fear of noise, admiration, papers, influence; a little office, a
daily task, something that hides rather than brings to light; sometimes
associating with harmless, cheerful beasts and fowls, the sight of which
refreshes; a mountain for company, but not a dead one, one with eyes
(that is, with lakes); in certain cases even a room in a crowded hotel
where one can reckon on not being recognised, and on being able to talk
with impunity to every one: here is the desertâoh, it is lonely enough,
believe me! I grant that when Heracleitus retreated to the courts and
cloisters of the colossal temple of Artemis, that âwildernessâ was
worthier; why do we lack such temples? (perchance we do not lack them: I
just think of my splendid study in the Piazza di San Marco, in spring,
of course, and in the morning, between ten and twelve). But that which
Heracleitus shunned is still just what we too avoid nowadays: the noise
and democratic babble of the Ephesians, their politics, their news from
the âempireâ (I mean, of course, Persia), their market-trade in âthe
things of to-day ââfor there is one thing from which we philosophers
especially need a restâfrom the things of âto-day.â We honour the
silent, the cold, the noble, the far, the past, everything, in fact, at
the sight of which the soul is not bound to brace itself up and defend
itselfâsomething with which one can speak without speaking aloud. Just
listen now to the tone a spirit has when it speaks; every spirit has its
own tone and loves its own tone. That thing yonder, for instance, is
bound to be an agitator, that is, a hollow head, a hollow mug: whatever
may go into him, everything comes back from him dull and thick, heavy
with the echo of the great void. That spirit yonder nearly always speaks
hoarse: has he, perchance, thought himself hoarse? It may be soâask the
physiologistsâbut he who thinks in words, thinks as a speaker and not as
a thinker (it shows that he does not think of objects or think
objectively, but only of his relations with objectsâthat, in point of
fact, he only thinks of himself and his audience). This third one speaks
aggressively, he comes too near our body, his breath blows on usâwe shut
our mouth involuntarily, although he speaks to us through a book: the
tone of his style supplies the reasonâhe has no time, he has small faith
in himself, he finds expression now or never. But a spirit who is sure
of himself speaks softly; he seeks secrecy, he lets himself be awaited,
A philosopher is recognised by the fact that he shuns three brilliant
and noisy thingsâfame, princes, and women: which is not to say that they
do not come to him. He shuns every glaring light: therefore he shuns his
time and its âdaylight.â Therein he is as a shadow; the deeper sinks the
sun, the greater grows the shadow. As for his humility, he endures, as
he endures darkness, a certain dependence and obscurity: further, he is
afraid of the shock of lightning, he shudders at the insecurity of a
tree which is too isolated and too exposed, on which every storm vents
its temper, every temper its storm. His âmaternalâ instinct, his secret
love for that which grows in him, guides him into states where he is
relieved from the necessity of taking care of himself, in the same way
in which the âmotherâ instinct in woman has thoroughly maintained up to
the present womanâs dependent position. After all, they demand little
enough, do these philosophers, their favourite motto is, âHe who
possesses is possessed.â All this is not, as I must say again and again,
to be attributed to a virtue, to a meritorious wish for moderation and
simplicity; but because their supreme lord so demands of them, demands
wisely and inexorably; their lord who is eager only for one thing, for
which alone he musters, and for which alone he hoards everythingâtime,
strength, love, interest. This kind of man likes not to be disturbed by
enmity, he likes not to be disturbed by friendship, it is a type which
forgets or despises easily. It strikes him as bad form to play the
martyr, âto suffer for truthââhe leaves all that to the ambitious and to
the stage-heroes of the intellect, and to all those, in fact, who have
time enough for such luxuries (they themselves, the philosophers, have
something to do for truth). They make a sparing use of big words; they
are said to be adverse to the word âtruthâ itself: it has a âhigh
falutinââ ring. Finally, as far as the chastity of philosophers is
concerned, the fruitfulness of this type of mind is manifestly in
another sphere than that of children; perchance in some other sphere,
too, they have the survival of their name, their little immortality
(philosophers in ancient India would express themselves with still
greater boldness: âOf what use is posterity to him whose soul is the
world?â). In this attitude there is not a trace of chastity, by reason
of any ascetic scruple or hatred of the flesh, any more than it is
chastity for an athlete or a jockey to abstain from women; it is rather
the will of the dominant instinct, at any rate, during the period of
their advanced philosophic pregnancy. Every artist knows the harm done
by sexual intercourse on occasions of great mental strain and
preparation; as far as the strongest artists and those with the surest
instincts are concerned, this is not necessarily a case of
experienceâhard experienceâbut it is simply their âmaternalâ instinct
which, in order to benefit the growing work, disposes recklessly (beyond
all its normal stocks and supplies) of the vigour of its animal life;
the greater power then absorbs the lesser. Let us now apply this
interpretation to gauge correctly the case of Schopenhauer, which we
have already mentioned: in his case, the sight of the beautiful acted
manifestly like a resolving irritant on the chief power of his nature
(the power of contemplation and of intense penetration); so that this
strength exploded and became suddenly master of his consciousness. But
this by no means excludes the possibility of that particular sweetness
and fulness, which is peculiar to the ĂŠsthetic state, springing directly
from the ingredient of sensuality (just as that âidealismâ which is
peculiar to girls at puberty originates in the same source)âit may be,
consequently, that sensuality is not removed by the approach of the
ĂŠsthetic state, as Schopenhauer believed, but merely becomes
transfigured, and ceases to enter into the consciousness as sexual
excitement. (I shall return once again to this point in connection with
the more delicate problems of the physiology of the ĂŠsthetic, a subject
which up to the present has been singularly untouched and unelucidated.)
9.
A certain asceticism, a grimly gay whole-hearted renunciation, is, as we
have seen, one of the most favourable conditions for the highest
intellectualism, and, consequently, for the most natural corollaries of
such intellectualism: we shall therefore be proof against any surprise
at the philosophers in particular always treating the ascetic ideal with
a certain amount of predilection. A serious historical investigation
shows the bond between the ascetic ideal and philosophy to be still much
tighter and still much stronger. It may be said that it was only in the
leading strings of this ideal that philosophy really learnt to make its
first steps and baby pacesâalas how clumsily, alas how crossly, alas how
ready to tumble down and lie on its stomach was this shy little darling
of a brat with its bandy legs! The early history of philosophy is like
that of all good things;âfor a long time they had not the courage to be
themselves, they kept always looking round to see if no one would come
to their help; further, they were afraid of all who looked at them. Just
enumerate in order the particular tendencies and virtues of the
philosopherâhis tendency to doubt, his tendency to deny, his tendency to
wait (to be âephecticâ), his tendency to analyse, search, explore, dare,
his tendency to compare and to equalise, his will to be neutral and
objective, his will for everything which is âsine ira et studioâ:âhas it
yet been realised that for quite a lengthy period these tendencies went
counter to the first claims of morality and conscience? (To say nothing
at all of Reason, which even Luther chose to call Frau KlĂŒglin,[6] the
sly whore.) Has it been yet appreciated that a philosopher, in the event
of his arriving at self-consciousness, must needs feel himself an
incarnate ânitimur in vetitumââand consequently guard himself against
âhis own sensations,â against self-consciousness? It is, I repeat, just
the same with all good things, on which we now pride ourselves; even
judged by the standard of the ancient Greeks, our whole modern life, in
so far as it is not weakness, but power and the consciousness of power,
appears pure âHybrisâ and godlessness: for the things which are the very
reverse of those which we honour to-day, have had for a long time
conscience on their side, and God as their guardian. âHybrisâ is our
whole attitude to nature nowadays, our violation of nature with the help
of machinery, and all the unscrupulous ingenuity of our scientists and
engineers. âHybrisâ is our attitude to God, that is, to some alleged
teleological and ethical spider behind the meshes of the great trap of
the causal web. Like Charles the Bold in his war with Louis the
Eleventh, we may say, âje combats lâuniverselle araignĂ©eâ; âHybrisâ is
our attitude to ourselvesâfor we experiment with ourselves in a way that
we would not allow with any animal, and with pleasure and curiosity open
our soul in our living body: what matters now to us the âsalvationâ of
the soul? We heal ourselves afterwards: being ill is instructive, we
doubt it not, even more instructive than being wellâinoculators of
disease seem to us to-day even more necessary than any medicine-men and
âsaviours.â There is no doubt we do violence to ourselves nowadays, we
crackers of the soulâs kernel, we incarnate riddles, who are ever asking
riddles, as though life were naught else than the cracking of a nut; and
even thereby must we necessarily become day by day more and more worthy
to be asked questions and worthy to ask them, even thereby do we
perchance also become worthier toâlive?
... All good things were once bad things; from every original sin has
grown an original virtue. Marriage, for example, seemed for a long time
a sin against the rights of the community; a man formerly paid a fine
for the insolence of claiming one woman to himself (to this phase
belongs, for instance, the jus primĂŠ noctis, to-day still in Cambodia
the privilege of the priest, that guardian of the âgood old customsâ).
The soft, benevolent, yielding, sympathetic feelingsâeventually valued
so highly that they almost became âintrinsic values,â were for a very
long time actually despised by their possessors: gentleness was then a
subject for shame, just as hardness is now (compare Beyond Good and
Evil, Aph. 260). The submission to law: oh, with what qualms of
conscience was it that the noble races throughout the world renounced
the vendetta and gave the law power over themselves! Law was long a
vetitum, a blasphemy, an innovation; it was introduced with force, like
a force, to which men only submitted with a sense of personal shame.
Every tiny step forward in the world was formerly made at the cost of
mental and physical torture. Nowadays the whole of this point of
viewââthat not only stepping forward, nay, stepping at all, movement,
change, all needed their countless martyrs,â rings in our ears quite
strangely. I have put it forward in the Dawn of Day, Aph. 18. âNothing
is purchased more dearly,â says the same book a little later, âthan the
modicum of human reason and freedom which is now our pride. But that
pride is the reason why it is now almost impossible for us to feel in
sympathy with those immense periods of the âMorality of Custom,â which
lie at the beginning of the âworldâs history,â constituting as they do
the real decisive historical principle which has fixed the character of
humanity; those periods, I repeat, when throughout the world suffering
passed for virtue, cruelty for virtue, deceit for virtue, revenge for
virtue, repudiation of the reason for virtue; and when, conversely,
well-being passed current for danger, the desire for knowledge for
danger, pity for danger, peace for danger, being pitied for shame, work
for shame, madness for divinity, and change for immorality and incarnate
corruption!â
10.
There is in the same book, Aph. 12, an explanation of the burden of
unpopularity under which the earliest race of contemplative men had to
liveâdespised almost as widely as they were first feared! Contemplation
first appeared on earth in a disguised shape, in an ambiguous form, with
an evil heart and often with an uneasy head: there is no doubt about it.
The inactive, brooding, unwarlike element in the instincts of
contemplative men long invested them with a cloud of suspicion: the only
way to combat this was to excite a definite fear. And the old Brahmans,
for example, knew to a nicety how to do this! The oldest philosophers
were well versed in giving to their very existence and appearance,
meaning, firmness, background, by reason whereof men learnt to fear
them; considered more precisely, they did this from an even more
fundamental need, the need of inspiring in themselves fear and
self-reverence. For they found even in their own souls all the
valuations turned against themselves; they had to fight down every kind
of suspicion and antagonism against âthe philosophic element in
themselves.â Being men of a terrible age, they did this with terrible
means: cruelty to themselves, ingenious self-mortificationâthis was the
chief method of these ambitious hermits and intellectual
revolutionaries, who were obliged to force down the gods and the
traditions of their own soul, so as to enable themselves to believe in
their own revolution. I remember the famous story of the King
Vicvamitra, who, as the result of a thousand years of self-martyrdom,
reached such a consciousness of power and such a confidence in himself
that he undertook to build a new heaven: the sinister symbol of the
oldest and newest history of philosophy in the whole world. Every one
who has ever built anywhere a ânew heavenâ first found the power thereto
in his own hell.... Let us compress the facts into a short formula. The
philosophic spirit had, in order to be possible to any extent at all, to
masquerade and disguise itself as one of the previously fixed types of
the contemplative man, to disguise itself as priest, wizard, soothsayer,
as a religious man generally: the ascetic ideal has for a long time
served the philosopher as a superficial form, as a condition which
enabled him to exist.... To be able to be a philosopher he had to
exemplify the ideal; to exemplify it, he was bound to believe in it. The
peculiarly etherealised abstraction of philosophers, with their negation
of the world, their enmity to life, their disbelief in the senses, which
has been maintained up to the most recent time, and has almost thereby
come to be accepted as the ideal philosophic attitudeâthis abstraction
is the result of those enforced conditions under which philosophy came
into existence, and continued to exist; inasmuch as for quite a very
long time philosophy would have been absolutely impossible in the world
without an ascetic cloak and dress, without an ascetic
self-misunderstanding. Expressed plainly and palpably, the ascetic
priest has taken the repulsive and sinister form of the caterpillar,
beneath which and behind which alone philosophy could live and slink
about....
Has all that really changed? Has that flamboyant and dangerous winged
creature, that âspiritâ which that caterpillar concealed within itself,
has it, I say, thanks to a sunnier, warmer, lighter world, really and
finally flung off its hood and escaped into the light? Can we to-day
point to enough pride, enough daring, enough courage, enough
self-confidence, enough mental will, enough will for responsibility,
enough freedom of the will, to enable the philosopher to be now in the
world reallyâpossible?
11.
And now, after we have caught sight of the ascetic priest, let us tackle
our problem. What is the meaning of the ascetic ideal? It now first
becomes seriousâvitally serious. We are now confronted with the real
representatives of the serious. âWhat is the meaning of all
seriousness?â This even more radical question is perchance already on
the tip of our tongue: a question, fairly, for physiologists, but which
we for the time being skip. In that ideal the ascetic priest finds not
only his faith, but also his will, his power, his interest. His right to
existence stands and falls with that ideal. What wonder that we here run
up against a terrible opponent (on the supposition, of course, that we
are the opponents of that ideal), an opponent fighting for his life
against those who repudiate that ideal!... On the other hand, it is from
the outset improbable that such a biased attitude towards our problem
will do him any particular good; the ascetic priest himself will
scarcely prove the happiest champion of his own ideal (on the same
principle on which a woman usually fails when she wishes to champion
âwomanâ)âlet alone proving the most objective critic and judge of the
controversy now raised. We shall thereforeâso much is already
obviousârather have actually to help him to defend himself properly
against ourselves, than we shall have to fear being too well beaten by
him. The idea, which is the subject of this dispute, is the value of our
life from the standpoint of the ascetic priests: this life, then
(together with the whole of which it is a part, âNature,â âthe world,â
the whole sphere of becoming and passing away), is placed by them in
relation to an existence of quite another character, which it excludes
and to which it is opposed, unless it deny its own self: in this case,
the case of an ascetic life, life is taken as a bridge to another
existence. The ascetic treats life as a maze, in which one must walk
backwards till one comes to the place where it starts; or he treats it
as an error which one may, nay must, refute by action: for he demands
that he should be followed; he enforces, where he can, his valuation of
existence. What does this mean? Such a monstrous valuation is not an
exceptional case, or a curiosity recorded in human history: it is one of
the most general and persistent facts that there are. The reading from
the vantage of a distant star of the capital letters of our earthly
life, would perchance lead to the conclusion that the earth was the
especially ascetic planet, a den of discontented, arrogant, and
repulsive creatures, who never got rid of a deep disgust of themselves,
of the world, of all life, and did themselves as much hurt as possible
out of pleasure in hurtingâpresumably their one and only pleasure. Let
us consider how regularly, how universally, how practically at every
single period the ascetic priest puts in his appearance: he belongs to
no particular race; he thrives everywhere; he grows out of all classes.
Not that he perhaps bred this valuation by heredity and propagated
itâthe contrary is the case. It must be a necessity of the first order
which makes this species, hostile, as it is, to life, always grow again
and always thrive again.âLife itself must certainly have an interest in
the continuance of such a type of self-contradiction. For an ascetic
life is a self-contradiction: here rules resentment without parallel,
the resentment of an insatiate instinct and ambition, that would be
master, not over some element in life, but over life itself, over lifeâs
deepest, strongest, innermost conditions; here is an attempt made to
utilise power to dam the sources of power; here does the green eye of
jealousy turn even against physiological well-being, especially against
the expression of such well-being, beauty, joy; while a sense of
pleasure is experienced and sought in abortion, in decay, in pain, in
misfortune, in ugliness, in voluntary punishment, in the exercising,
flagellation, and sacrifice of the self. All this is in the highest
degree paradoxical: we are here confronted with a rift that wills itself
to be a rift, which enjoys itself in this very suffering, and even
becomes more and more certain of itself, more and more triumphant, in
proportion as its own presupposition, physiological vitality, decreases.
âThe triumph just in the supreme agony:â under this extravagant emblem
did the ascetic ideal fight from of old; in this mystery of seduction,
in this picture of rapture and torture, it recognised its brightest
light, its salvation, its final victory. Crux, nux, luxâit has all these
three in one.
12.
Granted that such an incarnate will for contradiction and unnaturalness
is induced to philosophise; on what will it vent its pet caprice? On
that which has been felt with the greatest certainty to be true, to be
real; it will look for error in those very places where the life
instinct fixes truth with the greatest positiveness. It will, for
instance, after the example of the ascetics of the Vedanta Philosophy,
reduce matter to an illusion, and similarly treat pain, multiplicity,
the whole logical contrast of âSubjectâ and âObjectââerrors, nothing but
errors! To renounce the belief in oneâs own ego, to deny to oneâs self
oneâs own ârealityââwhat a triumph! and here already we have a much
higher kind of triumph, which is not merely a triumph over the senses,
over the palpable, but an infliction of violence and cruelty on reason;
and this ecstasy culminates in the ascetic self-contempt, the ascetic
scorn of oneâs own reason making this decree: there is a domain of truth
and of life, but reason is specially excluded therefrom.... By the bye,
even in the Kantian idea of âthe intellegible character of thingsâ there
remains a trace of that schism, so dear to the heart of the ascetic,
that schism which likes to turn reason against reason; in fact,
âintelligible characterâ means in Kant a kind of quality in things of
which the intellect comprehends this much, that for it, the intellect,
it is absolutely incomprehensible. After all, let us, in our character
of knowers, not be ungrateful towards such determined reversals of the
ordinary perspectives and values, with which the mind had for too long
raged against itself with an apparently futile sacrilege! In the same
way the very seeing of another vista, the very wishing to see another
vista, is no little training and preparation of the intellect for its
eternal âObjectivityââobjectivity being understood not as âcontemplation
without interestâ (for that is inconceivable and non-sensical), but as
the ability to have the pros and cons in oneâs power and to switch them
on and off, so as to get to know how to utilise, for the advancement of
knowledge, the difference in the perspective and in the emotional
interpretations. But let us, forsooth, my philosophic colleagues,
henceforward guard ourselves more carefully against this mythology of
dangerous ancient ideas, which has set up a âpure, will-less, painless,
timeless subject of knowledgeâ; let us guard ourselves from the
tentacles of such contradictory ideas as âpure reason,â âabsolute
spirituality,â âknowledge-in-itselfâ:âin these theories an eye that
cannot be thought of is required to think, an eye which ex hypothesi has
no direction at all, an eye in which the active and interpreting
functions are cramped, are absent; those functions, I say, by means of
which âabstractâ seeing first became seeing something; in these theories
consequently the absurd and the non-sensical is always demanded of the
eye. There is only a seeing from a perspective, only a âknowingâ from a
perspective, and the more emotions we express over a thing, the more
eyes, different eyes, we train on the same thing, the more complete will
be our âideaâ of that thing, our âobjectivity.â But the elimination of
the will altogether, the switching off of the emotions all and sundry,
granted that we could do so, what! would not that be called intellectual
castration?
13.
But let us turn back. Such a self-contradiction, as apparently manifests
itself among the ascetics, âLife turned against Life,â isâthis much is
absolutely obviousâfrom the physiological and not now from the
psychological standpoint, simply nonsense. It can only be an apparent
contradiction; it must be a kind of provisional expression, an
explanation, a formula, an adjustment, a psychological misunderstanding
of something, whose real nature could not be understood for a long time,
and whose real essence could not be described; a mere word jammed into
an old gap of human knowledge. To put briefly the facts against its
being real: the ascetic ideal springs from the prophylactic and
self-preservative instincts which mark a decadent life, which seeks by
every means in its power to maintain its position and fight for its
existence; it points to a partial physiological depression and
exhaustion, against which the most profound and intact life-instincts
fight ceaselessly with new weapons and discoveries. The ascetic ideal is
such a weapon: its position is consequently exactly the reverse of that
which the worshippers of the ideal imagineâlife struggles in it and
through it with death and against death; the ascetic ideal is a dodge
for the preservation of life. An important fact is brought out in the
extent to which, as history teaches, this ideal could rule and exercise
power over man, especially in all those places where the civilisation
and taming of man was completed: that fact is, the diseased state of man
up to the present, at any rate, of the man who has been tamed, the
physiological struggle of man with death (more precisely, with the
disgust with life, with exhaustion, with the wish for the âendâ). The
ascetic priest is the incarnate wish for an existence of another kind,
an existence on another plane,âhe is, in fact, the highest point of this
wish, its official ecstasy and passion: but it is the very power of this
wish which is the fetter that binds him here; it is just that which
makes him into a tool that must labour to create more favourable
conditions for earthly existence, for existence on the human planeâit is
with this very power that he keeps the whole herd of failures,
distortions, abortions, unfortunates, sufferers from themselves of every
kind, fast to existence, while he as the herdsman goes instinctively on
in front. You understand me already: this ascetic priest, this apparent
enemy of life, this denierâhe actually belongs to the really great
conservative and affirmative forces of life.... What does it come from,
this diseased state? For man is more diseased, more uncertain, more
changeable, more unstable than any other animal, there is no doubt of
itâhe is the diseased animal: what does it spring from? Certainly he has
also dared, innovated, braved more, challenged fate more than all the
other animals put together; he, the great experimenter with himself, the
unsatisfied, the insatiate, who struggles for the supreme mastery with
beast, Nature, and gods, he, the as yet ever uncompelled, the ever
future, who finds no more any rest from his own aggressive strength,
goaded inexorably on by the spur of the future dug into the flesh of the
present:âhow should not so brave and rich an animal also be the most
endangered, the animal with the longest and deepest sickness among all
sick animals?... Man is sick of it, oft enough there are whole epidemics
of this satiety (as about 1348, the time of the Dance of Death): but
even this very nausea, this tiredness, this disgust with himself, all
this is discharged from him with such force that it is immediately made
into a new fetter. His ânay,â which he utters to life, brings to light
as though by magic an abundance of graceful âyeasâ; even when he wounds
himself, this master of destruction, of self-destruction, it is
subsequently the wound itself that forces him to live.
14.
The more normal is this sickliness in manâand we cannot dispute this
normalityâthe higher honour should be paid to the rare cases of
psychical and physical powerfulness, the windfalls of humanity, and the
more strictly should the sound be guarded from that worst of air, the
air of the sick-room. Is that done? The sick are the greatest danger for
the healthy; it is not from the strongest that harm comes to the strong,
but from the weakest. Is that known? Broadly considered, it is not for a
minute the fear of man, whose diminution should be wished for; for this
fear forces the strong to be strong, to be at times terribleâit
preserves in its integrity the sound type of man. What is to be feared,
what does work with a fatality found in no other fate, is not the great
fear of, but the great nausea with, man; and equally so the great pity
for man. Supposing that both these things were one day to espouse each
other, then inevitably the maximum of monstrousness would immediately
come into the worldâthe âlast willâ of man, his will for nothingness,
Nihilism. And, in sooth, the way is well paved thereto. He who not only
has his nose to smell with, but also has eyes and ears, he sniffs almost
wherever he goes to-day an air something like that of a mad-house, the
air of a hospitalâI am speaking, as stands to reason, of the cultured
areas of mankind, of every kind of âEuropeâ that there is in fact in the
world. The sick are the great danger of man, not the evil, not the
âbeasts of prey.â They who are from the outset botched, oppressed,
broken, those are they, the weakest are they, who most undermine the
life beneath the feet of man, who instil the most dangerous venom and
scepticism into our trust in life, in man, in ourselves. Where shall we
escape from it, from that covert look (from which we carry away a deep
sadness), from that averted look of him who is misborn from the
beginning, that look which betrays what such a man says to himselfâthat
look which is a groan?â Would that I were something else,â so groans
this look, âbut there is no hope. I am what I am: how could I get away
from myself? And, verilyâI am sick of myself!â On such a soil of
self-contempt, a veritable swamp soil, grows that weed, that poisonous
growth, and all so tiny, so hidden, so ignoble, so sugary. Here teem the
worms of revenge and vindictiveness; here the air reeks of things secret
and unmentionable; here is ever spun the net of the most malignant
conspiracyâthe conspiracy of the sufferers against the sound and the
victorious; here is the sight of the victorious hated. And what lying so
as not to acknowledge this hate as hate! What a show of big words and
attitudes, what an art of ârighteousâ calumniation! These abortions!
what a noble eloquence gushes from their lips! What an amount of sugary,
slimy, humble submission oozes in their eyes! What do they really want?
At any rate to represent righteousness ness, love, wisdom, superiority,
that is the ambition of these âlowest ones,â these sick ones! And how
clever does such an ambition make them! You cannot, in fact, but admire
the counterfeiter dexterity with which the stamp of virtue, even the
ring, the golden ring of virtue, is here imitated. They have taken a
lease of virtue absolutely for themselves, have these weaklings and
wretched invalids, there is no doubt of it; âWe alone are the good, the
righteous,â so do they speak, âwe alone are the homines bonĂŠ
voluntatis.â They stalk about in our midst as living reproaches, as
warnings to usâas though health, fitness, strength, pride, the sensation
of power, were really vicious things in themselves, for which one would
have some day to do penance, bitter penance. Oh, how they themselves are
ready in their hearts to exact penance, how they thirst after being
hangmen!
Among them is an abundance of revengeful ones disguised as judges, who
ever mouth the word righteousness like a venomous spittleâwith mouth, I
say, always pursed, always ready to spit at everything, which does not
wear a discontented look, but is of good cheer as it goes on its way.
Among them, again, is that most loathsome species of the vain, the lying
abortions, who make a point of representing âbeautiful souls,â and
perchance of bringing to the market as âpurity of heartâ their distorted
sensualism swathed in verses and other bandages; the species of
âself-comfortersâ and masturbators of their own souls. The sick manâs
will to represent some form or other of superiority, his instinct for
crooked paths, which lead to a tyranny over the healthyâwhere can it not
be found, this will to power of the very weakest? The sick woman
especially: no one surpasses her in refinements for ruling, oppressing,
tyrannising. The sick woman, moreover, spares nothing living, nothing
dead; she grubs up again the most buried things (the Bogos say, âWoman
is a hyenaâ). Look into the background of every family, of every body,
of every community: everywhere the fight of the sick against the
healthyâa silent fight for the most part with minute poisoned powders,
with pin-pricks, with spiteful grimaces of patience, but also at times
with that diseased pharisaism of pure pantomime, which plays for choice
the rĂŽle of ârighteous indignation.â Right into the hallowed chambers of
knowledge can it make itself heard, can this hoarse yelping of sick
hounds, this rabid lying and frenzy of such ânobleâ Pharisees (I remind
readers, who have ears, once more of that Berlin apostle of revenge,
Eugen DĂŒhring, who makes the most disreputable and revolting use in all
present-day Germany of moral refuse; DĂŒhring, the paramount moral
blusterer that there is to-day, even among his own kidney, the
Anti-Semites). They are all men of resentment, are these physiological
distortions and worm-riddled objects, a whole quivering kingdom of
burrowing revenge, indefatigable and insatiable in its outbursts against
the happy, and equally so in disguises for revenge, in pretexts for
revenge: when will they really reach their final, fondest, most sublime
triumph of revenge? At that time, doubtless, when they succeed in
pushing their own misery, in fact, all misery, into the consciousness of
the happy; so that the latter begin one day to be ashamed of their
happiness, and perchance say to themselves when they meet, âIt is a
shame to be happy! there is too much misery!â ... But there could not
possibly be a greater and more fatal misunderstanding than that of the
happy, the fit, the strong in body and soul, beginning in this way to
doubt their right to happiness. Away with this âperverse worldâ! Away
with this shameful soddenness of sentiment! Preventing the sick making
the healthy sickâfor that is what such a soddenness comes toâthis ought
to be our supreme object in the worldâbut for this it is above all
essential that the healthy should remain separated from the sick, that
they should even guard themselves from the look of the sick, that they
should not even associate with the sick. Or may it, perchance, be their
mission to be nurses or doctors? But they could not mistake and disown
their mission more grosslyâthe higher must not degrade itself to be the
tool of the lower, the pathos of distance must to all eternity keep
their missions also separate. The right of the happy to existence, the
right of bells with a full tone over the discordant cracked bells, is
verily a thousand times greater: they alone are the sureties of the
future, they alone are bound to manâs future. What they can, what they
must do, that can the sick never do, should never do! but if they are to
be enabled to do what only they must do, how can they possibly be free
to play the doctor, the comforter, the âSaviourâ of the sick?... And
therefore good air! good air! and away, at any rate, from the
neighbourhood of all the madhouses and hospitals of civilisation! And
therefore good company, our own company, or solitude, if it must be so!
but away, at any rate, from the evil fumes of internal corruption and
the secret worm-eaten state of the sick! that, forsooth, my friends, we
may defend ourselves, at any rate for still a time, against the two
worst plagues that could have been reserved for usâagainst the great
nausea with man! against the great pity for man!
15.
If you have understood in all their depthsâand I demand that you should
grasp them profoundly and understand them profoundlyâthe reasons for the
impossibility of its being the business of the healthy to nurse the
sick, to make the sick healthy, it follows that you have grasped this
further necessityâthe necessity of doctors and nurses who themselves are
sick. And now we have and hold with both our hands the essence of the
ascetic priest. The ascetic priest must be accepted by us as the
predestined saviour, herdsman, and champion of the sick herd: thereby do
we first understand his awful historic mission. The lordship over
sufferers is his kingdom, to that points his instinct, in that he finds
his own special art, his master-skill, his kind of happiness. He must
himself be sick, he must be kith and kin to the sick and the abortions
so as to understand them, so as to arrive at an understanding with them;
but he must also be strong, even more master of himself than of others,
impregnable, forsooth, in his will for power, so as to acquire the trust
and the awe of the weak, so that he can be their hold, bulwark, prop,
compulsion, overseer, tyrant, god. He has to protect them, protect his
herdsâagainst whom? Against the healthy, doubtless also against the envy
towards the healthy. He must be the natural adversary and scorner of
every rough, stormy, reinless, hard, violently-predatory health and
power. The priest is the first form of the more delicate animal that
scorns more easily than it hates. He will not be spared the waging of
war with the beasts of prey, a war of guile (of âspiritâ) rather than of
force, as is self-evidentâhe will in certain cases find it necessary to
conjure up out of himself, or at any rate to represent practically a new
type of the beast of preyâa new animal monstrosity in which the polar
bear, the supple, cold, crouching panther, and, not least important, the
fox, are joined together in a trinity as fascinating as it is fearsome.
If necessity exacts it, then will he come on the scene with bearish
seriousness, venerable, wise, cold, full of treacherous superiority, as
the herald and mouthpiece of mysterious powers, sometimes going among
even the other kind of beasts of prey, determined as he is to sow on
their soil, wherever he can, suffering, discord, self-contradiction, and
only too sure of his art, always to be lord of sufferers at all times.
He brings with him, doubtless, salve and balsam; but before he can play
the physician he must first wound; so, while he soothes the pain which
the wound makes, he at the same time poisons the wound. Well versed is
he in this above all things, is this wizard and wild beast tamer, in
whose vicinity everything healthy must needs become ill, and everything
ill must needs become tame. He protects, in sooth, his sick herd well
enough, does this strange herdsman; he protects them also against
themselves, against the sparks (even in the centre of the herd) of
wickedness, knavery, malice, and all the other ills that the plaguey and
the sick are heir to; he fights with cunning, hardness, and stealth
against anarchy and against the ever imminent break-up inside the herd,
where resentment, that most dangerous blasting-stuff and explosive, ever
accumulates and accumulates. Getting rid of this blasting-stuff in such
a way that it does not blow up the herd and the herdsman, that is his
real feat, his supreme utility; if you wish to comprise in the shortest
formula the value of the priestly life, it would be correct to say the
priest is the diverter of the course of resentment. Every sufferer, in
fact, searches instinctively for a cause of his suffering; to put it
more exactly, a doer,âto put it still more precisely, a sentient
responsible doer,âin brief, something living, on which, either actually
or in effigie, he can on any pretext vent his emotions. For the venting
of emotions is the suffererâs greatest attempt at alleviation, that is
to say, stupefaction, his mechanically desired narcotic against pain of
any kind. It is in this phenomenon alone that is found, according to my
judgment, the real physiological cause of resentment, revenge, and their
family is to be foundâthat is, in a demand for the deadening of pain
through emotion: this cause is generally, but in my view very
erroneously, looked for in the defensive parry of a bare protective
principle of reaction, of a âreflex movementâ in the case of any sudden
hurt and danger, after the manner that a decapitated frog still moves in
order to get away from a corrosive acid. But the difference is
fundamental. In one case the object is to prevent being hurt any more;
in the other case the object is to deaden a racking, insidious, nearly
unbearable pain by a more violent emotion of any kind whatsoever, and at
any rate for the time being to drive it out of the consciousnessâfor
this purpose an emotion is needed, as wild an emotion as possible, and
to excite that emotion some excuse or other is needed. âIt must be
somebodyâs fault that I feel badââthis kind of reasoning is peculiar to
all invalids, and is but the more pronounced, the more ignorant they
remain of the real cause of their feeling bad, the physiological cause
(the cause may lie in a disease of the nervus sympathicus, or in an
excessive secretion of bile, or in a want of sulphate and phosphate of
potash in the blood, or in pressure in the bowels which stops the
circulation of the blood, or in degeneration of the ovaries, and so
forth). Ail sufferers have an awful resourcefulness and ingenuity in
finding excuses for painful emotions; they even enjoy their jealousy,
their broodings over base actions and apparent injuries, they burrow
through the intestines of their past and present in their search for
obscure mysteries, wherein they will be at liberty to wallow in a
torturing suspicion and get drunk on the venom of their own maliceâthey
tear open the oldest wounds, they make themselves bleed from the scars
which have long been healed, they make evil-doers out of friends, wife,
child, and everything which is nearest to them. âI suffer: it must be
somebodyâs faultââso thinks every sick sheep. But his herdsman, the
ascetic priest, says to him, âQuite so, my sheep, it must be the fault
of some one; but thou thyself art that some one, it is all the fault of
thyself aloneâit is the fault of thyself alone against thyselfâ: that is
bold enough, false enough, but one thing is at least attained; thereby,
as I have said, the course of resentment isâdiverted.
16.
You can see now what the remedial instinct of life has at least tried to
effect, according to my conception, through the ascetic priest, and the
purpose for which he had to employ a temporary tyranny of such
paradoxical and anomalous ideas as âguilt,â âsin,â âsinfulness,â
âcorruption,â âdamnation.â What was done was to make the sick harmless
up to a certain point, to destroy the incurable by means of themselves,
to turn the milder cases severely on to themselves, to give their
resentment a backward direction (âman needs but one thingâ), and to
exploit similarly the bad instincts of all sufferers with a view to
self-discipline, self-surveillance, self-mastery. It is obvious that
there can be no question at all in the case of a âmedicationâ of this
kind, a mere emotional medication, of any real healing of the sick in
the physiological sense; it cannot even for a moment be asserted that in
this connection the instinct of life has taken healing as its goal and
purpose. On the one hand, a kind of congestion and organisation of the
sick (the word âChurchâ is the most popular name for it): on the other,
a kind of provisional safeguarding of the comparatively healthy, the
more perfect specimens, the cleavage of a rift between healthy and
sickâfor a long time that was all! and it was much! it was very much!
I am proceeding, as you see, in this essay, from an hypothesis which, as
far as such readers as I want are concerned, does not require to be
proved; the hypothesis that âsinfulnessâ in man is not an actual fact,
but rather merely the interpretation of a fact, of a physiological
discomfort,âa discomfort seen through a moral religious perspective
which is no longer binding upon us. The fact, therefore, that any one
feels âguilty,â âsinful,â is certainly not yet any proof that he is
right in feeling so, any more than any one is healthy simply because he
feels healthy. Remember the celebrated witch-ordeals: in those days the
most acute and humane judges had no doubt but that in these cases they
were confronted with guilt,âthe âwitchesâ themselves had no doubt on the
point,âand yet the guilt was lacking. Let me elaborate this hypothesis:
I do not for a minute accept the very âpain in the soulâ as a real fact,
but only as an explanation (a casual explanation) of facts that could
not hitherto be precisely formulated; I regard it therefore as something
as yet absolutely in the air and devoid of scientific cogencyâjust a
nice fat word in the place of a lean note of interrogation. When any one
fails to get rid of his âpain in the soul,â the cause is, speaking
crudely, to be found not in his âsoulâ but more probably in his stomach
(speaking crudely, I repeat, but by no means wishing thereby that you
should listen to me or understand me in a crude spirit). A strong and
well-constituted man digests his experiences (deeds and misdeeds all
included) just as he digests his meats, even when he has some tough
morsels to swallow. If he fails to ârelieve himselfâ of an experience,
this kind of indigestion is quite as much physiological as the other
indigestionâand indeed, in more ways than one, simply one of the results
of the other. You can adopt such a theory, and yet entre nous be
nevertheless the strongest opponent of all materialism.
17.
But is he really a physician, this ascetic priest? We already understand
why we are scarcely allowed to call him a physician, however much he
likes to feel a âsaviourâ and let himself be worshipped as a saviour.[7]
It is only the actual suffering, the discomfort of the sufferer, which
he combats, not its cause, not the actual state of sicknessâthis needs
must constitute our most radical objection to priestly medication. But
just once put yourself into that point of view, of which the priests
have a monopoly, you will find it hard to exhaust your amazement, at
what from that standpoint he has completely seen, sought, and found. The
mitigation of suffering, every kind of âconsolingââall this manifests
itself as his very genius: with what ingenuity has he interpreted his
mission of consoler, with what aplomb and audacity has he chosen weapons
necessary for the part. Christianity in particular should be dubbed a
great treasure-chamber of ingenious consolations,âsuch a store of
refreshing, soothing, deadening drugs has it accumulated within itself;
so many of the most dangerous and daring expedients has it hazarded;
with such subtlety, refinement, Oriental refinement, has it divined what
emotional stimulants can conquer, at any rate for a time, the deep
depression, the leaden fatigue, the black melancholy of physiological
cripplesâfor, speaking generally, all religions are mainly concerned
with fighting a certain fatigue and heaviness that has infected
everything. You can regard it as prima facie probable that in certain
places in the world there was almost bound to prevail from time to time
among large masses of the population a sense of physiological
depression, which, however, owing to their lack of physiological
knowledge, did not appear to their consciousness as such, so that
consequently its âcauseâ and its cure can only be sought and essayed in
the science of moral psychology (this, in fact, is my most general
formula for what is generally called a âreligionâ). Such a feeling of
depression can have the most diverse origins; it may be the result of
the crossing of too heterogeneous races (or of classesâgenealogical and
racial differences are also brought out in the classes: the European
âWeltschmerz,â the âPessimismâ of the nineteenth century, is really the
result of an absurd and sudden class-mixture); it may be brought about
by a mistaken emigrationâa race falling into a climate for which its
power of adaptation is insufficient (the case of the Indians in India);
it may be the effect of old age and fatigue (the Parisian pessimism from
1850 onwards); it may be a wrong diet (the alcoholism of the Middle
Ages, the nonsense of vegetarianismâwhich, however, have in their favour
the authority of Sir Christopher in Shakespeare); it may be
blood-deterioration, malaria, syphilis, and the like (German depression
after the Thirty Yearsâ War, which infected half Germany with evil
diseases, and thereby paved the way for German servility, for German
pusillanimity). In such a case there is invariably recourse to a war on
a grand scale with the feeling of depression; let us inform ourselves
briefly on its most important practices and phases (I leave on one side,
as stands to reason, the actual philosophic war against the feeling of
depression which is usually simultaneousâit is interesting enough, but
too absurd, too practically negligible, too full of cobwebs, too much of
a hole-and-corner affair, especially when pain is proved to be a
mistake, on the naĂŻf hypothesis that pain must needs vanish when the
mistake underlying it is recognisedâbut behold! it does anything but
vanish ...). That dominant depression is primarily fought by weapons
which reduce the consciousness of life itself to the lowest degree.
Wherever possible, no more wishes, no more wants; shun everything which
produces emotion, which produces âbloodâ (eating no salt, the fakir
hygiene); no love; no hate; equanimity; no revenge; no getting rich; no
work; begging; as far as possible, no woman, or as little woman as
possible; as far as the intellect is concerned, Pascalâs principle, âil
faut sâabĂȘtir.â To put the result in ethical and psychological language,
âself-annihilation,â âsanctificationâ; to put it in physiological
language, âhypnotismââthe attempt to find some approximate human
equivalent for what hibernation is for certain animals, for what
ĂŠstivation is for many tropical plants, a minimum of assimilation and
metabolism in which life just manages to subsist without really coming
into the consciousness. An amazing amount of human energy has been
devoted to this objectâperhaps uselessly? There cannot be the slightest
doubt but that such sportsmen of âsaintliness,â in whom at times nearly
every nation has abounded, have really found a genuine relief from that
which they have combated with such a rigorous trainingâin countless
cases they really escaped by the help of their system of hypnotism away
from deep physiological depression; their method is consequently counted
among the most universal ethnological facts. Similarly it is improper to
consider such a plan for starving the physical element and the desires,
as in itself a symptom of insanity (as a clumsy species of
roast-beef-eating âfreethinkersâ and Sir Christophers are fain to do);
all the more certain is it that their method can and does pave the way
to all kinds of mental disturbances, for instance, âinner lightsâ (as
far as the case of the Hesychasts of Mount Athos), auditory and visual
hallucinations, voluptuous ecstasies and effervescences of sensualism
(the history of St. Theresa). The explanation of such events given by
the victims is always the acme of fanatical falsehood; this is
self-evident. Note well, however, the tone of implicit gratitude that
rings in the very will for an explanation of such a character. The
supreme state, salvation itself, that final goal of universal hypnosis
and peace, is always regarded by them as the mystery of mysteries, which
even the most supreme symbols are inadequate to express; it is regarded
as an entry and homecoming to the essence of things, as a liberation
from all illusions, as âknowledge,â as âtruth,â as âbeingâ as an escape
from every end, every wish, every action, as something even beyond Good
and Evil.
âGood and Evil,â quoth the Buddhists, âboth are fetters. The perfect man
is master of them both.â
âThe done and the undone,â quoth the disciple of the VedĂąnta, âdo him no
hurt; the good and the evil he shakes from off him, sage that he is; his
kingdom suffers no more from any act; good and evil, he goes beyond them
both.ââAn absolutely Indian conception, as much Brahmanist as Buddhist.
Neither in the Indian nor in the Christian doctrine is this âRedemptionâ
regarded as attainable by means of virtue and moral improvement, however
high they may place the value of the hypnotic efficiency of virtue: keep
clear on this pointâindeed it simply corresponds with the facts. The
fact that they remained true on this point is perhaps to be regarded as
the best specimen of realism in the three great religions, absolutely
soaked as they are with morality, with this one exception. âFor those
who know, there is no duty.â âRedemption is not attained by the
acquisition of virtues; for redemption consists in being one with
Brahman, who is incapable of acquiring any perfection; and equally
little does it consist in the giving up of faults, for the Brahman,
unity with whom is what constitutes redemption, is eternally pureâ
(these passages are from the Commentaries of the Cankara, quoted from
the first real European expert of the Indian philosophy, my friend Paul
Deussen). We wish, therefore, to pay honour to the idea of âredemptionâ
in the great religions, but it is somewhat hard to remain serious in
view of the appreciation meted out to the deep sleep by these exhausted
pessimists who are too tired even to dreamâto the deep sleep considered,
that is, as already a fusing into Brahman, as the attainment of the unio
mystica with God. âWhen he has completely gone to sleep,â says on this
point the oldest and most venerable âscript,â âand come to perfect rest,
so that he sees no more any vision, then, oh dear one, is he united with
Being, he has entered into his own selfâencircled by the Self with its
absolute knowledge, he has no more any consciousness of that which is
without or of that which is within. Day and night cross not these
bridges, nor age, nor death, nor suffering, nor good deeds, nor evil
deeds.â âIn deep sleep,â say similarly the believers in this deepest of
the three great religions, âdoes the soul lift itself from out this body
of ours, enters the supreme light and stands out therein in its true
shape: therein is it the supreme spirit itself, which travels about,
while it jests and plays and enjoys itself, whether with women, or
chariots, or friends; there do its thoughts turn no more back to this
appanage of a body, to which the âpranaâ (the vital breath) is harnessed
like a beast of burden to the cart.â None the less we will take care to
realise (as we did when discussing âredemptionâ) that in spite of all
its pomps of Oriental extravagance this simply expresses the same
criticism on life as did the clear, cold, Greekly cold, but yet
suffering Epicurus. The hypnotic sensation of nothingness, the peace of
deepest sleep, anĂŠsthesia in shortââthat is what passes with the
sufferers and the absolutely depressed for, forsooth, their supreme
good, their value of values; that is what must be treasured by them as
something positive, be felt by them as the essence of the Positive
(according to the same logic of the feelings, nothingness is in all
pessimistic religions called God).
18.
Such a hypnotic deadening of sensibility and susceptibility to pain,
which presupposes somewhat rare powers, especially courage, contempt of
opinion, intellectual stoicism, is less frequent than another and
certainly easier training which is tried against states of depression. I
mean mechanical activity. It is indisputable that a suffering existence
can be thereby considerably alleviated. This fact is called to-day by
the somewhat ignoble title of the âBlessing of work.â The alleviation
consists in the attention of the sufferer being absolutely diverted from
suffering, in the incessant monopoly of the consciousness by action, so
that consequently there is little room left for sufferingââfor narrow is
it, this chamber of human consciousness! Mechanical activity and its
corollaries, such as absolute regularity, punctilious unreasoning
obedience, the chronic routine of life, the complete occupation of time,
a certain liberty to be impersonal, nay, a training in âimpersonality,â
self-forgetfulness, âincuria suiâââwith what thoroughness and expert
subtlety have all these methods been exploited by the ascetic priest in
his war with pain!
When he has to tackle sufferers of the lower orders, slaves, or
prisoners (or women, who for the most part are a compound of
labour-slave and prisoner), all he has to do is to juggle a little with
the names, and to rechristen, so as to make them see henceforth a
benefit, a comparative happiness, in objects which they hatedâthe
slaveâs discontent with his lot was at any rate not invented by the
priests. An even more popular means of fighting depression is the
ordaining of a little joy, which is easily accessible and can be made
into a rule; this medication is frequently used in conjunction with the
former ones. The most frequent form in which joy is prescribed as a cure
is the joy in producing joy (such as doing good, giving presents,
alleviating, helping, exhorting, comforting, praising, treating with
distinction); together with the prescription of âlove your neighbour.â
The ascetic priest prescribes, though in the most cautious doses, what
is practically a stimulation of the strongest and most life-assertive
impulseâthe Will for Power. The happiness involved in the âsmallest
superiorityâ which is the concomitant of all benefiting, helping,
extolling, making oneâs self useful, is the most ample consolation, of
which, if they are well-advised, physiological distortions avail
themselves: in other cases they hurt each other, and naturally in
obedience to the same radical instinct. An investigation of the origin
of Christianity in the Roman world shows that co-operative unions for
poverty, sickness, and burial sprang up in the lowest stratum of
contemporary society, amid which the chief antidote against depression,
the little joy experienced in mutual benefits, was deliberately
fostered. Perchance this was then a novelty, a real discovery? This
conjuring up of the will for co-operation, for family organisation, for
communal life, for âCĆnaculaâ necessarily brought the Will for Power,
which had been already infinitesimally stimulated, to a new and much
fuller manifestation. The herd organisation is a genuine advance and
triumph in the fight with depression. With the growth of the community
there matures even to individuals a new interest, which often enough
takes him out of the more personal element in his discontent, his
aversion to himself, the âdespectus suiâ of Geulincx. All sick and
diseased people strive instinctively after a herd-organisation, out of a
desire to shake off their sense of oppressive discomfort and weakness;
the ascetic priest divines this instinct and promotes it; wherever a
herd exists it is the instinct of weakness which has wished for the
herd, and the cleverness of the priests which has organised it, for,
mark this: by an equally natural necessity the strong strive as much for
isolation as the weak for union: when the former bind themselves it is
only with a view to an aggressive joint action and joint satisfaction of
their Will for Power, much against the wishes of their individual
consciences; the latter, on the contrary, range themselves together with
positive delight in such a musterâtheir instincts are as much gratified
thereby as the instincts of the âborn masterâ (that is, the solitary
beast-of-prey species of man) are disturbed and wounded to the quick by
organisation. There is always lurking beneath every oligarchyâsuch is
the universal lesson of historyâthe desire for tyranny. Every oligarchy
is continually quivering with the tension of the effort required by each
individual to keep mastering this desire. (Such, e.g., was the Greek;
Plato shows it in a hundred places, Plato, who knew his
contemporariesâand himself.)
19.
The methods employed by the ascetic priest, which we have already learnt
to knowâstifling of all vitality, mechanical energy, the little joy, and
especially the method of âlove your neighbourâ herd-organisation, the
awaking of the communal consciousness of power, to such a pitch that the
individualâs disgust with himself becomes eclipsed by his delight in the
thriving of the communityâthese are, according to modern standards, the
âinnocentâ methods employed in the fight with depression; let us turn
now to the more interesting topic of the âguiltyâ methods. The guilty
methods spell one thing: to produce emotional excessâwhich is used as
the most efficacious anĂŠsthetic against their depressing state of
protracted pain; this is why priestly ingenuity has proved quite
inexhaustible in thinking out this one question: âBy what means can you
produce an emotional excess?â This sounds harsh: it is manifest that it
would sound nicer and would grate on oneâs ears less, if I were to say,
forsooth: âThe ascetic priest made use at all times of the enthusiasm
contained in all strong emotions.â But what is the good of still
soothing the delicate ears of our modern effeminates? What is the good
on our side of budging one single inch before their verbal
Pecksniffianism. For us psychologists to do that would be at once
practical Pecksniffianism, apart from the fact of its nauseating us. The
good taste (others might say, the righteousness) of a psychologist
nowadays consists, if at all, in combating the shamefully moralised
language with which all modern judgments on men and things are smeared.
For, do not deceive yourself: what constitutes the chief characteristic
of modern souls and of modern books is not the lying, but the innocence
which is part and parcel of their intellectual dishonesty. The
inevitable running up against this âinnocenceâ everywhere constitutes
the most distasteful feature of the somewhat dangerous business which a
modern psychologist has to undertake: it is a part of our great
dangerâit is a road which perhaps leads us straight to the great
nauseaâI know quite well the purpose which all modern books will and can
serve (granted that they last, which I am not afraid of, and granted
equally that there is to be at some future day a generation with a more
rigid, more severe, and healthier taste)âthe function which all
modernity generally will serve with posterity: that of an emetic,âand
this by reason of its moral sugariness and falsity, its ingrained
feminism, which it is pleased to call âIdealism,â and at any rate
believes to be idealism. Our cultured men of to-day, our âgoodâ men, do
not lieâthat is true; but it does not redound to their honour! The real
lie, the genuine, determined, âhonestâ lie (on whose value you can
listen to Plato) would prove too tough and strong an article for them by
a long way; it would be asking them to do what people have been
forbidden to ask them to do, to open their eyes to their own selves, and
to learn to distinguish between âtrueâ and âfalseâ in their own selves.
The dishonest lie alone suits them: everything which feels a good man is
perfectly incapable of any other attitude to anything than that of a
dishonourable liar, an absolute liar, but none the less an innocent
liar, a blue-eyed liar, a virtuous liar. These âgood men,â they are all
now tainted with morality through and through, and as far as honour is
concerned they are disgraced and corrupted for all eternity. Which of
them could stand a further truth âabout manâ? or, put more tangibly,
which of them could put up with a true biography? One or two instances:
Lord Byron composed a most personal autobiography, but Thomas Moore was
âtoo goodâ for it; he burnt his friendâs papers. Dr. Gwinner,
Schopenhauerâs executor, is said to have done the same; for Schopenhauer
as well wrote much about himself, and perhaps also against himself: (ΔጰÏ
áŒÎ±ÎœÏÏÎœ). The virtuous American Thayer, Beethovenâs biographer, suddenly
stopped his work: he had come to a certain point in that honourable and
simple life, and could stand it no longer. Moral: What sensible man
nowadays writes one honest word about himself? He must already belong to
the Order of Holy Foolhardiness. We are promised an autobiography of
Richard Wagner; who doubts but that it would be a clever autobiography?
Think, forsooth, of the grotesque horror which the Catholic priest
Janssen aroused in Germany with his inconceivably square and harmless
pictures of the German Reformation; what wouldnât people do if some real
psychologist were to tell us about a genuine Luther, tell us, not with
the moralist simplicity of a country priest or the sweet and cautious
modesty of a Protestant historian, but say with the fearlessness of a
Taine, that springs from force of character and not from a prudent
toleration of force. (The Germans, by the bye, have already produced the
classic specimen of this tolerationâthey may well be allowed to reckon
him as one of their own, in Leopold Ranke, that born classical advocate
of every causa fortior, that cleverest of all the clever opportunists.)
20.
But you will soon understand me.âPutting it shortly, there is reason
enough, is there not, for us psychologists nowadays never getting from a
certain mistrust of out own selves? Probably even we ourselves are still
âtoo goodâ for our work, probably, whatever contempt we feel for this
popular craze for morality, we ourselves are perhaps none the less its
victims, prey, and slaves; probably it infects even us. Of what was that
diplomat warning us, when he said to his colleagues: âLet us especially
mistrust our first impulses, gentlemen! they are almost always goodâ? So
should nowadays every psychologist talk to his colleagues. And thus we
get back to our problem, which in point of fact does require from us a
certain severity, a certain mistrust especially against âfirst
impulses.â The ascetic ideal in the service of projected emotional
excess:âhe who remembers the previous essay will already partially
anticipate the essential meaning compressed into these above ten words.
The thorough unswitching of the human soul, the plunging of it into
terror, frost, ardour, rapture, so as to free it, as through some
lightning shock, from all the smallness and pettiness of unhappiness,
depression, and discomfort: what ways lead to this goal? And which of
these ways does so most safely?... At bottom all great emotions have
this power, provided that they find a sudden outletâemotions such as
rage, fear, lust, revenge, hope, triumph, despair, cruelty; and, in
sooth, the ascetic priest has had no scruples in taking into his service
the whole pack of hounds that rage in the human kennel, unleashing now
these and now those, with the same constant object of waking man out of
his protracted melancholy, of chasing away, at any rate for a time, his
dull pain, his shrinking misery, but always under the sanction of a
religious interpretation and justification. This emotional excess has
subsequently to be paid for, this is self-evidentâit makes the ill more
illâand therefore this kind of remedy for pain is according to modern
standards a âguiltyâ kind.
The dictates of fairness, however, require that we should all the more
emphasise the fact that this remedy is applied with a good conscience,
that the ascetic priest has prescribed it in the most implicit belief in
its utility and indispensability;âoften enough almost collapsing in the
presence of the pain which he created;âthat we should similarly
emphasise the fact that the violent physiological revenges of such
excesses, even perhaps the mental disturbances, are not absolutely
inconsistent with the general tenor of this kind of remedy; this remedy,
which, as we have shown previously, is not for the purpose of healing
diseases, but of fighting the unhappiness of that depression, the
alleviation and deadening of which was its object. The object was
consequently achieved. The keynote by which the ascetic priest was
enabled to get every kind of agonising and ecstatic music to play on the
fibres of the human soulâwas, as every one knows, the exploitation of
the feeling of âguilt.â I have already indicated in the previous essay
the origin of this feelingâas a piece of animal psychology and nothing
else: we were thus confronted with the feeling of âguilt,â in its crude
state, as it were. It was first in the hands of the priest, real artist
that he was in the feeling of guilt, that it took shapeâoh, what a
shape! âSinââfor that is the name of the new priestly version of the
animal âbad-conscienceâ (the inverted cruelty)âhas up to the present
been the greatest event in the history of the diseased soul: in âsinâ we
find the most perilous and fatal masterpiece of religious
interpretation. Imagine man, suffering from himself, some way or other
but at any rate physiologically, perhaps like an animal shut up in a
cage, not clear as to the why and the wherefore! imagine him in his
desire for reasonsâreasons bring reliefâin his desire again for
remedies, narcotics at last, consulting one, who knows even the
occultâand see, lo and behold, he gets a hint from his wizard, the
ascetic priest, his first hint on the âcauseâ of his trouble: he must
search for it in himself, in his guiltiness, in a piece of the past, he
must understand his very suffering as a state of punishment. He has
heard, he has understood, has the unfortunate: he is now in the plight
of a hen round which a line has been drawn. He never gets out of the
circle of lines. The sick man has been turned into âthe sinnerââand now
for a few thousand years we never get away from the sight of this new
invalid, of âa sinnerââshall we ever get away from it?âwherever we just
look, everywhere the hypnotic gaze of the sinner always moving in one
direction (in the direction of guilt, the only cause of suffering);
everywhere the evil conscience, this âgreuliche thier,â[8] to use
Lutherâs language; everywhere rumination over the past, a distorted view
of action, the gaze of the âgreen-eyed monsterâ turned on all action;
everywhere the wilful misunderstanding of suffering, its transvaluation
into feelings of guilt, fear of retribution; everywhere the scourge, the
hairy shirt, the starving body, contrition; everywhere the sinner
breaking himself on the ghastly wheel of a restless and morbidly eager
conscience; everywhere mute pain, extreme fear, the agony of a tortured
heart, the spasms of an unknown happiness, the shriek for âredemption.â
In point of fact, thanks to this system of procedure, the old
depression, dullness, and fatigue were absolutely conquered, life itself
became very interesting again, awake, eternally awake, sleepless,
glowing, burnt away, exhausted and yet not tiredâsuch was the figure cut
by man, âthe sinner,â who was initiated into these mysteries. This grand
old wizard of an ascetic priest fighting with depressionâhe had clearly
triumphed, his kingdom had come: men no longer grumbled at pain, men
panted after pain: âMore pain! More pain!â So for centuries on end
shrieked the demand of his acolytes and initiates. Every emotional
excess which hurt; everything which broke, overthrew, crushed,
transported, ravished; the mystery of torture-chambers, the ingenuity of
hell itselfâall this was now discovered, divined, exploited, all this
was at the service of the wizard, all this served to promote the triumph
of his ideal, the ascetic ideal. âMy kingdom is not of this world,â
quoth he, both at the beginning and at the end: had he still the right
to talk like that?âGoethe has maintained that there are only thirty-six
tragic situations: we would infer from that, did we not know otherwise,
that Goethe was no ascetic priest. Heâknows more.
21.
So far as all this kind of priestly medicine-mongering, the âguiltyâ
kind, is concerned, every word of criticism is superfluous. As for the
suggestion that emotional excess of the type, which in these cases the
ascetic priest is fain to order to his sick patients (under the most
sacred euphemism, as is obvious, and equally impregnated with the
sanctity of his purpose), has ever really been of use to any sick man,
who, forsooth, would feel inclined to maintain a proposition of that
character? At any rate, some understanding should be come to as to the
expression âbe of use.â If you only wish to express that such a system
of treatment has reformed man, I do not gainsay it: I merely add that
âreformedâ conveys to my mind as much as âtamed,â âweakened,â
âdiscouraged,â ârefined,â âdaintified,â âemasculatedâ (and thus it means
almost as much as injured). But when you have to deal principally with
sick, depressed, and oppressed creatures, such a system, even granted
that it makes the ill âbetter,â under any circumstances also makes them
more ill: ask the mad-doctors the invariable result of a methodical
application of penance-torture, contrition, and salvation ecstasies.
Similarly ask history. In every body politic where the ascetic priest
has established this treatment of the sick, disease has on every
occasion spread with sinister speed throughout its length and breadth.
What was always the âresultâ? A shattered nervous system, in addition to
the existing malady, and this in the greatest as in the smallest, in the
individuals as in masses. We find, in consequence of the penance and
redemption-training, awful epileptic epidemics, the greatest known to
history, such as the St. Vitus and St. John dances of the Middle Ages;
we find, as another phase of its after-effect, frightful mutilations and
chronic depressions, by means of which the temperament of a nation or a
city (Geneva, Bale) is turned once for all into its opposite;âthis
training, again, is responsible for the witch-hysteria, a phenomenon
analogous to somnambulism (eight great epidemic outbursts of this only
between 1564 and 1605);âwe find similarly in its train those delirious
death-cravings of large masses, whose awful âshriek,â âevviva la morte!â
was heard over the whole of Europe, now interrupted by voluptuous
variations and anon by a rage for destruction, just as the same
emotional sequence with the same intermittencies and sudden changes is
now universally observed in every case where the ascetic doctrine of sin
scores once more a great success (religious neurosis appears as a
manifestation of the devil, there is no doubt of it. What is it?
QuĂŠritur). Speaking generally, the ascetic ideal and its sublime-moral
cult, this most ingenious, reckless, and perilous systematisation of all
methods of emotional excess, is writ large in a dreadful and
unforgettable fashion on the whole history of man, and unfortunately not
only on history. I was scarcely able to put forward any other element
which attacked the health and race efficiency of Europeans with more
destructive power than did this ideal; it can be dubbed,without
exaggeration, the real fatality in the history of the health of the
European man. At the most you can merely draw a comparison with the
specifically German influence: I mean the alcohol poisoning of Europe,
which up to the present has kept pace exactly with the political and
racial preâdominance of the Germans (where they inoculated their blood,
there too did they inoculate their vice). Third in the series comes
syphilisâmagno sed proximo intervallo.
22.
The ascetic priest has, wherever he has obtained the mastery, corrupted
the health of the soul, he has consequently also corrupted taste in
artibus et litterisâhe corrupts it still. âConsequently?â I hope I shall
be granted this âconsequently â; at any rate, I am not going to prove it
first. One solitary indication, it concerns the arch-book of Christian
literature, their real model, their âbook-in-itself.â In the very midst
of the GrĂŠco-Roman splendour, which was also a splendour of books, face
to face with an ancient world of writings which had not yet fallen into
decay and ruin, at a time when certain books were still to be read, to
possess which we would give nowadays half our literature in exchange, at
that time the simplicity and vanity of Christian agitators (they are
generally called Fathers of the Church) dared to declare: âWe too have
our classical literature, we do not need that of the Greeksââand
meanwhile they proudly pointed to their books of legends, their letters
of apostles, and their apologetic tractlets, just in the same way that
to-day the English âSalvation Armyâ wages its fight against Shakespeare
and other âheathensâ with an analogous literature. You already guess it,
I do not like the âNew Testamentâ; it almost upsets me that I stand so
isolated in my taste so far as concerns this valued, this over-valued
Scripture; the taste of two thousand years is against me; but what boots
it! âHere I stand! I cannot help myselfâ[9]âI have the courage of my bad
taste. The Old Testamentâyes, that is something quite different, all
honour to the Old Testament! I find therein great men, an heroic
landscape, and one of the rarest phenomena in the world, the
incomparable naïveté of the strong heart; further still, I find a
people. In the New, on the contrary, just a hostel of petty sects, pure
rococo of the soul, twisting angles and fancy touches, nothing but
conventicle air, not to forget an occasional whiff of bucolic sweetness
which appertains to the epoch (and the Roman province) and is less
Jewish than Hellenistic. Meekness and braggadocio cheek by jowl; an
emotional garrulousness that almost deafens; passionate hysteria, but no
passion; painful pantomime; here manifestly every one lacked good
breeding. How dare any one make so much fuss about their little failings
as do these pious little fellows! No one cares a straw about itâlet
alone God. Finally they actually wish to have âthe crown of eternal
life,â do all these little provincials! In return for what, in sooth?
For what end? It is impossible to carry insolence any further. An
immortal Peter! who could stand him! They have an ambition which makes
one laugh: the thing dishes up cut and dried his most personal life, his
melancholies, and common-or-garden troubles, as though the Universe
itself were under an obligation to bother itself about them, for it
never gets tired of wrapping up God Himself in the petty misery in which
its troubles are involved. And how about the atrocious form of this
chronic hobnobbing with God? This Jewish, and not merely Jewish,
slobbering and clawing importunacy towards God!âThere exist little
despised âheathen nationsâ in East Asia, from whom these first
Christians could have learnt something worth learning, a little tact in
worshiping; these nations do not allow themselves to say aloud the name
of their God. This seems to me delicate enough, it is certain that it is
too delicate, and not only for primitive Christians; to take a contrast,
just recollect Luther, the most âeloquentâ and insolent peasant whom
Germany has had, think of the Lutherian tone, in which he felt quite the
most in his element during his tĂȘte-Ă -tĂȘtes with God. Lutherâs
opposition to the mediĂŠval saints of the Church (in particular, against
âthat devilâs hog, the Popeâ), was, there is no doubt, at bottom the
opposition of a boor, who was offended at the good etiquette of the
Church, that worship-etiquette of the sacerdotal code, which only admits
to the holy of holies the initiated and the silent, and shuts the door
against the boors. These definitely were not to be allowed a hearing in
this planetâbut Luther the peasant simply wished it otherwise; as it
was, it was not German enough for him. He personally wished himself to
talk direct, to talk personally, to talk âstraight from the shoulderâ
with his God. Well, heâs done it. The ascetic ideal, you will guess, was
at no time and in no place, a school of good taste, still less of good
mannersâat the best it was a school for sacerdotal manners: that is, it
contains in itself something which was a deadly enemy to all good
manners. Lack of measure, opposition to measure, it is itself a ânon
plus ultra.â
23.
The ascetic ideal has corrupted not only health and taste, there are
also third, fourth, fifth, and sixth things which it has corruptedâI
shall take care not to go through the catalogue (when should I get to
the end?). I have here to expose not what this ideal effected; but
rather only what it means, on what it is based, what lies lurking behind
it and under it, that of which it is the provisional expression, an
obscure expression bristling with queries and misunderstandings. And
with this object only in view I presumed ânot to spareâ my readers a
glance at the awfulness of its results, a glance at its fatal results; I
did this to prepare them for the final and most awful aspect presented
to me by the question of the significance of that ideal. What is the
significance of the power of that ideal, the monstrousness of its power?
Why is it given such an amount of scope? Why is not a better resistance
offered against it? The ascetic ideal expresses one will: where is the
opposition will, in which an opposition ideal expresses itself? The
ascetic ideal has an aimâ this goal is, putting it generally, that all
the other interests of human life should, measured by its standard,
appear petty and narrow; it explains epochs, nations, men, in reference
to this one end; it forbids any other interpretation, any other end; it
repudiates, denies, affirms, confirms, only in the sense of its own
interpretation (and was there ever a more thoroughly elaborated system
of interpretation?); it subjects itself to no power, rather does it
believe in its own precedence over every powerâit believes that nothing
powerful exists in the world that has not first got to receive from âitâ
a meaning, a right to exist, a value, as being an instrument in its
work, a way and means to its end, to one end. Where is the counterpart
of this complete system of will, end, and interpretation? Why is the
counterpart lacking? Where is the other âone aimâ? But I am told it is
not lacking, that not only has it fought a long and fortunate fight with
that ideal, but that further it has already won the mastery over that
ideal in all essentials: let our whole modern science attest thisâthat
modern science, which, like the genuine reality-philosophy which it is,
manifestly believes in itself alone, manifestly has the courage to be
itself, the will to be itself, and has got on well enough without God,
another world, and negative virtues.
With all their noisy agitator-babble, however, they effect nothing with
me; these trumpeters of reality are bad musicians, their voices do not
come from the deeps with sufficient audibility, they are not the
mouthpiece for the abyss of scientific knowledgeâfor to-day scientific
knowledge is an abyssâthe word âscience,â in such trumpeter-mouths, is a
prostitution, an abuse, an impertinence. The truth is just the opposite
from what is maintained in the ascetic theory. Science has to-day
absolutely no belief in itself, let alone in an ideal superior to
itself, and wherever science still consists of passion, love, ardour,
suffering, it is not the opposition to that ascetic ideal, but rather
the incarnation of its latest and noblest form. Does that ring strange?
There are enough brave and decent working people, even among the learned
men of to-day, who like their little corner, and who, just because they
are pleased so to do, become at times indecently loud with their demand,
that people to-day should be quite content, especially in scienceâfor in
science there is so much useful work to do. I do not deny itâthere is
nothing I should like less than to spoil the delight of these honest
workers in their handiwork; for I rejoice in their work. But the fact of
science requiring hard work, the fact of its having contented workers,
is absolutely no proof of science as a whole having to-day one end, one
will, one ideal, one passion for a great faith; the contrary, as I have
said, is the case. When science is not the latest manifestation of the
ascetic idealâbut these are cases of such rarity, selectness, and
exquisiteness, as to preclude the general judgment being affected
therebyâscience is a hiding-place for every kind of cowardice,
disbelief, remorse, despectio sui, bad conscienceâit is the very anxiety
that springs from having no ideal, the suffering from the lack of a
great love, the discontent with an enforced moderation. Oh, what does
all science not cover to-day? How much, at any rate, does it not try to
cover? The diligence of our best scholars, their senseless industry,
their burning the candle of their brain at both endsâtheir very mastery
in their handiworkâhow often is the real meaning of all that to prevent
themselves continuing to see a certain thing? Science as a
self-anĂŠsthetic: do you know that? You wound themâevery one who consorts
with scholars experiences thisâyou wound them sometimes to the quick
through just a harmless word; when you think you are paying them a
compliment you embitter them beyond all bounds, simply because you
didnât have the finesse to infer the real kind of customers you had to
tackle, the sufferer kind (who wonât own up even to themselves what they
really are), the dazed and unconscious kind who have only one
fearâcoming to consciousness.
24.
And now look at the other side, at those rare cases, of which I spoke,
the most supreme idealists to be found nowadays among philosophers and
scholars. Have we, perchance, found in them the sought-for opponents of
the ascetic ideal, its anti-idealists? In fact, they believe themselves
to be such, these âunbelieversâ (for they are all of them that): it
seems that this idea is their last remnant of faith, the idea of being
opponents of this ideal, so earnest are they on this subject, so
passionate in word and gesture;âbut does it follow that what they
believe must necessarily be true? We âknowersâ have grown by degrees
suspicious of all kinds of believers, our suspicion has step by step
habituated us to draw just the opposite conclusions to what people have
drawn before; that is to say, wherever the strength of a belief is
particularly prominent to draw the conclusion of the difficulty of
proving what is believed, the conclusion of its actual improbability. We
do not again deny that âfaith produces salvationâ: for that very reason
we do deny that faith proves anything,âa strong faith, which produces
happiness, causes suspicion of the object of that faith, it does not
establish its âtruth,â it does establish a certain probability
ofâillusion. What is now the position in these cases? These solitaries
and deniers of to-day; these fanatics in one thing, in their claim to
intellectual cleanness; these hard, stern, continent, heroic spirits,
who constitute the glory of our time; all these pale atheists,
anti-Christians, immoralists, Nihilists; these sceptics, âephectics,â
and âhecticsâ of the intellect (in a certain sense they are the latter,
both collectively and individually); these supreme idealists of
knowledge, in whom alone nowadays the intellectual conscience dwells and
is aliveâin point of fact they believe themselves as far away as
possible from the ascetic ideal, do these âfree, very free spiritsâ: and
yet, if I may reveal what they themselves cannot seeâfor they stand too
near themselves: this ideal is simply their ideal, they represent it
nowadays and perhaps no one else, they themselves are its most
spiritualised product, its most advanced picket of skirmishers and
scouts, its most insidious delicate and elusive form of seduction.âIf I
am in any way a reader of riddles, then I will be one with this
sentence: for some time past there have been no free spirits; for they
still believe in truth. When the Christian Crusaders in the East came
into collision with that invincible order of assassins, that order of
free spirits par excellence, whose lowest grade lives in a state of
discipline such as no order of monks has ever attained, then in some way
or other they managed to get an inkling of that symbol and tally-word,
that was reserved for the highest grade alone as their secretum,
âNothing is true, everything is allowed,ââin sooth, that was freedom of
thought, thereby was taking leave of the very belief in truth. Has
indeed any European, any Christian freethinker, ever yet wandered into
this proposition and its labyrinthine consequences? Does he know from
experience the Minotauros of this den.âI doubt itânay, I know otherwise.
Nothing is more really alien to these âmono-fanatics,â these so-called
âfree spirits,â than freedom and unfettering in that sense; in no
respect are they more closely tied, the absolute fanaticism of their
belief in truth is unparalleled. I know all this perhaps too much from
experience at close quartersâthat dignified philosophic abstinence to
which a belief like that binds its adherents, that stoicism of the
intellect, which eventually vetoes negation as rigidly as it does
affirmation, that wish for standing still in front of the actual, the
factum brutum, that fatalism in âpetits faitsâ (ce petit faitalism, as I
call it), in which French Science now attempts a kind of moral
superiority over German, this renunciation of interpretation generally
(that is, of forcing, doctoring, abridging, omitting, suppressing,
inventing, falsifying, and all the other essential attributes of
interpretation)âall this, considered broadly, expresses the asceticism
of virtue, quite as efficiently as does any repudiation of the senses
(it is at bottom only a modus of that repudiation.) But what forces it
into that unqualified will for truth is the faith in the ascetic ideal
itself, even though it take the form of its unconscious
imperatives,âmake no mistake about it, it is the faith, I repeat, in a
metaphysical value, an intrinsic value of truth, of a character which is
only warranted and guaranteed in this ideal (it stands and falls with
that ideal). Judged strictly, there does not exist a science without its
âhypotheses,â the thought of such a science is inconceivable, illogical:
a philosophy, a faith, must always exist first to enable science to gain
thereby a direction, a meaning, a limit and method, a right to
existence. (He who holds a contrary opinion on the subjectâhe, for
example, who takes it upon himself to establish philosophy âupon a
strictly scientific basisââhas first got to âturn up-side-downâ not only
philosophy but also truth itselfâthe gravest insult which could possibly
be offered to two such respectable females!) Yes, there is no doubt
about itâand here I quote my Joyful Wisdom, cp. Book V. Aph. 344: âThe
man who is truthful in that daring and extreme fashion, which is the
presupposition of the faith in science, asserts thereby a different
world from that of life, nature, and history; and in so far as he
asserts the existence of that different world, come, must he not
similarly repudiate its counterpart, this world, our world? The belief
on which our faith in science is based has remained to this day a
metaphysical beliefâeven we knowers of to-day, we godless foes of
metaphysics, we too take our fire from that conflagration which was
kindled by a thousand-year-old faith, from that Christian belief, which
was also Platoâs belief, the belief that God is truth, that truth is
divine.... But what if this belief becomes more and more incredible,
what if nothing proves itself to be divine, unless it be error,
blindness, liesâwhat if God, Himself proved Himself to be our oldest
lie?ââIt is necessary to stop at this point and to consider the
situation carefully. Science itself now needs a justification (which is
not for a minute to say that there is such a justification). Turn in
this context to the most ancient and the most modern philosophers: they
all fail to realise the extent of the need of a justification on the
part of the Will for Truthâhere is a gap in every philosophyâwhat is it
caused by? Because up to the present the ascetic ideal dominated all
philosophy, because Truth was fixed as Being, as God, as the Supreme
Court of Appeal, because Truth was not allowed to be a problem. Do you
understand this âallowedâ? From the minute that the belief in the God of
the ascetic ideal is repudiated, there exists a new problem: the problem
of the value of truth. The Will for Truth needed a critiqueâlet us
define by these words our own taskâ-the value of truth is tentatively to
be called in question.... (If this seems too laconically expressed, I
recommend the reader to peruse again that passage from the Joyful Wisdom
which bears the title, âHow far we also are still pious,â Aph. 344, and
best of all the whole fifth book of that work, as well as the Preface to
The Dawn of Day.)
25.
No! You canât get round me with science, when I search for the natural
antagonists of the ascetic ideal, when I put the question: âWhere is the
opposed will in which the opponent ideal expresses itself?â Science is
not, by a long way, independent enough to fulfil this function; in every
department science needs an ideal value, a power which creates values,
and in whose service it can believe in itself âscience itself never
creates values. Its relation to the ascetic ideal is not in itself
antagonistic; speaking roughly, it rather represents the progressive
force in the inner evolution of that ideal. Tested more exactly, its
opposition and antagonism are concerned not with the ideal itself, but
only with that idealâs outworks, its outer garb, its masquerade, with
its temporary hardening, stiffening, and dogmatisingâit makes the life
in the ideal free once more, while it repudiates its superficial
elements. These two phenomena, science and the ascetic ideal, both rest
on the same basisââI have already made this clearââthe basis, I say, oft
the same over-appreciation of truth (more accurately the same belief in
the impossibility of valuing and of criticising truth), and consequently
they are necessarily allies, so that, in the event of their being
attacked, they must always be attacked and called into question
together. A valuation of the ascetic ideal inevitably entails a
valuation of science as well; lose no time in seeing this clearly, and
be sharp to catch it! (Art, I am speaking provisionally, for I will
treat it on some other occasion in greater detail,ââart, I repeat, in
which lying is sanctified and the will for deception has good conscience
on its side, is much more fundamentally opposed to the ascetic ideal
than is science: Platoâs instinct felt thisââPlato, the greatest enemy
of art which Europe has produced up to the present. Plato versus Homer,
that is the complete, the true antagonismââon the one side, the
wholeâhearted âtranscendental,â the great defamer of life; on the other,
its involuntary panegyrist, the golden nature. An artistic subservience
to the service of the ascetic ideal is consequently the most absolute
artistic corruption that there can be, though unfortunately it is one of
the most frequent phases, for nothing is more corruptible than an
artist.) Considered physiologically, moreover, science rests on the
same, basis as does the ascetic ideal: a certain impoverishment of life
is the presupposition of the latter as of the formerââadd, frigidity of
the emotions, slackening of the tempo, the substitution of dialectic for
instinct, seriousness impressed on mien and gesture (seriousness, that
most unmistakable sign of strenuous metabolism, of struggling, toiling
life). Consider the periods in a nation in which the learned man comes
into prominence; they are the periods of exhaustion, often of sunset, of
decayâthe effervescing strength, the confidence in life, the confidence
in the future are no more. The preponderance of the mandarins never
signifies any good, any more than does the advent of democracy, or
arbitration instead of war, equal rights for women, the religion of
pity, and all the other symptoms of declining life. (Science handled as
a problem! what is the meaning of science?âupon this point the Preface
to the Birth of Tragedy.) No! this âmodern scienceââmark you this
wellâis at times the best ally for the ascetic ideal, and for the very
reason that it is the ally which is most unconscious, most automatic,
most secret, and most subterranean! They have been playing into each
otherâs hands up to the present, have these âpoor in spiritâ and the
scientific opponents of that ideal (take care, by the bye, not to think
that these opponents are the antithesis of this ideal, that they are the
rich in spiritâthat they are not; I have called them the hectic in
spirit). As for these celebrated victories of science; there is no doubt
that they are victoriesâbut victories over what? There was not for a
single minute any victory among their list over the ascetic ideal,
rather was it made stronger, that is to say, more elusive, more
abstract, more insidious, from the fact that a wall, an outwork, that
had got built on to the main fortress and disfigured its appearance,
should from time to time be ruthlessly destroyed and broken down by
science. Does any one seriously suggest that the downfall of the
theological astronomy signified the downfall of that ideal?âHas,
perchance, man grown less in need of a transcendental solution of his
riddle of existence, because since that time this existence has become
more random, casual, and superfluous in the visible order of the
universe? Has there not been since the time of Copernicus an unbroken
progress in the self-belittling of man and his will for belittling
himself? Alas, his belief in his dignity, his uniquenesses
irreplaceableness in the scheme of existence, is goneâhe has become
animal, literal, unqualified, and unmitigated animal, he who in his
earlier belief was almost God (âchild of God,â âdemi-Godâ). Since
Copernicus man seems to have fallen on to a steep planeâhe rolls faster
and faster away from the centreâwhither? into nothingness? into the
âthrilling sensation of his own nothingnessââWell! this would be the
straight wayâto the old ideal?âAll science (and by no means only
astronomy, with regard to the humiliating and deteriorating effect of
which Kant has made a remarkable confession, âit annihilates my own
importanceâ), all science, natural as much as unnaturalâby unnatural I
mean the self-critique of reasonânowadays sets out to talk man out of
his present opinion of himself, as though that opinion had been nothing
but a bizarre piece of conceit; you might go so far as to say that
science finds its peculiar pride, its peculiar bitter form of stoical
ataraxia, in preserving manâs contempt of himself, that state which it
took so much trouble to bring about, as manâs final and most serious
claim to self-appreciation (rightly so, in point of fact, for he who
despises is always âone who has not forgotten how to appreciateâ). But
does all this involve any real effort to counteract the ascetic ideal?
Is it really seriously suggested that Kantâs victory over the
theological dogmatism about âGod,â âSoul,â âFreedom,â âImmortality,â has
damaged that ideal in any way (as the theologians have imagined to be
the case for a long time past)?ââ And in this connection it does not
concern us for a single minute, if Kant himself intended any such
consummation. It is certain that from the time of Kant every type of
transcendentalist is playing a winning gameââthey are emancipated from
the theologians; what luck!ââhe has revealed to them that secret art, by
which they can now pursue their âheartâs desireâ on their own
responsibility, and with all the respectability of science. Similarly,
who can grumble at the agnostics, reverers, as they are, of the unknown
and the absolute mystery, if they now worship their very query as God?
(Xaver Doudan talks somewhere of the ravages which lâhabitude dâadmirer
lâinintelligible au lieu de rester tout simplement dans lâinconnu has
producedââthe ancients, he thinks, must have been exempt from those
ravages.) Supposing that everything, âknownâ to man, fails to satisfy
his desires, and on the contrary contradicts and horrifies them, what a
divine way out of all this to be able to look for the responsibility,
not in the âdesiringâ but in âknowingâ!âââThere is no knowledge.
Consequentlyââthere is a Godâ; what a novel elegantia syllogismi! what a
triumph for the ascetic ideal!
26.
Or, perchance, does the whole of modern history show in its demeanour
greater confidence in life, greater confidence in its ideals? Its
loftiest pretension is now to be a mirror; it repudiates all teleology;
it will have no more âprovingâ; it disdains to play the judge, and
thereby shows its good tasteââit asserts as little as it denies, it
fixes, it âdescribes.â All this is to a high degree ascetic, but at the
same time it is to a much greater degree nihilistic; make no mistake
about this! You see in the historian a gloomy, hard, but determined
gaze,ââan eye that looks out as an isolated North Pole explorer looks
out (perhaps so as not to look within, so as not to look back?)ââthere
is snowââhere is life silenced, the last crows which caw here are called
âwhither?â âVanity,â âNadaâââhere nothing more flourishes and grows, at
the most the metapolitics of St. Petersburg and the âpityâ of Tolstoi.
But as for that other school of historians, a perhaps still more
âmodernâ school, a voluptuous and lascivious school which ogles life and
the ascetic ideal with equal fervour, which uses the word âartistâ as a
glove, and has nowadays established a âcornerâ for itself, in all the
praise given to contemplation; oh, what a thirst do these sweet
intellectuals excite even for ascetics and winter landscapes! Nay! The
devil take these âcontemplativeâ folk! How much liefer would I wander
with those historical Nihilists through the gloomiest, grey, cold
mist!âânay, I shall not mind listening (supposing I have to choose) to
one who is completely unhistorical and anti-historical (a man, like
DĂŒhring for instance, over whose periods a hitherto shy and unavowed
species of âbeautiful soulsâ has grown intoxicated in contemporary
Germany, the species anarchistica within the educated proletariate). The
âcontemplativeâ are a hundred times worseââI never knew anything which
produced such intense nausea as one of those âobjectiveâ chairs,[10] one
of those scented mannikins-about-town of history, a thing half-priest,
half-satyr (Renan parfum), which betrays by the high, shrill falsetto of
his applause what he lacks and where he lacks it, who betrays where in
this case the Fates have plied their ghastly shears, alas! in too
surgeon-like a fashion! This is distasteful to me, and irritates my
patience; let him keep patient at such sights who has nothing to lose
thereby,ââsuch a sight enrages me, such spectators embitter me against
the âplay,â even more than does the play itself (history itself, you
understand); Anacreontic moods imperceptibly come over me. This Nature,
who gave to the steer its horn, to the lion its ÏÎŹÏÎŒâ áœÎŽÎżÎœÏÏÎœ, for what
purpose did Nature give me my foot?ââTo kick, by St. Anacreon, and not
merely to run away! To trample on all the worm-eaten âchairs,â the
cowardly contemplators, the lascivious eunuchs of history, the flirters
with ascetic ideals, the righteous hypocrites of impotence! All
reverence on my part to the ascetic ideal, in so far as it is
honourable! So long as it believes in itself and plays no pranks on us!
But I like not all these coquettish bugs who have an insatiate ambition
to smell of the infinite, until eventually the infinite smells of bugs;
I like not the whited sepulchres with their stagey reproduction of life;
I like not the tired and the used up who wrap themselves in wisdom and
look âobjectiveâ; I like not the agitators dressed up as heroes, who
hide their dummy-heads behind the stalking-horse of an ideal; I like not
the ambitious artists who would fain play the ascetic and the priest,
and are at bottom nothing but tragic clowns; I like not, again, these
newest speculators in idealism, the Anti-Semites, who nowadays roll
their eyes in the patent Christian-Aryan-man-of-honour fashion, and by
an abuse of moralist attitudes and agitation dodges, so cheap as to
exhaust any patience, strive to excite all the blockhead elements in the
populace (the invariable success of every kind of intellectual
charlatanism in present-day Germany hangs together with the almost
indisputable and already quite palpable desolation of the German mind,
whose cause I look for in a too exclusive diet, of papers, politics,
beer, and Wagnerian music, not forgetting the condition precedent of
this diet, the national exclusiveness and vanity, the strong but narrow
principle, âGermany, Germany above everything,â[11] and finally the
paralysis agitans of âmodern ideasâ). Europe nowadays is, above all,
wealthy and ingenious in means of excitement; it apparently has no more
crying necessity than stimulantia and alcohol. Hence the enormous
counterfeiting of ideals, those most fiery spirits of the mind; hence
too the repulsive, evil-smelling, perjured, pseudoâalcoholic air
everywhere. I should like to know how many cargoes of imitation
idealism, of hero-costumes and high falutinâ clap-trap, how many casks
of sweetened pity liqueur (Firm: la religion de la souffrance), how many
crutches of righteous indignation for the help of these flat-footed
intellects, how many comedians of the Christian moral ideal would need
to-day to be exported from Europe, to enable its air to smell pure
again. It is obvious that, in regard to this over-production, a new
trade possibility lies open; it is obvious that there is a new business
to be done in little ideal idols and obedient âidealistsââdonât pass
over this tip! Who has sufficient courage? We have in our hands the
possibility of idealising the whole earth. But what am I talking about
courage? we only need one thing hereâa hand, a free, a very free hand.
27.
Enough! enough! let us leave these curiosities and complexities of the
modern spirit, which excite as much laughter as disgust. Our problem can
certainly do without them, the problem of meaning of the ascetic
idealâwhat has it got to do with yesterday or to-day? those things shall
be handled by me more thoroughly and severely in another connection
(under the title âA Contribution to the History of European Nihilism,â I
refer for this to a work which I am preparing: The Will to Power, an
Attempt at a Transvaluation of All Values). The only reason why I come
to allude to it here is this: the ascetic ideal has at times, even in
the most intellectual sphere, only one real kind of enemies and
damagers: these are the comedians of this idealâfor they awake mistrust.
Everywhere otherwise, where the mind is at work seriously, powerfully,
and without counterfeiting, it dispenses altogether now with an ideal
(the popular expression for this abstinence is âAtheismâ)âwith the
exception of the will for truth. But this will, this remnant of an
ideal, is, if you will believe me, that ideal itself in its severest and
cleverest formulation, esoteric through and through, stripped of all
outworks, and consequently not so much its remnant as its kernel.
Unqualified honest atheism (and its air only do we breathe, we, the most
intellectual men of this age) is not opposed to that ideal, to the
extent that it appears to be; it is rather one of the final phases of
its evolution, one of its syllogisms and pieces of inherent logicâit is
the awe-inspiring catastrophe of a two-thousand-year training in truth,
which finally forbids itself the lie of the belief in God. (The same
course of development in Indiaâquite independently, and consequently of
some demonstrative valueâthe same ideal driving to the same conclusion
the decisive point reached five hundred years before the European era,
or more precisely at the time of Buddhaâit started in the Sankhyam
philosophy, and then this was popularised through Buddha, and made into
a religion.)
What, I put the question with all strictness, has really triumphed over
the Christian God? The answer stands in my Joyful Wisdom, Aph. 357: âthe
Christian morality itself, the idea of truth, taken as it was with
increasing seriousness, the confessor-subtlety of the Christian
conscience translated and sublimated into the scientific conscience into
intellectual cleanness at any price. Regarding Nature as though it were
a proof of the goodness and guardianship of God; interpreting history in
honour of a divine reason, as a constant proof of a moral order of the
world and a moral teleology; explaining our own personal experiences, as
pious men have for long enough explained them, as though every
arrangement, every nod, every single thing were invented and sent out of
love for the salvation of the soul; all this is now done away with, all
this has the conscience against it, and is regarded by every subtler
conscience as disreputable, dishonourable, as lying, feminism, weakness,
cowardiceâby means of this severity, if by means of anything at all, are
we, in sooth, good Europeans and heirs of Europeâs longest and bravest
self-mastery.â... All great things go to ruin by reason of themselves,
by reason of an act of self-dissolution: so wills the law of life, the
law of necessary âself-masteryâ even in the essence of lifeâever is the
law-giver finally exposed to the cry, âpatere legem quam ipse tulistiâ;
in thus wise did Christianity go to ruin as a dogma, through its own
morality; in thus wise must Christianity go again to ruin to-day as a
moralityâwe are standing on the threshold of this event. After Christian
truthfulness has drawn one conclusion after the other, it finally draws
its strongest conclusion, its conclusion against itself; this, however,
happens, when it puts the question, âwhat is the meaning of every will
for truth?â And here again do I touch on my problem, on our problem, my
unknown friends (for as yet I know of no friends): what sense has our
whole being, if it does not mean that in our own selves that will for
truth has come to its own consciousness as a problem?â--By reason of
this attainment of self-consciousness on the part of the will for truth,
morality from henceforwardâthere is no doubt about itâgoes to pieces:
this is that great hundred-act play that is reserved for the next two
centuries of Europe, the most terrible, the most mysterious, and perhaps
also the most hopeful of all plays.
28.
If you except the ascetic ideal, man, the animal man had no meaning. His
existence on earth contained no end; âWhat is the purpose of man at
all?â was a question without an answer; the will for man and the world
was lacking; behind every great human destiny rang as a refrain a still
greater âVanity!â The ascetic ideal simply means this: that something
was lacking, that a tremendous void encircled manâhe did not know how to
justify himself, to explain himself, to affirm himself, he suffered from
the problem of his own meaning. He suffered also in other ways, he was
in the main a diseased animal; but his problem was not suffering itself,
but the lack of an answer to that crying question, âTo what purpose do
we suffer?â Man, the bravest animal and the one most inured to
suffering, does not repudiate suffering in itself: he wills it, he even
seeks it out, provided that he is shown a meaning for it, a purpose of
suffering. Not suffering, but the senselessness of suffering was the
curse which till then lay spread over humanityâand the ascetic ideal
gave it a meaning! It was up till then the only meaning; but any meaning
is better than no meaning; the ascetic ideal was in that connection the
âfaute de mieuxâ par excellence that existed at that time. In that ideal
suffering found an explanation; the tremendous gap seemed filled; the
door to all suicidal Nihilism was closed. The explanationâthere is no
doubt about itâbrought in its train new suffering, deeper, more
penetrating, more venomous, gnawing more brutally into life: it brought
all suffering under the perspective of guilt; but in spite of all
thatâman was saved thereby, he had a meaning, and from henceforth was no
more like a leaf in the wind, a shuttle-cock of chance, of nonsense, he
could now âwillâ somethingâabsolutely immaterial to what end, to what
purpose, with what means he wished: the will itself was saved. It is
absolutely impossible to disguise what in point of fact is made clear by
every complete will that has taken its direction from the ascetic ideal:
this hate of the human, and even more of the animal, and more still of
the material, this horror of the senses, of reason itself, this fear of
happiness and beauty, this desire to get right away from all illusion,
change, growth, death, wishing and even desiringâall this meansâlet us
have the courage to grasp itâa will for Nothingness, a will opposed to
life, a repudiation of the most fundamental conditions of life, but it
is and remains a will!âand to say at the end that which I said at the
beginningâman will wish Nothingness rather than not wish at all.
The following twenty-seven fragments were intended by Nietzsche to form
a supplement to Chapter VIII. of Beyond Good and Evil, dealing with
Peoples and Countries.
1.
The Europeans now imagine themselves as representing, in the main, the
highest types of men on earth.
2.
A characteristic of Europeans: inconsistency between word and deed; the
Oriental is true to himself in daily life. How the European has
established colonies is explained by his nature, which resembles that of
a beast of prey.
This inconsistency is explained by the fact that Christianity has
abandoned the class from which it sprang.
This is the difference between us and the Hellenes: their morals grew up
among the governing castes. Thucydidesâ morals are the same as those
that exploded everywhere with Plato.
Attempts towards honesty at the Renaissance, for example: always for the
benefit of the arts. Michael Angeloâs conception of God as the âTyrant
of the Worldâ was an honest one.
3.
I rate Michael Angelo higher than Raphael, because, through all the
Christian clouds and prejudices of his time, he saw the ideal of a
culture nobler than the Christo-Raphaelian: whilst Raphael truly and
modestly glorified only the values handed down to him, and did not carry
within himself any inquiring, yearning instincts. Michael Angelo, on the
other hand, saw and felt the problem of the law-giver of new values: the
problem of the conqueror made perfect, who first had to subdue the âhero
within himself,â the man exalted to his highest pedestal, master even of
his pity, who mercilessly shatters and annihilates everything that does
not bear his own stamp, shining in Olympian divinity. Michael Angelo was
naturally only at certain moments so high and so far beyond his age and
Christian Europe: for the most part he adopted a condescending attitude
towards the eternal feminine in Christianity; it would seem, indeed,
that in the end he broke down before her, and gave up the ideal of his
most inspired hours. It was an ideal which only a man in the strongest
and highest vigour of life could bear; but not a man advanced in years!
Indeed, he would have had to demolish Christianity with his ideal! But
he was not thinker and philosopher enough for that Perhaps Leonardo da
Vinci alone of those artists had a really super-Christian outlook. He
knows the East, the âland of dawn,â within himself as well as without
himself. There is something super-European and silent in him: a
characteristic of every one who has seen too wide a circle of things
good and bad.
4.
How much we have learnt and learnt anew in fifty years! The whole
Romantic School with its belief in âthe peopleâ is refuted! No Homeric
poetry as âpopularâ poetry! No deification of the great powers of
Nature! No deduction from language-relationship to race-relationship! No
âintellectual contemplationsâ of the supernatural! No truth enshrouded
in religion!
The problem of truthfulness is quite a new one. I am astonished. From
this standpoint we regard such natures as Bismarck as culpable out of
carelessness, such as Richard Wagner out of want of modesty; we would
condemn Plato for his pia fraus, Kant for the derivation of his
Categorical Imperative, his own belief certainly not having come to him
from this source.
Finally, even doubt turns against itself: doubt in doubt. And the
question as to the value of truthfulness and its extent lies there.
5.
What I observe with pleasure in the German is his Mephistophelian
nature; but, to tell the truth, one must have a higher conception of
Mephistopheles than Goethe had, who found it necessary to diminish his
Mephistopheles in order to magnify his âinner Faust.â The true German
Mephistopheles is much more dangerous, bold, wicked, and cunning, and
consequently more open-hearted: remember the nature of Frederick the
Great, or of that much greater Frederick, the Hohenstaufen, Frederick
II.
The real German Mephistopheles crosses the Alps, and believes that
everything there belongs to him. Then he recovers himself, like
Winckelmann, like Mozart. He looks upon Faust and Hamlet as caricatures,
invented to be laughed at, and upon Luther also. Goethe had his good
German moments, when he laughed inwardly at all these things. But then
he fell back again into his cloudy moods.
6.
Perhaps the Germans have only grown up in a wrong climate! There is
something in them that might be Hellenic!âsomething that is awakened
when they are brought into touch with the SouthâWinckelmann, Goethe,
Mozart. We should not forget, however, that we are still young. Luther
is still our last event; our last book is still the Bible. The Germans
have never yet âmoralised.â Also, the very food of the Germans was their
doom: its consequence, Philistinism.
7.
The Germans are a dangerous people: they are experts at inventing
intoxicants. Gothic, rococo (according to Semper), the historical sense
and exoticism, Hegel, Richard WagnerâLeibniz, too (dangerous at the
present day)â(they even idealised the serving soul as the virtue of
scholars and soldiers, also as the simple mind). The Germans may well be
the most composite people on earth.
âThe people of the Middle,â the inventors of porcelain, and of a kind of
Chinese breed of Privy Councillor.
8.
The smallness and baseness of the German soul were not and are not
consequences of the system of small states; for it is well known that
the inhabitants of much smaller states were proud and independent: and
it is not a large state per se that makes souls freer and more manly.
The man whose soul obeys the slavish command: âThou shalt and must
kneel!â in whose body there is an involuntary bowing and scraping to
titles, orders, gracious glances from aboveâwell, such a man in an
âEmpireâ will only bow all the more deeply and lick the dust more
fervently in the presence of the greater sovereign than in the presence
of the lesser: this cannot be doubted. We can still see in the lower
classes of Italians that aristocratic self-sufficiency; manly discipline
and self-confidence still form a part of the long history of their
country: these are virtues which once manifested themselves before their
eyes. A poor Venetian gondolier makes a far better figure than a Privy
Councillor from Berlin, and is even a better man in the endâany one can
see this. Just ask the women.
9.
Most artists, even some of the greatest (including the historians) have
up to the present belonged to the serving classes (whether they serve
people of high position or princes or women or âthe massesâ), not to
speak of their dependence upon the Church and upon moral law. Thus
Rubens portrayed the nobility of his age; but only according to their
vague conception of taste, not according to his own measure of beauty on
the whole, therefore, against his own taste. Van Dyck was nobler in this
respect: who in all those whom he painted added a certain amount of what
he himself most highly valued: he did not descend from himself, but
rather lifted up others to himself when he ârendered.â
The slavish humility of the artist to his public (as Sebastian Bach has
testified in undying and outrageous words in the dedication of his High
Mass) is perhaps more difficult to perceive in music; but it is all the
more deeply engrained. A hearing would be refused me if I endeavoured to
impart my views on this subject. Chopin possesses distinction, like Van
Dyck. The disposition of Beethoven is that of a proud peasant; of Haydn,
that of a proud servant. Mendelssohn, too, possesses distinctionâlike
Goethe, in the most natural way in the world.
10.
We could at any time have counted on the fingers of one hand those
German learned men who possessed wit: the remainder have understanding,
and a few of them, happily, that famous âchildlike characterâ which
divines.... It is our privilege: with this âdivinationâ German science
has discovered some things which we can hardly conceive of, and which,
after all, do not exist, perhaps. It is only the Jews among the Germans
who do not âdivineâ like them.
11.
As Frenchmen reflect the politeness and esprit of French society, so do
Germans reflect something of the deep, pensive earnestness of their
mystics and musicians, and also of their silly childishness. The Italian
exhibits a great deal of republican distinction and art, and can show
himself to be noble and proud without vanity.
12.
A larger number of the higher and better-endowed men will, I hope, have
in the end so much self-restraint as to be able to get rid of their bad
taste for affectation and sentimental darkness, and to turn against
Richard Wagner as much as against Schopenhauer. These two Germans are
leading us to ruin; they flatter our dangerous qualities. A stronger
future is prepared for us in Goethe, Beethoven, and Bismarck than in
these racial aberrations. We have had no philosophers yet.
13.
The peasant is the commonest type of noblesse, for he is dependent upon
himself most of all. Peasant blood is still the best blood in Germany
âfor example, Luther, Niebuhr, Bismarck.
Bismarck a Slav. Let any one look upon the face of Germans. Everything
that had manly, exuberant blood in it went abroad. Over the smug
populace remaining, the slave-souled people, there came an improvement
from abroad, especially by a mixture of Slavonic blood.
The Brandenburg nobility and the Prussian nobility in general (and the
peasant of certain North German districts), comprise at present the most
manly natures in Germany.
That the manliest men shall rule: this is only the natural order of
things.
14.
The future of German culture rests with the sons of the Prussian
officers.
15.
There has always been a want of wit in Germany, and mediocre heads
attain there to the highest honours, because even they are rare. What is
most highly prized is diligence and perseverance and a certain
cold-blooded, critical outlook, and, for the sake of such qualities,
German scholarship and the German military system have become paramount
in Europe.
16.
Parliaments may be very useful to a strong and versatile statesman: he
has something there to rely upon (every such thing must, however, be
able to resist!)âupon which he can throw a great deal of responsibility.
On the whole, however, I could wish that the counting mania and the
superstitious belief in majorities were not established in Germany, as
with the Latin races, and that one could finally invent something new
even in politics! It is senseless and dangerous to let the custom of
universal suffrageâwhich is still but a short time under cultivation,
and could easily be uprootedâtake a deeper root: whilst, of course, its
introduction was merely an expedient to steer clear of temporary
difficulties.
17.
Can any one interest himself in this German Empire? Where is the new
thought? Is it only a new combination of power? All the worse, if it
does not know its own mind. Peace and laisser aller are not types of
politics for which I have any respect. Ruling, and helping the highest
thoughts to victoryâthe only things that can make me interested in
Germany. Englandâs small-mindedness is the great danger now on earth. I
observe more inclination towards greatness in the feelings of the
Russian Nihilists than in those of the English Utilitarians. We require
an intergrowth of the German and Slav races, and we require, too, the
cleverest financiers, the Jews, for us to become masters of the world.
(a) The sense of reality.
(b) A giving-up of the English principle of the peopleâs right of
representation. We require the representation of the great interests.
(c) We require an unconditional union with Russia, together with a
mutual plan of action which shall not permit any English schemata to
obtain the mastery in Russia. No American future!
(d) A national system of politics is untenable, and embarrassment by
Christian views is a very great evil. In Europe all sensible people are
sceptics, whether they say so or not.
18.
I see over and beyond all these national wars, new âempires,â and
whatever else lies in the foreground. What I am concerned withâfor I see
it preparing itself slowly and hesitatinglyâis the United Europe. It was
the only real work, the one impulse in the souls, of all the
broad-minded and deep-thinking men of this centuryâthis preparation of a
new synthesis, and the tentative effort to anticipate the future of âthe
European.â Only in their weaker moments, or when they grew old, did they
fall back again into the national narrowness of the âFatherlandersââthen
they were once more âpatriots.â I am thinking of men like Napoleon,
Heinrich Heine, Goethe, Beethoven, Stendhal, Schopenhauer. Perhaps
Richard Wagner likewise belongs to their number, concerning whom, as a
successful type of German obscurity, nothing can be said without some
such âperhaps.â
But to the help of such minds as feel the need of a new unity there
comes a great explanatory economic fact: the small States of EuropeâI
refer to all our present kingdoms and âempiresââwill in a short time
become economically untenable, owing to the mad, uncontrolled struggle
for the possession of local and international trade. Money is even now
compelling European nations to amalgamate into one Power. In order,
however, that Europe may enter into the battle for the mastery of the
world with good prospects of victory (it is easy to perceive against
whom this battle will be waged), she must probably âcome to an
understandingâ with England. The English colonies are needed for this
struggle, just as much as modern Germany, to play her new rĂŽle of broker
and middleman, requires the colonial possessions of Holland. For no one
any longer believes that England alone is strong enough to continue to
act her old part for fifty years more; the impossibility of shutting out
homines novi from the government will ruin her, and her continual change
of political parties is a fatal obstacle to the carrying out of any
tasks which require to be spread out over a long period of time. A man
must to-day be a soldier first and foremost that he may not afterwards
lose his credit as a merchant. Enough; here, as in other matters, the
coming century will be found following in the footsteps of Napoleonâthe
first man, and the man of greatest initiative and advanced views, of
modern times. For the tasks of the next century, the methods of popular
representation and parliaments are the most inappropriate imaginable.
19.
The condition of Europe in the next century will once again lead to the
breeding of manly virtues, because men will live in continual danger.
Universal military service is already the curious antidote which we
possess for the effeminacy of democratic ideas, and it has grown up out
of the struggle of the nations. (Nationâmen who speak one language and
read the same newspapers. These men now call themselves ânations,â and
would far too readily trace their descent from the same source and
through the same history; which, however, even with the assistance of
the most malignant lying in the past, they have not succeeded in doing.)
20.
What quagmires and mendacity must there be about if it is possible, in
the modern European hotch-potch, to raise questions of âraceâ! (It being
premised that the origin of such writers is not in Horneo and Borneo.)
21.
Maxim: To associate with no man who takes any part in the mendacious
race swindle.
22.
With the freedom of travel now existing, groups of men of the same
kindred can join together and establish communal habits and customs. The
overcoming of ânations.â
23.
To make Europe a centre of culture, national stupidities should not make
us blind to the fact that in the higher regions there is already a
continuous reciprocal dependence. France and German philosophy. Richard
Wagner and Paris (1830â50). Goethe and Greece. All things are impelled
towards, a synthesis of the European past in the highest types of mind.
24.
Mankind has still much before itâhow, generally speaking, could the
ideal be taken from the past? Perhaps merely in relation to the present,
which latter is possibly a lower region.
25.
This is our distrust, which recurs again and again; our care, which
never lets us sleep; our question, which no one listens to or wishes to
listen to; our Sphinx, near which there is more than one precipice: we
believe that the men of present-day Europe are deceived in regard to the
things which we love best, and a pitiless demon (no, not pitiless, only
indifferent and puerile)âplays with our hearts and their enthusiasm, as
it may perhaps have already played with everything that lived and loved;
I believe that everything which we Europeans of to-day are in the habit
of admiring as the values of all these respected things called
âhumanity,â âmankind,â âsympathy,â âpity,â may be of some value as the
debilitation and moderating of certain powerful and dangerous primitive
impulses. Nevertheless, in the long run all these things are nothing
else than the belittlement of the entire type âman,â his mediocrisation,
if in such a desperate situation I may make use of such a desperate
expression. I think that the commedia umana for an epicurean
spectator-god must consist in this: that the Europeans, by virtue of
their growing morality, believe in all their innocence and vanity that
they are rising higher and higher, whereas the truth is that they are
sinking lower and lowerâi.e. through the cultivation of all the virtues
which are useful to a herd, and through the repression of the other and
contrary virtues which give rise to a new, higher, stronger, masterful
race of menâthe first-named virtues merely develop the herd-animal in
man and stabilitate the animal âman,â for until now man has been âthe
animal as yet unstabilitated.â
26.
Genius and Epoch.âHeroism is no form of selfishness, for one is
shipwrecked by it.... The direction of power is often conditioned by the
state of the period in which the great man happens to be born; and this
fact brings about the superstition that he is the expression of his
time. But this same power could be applied in several different ways;
and between him and his time there is always this difference: that
public opinion always worships the herd instinct,âi.e. the instinct of
the weak,âwhile he, the strong man, rights for strong ideals.
27.
The fate now overhanging Europe is simply this: that it is exactly her
strongest sons that come rarely and late to the spring-time of their
existence; that, as a rule, when they are already in their early youth
they perish, saddened, disgusted, darkened in mind, just because they
have already, with the entire passion of their strength, drained to the
dregs the cup of disillusionment, which in our days means the cup of
knowledge, and they would not have been the strongest had they not also
been the most disillusionised. For that is the test of their powerâthey
must first of all rise out of the illness of their epoch to reach their
own health. A late spring-time is their mark of distinction; also, let
us add, late merriment, late folly, the late exuberance of joy! For this
is the danger of to-day: everything that we loved when we were young has
betrayed us. Our last loveâthe love which makes us acknowledge her, our
love for Truthâlet us take care that she, too, does not betray us!
[1] An allusion to the celebrated monologue in William Tell.
[2] Mistress Sly.âTr.
[3] In the German text âHeiland.â This has the double meaning of
âhealerâ and âsaviour.ââH. B. S.
[4] âHorrible beast.â
[5] An allusion to the celebrated monologue in William Tell.
[6] Mistress Sly.âTr.
[7] In the German text âHeiland.â This has the double meaning of
âhealerâ and âsaviour.ââH. B. S.
[8] âHorrible beast.â
[9] âHere I stand! I cannot help myself. God help me! Amenââwere
Lutherâs words before the Reichstag at Worms.âH. B. S.
[10] E.g. Lectureships.
[11] An allusion to the well-known patriotic song.âH. B. S.