💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › alfredo-m-bonanno-why-a-vanguard.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:21:49. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Why a Vanguard?
Author: Alfredo M. Bonanno
Date: 1977
Language: en
Topics: organization
Source: Retrieved on October 10, 2010 from http://digitalelephant.blogspot.com/2010/08/why-vanguard.html
Notes: Original title: Avanguardia, perche? published in Movimento e progetto rivoluzionaria, Edizioni Anarchismo — Nuovi contributi per una rivoluzione anarchica — 1 — 1977. translated by Jean Weir

Alfredo M. Bonanno

Why a Vanguard?

The ideas that follow are aimed at going into the problem of the

relations between the movement of the exploited and the revolutionary

anarchist movement.

The conclusion is very simple and constitutes the starting point of a

reflection that we are proposing to all comrades: it is not within the

enclosure of the specific anarchist movement that one works for the

revolution, but outside in the reality of struggles, which at this

moment do not see us present. In this sense the anarchist movement still

has a long way to go. In the face of the urgency of the situation it has

become imperative for all sincere revolutionary anarchist comrades to

reflect on the ways and conditions of organising oneself to contribute

to the widening, in the libertarian sense, of the present situation of

crises and discomfort.

The time for hesitation and waiting is over. May whoever is available

for the revolutionary struggle seek his or her comrades and not indulge

in waiting for a sign or clarification on the part of the specific

movement.

AMB

Why a vanguard?

The problem of the vanguard has been gone into by all conscious

revolutionaries past and present. They fear its dangers and try to see

what causes it and how to eliminate it or attenuate its effects.

The problem is far more serious for anarchists. They do not accept the

political expedients that other revolutionaries end up justifying in

their haste to take power.

All the same, anarchists also end up producing vanguards but they are

careful not to call them such, a word they detest. But we have no fig

leaf with which to cover up reality, and if this includes structures

that are the same or similar to those of the authoritarians, it is

pointless to try to conceal the fact simply by using different words.

Is a vanguard necessary then?

There is no simple answer to this. Anarchists have tended to bury their

heads in the sand until now, hoping to solve the problem through the use

of metaphors.

We feel we must take a step forward and risk upsetting those that are

obstinately holding on to their positions like the same old octopus on

the same old rock.

Many have cut the problem short by simply stating that there is a need

for a vanguard. Pushing the underlying ideology — always present in

anarchism — in an authoritarian direction, they pull their sleeves up

and set to work. With the aid of some extremely distilled and refined

theories, they start to build mysterious constructions that are maxims

of control and selection.

Such a position does not differ much from those who, categorically

denying that there is any such thing as a vanguard in anarchism, refuse

to see reality as it is.

This tendency — usually wrapped up in humanistic rhetoric bordering on

nebulous idealism — is the sworn enemy of the former which it accuses of

being the most sinister Leninism camouflaged as anarchism. On the other

hand, the more sharp-witted part of the movement, aware of the

difficulties involved in trying to justify some of the leadership,

replace the term “vanguard” with “active minority” and similar

euphemisms.

However, the problem is not just a question of words. We are not

interested in substituting one term with another and explaining why, but

are trying to get to the root of the problems that such a concept leads

to.

And the question does not change if we call the “thing” a vanguard or an

active minority.

What is this thing then? What is a revolutionary vanguard?

The answer looks simple: it is an organic whole composed of the

individuals that make it up. This organisation tends to cut itself off

from and impose itself upon the revolutionary movement that produced it.

Let us look at this in stages.

There are many ways to justify the need for a specific organisation to

take on certain problems that mass organisations cannot solve.

Obviously, those who make up this organisation must have three

attributes: a) knowledge; b) commitment; c) time. Power establishes

itself on the basis of authoritativeness rather than authority in the

narrow sense of the word. We are talking of revolutionary organisations

in general, but let us not lose sight of those we are particularly

interested in examining, anarchist organisations. It is precisely in the

latter that elements of authoritativeness predominate over authority,

leaving the underlying problem intact: that of the growth and

consolidation of an organisation (therefore of a group of people) that

exerts control over the rest of the movement.

The revolution is eminently an organisational event, so it is no wonder

that a process of organisational superstructuring comes about when base

organisations multiply. This could quite well be limited (at least in

the early stages) by pointing to the questions that such an organisation

should concern itself with and controlling it through a recall of its

delegates. We shall see why such expedients (limitation of tasks and

recall of delegates) constitute very fragile bulwarks, and how these are

often simply used to solve consciences, i.e. as alibis, rather than as

instruments with which to limit power as such.

When the counterrevolution lets loose, this group tends to close in on

itself. Repression and clandestinity have the effect of making it turn

into a militarised group which (suddenly or gradually) loses its

relationship with the old base organisations, the first to succumb to

the repression. At other times the predominant organisational group

splits into a number of separate or coordinated groups that — still

limited in number — carry on the struggle, often drawing in those from

the base organisation who prefer to go into clandestinity. We are

looking at an extreme situation here that reduces the value of the work

done at other times when the counterrevolution leaves the revolutionary

movement relatively in peace. But the problems arising from this

radicalisation are none other than those that already existed, now in a

more rarified, obvious, form.

The conditions leading to the formation of the vanguard are therefore

linked to the development of revolutionary activity itself. An

organisation formed of men and women — the best available — emerges, and

along with it the danger of its beginning to reason independently in

keeping with the logic of all organisations, their main priority

becoming their own survival.

Such a conclusion would seem to implicate the inevitability of a

vanguard, yet, on the contrary, I believe that it is possible to go

beyond a minority logic. However, in order for this to become clear a

number of points need to be considered.

The organisational question

Nothing is possible without organisation. Human life would stop and

everything would fall into chaos. Organisation is indispensable to man

to such an extent that any improvement in the latter, even if carried

out by tyrants, is to be considered something positive. The very idea of

progress would never have come about had organisation not been essential

to man. In this sense, if history is the development of anything it is

the development of something organised.

The power structure is a fairly refined organisation aimed at attaining

ends for the benefit of a minority. The majority are engaged in bringing

about these ends. But we cannot deny that the interests of the minority

also hold certain positive aspects for the majority. The latter would

rebel or die otherwise and the former’s aims would not be reached.

The power structure is full of expedients for obtaining the maximum

whilst giving the minimum. It elaborates these expedients and puts them

into effect, modifying them from time to time in relation to the

struggle carried out by the majority, i.e. the exploited.

The latter, as a result of various — all dramatic — experiences of

struggle, have developed organisations of their own to make the clash

more effective. These have gradually entered the logic of exploitation

and become an integral part of it, coinciding with power’s discovery of

the untenability of absolutism and the idiocy of fascist irrationalism.

This is how democratic power was born, an organisation that continues to

exploit the majority to the benefit of the minority but does so using

the majority’s own organisations of defence.

Moreover, what has made this possible is the fact that the defence

organisations of the majority have nearly always come into effect after

becoming legalised.

But organisational activity should not necessarily be seen as something

that is built from the outside by specialists who make decisions

according to their own aims. This interpretation contains two basic

errors: what we could call the biological error, and the functionalist

one. According to this way of thinking an organisation must structure

itself more or less like an organism (have a head and limbs, therefore a

hierarchy) and fulfil the essential requirements of efficiency and

functionality. If the exploited majority cannot defend themselves

because they are dispersed in single units (like the cells of organic

tissue), we must put these cells together and build a body with a

precious structure (i.e. trades unions and unions in general) suited to

the aims in view, to oppose the bosses in the process of exploitation

and to defend the majority.

The justification for this is the concept that, because the bosses’

structure is monolithic, the defence structure should also be so.

The biological and functionalist analogy also dominated in the field of

political defence, as party structures increased in importance alongside

the decline of absolutist States.

The justification, the monolithicity of the State.

This is all quite pathetic. The great irony of history lies in the fact

that it was power itself to decide the terms of the huge defence

organisations. These terms were produced on an organic and functional

basis, often as the involuntary consequence of certain modifications

within the power structure itself. Clearly an organism of defence is a

product of a particular historical period, and nearly always

consolidates in a precise relationship with the power structure that

conditions it and renders it possible.

An incredible number of comrades maintain that they are revolutionary

yet insist on the validity of using the defence structures of the

exploited. They see the latter as instruments of struggle, unaware of

the intimate relationship of dependency that exists between them and the

structures of power.

But history has contributed to clarifying this question. Each time the

exploited have moved from defence to attack and a revolutionary

mechanism has sprung into effect, other kinds of organisational

structure have arisen.

The problem of the great defence organisations of the exploited is not

the fact that they exist — something that is natural and ineliminable —

but precisely the defensive dimension that they have adopted. That is

why they “copy” the organisations of the adversary and use the same

logic.

On the other hand, organisations of attack do not reproduce the

biological functionalism of the defensive ones. These organisational

forms have no intention of becoming a great monolithic structure, so

allow the process of breaking up to continue. They do not want to

reproduce the model of the adversary by using the same logic. It is true

that organisations of defence can also be mobilised to attack but this

turns out to be a military-style clash that might look revolutionary but

which can have no other outcome than the persistence of the old power or

the birth of a new one, possibly more tyrannical than the first.

Organisations of attack, on the other hand, are born on the basis of a

social logic that takes people’s needs, the level of exploitation and

the extent of radicalisation that the clash has reached into account.

These organisations do not suffer from functionalist illusions. They

cannot be improved upon, they do not hope to “grow”. Neither do they put

themselves in the logic of a “dialogue” with power. They are for the

destruction of all power from the moment they appear, so in their very

logic they are already “complete” in themselves. They can of course

perfect themselves from the point of view of tactics, the preparation of

their individual components or aspects of the military clash. But as far

as the organisational aspect is concerned there is nothing to be

improved upon and vice versa. They are beyond the logic of power. They

are “outlaws”.

Not seeking quantitative growth they have no need for a “head” or

“limbs”. They orientate themselves towards the reality of exploitation,

emerging in their organisational completeness at the moment in which

they attack power. They do not have one function among others, but have

the “definitive function” of destroying power.

It is not important to describe here what forms these organisations of

attack have taken in the history of the exploited (councils, soviets,

committees, etc.), or might take in the near future. Nor are we

interested in discussing an important and immediately obvious

characteristic of these organisations, autonomy.

On the contrary, we feel that it is necessary to reflect upon two

things: a) that these organisations never lose sight of the individual

(that is also an organisation); b) in the destructive moment they become

a model for the construction of the future society.

Now we have acquired a new problem. The single individual is an

organisation, or rather is the fundamental organisation. Here the

confusion concerning an apparent contradiction between individualism and

anarchist communism disappears. While the former sometimes adopts

attitudes that are strangely absurd (the defence of small property, the

will to power, a disdain for communist life, etc.), most of this is no

more than isolated attitudes that have had little contact with the

reality of the struggles of the exploited. A typical case is that of the

humanists who recognise themselves in anarchism but, hindered by their

idealistic interpretation of the vicissitudes of man, end up losing the

essential foundation of the exploiter/exploited relationship. They bring

the attributes of the old God down to earth and turn them into a new

myth, quite similar to the old one that only served the designs of

power.

This kind of individualism is clearly a distortion of the more rational

doctrines of egoism. It denies the concept of organisation and tends to

see man as continually realising himself within an animalistic dimension

of the struggle for life. It sees the communist dimension as the

negation of human development, the sacrifice of the individual to the

good society. It fights for the liberation of the individual outside a

communitarian perspective, avoiding the fundamental premise that the

slavery of one single individual in the world is also my own.

On the contrary, when individualism is seen correctly it starts from the

concept that, although simple and basic from the point of view of social

dynamics, the individual is already a complex organisation. This

organisation can establish precise relationships with other

organisation-individuals and is capable of changing or regulating them.

It can even realise itself in the absolute sacrifice, the conscious

negation of itself — death — when this seems necessary in order to

overturn the exploiter-exploited relationship that renders the

organisation-individual incomplete and unhappy.

Supreme egoism, i.e. autonomy, is the organisational perfectionment of

the individual, a precise relationship that does not infringe upon other

organisation-individuals.

A proper exposition of this problem is extremely important for

anarchism. It leads to a clearer vision of the struggle against

exploitation, even when this comes about in situations that are

confusing or in not quite orthodox organisational forms. When it comes

to defence it should be said that anarchist structures often condemn any

form of struggle that is produced independently of themselves,

considering them to be individualist in the negative sense of the word

and branding them “objectively provocatory”.

For individualism, the essential point is that the individual is an

autonomous organisation that usually reacts against what has been

established by power, often by working out its own precepts, clarifying

itself and taking the initiative. At that moment a precise moral event

sets in motion: the individual, no longer an unconscious instrument in

the hands of power, acquires an autonomous perspective that is of an

essentially organisational character.

The other aspect of the organisational moment we have defined “attack”

is its preparation as the destructive instrument to act upon the reality

of exploitation, and as a model to build from once this relationship is

abolished.

Objective conditions push the great mass of exploited to look for these

organisational models, which are impeded by the power of the adversary.

If the heavy power structure starts to show signs of weakness at some

point, needs and problems must be faced differently. Usually, in

building forms of attack, the mass also build forms to solve the

problems of survival. The latter are very significant because they are

based on communist relations.

The illusion of quantity

The main element of the organisational structuring of defence is

quantitative growth. This has been conditioned by the logic of power.

The greater the numbers, the more an organisation is considered to be

significant, strong, well known, important. In this sense, if the power

structure is the stronger organisation, if it is at its peak and covers

every manifestation of associated life, any organisation that intends to

contrast it and represent the rights of the great majority of exploited

must aim to be as strong as possible.

At first glance such statements seem quite unexceptional. And so they

are if one puts oneself in the logic of power. If we want to defend

ourselves from an evil force we need to oppose it with a good force

i.e., one that is, if not equally strong, at least strong enough to

scare it. But in this way one is putting oneself in the logic of power,

unaware that any significant growth in numbers simply shifts the class

relationship without actually putting the latter in question. It does

not abolish classes.

By channelling revolutionary and reformist organisations towards the

quantitative illusion, power has obtained one great result. It has

equalised the latter at the organisational level, reducing differences

to whoever shouts loudest. And we well know how he that shouts loudest

is often the one most easily disposed to stopping shouting all of a

sudden, or to start shouting for the opposite side.

Revolutionary organisations cannot grow quantitatively. If they do, that

being in the logic of power, the difference between revolutionaries and

reformists becomes no more than a question of semantics, something that

power does not fear.

Of course, quantity does not catch the reformists unaware. Betrayal is

implicit in their discourse and so is their insertion into relations

that are managed by power. Now dominated by the structures of

exploitation, they act out the role assigned to them in the modern

liberal-social setup.

On the other hand, even revolutionaries in good faith fall prey to the

quantitative illusion. That is the point that interests us most, which

we want to go into here.

A revolutionary comrade must be considered to be in good faith until

proved otherwise. Questions of clarification and criticism must never be

at a personal level but must focus on the comrade’s choices and the

consequences that they have on the whole organisation. In this sense the

comrade’s good faith must be put to the test through a decisive action

that gets to the root of things and does not stop at appearances, in

other words through a penetrating action that is not limited to the

field of abstract revolutionary ideology.

The quantitative illusion is very important for authoritarian comrades,

but always within certain limits. They realise that they are starting

off on the wrong foot and that it is not possible to go beyond something

that would merely like to become part of real situations of struggle.

Unfortunately, they often prefer to wait for that to come about (i.e. be

facilitated) by the precipitation of events. They proceed to build

strong organisations that are revolutionary in appearance alone, being

in fact organisations of defence, therefore losers before they start.

Numerical growth in the latter leads comrades to foster this illusion.

It makes them feel strong and secure. So they grow steadfastly in that

direction, which is precisely what power wants: the acceptance of an

innocuous expression of revolution as something that is quantitative and

nothing else, so it is easily pulled back into the logic of the power

system.

The illusion of quantity is absolutely critical for anarchist

organisations, which cannot become useless, sterile and

counterproductive, their growth simply quantitative. Nor would it be

plausible for them to simply wait for events to precipitate. Anarchists

would not be able to act in something that is structured as a defence

organisation, as they would not be willing to transform it into a

pyramidal structure. At a radical point in the struggle when events

precipitate, they would be forced to put their organisation to the test,

dismember it and take it back to the elementary form that it should have

had at the start. Much of the history of anarchism can be seen from this

optic: the failure of the Russian revolution, the authoritarian

involution of the Spanish one.

Many anarchists are now playing the part of Penelope, weaving what they

know they will have to unstitch, precisely at the moment when the aims

they are struggling for come about. Apart from a few marginal efforts,

the present organisational forms of the anarchist movement are no

different from any other organisation that is far from the reality of

the struggle. These organisations must accept the quantitative logic if

they do not want to seem anachronistic (or elitist), even though they

know that such a logic inevitably leads to their denying the basic

principles of anarchism, or to the complete undoing of what they have

just built.

If one holds on to the illusion of quantity, the role of the vanguard

must unavoidably be accepted. Authoritarians have nothing against this.

Anarchists, on the other hand, have a great deal against it.

Unfortunately, this being ‘against’ the vanguard often turns into a

sterile debate, the argument often turning to the difference between

authoritarian structures and libertarian ones. This point deserves to be

gone into further.

Authoritarian group and libertarian one

At this point we want to go into the concept of the group. Up until now

we have been speaking about organisation, comparing various

organisations that are objectively different but which all borrow the

logic of defence, therefore of power. These organisations are different

in many aspects but share one fundamental one, their capacity to be used

by power. Organisations for economic defence, political defence,

reformist organisations and revolutionary organisations are all the same

— words are meaningless — if they operate in forms that are outside the

struggle.

However, within that uniformity there is a difference between a

structure by groups and a structure by sections or other synonyms that

usually characterise unions and parties. If we look closely we can find

a semblance of reality, still external to the reality of the struggle

but which claims to make a difference. The structure made up of groups

considers itself to be libertarian and accuses the other of being

authoritarian.

Basically, it is easy to make this accusation as it is welcomed by those

responsible for the authoritarian parties and organisations themselves.

In fact, central committees, hierarchies and other similar devices are

not concealed but are justified by a series of discourses on the need

for the leader, representation, a transitional period and other

fantasies that are not worth mentioning here because they are as old as

the hills.

On the other hand, a structure by groups is seen as the basis of every

libertarian organisation. This is correct, but we need to know what kind

of groups we are talking about. Nothing prevents authoritarian

organisations from being based on groups, or the existence of actual

authoritarian groups. In fact the libertarian structure should not be

considered a typical group structure but rather one that is

characterised from within and distinguishes itself from the other kinds.

The authoritarian group has a leader and a hierarchical microstructure.

The leader makes the most important decisions without consulting the

group members, and makes them one at a time in such a way that the

others never know what the next decision will be. This situation of

uncertainty is what makes it possible for the leader’s authority to

become permanent, and from time to time the latter is called upon to set

out tasks for all the others. Nothing prevents vanguardist organisations

from structuring themselves this way. Moreover, this is often quite a

normal state of affairs in situations of clandestinity.

The libertarian group does not have a leader and does not have an

internal hierarchical structure. The distribution of tasks is decided

upon collectively. The line of behaviour is decided by all of the

components of the group and members can choose to carry out one task

rather than another, always with common agreement. The state of

uncertainty that exists in the face of a new event does not paralyse or

traumatize anyone and does not require the intervention of a

“specialist”, in that each individual is already aware of the situation

and is prepared to face it along with all the others.

If we are assuming that only authoritarian groups can constitute a

vanguard, we must look at the conditions that would prevent a

libertarian group from producing one.

Just because the libertarian group does not have a leader does not mean

that it is not capable of producing a vanguard. In itself this simple

fact is not alarming, it becomes serious when the group is operating in

a situation outside the struggle. Let us see why.

Above all, let us see how leaders do emerge within such groups. We have

said that decisions are worked out as openly as possible. Everybody

participates. But not everybody has the same level of preparation. It

therefore transpires that discussions move in the direction of one or

more particular points that correspond to the ideas of those who are

better prepared. In other words, the components of the group start to

divide, not on the basis of their own ideas, which can often be quite

vague or superficial, but on the basis of some interpretative lines

supplied by the better prepared elements. Then there is a passage from

polarisation to concentration, usually because the theses of the leaders

(by now identifiable) reach some agreement, i.e. divergences are blunted

in order to reach unanimity. In extreme cases, where a concentration of

opinion is not possible, a fracture and consequent separation results.

The problem of the formation of a majority and minority, or the

libertarian equivalent of the same, is not relevant here. What concerns

us is that the polarisation of opinions comes about on the basis of

interpretative lines that are supplied by some elements (a minority

within the group) constituted by the leaders. It should be added that

these elements are usually the ones that frequent the group most

assiduously, participate in all the work, engage themselves totally.

That often coincides with a certain level of freedom from other kinds of

work that are necessary in order to live. Without referring to the

extreme case of revolutionary professionalism, we could say that the

leaders of libertarian groups are usually comrades with a certain amount

of time at their disposal, which they dedicate to the life of the group.

The group unavoidably takes on their physiognomy, their cultural and

social characteristics that involuntarily but consistently select

themselves.

The other great problem is that, alongside the existence of leaders, it

is often possible to identify the existence of “problematics” that are

introduced to the group by the same, then submitted to the process of

democratic scrutiny for discussion, etc. In this way the choice of

methods of struggle, the theoretical foundations and various political

positions are dealt with outside the group then, with a typically

paternalistic process, everything is then discussed with all the

comrades. The group thus becomes an objective, abstract entity for the

individuals that make it up, as its relations only enter the reality of

some of them. A formal difference in the style of command within the

group turns out to be even more conditioned than the authoritarian one.

In other words we are faced with an essentially authoritarian structure

that is far more efficient than the authoritarian group itself. The

latter always has the problem of how to overcome individual uncertainty

in the case of having to act in the leader’s absence. The libertarian

group, on the other hand, reaches an envious homogeneity of decision by

acting as we have just seen, although there is little to be envied at

the subjective level.

The worst question they have to face is how to pilot problems instead of

confronting the group with them directly. Now, such a situation is

impossible if the group is acting directly within the struggle when, as

we shall see further on, a whole series of other problematics arise. So,

given that the group is acting in an external organisation, tied as we

have said to the illusory perspective of quantity, it becomes

indispensable for someone within the group to carry out the fundamental

tasks. On the contrary, in the case where the group is acting within

struggles, the function of the leader is quite simply that of

orientation on the grounds of his wider preparation and availability of

time, not that of choosing the problems to be discussed.

This distinction is of the greatest importance. It marks the watershed

between the fictitious movement and the real movement.

The relationship between groups: the vertical structure and the

horizontal one

A group, in that it is an elemental structure of a wider organisational

reality, would be insignificant if it were to remain isolated from other

groups. It would contain all the defects of an external organisation

without managing to have any effect on a wider range of opinion.

If the group consolidates on the basis of affinity emerging from the

ideas and opinions of some of the leaders, as well as its geographical

situation, which also exerts an influence, that does not mean that it

cannot develop a wider organisational base. It can establish relations

with other groups — those not too far from its own positions — based on

some of the theses put forward by the leaders.

These relations can come about vertically in the case of authoritarian

groups, or horizontally in the case of libertarian ones. It is the

horizontal structure that we are interested in looking at here, as this

is characteristic of anarchist groups.

Various groups federate or keep in contact in one way or another,

supporting each other in the minimum common intention that can be drawn

from a few basic principles and theoretical points worked out in

advance. Even a loose agreement concerning these ideas and principles is

sufficient to guarantee the persistence of the horizontal structure. No

one group predominates over any other, no group claims to carry out the

function of leader, and no group makes a decision concerning the others

without getting in touch with the rest of the federation or informal

union, who then state what they want. They can also use common

instruments such as papers or commissions. These are edited or compiled

by various groups, or by one single group, following a discussion among

delegates, using various procedures (ratification of the group, recall

of delegates, etc.) in order to try to guarantee the structure as far as

possible, keeping it horizontal.

Things are not quite like that in reality. Inevitable processes favour

the formation of a group of leaders that take over the federation or

union of groups, pushing them towards the basic interpretation of the

underlying thesis which, according to them, is the only one that is

valid for all the comrades. This is not reached directly. As we have

seen, each group produces its leaders, usually one or two, maximum

three. Very often their preparation and availability are greater than

that of the others. In this way a true leader emerges. We know how the

retrieval of opinion works, the process of decision-making within

groups. The phenomenon of polarisation is overcome, often in order to

try to give the group uniformity and cohesion but when taken to a wider

level (geographically), these phenomena do not fail to reappear.

It can be instructive to read accounts of debates or reports written by

delegates from individual groups to see what we are talking about. The

polarisation of ideas is quite evident. Usually only the leaders are

present at wider meetings, each one of whom is more “inside” the

problems of their own particular group. More often than not it is they

who have worked out the ideas that the group has ended up attributing to

itself. Hence a great divergence on whatever problem is being faced,

with a strong possibility of never reaching any precise conclusions.

Usually a broad program is established, be it old or new, with

propositions that are general enough for everyone to agree with. Care is

taken to limit the program to general principles, otherwise the internal

contradictions represented by the various interpretations would be

irreconcilable.

Even if the structure remains horizontal, if the revocable delegate

tries to avoid any form of professionalism, if the debate within the

structure is always alive — in fact, the further it finds itself from

the various points of struggle the more virulent it gets — that does not

mean that spontaneous formations acting along the lines of a vanguard do

not appear.

So now we have a series of groups that organise in a structure that is

outside the struggle. By this fact alone they see themselves as the

conscious vanguard of something that is considered to be

unconsciousness, therefore in need of being approached and receiving

clarification. Propaganda and proselytism are important for this

enlightened kind of vanguard. Within the latter, through an inevitable

process of selection, an even more restricted vanguard is formed, a

group of leaders that act starting from certain decisions concerning

basic ideas and the interpretation of individual problems that do not

always come from a wider base but are often elaborated in specific

places, i.e. at meetings of the restricted vanguard.

One thus becomes aware of the extreme apex of an organised whole, that

takes on the task of piloting an instrument for acting on the mass in

one way or another.

As far as the organised structure as a whole is concerned, its reduction

to a vanguard comes about because it is detached from the real struggle

and because it is seen as an instrument by the leaders who want to use

it as such.

At first glance it would seem that such things regard authoritarian

structures rather than libertarian ones, because, as we said they go

against the latter’s aims and intentions. Each and every militant that

enters a libertarian group is making a choice, not just on the basis of

an abstract program but also because he or she wants to live

differently, with a way of working together that is free from that

absurd situation of authoritarian groups where only the leader or

leaders know what is to be done and everyone else waits to take orders.

When it actually comes to it, reality takes charge of changing opinions

one way or another.

Authoritarian groups are finding it more and more difficult to hold on

to the classic centralised structure. Leaders are conceding a certain

freedom of action to their subalterns, even if processes of reification,

i.e. the transformation of the organisational apparatus into a “thing”

are always in act, considerably influencing the behaviour of the

individual militants.

In libertarian groups, as we have seen, the idyllic situation of maximum

freedom of expression is impeded by the lack of preparation and scarce

availability of most of the members. For this reason a certain

decision-making power ends up in the hands of a few leaders.

This situation is the same as the former in appearance alone. In reality

we are looking at two very different forms of degeneration that lead to

different consequences. In the first case, i.e. in the authoritarian

structure, the process of reification is such that individual militants

become so integrated with the organisation that it becomes inconceivable

for them to imagine that the latter could make a mistake. Hence their

failure to question orders from above. The structure must be right,

precisely because of some of its internal, quite irrational,

characteristics. Its reflection as an organised structure cannot be

wrong, in that they live the same life as the organisation. They

personify it in a way, giving it a human semblance. The personality cult

and all its consequences are a logical conclusion of this direction.

In the second case, i.e. in the horizontal, libertarian structure,

methods of discussion, a minimum of decency and various other elements

contribute to preventing a reification of the organisation. Even many

elements of the base who have nothing to say on certain arguments do not

accept the typically authoritarian principle that the organisation is

always right. In this case the leaders’ authority should more correctly

be called authoritativeness, although the use of a different word does

not alter the consequences of the phenomenon.

It should be added that there quite often exists what is know as an

esprit de corps. Militants of a libertarian organisation should be free

from such absurdities. Yet reality shows us how one often becomes a

prisoner of them. The militant at the base of the organised structure

sees the latter in a certain way, that usually coincides with the way

the leader that influences it sees it. By simply accepting this

situation, he cannot see his organisation at the same level as others

do. He sees something better in it, something more fitting to the

principles he vaguely feels are close to his “truth”, which are codified

succinctly for the non-initiated. The leader is even closer to

identifying with the organisation. He feels there is something

definitive in it, feels it is “his” to a much greater degree than the

simple militant does. Whereas for the latter the intermediary of the

leader was necessary, for him the relationship is direct. He feels the

pulsations directly. All this leads to his being extremely indulgent

towards his own organisation and extremely critical of others.

An irrational evaluation of the organisation one belongs to can lead to

strange situations. A great deal of effort is made to expand, perfect

and fortify a structure, without analysing whether it corresponds to the

needs of the struggle that it is supposed to be involved in. All kinds

of excuses are invented to camouflage the priority given to internal

work compared to that beyond the organisation. It is said that it is not

the right moment to do this or that, while it is always the time for the

work of internal growth, in that it is always the moment for waiting and

preparing to defend oneself from the attacks of the exploiters. The

outside is no longer seen as a field of struggle, a specific situation

that can be analysed, or as the necessary condition for preventing

abnormal growth or sterile conformity to past models, but only for

finding new militants. Proselytism is the most important part of the

organisation’s activities. In a few extreme cases the struggle, any

struggle whatsoever, is not carried out on the basis of the positive

consequences that it might determine in the exploited masses, but on the

basis of the propaganda that it might create for the organisation. Hence

a position of stalemate in the relation of the struggle between

exploiter and exploited is reached. If the relation concerns the problem

of abortion, for example, the latter is not faced in terms of how the

problem concerns the mass of exploited, but only in view of an outcome

in quantitative terms, and what the negative consequences of going in

the opposite direction would be for the organisation.

Authoritarian boss and libertarian leader

The first sets himself up as a constant point of reference. He gets his

authority from the position he occupies within the authoritarian

structure, a position that has — usually — been gained through total

dedication to the organisation itself, as well as his considerable

competence and preparation. He comes to be considered the interpreter of

the will of the organisation, therefore, indirectly, given that the

latter is considered holder of the truth, he is considered interpreter

and holder of the truth. The irrational relationship at the root of a

militant’s belonging to an authoritarian structure, consolidates itself

in his relationship with the direct head. The indirect leader, the one

who places himself at the top of the pyramid, then comes to be invested

with those charismatic forms that have a very strong irrational content.

Because there is no way to control the validity of his work, apart from

through the action of the intermediate leaders, the supreme head becomes

more a symbol than anything else, a symbol dispenser of charisma, i.e.

the truth.

Here it is necessary to point out the great difference that there is

between this situation and the counterrevolutionary authoritarian

structure. This is a delicate question. Objectively speaking an

authoritarian structure is always counterrevolutionary, because it

always tries to put obstacles in the way of ultimate liberation. But it

should be distinguished from the structures deliberately created by the

bosses to reach their aims. In this sense, let’s say, a fascist

organisational structure gives rise to certain hierarchical relations

that are flights from freedom, each single component grasps the charisma

of the head because he is scared of the freedom that he could find

elsewhere, because he has that special petit bourgeois vision of life

that makes him take refuge and comfort in the fixed structures of

authoritarianism. For the fascist, the acceptation of the authoritarian

structure is not a concession, it is a point of stability: his interior

conflict, typically existential, is resolved in the total and definitive

delegation, in the flight. The other possibility, that he vaguely sees,

the possibility of living free, scares him because the schema of

tradition, family, honour, homeland, and other such rubbish, suffocate

him, making him see freedom as chaos without rules, in which old the old

ghosts, that he has always run away from, equality in the first place,

would end up multiplying.

The authoritarian comrade is a comrade who intends to consciously make

the choice of freedom. He is not afraid, in fact all of his action is

aimed at breaking with the past, with tradition. Acceptance of the

authoritarian structure is the lesser of two evils for the militant who

naively convinces himself that nothing lasting can be obtained without

sacrifice. For this reason he is ready for the extreme sacrifice, the

sacrifice of his own freedom. Herein lies the tragedy. A person

struggling for freedom ends up sacrificing the latter in the illusion

that he is continuing to struggle for it. Even the acceptance of

charisma is always a mediated fact that involves a process of

“snobbery”, self-importance, little moral blackmails with oneself. He

usually starts off seeing the leader as a “comrade”, accepting him as

one who is more prepared and more aware. He would never admit to a

direct charismatic process. Then, as he is gradually absorbed into the

authoritarian structure he realises that any possibility of control from

the base is minimal. Next there is his accusation of superficial

snobbery. He finally ends up taking orders and sacrificing himself to

the structure itself which, as an indissoluble whole, he identifies with

freedom and truth.

Now let us look at the situation of the libertarian leader. He should

not become a point of reference. If he is, that has happened against his

will, as a direct consequence of his having more free time and due to

his greater involvement and preparation. As far as he is concerned, one

could speak of authoritativeness rather than authority. He cannot be

accused of interpreting the will of the organisation as the latter is

composed of the wills of all the members. Finally, as the organisation

itself is not considered the depository of truth, the leader towards

whom some militants turn in no way interprets or spreads the truth.

In actual fact, considerable modifications do occur within this schema.

The leader does end up becoming a point of reference, otherwise the

diversity of opinions within the structure would be enormous and make it

almost impossible to reach any decision. This organisation also ends up

being seen by militants in a deformed, irrational way as “their

organisation” due to the simple fact that they chose it as the

organisation which, although not carrier of the truth, is almost

certainly the one that gets closer to that than any other. Consequently,

even if the leader is not the interpreter or holder of truth he can in a

sense be considered something similar, a comrade to have faith in, so

much so as to accept his conclusions even if one does not fully grasp

them. All this comes about in the hope that we too will manage to see

clearly in the future in order to put the comrade, who for the time

being serves as a point of reference, into a proper critical dimension.

This awaiting better moments when we will all have time, when our

preparation is more accurate and detailed, also conceals renunciation

and accommodation. It conceals the acceptance of a situation that it is

very difficult to alter, which we are not really interested in going

into as such.

Then there is the question of the relationship between leaders. Another

delicate problem. If the clash between authoritarian leaders is taken

for granted as a result of the ranks that are built within the vertical

structure, one should not be able to say the same thing about

libertarian leaders. They also have clashes of opinion, find themselves

opposing those who diverge from their own point of view, have to

overcome organisational obstacles caused by the different tendencies,

but the means that they have recourse to should be different.

On the contrary, one often sees that the means employed are not so

different at all. The libertarian leader cannot let predominance over

the tendency he represents escape him, without risking the very negation

of the tendency and a distortion of the relationship with the part of

the base that he represents. There might be a hint of a relationship of

exchange, or reciprocal influence, between base and leader within the

wider organised structure. That does not alter the fact that the precise

interest of the leader, even a libertarian one, emerges to seal this

relationship, protecting it from the influence of other tendencies that

might threaten the clarity of his own position.

Hence the clash with other leaders. An idea of the intensity of the

clash is given by the rush for commissions and tasks to be carried out

within the organisation. Nothing changes because these commissions are

unpaid and produce a considerable burden of work and fatigue: they are

recompensed by influence and solidity. One could say that the more

widely a leader’s activity is developed within the organisation, the

clearer and less attackable his point of reference becomes.

One should not generalise however. In the libertarian organisational

structure, the formation of militants makes it possible for there to be

a constant exchange of ideas in circulation that ends up emarginating

tendencies that become crystallized. Then the comrade or comrades who

identify with that crystallized tendency, even when they keep in touch

with certain instruments such as papers, reviews, commissions and other

things, still end up creating a vacuum around themselves.

The libertarian organisation, even the one farthest from the struggle,

cannot fail to face the problem of aims and methods. And the discussion

of methods ends up creating relationships within the organisation that

render possible a debate which, although sterile at times, often leads

to unexpected results in other organisations.

It should be added that comrades in the libertarian organisation are

there by their own free choice. Generally speaking, belonging to a

libertarian organisation, even those with quite unclear perspectives,

involves risk, sacrifice, awareness of these risks and sacrifices and a

fairly clear evaluation of the reasons that determined such a choice. At

any level whatsoever, anarchist militants are indisputably militants who

can make decisions and question any doubts about positions or tendencies

that are not quite tenable (at least in their opinion). This fact, which

often gives rise to arguments, endless discussions, splits and conflict

between tendencies and has been considered the weak point of anarchism,

is actually one of its points of strength and vitality. Obtuse

uniformity would kill any lively tendency in favour of the grey will of

the winning side.

An attempt to examine the character structure of the libertarian

militant

Anarchist methodology vaguely gives us a model of a certain kind of

militant. More often than not this indication is not gained from the

reality of intervention in struggle, but from an idealisation of the

latter.

Moreover, it is possible to see the evolution of this model throughout

the history of the libertarian movement and the profound transformations

that have taken place from 1968 onwards.

The definition has precise characteristics: a coherent choice of means

for reaching the aims of justice, equality and freedom; intervention in

the quick of social struggles; refusal to prioritize the economic factor

in the evolving of the exploited/exploiter conflict; the elevation of a

liberatory culture to oppose the bourgeois culture of repression;

optimism; faith in man and his innate gifts; an a priori refusal of

doctrines; use of the empirical method “try and try again”; specific

solicitations on the social conflict in act with means of every kind

(insurrectional-violent or pacifist-educational).

This framework is not complete but it gives the rough contours of a

perspective that cannot be brought about in practice. Offspring of

social contradictions and the social struggle, anarchist militants are

not only products of their time, they would be insignificant automata if

they were to base their action on abstract principles without relating

them to the requirements of their intervention in reality.

It should not be forgotten that one of the most important points of

anarchism is precisely its ethical preoccupation, and this would

disappear if one were to try to obliterate the contradictory vitality of

the individual in favour of an idealism detached from history and its

events. If the strong point of anarchism is its methodology, great

freedom of action is possible within that framework. In fact, if one

were to dictate the main rules of anarchism in Ten Commandments,

throwing out anyone that failed to manifest the intention to follow them

scrupulously down to the last detail, and there was an accentuation of

internal norms and elaborate codes intended to confuse ideas or create

conflict, one would end up with a minority of revolutionaries with very

limited choices. This character model is marked by a net subordination

of one’s own happiness, interests and need for a private life to the

aims of the organisation and the revolution. By making the model of

reference rigid, people become rigid, personality falls into second

place. The abstract ideals of justice, equality and freedom come to be

considered important enough to justify self-oblivion, the nullification

of any stimulus towards the different (which ends up being considered

bourgeois, so is condemned).

Once they have conformed to the basic rigid model these comrades would

no doubt be disposed to make any sacrifice imaginable for the ideal,

even their own lives, but they would be throwing the cold veil of

separation between themselves, the ideal (now “their ideal”) and other

comrades, i.e., they would come to deny the unitarian and collective

process that the elaboration of the revolutionary model implies. Their

aim would be to apply in the sphere of reality the model that they had

crystallized in the sphere of analysis, without taking account of any

possible individual or group differences. Phenomena such as the birth of

a so-called “objective consciousness” would surface, leading to

suspicion, intolerance, exclusivity.

We are looking at this extreme situation here simply to point out the

dangers of a crystallisation of a model of anarchist intervention. In

reality, such a model must, in our opinion, result from constant

elaboration, verification and modification by all comrades, always

within the basic methodological perspective, which is that of the

correct choice of means for reaching the aims of justice, equality and

freedom.

Specific historical transformation has produced different kinds of

militants. There can be no doubt that the character of the French

comrades engaged in the struggle against the reaction up until 1890

differed greatly from those of the anarcho-syndicalist comrades who

later tried to address the struggle towards claiming better conditions,

convinced that that was still within a revolutionary perspective. Just

as there can be no doubt that profound differences existed between the

Spanish comrades of the FAI and the Italian comrades of similar

organisations. The same goes for the German comrades that went to work

in America and those who stayed at home, for the English comrades in

London and the Scottish ones, etc. The ‘model’ proposed by Ravachol is

not the same as that proposed by Henry, nor is it the same as that which

Bonnot was to propose. While basically remaining within the realm of

illegality, profoundly different characteristics emerge, leading to

differences in analyses and tendencies.

It is also possible to see differences at the level of language. The

language of anarchist writings from 1880 to 1895 in France is different

from that between 1895 and 1914. Galleani’s style differs from

Malatesta’s but is very similar to that of Cipriani and Ciancabilla.

The variety and flourishing of models since 1968 is even greater.

The development of cultural analysis, the widening of revolutionary

reading, the French phenomenon of May, a faster circulation of ideas,

the breakdown in traditional university structures, the crisis of the

most sacred values of the bourgeois world (science, projectuality,

salubrity, integrity), have all produced rapid changes. Anyone that

fails to adapt to the new era ends up being out of date and inefficient.

The persistence of old schema, even by very valid comrades, is the sign

of a difficulty in making the model pliable, but one goes ahead in any

case and new lines of intervention are developed. Amidst contrasts and

colossal blunders, amidst intuition and attempts at internal repression,

a profound cultural modification of the world anarchist movement comes

about. Hence the emergence of a new kind of militant that is still in

formation, one that flees rhetoric like the plague and only focuses on a

few points, but does so clearly.

The new anarchist militant places himself or herself in the libertarian

tradition but at the same time they try with all their might to sift

through the cultural contribution of the revolutionary left, as well as

cultural models of the bourgeoisie. This has opened up many

contradictions from which deep theoretical splits have arisen, but these

are very positive, breaking the circle of a cultural closure that had

ended up with outdated analytical models. Basically, if one were to draw

up a short inventory of the theoretical baggage of the anarchism of the

’fifties, especially in Italy, one would have to admit that some of the

old models (revolutionary syndicalism, Malatestian critique, Gorian

humanism, late-Bakuninist collectivism, Kropotkinian determinism) have

become acritical rhetoric. Also models that are more directly influenced

by action such as the ethical and strategic evaluation of armed

struggle, have been influenced by this cultural atrophy. The actions of

Sabate and Facerias were isolated acritically, often praised, often

condemned, without the message they contain being able to emerge in the

form of a concrete proposal to comrades beyond a mythisisation of armed

action for the sake of it.

If we were to look at some of the examples that were fossilized by this

cultural atrophying, we would have to point to the Sorel of the myth of

the general strike (behind revolutionary syndicalism), the Malatesta of

the final years (influenced by Gori’s humanism), the Kropotkin of Ethics

and Modern Science and Anarchy (as well as a little of Mutual Aid). That

would imply a direct intervention in the reality that is trying to

revive syndical models, now decidedly oriented in a reformist and

authoritarian direction, a logic of waiting and naturalist and

determinist ethical discourses.

Revolutionary culture’s sudden break (also the authoritarian strain)

with certain schema of the past (for example the sudden refusal of

Crocian historicism and the immediate — acritical — acceptance of

Marxism), produced considerable reflexes, also within the anarchist

movement that was debating themes and facing problems that had

previously been hidden under the ashes of badly digested rhetoric.

It is the ethical question that interests us here. Not that of text

books but of the relationship with life, the question facing all

militants that find themselves traumatically living the experience of

being an anarchist in a society of exploiters and parvenus, exploited

and acquiescent. And when anarchists refuse the bourgeois model at the

same time as they refuse the authoritarian-collectivist model of the

Marxists and Stalinists, they end up facing the problem of a socialised

personality in a personalised society, a development of total

self-management of the person in a society that does not crush man but

exalts him and offers the possibility of living a coherent life.

So the project of a militant that does not hide difficulties from

himself, does not have recourse to a huge apparatus of phrases and

commonplaces, in fact is almost afraid to use slogans and uniform

speech, forcing himself to work for the satisfaction of the global needs

of society as well as that of individuals and groups. It is the problem

of participation, of opening out and relating to others, refusing the

party apparatus, refusing the bourgeois ideology of civic consciousness.

The debate has moved away from the clash between individual and

organisation, the rights of the individual and those of the specific

organisation (of the revolutionary syndicalist or simply revolutionary

kind). It now concerns the autonomy of the militant’s personality in a

dimension of collective responsibility, within the process of the growth

of social revolutionary consciousness that cannot be left to itself.

As the dominant ideology conformed to economic progress (between the

’fifties and ’sixties) an anticonformism that attempted to rethink some

of the traditional models of political struggle appeared. Then, with the

modifications in the very structure of power, the economic reflux and

the entrance of the reformist forces of the Left into the dominant

class, anticonformism becomes more responsible: quality of life opposes

itself to the quantitative reduction in the class conflict. The stimulus

of the individual, the ethical stimulus, is added to the material one

with its partial analysis of a counterpower that had come to be

conditioned by a certain culture of power (political science and its

negation): politics starts living a new process of opening out.

This profound renewal is also part of a global crisis in the values of

late capitalist society. It cannot be said with precision whether the

fall of consumerist structures are a cause or effect of this crisis that

has lead a great number of people to suspend their judgement and open up

a kind of “parenthesis”, a life that refuses what is offered by capital.

In this world, which at the same time is out of this world, this

“parenthesis” is no longer restricted to an elite but is a mass

phenomenon that is too great to be ignored.

Today the anarchist is also conditioned by all this. It is all very well

to say that anarchists are not “perfect”, they are not “strange” beings

from another planet, possessors of truth capable of finding the right

answers and methods for intervening in any situation. Just as they are

not the monsters of violence and terror that a certain press in the

service of the bosses portrays them as. Nevertheless, they are not

“revealers” of truth. And it is precisely for this reason that we can

attempt, for the first time as far as we know, to outline the character

of the anarchist militant of the past few years, at least within the

limits of experiences in European countries where the movement has some

significance today: Italy, France, Spain (Spanish emigration), Germany,

England. If we were to consider anarchism a well-defined, crystallized

doctrine, we would have to conclude that anarchists are born such and

that anyone that “feels” for anarchy is either enrolled in some

anarchist federation and shouts “Long live Bakunin”, or reads no books

at all and swears on the negativity of culture.

On the contrary, if we see anarchism as the theoretical and practical

experience that emerges with a precise methodology in social struggles

at certain times, we see anarchist militants as men and women of their

time who are influenced by prevailing ideas — and the specific methods

of anarchism — , and are involved in struggles against the class in

power. The more the era is rich in contradictions, the more the crisis

in the power structure becomes evident and the more the instruments that

once belonged exclusively to the revolutionary forces come to be used by

power for the repression. The more confusing reality becomes, the more

anarchist methods become a relevant perspective. This is not absolute or

taken for granted, we need to verify things so that the struggle against

power can be organised correctly rather than resurge from the

revolutionary cinders of the past.

So, anarchists are also people that live the contradictions of their

time. Their character cannot escape the consequences. Their personality

will end up hosting a crucial conflict between the ascetic aspect of the

revolutionary: abnegation, agreement, and the ethical aspect of the

individual that opens up to autonomy and the organisation of society in

the egalitarian sense, seeing the limits and the need for progressive

approximation. It is much easier to intervene in reality and change it,

however limited the action might be, than to intervene in reality,

change it and in so doing, change oneself.

If more space is given to the first aspect of the conflict, we will have

one kind of intervention in reality, that leading to the formation of a

vanguard. In the second hypothesis we would see a growth in the

anarchist movement directly, in the reality of the struggle, with the

possible constitution of specific organisations that are expressions of

this reality in struggles where it would be difficult for them to become

vanguards.

This seems to us to be the most important problem that needs to be

faced. It is a complex problem, as the passage from the dimension of the

individual to the collective one is not just marked by the

organisational forms but also by the aims that the organisation gives

itself, those of the people that make it up, etc. If the tendency we

have defined “ascetic” can lead to the formation of a vanguard due to a

rationalisation of the conflict, the tendency which, with equal caution,

we have defined “ethical” can make the same mistake due to an

abstraction of the conflict as a result of the quantitative illusion.

The conflict between total and partial

We should say right away that in making a distinction between the

“ascetic” tendency and the “ethical” one we are not implying that the

moral aspect is absent from the former. This is a fundamental aspect of

anarchist methodology (as we have said): the choice of means we use

irremediably affects the ends we reach.

This said, it should be added that the problem of violence cannot be

solved by discriminating between the two tendencies. A comparison such

as “ascetic” = violence, “ethic” = nonviolence does not make sense.

Always on the basis of the anarchist principle that refuses that “the

end justifies the means”, violence can legitimately be used for

liberation without being seen as ambiguous moral relativism.

It goes without saying that in the clash with power, in the revolution,

one is often forced to make choices between the greater or lesser evil.

Debit and credit exists, even in ethics. But the contingent factors that

explain some mistakes must never be raised to a moral justification of

anarchist action.

Reality, with all its nuances, complications and contradictions, is

reflected in the contradictory personality of man, and consequently also

in the anarchist. So we can see that anarchist methodology is nourished

and modified by analyses that use various instruments, from the

intuition of individuals who decide to carry out a single action, to an

organisation that acts upon the reality around it.

But the anarchist, employing his or her methodology with exactitude and

recognising the contradictory aspects, causes modifications in reality

that are both cause and the effect of the resulting contradictions.

All the same, it is not easy to see where reality ends and appearances

begin in the conflict. It is not easy to separate men from their

ideologies, and this can lead to an attempt to isolate certain levels of

intervention by separating them from the ideological processes that

cover them. We often hear serenades to “doing” which, in the best

hypothesis, are naive romanticism. “Doing” cannot be autonomous, i.e. it

cannot justify itself alone.

To turn means into an end in themselves would correspond to the ascetic

excess of the revolutionary, and if this is also quite a rational

phenomenon (in the framework of the destructive process), as it cuts the

conflict between total and partial in too net a fashion. It denies the

latter, affirming the former, but camouflages both poles of the clash

thus making the distinction problematical. This is the extreme case of

an armed minority that have been radicalised by certain processes in the

clash that are imputable to their strategy (on the one hand), but also

and perhaps primarily to the decisions of power. Real motivations,

specific tendencies between individuals and social groups are

disregarded in favour of an acritical exaltation of the clash, the value

of the armed “deed”, attack and univocity of will. The militant is

deformed by objective consequences and as this is happening he thinks

that he is in charge of the situation. He becomes a professional,

enclosing the outside world into the asphyxiating framework of the

frontal clash, and from this perspective claims to judge the rest of

reality. Once again ideological alienation (always present), reflects

fundamental alienation. Then, in concrete, the requirements of the clash

itself necessitates these operative reductions. It reenters the logic of

the division of labour, one that it cannot escape as it is not possible

to flee such a dimension in the absence of a decisively revolutionary

and globalising act of rupture. That does not alter the fact that

radicalisation exists and is logically founded, we were about to say

“necessary”, just as it does not alter the fact that this should be

supported when there are cops and all their variety of accomplices on

the other side of the barricade. But that cannot deny us the right to

reflect and criticise. And the restrictive dimension, the dimension

which in restriction wants totality, that is, that can (theoretically)

aspire to totality precisely because it has reduced the world and all

its deeds to a pocket dimension, should be criticised. The vanguard that

comes out of this is as ambitious as ever. The greater the risks run to

procure means, the easier it is for them to become an end in themselves.

In this way the vanguard moves in the direction of becoming independent

of its own aims, even to the point of replacing them.

One obstacle to revolution is the fact that in coming up against reality

the vanguard, rather than consider itself a means, ends up preferring

its own aims. These in no way conform to the general aims of the

revolution, i.e. the definitive liberation of man.

We must distinguish between the model of the vanguard that we are

looking at here and the classical one suggested by Marxism. For

Marxists, the vanguard acts as mediator between the immediate and the

historical interests of the working class. The paradox is that this

vanguard must interpret the interests of the class whose conditions of

development it must create. For the ascetic kind of revolutionary

vanguard the problem of “mediation” does not exist, only that of

“action”. Only once the clash has evolved due to the reaction of power

is it possible to speak of a real coagulation of vanguardist forms, with

all the ensuing consequences (transformation into a military wing,

professional deformation, etc.).

Yet, in our opinion, this is not the most delicate point of the conflict

between totality and part. Far more radical is the underlying problem,

the conflict within the militant as an individual.

The clash between totality and part is consistently present for the

militant engaged in the struggle and, in the long run, this marks his

character profoundly. It deforms his vision of life to the point of, at

times — in the face of great delusions — making him refuse to accept

reality. We see the extent of the problem in the anguished cry of

Cafiero or in the painful writings of Coeurderoy.

The revolution is a globalising concept of human involvement. It is

totality. It does not allow joint ownership, cohabitation or compromise.

The anarchist struggle is the supreme recognition of the principle of

realisable totality whilst safeguarding the value of the individual, an

addition of great complexity in that it refuses to see revolutionary

means as ends in themselves. In this case totality becomes crystal

clear, dazzling. Everything goes towards it, one’s self, one’s family,

one’s affections, one’s habits, one’s hopes.

But all that (which no matter how grand it might sound to the individual

is still very small) soon burns out in the immense furnace of

revolutionary totality. And so one wants to act quickly to speed up a

process that takes its own time and goes at its own pace. We begin to

feel it weighing on us as though we had to carry it upon our shoulders.

Then we are forced to stand before the inexorable tribunal of the part.

To measure growth, estimate distances, consider relations, indicate

perspectives. We start to pay more attention to the pace of events. We

start to save ourselves, preparing for the long road ahead. We would

like it to go on for ever, our revolution, but we realise that we cannot

imprison totality within the limits of our desires, and we end up giving

in to care and strategy. We note that we are not alone, that facing us

and our project of liberation are the masses (who are not necessarily

ready to free themselves) and power. In full evidence and revolutionary

mystery, there before us stands a contradictory but constant

relationship between totality and part, dream and reality, ideal and

strategic project.

Some, enclosing totality inside a more restricted dimension, asceticise

their intervention. They wrap themselves up in a microcosm that they

recognise as such, which they intend to take to infinity, perfecting it,

claiming that it is capable of reproducing all the conditions of

revolutionary totality on a reduced scale. Through this reduction they

are trying to propose a “model”, give an example, a point of reference

so that many other “little” totalities will be formed, all together

capable of forming such a vast totality as to get close to the final

one. In one way or another this decision leads to the vanguard closing

in on itself. Through the activity of criminalisation, power will do the

rest.

Others, fully accepting the concept of partiality, dispose themselves

favourably to long periods of time, i.e. quantitative measurement. For

these comrades, basic doing turns into basic thinking. The relationship

with the mass becomes educational and moves into the particular, the

specific. The link with the totality that was made on the basis of a

more or less globalising analysis becomes purely theoretical. In this

way the quantitative degeneration of the ethical tendency is born, just

as in the preceding case there was a qualitative degeneration of the

ascetic tendency. Although different (the first open, the second

closed), these positions are both open to criticism.

Revolutionary alienation

“Revolutionary alienation” is the awareness of the contrast between

totality and part. It is disgust for the latter united with the

possibility of the former, leading to a form of extraneation that is

experienced as extreme discomfort in the face of the transformation of

the system.

In a way we are faced with a phenomenon similar to so-called “unhappy

consciousness” resulting from an inadequate reaction to one’s class

situation. Only, while unhappy consciousness is above all a sense of

discomfort before a class dislocation that one ends up feeling estranged

to, revolutionary alienation is the final breaking point in the process.

It is the awareness of not being able to realise totality, of losing

something in an effort towards totality, which we feel is the only

possible road to revolution.

We turn to a profound critique of the “human” significance of the

revolutionary being because one feels oneself to be a “thing”. This

process of reification comes about in the clash between the persistence

of partiality and the continual return of the need for totality.

This is not the “crisis” of the bourgeois who crumbles because of the

saturation of a life-style that has deliberately been built for him with

fabricated needs and stimuli studied in the laboratories of power. It is

not the crisis of consumerist well-being, boredom and remote-controlled

action, a constant repetition of programmed change.

It is not the suspension of involvement or judgement, a taking refuge in

an aristocratic dimension of reflection, or the power of the intellect

regulating the universe of one’s thoughts and illuding oneself that one

is regulating the world. It is not a cutting off from the things of

reality in order to go in search of the perfect utopian society, through

numbers, verses or the preferred Icaria.

It is not a “piloted” upheaval in a reality that is held suspended with

the help of some vehicle or other (drugs or whatever), that can

correspond to, or actually be, the effect of the mass product, following

fashion or a scale of values that the system itself can no longer

uphold.

It is not alienation in the Marxist sense of the term, the loss of

something that belongs to us, in the first place the social product,

because it is through the product of our work alone that we recognise

ourselves as human beings. It is not, that is, the alienation of the

worker that reacts in a certain way before the forced perspective that

the system of production is offering him.

The alienation we are talking about here is a lack of something, (a

process of generic alienation) but is also a lack of oneself, the self

that identifies with revolutionary totality. It is precisely this

perspective (totality) that provides an outlet from the general form of

alienation without, moreover, managing to completely avoid the danger of

alienation reemerging through the frustration of the need for

revolutionary totality.

When the alienated worker recognises his alienation, he becomes

conscious of it and overcomes it. In this way he enters the

revolutionary perspective. This can fall upon him like a ton of bricks

if he is not able to fulfil what the absence of primitive alienation

forces upon him: complete liberation and the realisation of

revolutionary totality. In this way, the very perspective of liberation

risks turning into a further form of alienation, that of lack of

totality.

This situation is far more serious for anarchist revolutionaries. Having

neither the charisma of the leader or the organisation, they have

nothing to hold on to. Assessment of their own work is of little help;

with one simple reflection they can put it into second place in the

perspective of revolutionary totality. If they try to see something

wrong with their situation, thus convincing themselves that a small

enclosed portion of reality is the microcosm that produces totality,

they transform themselves into a vanguardist mechanism and reify

alienation to the point of not being able see it any more, just as

happened in the phase of primitive alienation before the awakening of

consciousness. They thus reify their own alienation, accepting the

solution of partiality (analyses and long periods of intervention).

The fact is that revolutionary alienation is not simply a relationship

that is lacking in something (totality), it is also consciousness of

this lack. In other words, it is not just the recognition that something

is missing, it is also a recognition of not being able to do without

what the latter.

Do all anarchists engaged in the revolutionary struggle reach this

conclusion? There is no simple answer to that.

One thing that is certain is that if anarchism is the refusal of

authority, it is also a critical reflection on the basic conditions of

life and all the ensuing contradictions. In a sense, one of the

characteristics of anarchists is that they go into these contradictions

as it would be strange for authoritarian revolutionaries to gain

consciousness of this alienation through the tight mesh of the party

structure that they find themselves operating in. But if this alienation

is a consequence of a critical examination of reality, it should not be

considered something negative but rather a necessary step, a difficult

stage that needs to be overcome. To sum up, it is not the antechamber of

revolutionary engagement, but is the result of it, the consequence of

it. It is not even the ultimate solution, the final wall from which to

recede and commit suicide, but the passage to a further phase of the

deepening of one’s knowledge and gaining maturity.

Before going any further it is necessary to look at the conditions of

this particular kind of alienation.

The process starts from the absolute value given to the individual. Any

proposal to sacrifice the latter to revolutionary strategy, or even to

revolutionary totality, is rejected. The engagement can be total, can go

as far as complete dedication and death, but can never reach the

annulling of the individual. Anarchists who die for the revolution do

not reject the value of the individual, on the contrary they take the

latter to the maximum degree, as the sacrifice that leads to a society

where sacrifice will be impossible, a freed society. In all their

opening towards the struggle, in all the collective action that they

feel and make their own, they never lose the individual dimension.

Alienation comes to them when they realise that only by accepting a

worse form of alienation (the primitive kind or that of centralised

power) will they be able to escape the danger of seeing the project of

the liberation of the individual disappear. In actual fact, the

individual at least manages to partially realise himself under the

conditions of primitive alienation, albeit in a deformed (alienated)

way. But anarchists want the complete realisation of the individual and

want this in the social perspective of total liberation. They find

themselves in a serious crisis that comes from the contrast between

individual and totality. Entering a partial dimension would heal many

aspects of this crisis but would reproduce another alienated form, the

vanguard.

Alienation only becomes a crucial factor when one is aware that one is

alienated. And this is an effect of the individual’s will, of moving in

a situation of stalemate with no way forward leading to a consideration

of the other possibility, the conscious refusal of totality as the

immediate aim. The greater this awareness, the more the individual will

open up to other possibilities.

But simple awareness, recognising that one is in a state of “crisis”

could push the individual to sacrifice everything in order to come

through the latter in the shortest possible time. Intolerance of a

situation of uncertainty can push someone that is accustomed to

radicalising their action to extreme solutions. If totality leads to

“crisis”, if it is this aim that spoils the revolutionary project by

upsetting the destructive order that one imagined was deterministically

progressive, we must cut off this pole of contrast. In order to do so it

becomes necessary to undervalue it, accuse it of being utopian, a

fantasy, unfounded, deforming, petit bourgeois. The ultimate accusation

is precisely this last one. Anything that annoys us becomes a product of

bourgeois ideology and its shop-keeping accountancy. A product of

commodities and their reification.

However, by acting in this way one realises that one is losing a lot.

For a time one is convinced that one has solved the problem, then it

reappears. The perspective of revolutionary totality is what contained

the quality of the revolution, its liberatory essence. Quality is the

only thing that can give us the feeling of the totality of liberation at

any moment when we are acting progressively. Only quality can make us

live the final moment that we will never see, but which we must

nevertheless feel present, like a reflex that allows us to know where we

are. And this quality is often fantastic, utopian. It is very difficult

for it to relate with quantification. By struggling for revolutionary

totality we grasp the quality of the revolution and relive it in our

actions, in the small things that begin to acquire a progressive sense

of liberation. But all that also brings us alienation, discomfort,

suffering.

When we suffer, we remember the things of the past with a sense of loss.

This could be seen as nostalgia for primitive alienation. The world of

reification can be a nice little port in the storm and, with this going

backwards the suffering goes full circle. In horror we realise that

alienation consists of not wanting to be something one could be but is

in itself meaningless, and not being able to be something one would like

to be, that means everything.

Make no mistake, we are not looking for a detailed revision of

individualism, personalism or voluntaristic rationalism here. Certainly

what we know of the vicissitudes of the person (the transformation of

the mask) is not worth mentioning and is the fruit of bourgeois

irrationalism (existentialism, phenomenology, etc.). Much more would be

necessary, and it is not possible to go into that here. It is important

to understand that we are concerned with the relationship

individual/collectivity. Painful contradictions emerge in anarchist

militants not because they are individuals, but because they are

individuals who recognise their own value and that of the mass as two

values that are in opposition to each other but which cannot be

substituted the one for the other.

If revolutionary tension comes from the fact that the revolution is a

totalizing project, a project that revokes the quality of life and

claims to transform the latter completely, particular contradictions

arise from the need for the individual anarchist to establish a correct

relationship with the mass in order to avoid carrying out one single

aspect of their decision alone.

The revolutionary encompasses the totality of the life of the

individual. Hence the possibility of the realisation of the totality of

the revolution (therefore also the totality of life) that is reflected

in quality. But revolutionary decision is not something abstract. It is

not a “possibility” or a “necessity” according to the perspective of

whoever brings it about. It is real, it leads to profound changes in the

individual and in this sense is “necessary”. But in order to be such it

must go beyond “possibility”, i.e. must be realised. If the latter is

not realised, even through constant engagement, it will never become a

necessity. Herein lies the drama: it is the struggle that leads to going

from approximation to this necessary aspect of revolutionary decision,

leading to all the alienating consequences.

But possibility and necessity do not go hand in hand. Possibility draws

in personal involvement and can even reach necessity, but only as a move

towards something, as the singling out of an objective. Necessity as

such, as the conscious place of the profound modification of the quality

of life, comes from the mass, from what the mass produce. In a word,

necessity comes from the masses’ self-organisation.

One can wrap oneself up in the plots of revolutionary possibility to

infinity. One can dream of insurrectional clashes or fantasize about

long-term educational projects to the point of exhaustion, even to the

point of insufferance and annoyance. Not for this does one reach the

dimension where possibility becomes necessity, i.e. the recognition of

the need for this resolution, the acceptance of the only valid road,

that of going towards the self-organisation of the mass.

When we catch a glimpse of this perspective, the myriad of

possibilities, the very possibility of a probable solution of an

approaching totality, become unbearable for us. Time is required to

realise this possibility, and that is what we lack. We want to run. We

want the totality we caught a glimpse of to materialise. We want the

waiting to become reality. This situation has no outlet in the current

aspect of suffering. It is an intimate laceration, a contradiction that

— when you think about it — is the reflex of the class factor, with even

greater awareness, more suffering. And, because the process of awareness

is one-way, the suffering of class laceration cannot be eliminated.

Let us examine the other form of alienation for a moment, the

better-known one. This is an objective fact, i.e. the result of being

deprived of something (the social product of one’s work). With the

awakening of consciousness (increased awareness) one also gains an

awareness of alienation. The mechanism for correcting the situation of

suffering, so-called class consciousness, would not make sense or would

be a mere objective fact, if it did not include the possibilities that

this creates. Religious residuals act at this level, pushing this class

consciousness towards the search for mediated solutions such as looking

for a guide. That obviously cannot be seen as a correction of the

situation of suffering, but merely its “repression”.

Other difficulties arise at different level of awareness. The refusal of

the guide in some way corresponds to the refusal of the father. The

self-organisation of the struggle necessitates the a priori refusal to

discharge the responsibility of struggles on to someone or something. It

is always the level of awareness that is growing.

The development of this awareness in the individual leads to what we

have called revolutionary alienation under the conditions examined

above. The developing of the self-organisation of struggles determines a

transient feeling of discomfort, suffering, despondency in the mass that

can be compared to that of revolutionary alienation at a different

level.

But, whereas from the point of view of the individual there is only one

sequence of possibilities and an unnerving need for revolutionary

totality, from the point of view of the self-organising mass there is a

progressive identification with a need that is becoming clear. In this

case suffering and discomfort is the discovery of something that exists,

no matter how small, not something that will become, because anything

that is projected into the future (starting from the necessity of the

present) is merely quantitative growth.

So the suffering of the individual comes from lack of quality

(revolutionary totality), a lack that offers an infinite series of

possibilities that project themselves on to the need for the

self-organisation of the mass. On the other hand, the mass are

experiencing a stirring-up, discomfort, real suffering, because they are

beginning to discover the fact of self-organisation.

This dual situation of discomfort characterises the “human” field of the

revolutionary clash and supplies us with the key for solving the problem

of the vanguard. Before facing this final question it is necessary to

clarify the structural relationship that exists between individual,

minority and mass and examine the tension that emerges from it.

Revolutionary tension

Individual activity cannot be seen as something autonomous starting from

which reality becomes thinkable through its organisation of the

struggle. There is no such thing as a homogeneity of intent. In

observing the attitudes and activities of the single individual one

cannot reconstruct reality simply with an adjunctive action. The

contradictoriness of the latter is far more complex than that of the

individual and, moreover, is sustained by different structures. While

the individual, through awareness of oneself, can reach revolutionary

possibility and the need for revolutionary totality (hence alienation

and its overcoming in revolutionary tension); the second, through

self-organisation, reaches revolutionary necessity directly, so the

growth of a first nucleus, no matter how small, is already the

revolutionary totality at disposition.

We are faced with tendencies going in two different directions that

might never meet, at least in the sense of eliminating differences and

creating liberated reality beyond the reality of the struggles. In fact

the other encounter, that of the guide and the party with the minority

in the lead as memory and revolutionary reservoir of the mass, is not a

real encounter but the denial of the very concept of encounter from the

revolutionary point of view.

In fact, revolutionary totality, the new society, is not

deterministically certain. Perhaps obscurantists will always manage to

prevail and force the revolutionary project back, destroying progress

and reestablishing barbarity. This note of precarity and instability is

also to be found in revolutionary tension, rendering necessary a

continual effort of assessment, verification, precision.

The presence and development of self-organised forms of struggle are not

sufficient to guarantee the final resolution of theory in praxis, their

unification in the liberated society. It is only a question of a

tendency, including in this concept the profound sense of suffering

derived from the gestation of new forms of struggle. All this produces a

state of tension, of restlessness, in the movement of the exploited. New

forces arise, new needs emerge, ideals and idols of the past are

destroyed.

The tension of the movement of the exploited arises from the awareness

of the discrepancy between one’s being theory, and one’s realisation in

practice. This contradiction affects the movement deeply, often

unleashing one part of it against the other, thus playing the game of

the forces of power. But this tension is vital, it is the essential

strength of coordination towards the future. It is from within it that

the destructive and creative capacities of the revolution explode.

The anarchist minority also carry a profound laceration. The rigidity of

the closed model seen as the reproduction of revolutionary totality

risks depriving it of the quality of the revolution, that is of the new

quality of life. Only by accepting this renunciation and falling victim

to the quantitative illusion will it succeed in silencing the intimate

tension that plagues it. But in so doing it also destroys the meaning of

its own revolutionary anarchist project, cutting off any real contact

with the masses. Not only that, its militants, as individuals conscious

of revolutionary possibility in that they are (knowingly) cut out of the

revolutionary totality, are personally living another tension that is

felt all the more because it touches the life of each one. This other

tension cannot be satisfied with quantitative games, globalising

analyses or memories of the proletariat. It needs to identify itself in

another, still wider, tension, that of the mass itself. Either the

minority accepts living the tension of the single individuals that

compose it while at the same time living the tension of the mass, or it

is condemned to remain a vanguard and, as such, to become responsible

for all the consequences that ensue.

Consciousness of revolutionary tension is the first sign of going beyond

alienation.

For the movement of the exploited this consciousness expresses itself in

a more organic search for the self-organisation of struggles. What was

once lost in the individual behaviour of atomised defence against

repression and exploitation, an individual reaction in order to

reevaluate the life extinguished by the integrative process of

capitalism, now becomes a quantifying project. The movement of the

exploited begins to give itself an autonomous structure, it starts

seeking new internal relations and links. In this research and

realisation tension becomes construction. Theory increasingly takes form

and begins to resemble practice more and more.

For the anarchist minority, the awareness of revolutionary tension is a

sign of maturity. It gradually rids itself of the quantitative illusion,

of feeling itself to be carrier of “truth”, an “external” force, a

“memory”. This is only possible on condition that the internal tension

be lightened, that the single militants see the revolutionary

relationship possibility-totality, have been struggling against

alienation and been able to go beyond it in a personal tension. The

latter now reappears at the level of a minority, to find its place

within the wider tension of the movement of the exploited, the only

dimension in which it is possible to find a constructive road towards

quantitative growth.

The solution of the problem of the vanguard

To conclude, we can define the vanguard as an involution, a giving in in

the face of the revolutionary anarchist project. Now we can see that the

definition “an organic whole composed of individuals” that we made at

the beginning is no longer sufficient. The actual composition of the

vanguard becomes less important in the face of its significance within

the complex framework of revolutionary relations. The vanguard is

therefore an escape from the sensations of suffering and panic that are

caused by revolutionary alienation; it is the refusal of tension towards

the movement of the exploited, a tension that the latter develops in its

contradictory relationship between self-organisation and delegation of

the struggle. The vanguard takes the place of the quantitative task of

the movement of the exploited, wanting to reproduce at a reduced level

(either with edifying aims or with the aim of domination), the reality

of the struggles as a whole. It is a desire to quantify the

unquantifiable. It is a violent deformation of revolutionary possibility

into fictitious necessity (totality). The vanguard is the acceptance of

a globalising analysis that claims to “take account of everything” in an

exclusively theoretical field, fictitiously doing what the movement of

the exploited bring about in reality by becoming theory and praxis at

the same time.

On the contrary, full knowledge of revolutionary alienation allows

access to individual revolutionary tension, which would lose itself in a

postponement to the infinity of the total project of the revolution,

were it not to find its correct development within the tension of the

minority. If this gives up in the face of obstacles, it transforms

itself into a vanguard and acts accordingly. The tension of the minority

extinguishes itself in the quantitative illusion and in the analytical

project that claims to be global. The tension of the individual recedes

into the suffering of alienation, finding comfort in a thousand little

facets of the quantitative project cut off from the mass. In fact, the

more pressing the suffering caused by revolutionary alienation; the

greater the detachment, loss of totality and the quality of revolution,

the more paltry the engagement in quantitative daily praxis will be in

solving a guilty conscience. If the tension of the minority is inserted

within the wider tension of the movement of the exploited a point of

contact is made between self-organisation and delegation of struggles.

It develops a solicitation for self-organisation, adding one’s own

revolutionary tension to that of the movement of the exploited,

developing the anarchist revolutionary project fully in harmony with

this movement’s theory.

The more detail and clarification this theory acquires; the more it

becomes conscious of itself, advances in the self-organisation of the

struggle, gives itself an autonomous structure, connects internal

relations and establishes links, the more it will renounce the false

perspective of the delegate (parties and unions). The traditional

function of the anarchist minority will diminish, and, losing its value,

its revolutionary tension will increase. In fact, the aim of the

anarchist movement is to contribute to the construction of a society in

which there will no longer be exploitation. And exploitation no longer

existing, there will no longer be a need for the political struggle,

movements and consequently not even the anarchist movement.

The final negation of the anarchist minority as such will not be the

decision of a group or something that happens outside the minority. It

will be the realisation of revolutionary tension in revolutionary

totality, the liberated society. In this final phase, the movement of

the exploited will realise its own theory (that will no longer differ

from its practice), and through this realisation the vicissitudes of the

anarchist minority will come to an end.