💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › amedeo-bertolo-the-subersive-weed.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 06:32:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The subversive weed
Author: Amedeo Bertolo
Date: 1979
Language: en
Topics: self-management
Source: Retrieved on 17th May 2021 from https://autonomies.org/2021/04/amedeo-bertolo-the-subversive-weed/
Notes: This text was presented at the “Self-management” studies conference in Venice, 28–30 of September, 1979, and was subsequently published in Interrogations, nº. 17–18, 1979.

Amedeo Bertolo

The subversive weed

The temptation is strong for the anarchist: “self-management” is a new

word for something old, better, for many old things, because this word

also, as with almost all of the economic, political and social

vocabulary, can mean more than one thing.

In its broadest, “extremist” sense, self-management is synonymous, if

not with anarchy, with self-government (a term from the old anarchist

lexicon). It is what Philippe Oyhamburu defends, for example, when he

confronts the claims of those who advocate “self-management” with the

thought and achievements of anarchists and anarchism, highlighting the

fact that the self-management movement not only takes up the greater

part of the themes of the later, but arrives at the point of repeating

them word for word. Furthermore, the Yugoslavian term samoupravlje, from

which “was born” the translation to the word “self-management” at the

beginning of the 1970s, looks like a Serbo-Croatian variation on the

Russian samoupravljanje, already used by Bakunin, which can be

translated either as self-administration or as self-government.

In its more limited meaning, self-management is synonymous with

co-management, that is, the subaltern participation of workers, that is,

inter-classist collaboration, that is, deception. Between one extreme

and the other, there exist all of the possible intermediate nuances of

meaning and of the theoretical-practical choices of socialism, from the

libertarian to the authoritarian, from the revolutionary to the

reformist.

Therefore, there is a strong temptation to finish with the matter, above

all because of the inflated and mystifying use of the term, which can

only irritate us (we are offered “self-managed” vacations,

“self-managed” televised electoral propaganda by parties …). However, we

believe that, behind the success of the word, there exists more and

something more important than an umpteenth mystification and a subtle

recuperation, with a new terminology, of the anarchist tradition. The

very effort at mystification and recuperation, in itself, signifies a

social “demand” to which mystification and recuperation refer to.

A demand for anarchy

The fact is that self-management was before all else a widely diffused

demand and social practice over the course of the last decade.[1] The

self-management boom is perhaps, from the anarchist point of view, the

most important cultural phenomenon of this post-war. And by cultural

phenomenon, I do not mean the flourishing of texts about

self-management, which I see more as an effect rather than a cause of

the boom, but to the multiplication of practices in social conflicts,

above all since 1968, but already foreshadowed in the preceding years.

A growing desire for individual and collective self-determination

manifested itself over the length of this period (sometimes clearly,

more frequently, confusedly and contradictorily, but always “readable”)

in a thousand ways: from hippie communities to factory occupations, from

student struggles to the feminist movement, from the refusal of

delegation to the search for different interpersonal relations … Between

the “on fabrique, on vend, on se paie”[2] of the LIP[3] and “the body is

mine and it is I who control it”, there is continuity. The social

pursuit of self-management in fact exists in a multiplicity of ways and

at every level, which translates into a de-structuration of power in all

of the macro and micro-systems where power manifests itself: from the

family to the State, passing through the factory, the neighbourhood, the

school, the hospital, the labour union, the political party …

Is this a rejection of power or a pursuit of power? Reformists and

authoritarian revolutionaries prefer to qualify this social pursuit as a

pursuit of power: but is it still power when there is no desire to

become a faculty of “command and obedience”, but rather a faculty for

deciding autonomously? The aspiration to self-management seems to us to

be the libertarian equivalent in terms of power, parallel to the

egalitarian socialist aspiration in terms of property. In this instance,

what is required is the socialisation of power.

Now, a socialised power, that is, one not concentrated in specific

social roles (and therefore in individuals and dominant classes), but

diffused throughout the whole social body and in its articulations as a

universal and equal function, may correspond to a close approximation to

anarchism. If this is not the case for the

anarchism-of-the-absence-of-power (a limit concept like geometric

forms), it may at least hold for that dynamic compromise between the

ideal model and the bonds to material contexts and cultural givens,

which we could call “possible anarchism”. But a socialised power can

also be understood, conversely, as an abominable instrument of

omnipresent authoritarian control, in which power becomes a universal

though unequal function (graded from the top to the base), in a

continuous change that involves all of the roles of reciprocal

oppression. Brrr …

Means, end or method?

A profound and serious approach to the theme of self-management

configures two useful possibilities – to my mind, fundamental – for

anarchists: 1) to reflect on the contents and the more advanced forms

(in egalitarian and libertarian terms) assumed by contemporary social

conflicts and, at the same time, on the responses given by the dominant

classes; 2) to reflect on the problems of “possible anarchism”, that is,

on the problems of the social reconstruction, of the global

restructuring of the communitarian fabric according to non-hierarchical

models.

I believe accordingly that the debate around self-management can be an

important occasion for anarchists. If the demand for self-management is,

in a certain measure, a “demand for anarchy”, it is not necessary to add

a pair of slogans to our repertoire of words of order, but to extract

from it indications for our action. If sociologists, economists,

philosophers, psychologists, urbanists, increasingly use the

self-management key for a quasi-anarchist approach to the human sciences

and propose quasi-anarchist solutions to social problems, it is not

enough for us to congratulate ourselves for the phenomenon, much less

claim priority over the method. We must work seriously to propose

ourselves as the point of credible libertarian cultural reference here

and now … If politicians and bureaucrats and technocrats prattle on

about self-management, or worse, are in the process of elaborating and

realising partial or distorted versions of it, it is useless to shout

out, “thief!” We must rather demystify their game with convincing

arguments and exemplary struggles.

Self-management should not be, of course, a simple pretext for

“refreshing” our “beautiful ideal”. Very much on the contrary, it is a

matter of carrying out a real renewal of our cultural baggage and of

acting in a more useful manner, that is, 1) from real instances and not

only from an individual or movement demand that is ours, 2) organising

our reflection around a concept which constantly reminds us of the

consistency of the organisational forms.

I do not wish to say with this that all of the theoretical-practical

work of redefining the anarchist project be reduced, in a simple way, to

the category of self-management. The concept of self-management in

itself can in no way substitute the very rich problematic of the means

and ends of anarchism, something which is sustained by a vast conceptual

range of an ethical, aesthetic and scientific order …

In fact, the ambit specific to self-management is not that of ends, nor

of means, contrary to what may appear, sometimes, in its individual

manifestations in social conflicts. It falls rather in the intermediary

ambit of method, the ambit of the relations between ends and means. Even

while participating in both, self-management is not an end (or a sum of

ends), nor a means (or a sum of means), but a way to seek and express

the coherence between them in organisational terms and in relation both

to the theoretical-practical critique of what exists and the proposal of

alternative social structures.

To define self-management as an organisational method may seem

restrictive. In truth, what this means is that we attribute to it a

central importance. Significantly, the great fractures at the heart of

the socialist movement were verified not with regard to ends, which

seemed to be the same, but over method: over the choice of means and

over their coherence with chosen ends. To define self-management as a

method also means denying it the neutrality of a simple technique, good

for all occasions, to attribute to it a specific functionality in

relation to the values of freedom and equality adequate to it.

Between theory and social practice

Self-management understood as an end seems to me to derive from – and/or

lead to – a terribly limited and limiting concept of society and of

human beings. Self-management understood as a means lends itself to

mystifying uses. It is susceptible, in a more or less insignificant form

of decentralised power, to appropriation in new “participatory”

techno-bureaucratic systems. Both can give way to new and obscene forms

of “interiorised” power, that is, to an “induced” self-control”, a

“piloted” self-discipline in a hierarchical society, to a kind of

self-exploitation, a “consensual” domination.

Contrariwise, conceived as a method and placed in a position of

juncture, not only between means and ends, but also between theory and

social practice, self-management can express all of the wealth and all

of the difficulty of anti-hierarchical and anti-bureaucratic conflict

and thought. In this condition, it can become a formidable logical and

operational instrument; a subversive instrument not vulnerable to social

and conceptually classist systems, because irreducibly libertarian and

egalitarian.

Such wealth is moreover verified in reality, that is, in the

multiplicity of self-management demands expressed in social struggles

and, furthermore, in the thought of the theoreticians of generalised

self-management who, though in the majority Marxists, arrived not by

chance at the substantially anarchist positions of the rejection of the

State and of all hierarchy, of the party and of any vanguard …

The fact is that self-management, as we were saying, is only a

libertarian and egalitarian methodology if all of its presuppositions

and implications are fully accepted in depth and extension. That is,

when the conditions necessary for any individual to be truly the subject

and not the object of choices which affect them are studied and when, by

necessary coherence, the field of application of self-management of the

limited microcosm of business is extended to all spheres and to all

levels of social life. Generalised self-management thus becomes a

cultural dimension, in which can be found: individual and collective

revolts against all and any form (economic, political, sexual, ethnic,

ideological …) of relation of domination; efforts (great or small,

revolutionary or marginal) and experiences (extra or anti-institutional)

to re-establish, on new bases, collective life; tensions of ideals and

emotive drives not reducible to recognised necessities and more or less

satisfied by the large hierarchical systems; efforts to re-think

society, and therefore, human beings, to find new approaches and/or keys

to the reading of history.

Does not this generalised self-management organise itself, or tend to

organise itself, more like a true and proper system rather than a

method? For example, as an alternative model of global society with

socialised power, does it not end up as that possible anarchism that I

spoke of earlier? Yes, but because in this system, in this model, in

this cultural dimension, are introduced criteria of judgement (values)

and cognitive criteria (modes of selection and organisation of facts so

as to transform them into information) which, even though derived or

extracted from the organisational method, they are no longer just

method, they are no longer just about self-management. And because

self-management is not a neutral method, that which derives from it

either by induction or deduction has the anarchist seal, or better, is

that much more anarchist the greater is its depth and extension.

To graft and prune the old trunk

Generalised self-management therefore may well be another way of saying

libertarian socialism. Is it nothing new? On the contrary: it is rather

libertarian socialism rediscovered, or better, reconstructed in the

struggles, in the experiences, in the scientific and technical

innovations, in a word, in the culture, of these last two decades.

Generalised self-management is a theory still in construction, as any

living theory should be, but which has already defined references that

correspond to our own references. This is something which is not

surprising given that it followed, more or less, the same logical

itineraries we did, but it followed them today, whereas we did so

yesterday.

General formulations, such as the “first principle of self-management”

as defined by Bourdet (refusal of the delegation of power, revocability

of all mandates at any moment), give anarchists, who always theorised

and practised them, the impression of a discovery … an obvious

discovery. We cannot and should not however limit ourselves to viewing

the phenomenon with suspicion or with satisfaction, but yes, before the

pillage – more or less voluntary – and the recycling of our ideas

becomes irreversible, we should accelerate the restructuring of our

theoretical capital. The latter is an obsolete capital, not in its

general formulations – which also rightly confirm themselves as valid in

the debate on self-management – but in all of its intermediate

articulation and in its operational instruments.

Ecology, alternative technology, anti-authoritarian pedagogy and

institutional analysis cannot simply be added to anarchist thought,in

the same manner that occasional fragments of the social and human

sciences, from anthropology to economics, from psychology to sociology,

cannot be mechanically added to it. The operation that I desire is much

more complex. The old and solid trunk of anarchism is still vigorous,

but it must be energetically pruned so that young branches can sprout

and develop and so that it may receive new grafts without rejecting or

suffocating them. The blossoming of the practice and theory of

self-management seems to me in fact to be a good occasion to prune and

graft. From the debate on self-management, we can extract elements to

decide what to prune and what to graft.

Without undeserved inferiority complexes, but also without illusory

superiority complexes, anarchists can hope for, in the debate around

self-management, a precious contribution of openness in the direction of

what is new and different, of creative stimuli, of admonition against

hiding its own unresolved problems behind ready to hand formula. For

their part, anarchists can bring to the debate the precious contribution

of the collective memory of a movement that lived consciously (conscious

also of its own contradictions) the whole problematic of self-management

through victories and defeats, joys and sufferings, struggles and daily

life, through the hearts and minds of hundreds of thousands of

militants.

The hierarchical division of labour …

The debate on self-management moves first of all from the field of what

is by definition most proper to it: from the analysis of collective

decision making mechanisms, that is, from the reflection on how, in

hierarchical organisational structures, power is determined and on how,

inversely, it is possible concretely to organise the egalitarian

participation of all in decision making processes. It is a reflection on

the themes of authority and freedom and a reflection that leads directly

to the fulcral points of direct democracy and the division of labour.

In fact, it is easy to (re)discover from this perspective that the

fundamental distinction, common to all class societies, is that between

who holds power and who bears it, between who governs and who is

governed, and that the cause of this dichotomy is not the private

ownership of the means of production, which is one of its historically

determined juridical-economic forms. It is easy therefore to

(re)discover that the root of domination is the hierarchical division of

social labour and that, as a result, self-management is an empty shell

if it does not presuppose the integration (to recall Bakunin and

Kropotkin) of manual and intellectual, executive and organisational

labour.

Without this recomposition, self-management is already impossible at the

level of a business company, because the effective possibility and

capacity of all workers to operate and decide knowingly is absent (which

is the second of the two fundamental principles of self-management,

according to Bourdet). Without such a recomposition, there can be no

egalitarian participation based on knowledge and responsibility and

there is no, therefore, self-management, but rather asymmetrical

co-management between managers and subordinates, even if everyone is

formally a partner or member, or even if the first are formally

“dependent” on the second, following the Yugoslavian formula.

It is an unsuspicious witness of the regime (Milojko Drulovic) who tells

us that according to sociological studies, the frequent conflicts

between management and representative organs of the workers express an

“acute antagonism, a true struggle over the sharing of power and

authority” and one of the causes would be, oh look, the extravagant

pretension of the workers to “interfere in the domain of management”

based on a “primitive conception according to which self-management

would suppress the division of labour”. More truthfully, the integration

should be extended to the whole of society, because the hierarchical

division of social labour is not a phenomenon that can be simply reduced

to the sphere of businesses, nor even to that of economics, but it

refers to the whole of social functions. And even remaining within the

economic sphere, it is necessary to recognise in exploitation not only

the quantitative aspect, but also the qualitative, which consists in

reserving for a small minority the more gratifying types of work, while

to the majority fall the more thankless, exhausting, frustrating kinds

of labour. The cleaner of sewers continues to be a cleaner of sewers

even under self-management. The urban planner continues to be an urban

planner even under self-management. We can very well imagine a

self-managed collective of porters and a self-managed collective of

doctors; we can even imagine (it is a difficult abstraction, I admit)

that they exchange their labour on a level of equality: one hour of work

of the one is paid for by one hour of work of the other. But the

exchange will remain unequal, the qualitative exploitation persists.

This is masked by the fact that normally – and not by chance –,

quantitative exploitation is superimposed on it. Yet when the

paradoxical norm, according to which to the more unpleasant jobs

correspond the lower salaries, is contradicted, the qualitative

dimension of exploitation becomes evident. For example, today a street

cleaner earns more than a secondary school teacher, but the result is

not any tendency on the part of the teachers to be contracted as street

cleaners …

… and its egalitarian recomposition

The hierarchical division of social labour is therefore charged with

non-egalitarian meanings: exploitation, privilege and, above all, power.

The ideologies of power (whether they are capitalist or

techno-bureaucratic) justify the hierarchy with the organisational

necessities of complex societies. They shuffle the cards because they

falsely mix two things which are not necessarily tied. It is undeniable

that with social-economic structures more articulated than those found

in a tribe of hunters and gatherers that the social and technical

division of labour is not, to a certain degree, eliminable. It is

undeniable that these structures, from the business company to the local

community, and so on, to the broadest social systems, must articulate

themselves by functions. But it is by no means necessary that the

functions become fixed roles: rotation, for example, permits reconciling

division with equality. Furthermore, certain functions can very well

become collective, others still can be performed with a revocable

mandate, others, lastly, will completely disappear because they are only

useful and necessary to the hierarchical system; a system which

generates them in large quantities and continually so as to preserve and

justify itself.

What is there to prevent, for example, that in a hospital all of the

workers discharge manual and intellectual functions by rotation (that

all be, in different periods of the day, the week or the year,

doctors-nurses-auxiliaries), that the management be collective, with

administrative tasks attributed temporarily, along with internal and

external coordination? There is no real motive for this, but only the

false motives of a rationality internal to the logic of power, that is,

a deliberate, created and artificially maintained relative scarcity of

intellectual competencies used to justify the monopoly of a knowledge

class and, therefore, a hierarchy.

The objection that it would be a waste to underuse the minds of the

intellectuals, obliging them to dedicate a part of their time to manual

labour is repugnantly imbecilic. What to say then of the enormous waste

of creativity, intelligence and imagination of nine out of ten people,

mutilated in their capacities and condemned to a stupid and

disheartening routine in factories, offices, in domestic labour, such

that only one person can grow, think, invent? And why do we not also ask

ourselves how much the very intelligence of this person was impoverished

due to the privation of the stimuli that come from manual activities,

that is, from the direct contact with material reality?

From this perspective, the recent phenomenon of mass schooling acquires

a particular significance, with its demands for the right to study, with

its shoving against, a little ambitiously and a little demagogically,

the economic and meritocratic barriers placed in defence of privileged

knowing. Beyond the individual aspirations to a social promotion by

means of a diploma and a university degree, as a global phenomenon, as

the objective sum of individual motivations, what is at issue here is a

generalised search for intellectual labour, a search, which because it

is generalised, cannot be satisfied except through the negation of the

social pyramid and the non-egalitarian distribution among everyone of

either manual or intellectual work. And it is perhaps not a fortuitous

coincidence if self-management made a thunderous eruption, as a demand

and as a practice, in May 68, a popular explosion unleashed by the

Parisian students …

The integration of intellectual and manual work determines a condition

of equality in the effective possibilities and capacities of decision

making. However, it does not exhaust, but only introduces, the discourse

about direct democracy, as the division between manual and intellectual

work does not exhaust the discourse about power. In effect, not all

intellectual workers, on the contrary, only a minority among them, are

integrated into the dominant class. Neither scientists, for example, nor

doctors, neither professors nor engineers exercise, as such, functions

of power. They do so only if they occupy positions of control and social

management, if and while they exercise functions of “hetero-management”,

that is, management over other human beings.

Whatever its apparent origin and its justification (property ownership

or organisational capacity, merit or competence), whatever the manner by

which it was conferred or legitimised (mercantilist mechanisms or

meritocratic selection, investiture from on high or “democratic”

delegation from below), the power of rulers is always obtained by

confiscating it from society, that is, by negating the fact and the

right to all others of the faculty of individual and collective

self-determination.

The delegation of power that is expressed in representative democracy,

or indirect democracy, is perhaps the most subtly mystifying device for

legitimising hierarchy. It therefore threatens to be a Trojan horse of

power in the practice and thought of self-management, as historical and

contemporary experiences, from Spain to Yugoslavia, from the cooperative

movement to labour union bureaucracies, demonstrate. Presented as an

organisational technique, it is, on the contrary, a functional,

organisational mode of hierarchical power, incompatible with

self-management.

Let it be noted though that we are not here making any consideration

about the fact that, in a parliamentary democracy, elections are not a

means to nominate the political leaders, but only a very small part of

the formal representation of political power. And we omit the facile

irony about the mystifying nature of “electoral” choice. The socialist

himself, Giorgio Ruffulo, current candidate to the European elections,

defined three years ago the voting mechanism as an “applause-o-metre”

(an applause-o-metre flawed, we add, by the current sophisticated

techniques of public opinion manipulation). What we are interested in

highlighting here is that even if, in the abstract, all of the functions

of social management were elected, these same elected managers would

constitute themselves as a dominant class, by the very objective logic

of the delegation of power.

The astuteness of extending to the economic and business domain a few

measures of representative democracy (in the form of co-management or

technocratic “self-management”) is an even fairly transparent attempt at

recasting the consensus around productivist alienation in the face of

the bankruptcy of capitalist ideology. Even though representative

democracy already shows signs of wear in the political field and has

increasing difficulties in masking its true oligarchic nature, its

renovation in an economic frame can perhaps still exercise some

attraction because it is based on cultural values deposited in the

collective unconscious. The rejection of delegation is still a

relatively new “effervescent” social phenomenon that arises in times of

crisis.

… and direct democracy

If the delegation of power opens a fracture in the social body, between

“managers” and “managed”, self-management can only be recognised and

realised in direct democracy, that is, only on the condition that power

remains a collective function, that it is never separated from the

collectivity as a superior authority, not even if elected. Direct

democracy does not mean, reductively, assembly based democracy. Even if

the assembly is its fundamental organ, the subsequent articulation of

direct democracy draws on other formulas such as revocable mandates,

beyond the delegation of power. There is delegation of power when

someone is charged with taking imperative decisions over the

collectivity, in the name and on behalf of it, relative to a broad range

of questions and with ample discretionary power. If, on the contrary,

the mandate is specific and temporary, with limited and defined margins

of discretionary authority, and above all, if it is revocable at any

moment by the constituents, that is, by the collectivity that expressed

itself through the representative, then this latter does not replace or

substitute the collective will, nor can it freely interpret it (an old

trick of representative democracy), because its actions are subject to

permanent verification.

In general terms, direct democracy may be defined by a sovereign

assembly, revocable mandates and, lastly, the constant rotation (at more

or less long intervals, according to their nature) of all permanent

functions of coordination, of all “leadership” functions not

collectively exercised. And this is how popular democracy expressed

itself when, episodically and temporarily, it could manifest itself

without excessive objective and subjective constraints. The Spanish

libertarian collectives were so organised. And so are the numerous

Israeli kibbutzim still organised, in which, according to Rosner,

approximately some 50 percent of the members participate in committees

and management functions by rotation. And do not revocable mandates go

back to the Paris Commune? And do we not find revocable mandates and the

sovereign assembly as demands and as praxis in the workers struggles of

the last ten years? Direct democracy is already social practice, even if

only episodic and fragmentary.

The problem of dimension

Those who want to reduce self-management to marginality, or who would

deny it any chance whatsoever, say that direct democracy can only be

applied to small scale organisations. Let us then consider the question

of dimension. Paradoxically, I am also convinced that the large scale is

the dimension of power and that the small scale is that of direct

democracy. But I draw from this conviction different conclusions:

elementary associative units (productive, territorial, etc.) can and

should be small and, between them, a web of horizontal relations should

be woven. In other words, large units and the very pernicious

concept-myth of Unity with a capital letter should be rejected. The

small units, in turn, should not be the bricks of a pyramidal structure,

but the nodes of a sort of federative network of egalitarian connections

that go from the simple to the complex, and not from the base to the

vertex.

The large private enterprise, the megalopolises, the State, should be

rejected and broken down because the “large” segregates power within and

outside of itself. Large economic and political aggregates, large social

institutions, are the field where the power of the “new bosses-managers”

is affirmed and exercised: it is here that the techno-bureaucracy finds

its vital space and its functional justifications, whether in

late-capitalist or post-capitalist systems.

There is enough experience and scientific research to know that certain

dimensional limits cannot be exceeded if direct communication is to be

preserved, which is essential to direct democracy and which is

exemplified (though not reducible to it) in the active participation in

an assembly. A decision making assembly of thousands of people is

unimaginable. Such an assembly can only approve or reject simple

proposals, proposals previously simplified. Furthermore, an assembly of

this kind risks responding, credibly, more to emotional than to rational

solicitations, following the law of the psychology of the masses.

On the other hand, if it is true that direct communication can be joined

by other forms of horizontal communication (made possible by the

appropriate use of electronic and television media, as Prandstraller and

Flecchia suggest for example), it is also true that these last should

not replace the former, but merely add to them, especially at a federal

level, because they can more easily be an instrument of control and/or

of polling than of forming and expressing popular will. Accordingly, the

first fundamental sphere of collective self-determination can be none

other than the elementary associative unit – in the same way that the

first and fundamental sphere of freedom can only be the individual – and

this unit should be “at the scale of the assembly”. The self-management

approach to the problem of scale should therefore be posed, without

inhibition, following the line of thought synthesised by the felicitous

expression of E.F. Schumacher that, “small is beautiful”. It is a matter

of inverting the logical idea, which starts from what exists and its

“objective” tendencies towards economic, political and technological

gigantism, to then prove the “necessity” of the large scale. To fall

anew into that logic would be disastrous for the theory and practice of

self-management, for one would then arrive at the demonstration of the

impossibility of generalised self-management. It would also be a

mistake, because in truth it is not technology, the economy,

rationality, that impose macrostructures and macro-institutions, but a

technology, an economy, a rationality, determined by the logic of power,

even though, in turn, by a feedback effect, they become determining,

creating a diabolical circle in which each element mutually sustains

itself with “objective” and ideological motivations.

Conversely, self-management should rethink the economy, technology,

territorial organisation, etc., starting from its demands, applying its

rationality. This may carry some reduction in efficiency, but it is a

price, if revealed to be necessary, that should be accepted. It still

has to be demonstrated however that the higher costs of the small scale,

even within an accounting framework of technical and economic

efficiency, are greater than its benefits.

On the contrary, there is a whole new current of scientific thought that

is (re)discovering the signs of some of the “economies of scale” opposed

to those until recently brandished as justifications for gigantism. As

in many other cases, here also one may begin with an apparently

unquestionable definition to infer consequences contrary to those given

as certain and culturally dominant. We have, in fact, economies of scale

when we approach the optimal scale and, inversely, we have growing

diseconomies the more we move away from this optimum. But no one has

demonstrated, nor can they, that the optimal scale tends towards

infinity. On the contrary, there are sufficient elements to believe that

beyond certain dimensional limits (which are still not those that we

would define as small, being rather, let us say, medium), that we have

phenomena of economic inefficiency and congestion incompatible with any

system, that problems of management and social control so grave are

created that they annul, even within capitalist and technocratic logic,

the advantages of centralisation.

A recent French study of computer technology applied to business

management (to hetero-management, not to self-management) suggests that

for an optimal ascendant/descendent flux of information, the dimensional

limit should not surpass five hundred employees. And in Italy, the

discovery of the small business and its virtues dates from last year:

the small business is flexible, dynamic, versatile, sensitive,

efficient… From being a sign of backwardness, an obstacle to

development, it became, thanks to the work of journalists and “recycled”

researchers of the small, the spine, as well as the enabling element, of

the economy. Before the elephantiasis of Italian style large companies

(nationalised, irizzata,[4] gepizzata,[5] imizzata,[6] assisted,

sclerotic, somnolent, ministerial), the ambitious entrepreneurialism of

thousands of managers of small scale exploitation, an Italian style

entrepreneurialism also, naturally comprised not only of imagination,

but also of illegal labour, tax evasion, ecological banditry; an

entrepreneurialism that exploits and, in turn, in an ambivalent

relationship, that is exploited by large public and private companies.

Small is beautiful

A breach therefore begins to open (finally!) in the wall of the dominant

ideology of the “big is beautiful” and a growing number of researchers

contribute by demonstrating that a different technology is possible, a

small scale technology which is the instrument of man and not of which

man is the instrument; that it is possible to respond to the energy

crisis differently, without recourse to nuclear energy and the pillaging

of natural resources, and that the use of renewable energy sources is

more effective at small scales; that pollution becomes dramatic and

costly as a large scale phenomenon; that interpersonal communication,

which is an equally important social function of production, is not

richer on the large scale, but poorer (and accordingly the poverty of

relations is not only a characteristic of “rural stupidity”, but also of

a new “urban stupidity”); that, in their complexity, large social

structures are machines of decreasing output in relation to what they

“consume”, with the growth of their size …

And so on. The field of discoveries regarding the irrationality of the

large scale, opened by a “simple” inversion of perspective, continues to

be very fecund and its exploration is only at the beginning. This

current of thought, in its more radical expressions, is antithetical to

the scientific ideology of power. In its more tempered expressions,

however, it can be useful to power, just like a vaccine is an extremely

useful tempered form of the illness. In effect, it is the very owners of

the economy and the State who, for some years now, multiply experiences

of and proposals for decentralisation, for the dismantling (not

separation) of power, in the factory and society. It is a confession of

failure, but also an effort to found a different centralisation of

power, decongesting the centre, delegating what this cannot control to

peripheral zones of power, a decreasing control of the centre to the

periphery.

This decentralisation, and the philosophy which sustains it and the

science which lends it its instruments, is not the opposite of

concentration, but the other necessary side of concentration. This

decentralisation has nothing to do with the fabric of federative

organisation in which the very concepts of periphery and centre are

surpassed, because each point is in the centre of the relations that

concern it. The geometrical metaphor of a disk has the same hierarchical

validity as the pyramid metaphor: it is the two dimensional version of

the circle and it is not by chance that it immediately recalls the

hierarchical structure of the territory, where a capital occupies the

place of the capital, to use a little word play.

While in decentralised authoritarianism, the centre decides over

everything that it can and delegates that which escapes it, or runs the

risk of escaping it, in federative decentralisation it is the associated

unit which decides everything that falls under its competence and,

together with other units, that which falls under a common competence,

in accordance with agreements and temporary or permanent coordinating

organs. It is not word play, but a true logical inversion. It is a

matter, for example, of considering neighbourhood assemblies as the

decentralisation of municipal administration and this latter as the

decentralisation of the State or, conversely, of considering the city as

a federation of neighbourhoods (as the medieval commune was to some

extent, with a nostalgia for the past) and these, in turn, as

federations of smaller aggregate units. Even companies which surpass

certain dimensions can be conceived of as, in this light, a federation

of parts. Which is precisely what is presupposed, even if only along the

lines of a decentralised hierarchy, by the Yugoslav structure of

self-management for large companies and what is also behind the

non-expressed logic behind the factory councils, made up of section

delegates.

There is therefore no objective obstacle to the small scale. It is also,

in addition, perfectly compatible with a rich and variegated range of

inter-human relations, because with its potentiality for disaggregating

power, their also coexists a potentiality to re-aggregate and re-combine

society.

Equal but diverse

We said that the small was necessary, we said that the small is

possible, we said, finally, that the small is beautiful. This last

affirmation leads us to a further problematic knot: diversity. The small

is, in effect, also beautiful, and perhaps above all, because the small

is diverse. The discourse about equality cannot be separated from that

about diversity.

Far from being contradictory, the concepts of equality and diversity are

complementary: paradoxically, it is in fact inequality which leads to

uniformity, to levelling, to massification. Even though the ideologies

of inequality claim to ground themselves in “natural” variations, the

only diversity which they recognise is that which is inherent to the

hierarchical division of social labour, the only diversity that they

justify is the inequality of roles.

Power, by its nature, denies everything that opposes it and diversity

opposes it insofar as it is ungovernable: no power is sufficiently

elastic to manage the infinitely diverse. Only the diverse can manage

itself. What is diverse proclaims self-management, what is diverse is

the living negation of hetero-management. Power is therefore in a

continuous war – a war to the death – with the diverse; it must destroy

diversity, or at least channel it into inequality. In particular, the

tendency towards totalitarianism of the power of our times is the

implacable enemy of diversity. For technocratic and bureaucratic logic,

the ideal world is a standardised world whose “quality” is entirely

reducible to what can be computerised, planed, predicted, controlled,

registered, machine recorded, added to, subtracted from, multiplied,

divided … For classical capitalist logic, the ideal world is a global

market in which everything and everyone is a commodity. For the hybrid

logic of late-capitalism, the ideal world is mid-way between the

capitalist and the techno-bureaucratic ideals.

For power today, from the techno-bureaucratic East to the

late-capitalist West, as well as in the greater part of the Third World

that imitates both (in Africa, for example, tribal and ethnic

differences are combated, even pitilessly, so as to construct artificial

“national” unities), diversity is even more unacceptable than for any

other kind of historically known power. Like a compressor roll, power

tends to level cultural differences, destroy ethnicities, languages,

local, regional and national customs, beyond denying, as all earlier

powers did, individual diversity (reduced to inequality, as already

said, or mortified). Like a social bulldozer, power dreams of levelling

hills, filling valleys, straightening rivers, creating an endless plain

from which rise up only, at regular intervals, control towers and the

squalid castles of its privilege.

Until now, diversity was considered in the best of cases as a fact to

respect, an object to tolerate. This however is an inadequate

interpretation and, at the limit, dangerously reductive. Diversity, on

the contrary, must not only be accepted, but exalted, sought for,

continuously created and recreated, because diversity is a human

necessity, because diversity is a value in itself. The diverse is

beautiful. As it is beautiful that there are no two identical leaves, it

is also beautiful that each house, each landscape, each city, each

dialect, each person, each nation be unique and different.

The ethnic minorities which rediscover and claim their cultural

identity, the right to their language and to their traditions, are also

an expression of the human need for diversity and in this they are

consonant with the search for self-management. Even though the

repression of diversity can generate, by reaction and similarly to

sexual repression, perverse responses (such as neo-colonialism,

neo-racism, mini-statism, etc.), these centrifugal tendencies towards

the diverse bear within themselves a seed of equality and freedom.

Harmony and conflict

Diversity implies not only complementarity and, therefore, harmony, but

also conflict. This does not frighten me. A society without contrasts

never appeared to me to be an attractive model. It always gave me the

impression of being not the opposite of a totalitarian society, but its

inverse in an “affective” key. A pyramid turned upside down is not the

opposite of the pyramid, but its mirror image. The utopian ideal of a

society perfectly conciliated through fraternity (but why must brothers

always be in agreement?) seems to me to be reflectively similar to the

hierarchical utopia of coercive conciliation, equally asphyxiating, even

though without laws, regulations, police, judges, directors, priests. In

fact, the anarchist prefers to speak more of solidarity than fraternity,

which is not an insignificant nuance.

In this regard, the merely outlined interpretation by Clastres, in the

last phase of his life, of the bellicosity of primitive peoples as a

defence mechanism of the multiple (the diverse) against the One, of

society against the State, is challenging. With this interpretation of

conflict (of a certain kind of conflict), an equally positive reading is

proffered.

In effect, not all social conflict is born of inequality. On the

contrary, it may perhaps be assumed that the simplified antagonism of

interests, created by the hierarchical division of social labour,

compresses and hides a much more varied diversity of interests. It is

true that the conflict born in and of class society, a conflict which

justifies the “work” of the apparatuses of psychic and physical

repression, and which justifies a growing waste of social energy for the

creation of consensus and the containment of dissension, is an

incomparable conflict due to its intensity and devastating validity. The

conflict of diversity is not the conflict of inequality. The first does

not confront us with the insoluble problem that the second does for

inter-classist, mystifying ideologies: reconciling the irreconcilable,

that is, the interests of the bosses and of the servants. Nevertheless,

certain problems are raised.

The probable, and to a certain measure desirable, permanence of

conflicts takes us to the delicate territory of their regulation. To

affirm that contrasting interests, which are born of diversity between

equals, can and must be resolved according to libertarian modalities is

little more than to express a tautology. One has to go beyond this and

define the general lines of a new social right that guarantees the

permanence as well as the reciprocal and global compatibility of diverse

individual and collective interests, in a system of dynamic equilibrium.

Social Right

A first indication of the inspiring principles for a new social right is

rightly this: it must be thought essentially as the guarantee of the

solutions of equilibrium and not as the pre-established codification of

behaviours. The liberal ideological formula for the optimal solution of

the conflict of interests through the free play of commodity and

political competition is mystifying because it is applied to a

non-egalitarian society in which the game is not free, but rather

defined precisely by the falsifying laws of the hierarchical division of

social labour. However, there is here a true kernel of anti-totalitarian

thought, for it refers in fact to a concept of the “natural” equilibrium

of contrasting interests. In reality, there is nothing less natural and

more cultural than this equilibrium. It is human beings in society who

establish the rules of the game. There is no game, nor society, without

rules: the problem lies in how and by whom these are established and

applied.

A second indication in this direction comes expressly from the theory of

direct democracy. The constitutional separation of the legislative,

executive and judicial powers – in truth, more formal than real – has

value in a system where powers are separated from society and where they

are concentrated in dominant roles: only in such a context does it

guarantee, to some extent, through a certain “pluralism of powers”, the

less arbitrary exercise of power, even if, in substance, it is always

class power. In a system where power is socialised, the functions

inherent to law should also be attributes of direct democracy and its

organs. And if the old world has something of value to teach, it is

certainly not with its tribunals and its judges and its lawyers, but

perhaps with its popular juries and arbitration.

It is not by chance that I cited arbitrations. I believe, in effect,

that a third indication of principle is that a social right, founded on

values of individual and collective self-determination, should be

thought of as a frame of reference of few and simple general norms,

within which are to be found an infinite number of free agreements

between individuals and the collectivity, at all of the levels of

articulation of a society, from the local to the international. This

social right should have then a clearly contractual nature. Only thus is

it in fact possible to cover the myriad casuistry of situations, the

interrelations of complementarity and contrast and, thus, the possible

conflicts, which no code could in any way predict.

The MĂĽhlmann Effect

Even in a summary examination, such as that carried out hitherto, it

becomes clear that the problematic knots of self-management correspond

to the major themes of anarchist thought and practice, and that the

self-management approach to different social and political issues

reveals itself to have affinities with – when it is not identical to –

the libertarian approach. Of course, it is as an anarchist that I

followed the logical paths of self-management, by forcing myself to

proceed not by deduction from anarchist ideology, but through the

application of self-management methods to the essential questions of

human conviviality.

Analogous affinities can be identified by addressing the problems of

self-management strategy. Generally, all of the defenders of integral or

generalised self-management agree with the fact that it is not a matter

of reforming the existing social order, but of radically transforming

it. Self-management is a revolutionary theory-praxis.

The enormous question of revolution rises up here. Ruling out the idea

that revolution is simply an insurrection, established that it is a

period (perhaps even comprised of one or more insurrectional moments) of

accelerated institutional and cultural transformations, questions are

raised about how to arrive at unleashing the destructive-reconstructive

process (In only one country? In many countries at the same time? In the

late-capitalist metropole? In the fatherland of techno-bureaucratic

“socialism”? In the periphery of the great empires? In the Third World?)

in such a way that self-management solutions can affirm themselves

successfully over authoritarian solutions.

How to avoid, as always occurred, that the spaces of freedom opened by

the rapid destruction of the old values and structures do not become

spaces for a new slavery? I am not referring here to the external

enemies of the revolution and of self-management, but to the true great

internal enemy: the mechanisms of the reproduction of power which begin

immediately during the revolutionary process and which lead to

conclusions in contradiction with the premises of emancipation. How to

avoid what René Lourau called “the Mühlmann effect” [Wilhelm Emil

MĂĽhlmann], that is, an institutionalisation that denies the social

movement? If the generalised innovating tension can only be a short

lived phenomenon, how can reasonable hopes be nourished that the tension

not limit itself to breaking temporarily the dykes of class domination

to then rapidly set out again on the course of the hierarchical division

of social labour?

Self-management as a method is, in theory, the right response, because

it implies the permanent disruption and de-structuring of power, whether

it be in is its destructive or reconstructive aspects, and therefore,

even in the post-revolutionary institutionalisation, it is, in itself,

the bearer of a continuity of the project that is not exhausted in the

extraordinary tension, but which continues in the normal everyday.

However, this remains only a general logical solution. For it to become

an operational solution, it must be made richer by much more articulated

concrete determinations.

Re-reading History

It is obvious that the reflection on revolution develops entirely on the

basis of past experiences, through that continuous re-composition of

historical elements in function of the present, which makes history an

essential and living collective memory, just as individual memory

continually recomposes, in diverse ways, its elements on the basis of

new facts, new experiences, new necessities. In this sense,

self-management can also be a key to reading differently the

revolutionary experiences of the past, from which to take strategic

indications, a key that privileges amidst what is learned those things

inherent to the issue of organisational method.

Among all social revolutions, I believe that the richest in positive and

negative indications was the Spanish Revolution of 1936–1939, due to the

range and extent of the practice of popular self-management that it

involved. This revolution, with regards to the revolutionary problematic

that I mentioned earlier, schematically indicates the following:

capacities, they know how to find and apply spontaneously diverse and

appropriate self-management formulae, at least at the most “natural”

associative levels (the factory, the city …) and at the first levels of

coordination, when and while there is an absence of power;

anti-authoritarian, subversive convulsion, through the hetero-management

of the “great” problems (war, planning …) and, on the basis of these,

progressively returns to occupy the spaces temporarily left to

self-management;

proletarian organisations best vaccinated against it, such as

anarcho-syndicalist structures, and even in the most anti-bureaucratic

organisations, by ideology and by tradition; they can initiate

techno-bureaucratic tendencies, in perfect good-faith, due to “objective

demands”.

The Spanish Revolution – its preparation, its achievements, its defeat –

is, therefore, an extremely rich mine, still largely underused, from

which self-management thought can and should extract invaluable lessons,

above all if what is sought is not so much – as has been done until now

– the history of a war between fascists and anti-fascists, but, within

the anti-fascist camp, thehistory of a mortal struggle between

proletarians and the State, between self-management and bureaucracy. And

this even if, naturally (it should be superfluous to mention it),

self-management should think its revolution and its strategy in current

realities, which are not those of Spain in 1936 and much less those of

Russia in 1917 and France in 1871.

Towards self-management through self-management

The strategy, far from resolving itself in the problems of the

revolutionary period, also and above all covers the route between the

immediate present and the revolution. It is a matter, as I said, of

finding a path or paths to arrive at revolution in the most ideal way,

such that it is conceivable as an accelerated phase of the journey of

self-management and not an accelerated stage of transition between one

form of hetero-management and another.

Focusing on the first of the three points which I schematised as

indications of the Spanish Revolution, a first question arises: in the

popular self-management, how much was there of “natural” spontaneity and

how much of constructed spontaneity (or merely freed?) by half a century

of libertarian propaganda, agitation, organisation? And the question

arises because it is clear that, as I have already underlined, the

attitude and behaviour of the human being in society have very little to

do with nature (or perhaps even nothing, beyond social instinct) and

great deal to do with culture. Therefore, for the revolt of the slaves

to become a self-management project, for the class struggle to become an

emancipatory revolution, it is necessary that many parts or segments of

the exploited classes develop a culture – a desire and a capacity – of

self-management, educating themselves in individual and collective

self-determination. Passivity and dependence must cease to be

psychological characteristics of the workers. Initiative and

responsibility must cease to be the monopoly of restricted elites.

The formula “towards self-management through self-management” expresses,

beyond an obvious, almost tautological, internal coherence, a

self-pedagogical demand as well. As Félix García says, “there is no

libertarian organisation which is not a pedagogical organisation, in

which pedagogy does not cover each and every one of its pores”. One is

not educated for freedom, one educates oneself. The task of militants

who recognise themselves in the method of self-management is not

therefore to teach self-management, but to stimulate the creation and

multiplication of “situations” of self-education, that is, forms of

direct action and direct democracy, according to a lexicon that is

proper to the libertarian tradition, in which self-management is already

practiced.

The spaces of self-management

The self-management of struggles was not only one of the most successful

slogans, but perhaps also the most obvious manifestation of the demand

for self-management of the last decade, and this a little everywhere.

From the more traditional spaces of the class struggle, the places of

work, to new or partially new spaces, we are witness to the expansion of

this demand, which is the refusal to be used by leaders as soldiers, as

the particular fountain of the power of institutional managers

(political parties, labour unions …) of social conflict. It expresses

the desire to decide for oneself when and how to struggle for one’s own

interests and when and how to accept the inevitable temporary

armistices.

A new question imposes itself: what social subject can spark struggles

that allow for the revolutionary growth of self-management? Who is this

subject? The working class as it is more or less traditionally

conceived? Is it a social front that runs from the student to the

technician? Is it the marginal and the “precarious”? In my opinion, the

very extension of the social demand for self-management is a sign of how

the revolutionary subject, at least potentially and as a tendency, can

be identified with numerous social strata. When revolt is a revolt

against power, it gathers together all of those whom the dominant

minority robbed of their quota of power, in a sort of class accumulation

of “more power.”

The self-management front of struggles is therefore a front which opens

up to and encompasses, or can encompass, numerous social roles: domestic

worker, tenant, student, soldier, worker, peasant, wife, son, the

unemployed, the consumer of gas … It invades, with critical theory and

practice, numerous aspects of hetero-management, in now fragmentary and

episodic ways, always recuperated by the institutions, and which, even

then, contradictorily, always returns and reappears. This is a front

that is not in reality one, because it does not possess in fact a linear

trajectory and it calls to mind, in igniting and extinguishing itself

here and there in points and moments of contestation, a diffuse

guerrilla and not trench warfare. And this is its strength, because it

does not give itself over to a frontal clash, which would be to play

into the game of the enemy still – and until the revolution – more

powerful.

Can and should this guerrilla expand, as we believe, and come to

generalise and reproduce itself more than it is recuperated, it will

arrive, sooner or later, at the heart of the organisation. Should a

self-management project create permanent structures of interconnection?

I believe so because self-management is, by its nature, a synthesis of

spontaneity and organisation and because the growth of the revolutionary

project must accompany step by step the growth in the capacity of

self-organisation at all levels of complexity. I believe however that

there should not be one form and one structure of interconnection, but a

plurality of forms and structures, in coherence with the self-management

method, in a network structure, whose density and extent increases with

the growing dimension of the project.

A front that is not a front

The self-management of struggles is, at least as a general idea, an

almost obvious concept. It is an indisputably indispensible element of

self-management strategy. Without self-managed struggles, it is

impossible to see how one can arrive at a self-managed society. But a

final question imposes itself on this subject, last in time, but not in

importance: is the self-management of struggles the only form of

self-management possible before the revolution and, simultaneously, is

it a sufficient means to prepare the conditions for an egalitarian and

libertarian revolution?

The answer is not and cannot be categorical. An affirmative answer, at

least to the first part of the question, seems to follow logically from

the general affirmation according to which: a) what exists cannot be

self-managed because it is, by its nature, antithetical to

self-management, in each of its parts and as a whole; b) on the other

hand, a partial self-management can only be a more or less disguised

co-management. Even without denying the validity of this affirmation, I

am convinced that to infer from it, in an apodictic manner, the

impossibility or the counter-productiveness of experiences of

self-management is a mistake born of logical rigidity. Applying this

thesis fixedly, one could, in effect, arrive at the impossibility of the

self-management of struggles, because they are not in fact a pure

negation, but an element of what exists, even though conflictual.

Reality is much more complex and does not allow itself to be limited by

any simple and absolute definition. Who can affirm without the shadow of

a doubt that the self-management of a community, of a company, of a

nursing home, necessarily means managing an articulation of what exists

and not, on the contrary, a contradiction to what is? If it were so, if

a specific social-economic system did not admit anything except what is

similar and susceptible to assimilation to it, the historical norm of

change could not be explained, change which is precisely antithetical:

the new is born and develops, with differing fortunes, advances and

regressions, rightly next to or even in the heart of the old. Thus was

born the artisanal and merchant city in the feudal fabric, capitalist

industry in the corporative fabric, technical-bureaucracy in the

capitalist fabric …

Objections centred on the difficulties of constituting, developing and

defending “islands” of self-management are more convincing. In this

sense, experience is rich in failures. France’s LIP is an emblematic

case because the spontaneous choice by its workers of self-management

was emblematic. In Italy, analogous experiences of self-management

undertaken by workers to free companies from the bankruptcy of owner

management normally ended up with the delay of the bankruptcy or these

became simple cooperatives with a hierarchical management and intensive

self-exploitation. There is the recent failure of the ex-Fioravanti, a

pasta producing factory which, in 1974, experienced a long period of

self-management. There is also the recent news, apparently of a very

different kind of experience, that the ex-Motta di Segrate (a

cooperative of 160 members producing pastry and pre-cooked meals for

canteens) is operating under self-management. Sick leave is down from

20–30 percent to 2–3 percent, the President claims with satisfaction. Is

this due to the work being less alienating? No: it is rather the

intensification of alienation for fear of losing their jobs in a period

of economic crisis.

Examples of self-management as a result of owner bankruptcy also seem to

be multiplying in Spain in a similar context of crisis, with very

similar consequences, at least if one reads “Ajoblanco” (nº 43, 1979).

It concludes with a melancholy review of failures, asking itself whether

“islands of self-management” are in fact possible and with a statement

from a worker: “After all of the difficulties that we faced, we are

firmly convinced that self-management can only be realised if

generalised and in a different society”.

Is it therefore impossible, if not logically, at least practically, for

self-management to survive (and with greater reason, for it to develop)

within the rules of the capitalist game and/or the

techno-bureaucratically established rules by and for the hierarchical

division of social labour? Between failure and assimilation/integration,

is there in fact no intermediate space? I have a different opinion. I

believe that it is not a matter of impossibility, but of difficulty,

even though of great difficulty. The example of the Comunidad del Sur of

Montevideo, which functioned for two decades under libertarian and

egalitarian self-management, as a community and as a mid-sized

typographical business, seems to demonstrate that “islands of

self-management” are in reality possible and that their survival is not

necessarily linked to a supposed integration or even a substantial

innocuousness. The Comunidad functioned so well that it survived various

repressive waves and it was so little innocuous that it had to be

crushed by force of arms. It could be objected that the island of

self-management was not able to defend itself. But against the Uruguayan

military-fascist dictatorship, neither the mass labour unions, nor the

armed struggle Tupamaros, succedded in resisting.

I believe accordingly that islands of self-management are possible and

that these, amidst a thousand obstacles and hundreds of failures, can

and should become archipelagos. In reality, they are always more nodes

than islands in a network that bring together self-managed units, not

only between themselves, but also and above all, with the

self-management of struggles. These latter should be, in a certain

sense, the “realised” extension of the former, in a relationship of

reciprocal strengthening which mutually exalts the potentialities of

development and the capacities of defence. It is a matter of surpassing

the threshold of rejection or assimilation by the old organism of social

hierarchy. Beyond that threshold, self-management can be neither

assimilated nor rejected.

The subversive weed

Such a network of cooperatives, organisms of struggle, communities,

cultural associations, allows for the multiplication, in a progressive

process, of the contradictions of the hierarchical system, multiplying

all the while the pedagogical “situations” of self-management and

inversely reducing the repressive/integrative capacity of what exists.

As a subversive weed, self-management can press and pry into any

fissure, any crack, gaining root and breaking up the cement of the

system, and expanding exactly like an invasive plant, with the same

stubborn resistance to drought and poisons, with the same formidable

capacity of multiplication, with the same faculty of responding to

mutilations, regenerating a new plant with every fragment.

In this way manner, struggle becomes the life of every day and everyday

life becomes a struggle, preserving it from the symmetrical dangers of

self-marginalisation (perhaps felicitous, but only perhaps), the

realization of micro-utopias, the tiring Sisyphus like labour of

conflict functional to the system, the necessarily short, impatient,

blind forging ahead and the delays due to the intellectual separation

from reality. Developing all of its wealth of method, self-management

can bind each moment of a long journey through the “personal” and the

“political”. It can be a revolutionary strategy which, by means of the

daily and incessant de-structuring/de-struction of power, in psychic

infrastructures, institutional structures, ideological superstructures,

makes grow a libertarian and egalitarian counter-society in the

interstices of hierarchical society, until this latter breaks the global

cohesion and coherence, until it inverts the relationships of force

between the old and the new. Then, the necessity of anarchism can and

should break the shell of what denies it, and that is revolution.

Appendix

After the orgy of generalised participation in the pages above, I now

want to add, as a partial antidote, a brief excerpt from a presentation

by Henri Desroche at the international seminar on self-management and

workers participation in Europe (Bologna, 1970): “It is a first proposal

or a first hypothesis: the aspiration to participation is correlated

with the aspiration to gain distance. The engagement in the company is

correlated with a disengagement from the company. The propensity to be

part of the management is correlated with another propensity to be

outside of management. If this correlation is not taken into

consideration, participation runs the risk of becoming a burden or of

meeting with indifference and absenteeism. This trap may become

formidable in the eventuality of a generalised participation, […] of an

integral economic republic, in which each conscious and organised

citizen would have the right and the duty to participate in all

industrial, agricultural, financial, social, social-cultural affairs, on

which her/his life depends and, consequently, would be obliged to make

them dependent on her/his consciousness and domination. There would thus

be an invitation to not only comprehend and dominate moral relations,

but also administrative relations, budgets, the accounting of gains and

losses, etc. There would also be the complementary invitation to be

present in assemblies, meetings, commissions, committees, etc.,

naturally with the registration and qualification of that participation:

active, semi-active or inactive. One can imagine that the situation

would become very similar to laboratory experiments in which the

possibility of dreaming is taken from an individual, even in their

sleep. Before the neurotic danger of such a situation, the field of

participation could elaborate some solutions. For example, there could

be a right to non-participation, as in those places where you pay twice

as much for the right to place on the record player a silent disc to

have a brief period of time without noise. Furthermore, there could be

an integrated automation, thanks to central super-memories, of all of

those “committee-cratic” processes conceived by participatory activity

in its artisanal stage. In one case, as in the other, there would be a

participation restrained by distancing. Durkheim stated that “nothing is

good without measure”, while underlining that the two kinds of societies

with the highest incidences of suicide were either societies of

excessive individualism and insufficient socialisation, or, conversely,

societies of insufficient individualism and excessive socialisation.”

Bibliographical References

Given the nature of this text, which develops a line of thought that is

still a little tangled and some reflections written as a “chemical

reaction” to the crossing of my anarchism with the diverse / monotonous

/ rich / contradictory / stimulating/ irritating / original / deceiving

/ libertarian / crypto-authoritarian culture of self-management, I

purposefully avoided any bibliography. I list below the books that, in a

slightly disordered reading, accompanied my reflections:

Pietro Bellasi, Michele La Rosa, Giovanni Pellicciari (a cura di),

Fabbrica e societĂ . Autogestione e partecipazione operaia in Europa,

Angeli, Milano, 1974.

Alfredo Bonanno, Autogestione e anarchismo, La Fiaccola, Ragusa, 1975.

Murray Bookchin, Post-Scarcity Anarchism, Ramparts Press, Berkeley,

1971.

Yves Bourdet, Per l’autogestione. Analisi e prospettive, Moizzi, 1976;

Teoria politica dell’autogestione, Nuove Edizione Operaie, Milano, 1977;

L’Éspace de l’autogestion, Galilée, Paris, 1978.

Pierre Clastre, La societĂ  contra lo Stato, Feltrinelli, Milano, 1977.

Franco Crespi, Teoria sociologica e socializzazione del potere, Angeli,

Milano, 1974.

Henri Desroche, Autogestione, partecipazone e associazionismo

cooperativo, in Fabrica e societĂ , op. cit.

FĂ©lix GarcĂ­a, Coherencia libertaria (1), PedagogĂ­a y organizaciĂłn,

“Bicicleta”, nº 15, 1979, pp. 48–49.

Milojko Drulovic, La Democrazia autogestita, Editori Riuniti, Roma,

1977.

Piero Flecchia, La cultura della viltĂ , Emme, Milano, 1978.

Roberto Guiducci, La diseguaglianza tra glo uomini, Rizzoli, Milano,

1977; Un mondo capovolto, Rizzoli, Milano, 1979.

Michele La Rosa, Mauro Gori (a cura di), L’autogestione. Democrazia

politica e democrazia industriale, CittĂ  Nuova, Roma, 1978.

Georges Lapassade, L’autogestione pedagogica, Angeli, Milano, 1973.

René Lourau, L’Autogestion comme condition du dépérissement de l’État,

“Autogestion et socialisme”, nº 41–42, 1978, pp. 145–165; Lo Stato

incosciente, elèuthera, Milano, 1988.

Roberto Massari, La teoria dell’autogestione, Jaca Book, Milano, 1974.

Noir et Rouge, Lo Stato, la rivoluzione, l’autogestione, La Fiaccola,

Ragusa, 1974.

Philippe Oyhamburu, La Revance de Bakounine ou de l’anarchisme à

l’autogestion, Entente, Paris, 1975.

Gian Paolo Prandstraller, FelicitĂ  e societĂ , CominitĂ , Milano, 1978.

Pierre Rosanvallon, L’età dell’autogestione, Marsilio, Venezia, 1978.

Menahem Rosner, L’Autogestion industrilelle dans les kibbutzim,

“Sociologie du travail”, nº 1, janvier-mars 1974.

Ernst Friedrich Schumacher, Il piccolo è bello, Moizzi, Milano, 1977.

Leonardo Tomasetta, Partecipazione e autogestione, il Saggiatore,

Milano, 1972.

John F. Turner, L’abitare autogestito, Jaca Book, Milano, 1978.

Roberto Villetti (a cura di), Socialismo e divisione del lavoro,

Mondooperaio, Roma, 1978.

[1] The author is here referring to the 1970s. [Translator’s Note]

[2] The passage appears originally in French. This was a slogan of the

LIP workers: “we produce, we sell, we pay ourselves”. [TN]

[3] The author refers here to the well known experience of the

self-management of the LIP watch factory located on the periphery of

Besançon (native city of Proudhon) and begun on the 17^(th) of April of

1973. LIP was a solid company until it was purchased by a group of

“investors” who presented a plan for collective dismissals that reached

to 100s of workers, mostly women. The organised resistance by the

workers gave rise to a notable movement of struggle, which lasted years,

multiplied illegal actions without ever ceding to the temptation of

violence, basing itself on direct democracy and a fertile imagination.

The practice of self-management affirmed itself as a valid alternative.

[TN]

[4] A word for which there is no translation and invented by the author

on the basis of the acronym IRI (Istituto per la Ricostruzione

Industriale), a public entity created in 1933 by the Fascist regime to

finance banks and companies that had gone bankrupt during the Great

Depression. It was dissolved in 2002 [TN]

[5] A word for which there is no translation and invented by the author

on the basis of the acronym GEPI (SocietĂ  per le Gestioni e

Partecipazioni Industriali), a public entity created in 1971, in which

the IRI and IMI (see following note) participated and which was

integrated into, in 1977, the Sviluppo Italia agency. [TN]

[6] A word for which there is no translation and invented by the author

on the basis of the acronym IMI (Istituto Mobiliare Italiano), a public

credit institution created in 1931 to help companies overcome the

difficulties associated with the Great Depression. In 1998, it fused

with the Istituto Bancario San Paolo di Torino to become Sanpaolo IMI.

[TN]